id
int64 59
4.83M
| tag
stringlengths 1
12.4k
| cite
stringlengths 1
4.52k
| fullcite
stringlengths 1
105k
| summary
stringlengths 1
62.2k
| spoken
stringlengths 1
35k
| fulltext
stringlengths 4
388k
| textLength
int64 4
388k
| markup
stringlengths 35
397k
| pocket
stringlengths 1
8k
⌀ | hat
stringlengths 1
7.13k
⌀ | block
stringlengths 1
16.2k
⌀ | bucketId
int64 1
1.95M
| duplicateCount
int64 1
5.63k
| fileId
int64 1
172k
| filePath
stringlengths 49
182
| roundId
float64 565k
998k
⌀ | side
stringclasses 2
values | tournament
stringlengths 1
95
⌀ | round
stringclasses 56
values | opponent
stringlengths 1
65
⌀ | judge
stringlengths 1
128
⌀ | report
stringlengths 1
53.7k
⌀ | opensourcePath
stringlengths 37
170
⌀ | caselistUpdatedAt
stringlengths 19
19
⌀ | teamId
float64 48.4k
86.5k
⌀ | teamName
stringlengths 2
8
⌀ | teamDisplayName
stringlengths 6
45
⌀ | notes
stringclasses 631
values | debater1First
stringclasses 269
values | debater1Last
stringclasses 306
values | debater2First
stringclasses 224
values | debater2Last
stringclasses 259
values | schoolId
float64 18.7k
28.2k
⌀ | schoolName
stringlengths 3
35
⌀ | schoolDisplayName
stringlengths 3
40
⌀ | state
stringclasses 49
values | chapterId
float64 23
114k
⌀ | caselistId
float64 1k
2.01k
⌀ | caselistName
stringclasses 40
values | caselistDisplayName
stringclasses 39
values | year
float64 2.01k
2.02k
⌀ | event
stringclasses 3
values | level
stringclasses 2
values | teamSize
float64 1
2
⌀ |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
4,465,373 | Disease spread is existential---best studies prove. | Kim ’21 | Kim ’21 [Kiseong, Sunyong Yoo, Sangyeon Lee, Doheon Lee, and Kwang-Hyung Lee; March 26; Department of Bio and Brain Engineering, KAIST; Research and Development Center at BioBrain Inc.; Department of ICT Convergence System Engineering, Chonnam National University; Bio-Synergy Research Center; Moon Soul Graduate School of Future Strategy; Applied Sciences, “Network Analysis to Identify the Risk of Epidemic Spreading,” vol. 11] | epidemics, such as Black Death and Spanish flu threatened human life throughout history the sudden and fast spread of epidemic diseases remain undiscovered we present a epidemic simulation experiment revealing the relationship between epidemic parameters and pandemic risk certain diseases can infect all nodes in the human social networks These infectious diseases lead to human extinction
The emergence of a pandemic is frequently discussed as a human extinction event, and it is listed as one of the global catastrophic risks in studies several pandemics, such as the Black Death Spanish flu smallpox SARS and Ebola affected a large population throughout history. The risk of pandemics increases with population mobility threatening humankind
when the epidemic spreads to all nodes the fatality rate is 100%
We designed an epidemic simulation process
We adapted the Monte Carlo method to determine the status of the transition
Diseases causing extinctive spread are potential candidates of high pandemic risk extinctive spreading indicates disease will infect every person in the society
Many previous studies have made stochastic SIR models to analyze the dynamics or stability of epidemic diseases However, they did not conduct a quantitative assessment of pandemic risk taking into account physical contact between people we consider various connectivity and disease characteristics The results revealed that certain infectious diseases can lead to extinction human extinction is possible | epidemics threaten human life the sudden spread of diseases remain undiscovered a simulation reveal the risk diseases infect all nodes These lead to extinction
emergence is frequently a extinction event, and global risk Black Death smallpox and Ebola affected a large population risk increases with mobility
extinctive spread will infect every person
previous studies did not conduct quantitative assessment we consider various disease characteristics results reveal extinction | Several epidemics, such as the Black Death and the Spanish flu, have threatened human life throughout history; however, it is unclear if humans will remain safe from the sudden and fast spread of epidemic diseases. Moreover, the transmission characteristics of epidemics remain undiscovered. In this study, we present the results of an epidemic simulation experiment revealing the relationship between epidemic parameters and pandemic risk. To analyze the time-dependent risk and impact of epidemics, we considered two parameters for infectious diseases: the recovery time from infection and the transmission rate of the disease. Based on the epidemic simulation, we identified two important aspects of human safety with regard to the threat of a pandemic. First, humans should be safe if the fatality rate is below 100%. Second, even when the fatality rate is 100%, humans would be safe if the average degree of human social networks is below a threshold value. Nevertheless, certain diseases can potentially infect all nodes in the human social networks, and these diseases cause a pandemic when the average degree is larger than the threshold value. These results indicated that certain infectious diseases lead to human extinction and can be prevented by minimizing human contact.
1. Introduction
The emergence of a pandemic is one of the various scenarios frequently discussed as a human extinction event, and it is listed as one of the global catastrophic risks in studies regarding the future [1,2,3]. In particular, several pandemics, such as the Black Death [4,5], Spanish flu [6], and those caused by smallpox [7], severe acute respiratory syndrome (SARS) [8], and Ebola [9], have affected a large population throughout history. The risk of pandemics increases with an increase in population mobility between cities, nations, and continents, thereby threatening humankind [10,11,12]. It is essential to analyze the epidemic spread in society to minimize the damage from epidemic disasters; however, extinctive epidemic spreading experiments have limitations in real-world situations, as they predict stochastic effects on the spread without considering the structure of human society. Network-based approaches have been proposed to overcome these limitations and perform epidemic spreading simulations by considering the network structure of numerous real-world connections [13,14,15]. These methods use various models of epidemic spreading, such as the susceptible–infectious–susceptible (SIS) [16,17,18], susceptible–infectious–recovered (SIR) [19,20,21], and Watts threshold models [22]. While these methods are mathematically convenient, they are epidemiologically unrealistic for various infections because they require exponentially distributed incubation and infectious periods [23,24,25]. Moreover, previous epidemic studies did not perform quantitative assessment of the pandemic risk depending on the network connectivity in individuals and fatality rate of various diseases [26].
In the present study, we applied an SIR epidemic model to a scale-free network with Monte Carlo simulation to identify the quantitative relationship between infectious diseases and human existence. Our fundamental hypothesis states that when the epidemic spreads to all nodes of the network and the fatality rate is 100%, it can increase the pandemic risk. To address this, we initially constructed a scale-free network to simulate a society. Moreover, for the epidemic spreading simulation, an SIR model was applied to the network to describe the immune state of an individual after infection. From the simulation study, we found that the mean degree of a scale-free network was an essential factor in determining whether epidemics threaten humans. This approach provides important insights into epidemic spreading analysis by investigating the relationship between epidemic and scale-free network parameters. Furthermore, it highlights the necessity of determining information flow during an epidemic.
2. Materials and Methods
We designed an epidemic simulation process to identify the relationship between pandemic risk and network parameters. This study was performed in four steps (Figure 1): (i) generating a scale-free network model to reflect real-world conditions; (ii) applying an SIR model to the scale-free network for epidemic spreading simulations; (iii) adapting the Monte Carlo method to reflect the stochastic process in the node status of the SIR model; and (iv) iteratively performing simulation for every parameter set and analyzing the results. We have provided the source code and sample results of epidemic simulation in Supplementary Materials.
Figure 1. Overview of epidemic simulation process based on the Monte Carlo method. (A) We generated scale-free networks for a fixed population (N = 1,000,000) and various node degrees (k = 2, 5, 7, and 10). (B) Epidemic spreading was simulated by applying a susceptible–infectious–recovered (SIR) model to the scale-free network. We set the epidemic parameters, β and γd. β represents the spreading rate of epidemics, and γd is the reciprocal of γ and reflects the time interval between infection and recovery. Randomly, 0.05% of nodes were initially infected. (C) We adapted the Monte Carlo method to determine the status of the transition from the infection node to immunization node. Repeated simulations were performed until a steady state was achieved. (D) For every parameter set, 10,000 simulations were performed.
2.1. Network Generation Based on a Scale-Free Model
We constructed a network model for the epidemic spreading simulation (Figure 1). The nodes and edges of the network represent people in the society and their physical contacts, respectively. We used a scale-free network model, which follows the preferential attachment property observed in numerous real-world networks, such as social networks, physical systems, and economic networks [27,28,29]. In the scale-free network, when a node is added to the network, its likelihood of connecting to existing nodes increases with an increase in the node’s degree. Hub nodes, which lead to fast and vast spreading of epidemics, exist. Two characteristic parameters, including N and k, affect the form of scale-free networks. The parameter N denotes all nodes in the network. In the real world, N indicates the whole population size. The parameter k is the average degree of the network, which determines the degree of the newly attached node for each step during network generation. Following the characteristics of the network model, we generated scale-free networks representing human contacts for epidemic spread. The scale-free network was generated by the Barabasi–Albert graph distribution, in which the network is constructed from a cycle graph with three vertices, followed by the addition of k edges at each construction step [30]. The k edges are randomly attached to the vertex based on the degree distribution of the vertex. After network generation, we investigated the degree distribution properties of the network (Figure 2). The results indicate that the degree distributions have similar tendency for networks with varying number of nodes and edges. This study constructed scale-free networks with the largest number of nodes considering computational complexity (N = 1,000,000).
<<FIGURE 1 OMITTED>>
Figure 2. Degree distribution of the scale-free network. We analyzed the degree distribution of the network based on the number of nodes (N) and mean degree (k).
2.2. Epidemic Spreading Based on the SIR Model
For the epidemic spreading simulations, we applied an SIR model to the generated scale-free network. The classical SIR model can be expressed by the following nonlinear differential equations [21]:
<<EQUATIONS OMITTED>>
where S, I, and R represent susceptible, infected, and recovered compartments, respectively, in the whole population. S represents people who have not been infected yet but can be infected in future. I represents infected people who can spread the epidemic to susceptible people through physical contact. R denotes people who have recovered or died from the epidemic and who no longer participate in the epidemic spreading process. The sum of the S, I, and R values represents the whole population size N. Epidemics have two parameters in the SIR model, transmission rate (β) and recovery rate (γ), which arise from the basic reproduction number R0 (Figure 1B). The basic reproduction number is the number of infections caused by one infective node [31,32,33]. If the R0 is more than 1, the infection can spread in a population, whereas if R0 is less than 1, the infection cannot spread. We express the basic reproduction number as R0 = β/γ, where β represents the spreading rate of epidemics between infective nodes and adjacent susceptible nodes and γ represents the probability of recovery from infection [34]. We mainly used γd, which is the reciprocal of γ and reflects the time interval between infection and recovery.
2.3. Investigation of Epidemic Status Based on the Monte Carlo Method
The epidemic simulation was performed for a time series event by constructing epidemic status matrix (z) to represent the status of the nth node at time step t. For each node, the value of epidemic status matrix at time step t can be 0, 1, or 2, indicating that a node is susceptible, infective, or recovered, respectively. We initially (t = 0) set every value of epidemic status matrix to 0 because all nodes are susceptible before the epidemic spreads. At the initial infection stage, randomly selected 0.05% of nodes were infected. At every time period, we performed immunization and observed the infection stages (Figure 3).
<<FIGURE 3 OMITTED>>
At the immunization stage, we identified infective nodes and determined whether these nodes would be recovered in the next time step. To calculate the transition probability of infected and recovered phenomena, the Monte Carlo method was applied [35,36]. When infection and recovery parameters are provided, it is possible to investigate whether a node transitions from an epidemic state to another state. To accomplish this, we compared the method revealing the change in each population in every compartment over time (Figure 4).
<<FIGURE 4 OMITTED>>
The final steady state of the epidemic spreading simulation model indicates the total number of casualties of the epidemic who either are dead or have recovered from the disease. Infective nodes at time t (zn [t] = 1) are transformed to recovered nodes at time t + 1 (zn [t + 1] = 2) when 1/γd is larger than a random real number between 0 and 1. We determined whether the neighbor nodes of the infection node would be infected by identifying susceptible nodes adjacent to the infective nodes at time t (zn [t] = 0, with the adjacent infective node) (Figure 5). When β is larger than a random real number between 0 and 1, a susceptible node becomes an infective node at time t + 1 (zn [t + 1] = 1); this scenario represents epidemic spread. For each time step, we recorded the number of susceptible, infective, and recovered nodes during epidemic spread.
<<FIGURE 5 OMITTED>>
2.4. Simulation Parameters
We carried out simulation trials for various mean degrees of networks (k = 2, 5, 7, and 10). Each network considered the following epidemic parameters: β ranges from 0.05 to 0.95 and γd ranges from 1 to 10. The Monte Carlo model was repeatedly simulated to observe saturation of the recovery process. Considering that the simulation pipeline contains random processes such as initial infection and Monte Carlo trials, we performed the simulation iteratively until the status of nodes remained unchanged. After simulation, time series data from every simulation were interpolated in the time domain.
The fatality rate determines the ratio of deceased and recovered individuals in the final population [37,38,39]. If the fatality rate is below 100%, the recovered population contains both dead and recovered individuals. Such a situation does not always cause a pandemic. In this simulation, we assumed a 100% fatality rate. To accomplish this, we enumerated the recovered nodes as dead for considering the pandemic risk.
3. Results
Through our method, we obtained epidemic spreading data with various network and epidemic parameter sets. In the present study, we focused on the case where the epidemic infects all nodes and defined this phenomenon as “extinctive spread”. Diseases causing extinctive spread are potential candidates of high pandemic risk. In the real world, extinctive spreading indicates that the disease will infect every person in the society. From the simulation data, we calculated the extinctive spread score by dividing the total number of simulation trials by the number of extinctive spread cases. Thereafter, we identified that the number of extinctive spread cases is mainly influenced by spreading speed, which is determined by β, γd, and k (Figure 6).
<<FIGURE 6 OMITTED>>
The extinctive spread region (brown area in Figure 6) is expanded as the value of mean degree of network (k) is increased, thereby indicating that the area of extinctive spread becomes noticeably wider in a dense network than in a sparse network. Thus, the more contact between people, the higher the risk of epidemics. Moreover, high γd and high β cause extinctive spread across a large region, indicating that the high spreading rate and short time interval between infection and recovery are risk factors of epidemic diseases. In contrast, the infective nodes recover before they transmit the disease to their neighbors in low β and low γd scenarios, thus disconnecting the network and preventing extinctive spread. This occurs because the infective nodes need more time to transmit the disease in low β and high γd scenarios. Therefore, the disease begins to subside due to a lack of new infective nodes.
Furthermore, we investigated the range of β and γd for existing epidemics of the common cold [40,41] and fatal diseases, namely, cholera [42,43], Marburg [44,45], Ebola (Congo and Uganda) [46,47,48,49], SARS [50], and MERS [51] (Table 1). We selected diseases with relatively well-known epidemic parameters, such as average duration of infection and basic number of reproductions from previous studies. Transmission rates were calculated using the mean duration of infectious periods and basic reproduction numbers of the epidemics. Different studies reveal multiple values of infectious period and transmission rate for some of these diseases; we considered these values separately [40,41,42,43,46,47,48,49]. For example, the infectious period of a common cold is from 3 to 7 days and that of Ebola is 6.5 days. Next, we placed the possible regions of these epidemics as a disease band for various k values (colored lines in Figure 6). When k > 5, fatal diseases have an opportunity to cause a pandemic. Even when k = 5, diseases such as cholera and Ebola (Congo) can be threatening in regions of low γd and high, thus demonstrating that the knowledge of network parameters of the society and the characteristics of epidemic diseases can aid in quantifying the risk of epidemics.
<<TABLE 1 OMITTED>>
4. Discussion
Many previous studies have made stochastic SIR models to analyze the dynamics or stability of epidemic diseases. They investigated the distribution of susceptible, infected, and removed populations for specific epidemic disease spreading, such as cholera, SARS, Marburg, and MERS, based on mathematical modelling [52,53,54,55]. However, they did not conduct a quantitative assessment of pandemic risk taking into account physical contact between people. To solve this limitation, we performed epidemic spreading simulations by applying an SIR model to scale-free networks with Monte Carlo simulation. In the simulation, we consider various connectivity and disease characteristics on scale-free networks. For each network and epidemic parameter set, the probability of extinctive spread was calculated. The results revealed that certain infectious diseases can lead to extinction. Moreover, even if the disease band extends over the extinctive spread regions, it does not indicate that human extinction results from the disease, as the fatality rate is below 100%; however, in the case of 100% fatality, the disease can cause a human extinction event. The risk of infectious disease is influenced by the network structure. A dense network has a higher risk of spreading infectious disease than a sparse network, as we observed in the extinctive spreading maps. According to our results, when the average degree of human social networks is below the risk threshold, i.e., less than 4 in this study, human society is safe from an extinctive outbreak based on our knowledge regarding the epidemic parameters of the infectious disease. Nevertheless, in other cases, human extinction is possible. For example, if the population is 1,000,000 and there are 4 or more instances of physical contact between people, human extinction events may occur, depending on the fatality rate of the epidemics. Hence, physical contact between people is closely related to an extinction event of infectious diseases. Eventually, from a public health perspective, lowering the average contact level of society is an appropriate way to increase the robustness of strategies against the occurrence of extinction. In the real world, reducing network density can be accomplished by epidemic prevention activity, such as isolation and quarantine treatment. This action prevents epidemic risk to the society, thereby avoiding human extinction. | 17,623 | <h4>Disease spread is <u>existential</u>---<u>best studies</u><strong> prove. </h4><p>Kim ’21 </strong>[Kiseong, Sunyong Yoo, Sangyeon Lee, Doheon Lee, and Kwang-Hyung Lee; March 26; Department of Bio and Brain Engineering, KAIST; Research and Development Center at BioBrain Inc.; Department of ICT Convergence System Engineering, Chonnam National University; Bio-Synergy Research Center; Moon Soul Graduate School of Future Strategy; Applied Sciences, “Network Analysis to Identify the Risk of Epidemic Spreading,” vol. 11]</p><p>Several <u><strong><mark>epidemics</strong></mark>, such as</u> the <u>Black Death and</u> the <u>Spanish flu</u>, have <u><mark>threaten</mark>ed <strong><mark>human life</strong></mark> throughout <strong>history</u></strong>; however, it is unclear if humans will remain safe from <u><mark>the <strong>sudden</strong></mark> and <strong>fast <mark>spread</strong> of</mark> epidemic <mark>diseases</u></mark>. Moreover, the transmission characteristics of epidemics <u><mark>remain undiscovered</u></mark>. In this study, <u>we present</u> the results of <u><mark>a</u></mark>n <u>epidemic <strong><mark>simulation</mark> experiment</strong> <mark>reveal</mark>ing <mark>the</mark> relationship between <strong>epidemic</strong> parameter<strong>s</strong> and <strong>pandemic <mark>risk</u></strong></mark>. To analyze the time-dependent risk and impact of epidemics, we considered two parameters for infectious diseases: the recovery time from infection and the transmission rate of the disease. Based on the epidemic simulation, we identified two important aspects of human safety with regard to the threat of a pandemic. First, humans should be safe if the fatality rate is below 100%. Second, even when the fatality rate is 100%, humans would be safe if the average degree of human social networks is below a threshold value. Nevertheless, <u>certain <mark>diseases</mark> can</u> potentially <u><mark>infect <strong>all nodes</strong></mark> in the human social networks</u>, and these diseases cause a pandemic when the average degree is larger than the threshold value. <u><mark>These</u></mark> results indicated that certain <u>infectious diseases <mark>lead to</mark> <strong>human <mark>extinction</u></strong></mark> and can be prevented by minimizing human contact.</p><p>1. Introduction</p><p><u>The <mark>emergence</mark> of a <strong>pandemic</strong> <mark>is</u></mark> one of the various scenarios <u><strong><mark>frequently</strong></mark> discussed as <mark>a</mark> <strong>human <mark>extinction event</strong>, and</mark> it is listed as one of the <strong><mark>global</mark> catastrophic <mark>risk</strong></mark>s in studies</u> regarding the future [1,2,3]. In particular, <u>several pandemics, such as the <strong><mark>Black Death</u></strong></mark> [4,5], <u>Spanish flu</u> [6], and those caused by <u><strong><mark>smallpox</u></strong></mark> [7], severe acute respiratory syndrome (<u><strong>SARS</u></strong>) [8], <u><mark>and <strong>Ebola</u></strong></mark> [9], have <u><mark>affected a <strong>large population</strong></mark> throughout <strong>history</strong>. The <mark>risk</mark> of pandemics <strong><mark>increases</strong> with</u></mark> an increase in <u>population <strong><mark>mobility</strong></mark> </u>between cities, nations, and continents, thereby <u>threatening humankind</u> [10,11,12]. It is essential to analyze the epidemic spread in society to minimize the damage from epidemic disasters; however, extinctive epidemic spreading experiments have limitations in real-world situations, as they predict stochastic effects on the spread without considering the structure of human society. Network-based approaches have been proposed to overcome these limitations and perform epidemic spreading simulations by considering the network structure of numerous real-world connections [13,14,15]. These methods use various models of epidemic spreading, such as the susceptible–infectious–susceptible (SIS) [16,17,18], susceptible–infectious–recovered (SIR) [19,20,21], and Watts threshold models [22]. While these methods are mathematically convenient, they are epidemiologically unrealistic for various infections because they require exponentially distributed incubation and infectious periods [23,24,25]. Moreover, previous epidemic studies did not perform quantitative assessment of the pandemic risk depending on the network connectivity in individuals and fatality rate of various diseases [26].</p><p>In the present study, we applied an SIR epidemic model to a scale-free network with Monte Carlo simulation to identify the quantitative relationship between infectious diseases and human existence. Our fundamental hypothesis states that <u>when the epidemic spreads to <strong>all nodes</u></strong> of the network and <u>the fatality rate is <strong>100%</u></strong>, it can increase the pandemic risk. To address this, we initially constructed a scale-free network to simulate a society. Moreover, for the epidemic spreading simulation, an SIR model was applied to the network to describe the immune state of an individual after infection. From the simulation study, we found that the mean degree of a scale-free network was an essential factor in determining whether epidemics threaten humans. This approach provides important insights into epidemic spreading analysis by investigating the relationship between epidemic and scale-free network parameters. Furthermore, it highlights the necessity of determining information flow during an epidemic.</p><p>2. Materials and Methods</p><p><u>We designed an epidemic <strong>simulation process</u></strong> to identify the relationship between pandemic risk and network parameters. This study was performed in four steps (Figure 1): (i) generating a scale-free network model to reflect real-world conditions; (ii) applying an SIR model to the scale-free network for epidemic spreading simulations; (iii) adapting the Monte Carlo method to reflect the stochastic process in the node status of the SIR model; and (iv) iteratively performing simulation for every parameter set and analyzing the results. We have provided the source code and sample results of epidemic simulation in Supplementary Materials.</p><p>Figure 1. Overview of epidemic simulation process based on the Monte Carlo method. (A) We generated scale-free networks for a fixed population (N = 1,000,000) and various node degrees (k = 2, 5, 7, and 10). (B) Epidemic spreading was simulated by applying a susceptible–infectious–recovered (SIR) model to the scale-free network. We set the epidemic parameters, β and γd. β represents the spreading rate of epidemics, and γd is the reciprocal of γ and reflects the time interval between infection and recovery. Randomly, 0.05% of nodes were initially infected. (C) <u>We adapted the <strong>Monte Carlo method</u></strong> <u>to determine the status of the transition</u> from the infection node to immunization node. Repeated simulations were performed until a steady state was achieved. (D) For every parameter set, 10,000 simulations were performed.</p><p>2.1. Network Generation Based on a Scale-Free Model</p><p>We constructed a network model for the epidemic spreading simulation (Figure 1). The nodes and edges of the network represent people in the society and their physical contacts, respectively. We used a scale-free network model, which follows the preferential attachment property observed in numerous real-world networks, such as social networks, physical systems, and economic networks [27,28,29]. In the scale-free network, when a node is added to the network, its likelihood of connecting to existing nodes increases with an increase in the node’s degree. Hub nodes, which lead to fast and vast spreading of epidemics, exist. Two characteristic parameters, including N and k, affect the form of scale-free networks. The parameter N denotes all nodes in the network. In the real world, N indicates the whole population size. The parameter k is the average degree of the network, which determines the degree of the newly attached node for each step during network generation. Following the characteristics of the network model, we generated scale-free networks representing human contacts for epidemic spread. The scale-free network was generated by the Barabasi–Albert graph distribution, in which the network is constructed from a cycle graph with three vertices, followed by the addition of k edges at each construction step [30]. The k edges are randomly attached to the vertex based on the degree distribution of the vertex. After network generation, we investigated the degree distribution properties of the network (Figure 2). The results indicate that the degree distributions have similar tendency for networks with varying number of nodes and edges. This study constructed scale-free networks with the largest number of nodes considering computational complexity (N = 1,000,000).</p><p><<FIGURE 1 OMITTED>></p><p>Figure 2. Degree distribution of the scale-free network. We analyzed the degree distribution of the network based on the number of nodes (N) and mean degree (k).</p><p>2.2. Epidemic Spreading Based on the SIR Model</p><p>For the epidemic spreading simulations, we applied an SIR model to the generated scale-free network. The classical SIR model can be expressed by the following nonlinear differential equations [21]:</p><p><<EQUATIONS OMITTED>></p><p>where S, I, and R represent susceptible, infected, and recovered compartments, respectively, in the whole population. S represents people who have not been infected yet but can be infected in future. I represents infected people who can spread the epidemic to susceptible people through physical contact. R denotes people who have recovered or died from the epidemic and who no longer participate in the epidemic spreading process. The sum of the S, I, and R values represents the whole population size N. Epidemics have two parameters in the SIR model, transmission rate (β) and recovery rate (γ), which arise from the basic reproduction number R0 (Figure 1B). The basic reproduction number is the number of infections caused by one infective node [31,32,33]. If the R0 is more than 1, the infection can spread in a population, whereas if R0 is less than 1, the infection cannot spread. We express the basic reproduction number as R0 = β/γ, where β represents the spreading rate of epidemics between infective nodes and adjacent susceptible nodes and γ represents the probability of recovery from infection [34]. We mainly used γd, which is the reciprocal of γ and reflects the time interval between infection and recovery.</p><p>2.3. Investigation of Epidemic Status Based on the Monte Carlo Method</p><p>The epidemic simulation was performed for a time series event by constructing epidemic status matrix (z) to represent the status of the nth node at time step t. For each node, the value of epidemic status matrix at time step t can be 0, 1, or 2, indicating that a node is susceptible, infective, or recovered, respectively. We initially (t = 0) set every value of epidemic status matrix to 0 because all nodes are susceptible before the epidemic spreads. At the initial infection stage, randomly selected 0.05% of nodes were infected. At every time period, we performed immunization and observed the infection stages (Figure 3).</p><p><<FIGURE 3 OMITTED>></p><p>At the immunization stage, we identified infective nodes and determined whether these nodes would be recovered in the next time step. To calculate the transition probability of infected and recovered phenomena, the Monte Carlo method was applied [35,36]. When infection and recovery parameters are provided, it is possible to investigate whether a node transitions from an epidemic state to another state. To accomplish this, we compared the method revealing the change in each population in every compartment over time (Figure 4).</p><p><<FIGURE 4 OMITTED>></p><p>The final steady state of the epidemic spreading simulation model indicates the total number of casualties of the epidemic who either are dead or have recovered from the disease. Infective nodes at time t (zn [t] = 1) are transformed to recovered nodes at time t + 1 (zn [t + 1] = 2) when 1/γd is larger than a random real number between 0 and 1. We determined whether the neighbor nodes of the infection node would be infected by identifying susceptible nodes adjacent to the infective nodes at time t (zn [t] = 0, with the adjacent infective node) (Figure 5). When β is larger than a random real number between 0 and 1, a susceptible node becomes an infective node at time t + 1 (zn [t + 1] = 1); this scenario represents epidemic spread. For each time step, we recorded the number of susceptible, infective, and recovered nodes during epidemic spread.</p><p><<FIGURE 5 OMITTED>></p><p>2.4. Simulation Parameters</p><p>We carried out simulation trials for various mean degrees of networks (k = 2, 5, 7, and 10). Each network considered the following epidemic parameters: β ranges from 0.05 to 0.95 and γd ranges from 1 to 10. The Monte Carlo model was repeatedly simulated to observe saturation of the recovery process. Considering that the simulation pipeline contains random processes such as initial infection and Monte Carlo trials, we performed the simulation iteratively until the status of nodes remained unchanged. After simulation, time series data from every simulation were interpolated in the time domain.</p><p>The fatality rate determines the ratio of deceased and recovered individuals in the final population [37,38,39]. If the fatality rate is below 100%, the recovered population contains both dead and recovered individuals. Such a situation does not always cause a pandemic. In this simulation, we assumed a 100% fatality rate. To accomplish this, we enumerated the recovered nodes as dead for considering the pandemic risk.</p><p>3. Results</p><p>Through our method, we obtained epidemic spreading data with various network and epidemic parameter sets. In the present study, we focused on the case where the epidemic infects all nodes and defined this phenomenon as “extinctive spread”. <u>Diseases causing <mark>extinctive spread</mark> are potential candidates of <strong>high pandemic risk</u></strong>. In the real world, <u>extinctive spreading indicates</u> that the <u>disease <mark>will <strong>infect every person</mark> in the society</u></strong>. From the simulation data, we calculated the extinctive spread score by dividing the total number of simulation trials by the number of extinctive spread cases. Thereafter, we identified that the number of extinctive spread cases is mainly influenced by spreading speed, which is determined by β, γd, and k (Figure 6).</p><p><<FIGURE 6 OMITTED>></p><p>The extinctive spread region (brown area in Figure 6) is expanded as the value of mean degree of network (k) is increased, thereby indicating that the area of extinctive spread becomes noticeably wider in a dense network than in a sparse network. Thus, the more contact between people, the higher the risk of epidemics. Moreover, high γd and high β cause extinctive spread across a large region, indicating that the high spreading rate and short time interval between infection and recovery are risk factors of epidemic diseases. In contrast, the infective nodes recover before they transmit the disease to their neighbors in low β and low γd scenarios, thus disconnecting the network and preventing extinctive spread. This occurs because the infective nodes need more time to transmit the disease in low β and high γd scenarios. Therefore, the disease begins to subside due to a lack of new infective nodes.</p><p>Furthermore, we investigated the range of β and γd for existing epidemics of the common cold [40,41] and fatal diseases, namely, cholera [42,43], Marburg [44,45], Ebola (Congo and Uganda) [46,47,48,49], SARS [50], and MERS [51] (Table 1). We selected diseases with relatively well-known epidemic parameters, such as average duration of infection and basic number of reproductions from previous studies. Transmission rates were calculated using the mean duration of infectious periods and basic reproduction numbers of the epidemics. Different studies reveal multiple values of infectious period and transmission rate for some of these diseases; we considered these values separately [40,41,42,43,46,47,48,49]. For example, the infectious period of a common cold is from 3 to 7 days and that of Ebola is 6.5 days. Next, we placed the possible regions of these epidemics as a disease band for various k values (colored lines in Figure 6). When k > 5, fatal diseases have an opportunity to cause a pandemic. Even when k = 5, diseases such as cholera and Ebola (Congo) can be threatening in regions of low γd and high, thus demonstrating that the knowledge of network parameters of the society and the characteristics of epidemic diseases can aid in quantifying the risk of epidemics.</p><p><<TABLE 1 OMITTED>></p><p>4. Discussion</p><p><u>Many <strong><mark>previous</strong> studies</mark> have made <strong>stochastic</strong> SIR models to analyze the dynamics or stability of epidemic diseases</u>. They investigated the distribution of susceptible, infected, and removed populations for specific epidemic disease spreading, such as cholera, SARS, Marburg, and MERS, based on mathematical modelling [52,53,54,55]. <u>However, they <mark>did not conduct</mark> a</u> <u><strong><mark>quantitative</u></strong> <u>assessment</mark> of pandemic risk taking into account</u> <u><strong>physical contact between people</u></strong>. To solve this limitation, we performed epidemic spreading simulations by applying an SIR model to scale-free networks with Monte Carlo simulation. In the simulation, <u><mark>we consider <strong>various</strong></mark> connectivity and <strong><mark>disease</strong> characteristics</u></mark> on scale-free networks. For each network and epidemic parameter set, the probability of extinctive spread was calculated. <u>The <mark>results <strong>reveal</strong></mark>ed that certain <strong>infectious diseases</strong> can lead to <strong>extinction</u></strong>. Moreover, even if the disease band extends over the extinctive spread regions, it does not indicate that human extinction results from the disease, as the fatality rate is below 100%; however, in the case of 100% fatality, the disease can cause a human extinction event. The risk of infectious disease is influenced by the network structure. A dense network has a higher risk of spreading infectious disease than a sparse network, as we observed in the extinctive spreading maps. According to our results, when the average degree of human social networks is below the risk threshold, i.e., less than 4 in this study, human society is safe from an extinctive outbreak based on our knowledge regarding the epidemic parameters of the infectious disease. Nevertheless, in other cases, <u><strong>human <mark>extinction</strong></mark> is possible</u>. For example, if the population is 1,000,000 and there are 4 or more instances of physical contact between people, human extinction events may occur, depending on the fatality rate of the epidemics. Hence, physical contact between people is closely related to an extinction event of infectious diseases. Eventually, from a public health perspective, lowering the average contact level of society is an appropriate way to increase the robustness of strategies against the occurrence of extinction. In the real world, reducing network density can be accomplished by epidemic prevention activity, such as isolation and quarantine treatment. This action prevents epidemic risk to the society, thereby avoiding human extinction.</p> | 1AC---Octas---Georgetown | Patent Law---1AC | null | 19,827 | 1,049 | 146,729 | ./documents/ndtceda22/Michigan/PiPh/Michigan-PiPh-Aff-Georgetown-Octas.docx | 960,453 | A | Georgetown | Octas | Kentucky GK | Brian Klarman, Johnnie Stupek, Nathan Rice | 1AC
Inventorship
2NR
First Amendment DA | ndtceda22/Michigan/PiPh/Michigan-PiPh-Aff-Georgetown-Octas.docx | 2023-01-07 19:03:17 | 81,260 | PiPh | Michigan PiPh | null | Ra..... | Pi..... | Ke..... | Ph..... | 26,992 | Michigan | Michigan | null | null | 2,001 | ndtceda22 | NDT/CEDA College 2022-23 | 2,022 | cx | college | 2 |
686,410 | Food prices don’t cause conflict---reject their bad studies. | Demarest 15 , Vol. 27, No. 5, p. 650-671, Emory Libraries] | Demarest 15—PhD Researcher at the Centre for Research on Peace and Development [Leila, “Food price rises and political instability: Problematizing a complex relationship,” The European Journal of Development Research, Vol. 27, No. 5, p. 650-671, Emory Libraries] | 6. Conclusions and Way Forward
important gaps remain conflict and political instability are used interchangeably The ‘food riot’ concept leads to confusion many peaceful events are gathered under this term, while violence is committed by the state rather than by hungry consumers The term presupposes that food is the central issue at hand, which does not have to be the case Many misunderstanding arise from the uncritical data gathering based on international news reports Not only are these remarkably inconsistent, they make use of classifications which are not scientifically investigated causal mechanisms in the relationship between rising food prices and conflict lack empirical foundation
The causal role of economic factors alone has continuously been questioned, and ‘context’ or prevailing political, economic, and social factors play a crucial role in the conflict outcome adverse economic shocks seem more of a trigger to conflict Yet while many authors acknowledge this, the focus often remains on the trigger In the end, most admit that these factors do not automatically lead to conflict everywhere, and stress the importance of context
Contextual data are currently collected at the aggregate, national level, and only on a yearly basis, which can lead to spurious relations we doubt their strength in the study of highly localized, one-time events such as riots | The ‘food riot’ concept leads to confusion peaceful events are gathered under this term Many misunderstanding arise from uncritical data gathering Not only are these remarkably inconsistent, they use classifications which are not scientifically investigated causal mechanisms between food prices and conflict lack empirical foundation
most admit that these factors do not lead to conflict
Contextual data lead to spurious relations we doubt their strength in the study one-time events such as riots | 6. Conclusions and Way Forward
While some progress has been made in improving our understanding of the linkages between rising food prices and conflict, several important gaps remain. Firstly, notions of conflict and political instability are often used interchangeably, while these concepts and the relationships between them remain to some extent vague. The ‘food riot’ concept in particular leads to confusion. Although it is popularly seen as a violent rise of the masses, in reality, many peaceful events are gathered under this term, while violence is often committed by the state rather than by hungry consumers. The term also presupposes that food is the central issue at hand, which does not necessarily have to be the case. Many misunderstanding arise from the second gap identified in this paper: the uncritical data gathering based on international news reports. Not only are these remarkably inconsistent, they also make use of classifications which are not scientifically investigated. Finally, causal mechanisms in the relationship between rising food prices and conflict often remain assumptions in the literature and lack empirical foundation. Three crosscutting avenues for improvement therefore exist: better concept definitions, better data gathering, and more focus on contexts.
