text
stringlengths 0
1.71k
|
---|
by analogy is considered as an indispensable accompaniment of scientifi |
c thought as far as induction forms the basic scientifi c method. |
In early Greek philosophy, analogy is a pattern of thought that underlies |
the fi rst attempts for an explanation of the cosmos. This is initially found |
in the Milesians thinkers Thales ( fl . c. 585 bce ) and Anaximenes ( fl . c. 546 |
bce ). Thales argued that β as a piece of wood fl oats on a pond, so the whole |
earth fl oats on water β (DK 11A14; cf., DK 11A12). According to Aristotle: |
Others say that the earth rests on water. For this is the most ancient |
account we have received, which they say was given by Thales the Milesian, |
that it stays in place through fl oating like a log or some other such thing (for |
none of these rests by nature on air, but on water) β as though the same argument |
did not apply to the water supporting the earth as to the earth itself. |
(Aristotle B13, 294a28) |
Thales β inductive reasoning refl ects an argument by analogy: if two |
things have certain properties in common on a small scale, then they have |
the same properties in common on a cosmic scale: |
Small scale: a piece of wood fl oats on a pond. |
Large scale: the Earth fl oats on Okeanos. |
Likewise, Anaximenes claims an analogy between human soul and the |
cosmos: |
As our soul, which is air, maintain us, so breath and air surround the whole |
world. (DK, 13B2) |
Anaximenes offers an argument by analogy: |
Small scale: the human soul (human breath) maintains the single individual |
organism (microcosm). |
Large scale: the soul of the cosmos (universal breath) surrounds and |
maintains the whole universe. |
Analogy as a pattern of thought seems to underlie Anaximenes β inductive |
thinking used for rhetorical, metaphoric, and explanatory purposes. This is |
evident in some of his extant fragments and testimonies ( Die Fragmente der |
Vorsokratiker ): |
182 Giannis Stamatellos |
The stars move around the earth, just as turban winds round our head. |
[A7] |
The universe whirls like a mill - stone. [A12] |
The stars are fi xed in the crystalline in the manner of nails. [A14] |
The sun is fl at like a leaf. [A15] |
In the above examples, analogy is used by Anaximenes to explain macrocosm |
through common observation. Thales β and Anaximenes β arguments |
by analogy are considered as one of the fi rst incidences of inductive reasoning. |
The relationship between microcosm (small scale) and macrocosm |
(cosmic scale) refl ects Thales β hylozoism and mathematical expertise |
(e.g., measurement of the pyramids and predictions of the eclipses) and |
Anaximenes β natural philosophy and cosmological discoveries. Early Greek |
philosophical argumentation by analogy, as a form of induction, marks the |
beginning of scientifi c explanation and thought. |
47 |
Quine β s Epistemology |
Naturalized |
Robert Sinclair |
Quine , W. V. β Epistemology Naturalized , β in Ontological Relativity and |
Other Essays , 69 β 90 . New York : Columbia University Press , 1969 . |
Gregory , Paul . Quine β s Naturalism: Language, Theory and the Knowing |
Subject . New York : Continuum , 2008 . |
Roth , Paul . β The Epistemology of β Epistemology Naturalized β . β Dialectica |
53 ( 1999 ): 87 β 109 . |
In his highly infl uential article β Epistemology Naturalized, β W. V. Quine |
argued that the problems found in the history of modern empiricism should |
lead us to rethink the overall aims of contemporary epistemology. More |
specifi cally, he offered a historical reconstruction of post - Humean empiricism, |
highlighting where attempts to support or to justify our knowledge |
of the world through sensory experience fell into insurmountable problems |
and suggesting further the need to locate the grounds of knowledge within |
science itself. On his view, epistemology should then be β naturalized β in |
the sense that it becomes a scientifi c project where philosophers must use |
the resources of science to explain, to describe, and to justify our knowledge |
of the world. |
His basic argument appeals to an analogy between studies in the foundations |
of mathematical knowledge and the empiricist attempt to provide a |
sensory foundation for scientifi c knowledge. The project in the philosophy |
Just the Arguments: 100 of the Most Important Arguments in Western Philosophy, |
First Edition. Edited by Michael Bruce and Steven Barbone. |
Β© 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. Published 2011 by Blackwell Publishing Ltd. |
184 Robert Sinclair |
of mathematics that is Quine β s focus is known as β logicism, β which held |
that mathematical truths could be defi ned in terms of a more basic logical |
language. Here, on what Quine calls the β conceptual β side, mathematical |
concepts could be rewritten and, in that sense, reduced to what was thought |
to be a more certain and obviously true logical vocabulary. This would also |
help deal with a further β doctrinal β concern over the justifi cation of mathematical |
truths, since they could be restated as basic logical truths with a |
similar degree of logical certainty. Unfortunately, this project cannot be |
completed, since the proposed reduction of mathematical concepts requires |
set theory, which contains its own logical paradoxes and does not then have |
the same obviousness or certainty assumed to be had within logic. Moreover, |
G ΓΆ del β s famous incompleteness theorems undermine the doctrinal aim, |
since they demonstrate that no logical rendering of all the truths of mathematics |
is possible. |
With this as background, Quine proceeds to develop further his analogy |
between logicism and empiricism. Like logicism, the empiricist attempt to |
validate scientifi c truths within sensory experience contains a conceptual |
side focused on defi ning concepts in sensory terms and a doctrinal side that |
seeks to justify truths of nature through sensory experience. However, these |
two aims cannot be met. The conceptual side falters because of β holism, β |
the view that terms and sentences have implications for experience only |
through their interconnections and never by themselves in isolation. What |
this suggests is that, in general, no concept or theoretical claim has its own |
consequences for experience, and thus no single concept or statement could |
then be assigned to or reduced to its own specifi c element of experience. |
The doctrinal aim fails because of what Quine calls β Hume β s problem, β |
Subsets and Splits
No community queries yet
The top public SQL queries from the community will appear here once available.