Clearly defined concepts and categorizations of conflict and instability are a necessary foundation for research on the linkages between rising food prices and conflict. For (food) protests in particular, purposeful categorizations require an enhanced insight in the events that took place on the ground. Local news sources for data gathering can prove to be more reliable than Western (English) media to accomplish this. Event descriptions are also likely to be more detailed in local sources, which allows for a first-hand qualitative analysis of causes and context.
As international food prices are likely to remain high, improving our understanding of the causal mechanisms which can lead to conflict remains crucial. We can draw important lessons from the literature on poverty and conflict, resource scarcity and conflict, and regime transition in Africa. The causal role of economic factors alone has continuously been questioned, and ‘context’ or prevailing political, economic, and social factors play a crucial role in the conflict outcome. The argument that adverse economic shocks seem more of a trigger to conflict rather than an important cause is not particularly remarkable in itself. Yet while many authors acknowledge this, the focus often remains on the trigger. Resource scarcity, climate change, population growth, or food insecurity often remain the starting point of analyses, with researchers consequently tracing the divergent (theoretical) possibilities for conflict. In the end, most admit that these factors do not automatically lead to conflict everywhere, and stress the importance of context. Because the theoretical possibilities for conflict are so large, however, the context factor remains rather understudied with as most agreed upon notions that elements of ‘grievance’ and ‘collective action’ are required.
It is hence important to focus more on the ‘contexts’ that can lead to conflict and, in doing so, to make the distinction between different forms of conflict. This also implies a data collection exercise. Contextual data are currently collected at the aggregate, national level, and only on a yearly basis, which can lead to spurious relations. While the use of these variables is increasingly questioned in civil war studies, we can also doubt their strength in the study of highly localized, one-time events such as riots. I particularly make the case for ‘bringing politics back in’. The policies taken by the government are crucial in the violent escalation of social conflict (e.g. accommodation versus repression), but the only variable currently in use to explain state behaviour seems to be the country-level regime type variable (Polity IV or Freedom House), which is also used with regards to highly localized conflicts. Other ways in which politics matter, can be the strength of the political opposition. The Muslim Brotherhood in Egypt, for example, was probably better organized than other opposition groups to make use of economic unrest. | 4,298 | <h4>Food prices don’t cause conflict---reject their bad studies. </h4><p><strong>Demarest 15</strong>—PhD Researcher at the Centre for Research on Peace and Development [Leila, “Food price rises and political instability: Problematizing a complex relationship,” The European Journal of Development Research<u><strong>, Vol. 27, No. 5, p. 650-671, Emory Libraries] </p><p>6. Conclusions and Way Forward</p><p></u></strong>While some progress has been made in improving our understanding of the linkages between rising food prices and conflict, several <u><strong>important gaps remain</u></strong>. Firstly, notions of <u><strong>conflict and political instability are</u></strong> often <u><strong>used interchangeably</u></strong>, while these concepts and the relationships between them remain to some extent vague. <u><strong><mark>The ‘food riot’ concept</u></strong></mark> in particular <u><strong><mark>leads to confusion</u></strong></mark>. Although it is popularly seen as a violent rise of the masses, in reality, <u><strong>many <mark>peaceful events are gathered under this term</mark>, while violence is</u></strong> often <u><strong>committed by the state rather than by hungry consumers</u></strong>. <u><strong>The term</u></strong> also <u><strong>presupposes that food is the central issue at hand, which does not</u></strong> necessarily <u><strong>have to be the case</u></strong>. <u><strong><mark>Many misunderstanding arise from</mark> the</u></strong> second gap identified in this paper: the <u><strong><mark>uncritical data gathering</mark> based on international news reports</u></strong>. <u><strong><mark>Not only are these remarkably inconsistent, they</u></strong></mark> also <u><strong>make <mark>use</mark> of <mark>classifications which are not scientifically investigated</u></strong></mark>. Finally, <u><strong><mark>causal mechanisms</mark> in the relationship <mark>between</mark> rising <mark>food prices and conflict</u></strong></mark> often remain assumptions in the literature and <u><strong><mark>lack empirical foundation</u></strong></mark>. Three crosscutting avenues for improvement therefore exist: better concept definitions, better data gathering, and more focus on contexts.</p><p>Clearly defined concepts and categorizations of conflict and instability are a necessary foundation for research on the linkages between rising food prices and conflict. For (food) protests in particular, purposeful categorizations require an enhanced insight in the events that took place on the ground. Local news sources for data gathering can prove to be more reliable than Western (English) media to accomplish this. Event descriptions are also likely to be more detailed in local sources, which allows for a first-hand qualitative analysis of causes and context.</p><p>As international food prices are likely to remain high, improving our understanding of the causal mechanisms which can lead to conflict remains crucial. We can draw important lessons from the literature on poverty and conflict, resource scarcity and conflict, and regime transition in Africa. <u><strong>The causal role of economic factors alone has continuously been questioned, and ‘context’ or prevailing political, economic, and social factors play a crucial role in the conflict outcome</u></strong>. The argument that <u><strong>adverse economic shocks seem more of a trigger to conflict</u></strong> rather than an important cause is not particularly remarkable in itself. <u><strong>Yet while many authors acknowledge this, the focus often remains on the trigger</u></strong>. Resource scarcity, climate change, population growth, or food insecurity often remain the starting point of analyses, with researchers consequently tracing the divergent (theoretical) possibilities for conflict. <u><strong>In the end, <mark>most admit that these factors do not</mark> automatically <mark>lead to conflict</mark> everywhere, and stress the importance of context</u></strong>. Because the theoretical possibilities for conflict are so large, however, the context factor remains rather understudied with as most agreed upon notions that elements of ‘grievance’ and ‘collective action’ are required.</p><p>It is hence important to focus more on the ‘contexts’ that can lead to conflict and, in doing so, to make the distinction between different forms of conflict. This also implies a data collection exercise. <u><strong><mark>Contextual data</mark> are currently collected at the aggregate, national level, and only on a yearly basis, which can <mark>lead to spurious relations</u></strong></mark>. While the use of these variables is increasingly questioned in civil war studies, <u><strong><mark>we</u></strong></mark> can also <u><strong><mark>doubt their strength in the study</mark> of highly localized, <mark>one-time events such as riots</u></strong></mark>. I particularly make the case for ‘bringing politics back in’. The policies taken by the government are crucial in the violent escalation of social conflict (e.g. accommodation versus repression), but the only variable currently in use to explain state behaviour seems to be the country-level regime type variable (Polity IV or Freedom House), which is also used with regards to highly localized conflicts. Other ways in which politics matter, can be the strength of the political opposition. The Muslim Brotherhood in Egypt, for example, was probably better organized than other opposition groups to make use of economic unrest.</p> | null | 1NC | Case – Sustainablity Adv | 13,000 | 222 | 14,417 | ./documents/ndtceda16/Emory/MaMo/Emory-Marcus-Morbeck-Neg-D6-Round4.docx | 587,857 | N | D6 | 4 | Georgia AR | Joe Keeton | 1AC - FITs - Sustainability and Grid
1NC - Trump Bad DA LNG DA Econ DA Biomass PIC States CP Restrictions PIC
2NR - Trump Bad DA | ndtceda16/Emory/MaMo/Emory-Marcus-Morbeck-Neg-D6-Round4.docx | null | 50,213 | MaMo | Emory MaMo | null | Er..... | Ma..... | Ga..... | Mo..... | 19,021 | Emory | Emory | null | null | 1,006 | ndtceda16 | NDT/CEDA 2016-17 | 2,016 | cx | college | 2 |
2,663,078 | No great power involvement in Middle East war---every external actor will limit damage from regional instability rather than get involved | Stepanova 16 | Ekaterina Stepanova 16, researcher at the Institute of World Economy and International Relations, Summer 2016, “Russia in the Middle East: Back to a “Grand Strategy” – or Enforcing Multilateralism?,” http://www.cairn-int.info/article-E_PE_162_0023--russia-in-the-middle-east.htm | In contrast to the early years of the 21st century, the regional crisis in the 2010s developed when the role and leverage of major powers external to the Middle East, as active meddlers or security guarantors declined rather than increased. The U S serves as the most evident case in point The same even more strongly applies to the European powers regional actors appeared to outplay external powers and influence
the main response by key external powers to turbulent developments in the Middle East boils down to limited containment Despite the growing centrality of the Middle East to global politics and security this damage limitation course taken by key external actors has not been very different from the approach taken by the U S Russia and China) to Afghanistan | In contrast to the early 21st century, the crisis in the 2010s developed when the role and leverage of major powers external to the Middle East, as meddlers or security guarantors declined
the main response boils down to limited containment Despite the centrality of the Middle East to global politics this damage limitation course has not been different from the approach by the U S Russia and China to Afghanistan | In contrast to the 20th century and the early years of the 21st century, the regional crisis in the 2010s developed at a time when, overall, the role and leverage of major powers external to the Middle East, as either active meddlers or security guarantors in the region, or both, actually declined rather than increased. The United States serves as the most evident case in point: the “post-interventionist” US administration has clearly become “tired of the Middle East”, struggling and often failing to keep pace with the dynamically changing situation and unable to alter or decisively affect the course of events. The same even more strongly applies to the European powers. In terms of activity and impact, regional actors (Iran, Saudi Arabia, Qatar, UAE and Turkey) increasingly appeared to outplay external powers and influence.
For external powers, however, that did not remove a number of risks and threats connected to, or emanating from, the Middle East. The increase and diversification of global energy supply and the latest crisis in energy prices made the region less central to the global economy than it had been in the past. At the same time, the fundamental socio-political, statehood and security crisis in the Middle East brought with it new security concerns and implications. They mostly stemmed from reinforced perceptions about the long-term nature of regional instability, the continuing potential for further destabilization, and the related consequences and implications beyond the region, ranging from terrorist connections to migration flows. These challenges affect external powers unevenly. For instance, the role of the Iraq-Syria area as the main focal point for global terrorism activity and magnet for transnational flows of violent extremists in the mid-2010s poses a threat to everyone (but mostly to the countries of the region itself, as well as to those in Europe and Eurasia). In contrast, the avalanche of refugee and migrant flows from the Middle East primarily targets Europe (rather than North America, Eurasia, or other regions).
Until recently, the main type of response by key (Western) external powers to turbulent developments in the Middle East, while not amounting to a hands-off approach, boils down to limited containment. Examples range from limited air strikes against “Islamic State” positions in Iraq and Syria, carried out by the US-led coalition since 2014, to the 2013 deal on Syria’s chemical disarmament co-brokered by the United States and Russia. Not surprisingly, this limited-containment approach has had equally limited results for Syria, Iraq and the region – as well as for the West itself (as shown, e.g., by the persistent migrant flows and accelerating terrorist attacks in Europe). Despite the growing centrality of the Middle East to global politics and security, and its more direct impact on and ties to the West, this damage limitation course taken by key external actors has not been very different from, e.g., the approach taken by the United States and its Western allies (and also by Russia and China) to the Afghanistan problem in recent years. | 3,128 | <h4><u>No</u> great power involvement in Middle East war---<u>every</u> external actor will <u>limit damage</u> from regional instability <u>rather than</u> get involved </h4><p>Ekaterina <strong>Stepanova 16</strong>, researcher at the Institute of World Economy and International Relations, Summer 2016, “Russia in the Middle East: Back to a “Grand Strategy” – or Enforcing Multilateralism?,” http://www.cairn-int.info/article-E_PE_162_0023--russia-in-the-middle-east.htm</p><p><u><strong><mark>In contrast</strong> to</u></mark> the 20th century and <u><mark>the early</mark> years of the <mark>21st century, the</u></mark> <u>regional <mark>crisis in the 2010s</u> <u>developed</u></mark> at a time <u><mark>when</u></mark>, overall, <u><mark>the <strong>role and leverage of major powers</strong> external to the Middle East, as</u></mark> either <u>active <mark>meddlers or security guarantors</u></mark> in the region, or both, actually <u><strong><mark>declined</mark> rather than increased</strong>. The U</u>nited <u>S</u>tates <u>serves as the most evident case in point</u>: the “post-interventionist” US administration has clearly become “tired of the Middle East”, struggling and often failing to keep pace with the dynamically changing situation and unable to alter or decisively affect the course of events. <u>The same even more strongly applies to the European powers</u>. In terms of activity and impact, <u><strong>regional actors</u></strong> (Iran, Saudi Arabia, Qatar, UAE and Turkey) increasingly <u>appeared to outplay external powers and influence</u>.</p><p>For external powers, however, that did not remove a number of risks and threats connected to, or emanating from, the Middle East. The increase and diversification of global energy supply and the latest crisis in energy prices made the region less central to the global economy than it had been in the past. At the same time, the fundamental socio-political, statehood and security crisis in the Middle East brought with it new security concerns and implications. They mostly stemmed from reinforced perceptions about the long-term nature of regional instability, the continuing potential for further destabilization, and the related consequences and implications beyond the region, ranging from terrorist connections to migration flows. These challenges affect external powers unevenly. For instance, the role of the Iraq-Syria area as the main focal point for global terrorism activity and magnet for transnational flows of violent extremists in the mid-2010s poses a threat to everyone (but mostly to the countries of the region itself, as well as to those in Europe and Eurasia). In contrast, the avalanche of refugee and migrant flows from the Middle East primarily targets Europe (rather than North America, Eurasia, or other regions).</p><p>Until recently, <u><mark>the main</u></mark> type of <u><mark>response</mark> by key</u> (Western) <u>external powers to turbulent developments in the Middle East</u>, while not amounting to a hands-off approach, <u><mark>boils down to <strong>limited containment</u></strong></mark>. Examples range from limited air strikes against “Islamic State” positions in Iraq and Syria, carried out by the US-led coalition since 2014, to the 2013 deal on Syria’s chemical disarmament co-brokered by the United States and Russia. Not surprisingly, this limited-containment approach has had equally limited results for Syria, Iraq and the region – as well as for the West itself (as shown, e.g., by the persistent migrant flows and accelerating terrorist attacks in Europe). <u><mark>Despite the</mark> growing <mark>centrality of the Middle East to global politics</mark> and security</u>, and its more direct impact on and ties to the West, <u><mark>this <strong>damage limitation</strong> course</mark> taken by key external actors <mark>has not been</mark> very <mark>different from</u></mark>, e.g., <u><mark>the approach</mark> taken <mark>by the U</u></mark>nited <u><mark>S</u></mark>tates and its Western allies (and also by <u><mark>Russia and China</mark>) <mark>to</u></mark> the <u><mark>Afghanistan</u></mark> problem in recent years.</p> | 1 NR | null | ME WAR | 7,401 | 185 | 84,707 | ./documents/hspolicy19/Altamont/MaAn/Altamont-Maldia-Anders-Neg-Peach%20State%20Classic-Round5.docx | 706,218 | N | Peach State Classic | 5 | Henry W Grady Kamel Tak | Matt Cekanor | 1 AC- Saudi aff with Yemeni advantage
1 NC- T Pearson conditions cp alliance da heg da oil da
2 AC- disclosure theory
2 NR- conditions cp oil da | hspolicy19/Altamont/MaAn/Altamont-Maldia-Anders-Neg-Peach%20State%20Classic-Round5.docx | null | 60,088 | MaAn | Altamont MaAn | null | Is..... | Ma..... | Ar..... | An..... | 21,078 | Altamont | Altamont | AL | null | 1,018 | hspolicy19 | HS Policy 2019-20 | 2,019 | cx | hs | 2 |
3,554,416 | Destroying trade ensures nuclear war | Roubini 17 | Nouriel Roubini 17, professor at NYU’s Stern School of Business and Chairman of Roubini Macro Associates, was Senior Economist for International Affairs in the White House's Council of Economic Advisers during the Clinton Administration, 1/2/17, ““America First” and Global Conflict Next,” https://www.project-syndicate.org/commentary/trump-isolationism-undermines-peace-worldwide-by-nouriel-roubini-2017-01 | policies that hinder trade helped sow the seeds of World War II. Protectionism triggered retaliatory trade and currency wars that worsened the Great Depression American isolationism allowed Germany and Japan to threaten the entire world Today pursuit of strictly US national interests may lead to a global conflict As in the 1930s, when protectionist US policies hampered global economic growth and trade, and created conditions for rising powers to start a world war, similar policy impulses could set the stage for new powers to challenge and undermine the American-led international order An isolationist Trump administration may think Russia, China, and Iran pose no direct threat But the US is still a global economic and financial power in a deeply interconnected world left unchecked, these countries will threaten core US economic and security interests especially if they expand their nuclear capacities protectionism, isolationism, and “America first” policies are a recipe for economic and military disaster | policies that hinder trade helped sow seeds of World War II. Protectionism triggered retaliatory trade wars American isolationism allowed Germany and Japan to threaten the world Today pursuit of strictly US interests may lead to global conflict Russia, China, and Iran left unchecked will threaten core US economic and security interests especially if they expand nuclear capacities protectionism and “America first” policies are a economic and military disaster. | Trump, however, may pursue populist, anti-globalization, and protectionist policies that hinder trade and restrict the movement of labor and capital. And he has cast doubt on existing US security guarantees by suggesting that he will force America’s allies to pay for more of their own defense. If Trump is serious about putting “America first,” his administration will shift US geopolitical strategy toward isolationism and unilateralism, pursuing only the national interests of the homeland. When the US pursued similar policies in the 1920s and 1930s, it helped sow the seeds of World War II. Protectionism – starting with the Smoot-Hawley Tariff, which affected thousands of imported goods – triggered retaliatory trade and currency wars that worsened the Great Depression. More important, American isolationism – based on a false belief that the US was safely protected by two oceans – allowed Nazi Germany and Imperial Japan to wage aggressive war and threaten the entire world. With the attack on Pearl Harbor in December 1941, the US was finally forced to take its head out of the sand. Today, too, a US turn to isolationism and the pursuit of strictly US national interests may eventually lead to a global conflict. Even without the prospect of American disengagement from Europe, the European Union and the eurozone already appear to be disintegrating, particularly in the wake of the United Kingdom’s June Brexit vote and Italy’s failed referendum on constitutional reforms in December. Moreover, in 2017, extreme anti-Europe left- or right-wing populist parties could come to power in France and Italy, and possibly in other parts of Europe. Without active US engagement in Europe, an aggressively revanchist Russia will step in. Russia is already challenging the US and the EU in Ukraine, Syria, the Baltics, and the Balkans, and it may capitalize on the EU’s looming collapse by reasserting its influence in the former Soviet bloc countries, and supporting pro-Russia movements within Europe. If Europe gradually loses its US security umbrella, no one stands to benefit more than Russian President Vladimir Putin. Trump’s proposals also threaten to exacerbate the situation in the Middle East. He has said that he will make America energy independent, which entails abandoning US interests in the region and becoming more reliant on domestically produced greenhouse-gas-emitting fossil fuels. And he has maintained his position that Islam itself, rather than just radical militant Islam, is dangerous. This view, shared by Trump’s incoming National Security Adviser, General Michael Flynn, plays directly into Islamist militants’ own narrative of a clash of civilizations. Meanwhile, an “America first” approach under Trump will likely worsen the longstanding Sunni-Shia proxy wars between Saudi Arabia and Iran. And if the US no longer guarantees its Sunni allies’ security, all regional powers – including Iran, Saudi Arabia, Turkey, and Egypt – might decide that they can defend themselves only by acquiring nuclear weapons, and even more deadly conflict will ensue. In Asia, US economic and military primacy has provided decades of stability; but a rising China is now challenging the status quo. US President Barack Obama’s strategic “pivot” to Asia depended primarily on enacting the 12-country Trans-Pacific Partnership, which Trump has promised to scrap on his first day in office. Meanwhile, China is quickly strengthening its own economic ties in Asia, the Pacific, and Latin America through its “one belt, one road” policy, the Asian Infrastructure Investment Bank, the New Development Bank (formerly known as the BRICS bank), and its own regional free-trade proposal to rival the TPP. If the US gives up on its Asian allies such as the Philippines, South Korea, and Taiwan, those countries may have no choice but to prostrate themselves before China; and other US allies, such as Japan and India, may be forced to militarize and challenge China openly. Thus, an American withdrawal from the region could very well eventually precipitate a military conflict there. As in the 1930s, when protectionist and isolationist US policies hampered global economic growth and trade, and created the conditions for rising revisionist powers to start a world war, similar policy impulses could set the stage for new powers to challenge and undermine the American-led international order. An isolationist Trump administration may see the wide oceans to its east and west, and think that increasingly ambitious powers such as Russia, China, and Iran pose no direct threat to the homeland. But the US is still a global economic and financial power in a deeply interconnected world. If left unchecked, these countries will eventually be able to threaten core US economic and security interests – at home and abroad – especially if they expand their nuclear and cyberwarfare capacities. The historical record is clear: protectionism, isolationism, and “America first” policies are a recipe for economic and military disaster. | 5,033 | <h4>Destroying trade ensures nuclear war</h4><p>Nouriel <strong>Roubini 17</strong>, professor at NYU’s Stern School of Business and Chairman of Roubini Macro Associates, was Senior Economist for International Affairs in the White House's Council of Economic Advisers during the Clinton Administration, 1/2/17, ““America First” and Global Conflict Next,” https://www.project-syndicate.org/commentary/trump-isolationism-undermines-peace-worldwide-by-nouriel-roubini-2017-01</p><p>Trump, however, may pursue populist, anti-globalization, and protectionist <u><strong><mark>policies that hinder trade</u></strong></mark> and restrict the movement of labor and capital. And he has cast doubt on existing US security guarantees by suggesting that he will force America’s allies to pay for more of their own defense. If Trump is serious about putting “America first,” his administration will shift US geopolitical strategy toward isolationism and unilateralism, pursuing only the national interests of the homeland. When the US pursued similar policies in the 1920s and 1930s, it <u><strong><mark>helped sow</mark> the <mark>seeds of World War II. Protectionism</u></strong></mark> – starting with the Smoot-Hawley Tariff, which affected thousands of imported goods – <u><strong><mark>triggered retaliatory trade</mark> and currency <mark>wars</mark> that worsened the Great Depression</u></strong>. More important, <u><strong><mark>American isolationism</u></strong></mark> – based on a false belief that the US was safely protected by two oceans – <u><strong><mark>allowed</u></strong></mark> Nazi <u><strong><mark>Germany and</u></strong></mark> Imperial <u><strong><mark>Japan to</u></strong></mark> wage aggressive war and <u><strong><mark>threaten the</mark> entire <mark>world</u></strong></mark>. With the attack on Pearl Harbor in December 1941, the US was finally forced to take its head out of the sand. <u><strong><mark>Today</u></strong></mark>, too, a US turn to isolationism and the <u><strong><mark>pursuit of strictly US</mark> national <mark>interests may</u></strong></mark> eventually <u><strong><mark>lead to</mark> a <mark>global conflict</u></strong></mark>. Even without the prospect of American disengagement from Europe, the European Union and the eurozone already appear to be disintegrating, particularly in the wake of the United Kingdom’s June Brexit vote and Italy’s failed referendum on constitutional reforms in December. Moreover, in 2017, extreme anti-Europe left- or right-wing populist parties could come to power in France and Italy, and possibly in other parts of Europe. Without active US engagement in Europe, an aggressively revanchist Russia will step in. Russia is already challenging the US and the EU in Ukraine, Syria, the Baltics, and the Balkans, and it may capitalize on the EU’s looming collapse by reasserting its influence in the former Soviet bloc countries, and supporting pro-Russia movements within Europe. If Europe gradually loses its US security umbrella, no one stands to benefit more than Russian President Vladimir Putin. Trump’s proposals also threaten to exacerbate the situation in the Middle East. He has said that he will make America energy independent, which entails abandoning US interests in the region and becoming more reliant on domestically produced greenhouse-gas-emitting fossil fuels. And he has maintained his position that Islam itself, rather than just radical militant Islam, is dangerous. This view, shared by Trump’s incoming National Security Adviser, General Michael Flynn, plays directly into Islamist militants’ own narrative of a clash of civilizations. Meanwhile, an “America first” approach under Trump will likely worsen the longstanding Sunni-Shia proxy wars between Saudi Arabia and Iran. And if the US no longer guarantees its Sunni allies’ security, all regional powers – including Iran, Saudi Arabia, Turkey, and Egypt – might decide that they can defend themselves only by acquiring nuclear weapons, and even more deadly conflict will ensue. In Asia, US economic and military primacy has provided decades of stability; but a rising China is now challenging the status quo. US President Barack Obama’s strategic “pivot” to Asia depended primarily on enacting the 12-country Trans-Pacific Partnership, which Trump has promised to scrap on his first day in office. Meanwhile, China is quickly strengthening its own economic ties in Asia, the Pacific, and Latin America through its “one belt, one road” policy, the Asian Infrastructure Investment Bank, the New Development Bank (formerly known as the BRICS bank), and its own regional free-trade proposal to rival the TPP. If the US gives up on its Asian allies such as the Philippines, South Korea, and Taiwan, those countries may have no choice but to prostrate themselves before China; and other US allies, such as Japan and India, may be forced to militarize and challenge China openly. Thus, an American withdrawal from the region could very well eventually precipitate a military conflict there. <u><strong>As in the 1930s, when protectionist</u></strong> and isolationist <u><strong>US policies hampered global economic growth and trade, and created</u></strong> the <u><strong>conditions for rising</u></strong> revisionist <u><strong>powers to start a world war, similar policy impulses could set the stage for new powers to challenge and undermine the American-led international order</u></strong>. <u><strong>An isolationist Trump administration may</u></strong> see the wide oceans to its east and west, and <u><strong>think</u></strong> that increasingly ambitious powers such as <u><strong><mark>Russia, China, and Iran</mark> pose no direct threat</u></strong> to the homeland. <u><strong>But the US is still a global economic and financial power in a deeply interconnected world</u></strong>. If <u><strong><mark>left unchecked</mark>, these countries <mark>will</u></strong></mark> eventually be able to <u><strong><mark>threaten core US economic and security interests</u></strong></mark> – at home and abroad – <u><strong><mark>especially if they expand</mark> their <mark>nuclear</u></strong></mark> and cyberwarfare <u><strong><mark>capacities</u></strong></mark>. The historical record is clear: <u><strong><mark>protectionism</mark>, isolationism, <mark>and “America first” policies are a</mark> recipe for <mark>economic and military disaster</u></strong>.</p></mark> | 1nc | 4 | null | 32,871 | 378 | 117,892 | ./documents/ndtceda17/Wyoming/HeCu/Wyoming-Henman-Culver-Neg-Nwfallchamp-Semis.docx | 601,702 | N | Nwfallchamp | Semis | Minnesota Dharmadhikari-Le | Frappier, Guevara, Stevenson | 1ac - single payer - costs coverage and opiods
1nc - t-financing spec trade da states cp midterms da
2nc - states cp and case
1nr - midterms da
2nr - states and midterms | ndtceda17/Wyoming/HeCu/Wyoming-Henman-Culver-Neg-Nwfallchamp-Semis.docx | null | 51,180 | HeCu | Wyoming HeCu | null | Ca..... | He..... | Sp..... | Cu..... | 19,161 | Wyoming | Wyoming | null | null | 1,007 | ndtceda17 | NDT/CEDA 2017-18 | 2,017 | cx | college | 2 |
3,160,602 | Debate’s focus shouldn’t solely be the production of ethical subjectivities. Rather, taking stances on global issues is necessary to develop accountability to global violence | Chandler 9 | Chandler 9—Professor of international relations at the University of Westminster [David, “Questioning Global Political Activism,” in What is Radical Politics Today? Ed. Jonathan Pugh, p. 81-84] | more and more people are ‘doing politics’ in their academic work the attraction of IR for many people has not been IR theory but the desire to practise global ethics However this has been a product of an ethical act of rejection of Realism's ontological focus
It seems that our ideas and our theories say much more about us than the world we live in. Normative theorists and Constructivists tend to support the global ethical turn arguing that we should not be as concerned with 'what is' as with the potential for the emergence of a global ethical community. Constructivists focus upon the ethical language which elites espouse rather than the practices of power. But the most dangerous trends in the discipline today are those frameworks which have taken up Critical Theory and argue that focusing on the world as it exists is conservative problem-solving while the task for critical theorists is to focus on emancipatory alternative forms of living or of thinking about the world. Critical thought then becomes a process of wishful thinking rather than one of engagement, with its advocates arguing that we need to focus on clarifying our own ethical frameworks and positionality, before thinking about or teaching on world affairs. This becomes 'me-search' rather than research
theoretical preferences were based on what their choices said about them as ethical individuals, than about how theory might be used to understand and engage with the world
Politics has become a religious activity, an activity which is no longer socially mediated; it is less and less an activity based on social engagement and the testing of ideas Doing politics today, whether in radical activism, government policy-making or in academia, seems to bring people into a one-to-one relationship with global issues in the same way religious people have a one-to-one relationship with their God
Politics is increasingly like religion because when we look for meaning we find it inside ourselves rather than in the external consequences of our 'political' acts. What matters is the conviction The more we engage in the new politics where there is an unmediated relationship between us as individuals and global issues, the less we engage instrumentally with the outside world, and the less we engage with our peers at the level of debate
the solution is not purely an intellectual one; the demand for global ethics is generated by our social reality and social experiences it is more difficult to see an emerging political subject which can fulfil the task of 'changing the world' rather than merely 'reinterpreting it' through philosophy
there is a pressing need for an intellectual struggle against the idealism of global ethics our freedom to engage in politics, to choose our identities and political campaigns, as well as governments' freedom to choose their ethical campaigns and wars of choice, reflects a lack of social engagement. There is no global political struggle between 'Empire' and its 'Radical Discontents'; the temptation to see power and resistance everywhere is a product of wishful or lazy thinking The stakes are not in the global stratosphere but much closer to home. Politics appears to have gone global because there is a breakdown of genuine community and the construction of fantasy communities and fantasy connections in global space. Unless we bring politics back down to earth from heaven, our critical, social and intellectual lives will continue to be diminished ones
we should take more seriously injunction to subordinate ourselves to the 'discipline of the real'. Subordination to the world outside us is a powerful factor that can bind those interested in critical research, whereas the turn away from the world and the focus on our personal values can ultimately only be divisive. To facilitate external engagement and external judgement experiment with ways to build up social bonds with our peers that can limit our freedoms and develop our sense of responsibility and accountability to others. We may have to construct these social connections artificially but their value and instrumentality will have to be proven through our ability to engage with, understand, critique and overcome the practices of our time | dangerous trends which focus on emancipatory forms of living becomes a process of wishful thinking rather than engagement ethical frameworks before world affairs becomes 'me-search' rather than research
Politics is religion we look for meaning inside ourselves rather than external consequences of 'political' acts
the solution is not purely intellectual
to choose our identities reflects a lack of social engagement to see resistance everywhere is lazy thinking
focus on personal values can only be divisive external engagement can develop responsibility and accountability | Today more and more people are ‘doing politics’ in their academic work. This is the reason for the boom in International Relations (IR) study and the attraction of other social sciences to the global sphere. I would argue that the attraction of IR for many people has not been IR theory but the desire to practise global ethics. The boom in the IR discipline has coincided with a rejection of Realist theoretical frameworks of power and interests and the sovereignty/anarchy problematic. However, I would argue that this rejection has not been a product of theoretical engagement with Realism but an ethical act of rejection of Realism's ontological focus.
It seems that our ideas and our theories say much more about us than the world we live in. Normative theorists and Constructivists tend to support the global ethical turn arguing that we should not be as concerned with 'what is' as with the potential for the emergence of a global ethical community. Constructivists, in particular, focus upon the ethical language which political elites espouse rather than the practices of power. But the most dangerous trends in the discipline today are those frameworks which have taken up Critical Theory and argue that focusing on the world as it exists is conservative problem-solving while the task for critical theorists is to focus on emancipatory alternative forms of living or of thinking about the world. Critical thought then becomes a process of wishful thinking rather than one of engagement, with its advocates arguing that we need to focus on clarifying our own [END PAGE 81] ethical frameworks and biases and positionality, before thinking about or teaching on world affairs. This becomes 'me-search' rather than research. We have moved a long way from Hedley Bull's (1995) perspective that, for academic research to be truly radical, we had to put our values to the side to follow where the question or inquiry might lead.
The inward-looking and narcissistic trends in academia, where we are more concerned with our reflectivity- the awareness of our own ethics and values - than with engaging with the world, was brought home to me when I asked my IR students which theoretical frameworks they agreed with most. They mostly replied Critical Theory and Constructivism. This is despite the fact that the students thought that states operated on the basis of power and self-interest in a world of anarchy. Their theoretical preferences were based more on what their choices said about them as ethical individuals, than about how theory might be used to understand and engage with the world.
Conclusion
I have attempted to argue that there is a lot at stake in the radical understanding of engagement in global politics. Politics has become a religious activity, an activity which is no longer socially mediated; it is less and less an activity based on social engagement and the testing of ideas in public debate or in the academy. Doing politics today, whether in radical activism, government policy-making or in academia, seems to bring people into a one-to-one relationship with global issues in the same way religious people have a one-to-one relationship with their God.
Politics is increasingly like religion because when we look for meaning we find it inside ourselves rather than in the external consequences of our 'political' acts. What matters is the conviction or the act in itself: its connection to the global sphere is one that we increasingly tend to provide idealistically. Another way of expressing this limited sense of our subjectivity is in the popularity of globalisation theory - the idea that instrumentality is no longer possible today because the world is such a complex and interconnected place and therefore there is no way of knowing the consequences of our actions. The more we engage in the new politics where there is an unmediated relationship between us as individuals and global issues, the less we engage instrumentally with the outside world, and the less we engage with our peers and colleagues at the level of political or intellectual debate and organisation. [END PAGE 82]
You may be thinking that I have gone some way to describing or identifying what the problems might be but I have not mentioned anything about a solution. I won't dodge the issue. One thing that is clear is that the solution is not purely an intellectual or academic one; the demand for global ethics is generated by our social reality and social experiences. Marx spent some time considering a similar crisis of political subjectivity in 1840s Germany and in his writings - The German Ideology, Introduction to the Critique of Hegel's Philosophy of Right, Theses on Feuerbach, and elsewhere - he raged against the idealism of contemporary thought and argued that the criticism of religion needed to be replaced by the criticism of politics - by political activism and social change based on the emerging proletariat (see Marx, 1975, for example). Nearly two centuries later it is more difficult to see an emerging political subject which can fulfil the task of 'changing the world' rather than merely 'reinterpreting it' through philosophy.
I have two suggestions. Firstly, that there is a pressing need for an intellectual struggle against the idealism of global ethics. The point needs to be emphasised that our freedom to engage in politics, to choose our identities and political campaigns, as well as governments' freedom to choose their ethical campaigns and wars of choice, reflects a lack of socialties and social engagement. There is no global political struggle between 'Empire' and its 'Radical Discontents'; the Foucauldian temptation to see power and resistance everywhere is a product of wishful or lazy thinking dominated by the social categories of the past. The stakes are not in the global stratosphere but much closer to home. Politics appears to have gone global because there is a breakdown of genuine community and the construction of fantasy communities and fantasy connections in global space. Unless we bring politics back down to earth from heaven, our critical, social and intellectual lives will continue to be diminished ones.
Secondly, on the basis that the political freedom of our social atomisation leads us into increasingly idealised approaches to the world we live in, we should take more seriously Hedley Bull's (1995) injunction to pursue the question, or in Alain Badiou's (2004: 237-8) words subordinate ourselves to the 'discipline of the real'. Subordination to the world outside us is a powerful factor that can bind those interested in critical research, whereas the turn away from the world and the focus on our personal values can ultimately only be divisive. To facilitate external engagement and external judgement, I suggest we experiment with ways to build up social bonds with our peers that can limit our freedoms and develop our sense of responsibility and accountability to others. We may have to construct these social connections artificially but their [END PAGE 83] value and instrumentality will have to be proven through our ability to engage with, understand, critique and ultimately overcome the practices and subjectivities of our time. | 7,219 | <h4>Debate’s focus shouldn’t solely be the production of ethical subjectivities. Rather, taking <u>stances</u> on <u>global issues</u> is necessary to develop accountability to global violence</h4><p><strong>Chandler 9</strong>—Professor of international relations at the University of Westminster [David, “Questioning Global Political Activism,” in What is Radical Politics Today? Ed. Jonathan Pugh, p. 81-84]</p><p>Today <u>more and more people are ‘doing politics’ in their academic work</u>. This is the reason for the boom in International Relations (IR) study and the attraction of other social sciences to the global sphere. I would argue that <u>the attraction of IR for many people has not been IR theory but the desire to practise global ethics</u>. The boom in the IR discipline has coincided with a rejection of Realist theoretical frameworks of power and interests and the sovereignty/anarchy problematic. <u>However</u>, I would argue that <u>this</u> rejection <u>has</u> not <u>been a product of</u> theoretical engagement with Realism but <u>an ethical act of rejection of Realism's ontological focus</u>.</p><p><u>It seems that our ideas and our theories say much more about us than the world we live in. Normative theorists and Constructivists tend to support the global ethical turn arguing that we should not be as concerned with 'what is' as with the potential for the emergence of a global ethical community. Constructivists</u>, in particular, <u>focus upon the ethical language which</u> political <u>elites espouse rather than the practices of power. But the most <mark>dangerous trends</mark> in the discipline today are those frameworks <mark>which</mark> have taken up Critical Theory and argue that focusing on the world as it exists is conservative problem-solving while the task for critical theorists is to <mark>focus on emancipatory </mark>alternative <mark>forms of living</mark> or of thinking about the world. Critical thought then <mark>becomes a process of wishful thinking rather than</mark> one of <mark>engagement</mark>, with its advocates arguing that we need to focus on clarifying our own</u> [END PAGE 81] <u><mark>ethical frameworks</mark> and</u> biases and <u>positionality, <mark>before </mark>thinking about or teaching on <mark>world affairs</mark>. This <mark>becomes 'me-search' rather than research</u></mark>. We have moved a long way from Hedley Bull's (1995) perspective that, for academic research to be truly radical, we had to put our values to the side to follow where the question or inquiry might lead.</p><p>The inward-looking and narcissistic trends in academia, where we are more concerned with our reflectivity- the awareness of our own ethics and values - than with engaging with the world, was brought home to me when I asked my IR students which theoretical frameworks they agreed with most. They mostly replied Critical Theory and Constructivism. This is despite the fact that the students thought that states operated on the basis of power and self-interest in a world of anarchy. Their <u>theoretical preferences were based</u> more <u>on what their choices said about them as ethical individuals, than about how theory might be used to understand and engage with the world</u>.</p><p>Conclusion</p><p>I have attempted to argue that there is a lot at stake in the radical understanding of engagement in global politics. <u>Politics has become a religious activity, an activity which is no longer socially mediated; it is less and less an activity based on social engagement and the testing of ideas</u> in public debate or in the academy. <u>Doing politics today, whether in radical activism, government policy-making or in academia, seems to bring people into a one-to-one relationship with global issues in the same way religious people have a one-to-one relationship with their God</u>.</p><p><u><mark>Politics is </mark>increasingly like <mark>religion</mark> because when <mark>we look for meaning </mark>we find it <mark>inside ourselves rather than </mark>in the <mark>external consequences of </mark>our <mark>'political' acts</mark>. What matters is the conviction</u> or the act in itself: its connection to the global sphere is one that we increasingly tend to provide idealistically. Another way of expressing this limited sense of our subjectivity is in the popularity of globalisation theory - the idea that instrumentality is no longer possible today because the world is such a complex and interconnected place and therefore there is no way of knowing the consequences of our actions. <u>The more we engage in the new politics where there is an unmediated relationship between us as individuals and global issues, the less we engage instrumentally with the outside world, and the less we engage with our peers</u> and colleagues <u>at the level of</u> political or intellectual <u>debate</u> and organisation. [END PAGE 82]</p><p>You may be thinking that I have gone some way to describing or identifying what the problems might be but I have not mentioned anything about a solution. I won't dodge the issue. One thing that is clear is that <u><mark>the solution is not purely</mark> an <mark>intellectual</u></mark> or academic <u>one; the demand for global ethics is generated by our social reality and social experiences</u>. Marx spent some time considering a similar crisis of political subjectivity in 1840s Germany and in his writings - The German Ideology, Introduction to the Critique of Hegel's Philosophy of Right, Theses on Feuerbach, and elsewhere - he raged against the idealism of contemporary thought and argued that the criticism of religion needed to be replaced by the criticism of politics - by political activism and social change based on the emerging proletariat (see Marx, 1975, for example). Nearly two centuries later <u>it is more difficult to see an emerging political subject which can fulfil the task of 'changing the world' rather than merely 'reinterpreting it' through philosophy</u>.</p><p>I have two suggestions. Firstly, that <u>there is a pressing need for an intellectual struggle against the idealism of global ethics</u>. The point needs to be emphasised that <u>our freedom to engage in politics, <mark>to choose our identities </mark>and political campaigns, as well as governments' freedom to choose their ethical campaigns and wars of choice, <mark>reflects a lack of</u></mark> socialties and <u><mark>social engagement</mark>. There is no global political struggle between 'Empire' and its 'Radical Discontents'; the</u> Foucauldian <u>temptation <mark>to see </mark>power and <mark>resistance everywhere is</mark> a product of wishful or <mark>lazy thinking</u></mark> dominated by the social categories of the past. <u>The stakes are not in the global stratosphere but much closer to home. Politics appears to have gone global because there is a breakdown of genuine community and the construction of fantasy communities and fantasy connections in global space. Unless we bring politics back down to earth from heaven, our critical, social and intellectual lives will continue to be diminished ones</u>.</p><p>Secondly, on the basis that the political freedom of our social atomisation leads us into increasingly idealised approaches to the world we live in, <u>we should take more seriously</u> Hedley Bull's (1995) <u>injunction to</u> pursue the question, or in Alain Badiou's (2004: 237-8) words <u>subordinate ourselves to the 'discipline of the real'. Subordination to the world outside us is a powerful factor that can bind those interested in critical research, whereas the turn away from the world and the <mark>focus on</mark> our <mark>personal values can</mark> ultimately <mark>only be divisive</mark>. To facilitate <mark>external engagement</mark> and external judgement</u>, I suggest we <u>experiment with ways to build up social bonds with our peers that <mark>can</mark> limit our freedoms and <mark>develop </mark>our sense of <mark>responsibility and accountability</mark> to others. We may have to construct these social connections artificially but their</u> [END PAGE 83] <u>value and instrumentality will have to be proven through our ability to engage with, understand, critique and</u> ultimately <u>overcome the practices</u> and subjectivities <u>of our time</u>.</p> | 2NC | Case | 2NC – Ethics Not First | 65,682 | 475 | 102,337 | ./documents/ndtceda18/Northwestern/GaYo/Northwestern-GarciaMendoza-Young-Neg-GSU-Round8.docx | 607,505 | N | GSU | 8 | Wake EF | Erik Mathis | 1AC - Black Bomb
1NC - T Cap
2NR - T | ndtceda18/Northwestern/GaYo/Northwestern-GarciaMendoza-Young-Neg-GSU-Round8.docx | null | 51,522 | GaYo | Northwestern GaYo | null | Ca..... | Ga..... | Me..... | Yo..... | 19,208 | Northwestern | Northwestern | null | null | 1,008 | ndtceda18 | NDT/CEDA 2018-19 | 2,018 | cx | college | 2 |
2,567,060 | No escalation from space war – resilience, deterrence and low level attacks | Cooper, 18 | Cooper, 18 (Zack Cooper senior fellow for Asian security at the Center for Strategic and International Studies (CSIS). Thomas G. Roberts is a research assistant and program coordinator for the Aerospace Security Project at CSIS, "Deterrence in the Last Sanctuary," War on the Rocks, https://warontherocks.com/2018/01/deterrence-last-sanctuary/) | new architectures could enhance resilience and prevent critical military operations from being significantly impeded in an attack American investments in smaller satellites and more distributed space architectures could minimize adversary incentives to carry out first strikes in space. minor escalations against space systems were treated as major events, since they typically threatened the superpowers’ nuclear architectures. Today, the proliferation
of counter-space capabilities and the wide array of possible types of attacks means that most attacks against U.S. space systems are unlikely to warrant a nuclear response. Competitors may attempt to use non-kinetic weapons and reversible actions to stay below the threshold that would trigger a strong U.S. response space has been the exception: the one domain that has remained free from the scars of war. By better understanding the dynamics of the second space age, we may be able to keep it that way. | new architectures enhance resilience and prevent operations from being impeded in attack investments in smaller satellites and distributed architectures minimize adversary incentives to carry out first strikes in space
of capabilities and wide array of attacks means most attacks against space systems are unlikely to warrant a nuclear response Competitors may stay below the threshold that would trigger response | Until recently, resilience in space was largely an afterthought. It was assumed that a conflict in space would likely lead to or precede a major nuclear exchange. Therefore, the focus was on cost-effective architectures that maximized satellite capabilities, often at the cost of resilience. Recently, however, some have hoped that new architectures could enhance resilience and prevent critical military operations from being significantly impeded in an attack. Although resilience can be expensive, American investments in smaller satellites and more distributed space architectures could minimize adversary incentives to carry out first strikes in space. In the late 20th century, minor escalations against space systems were treated as major events, since they typically threatened the superpowers’ nuclear architectures. Today, the proliferation
of counter-space capabilities and the wide array of possible types of attacks means that most attacks against U.S. space systems are unlikely to warrant a nuclear response. It is critical that policymakers understand the likely break points in any conflict involving space systems. Strategists should explore whether the characteristics of different types of attacks against space systems create different thresholds, paying particular attention to attribution, reversibility, the defender’s awareness of an attack, the attacker’s ability to assess an attack’s effectiveness, and the risks of collateral damage (e.g., orbital debris). Competitors may attempt to use non-kinetic weapons and reversible actions to stay below the threshold that would trigger a strong U.S. response. The 2017 National Security Strategy warns: Any harmful interference with or an attack upon critical components of our space architecture that directly affects this vital U.S. interest will be met with a deliberate response at a time, place, manner, and domain of our choosing. In order to fulfill this promise, the United States will want to ensure that it has capabilities to respond both above and below various thresholds to ensure a full-spectrum of deterrence options for the full range of potential actors. In the first space age, the two superpowers had largely symmetric capabilities and interests in outer space (with a few notable exceptions). In the second space age, however, the space domain includes many disparate players with vastly different asymmetric capabilities and interests. The United States is more reliant on space than any other country in the world, but it also retains greater space capabilities than any of its competitors. Although the 2011 National Security Space Strategy states, “Space capabilities provide the United States and our allies unprecedented advantages in national decision-making, military operations, and homeland security,” this also means that that the United States has more to lose. From the dawn of the first space age, Americans understood the many benefits that could come from the peaceful uses of space and the great harm that could result from hostile uses of space. In 1962, President John F. Kennedy addressed the dilemma of how to reap the benefits of space without conflict, stating only if the United States occupies a position of pre-eminence can we help decide whether this new ocean will be a sea of peace or a new terrifying theater of war… space can be explored and mastered without feeding the fires of war, without repeating the mistakes that man has made in extending his writ around this globe of ours. For 60 years, space has been the exception: the one domain that has remained free from the scars of war. By better understanding the dynamics of the second space age, we may be able to keep it that way. | 3,708 | <h4>No escalation from space war – resilience, deterrence and low level attacks</h4><p><strong>Cooper, 18 <u></strong>(Zack Cooper senior fellow for Asian security at the Center for Strategic and International Studies (CSIS). Thomas G. Roberts is a research assistant and program coordinator for the Aerospace Security Project at CSIS, "Deterrence in the Last Sanctuary," War on the Rocks, https://warontherocks.com/2018/01/deterrence-last-sanctuary/)</p><p></u>Until recently, resilience in space was largely an afterthought. It was assumed that a conflict in space would likely lead to or precede a major nuclear exchange. Therefore, the focus was on cost-effective architectures that maximized satellite capabilities, often at the cost of resilience. Recently, however, some have hoped that <u><mark>new architectures</mark> could <mark>enhance resilience</mark> <mark>and prevent</mark> critical military <mark>operations from being</mark> significantly <mark>impeded in</mark> an <mark>attack</u></mark>. Although resilience can be expensive, <u>American <mark>investments in smaller satellites and</mark> more <mark>distributed</mark> space <mark>architectures</mark> could <strong><mark>minimize adversary incentives to carry out first strikes in space</mark>. </u></strong>In the late 20th century, <u>minor escalations against space systems were treated as major events, since they typically threatened the superpowers’ nuclear architectures. Today, the proliferation</p><p> <mark>of</mark> counter-space <mark>capabilities and</mark> the <mark>wide array of</mark> possible types of <mark>attacks means</mark> that <strong><mark>most attacks against</mark> U.S. <mark>space systems are unlikely to warrant a nuclear response</strong></mark>.</u> It is critical that policymakers understand the likely break points in any conflict involving space systems. Strategists should explore whether the characteristics of different types of attacks against space systems create different thresholds, paying particular attention to attribution, reversibility, the defender’s awareness of an attack, the attacker’s ability to assess an attack’s effectiveness, and the risks of collateral damage (e.g., orbital debris). <u><mark>Competitors may</mark> attempt to use non-kinetic weapons and reversible actions to <mark>stay below the threshold that would trigger</mark> a strong U.S. <mark>response</u></mark>. The 2017 National Security Strategy warns: Any harmful interference with or an attack upon critical components of our space architecture that directly affects this vital U.S. interest will be met with a deliberate response at a time, place, manner, and domain of our choosing. In order to fulfill this promise, the United States will want to ensure that it has capabilities to respond both above and below various thresholds to ensure a full-spectrum of deterrence options for the full range of potential actors. In the first space age, the two superpowers had largely symmetric capabilities and interests in outer space (with a few notable exceptions). In the second space age, however, the space domain includes many disparate players with vastly different asymmetric capabilities and interests. The United States is more reliant on space than any other country in the world, but it also retains greater space capabilities than any of its competitors. Although the 2011 National Security Space Strategy states, “Space capabilities provide the United States and our allies unprecedented advantages in national decision-making, military operations, and homeland security,” this also means that that the United States has more to lose. From the dawn of the first space age, Americans understood the many benefits that could come from the peaceful uses of space and the great harm that could result from hostile uses of space. In 1962, President John F. Kennedy addressed the dilemma of how to reap the benefits of space without conflict, stating only if the United States occupies a position of pre-eminence can we help decide whether this new ocean will be a sea of peace or a new terrifying theater of war… space can be explored and mastered without feeding the fires of war, without repeating the mistakes that man has made in extending his writ around this globe of ours. For 60 years, <u>space has been the exception: the one domain that has remained free from the scars of war. By better understanding the dynamics of the second space age, we may be able to keep it that way.</p></u> | 1NC v UTD | Space War | New Cards | 13,335 | 223 | 82,554 | ./documents/ndtceda19/MissouriState/VaRe/Missouri%20State-VanDyke-Reeves-Neg-UMKC-Round4.docx | 614,195 | N | UMKC | 4 | UTD BL | David Kilpatrick | 1AC - Co-Orbital Asats (Chow)
2NR - Track 2 CP
Xi DA
2AR - Condo | ndtceda19/MissouriState/VaRe/Missouri%20State-VanDyke-Reeves-Neg-UMKC-Round4.docx | null | 51,985 | VaRe | Missouri State VaRe | null | Al..... | Va..... | Pe..... | Re..... | 19,273 | MissouriState | Missouri State | null | null | 1,009 | ndtceda19 | NDT/CEDA 2019-20 | 2,019 | cx | college | 2 |
2,176,662 | US-Russia military competition is inevitable, but AWS ensures it goes nuclear – it collapses deterrence, motivates first strikes, undermines diplomatic offramps, and automated systems will misinterpret signals and escalate low level conflicts | Laird 6/3 | Laird 6/3/20 [Burgess RAND Corporation, “The Risks of Autonomous Weapons Systems for Crisis Stability and Conflict Escalation in Future U.S.-Russia Confrontations”] [DS] [https://www.rand.org/blog/2020/06/the-risks-of-autonomous-weapons-systems-for-crisis.html] | the development and posturing of AI-enabled autonomous weapons systems (AWS) is likely to raise significant risks for crisis instability and conflict escalation in future confrontations between the United States and Russia. Policymakers would do well to consider—now—whether the potential risks are worth the hoped-for operational advantages.
Still, as we enter the third decade of the 21st century, it has become clear that a growing number of countries are engaged in efforts to develop and field AWS and other AI-enabled military systems
Motivations and General Aims Driving AWS Development Efforts
China's P L A anticipates that AI could fundamentally change the character of warfare
Russia's It supports research (PDF) in a number of AI application areas; in just the past three years, the Kremlin has declared its intent to establish six new national initiatives dedicated to AI research and development, including the Advanced Research Foundation (ARF), Russia's analogue to the U.S. Defense Department's Defense Advanced Research Projects Agency (DARPA). As recently as April 21, ARF's deputy director boasted to RIA Novosti that as a result of the foundation's research, “Living fighters will gradually begin to be replaced by their robotic 'brothers' who can act faster, more accurately and more selectively than people.” Russia places great emphasis on the development of AI for information warfare aimed, as a recent comprehensive report by my RAND colleagues documents, at causing political and societal damage to the target state.
While holding out the promise of significant operational advantages, AWS simultaneously could increase the potential for undermining crisis stability and fueling conflict escalation in contests between the United States and Russia. Defined as “the degree to which mutual deterrence between dangerous adversaries can hold in a confrontation,” as my RAND colleague Forrest Morgan explains, crisis stability and the ways to achieve it are not about warfighting, but about “building and posturing forces in ways that allow a state, if confronted, to avoid war without backing down” on important political or military interests. Thus, the military capabilities developed by nuclear-armed states like the United States and Russia and how they posture them are key determinants of whether crises between them will remain stable or devolve into conventional armed conflict, as well as the extent to which such conflict might escalate in intensity and scope, including to the level of nuclear use AWS could foster crisis instability and conflict escalation in contests between the United States and Russia in a number of ways; in this short essay I will highlight only four. While holding out the promise of significant operational advantages, AWS simultaneously could increase the potential for undermining crisis stability and fueling conflict escalation.
First, a state facing an adversary with AWS capable of making decisions at machine speeds is likely to fear the threat of sudden and potent attack, a threat that would compress the amount of time for strategic decisionmaking. The posturing of AWS during a crisis would likely create fears that one's forces could suffer significant, if not decisive, strikes. These fears in turn could translate into pressures to strike first—to preempt—for fear of having to strike second from a greatly weakened position. Similarly, within conflict, the fear of losing at machine speeds would be likely to cause a state to escalate the intensity of the conflict possibly even to the level of nuclear use.
Second, as the speed of military action in a conflict involving the use of AWS as well as hypersonic weapons and other advanced military capabilities begins to surpass the speed of political decisionmaking, leaders could lose the ability to manage the crisis and with it the ability to control escalation. With tactical and operational action taking place at speeds driven by machines, the time for exchanging signals and communications and for assessing diplomatic options and offramps will be significantly foreclosed. However, the advantages of operating inside the OODA loop of a state adversary like Iraq or Serbia is one thing, while operating inside the OODA loop of a nuclear-armed adversary is another. As the renowned scholar Alexander George emphasized (PDF), especially in contests between nuclear armed competitors, there is a fundamental tension between the operational effectiveness sought by military commanders and the requirements for political leaders to retain control of events before major escalation takes place.
Third, and perhaps of greatest concern to policymakers should be the likelihood that, from the vantage point of Russia's leaders, in U.S. hands the operational advantages of AWS are likely to be understood as an increased U.S. capability for what Georgetown professor Caitlin Talmadge refers to as “conventional counterforce” operations. In brief, in crises and conflicts, Moscow is likely to see the United States as confronting it with an array of advanced conventional capabilities backstopped by an interconnected shield of theater and homeland missile defenses. Russia will perceive such capabilities as posing both a conventional war-winning threat and a conventional counterforce threat (PDF) poised to degrade the use of its strategic nuclear forces. The likelihood that Russia will see them this way is reinforced by the fact that it currently sees U.S. conventional precision capabilities precisely in this manner. As a qualitatively new capability that promises new operational advantages, the addition of AWS to U.S. conventional capabilities could further cement Moscow's view and in doing so increase the potential for crisis instability and escalation in confrontations with U.S. forces.
Take for example, a hypothetical scenario set in the Baltics in the 2030 timeframe which finds NATO forces employing swarming AWS to suppress Russian air defense networks and key command and control nodes in Kaliningrad as part of a larger strategy of expelling a Russian invasion force. What to NATO is a logical part of a conventional campaign could well appear to Moscow as initial moves of a larger plan designed to degrade the integrated air defense and command and control networks upon which Russia's strategic nuclear arsenal relies. In turn, such fears could feed pressures for Moscow to escalate to nuclear use while it still has the ability to do so.
Finally, even if the employment of AWS does not drive an increase in the speed and momentum of action that forecloses the time for exchanging signals, a future conflict in which AWS are ubiquitous will likely prove to be a poor venue both for signaling and interpreting signals AWS programmed to exploit every tactical opportunity might read the modulation as an opportunity to escalate offensive operations and thus gain tactical advantage. Such AWS could also misunderstand adversary attempts to signal resolve solely as adversary preparations for imminent attack. Of course, correctly interpreting signals sent in crisis and conflict is vexing enough when humans are making all the decisions, but in future confrontations in which decisionmaking has willingly or unwillingly been ceded to machines, the problem is likely only to be magnified | development of (AWS) likely to raise significant risks for crisis instability and escalation in future confrontations between the U S and Russia. consider the risks
countries are engaged AWS and AI-enabled military systems
China's P L A anticipates AI could fundamentally change warfare
Russia declared intent to establish six new national initiatives boasted Living fighters will gradually begin to be replaced by their robotic 'brothers'
crisis stability are about “building forces to avoid war without backing down” military capabilities are key determinants of whether crises escalate to nuclear . AWS could foster crisis instability and conflict escalation While holding out the promise of significant operational advantages, AWS simultaneously could increase the potential for undermining crisis stability and fueling conflict escalation.
First, a state facing an adversary making decisions at machine speeds is likely to fear the threat of sudden and potent attack that would compress the amount of time for decisionmaking fears translate into pressures to strike first Similarly cause a state to escalate the intensity of the conflict to nuclear use.
Second, as the speed of military action begins to surpass decisionmaking, leaders lose the ability to manage the crisis and control escalation time for exchanging signals and communications and offramps will be foreclosed
Third greatest concern should be from the vantage point of Russia's leaders U.S. AWS are understood as an increased U.S. capability for conventional counterforce” operations M capabilities degrade the use of nuclear forces Russia will see them this way AWS could further cement Moscow's view and increase the potential for crisis instability and escalation
Finally a future conflict in which AWS are ubiquitous will prove to be a poor venue both for signaling and interpreting signals AWS programmed to exploit every tactical opportunity might read modulation as an opportunity to escalate AWS could misunderstand attempts to signal resolve as preparations for imminent attack correctly interpreting signals in crisis is vexing enough when humans are making all the decisions in future confrontations in which decisionmaking has been ceded to machines, the problem is likely magnified | What advances in artificial intelligence (AI) will mean for the future battlefield remains opaque. Mainline discourse is overly influenced by exaggerated forecasts such as that reflected in Russian President Vladimir Putin's often repeated 2017 declaration that “whoever becomes the leader” in the sphere of artificial intelligence “will become the ruler of the world” and a broadly similar claim he advanced as recently as May 18 when he insisted that without artificial intelligence, hypersonic weapons and other new technologies, “it would be impossible to secure the future of our [Russia's] civilization.” Whatever security benefits and military advantages they may bring, as I argue in this piece, the development and posturing of AI-enabled autonomous weapons systems (AWS) is likely to raise significant risks for crisis instability and conflict escalation in future confrontations between the United States and Russia. Policymakers would do well to consider—now—whether the potential risks are worth the hoped-for operational advantages.
With the exception of the advent of nuclear weapons, history counsels skepticism regarding the many recurrent predictions of the revolutionary impact of technological innovation on the character of warfare. Maintaining objectivity and historically-informed skepticism is no less warranted when considering the potential battlefield effects of AWS, or systems that, once activated, are intended to select and engage targets (PDF) without further intervention or guidance from a human. Still, as we enter the third decade of the 21st century, it has become clear that a growing number of countries are engaged in efforts to develop and field AWS and other AI-enabled military systems. These efforts are by far best funded in the United States and China, with Russia lagging behind in spite of all Putin's motivational rhetoric. Unsurprisingly, these efforts are motivated by a desire to secure military operational advantages on the future battlefield.
Motivations and General Aims Driving AWS Development Efforts
The Pentagon views AI and robotics, along with several other emerging technologies including hypersonics and directed-energy, as key to offsetting the anti-access and area-denial capabilities and concepts developed by China and Russia over the past two decades, thereby regaining and sustaining U.S. conventional deterrence overmatch. Meanwhile, China's People's Liberation Army anticipates that AI could fundamentally change the character of warfare even as it fears the emergence of a generational gap between its capabilities and that of the U.S. military. It thus seeks to develop AI and other “strategic front-line” technologies in future military competition with the United States.
Nominally at least, Russia's vision regarding the aims of exploiting AI for military purposes are not dissimilar from those of the United States and China. It supports research (PDF) in a number of AI application areas; in just the past three years, the Kremlin has declared its intent to establish six new national initiatives dedicated to AI research and development, including the Advanced Research Foundation (ARF), Russia's analogue to the U.S. Defense Department's Defense Advanced Research Projects Agency (DARPA). As recently as April 21, ARF's deputy director boasted to RIA Novosti that as a result of the foundation's research, “Living fighters will gradually begin to be replaced by their robotic 'brothers' who can act faster, more accurately and more selectively than people.” Despite what Putin's bold assertion might otherwise seem to suggest, Western experts generally agree that Russian AI development significantly lags behind that of the United States and China. However, in stark contrast to U.S. AWS development efforts, if only marginally less so than China's, Russia places great emphasis on the development of AI for information warfare aimed, as a recent comprehensive report by my RAND colleagues documents, at causing political and societal damage to the target state. As argued below, instead of seeking to gain military operational advantages by competing to match U.S. AWS developments, Russia is much more likely to emphasize and invest in two other military capability areas.
Operational Advantages of AWS
U.S. military planners believe AWS promise to provide a number of significant operational advantages on the future battlefield. Less dependent on human control and decisionmaking, AWS are anticipated to be far faster and more agile than today's manned weapons systems undertaking thousands of complex and highly coordinated decisions at machine speeds. Today's remotely piloted drones rely on communications links to distant command and control and information analysis centers, which can result in inevitable communications delays and leave them vulnerable to jamming or denial through electronic warfare techniques. AWS, on the other hand, will be designed to operate on their own, if necessary, in such information contested environments (PDF), conferring degrees of stealth, decisional agility, persistence and survivability not enjoyed since the earliest days of stealth aircraft, if then.
AWS are expected to operate in large swarms comprising hundreds, or even thousands of small, relatively low-cost and expendable vehicles with networked sensors and on-board computing. Fighting in swarms, AWS hold the promise, as Paul Scharre notes, of effectively returning mass to the battlefield as they will be capable of rapidly and autonomously coordinating their own tactical movement in response to enemy actions. As a consequence, AWS are expected to provide the capability of synchronized attack or defense that enables one to fight inside the enemy's decision cycle or OODA loop, overwhelming and defeating (PDF) the enemy's abilities through mass, intelligence, coordination and speed. In conflicts against opponents lacking similar capabilities, U.S. military planners maintain that the combination of such characteristics will provide decisive operational advantage.
Finally, like today's drones, AWS will reduce the numbers of casualties and body bags in conflict. But, in contrast to current drones, AWS are expected to lead to cost savings as the frequently overlooked need for large rotating teams (PDF) of remotely located and highly trained pilots and operators would be eliminated. Such cost-savings could be substantial if realized not only from the advent of AWS, but from the diffusion of AI and autonomy to other military functions such as logistics and transportation, battlefield healthcare, cybersecurity and combat simulation and training—a benefit that would reduce the demand for personnel and could lead to smaller militaries.
Russia Unlikely to Seek to Match U.S. AWS Developments
The economic outlook for Russia, which remains dependent on exports of oil and gas for much of its revenues, is grim at least in the short-term. COVID-19 forced Russia to agree to a deal with OPEC to significantly cut production and exports, which it initially rejected in March, and sent oil prices down in what is bound to reduce budget revenues and cause economic contraction. Russia is now forecast to experience a GDP contraction of 5.5. percent and an increase in unemployment from 2.5 million to 8 million workers this year. Moreover, continued dependence on exports of commodities whose prices Russia cannot control, depopulation (PDF), and a host of other structural factors indicates that the economic outlook for Russia will remain bleak in the longer term, too, in absence of deep reforms. As a result, for the foreseeable future, Russia's federal budget is likely to be constrained. If for no other reason than that, the Kremlin will be unlikely to respond to U.S. AWS advancements by substantially increasing investments in the area, at least in comparison to two other capabilities it is more likely to prioritize well ahead of AWS as discussed immediately below. But there is yet another reason. In brief, such symmetrical responses to capability differences have seldom been part of Russia's playbook in the post–Cold War era. In this respect, it is too early to identify just where Russia may be heading in terms of the character of AWS ground, air, or naval capabilities it is likely to field, let alone to discern any associated operational concepts. The time doing so is likely to prove time misspent. Instead, Moscow is much more likely to look to two other capability areas in search of comparative military operational advantage with respect to the United States and NATO.
First, the Kremlin can be counted upon to continue with its customary strategy of underscoring and even increasing its reliance upon nuclear weapons both for deterrence and possibly even warfighting, a cost-effective strategy, comparatively speaking, that Vasily Kashin and Michael Raska economically refer to as “countering the Third Offset Strategy with the First Offset Strategy (PDF).” In this regard, Putin's unveiling of the five nuclear “superweapons” in his March 2018 nationally televised speech to the Russian Federal Assembly can be seen as exhibit one of this strategy. Still, Moscow's continued reliance on nuclear weapons by no means suggests that it will be willing to cede leadership in emerging disruptive technologies entirely to the United States.
In fact, the second military capability area Russia is likely to emphasize is that of hypersonic missiles, one of the few weapons realms, outside of nuclear weapons, in which it is building a track-record for both developing and fielding apparently functioning, sophisticated 21st century weapons systems. In just a few short years, it has developed and deployed two hypersonic missile systems, and is currently testing a third. Deployment of the Avangard hypersonic glide vehicle has already begun, as Russian officials announced in late December 2019 that one missile regiment on the border with Kazakhstan was armed with the hypersonic glide vehicle. The Kh-47M2 Kinzhal air-launched ballistic missile appears slated to be deployed by 2024 by a MiG-31K regiment operating from the VKS base in the Siberian city of Kansk. While a deployment date for the 3M-22 Tsirkon anti-ship hypersonic cruise missile is still uncertain, a Russian navy frigate fired the weapon from the Barents Sea against a ground target in a purportedly successful test in January of this year.
Implications for Crisis Stability and Conflict Escalation in U.S.-Russia Confrontations
While holding out the promise of significant operational advantages, AWS simultaneously could increase the potential for undermining crisis stability and fueling conflict escalation in contests between the United States and Russia. Defined as “the degree to which mutual deterrence between dangerous adversaries can hold in a confrontation,” as my RAND colleague Forrest Morgan explains, crisis stability and the ways to achieve it are not about warfighting, but about “building and posturing forces in ways that allow a state, if confronted, to avoid war without backing down” on important political or military interests. Thus, the military capabilities developed by nuclear-armed states like the United States and Russia and how they posture them are key determinants of whether crises between them will remain stable or devolve into conventional armed conflict, as well as the extent to which such conflict might escalate in intensity and scope, including to the level of nuclear use. AWS could foster crisis instability and conflict escalation in contests between the United States and Russia in a number of ways; in this short essay I will highlight only four. While holding out the promise of significant operational advantages, AWS simultaneously could increase the potential for undermining crisis stability and fueling conflict escalation.
First, a state facing an adversary with AWS capable of making decisions at machine speeds is likely to fear the threat of sudden and potent attack, a threat that would compress the amount of time for strategic decisionmaking. The posturing of AWS during a crisis would likely create fears that one's forces could suffer significant, if not decisive, strikes. These fears in turn could translate into pressures to strike first—to preempt—for fear of having to strike second from a greatly weakened position. Similarly, within conflict, the fear of losing at machine speeds would be likely to cause a state to escalate the intensity of the conflict possibly even to the level of nuclear use.
Second, as the speed of military action in a conflict involving the use of AWS as well as hypersonic weapons and other advanced military capabilities begins to surpass the speed of political decisionmaking, leaders could lose the ability to manage the crisis and with it the ability to control escalation. With tactical and operational action taking place at speeds driven by machines, the time for exchanging signals and communications and for assessing diplomatic options and offramps will be significantly foreclosed. However, the advantages of operating inside the OODA loop of a state adversary like Iraq or Serbia is one thing, while operating inside the OODA loop of a nuclear-armed adversary is another. As the renowned scholar Alexander George emphasized (PDF), especially in contests between nuclear armed competitors, there is a fundamental tension between the operational effectiveness sought by military commanders and the requirements for political leaders to retain control of events before major escalation takes place.
Third, and perhaps of greatest concern to policymakers should be the likelihood that, from the vantage point of Russia's leaders, in U.S. hands the operational advantages of AWS are likely to be understood as an increased U.S. capability for what Georgetown professor Caitlin Talmadge refers to as “conventional counterforce” operations. In brief, in crises and conflicts, Moscow is likely to see the United States as confronting it with an array of advanced conventional capabilities backstopped by an interconnected shield of theater and homeland missile defenses. Russia will perceive such capabilities as posing both a conventional war-winning threat and a conventional counterforce threat (PDF) poised to degrade the use of its strategic nuclear forces. The likelihood that Russia will see them this way is reinforced by the fact that it currently sees U.S. conventional precision capabilities precisely in this manner. As a qualitatively new capability that promises new operational advantages, the addition of AWS to U.S. conventional capabilities could further cement Moscow's view and in doing so increase the potential for crisis instability and escalation in confrontations with U.S. forces.
In other words, the fielding of U.S. AWS could augment what Moscow already sees as a formidable U.S. ability to threaten a range of important targets including its command and control networks, air defenses, and early warning radars, all of which are unquestionably critical components of Russian conventional forces. In many cases, however, they also serve as critical components of Russia's nuclear force operations. As Talmadge argues, attacks on such targets, even if intended solely to weaken Russian conventional capabilities, will likely raise Russian fears that the U.S. conventional campaign is in fact a counterforce campaign aimed at neutering Russia's nuclear capabilities. Take for example, a hypothetical scenario set in the Baltics in the 2030 timeframe which finds NATO forces employing swarming AWS to suppress Russian air defense networks and key command and control nodes in Kaliningrad as part of a larger strategy of expelling a Russian invasion force. What to NATO is a logical part of a conventional campaign could well appear to Moscow as initial moves of a larger plan designed to degrade the integrated air defense and command and control networks upon which Russia's strategic nuclear arsenal relies. In turn, such fears could feed pressures for Moscow to escalate to nuclear use while it still has the ability to do so.
Finally, even if the employment of AWS does not drive an increase in the speed and momentum of action that forecloses the time for exchanging signals, a future conflict in which AWS are ubiquitous will likely prove to be a poor venue both for signaling and interpreting signals. In such a conflict, instead of interpreting a downward modulation in an adversary's operations as a possible signal of restraint or perhaps as signaling a willingness to pause in an effort to open up space for diplomatic negotiations, AWS programmed to exploit every tactical opportunity might read the modulation as an opportunity to escalate offensive operations and thus gain tactical advantage. Such AWS could also misunderstand adversary attempts to signal resolve solely as adversary preparations for imminent attack. Of course, correctly interpreting signals sent in crisis and conflict is vexing enough when humans are making all the decisions, but in future confrontations in which decisionmaking has willingly or unwillingly been ceded to machines, the problem is likely only to be magnified | 17,223 | <h4>US-Russia military competition is inevitable, but AWS ensures it <u>goes nuclear</u> – it collapses <u>deterrence</u>, motivates <u>first strikes</u>, undermines diplomatic offramps, and <u>automated systems</u> will <u>misinterpret</u> signals and <u>escalate</u> low level conflicts </h4><p><strong>Laird 6/3<u></strong>/20 [Burgess RAND Corporation, “The Risks of Autonomous Weapons Systems for Crisis Stability and Conflict Escalation in Future U.S.-Russia Confrontations”] [DS] [https://www.rand.org/blog/2020/06/the-risks-of-autonomous-weapons-systems-for-crisis.html]</p><p></u>What advances in artificial intelligence (AI) will mean for the future battlefield remains opaque. Mainline discourse is overly influenced by exaggerated forecasts such as that reflected in Russian President Vladimir Putin's often repeated 2017 declaration that “whoever becomes the leader” in the sphere of artificial intelligence “will become the ruler of the world” and a broadly similar claim he advanced as recently as May 18 when he insisted that without artificial intelligence, hypersonic weapons and other new technologies, “it would be impossible to secure the future of our [Russia's] civilization.” Whatever security benefits and military advantages they may bring, as I argue in this piece, <u>the <mark>development </mark>and posturing <mark>of</mark> AI-enabled autonomous weapons systems <mark>(<strong>AWS</strong>) </mark>is <mark>likely to raise <strong>significant risks</strong> for crisis <strong>instability</strong> and </mark>conflict <strong><mark>escalation</strong> in future <strong>confrontations</strong> between the <strong>U</strong></mark>nited <strong><mark>S</strong></mark>tates <mark>and Russia. </mark>Policymakers would do well to <mark>consider</mark>—now—whether <mark>the </mark>potential <mark>risks </mark>are worth the hoped-for operational advantages. </p><p></u>With the exception of the advent of nuclear weapons, history counsels skepticism regarding the many recurrent predictions of the revolutionary impact of technological innovation on the character of warfare. Maintaining objectivity and historically-informed skepticism is no less warranted when considering the potential battlefield effects of AWS, or systems that, once activated, are intended to select and engage targets (PDF) without further intervention or guidance from a human. <u>Still, as we enter the third decade of the 21st century, it has become clear that a growing number of <mark>countries are engaged</mark> in efforts to develop and field <strong><mark>AWS</strong> and </mark>other <strong><mark>AI-enabled military systems</u></strong></mark>. These efforts are by far best funded in the United States and China, with Russia lagging behind in spite of all Putin's motivational rhetoric. Unsurprisingly, these efforts are motivated by a desire to secure military operational advantages on the future battlefield. </p><p><u>Motivations and General Aims Driving AWS Development Efforts </p><p></u>The Pentagon views AI and robotics, along with several other emerging technologies including hypersonics and directed-energy, as key to offsetting the anti-access and area-denial capabilities and concepts developed by China and Russia over the past two decades, thereby regaining and sustaining U.S. conventional deterrence overmatch. Meanwhile, <u><mark>China's</u></mark> <u><strong><mark>P</u></strong></mark>eople's <u><strong><mark>L</u></strong></mark>iberation <u><strong><mark>A</u></strong></mark>rmy <u><mark>anticipates</mark> that <strong><mark>AI</strong></mark> <mark>could fundamentally change</mark> the character of <strong><mark>warfare</u></strong></mark> even as it fears the emergence of a generational gap between its capabilities and that of the U.S. military. It thus seeks to develop AI and other “strategic front-line” technologies in future military competition with the United States.</p><p>Nominally at least, <u><mark>Russia</mark>'s</u> vision regarding the aims of exploiting AI for military purposes are not dissimilar from those of the United States and China. <u>It supports research (PDF) in a number of AI application areas; in just the past three years, the Kremlin has <mark>declared </mark>its <mark>intent to establish <strong>six new national initiatives</strong></mark> dedicated to AI research and development, including the Advanced Research Foundation (ARF), Russia's analogue to the U.S. Defense Department's Defense Advanced Research Projects Agency (DARPA). As recently as April 21, ARF's deputy director <mark>boasted</mark> to RIA Novosti that as a result of the foundation's research, “<mark>Living <strong>fighters</strong> will gradually begin to be replaced by their <strong>robotic 'brothers'</strong> </mark>who can act faster, more accurately and more selectively than people.” </u>Despite what Putin's bold assertion might otherwise seem to suggest, Western experts generally agree that Russian AI development significantly lags behind that of the United States and China. However, in stark contrast to U.S. AWS development efforts, if only marginally less so than China's, <u>Russia places great emphasis on the development of AI for information warfare aimed, as a recent comprehensive report by my RAND colleagues documents, at causing political and societal damage to the target state.</u> As argued below, instead of seeking to gain military operational advantages by competing to match U.S. AWS developments, Russia is much more likely to emphasize and invest in two other military capability areas. </p><p>Operational Advantages of AWS </p><p>U.S. military planners believe AWS promise to provide a number of significant operational advantages on the future battlefield. Less dependent on human control and decisionmaking, AWS are anticipated to be far faster and more agile than today's manned weapons systems undertaking thousands of complex and highly coordinated decisions at machine speeds. Today's remotely piloted drones rely on communications links to distant command and control and information analysis centers, which can result in inevitable communications delays and leave them vulnerable to jamming or denial through electronic warfare techniques. AWS, on the other hand, will be designed to operate on their own, if necessary, in such information contested environments (PDF), conferring degrees of stealth, decisional agility, persistence and survivability not enjoyed since the earliest days of stealth aircraft, if then. </p><p>AWS are expected to operate in large swarms comprising hundreds, or even thousands of small, relatively low-cost and expendable vehicles with networked sensors and on-board computing. Fighting in swarms, AWS hold the promise, as Paul Scharre notes, of effectively returning mass to the battlefield as they will be capable of rapidly and autonomously coordinating their own tactical movement in response to enemy actions. As a consequence, AWS are expected to provide the capability of synchronized attack or defense that enables one to fight inside the enemy's decision cycle or OODA loop, overwhelming and defeating (PDF) the enemy's abilities through mass, intelligence, coordination and speed. In conflicts against opponents lacking similar capabilities, U.S. military planners maintain that the combination of such characteristics will provide decisive operational advantage. </p><p>Finally, like today's drones, AWS will reduce the numbers of casualties and body bags in conflict. But, in contrast to current drones, AWS are expected to lead to cost savings as the frequently overlooked need for large rotating teams (PDF) of remotely located and highly trained pilots and operators would be eliminated. Such cost-savings could be substantial if realized not only from the advent of AWS, but from the diffusion of AI and autonomy to other military functions such as logistics and transportation, battlefield healthcare, cybersecurity and combat simulation and training—a benefit that would reduce the demand for personnel and could lead to smaller militaries. </p><p>Russia Unlikely to Seek to Match U.S. AWS Developments </p><p>The economic outlook for Russia, which remains dependent on exports of oil and gas for much of its revenues, is grim at least in the short-term. COVID-19 forced Russia to agree to a deal with OPEC to significantly cut production and exports, which it initially rejected in March, and sent oil prices down in what is bound to reduce budget revenues and cause economic contraction. Russia is now forecast to experience a GDP contraction of 5.5. percent and an increase in unemployment from 2.5 million to 8 million workers this year. Moreover, continued dependence on exports of commodities whose prices Russia cannot control, depopulation (PDF), and a host of other structural factors indicates that the economic outlook for Russia will remain bleak in the longer term, too, in absence of deep reforms. As a result, for the foreseeable future, Russia's federal budget is likely to be constrained. If for no other reason than that, the Kremlin will be unlikely to respond to U.S. AWS advancements by substantially increasing investments in the area, at least in comparison to two other capabilities it is more likely to prioritize well ahead of AWS as discussed immediately below. But there is yet another reason. In brief, such symmetrical responses to capability differences have seldom been part of Russia's playbook in the post–Cold War era. In this respect, it is too early to identify just where Russia may be heading in terms of the character of AWS ground, air, or naval capabilities it is likely to field, let alone to discern any associated operational concepts. The time doing so is likely to prove time misspent. Instead, Moscow is much more likely to look to two other capability areas in search of comparative military operational advantage with respect to the United States and NATO. </p><p>First, the Kremlin can be counted upon to continue with its customary strategy of underscoring and even increasing its reliance upon nuclear weapons both for deterrence and possibly even warfighting, a cost-effective strategy, comparatively speaking, that Vasily Kashin and Michael Raska economically refer to as “countering the Third Offset Strategy with the First Offset Strategy (PDF).” In this regard, Putin's unveiling of the five nuclear “superweapons” in his March 2018 nationally televised speech to the Russian Federal Assembly can be seen as exhibit one of this strategy. Still, Moscow's continued reliance on nuclear weapons by no means suggests that it will be willing to cede leadership in emerging disruptive technologies entirely to the United States. </p><p>In fact, the second military capability area Russia is likely to emphasize is that of hypersonic missiles, one of the few weapons realms, outside of nuclear weapons, in which it is building a track-record for both developing and fielding apparently functioning, sophisticated 21st century weapons systems. In just a few short years, it has developed and deployed two hypersonic missile systems, and is currently testing a third. Deployment of the Avangard hypersonic glide vehicle has already begun, as Russian officials announced in late December 2019 that one missile regiment on the border with Kazakhstan was armed with the hypersonic glide vehicle. The Kh-47M2 Kinzhal air-launched ballistic missile appears slated to be deployed by 2024 by a MiG-31K regiment operating from the VKS base in the Siberian city of Kansk. While a deployment date for the 3M-22 Tsirkon anti-ship hypersonic cruise missile is still uncertain, a Russian navy frigate fired the weapon from the Barents Sea against a ground target in a purportedly successful test in January of this year. </p><p>Implications for Crisis Stability and Conflict Escalation in U.S.-Russia Confrontations </p><p><u>While holding out the promise of significant operational advantages, AWS simultaneously could increase the potential for undermining crisis stability and fueling conflict escalation in contests between the United States and Russia. Defined as “the degree to which mutual deterrence between dangerous adversaries can hold in a confrontation,” as my RAND colleague Forrest Morgan explains, <strong><mark>crisis stability</strong></mark> and the ways to achieve it <mark>are</mark> not about warfighting, but <mark>about “building </mark>and posturing <mark>forces </mark>in ways that allow a state, if confronted, <mark>to</mark> <mark>avoid <strong>war</strong> without backing down”</mark> on important political or military interests. Thus, the <mark>military <strong>capabilities</strong></mark> developed by nuclear-armed states like the United States and Russia and how they posture them <mark>are <strong>key determinants</strong> of whether crises</mark> between them will remain stable or devolve into conventional armed conflict, as well as the extent to which such conflict might <strong><mark>escalate</strong> </mark>in intensity and scope, including <mark>to</mark> the level of <mark>nuclear </mark>use</u><mark>.<u> <strong>AWS</strong> could foster <strong>crisis instability</strong> and <strong>conflict escalation</strong></mark> in contests between the United States and Russia in a number of ways; in this short essay I will highlight only four. <mark>While holding out the promise of significant operational advantages, AWS simultaneously could increase the potential for undermining crisis stability and fueling conflict escalation. </p><p><strong>First</strong>, a state facing an adversary </mark>with AWS capable of <mark>making decisions at <strong>machine speeds</strong> is likely to fear the threat of <strong>sudden</strong> and <strong>potent attack</strong></mark>, a threat <mark>that would <strong>compress</strong> the amount of <strong>time</strong> for </mark>strategic <strong><mark>decisionmaking</strong></mark>. The posturing of AWS during a crisis would likely create fears that one's forces could suffer significant, if not decisive, strikes. These <mark>fears</mark> in turn could <mark>translate into <strong>pressures to strike first</strong></mark>—to preempt—for fear of having to strike second from a greatly weakened position. <mark>Similarly</mark>, within conflict, the fear of losing at machine speeds would be likely to <mark>cause a state to <strong>escalate</strong> the <strong>intensity</strong> of the conflict</mark> possibly even <mark>to</mark> the level of <strong><mark>nuclear use</strong>. </p><p><strong>Second</strong>, as the speed of military action</mark> in a conflict involving the use of AWS as well as hypersonic weapons and other advanced military capabilities <mark>begins to surpass </mark>the speed of political <mark>decisionmaking, leaders</mark> could <strong><mark>lose the ability to manage the crisis</strong> and</mark> with it the ability to <strong><mark>control escalation</strong></mark>. With tactical and operational action taking place at speeds driven by machines, the <mark>time for exchanging <strong>signals</strong> and <strong>communications</strong> and </mark>for assessing diplomatic options and <mark>offramps will be </mark>significantly <mark>foreclosed</mark>. However, the advantages of operating inside the OODA loop of a state adversary like Iraq or Serbia is one thing, while operating inside the OODA loop of a nuclear-armed adversary is another. As the renowned scholar Alexander George emphasized (PDF), especially in contests between nuclear armed competitors, there is a fundamental tension between the operational effectiveness sought by military commanders and the requirements for political leaders to retain control of events before major escalation takes place. </p><p><mark>Third</mark>, and perhaps of <strong><mark>greatest concern</strong></mark> to policymakers <mark>should be</mark> the likelihood that, <mark>from the vantage point of Russia's leaders</mark>, in <strong><mark>U.S.</strong></mark> hands the operational advantages of <strong><mark>AWS</strong> are</mark> likely to be <mark>understood as an increased U.S. capability for</mark> what Georgetown professor Caitlin Talmadge refers to as “<strong><mark>conventional counterforce</strong>” operations</mark>. In brief, in crises and conflicts, <mark>M</mark>oscow is likely to see the United States as confronting it with an array of advanced conventional capabilities backstopped by an interconnected shield of theater and homeland missile defenses. Russia will perceive such <mark>capabilities </mark>as posing both a conventional war-winning threat and a conventional counterforce threat (PDF) poised to <mark>degrade the use of </mark>its strategic <mark>nuclear forces</mark>. The likelihood that <mark>Russia will <strong>see them this way</strong></mark> is reinforced by the fact that it currently sees U.S. conventional precision capabilities precisely in this manner. As a qualitatively new capability that promises new operational advantages, the addition of <strong><mark>AWS</strong> </mark>to U.S. conventional capabilities <mark>could further <strong>cement Moscow's view</strong> and </mark>in doing so <mark>increase the <strong>potential</strong> for <strong>crisis instability and escalation</strong></mark> in confrontations with U.S. forces. </p><p></u>In other words, the fielding of U.S. AWS could augment what Moscow already sees as a formidable U.S. ability to threaten a range of important targets including its command and control networks, air defenses, and early warning radars, all of which are unquestionably critical components of Russian conventional forces. In many cases, however, they also serve as critical components of Russia's nuclear force operations. As Talmadge argues, attacks on such targets, even if intended solely to weaken Russian conventional capabilities, will likely raise Russian fears that the U.S. conventional campaign is in fact a counterforce campaign aimed at neutering Russia's nuclear capabilities.<u> Take for example, a hypothetical scenario set in the <strong>Baltics</strong> in the 2030 timeframe which finds NATO forces employing swarming AWS to suppress Russian air defense networks and key command and control nodes in Kaliningrad as part of a larger strategy of expelling a Russian invasion force. What to NATO is a logical part of a conventional campaign could well appear to Moscow as initial moves of a larger plan designed to degrade the integrated air defense and command and control networks upon which Russia's strategic nuclear arsenal relies. In turn, such fears could feed <strong>pressures</strong> for Moscow to <strong>escalate to nuclear use</strong> while it still has the <strong>ability</strong> to do so. </p><p><strong><mark>Finally</strong></mark>, even if the employment of AWS does not drive an increase in the speed and momentum of action that forecloses the time for exchanging signals, <mark>a future conflict in which <strong>AWS</strong> are <strong>ubiquitous</strong> will </mark>likely <mark>prove to be a poor venue both for <strong>signaling</strong> and <strong>interpreting signals</u></strong></mark>. In such a conflict, instead of interpreting a downward modulation in an adversary's operations as a possible signal of restraint or perhaps as signaling a willingness to pause in an effort to open up space for diplomatic negotiations, <u><strong><mark>AWS</strong> programmed to <strong>exploit</strong> every tactical <strong>opportunity</strong> might read </mark>the <mark>modulation as an opportunity to <strong>escalate</strong> </mark>offensive operations and thus gain tactical advantage. Such <strong><mark>AWS</strong> could</mark> also <mark>misunderstand</mark> adversary <mark>attempts to signal <strong>resolve</strong></mark> solely <mark>as</mark> adversary <mark>preparations for <strong>imminent attack</strong></mark>. Of course, <mark>correctly interpreting signals</mark> sent <mark>in crisis</mark> and conflict <mark>is vexing enough when <strong>humans are making all the decisions</strong></mark>, but <mark>in future confrontations in which decisionmaking has</mark> willingly or unwillingly <mark>been ceded to machines, the problem is likely </mark>only to be <strong><mark>magnified</strong></mark> </p></u> | null | null | 1AC | 1,650,790 | 860 | 66,511 | ./documents/hsld20/Harker/Sh2/Harker-Shahh-Aff-MS%20TOC-Round1.docx | 860,521 | A | MS TOC | 1 | Marlborough PS | Kyle Groner | 1AC - nukes
1NC - moratorium cp | hsld20/Harker/Sh2/Harker-Shahh-Aff-MS%20TOC-Round1.docx | null | 73,101 | SoSh | Harker SoSh | null | So..... | Sh..... | null | null | 24,534 | Harker | Harker | CA | null | 1,028 | hsld20 | HS LD 2020-21 | 2,020 | ld | hs | 1 |
1,193,338 | 5---copper, lithium, manganese---answers green tech | Ahmed 20 | Ahmed 20 [Nafeez. M.A. in contemporary war & peace studies and a DPhil (April 2009) in international relations from the School of Global Studies at Sussex University. Capitalism Will Ruin the Earth By 2050, Scientists Say. Vice. 10-21-2020. https://www.vice.com/en/article/v7m48d/capitalism-will-ruin-the-earth-by-2050-scientists-say] | Endless growth will generate minerals scarcity within decades
Electrification of roads and rail will require upgraded smart grids, complex routes connected to high power lines, and regular battery-swap stations
the economy begins to stagnate “due to peak oil limits at around 2025-2040,”
the economy hits the limits of mineral and material production to sustain this electric transition—in just three decades this is even with high levels of minerals recycling
the EV transition will “require higher amounts of copper, lithium and manganese than current reserves copper and manganese the depletion is mainly due to the demand from the rest of the economy this alone “depletes its estimated global reserves
Mineral depletion takes place even with “a very high increase in recycling rates”
realistic upper level recycling rates of 57 percent, 30 percent and 74 percent to copper, lithium and manganese respectively extremely optimistic projections
even these high recycling rates wouldn’t prevent depletion of all current estimated reserves by 2050 conclusion corroborates findings of other studies, estimating an expected bottleneck for lithium by 2042-2045 and for manganese by 2038-2050
Actual bottlenecks could come even earlier because existing studies don’t account for material requirements needed for internal wiring, the EV motor, EV chargers, building and maintaining the grid to connect and charge EV batteries as well as inherent difficulties in recycling metals | Endless growth generate minerals scarcity
Electrification require smart grids power lines and battery
economy hits limits of mineral
copper, lithium and manganese depletion is due to demand
even high recycling wouldn’t prevent depletion of lithium by 42 and manganese by 38
bottlenecks could come earlier existing studies don’t account for requirements needed for wiring as well as difficulties in recycling | Endless growth will generate minerals scarcity within decades
The EV transition is, in short, a massive industrial project. Electrification of roads and rail will require upgraded smart grids, complex routes connected to high power lines, and regular battery-swap stations. The paper explores several scenarios to explore how such a transition would take place.
In a continuing GDP growth scenario, the authors note that the economy begins to stagnate “due to peak oil limits at around 2025-2040,” but GDP is able to continue growing thanks to the EV transition. This shows that the reduction in liquid fuels in transportation can play a powerful role in avoiding “energy shortages in the economy as a whole.”
But then the economy hits the limits of mineral and material production to sustain this electric transition—in just three decades. And this is even with high levels of minerals recycling.
By 2050, in this scenario, the EV transition will “require higher amounts of copper, lithium and manganese than current reserves. For the cases of copper and manganese the depletion is mainly due to the demand from the rest of the economy,” but most lithium demand “is for EV batteries,” and this alone “depletes its estimated global reserves.”
Mineral depletion takes place even with “a very high increase in recycling rates” in a continuing GDP growth scenario.
In one such scenario, the authors apply what they consider to be realistic upper level recycling rates of 57 percent, 30 percent and 74 percent to copper, lithium and manganese respectively. These are based on extremely optimistic projections of recycling capabilities relative to their costs.
But still they find that even these high recycling rates wouldn’t prevent depletion of all current estimated reserves by 2050. The conclusion corroborates findings of other studies, estimating an expected bottleneck for lithium by 2042-2045 and for manganese by 2038-2050.
Actual bottlenecks could come even earlier because existing studies—including the MEDEAS model—don’t account for material requirements needed for internal wiring, the EV motor, EV chargers, building and maintaining the grid to connect and charge EV batteries, the catenaries to electrify the railways, as well as inherent difficulties in recycling metals. | 2,284 | <h4>5---copper, lithium, manganese---answers green tech</h4><p><strong>Ahmed 20</strong> [Nafeez. M.A. in contemporary war & peace studies and a DPhil (April 2009) in international relations from the School of Global Studies at Sussex University. Capitalism Will Ruin the Earth By 2050, Scientists Say. Vice. 10-21-2020. https://www.vice.com/en/article/v7m48d/capitalism-will-ruin-the-earth-by-2050-scientists-say]</p><p><u><mark>Endless growth</mark> will <mark>generate</u> <u><strong>minerals scarcity</strong></mark> within <strong>decades</u></strong> </p><p>The EV transition is, in short, a massive industrial project. <u><mark>Electrification</mark> of roads and rail will <mark>require</mark> upgraded <mark>smart grids</mark>, complex routes connected to high <mark>power lines</mark>, <mark>and</mark> regular <mark>battery</mark>-swap stations</u>. The paper explores several scenarios to explore how such a transition would take place. </p><p>In a continuing GDP growth scenario, the authors note that <u>the economy begins to <strong>stagnate </strong>“due to <strong>peak oil limits</strong> at around 2025-2040,”</u> but GDP is able to continue growing thanks to the EV transition. This shows that the reduction in liquid fuels in transportation can play a powerful role in avoiding “energy shortages in the economy as a whole.” </p><p>But then <u>the <mark>economy hits</mark> the <mark>limits of mineral </mark>and material production to sustain this electric transition—in just <strong>three decades</u></strong>. And <u>this is <strong>even with</strong> high levels of <strong>minerals recycling</u></strong>.</p><p>By 2050, in this scenario, <u>the EV transition will “require higher amounts of <mark>copper, lithium and manganese</mark> than current reserves</u>. For the cases of <u>copper and manganese the <mark>depletion is</mark> mainly <mark>due to</mark> the <mark>demand </mark>from the rest of the economy</u>,” but most lithium demand “is for EV batteries,” and <u>this alone “<strong>depletes</strong> its estimated <strong>global reserves</u></strong>.”</p><p><u>Mineral depletion takes place even with “a very high increase in recycling rates” </u>in a continuing GDP growth scenario. </p><p>In one such scenario, the authors apply what they consider to be <u>realistic upper level recycling rates of 57 percent, 30 percent and 74 percent to copper, lithium and manganese respectively</u>. These are based on <u><strong>extremely optimistic projections</u></strong> of recycling capabilities relative to their costs. </p><p>But still they find that <u><mark>even</mark> these <mark>high recycling </mark>rates <strong><mark>wouldn’t prevent depletion</strong> of</mark> all current estimated reserves by 2050</u>. The <u>conclusion corroborates findings of other studies, estimating an expected <strong>bottleneck for <mark>lithium</strong> by</mark> 20<mark>42</mark>-2045 <mark>and</mark> <strong>for <mark>manganese</strong> by</mark> 20<mark>38</mark>-2050</u>. </p><p><u>Actual <mark>bottlenecks could <strong>come </mark>even <mark>earlier</strong></mark> because <mark>existing studies</u></mark>—including the MEDEAS model—<u><mark>don’t account for </mark>material <mark>requirements needed for </mark>internal <mark>wiring</mark>, the EV motor, EV chargers, building and maintaining the grid to connect and charge EV batteries</u>, the catenaries to electrify the railways, <u><mark>as well as </mark>inherent<mark> difficulties in recycling</mark> metals</u>. </p> | null | 2NC | K—Capitalism | 12,010 | 238 | 29,199 | ./documents/hspolicy21/NewTrier/ShWi/New%20Trier-Shapiro-Wilson-Neg-A%20-%20Greenhill-Round6.docx | 752,114 | N | A - Greenhill | 6 | Lowell ST | Josh Clark | 1AC - Icebreakers
1NC - T-Protection T-Oceans Russia Cooperation CP Cap K
2NR - T-Oceans | hspolicy21/NewTrier/ShWi/New%20Trier-Shapiro-Wilson-Neg-A%20-%20Greenhill-Round6.docx | null | 64,132 | ShWi | New Trier ShWi | null | Ro..... | Sh..... | Ni..... | Wi..... | 22,064 | NewTrier | New Trier | IL | null | 1,020 | hspolicy21 | HS Policy 2021-22 | 2,021 | cx | hs | 2 |
3,968,570 | Only warming causes extinction | McDonald 19 | McDonald 19, Geography PhD student at University of Oxford studying the intersection of grassroots movements and energy transition. (Samuel Miller, 1-4-2019, “Deathly Salvation”, The Trouble, https://www.the-trouble.com/content/2019/1/4/deathly-salvation) | nuclear exchange does not inevitably result in apocalyptic loss of life. Nuclear winter is based on shaky science. There’s no reliable model that can determine how many megatons would decimate agriculture or make humans extinct. Nations have already detonated 2,476 nuc es humans can survive and recover from war, probably even a nuclear one. Humans cannot recover from runaway climate change. Nuclear war is not an inevitable extinction event; warming is | nuclear exchange does not result in apocalyptic loss of life. Nuclear winter is based on shaky science. There’s no reliable model that can determine how many megatons would make humans extinct. Nations have already detonated 2,476 nuc s humans can survive and recover from war, even a nuclear one. Humans cannot recover from runaway climate change. Nuclear war is not an inevitable extinction event; warming is | A devastating fact of climate collapse is that there may be a silver lining to the mushroom cloud. First, it should be noted that a nuclear exchange does not inevitably result in apocalyptic loss of life. Nuclear winter—the idea that firestorms would make the earth uninhabitable—is based on shaky science. There’s no reliable model that can determine how many megatons would decimate agriculture or make humans extinct. Nations have already detonated 2,476 nuclear devices. An exchange that shuts down the global economy but stops short of human extinction may be the only blade realistically likely to cut the carbon knot we’re trapped within. It would decimate existing infrastructures, providing an opportunity to build new energy infrastructure and intervene in the current investments and subsidies keeping fossil fuels alive. In the near term, emissions would almost certainly rise as militaries are some of the world’s largest emitters. Given what we know of human history, though, conflict may be the only way to build the mass social cohesion necessary for undertaking the kind of huge, collective action needed for global sequestration and energy transition. Like the 20th century’s world wars, a nuclear exchange could serve as an economic leveler. It could provide justification for nationalizing energy industries with the interest of shuttering fossil fuel plants and transitioning to renewables and, uh, nuclear energy. It could shock us into reimagining a less suicidal civilization, one that dethrones the death-cult zealots who are currently in power. And it may toss particulates into the atmosphere sufficient to block out some of the solar heat helping to drive global warming. Or it may have the opposite effects. Who knows? What we do know is that humans can survive and recover from war, probably even a nuclear one. Humans cannot recover from runaway climate change. Nuclear war is not an inevitable extinction event; six degrees of warming is. | 1,970 | <h4><u>Only</u> warming causes extinction</h4><p><strong>McDonald 19</strong>, Geography PhD student at University of Oxford studying the intersection of grassroots movements and energy transition. (Samuel Miller, 1-4-2019, “Deathly Salvation”, The Trouble, https://www.the-trouble.com/content/2019/1/4/deathly-salvation)</p><p>A devastating fact of climate collapse is that there may be a silver lining to the mushroom cloud. First, it should be noted that a <u><mark>nuclear exchange does not</mark> inevitably <mark>result in apocalyptic loss of life. Nuclear winter</u></mark>—the idea that firestorms would make the earth uninhabitable—<u><mark>is based on shaky science. There’s no reliable model that can determine how many megatons would</mark> decimate agriculture or <mark>make humans extinct. Nations have already detonated 2,476 nuc</u></mark>lear devic<u>e<mark>s</u></mark>. An exchange that shuts down the global economy but stops short of human extinction may be the only blade realistically likely to cut the carbon knot we’re trapped within. It would decimate existing infrastructures, providing an opportunity to build new energy infrastructure and intervene in the current investments and subsidies keeping fossil fuels alive. In the near term, emissions would almost certainly rise as militaries are some of the world’s largest emitters. Given what we know of human history, though, conflict may be the only way to build the mass social cohesion necessary for undertaking the kind of huge, collective action needed for global sequestration and energy transition. Like the 20th century’s world wars, a nuclear exchange could serve as an economic leveler. It could provide justification for nationalizing energy industries with the interest of shuttering fossil fuel plants and transitioning to renewables and, uh, nuclear energy. It could shock us into reimagining a less suicidal civilization, one that dethrones the death-cult zealots who are currently in power. And it may toss particulates into the atmosphere sufficient to block out some of the solar heat helping to drive global warming. Or it may have the opposite effects. Who knows? What we do know is that <u><mark>humans can survive and recover from war,</mark> probably <mark>even a nuclear one. Humans cannot recover from runaway climate change. Nuclear war is not an inevitable extinction event;</u></mark> six degrees of <u><mark>warming is</u></mark>.</p> | 1nr | Cap K | 2nc – ov – ontology | 7,678 | 340 | 134,114 | ./documents/ndtceda21/UTD/BeMu/UTD-Beutelspacher-Mubarak-Neg-00%20NDT-Round5.docx | 627,482 | N | 00 NDT | 5 | Wichita HP | Galloway, Strong, Aaronson | 1ac - coops
1nc -
civil rico cp
regs cp
states cp
cap k
t per se
doj da
ptx
2nr -
civil rico cp | ndtceda21/UTD/BeMu/UTD-Beutelspacher-Mubarak-Neg-00%20NDT-Round5.docx | null | 52,916 | BeMu | UTD BeMu | null | Du..... | Be..... | Ha..... | Mu..... | 19,424 | UTD | UTD | null | null | 1,011 | ndtceda21 | NDT/CEDA 2021-22 | 2,021 | cx | college | 2 |
1,044,943 | Solves global conflict. | Vakulchuk 20 | Roman Vakulchuk 20, PhD in economics, senior research fellow at the Norwegian Institute of International Affairs, and adjust professor at Nord University, “Renewable energy and geopolitics: A review,” 1/7/2020, Renewable And Sustainable Energy Reviews, https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S1364032119307555#!, cc | geopolitical tensions as less likely in a world that has renewables as its main source of energy it is more difficult to control, cut the supply or manipulate the price of renewable energy than of fossil fuels therefore lead to self-sufficiency and less conflict
renewables are more difficult than fossil fuels to manipulate due to its geographic and technical characteristics, renewable energy creates few geopolitical motivations for states to start conflicts in order to control it a more equitable energy distribution and energy-based economic power leading to reduced geopolitical tensions power will be more evenly distributed after a complete transition partnerships could “reduce economic imbalances and create global markets for technologies without having to fear conflicts over scarce resources
a resource scarcity perspective to the geopolitics of oil triggers aggressive behaviour This perspective is not simple to transpose onto renewables, as they are both non-exhaustible and abundant renewable energy reduce energy dependence and improve its security access to resources is less important than distribution and infrastructure management
if countries produce electricity from domestic renewable energy sources, geopolitical tensions and risks might recede geopolitical risks associated with domestically produced renewable energy are close to zero if we apply energy-security standards the consumption of renewable energy at the location of production will prevail over large-scale regional production and distribution
international affairs should benefit from renewables in many ways because their distribution will not be exposed “to strategic dilemmas wrought by dependence on hydrocarbons the use of hegemonic power to cut off transport bottlenecks will be greatly reduced due to increased rerouting possibilities, decentralised power generation and the absence of global electricity connections | tensions less likely in a world that has renewables it is difficult to manipulate therefore lead to self-sufficiency and less conflict
due to geographic characteristics, renewable energy reduce imbalances without conflicts over resources
resource scarcity to oil triggers aggressive behaviour
if countries produce domestic renewable sources tensions recede risks are zero
international affairs will not be exposed “to strategic dilemmas wrought by hydrocarbons | By contrast, the reduced conflict camp sees geopolitical tensions as less likely in a world that has renewables as its main source of energy (Peters [91], Verrastro et al. [92], Lacher and Kumetat [93], Kostyuk et al. [94], Escribano et al. [95], Johansson [96], Hoggett [97], Sweijs et al. [70], Månsson [72], Paltsev [98], Scholten and Bosman [54], Smith Stegen [99], Escribano [84], Freeman [85]). This camp emphasises that it is more difficult to control, cut the supply or manipulate the price of renewable energy than of fossil fuels and the expansion of renewables will therefore lead to greater energy self-sufficiency and less conflict. It shifts the focus from the external to the internal supply of energy, reducing the scope for conflict among states.
An argument frequently used by this camp is that renewables are more difficult than fossil fuels to manipulate as they are less dense and more evenly distributed geographically. Månsson [72] holds the view that due to its geographic and technical characteristics, renewable energy creates few geopolitical motivations for states to start conflicts in order to control it. Peters [91], Tsao et al. [100] and Kostyuk et al. [94] similarly note that developing renewable energy would lead to a more equitable energy distribution and energy-based economic power, in turn leading to reduced geopolitical tensions. Also Overland et al. [101] found that geopolitical power will be more evenly distributed after a complete transition to renewable energy. In a related vein, Krewitt et al. [61] argue that the creation of international solar energy partnerships would have geopolitical advantages because they could “reduce economic imbalances between the North and the South and create global markets for future-oriented energy technologies without having to fear conflicts over scarce resources” (p. 23).
The application of a resource scarcity perspective to the geopolitics of oil triggers energy-insecurity anxiety among states and implicitly or explicitly justifies aggressive behaviour in resource conflicts (Jaffe and Soligo [102], Stern [103]). This perspective is not simple to transpose onto renewables, as they are both non-exhaustible and abundant, except for the critical materials used in the production of renewable energy technologies (see Section 3.4 for more on this). Fischhendler et al. [104,105] exemplify how geopolitical arguments have been used to convince Israeli decision-makers to adopt renewable energy to reduce the country's energy dependence and improve its security. These arguments have led others to draw further conclusions. Compared to an energy system based on fossil fuels, in a system dominated by renewables, access to resources is less important than distribution and infrastructure management (Scholten and Bosman [54]). Escribano [84] implies the same when he writes that “[e]nergy dependence and security of supply lose geopolitical relevance, whereas technical and regulatory aspects gain weight” (p. 7).
Many publications share an understanding that the location of renewable energy resources is as important as that of fossil fuels (Skeet [106], Criekemans [67], Criekemans [107]). However, location as a geopolitical concern is mainly relevant for the large-scale and not for the small-scale domestically-oriented production and transmission of electricity from renewable energy. O'Sullivan et al. [75] argue that if renewable energy is deployed on a large scale and cross-border trade in electricity grows, then the principle of territorial control will be similar to that for oil and gas pipelines: “[c]ountries like Algeria, Mexico or Morocco, or transit countries, or actors such as the Islamic State, could still try to leverage their geographical position and in case of conflict they could threaten to interrupt electricity supplies” (p. 41). Several authors also ask whether an external supply of electricity can be used as an “energy weapon” (e.g. Escribano et al. [95]). Renewable energy infrastructure, such as the ambitious but failed Desertec project, can also be an easy target for terrorists (Smith Stegen et al. [108]). The same logic can be applied to the location of biofuels.
On the other hand, if countries produce electricity from domestic renewable energy sources, geopolitical tensions and risks might recede due to falling energy imports and reduced interdependence between countries (Strunz and Gawel [66]). Escribano et al. [95] and Scholten and Bosman [54] argue that the geopolitical risks associated with domestically produced renewable energy are close to zero if we apply the energy-security standards of IEA. Hoggett [97] similarly notes that small-scale photovoltaics (and nuclear power) technologies are likely to promote a secure low-carbon transition with reduced geopolitical risks. Some believe that it is likely that the consumption of renewable energy at the location of production will prevail over large-scale regional production and distribution as it is seen as much more efficient and cost-effective when compared to the long-distance distribution of electricity (Proedrou [109], Sovacool [110]). These authors therefore see geographical location as less important for renewable energy resources than for fossil fuels from a geopolitical perspective. Nevertheless, there is a risk of local conflicts involving non-state actors that could potentially be caused by increased global competition for the land required for renewable energy installations (Capellan-Perez et al. [82], Månsson [72], Johansson [96], Walker [111]).
One issue seems to be stuck between the two camps: new interdependencies among states as a result of electricity interconnectors. Hache [81] discusses the possible emergence of new and unfamiliar inter-state interdependencies. Similarly, Westphal and Droege [64] argue that more electricity interconnectors between countries will lead to greater interdependence, which may translate into reduced international security. Pierri et al. [112] examine this question in the context of the European Union. Konstantelos et al. [113] discuss the division of costs and benefits among members of an integrated North Sea grid, making it similar to the difficulties caused by major pipeline projects. By contrast, Smith Stegen [99] argues that international affairs should benefit from renewables in many ways because their distribution will not be exposed “to the political and strategic dilemmas wrought by dependence on hydrocarbons” (p. 92). In a similar vein, IRENA [76] notes that electricity cut-offs and the use of hegemonic power to cut off transport bottlenecks will be greatly reduced due to increased rerouting possibilities, decentralised power generation and the absence of global electricity connections. But Smith Stegen [99] acknowledges that some tensions are possible due to increased interdependencies in such areas as high-voltage direct current (HVDC) transmission lines, biofuels and rare earth elements. Similarly, Verrastro et al. [92] and Lacher and Kumetat [93] see that renewable energy may strengthen energy security while facilitating the emergence of new interdependencies among states. | 7,176 | <h4>Solves <u>global conflict</u><strong>.</h4><p></strong>Roman <strong>Vakulchuk 20</strong>, PhD in economics, senior research fellow at the Norwegian Institute of International Affairs, and adjust professor at Nord University, “Renewable energy and geopolitics: A review,” 1/7/2020, Renewable And Sustainable Energy Reviews, https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S1364032119307555#!, cc</p><p>By contrast, the reduced conflict camp sees <u><strong>geopolitical <mark>tensions</strong></mark> as <strong><mark>less likely</strong> in a world that has renewables</mark> as its <strong>main source of energy</u></strong> (Peters [91], Verrastro et al. [92], Lacher and Kumetat [93], Kostyuk et al. [94], Escribano et al. [95], Johansson [96], Hoggett [97], Sweijs et al. [70], Månsson [72], Paltsev [98], Scholten and Bosman [54], Smith Stegen [99], Escribano [84], Freeman [85]). This camp emphasises that <u><mark>it is</mark> more <strong><mark>difficult to</mark> control</strong>, cut the <strong>supply</strong> or <strong><mark>manipulate</mark> the price</strong> of renewable energy than of fossil fuels</u> and the expansion of renewables will<u> <mark>therefore lead to</u></mark> greater energy <u><strong><mark>self-sufficiency</strong> and <strong>less conflict</u></strong></mark>. It shifts the focus from the external to the internal supply of energy, reducing the scope for conflict among states.</p><p>An argument frequently used by this camp is that <u>renewables are <strong>more difficult</strong> than fossil fuels to manipulate </u>as they are less dense and more evenly distributed geographically. Månsson [72] holds the view that <u><mark>due to</mark> its <strong><mark>geographic</strong></mark> and <strong>technical <mark>characteristics</strong>, renewable energy</mark> creates <strong>few geopolitical motivations</strong> for states to <strong>start conflicts</strong> in order to control it</u>. Peters [91], Tsao et al. [100] and Kostyuk et al. [94] similarly note that developing renewable energy would lead to <u>a more equitable energy distribution and energy-based economic power</u>, in turn <u>leading to reduced geopolitical tensions</u>. Also Overland et al. [101] found that geopolitical <u>power will be more evenly distributed after a complete transition</u> to renewable energy. In a related vein, Krewitt et al. [61] argue that the creation of international solar energy <u>partnerships</u> would have geopolitical advantages because they <u>could “<mark>reduce</mark> <strong>economic <mark>imbalances</u></strong></mark> between the North and the South <u>and create <strong>global markets</strong> for</u> future-oriented energy <u>technologies <mark>without</mark> having to fear <strong><mark>conflicts</strong> over</mark> <strong>scarce <mark>resources</u></strong></mark>” (p. 23).</p><p>The application of <u>a <strong><mark>resource scarcity</mark> perspective</strong> <mark>to</mark> the <strong>geopolitics of <mark>oil</strong> triggers</u></mark> energy-insecurity anxiety among states and implicitly or explicitly justifies <u><strong><mark>aggressive behaviour</u></strong></mark> in resource conflicts (Jaffe and Soligo [102], Stern [103]). <u>This perspective is not simple to <strong>transpose onto renewables</strong>, as they are both <strong>non-exhaustible</strong> and <strong>abundant</u></strong>, except for the critical materials used in the production of renewable energy technologies (see Section 3.4 for more on this). Fischhendler et al. [104,105] exemplify how geopolitical arguments have been used to convince Israeli decision-makers to adopt <u>renewable energy</u> to <u>reduce</u> the country's <u><strong>energy dependence</strong> and improve its <strong>security</u></strong>. These arguments have led others to draw further conclusions. Compared to an energy system based on fossil fuels, in a system dominated by renewables, <u>access to resources is less important than distribution and infrastructure management</u> (Scholten and Bosman [54]). Escribano [84] implies the same when he writes that “[e]nergy dependence and security of supply lose geopolitical relevance, whereas technical and regulatory aspects gain weight” (p. 7).</p><p>Many publications share an understanding that the location of renewable energy resources is as important as that of fossil fuels (Skeet [106], Criekemans [67], Criekemans [107]). However, location as a geopolitical concern is mainly relevant for the large-scale and not for the small-scale domestically-oriented production and transmission of electricity from renewable energy. O'Sullivan et al. [75] argue that if renewable energy is deployed on a large scale and cross-border trade in electricity grows, then the principle of territorial control will be similar to that for oil and gas pipelines: “[c]ountries like Algeria, Mexico or Morocco, or transit countries, or actors such as the Islamic State, could still try to leverage their geographical position and in case of conflict they could threaten to interrupt electricity supplies” (p. 41). Several authors also ask whether an external supply of electricity can be used as an “energy weapon” (e.g. Escribano et al. [95]). Renewable energy infrastructure, such as the ambitious but failed Desertec project, can also be an easy target for terrorists (Smith Stegen et al. [108]). The same logic can be applied to the location of biofuels.</p><p>On the other hand, <u><mark>if countries produce</mark> electricity from <strong><mark>domestic renewable</mark> energy <mark>sources</strong></mark>, <strong>geopolitical <mark>tensions</strong></mark> and risks might <strong><mark>recede</u></strong></mark> due to falling energy imports and reduced interdependence between countries (Strunz and Gawel [66]). Escribano et al. [95] and Scholten and Bosman [54] argue that the <u><strong>geopolitical <mark>risks</strong></mark> associated with domestically produced renewable energy <mark>are</mark> close to <strong><mark>zero</strong></mark> if we apply</u> the <u>energy-security standards</u> of IEA. Hoggett [97] similarly notes that small-scale photovoltaics (and nuclear power) technologies are likely to promote a secure low-carbon transition with reduced geopolitical risks. Some believe that it is likely that <u>the consumption of renewable energy at the <strong>location of production</strong> will prevail over large-scale regional <strong>production and distribution</u></strong> as it is seen as much more efficient and cost-effective when compared to the long-distance distribution of electricity (Proedrou [109], Sovacool [110]). These authors therefore see geographical location as less important for renewable energy resources than for fossil fuels from a geopolitical perspective. Nevertheless, there is a risk of local conflicts involving non-state actors that could potentially be caused by increased global competition for the land required for renewable energy installations (Capellan-Perez et al. [82], Månsson [72], Johansson [96], Walker [111]).</p><p>One issue seems to be stuck between the two camps: new interdependencies among states as a result of electricity interconnectors. Hache [81] discusses the possible emergence of new and unfamiliar inter-state interdependencies. Similarly, Westphal and Droege [64] argue that more electricity interconnectors between countries will lead to greater interdependence, which may translate into reduced international security. Pierri et al. [112] examine this question in the context of the European Union. Konstantelos et al. [113] discuss the division of costs and benefits among members of an integrated North Sea grid, making it similar to the difficulties caused by major pipeline projects. By contrast, Smith Stegen [99] argues that <u><strong><mark>international affairs</strong></mark> should benefit from renewables in many ways because their distribution <mark>will not be exposed “to</u></mark> the political and <u><strong><mark>strategic dilemmas</u></strong> <u>wrought by</mark> <strong>dependence on <mark>hydrocarbons</u></strong></mark>” (p. 92). In a similar vein, IRENA [76] notes that electricity cut-offs and <u>the use of <strong>hegemonic power</strong> to cut off <strong>transport bottlenecks</strong> will be <strong>greatly reduced</strong> due to increased <strong>rerouting possibilities</strong>, <strong>decentralised power generation</strong> and the absence of <strong>global electricity connections</u></strong>. But Smith Stegen [99] acknowledges that some tensions are possible due to increased interdependencies in such areas as high-voltage direct current (HVDC) transmission lines, biofuels and rare earth elements. Similarly, Verrastro et al. [92] and Lacher and Kumetat [93] see that renewable energy may strengthen energy security while facilitating the emergence of new interdependencies among states.</p> | 1AC – Original Jurisdiction | 1AC – Equitable Apportionment | null | 33,680 | 204 | 25,267 | ./documents/hspolicy21/Bellarmine/MaTa/Bellarmine-Manens-Talur-Aff-ASU-Round3.docx | 743,991 | A | ASU | 3 | Damien DL | Young Park | 1AC - Original Jurisdiction v3
2NR - Security K | hspolicy21/Bellarmine/MaTa/Bellarmine-Manens-Talur-Aff-ASU-Round3.docx | null | 63,368 | MaTa | Bellarmine MaTa | null | Be..... | Ma..... | Ni..... | Ta..... | 21,887 | Bellarmine | Bellarmine | CA | null | 1,020 | hspolicy21 | HS Policy 2021-22 | 2,021 | cx | hs | 2 |
1,091,612 | Protection means ‘permitting’ not ‘prevention’ | COLANGELO, 20 | VICTORIA COLANGELO, 20 – legal expert on mitigation banks and CWA section 404 permitting, former President of the Florida Association of Mitigation Bankers, CEO of the Mitigation Banking Group Inc., and appointee to the Seminole County Parks and Preservation Advisory Committee. **A mitigation bank is a type of aquatic resource area established under the CWA for the purpose of providing compensation for resources permitted under Section 404. (“THE NAVIGABLE WATERS PROTECTION RULE UPDATE” JULY 6, 2020, https://mitigationbankinginc.com/navigable-waters-protection-rule-update-by-victoria-colangelo/ //DH | Under the (CWA), “protection” does not mean “prevention” of development, it means “permitting”, because landowners planning projects that impact waters” must first get approval Landowners have to reduce impacts and then mitigate for wetland loss | Under the (CWA), “protection” does not mean “prevention” it means “permitting”, because landowners planning projects that impact waters” must first get approval Landowners have to reduce impacts | Under the Clean Water Act (CWA), “protection” does not mean “prevention” of development, it means “permitting”, because landowners planning for projects that impact “navigable waters” must first get approval from The Army Corps of Engineers (ACOE) and/or a state agency. Landowners have to reduce impacts and then mitigate for wetland loss by restoring wetlands of equal or greater hydrologic value by purchasing mitigation credits, doing on-site or off-site mitigation. | 470 | <h4><strong>Protection means ‘permitting’ not ‘prevention’ </h4><p></strong>VICTORIA <strong>COLANGELO, 20 </strong>– legal expert on mitigation banks and CWA section 404 permitting, former President of the Florida Association of Mitigation Bankers, CEO of the Mitigation Banking Group Inc., and appointee to the Seminole County Parks and Preservation Advisory Committee. **A mitigation bank is a type of aquatic resource area established under the CWA for the purpose of providing compensation for resources permitted under Section 404. (“THE NAVIGABLE WATERS PROTECTION RULE UPDATE” JULY 6, 2020, https://mitigationbankinginc.com/navigable-waters-protection-rule-update-by-victoria-colangelo/ //DH</p><p><u><mark>Under the</u></mark> Clean Water Act <u><mark>(CWA), “protection” does not mean “prevention”</mark> of development, <mark>it means “permitting”, because landowners planning</u></mark> for <u><mark>projects</u> <u>that impact</u></mark> “navigable <u><mark>waters” must first get approval</mark> </u>from The Army Corps of Engineers (ACOE) and/or a state agency. <u><mark>Landowners have to reduce impacts</mark> and then mitigate for wetland loss</u><strong> by restoring wetlands of equal or greater hydrologic value by purchasing mitigation credits, doing on-site or off-site mitigation.</p></strong> | 1NC | OFF | 1NC---OFF | 1,240,549 | 228 | 25,983 | ./documents/hspolicy21/CalvertHall/LoSa/Calvert%20Hall-Lobo-Sanico-Neg-09%20-%20Harvard-Round5.docx | 744,963 | N | 09 - Harvard | 5 | MBA CP | Jason Young | 1AC - Nukes
1NC - T Cessation State Bargaining CP ADV CP EPA DA Filibuster DA ECA Security K Dedev Case
2NC - Dedev Case
1NR - Security K
2NR - Security K Case | hspolicy21/CalvertHall/LoSa/Calvert%20Hall-Lobo-Sanico-Neg-09%20-%20Harvard-Round5.docx | null | 63,452 | LoSa | Calvert Hall LoSa | null | Lu..... | Lo..... | Da..... | Sa..... | 21,905 | CalvertHall | Calvert Hall | MD | null | 1,020 | hspolicy21 | HS Policy 2021-22 | 2,021 | cx | hs | 2 |
4,136,760 | No food wars | Vestby 18 | Jonas Vestby 18, Doctoral Researcher at the Peace Research Institute Oslo, Ida Rudolfsen, doctoral researcher at the Department of Peace and Conflict Research at Uppsala University and PRIO, and Halvard Buhaug, Research Professor at the Peace Research Institute Oslo (PRIO); Professor of Political Science at the Norwegian University of Science and Technology (NTNU); and Associate Editor of the Journal of Peace Research and Political Geography, “Does hunger cause conflict?”, 5/18/18, https://blogs.prio.org/ClimateAndConflict/2018/05/does-hunger-cause-conflict/] | there is little scholarly merit in the notion that a short-term reduction in access to food increases the probability that conflict will break out. to start or participate in violent conflict requires people to have both the means and the will. Most people on the brink of starvation are not in the position to resort to violence, whether against the government or other social groups the urban middle classes tend to be the most likely to protest against rises in food prices, since they often have the best opportunities, the most energy, and the best skills to coordinate and participate in protests.
there is a widespread misapprehension that social unrest in periods of high food prices relates primarily to food shortages sources of discontent are considerably more complex – linked to political structures, land ownership, corruption, the desire for democratic reforms and general economic problems – where the price of food is seen in the context of general increases in the cost of living | little scholarly merit that a reduction food increases probability conflict break out to start conflict requires means and will people on the brink of starvation are not in the position to resort
widespread misapprehension social unrest in periods of high prices relates to shortages sources of discontent are more complex political structures, land corruption democratic reforms and economic problems | It is perhaps surprising, then, that there is little scholarly merit in the notion that a short-term reduction in access to food increases the probability that conflict will break out. This is because to start or participate in violent conflict requires people to have both the means and the will. Most people on the brink of starvation are not in the position to resort to violence, whether against the government or other social groups. In fact, the urban middle classes tend to be the most likely to protest against rises in food prices, since they often have the best opportunities, the most energy, and the best skills to coordinate and participate in protests.
Accordingly, there is a widespread misapprehension that social unrest in periods of high food prices relates primarily to food shortages. In reality, the sources of discontent are considerably more complex – linked to political structures, land ownership, corruption, the desire for democratic reforms and general economic problems – where the price of food is seen in the context of general increases in the cost of living. Research has shown that while the international media have a tendency to seek simple resource-related explanations – such as drought or famine – for conflicts in the Global South, debates in the local media are permeated by more complex political relationships. | 1,353 | <h4>No food wars</h4><p>Jonas <strong>Vestby 18</strong>, Doctoral Researcher at the Peace Research Institute Oslo, Ida Rudolfsen, doctoral researcher at the Department of Peace and Conflict Research at Uppsala University and PRIO, and Halvard Buhaug, Research Professor at the Peace Research Institute Oslo (PRIO); Professor of Political Science at the Norwegian University of Science and Technology (NTNU); and Associate Editor of the Journal of Peace Research and Political Geography, “Does hunger cause conflict?”, 5/18/18, https://blogs.prio.org/ClimateAndConflict/2018/05/does-hunger-cause-conflict/]</p><p>It is perhaps surprising, then, that <u>there is</u> <u><strong><mark>little scholarly merit</u></strong></mark> <u>in the notion</u> <u><mark>that a</u></mark> <u>short-term</u> <u><mark>reduction</u></mark> <u>in access to</u> <u><strong><mark>food increases</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>the</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>probability</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>that</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>conflict</u></strong></mark> <u>will</u> <u><mark>break out</mark>.</u> This is because <u><mark>to start</u></mark> <u>or participate in violent</u> <u><mark>conflict requires</u></mark> <u>people to have both the</u> <u><mark>means and</u></mark> <u>the</u> <u><mark>will</mark>. Most</u> <u><mark>people on the</u> <u><strong>brink of starvation are not in the position to resort</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>to violence</strong>, whether against the government or other social groups</u>. In fact, <u>the urban middle classes tend to be the most likely to protest against rises in food prices, since they often have the best opportunities, the most energy, and the best skills to coordinate and participate in protests.</p><p></u>Accordingly, <u>there is a</u> <u><strong><mark>widespread misapprehension</u></strong></mark> <u>that</u> <u><mark>social unrest in periods of high</u></mark> <u>food</u> <u><mark>prices relates</u></mark> <u>primarily</u> <u><mark>to</u></mark> <u>food</u> <u><mark>shortages</u></mark>. In reality, the <u><mark>sources of discontent are</u></mark> <u>considerably</u> <u><strong><mark>more complex</u></strong></mark> <u>– linked to</u> <u><strong><mark>political structures</strong>,</u> <u><strong>land</u></strong></mark> <u>ownership,</u> <u><strong><mark>corruption</strong></mark>, the desire for</u> <u><strong><mark>democratic reforms</u></strong> <u>and</u></mark> <u>general</u> <u><strong><mark>economic problems</u></strong></mark> <u>– where the price of food is seen in the context of general increases in the cost of living</u>. Research has shown that while the international media have a tendency to seek simple resource-related explanations – such as drought or famine – for conflicts in the Global South, debates in the local media are permeated by more complex political relationships.</p> | 1NC | Case | Disease | 6,854 | 1,148 | 142,139 | ./documents/hsld22/Harker/AnSh/Harker-AnSh-Neg-greenhill-Round-4.docx | 926,066 | N | Greenhill Fall Classic | 4 | basis jk | lukas krause | 1ac - telehealth
1nc - cp-disease da-trust da-eca cp-cil
1ar - condo bad alt agent fiat bad wipeout
2nr - all
2ar - condo | hsld22/Harker/AnSh/Harker-AnSh-Neg-greenhill-Round-4.docx | 2023-04-14 13:25:13 | 80,998 | AnSh | Harker AnSh | null | An..... | Sh..... | null | null | 26,565 | Harker | Harker | CA | null | 2,003 | hsld22 | HS LD 2022-23 | 2,022 | ld | hs | 1 |
4,741,136 | FMP is crucial for African integration and rejecting harmful colonial borders. | Hirsch 21 | Hirsch 21 [Alan Hirsch (Professor of Development Policy and Practice at The Nelson Mandela School of Public Governance at University of Cape Town), “The African Union’s Free Movement of Persons Protocol: Why has it faltered and how can its objectives be achieved?”, South African Journal of International Affairs, 28:4, 497-517, (2021). DOI: 10.1080/10220461.2021.2007788] CT | The FMP Protocol explains its rationale:
the free movement of persons, capital goods and services will promote integration, Pan- Africanism, enhance science, technology, education, research and foster tourism, facilitate inter-African trade and investment, increase remittances within Africa, promote mobility of labour, create employment, improve the standards of living of the people of Africa and facili- tate the mobilization and utilization of the human and material resources of Africa in order to achieve self-reliance and development ... .4
As Stephen Gelb and Aarti Krishnan have shown, the developmental rationale is broadly supported in the literature.5 Most modern African borders derive from the scramble for Africa era of colonialism when the European powers’ lust for foreign land and resources resulted in African terri- torial borders drawn conveniently only for the colonial project. Colonial boundaries sliced through economic regions and ethnic groups. Another outcome was fragmentation of the continent into many territories, most relatively small. One of Pan-Africanism’s focal points is the right of Africans to cross national borders within the continent without undue restrictions In 1991 in Abuja, when the focus of the Organisation of African Unity (OAU) shifted from liberation to economic integration, African countries committed to the establish- ment of an African economic community. The African Economic Community Treaty, commonly known as the Abuja Treaty, officially came into force in 1994. The free movement of persons, rights of residence and rights of establishment by Africans across the borders of AU member states are included in Article 4(2)(i) of that treaty. he Constitutive Act of the African Union in 2001 carried over the mandate from the OAU, and in 2006 in Bangui, a Migration Policy Framework for Africa was endorsed by AU members – this framework also included the right to gainful employment across African borders.8 Africa’s Agenda 2063, adopted by the AU in 2013, has ‘The African Passport and the free movement of people’ as one of its 11 flagship projects In 2017 the Peace and Security Council of the AU acknowledged that the benefits of free movement of Africans across African borders outweighed the real and imagined economic and secur- ity challenges that such a reform might pose.11 Finally, in January 2018, the Free Movement of Persons Protocol to the AEC treaty was signed by most AU heads of state at the AU summit.12 It was accompanied by an implementation ‘roadmap’ | the free movement of persons will promote Pan- Africanism self-reliance and development
modern African borders derive from the European colonial project Colonial boundaries sliced through economic regions and ethnic groups One of Pan-Africanism’s focal points is the right of Africans to cross national borders within the continent without undue restrictions | The FMP Protocol explains its rationale:
... the free movement of persons, capital goods and services will promote integration, Pan- Africanism, enhance science, technology, education, research and foster tourism, facilitate inter-African trade and investment, increase remittances within Africa, promote mobility of labour, create employment, improve the standards of living of the people of Africa and facili- tate the mobilization and utilization of the human and material resources of Africa in order to achieve self-reliance and development ... .4
As Stephen Gelb and Aarti Krishnan have shown, the developmental rationale is broadly supported in the literature.5 Most modern African borders derive from the scramble for Africa era of colonialism when the European powers’ lust for foreign land and resources resulted in African terri- torial borders drawn conveniently only for the colonial project. Colonial boundaries sliced through economic regions and ethnic groups. Another outcome was fragmentation of the continent into many territories, most relatively small.6 One of Pan-Africanism’s focal points is the right of Africans to cross national borders within the continent without undue restrictions.7 In 1991 in Abuja, when the focus of the Organisation of African Unity (OAU) shifted from liberation to economic integration, African countries committed to the establish- ment of an African economic community. The African Economic Community Treaty, commonly known as the Abuja Treaty, officially came into force in 1994. The free movement of persons, rights of residence and rights of establishment by Africans across the borders of AU member states are included in Article 4(2)(i) of that treaty. The Constitutive Act of the African Union in 2001 carried over the mandate from the OAU, and in 2006 in Bangui, a Migration Policy Framework for Africa was endorsed by AU members – this framework also included the right to gainful employment across African borders.8 Africa’s Agenda 2063, adopted by the AU in 2013, has ‘The African Passport and the free movement of people’ as one of its 11 flagship projects.9 In 2016 in Kigali, Rwanda, the African Passport was launched.10 It is meant to facilitate the free movement of people on the continent, though the take-up is slow. In 2017 the Peace and Security Council of the AU acknowledged that the benefits of free movement of Africans across African borders outweighed the real and imagined economic and secur- ity challenges that such a reform might pose.11 Finally, in January 2018, the Free Movement of Persons Protocol to the AEC treaty was signed by most AU heads of state at the AU summit.12 It was accompanied by an implementation ‘roadmap’.13 A revised version, in the form of the Migration Policy Frame- work for Africa, was issued by the AU Commission in May 2018. It too had an implemen- tation plan calibrated against a timeframe. | 2,903 | <h4>FMP is crucial for African integration and rejecting harmful colonial borders. </h4><p><strong>Hirsch 21</strong> [Alan Hirsch (Professor of Development Policy and Practice at The Nelson Mandela School of Public Governance at University of Cape Town), “The African Union’s Free Movement of Persons Protocol: Why has it faltered and how can its objectives be achieved?”, South African Journal of International Affairs, 28:4, 497-517, (2021). DOI: 10.1080/10220461.2021.2007788] CT</p><p><u>The FMP Protocol explains its rationale:</p><p></u>... <u><mark>the free movement of persons</mark>, capital goods and services <mark>will promote</mark> integration, <mark>Pan- Africanism</mark>, enhance science, technology, education, research and foster tourism, facilitate inter-African trade and investment, increase remittances within Africa, promote mobility of labour, create employment, improve the standards of living of the people of Africa and facili- tate the mobilization and utilization of the human and material resources of Africa in order to achieve <mark>self-reliance and development</mark> ... .4</p><p>As Stephen Gelb and Aarti Krishnan have shown, the developmental rationale is broadly supported in the literature.5 Most <mark>modern African borders derive from</mark> the scramble for Africa era of colonialism when <mark>the</mark> <mark>European</mark> powers’ lust for foreign land and resources resulted in African terri- torial borders drawn conveniently only for the <mark>colonial project</mark>. <mark>Colonial boundaries sliced through economic regions and ethnic groups</mark>. Another outcome was fragmentation of the continent into many territories, most relatively small.</u>6 <u><strong><mark>One of Pan-Africanism’s focal points is the right of Africans to cross national borders within the continent without undue restrictions</u></strong></mark>.7 <u>In 1991 in Abuja, when the focus of the Organisation of African Unity (OAU) shifted from liberation to economic integration, African countries committed to the establish- ment of an African economic community. The African Economic Community Treaty, commonly known as the Abuja Treaty, officially came into force in 1994. The free movement of persons, rights of residence and rights of establishment by Africans across the borders of AU member states are included in Article 4(2)(i) of that treaty. </u>T<u>he Constitutive Act of the African Union in 2001 carried over the mandate from the OAU, and in 2006 in Bangui, a Migration Policy Framework for Africa was endorsed by AU members – this framework also included the right to gainful employment across African borders.8 Africa’s Agenda 2063, adopted by the AU in 2013, has ‘The African Passport and the free movement of people’ as one of its 11 flagship projects</u>.9 In 2016 in Kigali, Rwanda, the African Passport was launched.10 It is meant to facilitate the free movement of people on the continent, though the take-up is slow. <u>In 2017 the Peace and Security Council of the AU acknowledged that the benefits of free movement of Africans across African borders outweighed the real and imagined economic and secur- ity challenges that such a reform might pose.11 Finally, in January 2018, the Free Movement of Persons Protocol to the AEC treaty was signed by most AU heads of state at the AU summit.12 It was accompanied by an implementation ‘roadmap’</u>.13 A revised version, in the form of the Migration Policy Frame- work for Africa, was issued by the AU Commission in May 2018. It too had an implemen- tation plan calibrated against a timeframe.</p> | AC | AC Shell | Colonialism | 1,704,178 | 193 | 165,658 | ./documents/hsld22/Marlborough/LuSa/Marlborough-LuSa-Aff-Harvard-Westlake-Debates-All-Rounds.docx | 966,082 | A | Harvard Westlake Debates | All | null | null | null | hsld22/Marlborough/LuSa/Marlborough-LuSa-Aff-Harvard-Westlake-Debates-All-Rounds.docx | 2023-01-21 19:31:44 | 81,673 | LuSa | Marlborough LuSa | null | Lu..... | Sa..... | null | null | 26,925 | Marlborough | Marlborough | CA | null | 2,003 | hsld22 | HS LD 2022-23 | 2,022 | ld | hs | 1 |
3,522,304 | Infectious diseases don’t cause extinction | Barratt 17 | Owen Cotton-Barratt 17, et al, PhD in Pure Mathematics, Oxford, Lecturer in Mathematics at Oxford, Research Associate at the Future of Humanity Institute, 2/3/2017, Existential Risk: Diplomacy and Governance, https://www.fhi.ox.ac.uk/wp-content/uploads/Existential-Risks-2017-01-23.pdf | natural pandemics are very unlikely to cause human extinction. of the 833 recorded plant and animal species extinctions known to have occurred since 1500, less than 4% (31 species) were ascribed to infectious disease None of the mammals and amphibians on this list were globally dispersed, and other factors aside from infectious disease also contributed to their extinction. It seems that our own species, which is very numerous, globally dispersed, and capable of a rational response to problems, is very unlikely to be killed off by a natural pandemic.
that highly lethal pathogens can kill their hosts before they have a chance to spread there is a selective pressure for pathogens not to be highly lethal | natural pandemics are unlikely to cause extinction. of 833 plant and animal extinctions since 1500, less than 4% were ascribed to infectious disease. our species is very numerous, globally dispersed, and capable of a rational response very unlikely to be killed by a pandemic.
highly lethal pathogens can kill hosts before they spread there is a selective pressure for pathogens not to be lethal | For most of human history, natural pandemics have posed the greatest risk of mass global fatalities.37 However, there are some reasons to believe that natural pandemics are very unlikely to cause human extinction. Analysis of the International Union for Conservation of Nature (IUCN) red list database has shown that of the 833 recorded plant and animal species extinctions known to have occurred since 1500, less than 4% (31 species) were ascribed to infectious disease.38 None of the mammals and amphibians on this list were globally dispersed, and other factors aside from infectious disease also contributed to their extinction. It therefore seems that our own species, which is very numerous, globally dispersed, and capable of a rational response to problems, is very unlikely to be killed off by a natural pandemic.
One underlying explanation for this is that highly lethal pathogens can kill their hosts before they have a chance to spread, so there is a selective pressure for pathogens not to be highly lethal. Therefore, pathogens are likely to co-evolve with their hosts rather than kill all possible hosts.39 | 1,121 | <h4>Infectious diseases don’t cause extinction </h4><p>Owen Cotton-<strong>Barratt 17</strong>, et al, PhD in Pure Mathematics, Oxford, Lecturer in Mathematics at Oxford, Research Associate at the Future of Humanity Institute, 2/3/2017, Existential Risk: Diplomacy and Governance, https://www.fhi.ox.ac.uk/wp-content/uploads/Existential-Risks-2017-01-23.pdf</p><p>For most of human history, natural pandemics have posed the greatest risk of mass global fatalities.37 However, there are some reasons to believe that<u> <mark>natural pandemics are</mark> <strong>very <mark>unlikely to cause </mark>human <mark>extinction</strong>.</u></mark> Analysis of the International Union for Conservation of Nature (IUCN) red list database has shown that<u> <mark>of</mark> the <mark>833</mark> recorded <mark>plant and animal</mark> species <mark>extinctions</mark> known to have occurred <mark>since 1500, <strong>less than 4%</strong></mark> (31 species) <mark>were ascribed to infectious disease</u>.</mark>38 <u>None of the mammals and amphibians on this list were globally dispersed, and other factors aside from infectious disease also contributed to their extinction.</u> <u>It </u>therefore <u>seems that <mark>our</mark> own <mark>species</mark>, which <mark>is <strong>very numerous</strong>, <strong>globally dispersed</strong>, and capable of a <strong>rational response</mark> to problems</strong>, is <mark>very unlikely to be killed</mark> off <mark>by a</mark> natural <mark>pandemic.</p><p></u></mark>One underlying explanation for this is <u>that <mark>highly lethal pathogens can kill</mark> their <mark>hosts before they</mark> have a chance to <mark>spread</u></mark>, so <u><mark>there is a <strong>selective pressure for pathogens not to be</mark> highly <mark>lethal</u></strong></mark>. Therefore, pathogens are likely to co-evolve with their hosts rather than kill all possible hosts.39</p> | 1NC | null | Coverage Advantage | 2,356 | 2,146 | 116,574 | ./documents/ndtceda17/Northwestern/CaEs/Northwestern-Callahan-Esman-Neg-ADA-Semis.docx | 599,616 | N | ADA | Semis | Minnesota AL | Bricker, Viveth, Lastovica | 1AC - Single Payer
1NC - Medicaid Federalism DA - Midterms DA - France DA - Medicare Part E CP - Economy Turns - Case
2NC - Medicare Part E CP - Case
1NR - Economy Turns
2NR - Economy Turns | ndtceda17/Northwestern/CaEs/Northwestern-Callahan-Esman-Neg-ADA-Semis.docx | null | 51,028 | CaEs | Northwestern CaEs | null | Ch..... | Ca..... | Pa..... | Es..... | 19,135 | Northwestern | Northwestern | null | null | 1,007 | ndtceda17 | NDT/CEDA 2017-18 | 2,017 | cx | college | 2 |
1,384,755 | Its is possessive and refers to the party preceding its use—the USFG | US District Court 7 | US District Court 7
(United States District Court for the District of the Virgin Islands, Division of St. Thomas and St. John, “AGF Marine Aviation & Transp. v. Cassin, 2007 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 90808,” Lexis)//BB | the word "its." The possessive pronoun intended to refer to the party preceding its use | "its." The possessive pronoun intended to refer to the party preceding its use- | The Court inadvertently used the word "his" when the Court intended to use the word "its." The possessive pronoun was intended to refer to the party preceding its use--AGF. Indeed, that reference is consistent with the undisputed facts in this case, which indicate that Cassin completed an application for the insurance policy and submitted it to his agent, Theodore Tunick & Company ("Tunick"). Tunick, in turn, submitted the application to AGF's underwriting agent, TL Dallas. (See Pl.'s Mem. of Law in Supp. of Mot. for Summ. J. 5.) | 535 | <h4>Its is possessive and refers to the party preceding its use—<strong>the USFG</h4><p>US District Court 7</p><p></strong>(United States District Court for the District of the Virgin Islands, Division of St. Thomas and St. John, “AGF Marine Aviation & Transp. v. Cassin, 2007 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 90808,” Lexis)//BB</p><p>The Court inadvertently used the word "his" when the Court intended to use <u>the word <mark>"its."</u> <u>The possessive pronoun</u></mark> was <u><mark>intended to refer to the party preceding its use</u>-</mark>-AGF. Indeed, that reference is consistent with the undisputed facts in this case, which indicate that Cassin completed an application for the insurance policy and submitted it to his agent, Theodore Tunick & Company ("Tunick"). Tunick, in turn, submitted the application to AGF's underwriting agent, TL Dallas. (See Pl.'s Mem. of Law in Supp. of Mot. for Summ. J. 5.)</p> | 1NC | L E T S G O B O Y S | 2 | 14,895 | 271 | 36,647 | ./documents/hspolicy14/Edgemont/XuKo/Edgemont-Xu-Kohli-Neg-TOC-Round7.docx | 631,145 | N | TOC | 7 | Westminster FG | Donnie Grasse | 1AC
Offshore Aquaculture Regulations
Environment Advantage
1NC
Anthropocene K
T - Regulations
Queer Disability K
Case
Post-Politics K
Biodiversity Militarization K
Biological Carcasses K
Queer Ecology K
Scientific Objectivity K
2NR
Queer Disability K
Case Defense | hspolicy14/Edgemont/XuKo/Edgemont-Xu-Kohli-Neg-TOC-Round7.docx | null | 53,291 | XuKo | Edgemont XuKo | null | Al..... | Xu..... | Vi..... | Ko..... | 19,525 | Edgemont | Edgemont | null | null | 1,013 | hspolicy14 | HS Policy 2014-15 | 2,014 | cx | hs | 2 |
641,393 | 3. The 1AC isn’t reformism – it doesn’t conflate change with progress or validate legal institutions – it’s a tactical intervention that reduces violence while exposing the contradictions within law. | Spade 13 | Spade 13 [Dean Spade, associate professor of law @ Seattle University, “Intersectional Resistance and Law Reform” Signs Vol. 38, No. 4, Summer 2013] | Social movements using critical intersectional tools are making demands that are often difficult for legal scholars to comprehend because of the ways that they throw US law into crisis Because they recognize that legal equality contains and neutralizes resistance and perpetuates intersectional violence and because they identify purportedly neutral administrative systems as key vectors of that violence These kinds of demands and the analysis they represent produce a different relation to law reform strategies than the national narrative about law reform and equality legal equality “victories” are being exposed as primarily symbolic declarations violence Instead, law reform, in this view, might be used as a tactic of transformation focused on interventions that materially reduce violence or maldistribution without inadvertently expanding harmful systems in the name of reform. One recent example is the campaign against gang injunctions in Oakland succeeded
Furthermore, the coalition frames its campaign within a larger set of demands not limited to what can be won within the current structure of American law but focused on population-level conditions of maldistribution. The demands include stopping all gang injunctions and police violence; putting resources toward reentry support and services for people returning from prison, including fully funded and immediate access to identity documents, housing, job training, drug and alcohol treatment, and education; banning employers from asking about prior convictions on job applications; ending curfews for people on parole and probation; repealing California’s three-strikes law; reallocating funds from prison construction to education; ending all collaborations between Oakland’s government and ICE | movements are making demands throw US law into crisis because they identify purportedly neutral systems as key vectors of violence These analysis produce a different relation to law reform strategies than the narrative about law reform reform used as a tactic of transformation focused on interventions that reduce violence without expanding harmful systems campaign against gang injunctions in Oakland succeeded
the coalition frames it within a larger set of demands not limited to the current structure of American law reentry support fully funded identity documents, housing, job training ending curfews repealing California’s three-strikes law ending all collaborations between government and ICE | Repeal of 3 strikes law, challenges to ICE, ending gang injunctions in Oakland
You can defend specific state actioin that break down state power to go against corruption
What intersectional politics demands
Social movements using critical intersectional tools are making demands that are often difficult for legal scholars to comprehend because of the ways that they throw US law and the nation-state form into crisis. Because they recognize the fact that legal equality contains and neutralizes resistance and perpetuates intersectional violence and because they identify purportedly neutral administrative systems as key vectors of that violence, critical scholars and activists are making demands that include ending immigration enforcement and abolishing policing and prisons. These demands suggest that the technologies of gendered racialization that form the nation cannot be reformed into fair and neutral systems. These systems are technologies of racialized-gendered population control that cannot operate otherwise—they are built to extinguish perceived threats and drains in order to protect and enhance the livelihood of the national population. These kinds of demands and the analysis they represent produce a different relation to law reform strategies than the national narrative about law reform suggests, and different than what is often assumed by legal scholars interested in the field of “equality law.” Because legal equality “victories” are being exposed as primarily symbolic declarations that stabilize the status quo of violence, declarations from courts or legislatures become undesirable goals. Instead, law reform, in this view, might be used as a tactic of transformation focused on interventions that materially reduce violence or maldistribution without inadvertently expanding harmful systems in the name of reform. One recent example is the campaign against gang injunctions in Oakland, California. A broad coalition—comprising organizations focused on police violence, economic justice, imprisonment, youth development, immigration, gentrification, and violence against queer and trans people—succeeded in recent years in bringing significant attention to the efforts of John Russo, Oakland’s city attorney, to introduce gang injunctions (Critical Resistance 2011). The organizations in this coalition are prioritizing anticriminalization work that might usually be cast as irrelevant or marginal to organizations focused on the single axis of women’s or LGBT equality. The campaign has a law reform target in that it seeks to prevent the enactment of certain law enforcement mechanisms that are harmful to vulnerable communities. However, it is not a legal-equality campaign. Rather than aiming to change a law or policy that explicitly excludes a category of people, it aims to expose the fact that a facially neutral policy is administered in a racially targeted manner (Davis 2011; Stop the Injunctions 2011).
Furthermore, the coalition frames its campaign within a larger set of demands not limited to what can be won within the current structure of American law but focused on population-level conditions of maldistribution. The demands of the coalition include stopping all gang injunctions and police violence; putting resources toward reentry support and services for people returning from prison, including fully funded and immediate access to identity documents, housing, job training, drug and alcohol treatment, and education; banning employers from asking about prior convictions on job applications; ending curfews for people on parole and probation; repealing California’s three-strikes law; reallocating funds from prison construction to education; ending all collaborations between Oakland’s government and Immigration and Customs Enforcement (ICE); | 3,801 | <h4>3. The 1AC isn’t reformism – it doesn’t conflate <u>change</u> with <u>progress</u> or validate legal institutions – it’s a <u>tactical intervention</u> that reduces violence while exposing the contradictions within law.</h4><p><strong>Spade 13</strong> [Dean Spade, associate professor of law @ Seattle University, “Intersectional Resistance and Law Reform” Signs Vol. 38, No. 4, Summer 2013] </p><p>Repeal of 3 strikes law, challenges to ICE, ending gang injunctions in Oakland</p><p>You can defend specific state actioin that break down state power to go against corruption</p><p>What intersectional politics demands</p><p><u><strong>Social <mark>movements</mark> using critical intersectional tools <mark>are making demands</mark> that are often difficult for legal scholars to comprehend because of the ways that they <mark>throw US law</u></strong></mark> and the nation-state form <u><strong><mark>into crisis</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong>Because they recognize</u></strong> the fact <u><strong>that legal equality</u></strong> <u><strong>contains and neutralizes resistance and perpetuates intersectional violence and <mark>because they identify purportedly neutral</mark> administrative <mark>systems as key vectors of</mark> that <mark>violence</u></strong></mark>, critical scholars and activists are making demands that include ending immigration enforcement and abolishing policing and prisons. These demands suggest that the technologies of gendered racialization that form the nation cannot be reformed into fair and neutral systems. These systems are technologies of racialized-gendered population control that cannot operate otherwise—they are built to extinguish perceived threats and drains in order to protect and enhance the livelihood of the national population. <u><strong><mark>These</mark> kinds of demands and the <mark>analysis</mark> they represent</strong> <strong><mark>produce a different relation to law reform strategies than the</mark> national <mark>narrative about law reform</u></strong></mark> suggests, <u><strong>and</u></strong> different than what is often assumed by legal scholars interested in the field of “<u><strong>equality</u></strong> law.” Because <u><strong>legal equality “victories” are being exposed as primarily symbolic declarations</u></strong> that stabilize the status quo of <u><strong>violence</u></strong>, declarations from courts or legislatures become undesirable goals. <u><strong>Instead, law <mark>reform</mark>, in this view, might be <mark>used as a tactic of transformation focused on interventions that</mark> materially <mark>reduce violence</mark> or maldistribution <mark>without </mark>inadvertently <mark>expanding harmful systems</mark> in the name of reform. One recent example is the <mark>campaign against gang injunctions in Oakland</u></strong></mark>, California. A broad coalition—comprising organizations focused on police violence, economic justice, imprisonment, youth development, immigration, gentrification, and violence against queer and trans people—<u><mark>succeeded</u></mark> in recent years in bringing significant attention to the efforts of John Russo, Oakland’s city attorney, to introduce gang injunctions (Critical Resistance 2011). The organizations in this coalition are prioritizing anticriminalization work that might usually be cast as irrelevant or marginal to organizations focused on the single axis of women’s or LGBT equality. The campaign has a law reform target in that it seeks to prevent the enactment of certain law enforcement mechanisms that are harmful to vulnerable communities. However, it is not a legal-equality campaign. Rather than aiming to change a law or policy that explicitly excludes a category of people, it aims to expose the fact that a facially neutral policy is administered in a racially targeted manner (Davis 2011; Stop the Injunctions 2011).</p><p><u>Furthermore, <mark>the coalition frames it</mark>s campaign <mark>within a <strong>larger set of demands not limited to</mark> what can be won within <mark>the current structure of American law</mark> but focused on population-level conditions of maldistribution.</u> <u></strong>The demands</u><strong> </strong>of the coalition<strong> <u></strong>include stopping all gang injunctions and police violence; putting resources toward <mark>reentry support</mark> and services for people returning from prison, including <mark>fully funded</mark> and immediate access to <mark>identity documents, housing, job training</mark>, drug and alcohol treatment, and education; banning employers from asking about prior convictions on job applications; <mark>ending curfews</mark> for people on parole and probation; <mark>repealing California’s three-strikes law</mark>; reallocating funds from prison construction to education; <mark>ending all collaborations between</mark> Oakland’s <mark>government and</u></mark> Immigration and Customs Enforcement (<u><mark>ICE</u></mark>); </p> | null | null | Underview | 49,043 | 349 | 12,312 | ./documents/hsld19/CarnegieVanguard/Bu/Carnegie%20Vanguard-Burudgunte-Aff-UH-Round4.docx | 834,679 | A | UH | 4 | Cypress Ranch MZ | Eric Schwerdtfeger | AC - NoKo
NC - T Plural Discourse K China DA Politics DA Determinism NC
1AR - All
2NR - T
2AR - T | hsld19/CarnegieVanguard/Bu/Carnegie%20Vanguard-Burudgunte-Aff-UH-Round4.docx | null | 71,343 | ArBu | Carnegie Vanguard ArBu | null | Ar..... | Bu..... | null | null | 24,027 | CarnegieVanguard | Carnegie Vanguard | TX | null | 1,027 | hsld19 | HS LD 2019-20 | 2,019 | ld | hs | 1 |
1,352,089 | War turns structural violence and causes deaths | Bulloch 8 | Bulloch 8 Millennium - Journal of International Studies May 2008 vol. 36 no. 3 575-595 Douglas Bulloch, IR Department, London School of Economics and Political Science, He is currently completing his PhD in International Relations at the London School of Economics, during which time he spent a year editing Millennium: Journal of International Studies | the idea that poverty and peace are directly related presupposes that wealth inequalities are unjust, and that the solution to the problem of war is to alleviate poverty. it rarely suffers any examination that war causes poverty is an obvious truth, but the opposite is quite hard to believe. War is an expensive business even asymmetrically. the problem of peace and war the Peace Prize itself has simply become Western liberal wish-fulfilment It is comforting to believe that poverty causes violence, as it serves to endorse all problems as fundamentally economic rather than deeply – and potentially radically – political. | that war causes poverty is an obvious truth, but the opposite is hard to believe. War is expensive It is comforting to believe that poverty causes violence to endorse all problems as economic rather than political | But the idea that poverty and peace are directly related presupposes that wealth inequalities are – in and of themselves – unjust, and that the solution to the problem of war is to alleviate the injustice that inspires conflict, namely poverty. However, it also suggests that poverty is a legitimate inspiration for violence, otherwise there would be no reason to alleviate it in the interests of peace. It has become such a commonplace to suggest that poverty and conflict are linked that it rarely suffers any examination. To suggest that war causes poverty is to utter an obvious truth, but to suggest the opposite is – on reflection – quite hard to believe. War is an expensive business in the twenty-first century, even asymmetrically. And just to examine Bangladesh for a moment is enough at least to raise the question concerning the actual connection between peace and poverty. The government of Bangladesh is a threat only to itself, and despite 30 years of the Grameen Bank, Bangladesh remains in a state of incipient civil strife. So although Muhammad Yunus should be applauded for his work in demonstrating the efficacy of micro-credit strategies in a context of development, it is not at all clear that this has anything to do with resolving the social and political crisis in Bangladesh, nor is it clear that this has anything to do with resolving the problem of peace and war in our times. It does speak to the Western liberal mindset – as Geir Lundestad acknowledges – but then perhaps this exposes the extent to which the Peace Prize itself has simply become an award that reflects a degree of Western liberal wish-fulfilment. It is perhaps comforting to believe that poverty causes violence, as it serves to endorse a particular kind of concern for the developing world that in turn regards all problems as fundamentally economic rather than deeply – and potentially radically – political. | 1,907 | <h4>War turns structural violence and causes deaths</h4><p><strong>Bulloch 8</strong> Millennium - Journal of International Studies May 2008 vol. 36 no. 3 575-595 Douglas Bulloch, IR Department, London School of Economics and Political Science, He is currently completing his PhD in International Relations at the London School of Economics, during which time he spent a year editing Millennium: Journal of International Studies<u> </p><p></u> But <u>the idea that poverty and peace are directly related presupposes that wealth inequalities are</u> – in and of themselves – <u>unjust, and that the solution to the problem of war is to alleviate</u> the injustice that inspires conflict, namely <u>poverty. </u>However, it also suggests that poverty is a legitimate inspiration for violence, otherwise there would be no reason to alleviate it in the interests of peace. It has become such a commonplace to suggest that poverty and conflict are linked that <u><strong>it rarely suffers any examination</u></strong>. To suggest <u><mark>that war causes poverty</u> <u>is</u></mark> to utter <u><strong><mark>an obvious truth,</u></strong> <u>but</u> </mark>to suggest <u><mark>the opposite is</u></mark> – on reflection – <u>quite <strong><mark>hard to believe. War is</strong></mark> an <mark>expensive</mark> business</u> in the twenty-first century, <u>even asymmetrically.</u> And just to examine Bangladesh for a moment is enough at least to raise the question concerning the actual connection between peace and poverty. The government of Bangladesh is a threat only to itself, and despite 30 years of the Grameen Bank, Bangladesh remains in a state of incipient civil strife. So although Muhammad Yunus should be applauded for his work in demonstrating the efficacy of micro-credit strategies in a context of development, it is not at all clear that this has anything to do with resolving the social and political crisis in Bangladesh, nor is it clear that this has anything to do with resolving <u>the problem of peace and war </u>in our times. It does speak to the Western liberal mindset – as Geir Lundestad acknowledges – but then perhaps this exposes the extent to which <u>the Peace Prize itself has simply become</u> an award that reflects a degree of <u>Western liberal wish-fulfilment</u>. <u><mark>It is</u></mark> perhaps <u><mark>comforting to believe that <strong>poverty causes violence</mark>,</u></strong> <u>as it serves <mark>to endorse</u></mark> a particular kind of concern for the developing world that in turn regards <u><mark>all problems as</mark> fundamentally <mark>economic rather than</mark> deeply – and potentially radically – <mark>political</mark>. </p></u> | GMU KL – Harvard Rd 7 – Neg vs Emory FH | 1NR | O/V | 62,855 | 213 | 35,351 | ./documents/ndtceda14/GeorgeMason/KwLa/George%20Mason-Kwon-Lastovica-Neg-Harvard-Round7.docx | 565,794 | N | Harvard | 7 | Emory FH | Layne Kirshon | 1NC T - Spec CP - Presumed Consent CP - Courts Midterms DA Public Health DA Case
Block2NR CP - Presumed Consent Midterms DA Case | ndtceda14/GeorgeMason/KwLa/George%20Mason-Kwon-Lastovica-Neg-Harvard-Round7.docx | null | 48,516 | KwLa | George Mason KwLa | null | Yo..... | Kw..... | Ky..... | La..... | 18,771 | GeorgeMason | George Mason | null | null | 1,004 | ndtceda14 | NDT/CEDA 2014-15 | 2,014 | cx | college | 2 |
3,732,153 | ‘Restriction’ requires a cap---the plan must mandate a ceiling on private sector emissions | Supreme Court of Florida 1917 | Supreme Court of Florida 1917 (Atlantic C. L. R. Co. v. State, 73 Fla. 609, Lexis) | The word restriction is defined by the best lexicographers to mean limitation, confinement within bounds The word regulation has a different signification | The word restriction is defined by the best lexicographers to mean limitation confinement within bounds regulation has a different signification | There would seem to be no occasion to discuss whether or not the Railroad Commissioners had the power and authority to make the order, requiring the three specified railroads running into the City of Tampa to erect a union passenger station in such city, which is set out in the declaration in the instant case and which we have copied above. It is sufficient to say that under the reasoning and the authorities cited in State v. Atlantic Coast Line R. Co., 67 Fla. 441, 458, 63 South. Rep. 729, 65 South. Rep. 654, and State v. Jacksonville Terminal [631] Co., supra, it would seem that HN14 the Commissioners had power and authority. The point which we are required to determine is whether or not the Commissioners were given the authority to impose the fine or penalty upon the three railroads for the recovery of which this action is brought. In order to decide this question we must examine Section 2908 of the General Statutes of 1906, which we have copied above, in the light of the authorities which we have cited and from some of which we have quoted. It will be observed that the declaration alleges that the penalty imposed upon the three railroads was for the violation of what is designated as "Order No. 282," which is set out and which required such railroads to erect and complete a union depot at Tampa within a certain specified time. If the Commissioners had the authority to make such order, it necessarily follows that they could enforce a compliance with the same by appropriate proceedings in the courts, but it does not necessarily follow that they had the power and authority to penalize the roads for a failure to comply therewith. That is a different matter. HN15 Section 2908 of the General Statutes of 1906, which originally formed Section 12 of Chapter 4700 of the Laws of Florida, (Acts of 1899, p. 86), expressly authorizes the imposition of a penalty by the Commissioners upon "any railroad, railroad company or other common carrier doing business in this State," for "a violation or disregard of any rate, schedule, rule or regulation, provided or prescribed by said commission," or for failure "to make any report required to be made under the provisions of this Chapter," or for the violation of "any provision of this Chapter." It will be observed that the word "Order" is not mentioned in such section. Are the other words used therein sufficiently comprehensive to embrace an order made by the Commissioners, such as the one now under consideration? [632] It could not successfully be contended, nor is such contention attempted, that this order is covered by or embraced within the words "rate," "schedule" or "any report,' therefore we may dismiss these terms from our consideration and direct our attention to the words "rule or regulation." As is frankly stated in the brief filed by the defendant in error: "It is admitted that an order for the erection of a depot is not a 'rate' or 'schedule' and if it is not a 'rule' or 'regulation' then there is no power in the Commissioners to enforce it by the imposition of a penalty." It is earnestly insisted that the words "rule or regulation" are sufficiently comprehensive to embrace such an order and to authorize the penalty imposed, and in support of this contention the following authorities are cited: Black's Law Dictionary, defining regulation and order; Rapalje & Lawrence's Law Dictionary, defining rule; Abbott's Law Dictionary, defining rule; Bouvier's Law Dictionary, defining order and rule of court; Webster's New International Dictionary, defining regulation; Curry v. Marvin, 2 Fla. 411, text 515; In re Leasing of State Lands, 18 Colo. 359, 32 Pac. Rep. 986; Betts v. Commissioners of the Land Office, 27 Okl. 64, 110 Pac. Rep. 766; Carter V. Louisiana Purchase Exposition Co., 124 Mo. App. 530, 102 S.W. Rep. 6, text 9; 34 Cyc. 1031. We have examined all of these authorities, as well as those cited by the plaintiffs in error and a number of others, but shall not undertake an analysis and discussion of all of them. While it is undoubtedly true that the words, rule, regulation and order are frequently used as synonyms, as the dictionaries, both English and law, and the dictionaries of synonyms, such as Soule's show, it does not follow that these words always mean the same thing or are interchangeable at will. It is well known that the same word used in different contexts may mean a different thing by virtue of the coloring which the word [633] takes on both from what precedes it in the context and what follows after. Thus in discussing the proper constructions to be placed upon the words "restrictions and regulations" as used in the Constitution of this State, then in force, Chap. 4, Sec. 2, No. 1, of Thompson's Digest, page 50, this court in Curry v. Marvin, 2 Fla. 411, text 415, which case is cited to us and relied upon by both the parties litigant, makes the following statement: "The word restriction is defined by the best lexicographers to mean limitation, confinement within bounds, and would seem, as used in the constitution, to apply to the amount and to the time within which an appeal might to be taken, or a writ of error sued out. The word regulation has a different signification -- it means method, and is defined by Webster in his Dictionary, folio 31, page 929, to be 'a rule or order prescribed by a superior for the management of some business, or for the government of a company or society.' This more properly perhaps applies to the mode and form of proceeding in taking and prosecuting appeals and writs of error. By the use of both of those terms, we think that something more was intended than merely regulating the mode and form of proceedings in such cases." Thus, in Carter v. Louisiana Purchase Exposition Co., 124 Mo. App. 530, text 538, 102 S.W. Rep. 6, text 9, it is said, "The definition of a rule or order, which are synonymous terms, include commands to lower courts or court officials to do ministerial acts." In support of this proposition is cited 24 Amer. & Eng. Ency. of Law 1016, which is evidently an erroneous citation, whether the first or second edition is meant. See the definition of regulate and rule, 24 amer. & Eng. Ency. of Law (2nd Ed.) pages 243 to 246 and 1010, and it will be seen that the two words are not always synonymous, much necessarily depending upon the context and the sense in which the words are used. Also see the discussion [634] of the word regulation in 34 Cyc. 1031. We would call especial attention to Morris v. Board of Pilot Commissioners, 7 Del. chan. 136, 30 Atl. Rep. 667, text 669, wherein the following statement is made by the court: "These words 'rule' and the 'order,' when used in a statute, have a definite signification. They are different in their nature and extent. A rule, to be valid, must be general in its scope, and undiscriminating in its application; an order is specific and not limited in its application. The function of an order relates more particularly to the execution or enforcement of a rule previously made." Also see 7 Words & Phrases 6271 and 6272, and 4 Words & Phrases (2nd Ser.) 419, 420. As we held in City of Los Angeles v. Gager, 10 Cal. App. 378, 102 Pac. Rep. 17, "The meaning of the word 'rules' is of wide and varied significance, depending upon the context; in a legal sense it is synonymous with 'laws.'" If Section 2908 had contained the word order, or had authorized the Commissioners to impose a penalty for the violation of any order made by them, there would be no room for construction. The Georgia statute, Acts of 1905, p. 120, generally known as the "Steed Bill," entitled "An act to further extend the powers of the Railroad Commission of this State, and to confer upon the commission the power to regulate the time and manner within which the several railroads in this State shall receive, receipt for, forward and deliver to its destination all freight of every character, which may be tendered or received by them for transportation; to provide a penalty for non-compliance with any and all reasonable rules, regulations and orders prescribed by the said commission in the execution of these powers, and for other purposes," expressly authorized the Railroad Commissioners "to provide a penalty for non-compliance with any and all reasonable rules, regulations and orders prescribed by the said Commision." [635] See Pennington v. Douglas, A. & G. Ry. Co., 3 Ga. App. 665, 60 S.E. Rep. 485, which we cited with approval in State v. Atlantic Coast Line R. Co., 56 fla. 617, text 651, 47 South. Rep. 969, 32 L.R.A. (N.S.) 639. Under the reasoning in the cited authorities, especially State v. Atlantic Coast Line R. Co., supra, and Morris v. Board of Pilot Commissioners, we are constrained to hold that the fourth and eighth grounds of the demurrer are well founded and that HN16 the Railroad Commissioners were not empowered or authorized to impose a penalty upon the three railroads for failure to comply with the order for the erection of a union depot. | 9,024 | <h4> ‘Restriction’ requires a <u>cap</u>---the plan must mandate a <u>ceiling</u> on private sector emissions</h4><p><strong>Supreme Court of Florida 1917</strong> (Atlantic C. L. R. Co. v. State, 73 Fla. 609, Lexis)</p><p>There would seem to be no occasion to discuss whether or not the Railroad Commissioners had the power and authority to make the order, requiring the three specified railroads running into the City of Tampa to erect a union passenger station in such city, which is set out in the declaration in the instant case and which we have copied above. It is sufficient to say that under the reasoning and the authorities cited in State v. Atlantic Coast Line R. Co., 67 Fla. 441, 458, 63 South. Rep. 729, 65 South. Rep. 654, and State v. Jacksonville Terminal [631] Co., supra, it would seem that HN14 the Commissioners had power and authority. The point which we are required to determine is whether or not the Commissioners were given the authority to impose the fine or penalty upon the three railroads for the recovery of which this action is brought. In order to decide this question we must examine Section 2908 of the General Statutes of 1906, which we have copied above, in the light of the authorities which we have cited and from some of which we have quoted. It will be observed that the declaration alleges that the penalty imposed upon the three railroads was for the violation of what is designated as "Order No. 282," which is set out and which required such railroads to erect and complete a union depot at Tampa within a certain specified time. If the Commissioners had the authority to make such order, it necessarily follows that they could enforce a compliance with the same by appropriate proceedings in the courts, but it does not necessarily follow that they had the power and authority to penalize the roads for a failure to comply therewith. That is a different matter. HN15 Section 2908 of the General Statutes of 1906, which originally formed Section 12 of Chapter 4700 of the Laws of Florida, (Acts of 1899, p. 86), expressly authorizes the imposition of a penalty by the Commissioners upon "any railroad, railroad company or other common carrier doing business in this State," for "a violation or disregard of any rate, schedule, rule or regulation, provided or prescribed by said commission," or for failure "to make any report required to be made under the provisions of this Chapter," or for the violation of "any provision of this Chapter." It will be observed that the word "Order" is not mentioned in such section. Are the other words used therein sufficiently comprehensive to embrace an order made by the Commissioners, such as the one now under consideration? [632] It could not successfully be contended, nor is such contention attempted, that this order is covered by or embraced within the words "rate," "schedule" or "any report,' therefore we may dismiss these terms from our consideration and direct our attention to the words "rule or regulation." As is frankly stated in the brief filed by the defendant in error: "It is admitted that an order for the erection of a depot is not a 'rate' or 'schedule' and if it is not a 'rule' or 'regulation' then there is no power in the Commissioners to enforce it by the imposition of a penalty." It is earnestly insisted that the words "rule or regulation" are sufficiently comprehensive to embrace such an order and to authorize the penalty imposed, and in support of this contention the following authorities are cited: Black's Law Dictionary, defining regulation and order; Rapalje & Lawrence's Law Dictionary, defining rule; Abbott's Law Dictionary, defining rule; Bouvier's Law Dictionary, defining order and rule of court; Webster's New International Dictionary, defining regulation; Curry v. Marvin, 2 Fla. 411, text 515; In re Leasing of State Lands, 18 Colo. 359, 32 Pac. Rep. 986; Betts v. Commissioners of the Land Office, 27 Okl. 64, 110 Pac. Rep. 766; Carter V. Louisiana Purchase Exposition Co., 124 Mo. App. 530, 102 S.W. Rep. 6, text 9; 34 Cyc. 1031. We have examined all of these authorities, as well as those cited by the plaintiffs in error and a number of others, but shall not undertake an analysis and discussion of all of them. While it is undoubtedly true that the words, rule, regulation and order are frequently used as synonyms, as the dictionaries, both English and law, and the dictionaries of synonyms, such as Soule's show, it does not follow that these words always mean the same thing or are interchangeable at will. It is well known that the same word used in different contexts may mean a different thing by virtue of the coloring which the word [633] takes on both from what precedes it in the context and what follows after. Thus in discussing the proper constructions to be placed upon the words "restrictions and regulations" as used in the Constitution of this State, then in force, Chap. 4, Sec. 2, No. 1, of Thompson's Digest, page 50, this court in Curry v. Marvin, 2 Fla. 411, text 415, which case is cited to us and relied upon by both the parties litigant, makes the following statement: "<u><mark>The word restriction is defined by the best</mark> <mark>lexicographers to mean</mark> <mark>limitation</mark>, <strong><mark>confinement within bounds</u></strong></mark>, and would seem, as used in the constitution, to apply to the amount and to the time within which an appeal might to be taken, or a writ of error sued out. <u>The word <mark>regulation has a</mark> <mark>different signification</u></mark> -- it means method, and is defined by Webster in his Dictionary, folio 31, page 929, to be 'a rule or order prescribed by a superior for the management of some business, or for the government of a company or society.' This more properly perhaps applies to the mode and form of proceeding in taking and prosecuting appeals and writs of error. By the use of both of those terms, we think that something more was intended than merely regulating the mode and form of proceedings in such cases." Thus, in Carter v. Louisiana Purchase Exposition Co., 124 Mo. App. 530, text 538, 102 S.W. Rep. 6, text 9, it is said, "The definition of a rule or order, which are synonymous terms, include commands to lower courts or court officials to do ministerial acts." In support of this proposition is cited 24 Amer. & Eng. Ency. of Law 1016, which is evidently an erroneous citation, whether the first or second edition is meant. See the definition of regulate and rule, 24 amer. & Eng. Ency. of Law (2nd Ed.) pages 243 to 246 and 1010, and it will be seen that the two words are not always synonymous, much necessarily depending upon the context and the sense in which the words are used. Also see the discussion [634] of the word regulation in 34 Cyc. 1031. We would call especial attention to Morris v. Board of Pilot Commissioners, 7 Del. chan. 136, 30 Atl. Rep. 667, text 669, wherein the following statement is made by the court: "These words 'rule' and the 'order,' when used in a statute, have a definite signification. They are different in their nature and extent. A rule, to be valid, must be general in its scope, and undiscriminating in its application; an order is specific and not limited in its application. The function of an order relates more particularly to the execution or enforcement of a rule previously made." Also see 7 Words & Phrases 6271 and 6272, and 4 Words & Phrases (2nd Ser.) 419, 420. As we held in City of Los Angeles v. Gager, 10 Cal. App. 378, 102 Pac. Rep. 17, "The meaning of the word 'rules' is of wide and varied significance, depending upon the context; in a legal sense it is synonymous with 'laws.'" If Section 2908 had contained the word order, or had authorized the Commissioners to impose a penalty for the violation of any order made by them, there would be no room for construction. The Georgia statute, Acts of 1905, p. 120, generally known as the "Steed Bill," entitled "An act to further extend the powers of the Railroad Commission of this State, and to confer upon the commission the power to regulate the time and manner within which the several railroads in this State shall receive, receipt for, forward and deliver to its destination all freight of every character, which may be tendered or received by them for transportation; to provide a penalty for non-compliance with any and all reasonable rules, regulations and orders prescribed by the said commission in the execution of these powers, and for other purposes," expressly authorized the Railroad Commissioners "to provide a penalty for non-compliance with any and all reasonable rules, regulations and orders prescribed by the said Commision." [635] See Pennington v. Douglas, A. & G. Ry. Co., 3 Ga. App. 665, 60 S.E. Rep. 485, which we cited with approval in State v. Atlantic Coast Line R. Co., 56 fla. 617, text 651, 47 South. Rep. 969, 32 L.R.A. (N.S.) 639. Under the reasoning in the cited authorities, especially State v. Atlantic Coast Line R. Co., supra, and Morris v. Board of Pilot Commissioners, we are constrained to hold that the fourth and eighth grounds of the demurrer are well founded and that HN16 the Railroad Commissioners were not empowered or authorized to impose a penalty upon the three railroads for failure to comply with the order for the erection of a union depot.</p> | 1NC | 2 | 1NC - Resource Wars | 97,770 | 199 | 124,248 | ./documents/ndtceda16/MissouriState/EvMo/Missouri%20State-Evans-Morrison-Aff-UNT-Round6.docx | 591,559 | A | UNT | 6 | Kansas ST | Abraha, Danny | 1AC Carbon Tax (Heg Econ)
1NC T-Restrict Oil DA Politics States
2NR went for T | ndtceda16/MissouriState/EvMo/Missouri%20State-Evans-Morrison-Aff-UNT-Round6.docx | null | 50,451 | EvMo | Missouri State EvMo | null | Ky..... | Ev..... | Ga..... | Mo..... | 19,050 | MissouriState | Missouri State | null | null | 1,006 | ndtceda16 | NDT/CEDA 2016-17 | 2,016 | cx | college | 2 |
3,106,134 | No US/China war – relatively high relations/low hostility, trade networks, cooperation on mutual issues, peaceful military postures, lack of public support for conflict and empirics – answers miscalc and accidental war | Heath 17 http://nationalinterest.org/feature/us-china-tensions-are-unlikely-lead-war-20411?page=2 | Heath 17 ---- Timothy, senior international defense researcher (RAND Corporation), former senior analyst for the USPACOM China Strategic Focus Group, M.A. in Asian studies (George Washington University), B.A. in philosophy (College of William and Mary), Ph.D. candidate in Political Science (George Mason University), written with William R. Thompson who is a Professor of Political Science (Indiana University), “U.S.-China Tensions Are Unlikely to Lead to War,” National Interest, 4/30, http://nationalinterest.org/feature/us-china-tensions-are-unlikely-lead-war-20411?page=2 | Allison explores how misperceptions and dysfunction could accelerate crisis into war the article neglects key political and geostrategic conditions Without conditions in place risk that a crisis could accidentally escalate becomes far lower U.S.-China relations may trend to tension, but the relative stability and overall low level of hostility make accidental war extremely unlikely
Allison fails to persuade because he fails to specify political and strategic conditions that make war plausible Allison implies U S and China are in a situation analogous to the Cold War
By contrast U.S.-China relations operate at a much lower level of hostility and threat China and U S may be experiencing tensions but the two remain far from the bitter, acrimonious rivalry that defined U.S.-Soviet relations Neither Washington nor Beijing regards the other as its principal enemy rivals they view each other as important trade partners and partners on shared concerns such as Korea, as the recent summit between Trump and Xi illustrated behavior of militaries underscores relatively restrained rivalry military competition operates at a far lower level than arms racing that typified the Soviet standoff. And U.S. and Chinese militaries are not postured to fight Moreover, polls show people regard each other with mixed views a considerable contrast from the hostile sentiment expressed by U.S. and Soviet publics Lacking preparations for major war and a constituency for conflict, leaders have less incentive to misjudge crisis situations in favor of unwarranted escalation
To the contrary leaders and bureaucracies face a strong incentive to find ways of defusing crises in a manner that avoids unwanted escalation This inclination manifested itself in the airplane collision in 2001, and incidents involving ships and aircraft in 2009 | relations may trend to tension, but relative stability make accidental war extremely unlikely
China and U S remain far from the bitter rivalry that defined Soviet relations they view each other as trade partners behavior of militaries underscores restrained rivalry Lacking preparations and a constituency leaders have less incentive to misjudge situations
To the contrary leaders face strong incentive to defus crises | Graham Allison's April 12 article, “How America and China Could Stumble to War,” explores how misperceptions and bureaucratic dysfunction could accelerate a militarized crisis involving the United States and China into an unwanted war. However, the article fails to persuade because it neglects the key political and geostrategic conditions that make war plausible in the first place. Without those conditions in place, the risk that a crisis could accidentally escalate into war becomes far lower. The U.S.-China relationship today may be trending towards greater tension, but the relative stability and overall low level of hostility make the prospect of an accidental escalation to war extremely unlikely.
In a series of scenarios centered around the South China Sea, Taiwan and the East China Sea, Allison explored how well-established flashpoints involving China and the United States and its allies could spiral into unwanted war. Allison’s article argues that given the context of strategic rivalry between a rising power and a status-quo power, organizational and bureaucratic misjudgments increase the likelihood of unintended escalation. According to Allison, “the underlying stress created by China’s disruptive rise creates conditions in which accidental, otherwise inconsequential events could trigger a large-scale conflict.” This argument appears persuasive on its surface, in no small part because it evokes insights from some of Allison’s groundbreaking work on the organizational pathologies that made the Cuban Missile Crisis so dangerous.
However, Allison ultimately fails to persuade because he fails to specify the political and strategic conditions that make war plausible in the first place. Allison’s analysis implies that the United States and China are in a situation analogous to that of the Soviet Union and the United States in the early 1960s. In the Cold War example, the two countries faced each other on a near-war footing and engaged in a bitter geostrategic and ideological struggle for supremacy. The two countries experienced a series of militarized crises and fought each other repeatedly through proxy wars. It was this broader context that made issues of misjudgment so dangerous in a crisis.
By contrast, the U.S.-China relationship today operates at a much lower level of hostility and threat. China and the United States may be experiencing an increase in tensions, but the two countries remain far from the bitter, acrimonious rivalry that defined the U.S.-Soviet relationship in the early 1960s. Neither Washington nor Beijing regards the other as its principal enemy. Today’s rivals may view each other warily as competitors and threats on some issues, but they also view each other as important trade partners and partners on some shared concerns, such as North Korea, as the recent summit between President Donald Trump and Chinese president Xi Jinping illustrated. The behavior of their respective militaries underscores the relatively restrained rivalry. The military competition between China and the United States may be growing, but it operates at a far lower level of intensity than the relentless arms racing that typified the U.S.-Soviet standoff. And unlike their Cold War counterparts, U.S. and Chinese militaries are not postured to fight each other in major wars. Moreover, polls show that the people of the two countries regard each other with mixed views—a considerable contrast from the hostile sentiment expressed by the U.S. and Soviet publics for each other. Lacking both preparations for major war and a constituency for conflict, leaders and bureaucracies in both countries have less incentive to misjudge crisis situations in favor of unwarranted escalation.
To the contrary, political leaders and bureaucracies currently face a strong incentive to find ways of defusing crises in a manner that avoids unwanted escalation. This inclination manifested itself in the EP-3 airplane collision off Hainan Island in 2001, and in subsequent incidents involving U.S. and Chinese ships and aircraft, such as the harassment of the USNS Impeccable in 2009. This does not mean that there is no risk, however. Indeed, the potential for a dangerous militarized crisis may be growing. Moreover, key political and geostrategic developments could shift the incentives for leaders in favor of more escalatory options in a crisis and thereby make Allison’s scenarios more plausible. Past precedents offer some insight into the types of developments that would most likely propel the U.S.-China relationship into a hostile, competitive one
featuring an elevated risk of conflict. | 4,629 | <h4>No US/China war – relatively high relations/low hostility, trade networks, cooperation on mutual issues, peaceful military postures, lack of public support for conflict and empirics – answers miscalc and accidental war</h4><p><strong>Heath 17</strong> ---- Timothy, senior international defense researcher (RAND Corporation), former senior analyst for the USPACOM China Strategic Focus Group, M.A. in Asian studies (George Washington University), B.A. in philosophy (College of William and Mary), Ph.D. candidate in Political Science (George Mason University), written with William R. Thompson who is a Professor of Political Science (Indiana University), “U.S.-China Tensions Are Unlikely to Lead to War,” National Interest, 4/30, <strong>http://nationalinterest.org/feature/us-china-tensions-are-unlikely-lead-war-20411?page=2</p><p></strong>Graham <u>Allison</u>'s April 12 article, “How America and China Could Stumble to War,” <u>explores how misperceptions and</u> bureaucratic <u>dysfunction could accelerate</u> a militarized <u>crisis</u> involving the United States and China <u>into</u> an unwanted <u>war</u>. However, <u>the article</u> fails to persuade because it <u>neglects</u> the <u><strong>key</u></strong> <u>political and geostrategic conditions</u> that make war plausible in the first place. <u>Without</u> those <u>conditions in place</u>, the <u>risk that a crisis could accidentally escalate</u> into war <u><strong>becomes far lower</u></strong>. The <u>U.S.-China</u> <u><mark>relations</u></mark>hip today <u><mark>may</u></mark> be <u><mark>trend</u></mark>ing <u><mark>to</u></mark>wards greater <u><mark>tension, but</mark> the</u> <u><strong><mark>relative stability</u></strong> <u></mark>and overall</u> <u><strong>low level of hostility</u></strong> <u><mark>make</u></mark> the prospect of an <u><mark>accidental</u></mark> escalation to <u><mark>war</u> <u><strong>extremely unlikely</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>In a series of scenarios centered around the South China Sea, Taiwan and the East China Sea, Allison explored how well-established flashpoints involving China and the United States and its allies could spiral into unwanted war. Allison’s article argues that given the context of strategic rivalry between a rising power and a status-quo power, organizational and bureaucratic misjudgments increase the likelihood of unintended escalation. According to Allison, “the underlying stress created by China’s disruptive rise creates conditions in which accidental, otherwise inconsequential events could trigger a large-scale conflict.” This argument appears persuasive on its surface, in no small part because it evokes insights from some of Allison’s groundbreaking work on the organizational pathologies that made the Cuban Missile Crisis so dangerous.</p><p>However, <u>Allison</u> ultimately <u>fails to persuade because he fails to specify</u> the <u>political and strategic conditions that make war</u> <u>plausible</u> in the first place. <u>Allison</u>’s analysis <u>implies</u> that the <u><strong>U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates <u>and China are in a situation analogous to</u> that of the Soviet Union and the United States in the early 1960s. In <u>the Cold War</u> example, the two countries faced each other on a near-war footing and engaged in a bitter geostrategic and ideological struggle for supremacy. The two countries experienced a series of militarized crises and fought each other repeatedly through proxy wars. It was this broader context that made issues of misjudgment so dangerous in a crisis.</p><p><u><strong>By contrast</u></strong>, the <u>U.S.-China relations</u>hip today <u>operate</u>s <u>at a <strong>much lower level of hostility and threat</u></strong>. <u><mark>China and</u></mark> the <u><strong><mark>U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates <u>may be experiencing</u> an increase in <u>tensions</u>, <u><strong>but</u></strong> <u>the two</u> countries <u><mark>remain</u> <u><strong>far from the bitter</mark>, acrimonious <mark>rivalry</u></strong> <u>that defined</mark> </u>the <u>U.S.-<mark>Soviet</mark> <mark>relations</u></mark>hip in the early 1960s. <u>Neither Washington nor Beijing regards the other as its principal enemy</u>. Today’s <u>rivals</u> may view each other warily as competitors and threats on some issues, but <u><mark>they</u></mark> also <u><mark>view each other as</mark> important</u> <u><strong><mark>trade partners</u></strong> <u></mark>and</u> <u>partners on</u> some <u><strong>shared concerns</u></strong>, <u>such as</u> North <u>Korea, as the recent summit between</u> President Donald <u>Trump and</u> Chinese president <u>Xi</u> Jinping <u>illustrated</u>. The <u><mark>behavior of</u></mark> their respective <u><mark>militaries</mark> <mark>underscores</u></mark> the <u><strong>relatively <mark>restrained</u></strong> <u>rivalry</u></mark>. The <u>military competition</u> between China and the United States may be growing, but it <u>operates at a <strong>far lower</u></strong> <u>level</u> of intensity <u>than</u> the relentless <u>arms racing that typified the</u> U.S.-<u>Soviet standoff. And</u> unlike their Cold War counterparts, <u>U.S. and Chinese militaries are not postured to fight</u> each other in major wars. <u>Moreover, polls show</u> that the <u>people</u> of the two countries <u>regard each other with mixed views</u>—<u>a</u> <u><strong>considerable contrast</u></strong> <u>from the hostile sentiment expressed by</u> the <u>U.S. and Soviet publics</u> for each other. <u><strong><mark>Lacking</u></strong></mark> both <u><mark>preparations</mark> for major war <mark>and a constituency </mark>for conflict, <mark>leaders</u></mark> and bureaucracies in both countries <u><mark>have</u> <u><strong>less incentive</u></strong> <u>to</u> <u><strong>misjudge</mark> crisis <mark>situations</u></strong></mark> <u>in favor of <strong>unwarranted</strong> escalation</u>.</p><p><u><strong><mark>To the contrary</u></strong></mark>, political <u><mark>leaders</mark> and bureaucracies</u> currently <u><mark>face </mark>a</u> <u><strong><mark>strong incentive</u></strong> <u>to </mark>find ways of <mark>defus</mark>ing <mark>crises</mark> in a manner</u> <u>that</u> <u><strong>avoids unwanted escalation</u></strong>. <u>This inclination manifested itself in the</u> EP-3 <u>airplane collision</u> off Hainan Island <u>in 2001, and</u> in subsequent <u>incidents involving</u> U.S. and Chinese <u>ships and aircraft</u>, such as the harassment of the USNS Impeccable <u>in 200<strong>9</u></strong>. This does not mean that there is no risk, however. Indeed, the potential for a dangerous militarized crisis may be growing. Moreover, key political and geostrategic developments could shift the incentives for leaders in favor of more escalatory options in a crisis and thereby make Allison’s scenarios more plausible. Past precedents offer some insight into the types of developments that would most likely propel the U.S.-China relationship into a hostile, competitive one </p><p>featuring an elevated risk of conflict.</p> | 1NC | Crisis Stability | A2: China/US War---1NC | 9,854 | 977 | 101,447 | ./documents/ndtceda18/MichiganState/BrPe/Michigan%20State-Brown-Pepper-Neg-Indiana-Round3.docx | 606,327 | N | Indiana | 3 | Kentucky SW | Ari Hoffman | 1AC - NFU
1NC - 2020 ESR Debt DA ICJ CP Death K
2NR - ESR 2020 | ndtceda18/MichiganState/BrPe/Michigan%20State-Brown-Pepper-Neg-Indiana-Round3.docx | null | 51,458 | BrPe | Michigan State BrPe | null | Al..... | Br..... | La..... | Pe..... | 19,201 | MichiganState | Michigan State | null | null | 1,008 | ndtceda18 | NDT/CEDA 2018-19 | 2,018 | cx | college | 2 |
4,703,373 | “Resolved” means certain | Collins 3 Collins English Dictionary – Complete and Unabridged © HarperCollins Publishers 1991, 1994, 1998, 2000, 2003 | Collins 3 Collins English Dictionary – Complete and Unabridged © HarperCollins Publishers 1991, 1994, 1998, 2000, 2003 | resolve fixed in purpose or intention; determined | resolved fixed in purpose determined | http://www.thefreedictionary.com/resolved resolved [rɪˈzɒlvd] adj fixed in purpose or intention; determined | 107 | <h4><strong>“Resolved” means certain </h4><p><u>Collins 3 Collins English Dictionary – Complete and Unabridged © HarperCollins Publishers 1991, 1994, 1998, 2000, 2003</p><p></u></strong>http://www.thefreedictionary.com/resolved <u><strong><mark>resolve</u></strong>d</mark> [rɪˈzɒlvd] adj <u><strong><mark>fixed in purpose</mark> or intention; <mark>determined</p></u></strong></mark> | 1NC | 2 | null | 50,434 | 131 | 163,699 | ./documents/hsld22/HarvardWestlake/LiSt/HarvardWestlake-LiSt-Neg-37th-Annual-Stanford-Invitational-Round-6.docx | 984,630 | N | 37th Annual Stanford Invitational | 6 | Millard North NL | Fleming | 1ac -- hukou
1nc -- t countries, consult the people
1ar -- all
2nr -- t
2ar -- t | hsld22/HarvardWestlake/LiSt/HarvardWestlake-LiSt-Neg-37th-Annual-Stanford-Invitational-Round-6.docx | 2023-02-27 16:31:25 | 80,530 | LiSt | Harvard Westlake LiSt | null | Li..... | St..... | null | null | 26,554 | HarvardWestlake | Harvard Westlake | CA | null | 2,003 | hsld22 | HS LD 2022-23 | 2,022 | ld | hs | 1 |
583,864 | Warming causes extinction – a confluence of nonlinear and unpredictable effects will make human and natural systems inhospitable while increasing escalatory conflicts – even if the impacts are far off, only drastic action now solves | Melton 19 | Melton 19 [Michelle Melton is a 3L at Harvard Law School. Before law school, she was an associate fellow in the Energy and National Security Program at the Center for Strategic and International Studies, where she focused on climate policy. Climate Change and National Security, Part II: How Big a Threat is the Climate? January 7, 2019. https://www.lawfareblog.com/climate-change-and-national-security-part-ii-how-big-threat-climate] | climate change will remain a creeping threat that will exacerbate and amplify existing, structural global inequalities climate change will exacerbate humanitarian crises some of which will result in the deployment of military personnel It will aggravate resource constraints contributing to conflict over water, food and energy if emissions continue to creep upward threats could be existential The question for the next hundred years is not can the global order, premised on the nation-state system, itself based on territorial sovereignty, survive in a world in which substantial swathes of territory are potentially uninhabitable Even small differences in global average temperatures result in significant environmental changes, with attendant social, economic and political consequences climate change will wreak increasing havoc on human and natural systems with profound consequences for national security changes in temperature, the hydrological cycle and the ranges of insects will impact food availability and food access in much of the world, increasing food insecurity Storms, flooding, changes in ocean pH and other climate-linked changes will damage infrastructure and negatively impact labor productivity and economic growth Vector-borne diseases will also become more prevalent as climate change will expand the geographic range and intensity of transmission of diseases like malaria, West Nile, Zika and dengue fever, and cholera Rising public health challenges, economic devastation and food insecurity will translate into an increased demand for humanitarian assistance provided by the military, increased migration and geopolitical conflict food insecurity, economic losses and public health crises, combined with weak and ineffectual governance, could precipitate future conflicts changes to the climate could fundamentally reshape geopolitics there will 70 percent decline in wheat production in Central America and the Caribbean 75 percent of the land area in the Middle East 50 percent in South Asia will be affected by highly unusual heat, and sea level rise could displace and imperil the lives hundreds of millions of people even higher levels of warming are physically possible within this century some regions of the world would be literally uninhabitable to say nothing of the consequences of sea-level rise for economically important cities such as Amsterdam and New York Even if newly warmed regions of the far north could theoretically accommodate the resulting migrants, this presumes that the political response to this unprecedented global displacement would be orderly and conflict-free borders on fantasy more challenging for national security is the possibility that the until-now linear changes give way to abrupt and irreversible ones at higher levels of warming humanity could trigger catastrophic, abrupt and unavoidable consequences to the ecosystem The IPCC has considered nine such abrupt changes one example is the shutting down of the Indian summer monsoon Over a billion people are dependent upon the Indian monsoon which provides parts of South Asia with about 80 percent of its annual rainfall the Defense Department contractor highlighted the increased risk of inter- and intra-state conflict over natural resources and immigration while the head-turning national security impacts of climate change are probably several decades away, the nature of the threat is such that waiting until these changes manifest is not a viable option By the time the climate consequences are severe enough to compel action, there is likely to be little that can be done on human timescales to undo the changes to environmental systems and the human societies dependent upon them. | climate change will amplify humanitarian crises which result in deployment of military personnel It will aggravate conflict over water, food and energy The question is can the global order survive Even small differences in temperatures result in significant changes with social economic and political consequences changes in temperature hydrological cycle and ranges of insects will impact food availability Storms flooding changes in ocean pH will damage infrastructure labor productivity and growth diseases will be prevalent challenges will translate into migration and geopolitical conflict 70 percent decline in wheat in Central America and 75 percent of land area in Mid East sea level rise could displace hundreds of millions linear changes give way to abrupt irreversible ones humanity could trigger catastrophic abrupt and unavoidable consequences one example waiting until these changes manifest is not viable By the time consequences are severe enough there is little that can be done to undo changes to environmental systems and human societies dependent upon them | At least until 2050, and possibly for decades after, climate change will remain a creeping threat that will exacerbate and amplify existing, structural global inequalities. While the developed world will be negatively affected by climate change through 2050, the consequences of climate change will be felt most acutely in the developing world. The national security threats posed by climate change to 2050 are likely to differ in degree, not kind, from the kinds of threats already posed by climate change. For the next few decades, climate change will exacerbate humanitarian crises—some of which will result in the deployment of military personnel, as well as material and financial assistance. It will also aggravate natural resource constraints, potentially contributing to political and economic conflict over water, food and energy. The question for the next 30 years is not “can humanity survive as a species with 1.5°C or 2°C of warming,” but, “how much will the existing disparities between the developed and developing world widen, and how long (and how successfully) can these widening political/economic disparities be sustained?” The urgency of the climate threat in the next few decades will depend, to a large degree, on whether and how much the U.S. government perceives a widening of these global inequities as a threat to U.S. national security. By contrast, if emissions continue to creep upward (or if they do not decline rapidly), by 2100 climate-related national security threats could be existential. The question for the next hundred years is not, “are disparities politically and economically manageable?” but, “can the global order, premised on the nation-state system, itself based on territorial sovereignty, survive in a world in which substantial swathes of territory are potentially uninhabitable?” National Security Consequences of Climate Change to 2050 Scientists can predict the consequences of climate change to 2050 with some measure of certainty. (Beyond that date, the pace and magnitude of climate change—and therefore, the national security threat posed by it—depend heavily on the level of emissions in the coming years, as I have explained.) There is relative agreement across modeled climate scenarios that the world will likely warm, on average, at least 1.5°C above pre-industrial levels by about 2050—but perhaps as soon as 2030. This level of warming is likely to occur even if the world succeeds in dramatically reducing greenhouse gas emissions, as even the recent Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC) report implicitly admits. In other words, a certain amount of additional warming—at least 1.5°C, and probably more than that—is presumptively unavoidable. Looking ahead to 2050, it can be said with relative confidence that the national security consequences of climate change will vary in degree, not in kind, from the national security threats already facing the United States. This is hardly good news. Even small differences in global average temperatures result in significant environmental changes, with attendant social, economic and political consequences. By 2050, climate change will wreak increasing havoc on human and natural systems—predominantly, but not exclusively, in the developing world—with attenuated but profound consequences for national security. In particular, changes in temperature, the hydrological cycle and the ranges of insects will impact food availability and food access in much of the world, increasing food insecurity. Storms, flooding, changes in ocean pH and other climate-linked changes will damage infrastructure and negatively impact labor productivity and economic growth in much of the world. Vector-borne diseases will also become more prevalent, as climate change will expand the geographic range and intensity of transmission of diseases like malaria, West Nile, Zika and dengue fever, and cholera. Rising public health challenges, economic devastation and food insecurity will translate into an increased demand for humanitarian assistance provided by the military, increased migration—especially from tropical and subtropical regions—and geopolitical conflict. Long-term trends such as declining food security, coupled with short-term events like hurricanes, could sustain unprecedented levels of migration. The 2015 refugee crisis in Europe portends the kinds of population movements that will only accelerate in the coming decades: people from Africa, Southwest and South Asia and elsewhere crossing land and water to reach Europe. For the United States, this likely means greater numbers of people seeking entry from both Central America and the Caribbean. Such influxes are not unprecedented, but they are unlikely to abate and could increase in volume over the next few decades, driven in part by climate change-related food insecurity, climate change-related storms and also by economic and political instability. Food insecurity, economic losses and loss of human life are also likely to exacerbate existing political tensions in the developing world, especially in regions with poor governance and/or where the climate is particularly vulnerable to warming (e.g., the Mediterranean basin). While the Arab Spring had many underlying causes, it also coincided with a period of high food prices, which arguably contributed to the protests. In some situations, food insecurity, economic losses and public health crises, combined with weak and ineffectual governance, could precipitate future conflicts of this kind—although it will be difficult to know where and when without more precise local studies of both underlying political dynamics and the regionally-specific impacts of climate change. 2100 and Beyond While the national security impacts of climate change to 2050 are likely to be costly and disruptive for the U.S. military—and devastating for many people around the world—at some point after 2050, if warming continues at its current pace, changes to the climate could fundamentally reshape geopolitics and possibly even the current nation-state basis of the current global order. To be clear, both the ultimate level of warming and its attendant political consequences is highly speculative, for the reasons I explained in my last post. Nonetheless, we do know that the planet is currently on track for at least 3-4°C of warming by 2100. The “known knowns” of higher levels of warming—say, 3°C—are frightening. At that 3°C of warming, for example, scientists project that there will be a nearly 70 percent decline in wheat production in Central America and the Caribbean, 75 percent of the land area in the Middle East and more than 50 percent in South Asia will be affected by highly unusual heat, and sea level rise could displace and imperil the lives hundreds of millions of people, among other consequences. But even higher levels of warming are physically possible within this century. At these levels of warming, some regions of the world would be literally uninhabitable, likely resulting in the depopulation of the tropics, to say nothing of the consequences of sea-level rise for economically important cities such as Amsterdam and New York. Even if newly warmed regions of the far north could theoretically accommodate the resulting migrants, this presumes that the political response to this unprecedented global displacement would be orderly and conflict-free borders on fantasy. The geopolitical consequences of significant levels of warming are severe, but if these changes occur in a linear way, at least there will be time for human systems to adjust. Perhaps more challenging for national security is the possibility that the until-now linear changes give way to abrupt and irreversible ones. Scientists forecast that, at higher levels of warming—precisely what level is speculative—humanity could trigger catastrophic, abrupt and unavoidable consequences to the ecosystem. The IPCC has considered nine such abrupt changes; one example is the potential shutting down of the Indian summer monsoon. Over a billion people are dependent upon the Indian monsoon, which provides parts of South Asia with about 80 percent of its annual rainfall; relatively minor changes in the monsoon in either direction can cause disasters. In 2010, a wetter monsoon led to the catastrophic flooding in Pakistan, which directly affected 20 million people; a drier monsoon in 2002 led to devastating drought. Studies suggest that the Indian summer monsoon has two stable states: wet (i.e., the current state) and dry (characterized by low precipitation over the subcontinent). At some point, if warming continues, the monsoon could abruptly shift into the second, “dry” state, with catastrophic consequences for over a billion people dependent on monsoon-fed agriculture. The IPCC suggests that such a state-shift is “unlikely”—that is, there is a 10 to 33 percent chance that a state-shift will happen in the 21st century—but scientists also have relatively low confidence in their understanding of the underlying mechanisms in this and other large-scale natural systems. The consequences of abrupt, severe warming for national security are obvious in general, if unclear in the specifics. In 2003, the Defense Department asked a contractor to explore such a scenario. The resulting report outlined the offensive and defensive national security strategies countries may adopt if faced with abrupt climate change, and highlighted the increased risk of inter- and intra-state conflict over natural resources and immigration. Although the report may be off in its imagined timeframe (positing abrupt climate change by 2020), the world it conjures is improbable but not outlandish. If the Indian monsoon were to switch to dry state, and a billion people were suddenly without reliable food sources, for example, it is not clear how the Indian government would react, assuming it would survive in its current form. Major wars or low-intensity proxy conflicts seem likely, if not inevitable, in such a scenario. This is not to say that a parade of climate horribles is certain—or even likely—to come to pass. Scientific understanding of the sensitivities in the climate system are far from perfect. It is also possible that emissions will decline more rapidly than anticipated, averting the worst consequences of climate change. But this outcome is far from guaranteed. And even if global emissions decline precipitously, humanity cannot be sure when or whether the planet has crossed a climate tipping point beyond which the incremental nature of the current changes shifts from the current linear, gradual progression to a non-linear and abrupt process. Within the next few decades, the most likely scenario involves manageable, but costly, consequences on infrastructure, food security and natural disasters, which will be borne primarily by the world’s most impoverished citizens and the members of the military who provide them with humanitarian assistance and disaster relief. But while the head-turning national security impacts of climate change are probably several decades away, the nature of the threat is such that waiting until these changes manifest is not a viable option. By the time the climate consequences are severe enough to compel action, there is likely to be little that can be done on human timescales to undo the changes to environmental systems and the human societies dependent upon them. | 11,436 | <h4>Warming causes <u>extinction</u> – a <u>confluence</u> of <u>nonlinear</u> and <u>unpredictable</u> effects will make human and natural systems inhospitable while increasing <u>escalatory conflicts</u> – even if the impacts are <u>far off</u>, only drastic action <u>now</u> solves</h4><p><strong>Melton 19</strong> [Michelle Melton is a 3L at Harvard Law School. Before law school, she was an associate fellow in the Energy and National Security Program at the Center for Strategic and International Studies, where she focused on climate policy. Climate Change and National Security, Part II: How Big a Threat is the Climate? January 7, 2019. https://www.lawfareblog.com/climate-change-and-national-security-part-ii-how-big-threat-climate]</p><p>At least until 2050, and possibly for decades after, <u><mark>climate change will</mark> remain a <strong>creeping threat</strong> that will <strong>exacerbate and <mark>amplify</strong></mark> existing, <strong>structural</strong> global <strong>inequalities</u></strong>. While the developed world will be negatively affected by climate change through 2050, the consequences of climate change will be felt most acutely in the developing world. The national security threats posed by climate change to 2050 are likely to differ in degree, not kind, from the kinds of threats already posed by climate change. For the next few decades, <u>climate change will <strong>exacerbate <mark>humanitarian crises</u></strong></mark>—<u>some of <mark>which</mark> will <mark>result in</mark> the <mark>deployment of <strong>military personnel</u></strong></mark>, as well as material and financial assistance. <u><mark>It will</u></mark> also <u><strong><mark>aggravate</u></strong></mark> natural <u><strong>resource constraints</u></strong>, potentially <u>contributing to</u> political and economic <u><strong><mark>conflict</strong> over <strong>water</strong>, <strong>food</strong> and <strong>energy</u></strong></mark>. The question for the next 30 years is not “can humanity survive as a species with 1.5°C or 2°C of warming,” but, “how much will the existing disparities between the developed and developing world widen, and how long (and how successfully) can these widening political/economic disparities be sustained?” The urgency of the climate threat in the next few decades will depend, to a large degree, on whether and how much the U.S. government perceives a widening of these global inequities as a threat to U.S. national security. By contrast, <u>if emissions continue to <strong>creep upward</u></strong> (or if they do not decline rapidly), by 2100 climate-related national security <u>threats could be <strong>existential</u></strong>. <u><mark>The question</mark> for the next hundred years <mark>is</mark> not</u>, “are disparities politically and economically manageable?” but, “<u><mark>can the <strong>global order</strong></mark>, premised on the <strong>nation-state system</strong>, itself based on territorial sovereignty, <strong><mark>survive</strong></mark> in a world in which <strong>substantial swathes of territory</strong> are potentially <strong>uninhabitable</u></strong>?” National Security Consequences of Climate Change to 2050 Scientists can predict the consequences of climate change to 2050 with some measure of certainty. (Beyond that date, the pace and magnitude of climate change—and therefore, the national security threat posed by it—depend heavily on the level of emissions in the coming years, as I have explained.) There is relative agreement across modeled climate scenarios that the world will likely warm, on average, at least 1.5°C above pre-industrial levels by about 2050—but perhaps as soon as 2030. This level of warming is likely to occur even if the world succeeds in dramatically reducing greenhouse gas emissions, as even the recent Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC) report implicitly admits. In other words, a certain amount of additional warming—at least 1.5°C, and probably more than that—is presumptively unavoidable. Looking ahead to 2050, it can be said with relative confidence that the national security consequences of climate change will vary in degree, not in kind, from the national security threats already facing the United States. This is hardly good news. <u><mark>Even <strong>small differences</strong> in</mark> global average <strong><mark>temperatures</strong> result in <strong>significant</mark> environmental <mark>changes</strong></mark>, <mark>with</mark> attendant <strong><mark>social</strong></mark>, <strong><mark>economic</strong> and <strong>political consequences</u></strong></mark>. By 2050, <u>climate change will <strong>wreak increasing havoc</strong> on <strong>human</strong> and <strong>natural systems</u></strong>—predominantly, but not exclusively, in the developing world—<u>with</u> attenuated but <u><strong>profound consequences</strong> for <strong>national security</u></strong>. In particular, <u><mark>changes in <strong>temperature</strong></mark>, the <strong><mark>hydrological cycle</strong></mark> <mark>and</mark> the <strong><mark>ranges of insects</strong> will impact <strong>food availability</strong></mark> and food access in much of the world, increasing food insecurity</u>. <u><strong><mark>Storms</strong></mark>, <strong><mark>flooding</strong></mark>, <strong><mark>changes in ocean pH</strong></mark> and other climate-linked changes <mark>will damage <strong>infrastructure</strong></mark> and negatively impact <strong><mark>labor productivity</strong> and</mark> economic <strong><mark>growth</u></strong></mark> in much of the world. <u>Vector-borne <strong><mark>diseases</strong> will</mark> also <mark>be</mark>come <strong>more <mark>prevalent</u></strong></mark>, <u>as climate change will expand the geographic <strong>range</strong> and <strong>intensity</strong> of <strong>transmission</strong> of diseases like malaria, West Nile, Zika and dengue fever, and cholera</u>. <u>Rising <strong>public health <mark>challenges</strong></mark>, <strong>economic devastation</strong> and <strong>food insecurity</strong> <mark>will translate into</mark> an increased <strong>demand</strong> for <strong>humanitarian assistance</strong> provided by the <strong>military</strong>, increased <strong><mark>migration</u></strong></mark>—especially from tropical and subtropical regions—<u><mark>and <strong>geopolitical conflict</u></strong></mark>. Long-term trends such as declining food security, coupled with short-term events like hurricanes, could sustain unprecedented levels of migration. The 2015 refugee crisis in Europe portends the kinds of population movements that will only accelerate in the coming decades: people from Africa, Southwest and South Asia and elsewhere crossing land and water to reach Europe. For the United States, this likely means greater numbers of people seeking entry from both Central America and the Caribbean. Such influxes are not unprecedented, but they are unlikely to abate and could increase in volume over the next few decades, driven in part by climate change-related food insecurity, climate change-related storms and also by economic and political instability. Food insecurity, economic losses and loss of human life are also likely to exacerbate existing political tensions in the developing world, especially in regions with poor governance and/or where the climate is particularly vulnerable to warming (e.g., the Mediterranean basin). While the Arab Spring had many underlying causes, it also coincided with a period of high food prices, which arguably contributed to the protests. In some situations, <u><strong>food insecurity</strong>, <strong>economic losses</strong> and <strong>public health crises</strong>, combined with <strong>weak</strong> and ineffectual <strong>governance</strong>, could <strong>precipitate future conflicts</u></strong> of this kind—although it will be difficult to know where and when without more precise local studies of both underlying political dynamics and the regionally-specific impacts of climate change. 2100 and Beyond While the national security impacts of climate change to 2050 are likely to be costly and disruptive for the U.S. military—and devastating for many people around the world—at some point after 2050, if warming continues at its current pace, <u>changes to the climate could <strong>fundamentally reshape geopolitics</u></strong> and possibly even the current nation-state basis of the current global order. To be clear, both the ultimate level of warming and its attendant political consequences is highly speculative, for the reasons I explained in my last post. Nonetheless, we do know that the planet is currently on track for at least 3-4°C of warming by 2100. The “known knowns” of higher levels of warming—say, 3°C—are frightening. At that 3°C of warming, for example, scientists project that <u>there will</u> be a nearly <u><strong><mark>70 percent decline</strong> in <strong>wheat</strong></mark> production <mark>in <strong>Central America</strong> and</mark> the Caribbean</u>, <u><strong><mark>75 percent</strong> of</mark> the <strong><mark>land area</strong> in</mark> the <strong><mark>Mid</strong></mark>dle <strong><mark>East</u></strong></mark> and more than <u>50 percent in South Asia will be affected by highly unusual heat, and <strong><mark>sea level rise</strong> could <strong>displace</strong></mark> and imperil the lives <strong><mark>hundreds of millions</strong></mark> of people</u>, among other consequences. But <u>even higher levels of warming are physically possible within this century</u>. At these levels of warming, <u>some <strong>regions of the world</strong> would be <strong>literally uninhabitable</u></strong>, likely resulting in the depopulation of the tropics, <u>to say nothing of the consequences of <strong>sea-level rise</strong> for <strong>economically important cities</strong> such as Amsterdam and New York</u>. <u>Even if newly warmed regions of the far north could <strong>theoretically accommodate</strong> the resulting <strong>migrants</strong>, this <strong>presumes</strong> that the <strong>political response</strong> to this unprecedented <strong>global displacement</strong> would be <strong>orderly</strong> and <strong>conflict-free</strong> <strong>borders on fantasy</u></strong>. The geopolitical consequences of significant levels of warming are severe, but if these changes occur in a linear way, at least there will be time for human systems to adjust. Perhaps <u>more challenging for national security is the possibility that the until-now <strong><mark>linear changes give way</strong> to <strong>abrupt</strong></mark> and <strong><mark>irreversible ones</u></strong></mark>. Scientists forecast that, <u>at higher levels of warming</u>—precisely what level is speculative—<u><mark>humanity could trigger <strong>catastrophic</strong></mark>, <strong><mark>abrupt</strong> and <strong>unavoidable consequences</strong></mark> to the <strong>ecosystem</u></strong>. <u>The IPCC has considered <strong>nine</strong> such abrupt changes</u>; <u><mark>one example</mark> is the</u> potential <u><strong>shutting down</strong> of the <strong>Indian summer monsoon</u></strong>. <u>Over a <strong>billion</strong> people are <strong>dependent</strong> upon the Indian monsoon</u>, <u>which provides parts of South Asia with about 80 percent of its annual rainfall</u>; relatively minor changes in the monsoon in either direction can cause disasters. In 2010, a wetter monsoon led to the catastrophic flooding in Pakistan, which directly affected 20 million people; a drier monsoon in 2002 led to devastating drought. Studies suggest that the Indian summer monsoon has two stable states: wet (i.e., the current state) and dry (characterized by low precipitation over the subcontinent). At some point, if warming continues, the monsoon could abruptly shift into the second, “dry” state, with catastrophic consequences for over a billion people dependent on monsoon-fed agriculture. The IPCC suggests that such a state-shift is “unlikely”—that is, there is a 10 to 33 percent chance that a state-shift will happen in the 21st century—but scientists also have relatively low confidence in their understanding of the underlying mechanisms in this and other large-scale natural systems. The consequences of abrupt, severe warming for national security are obvious in general, if unclear in the specifics. In 2003, <u>the Defense Department</u> asked a <u>contractor</u> to explore such a scenario. The resulting report outlined the offensive and defensive national security strategies countries may adopt if faced with abrupt climate change, and <u>highlighted the <strong>increased risk</strong> of inter- and intra-state <strong>conflict</strong> over natural <strong>resources</strong> and <strong>immigration</u></strong>. Although the report may be off in its imagined timeframe (positing abrupt climate change by 2020), the world it conjures is improbable but not outlandish. If the Indian monsoon were to switch to dry state, and a billion people were suddenly without reliable food sources, for example, it is not clear how the Indian government would react, assuming it would survive in its current form. Major wars or low-intensity proxy conflicts seem likely, if not inevitable, in such a scenario. This is not to say that a parade of climate horribles is certain—or even likely—to come to pass. Scientific understanding of the sensitivities in the climate system are far from perfect. It is also possible that emissions will decline more rapidly than anticipated, averting the worst consequences of climate change. But this outcome is far from guaranteed. And even if global emissions decline precipitously, humanity cannot be sure when or whether the planet has crossed a climate tipping point beyond which the incremental nature of the current changes shifts from the current linear, gradual progression to a non-linear and abrupt process. Within the next few decades, the most likely scenario involves manageable, but costly, consequences on infrastructure, food security and natural disasters, which will be borne primarily by the world’s most impoverished citizens and the members of the military who provide them with humanitarian assistance and disaster relief. But <u><strong>while</strong> the head-turning national security <strong>impacts</strong> of climate change are <strong>probably</strong> several <strong>decades away</strong>, the <strong>nature of the threat</strong> is such that <strong><mark>waiting until</strong> these <strong>changes manifest</strong> is <strong>not</mark> a <mark>viable</mark> option</u></strong>. <u><mark>By the time</mark> the climate <mark>consequences are severe enough</mark> to compel action, <mark>there is</mark> likely to be <mark>little that can be done</mark> on human timescales <mark>to undo</mark> the <mark>changes to <strong>environmental systems</strong></mark> <mark>and</mark> the <strong><mark>human societies dependent upon them</strong></mark>.</p></u> | null | 1AC | 1AC – Advantage | 29,415 | 406 | 9,505 | ./documents/hsld20/Harker/Sh1/Harker-Sheth-Aff-Glenbrooks-Round7.docx | 860,009 | A | Glenbrooks | 7 | Lexington AL | Tom Evnen | 1AC - Green Jobs
1NC - T-Spec NC-Kant DA-Readiness
2NR - Induction fails | hsld20/Harker/Sh1/Harker-Sheth-Aff-Glenbrooks-Round7.docx | null | 73,085 | AnSh | Harker AnSh | null | An..... | Sh..... | null | null | 24,534 | Harker | Harker | CA | null | 1,028 | hsld20 | HS LD 2020-21 | 2,020 | ld | hs | 1 |
3,369,941 | 2] Reject “1% risk of extinction”– it collapses all policymaking | Meskill 09 (David, professor at Colorado School of Mines and PhD from Harvard, “The "One Percent Doctrine" and Environmental Faith,” Dec 9, http://davidmeskill.blogspot.com/2009/12/one-percent-doctrine-and-environmental.html) | Meskill 09 (David, professor at Colorado School of Mines and PhD from Harvard, “The "One Percent Doctrine" and Environmental Faith,” Dec 9, http://davidmeskill.blogspot.com/2009/12/one-percent-doctrine-and-environmental.html) | one percent doctrine is both intellectually incoherent and practically irrelevant it cannot be applied consistently in a world with many potential disaster scenarios. In addition to the global-warming risk, there's also the asteroid-hitting-the-earth risk, the terrorists-with-nuclear-weapons risk the super-duper-pandemic risk, etc one percent doctrine," would deserve all of our attention, we cannot address all of them simultaneously we'd have to begin prioritizing But why then should we only make these trade-offs between responses to disaster scenarios? Why not also choose between them and other, much more cotidien, things we value
Why treat the unlikely but cataclysmic event as somehow fundamentally different, something that cannot be integrated into all the other calculations we make We get into our cars buy a cup of coffee We are constantly risking death, if slightly, in order to pursue the things we value Any creature that adopted the "precautionary principle" That creature would neither be able to act, nor not act, since it would nowhere discover perfect safety our response to this news should be is another matter entirely. | one percent doctrine cannot be applied in a world with many disaster scenarios global-warming asteroid- terrorists , etc would deserve all attention, we cannot address them simultaneously we'd have to prioritiz why then should we only make these Why not choose other things we value?
Why treat the cataclysmic event as fundamentally different We get into our cars buy coffee constantly risking death to pursue the things we value. Any creature that adopted the "precautionary principle would neither be able to act, nor not act | Tom Friedman's piece today in the Times on the environment (http://www.nytimes.com/2009/12/09/opinion/09friedman.html?_r=1) is one of the flimsiest pieces by a major columnist that I can remember ever reading. He applies Cheney's "one percent doctrine" (which is similar to the environmentalists' "precautionary principle") to the risk of environmental armageddon. But this doctrine is both intellectually incoherent and practically irrelevant. It is intellectually incoherent because it cannot be applied consistently in a world with many potential disaster scenarios. In addition to the global-warming risk, there's also the asteroid-hitting-the-earth risk, the terrorists-with-nuclear-weapons risk (Cheney's original scenario), the super-duper-pandemic risk, etc. Since each of these risks, on the "one percent doctrine," would deserve all of our attention, we cannot address all of them simultaneously. That is, even within the one-percent mentality, we'd have to begin prioritizing, making choices and trade-offs. But why then should we only make these trade-offs between responses to disaster scenarios? Why not also choose between them and other, much more cotidien, things we value?
Why treat the unlikely but cataclysmic event as somehow fundamentally different, something that cannot be integrated into all the other calculations we make? And in fact, this is how we behave all the time. We get into our cars in order to buy a cup of coffee, even though there's some chance we will be killed on the way to the coffee shop. We are constantly risking death, if slightly, in order to pursue the things we value. Any creature that adopted the "precautionary principle" would sit at home - no, not even there, since there is some chance the building might collapse. That creature would neither be able to act, nor not act, since it would nowhere discover perfect safety. Friedman's approach reminds me somehow of Pascal's wager - quasi-religious faith masquerading as rational deliberation (as Hans Albert has pointed out, Pascal's wager itself doesn't add up: there may be a God, in fact, but it may turn out that He dislikes, and even damns, people who believe in him because they've calculated it's in their best interest to do so). As my friend James points out, it's striking how descriptions of the environmental risk always describe the situation as if it were five to midnight. It must be near midnight, since otherwise there would be no need to act. But it can never be five *past* midnight, since then acting would be pointless and we might as well party like it was 2099. Many religious movements - for example the early Jesus movement - have exhibited precisely this combination of traits: the looming apocalypse, with the time (just barely) to take action. None of this is to deny - at least this is my current sense - that human action is contributing to global warming. But what our response to this news should be is another matter entirely. | 2,962 | <h4>2] Reject “1% risk of extinction”– it collapses all policymaking</h4><p><strong>Meskill 09</strong> <strong>(David, professor at Colorado School of Mines and PhD from Harvard, “The "One Percent Doctrine" and Environmental Faith,” Dec 9, http://davidmeskill.blogspot.com/2009/12/one-percent-doctrine-and-environmental.html)</p><p></strong>Tom Friedman's piece today in the Times on the environment (http://www.nytimes.com/2009/12/09/opinion/09friedman.html?_r=1) is one of the flimsiest pieces by a major columnist that I can remember ever reading. He applies Cheney's "<u><strong><mark>one percent doctrine</u></strong></mark>" (which is similar to the environmentalists' "precautionary principle") to the risk of environmental armageddon. But this doctrine <u><strong>is both intellectually incoherent and practically irrelevant</u></strong>. It is intellectually incoherent because <u><strong>it <mark>cannot be applied </mark>consistently <mark>in a world with many</mark> potential <mark>disaster scenarios</mark>. In addition to the <mark>global-warming</mark> risk, there's also the <mark>asteroid-</mark>hitting-the-earth risk, the <mark>terrorists</mark>-with-nuclear-weapons risk</u></strong> (Cheney's original scenario), <u><strong>the super-duper-pandemic risk<mark>, etc</u></strong></mark>. Since each of these risks, on the "<u><strong>one percent doctrine," <mark>would deserve all</mark> of our <mark>attention, we cannot address</mark> all of <mark>them simultaneously</u></strong></mark>. That is, even within the one-percent mentality, <u><strong><mark>we'd have to</mark> begin <mark>prioritiz</mark>ing</u></strong>, making choices and trade-offs. <u><strong>But <mark>why then should we only make these </mark>trade-offs between responses to disaster scenarios? <mark>Why not</mark> also <mark>choose</mark> between them and <mark>other</mark>, much more cotidien, <mark>things we value</u></strong>?<u><strong></mark> </p><p><mark>Why treat the</mark> unlikely but <mark>cataclysmic event as</mark> somehow <mark>fundamentally different</mark>, something that cannot be integrated into all the other calculations we make</u></strong>? And in fact, this is how we behave all the time. <u><strong><mark>We get into our cars</u></strong></mark> in order to <u><strong><mark>buy </mark>a cup of <mark>coffee</u></strong></mark>, even though there's some chance we will be killed on the way to the coffee shop. <u><strong>We are <mark>constantly risking death</mark>, if slightly, in order <mark>to pursue the things we value</u></strong>. <u><strong>Any creature that adopted the "precautionary principle</mark>"</u></strong> would sit at home - no, not even there, since there is some chance the building might collapse. <u><strong>That creature <mark>would neither be able to act, nor not act</mark>, since it would nowhere discover perfect safety</u></strong>. Friedman's approach reminds me somehow of Pascal's wager - quasi-religious faith masquerading as rational deliberation (as Hans Albert has pointed out, Pascal's wager itself doesn't add up: there may be a God, in fact, but it may turn out that He dislikes, and even damns, people who believe in him because they've calculated it's in their best interest to do so). As my friend James points out, it's striking how descriptions of the environmental risk always describe the situation as if it were five to midnight. It must be near midnight, since otherwise there would be no need to act. But it can never be five *past* midnight, since then acting would be pointless and we might as well party like it was 2099. Many religious movements - for example the early Jesus movement - have exhibited precisely this combination of traits: the looming apocalypse, with the time (just barely) to take action. None of this is to deny - at least this is my current sense - that human action is contributing to global warming. But what <u><strong>our response to this news should be is another matter entirely.</p></u></strong> | null | 1AC | Contention 3 is Framing | 46,317 | 378 | 112,458 | ./documents/hsld18/WestlakeCA/El/Westlake%20CA-Elasky-Aff-calinvitationalucberkeley-Round2.docx | 831,716 | A | calinvitationalucberkeley | 2 | Holy Cross BZ | Cang | 1ac - yemen
1nc - fill in da conditions cp terror da case
1ar2nr2ar - all | hsld18/WestlakeCA/El/Westlake%20CA-Elasky-Aff-calinvitationalucberkeley-Round2.docx | null | 71,092 | EtEl | Westlake CA EtEl | null | Et..... | El..... | null | null | 23,949 | WestlakeCA | Westlake CA | null | null | 1,026 | hsld18 | HS LD 2018-19 | 2,018 | ld | hs | 1 |
3,983,773 | Warming doesn’t cause extinction---new studies. | Nordhaus 20 | Nordhaus 20 Ted Nordhaus, an American author, environmental policy expert, and the director of research at The Breakthrough Institute, citing new climate change forecasts. [Ignore the Fake Climate Debate, 1-23-2020, https://www.wsj.com/articles/ignore-the-fake-climate-debate-11579795816]//BPS | Beyond headlines and social media “alarmists” and “deniers” there is a real climate debate in scientific journals It gets less attention most pessimists do not believe runaway climate change or a hothouse earth are plausible scenarios, much less that human extinction is imminent A richer world will be more technologically advanced, which means energy should be less carbon-intensive New research finds global economic growth has reduced climate mortality by a factor of five recent forecasts suggest the worst-case climate scenarios are very unlikely. There is still substantial uncertainty about temperatures the best estimates suggest the world is on track for 3 degrees of warming energy intensity continues to fall. Lower-carbon natural gas displaced coal falling cost of wind and solar energy have an effect on fossil fuels. Even nuclear energy made a modest comeback | Beyond social media there is debate in journals pessimists do not believe runaway or hothouse are plausible much less extinction richer world will be be less carbon-intensive growth reduced mortality by five forecasts suggest worst-case are unlikely. There is uncertainty estimates suggest world is on 3 degrees | Beyond the headlines and social media, where Greta Thunberg, Donald Trump and the online armies of climate “alarmists” and “deniers” do battle, there is a real climate debate bubbling along in scientific journals, conferences and, occasionally, even in the halls of Congress. It gets a lot less attention than the boisterous and fake debate that dominates our public discourse, but it is much more relevant to how the world might actually address the problem. In the real climate debate, no one denies the relationship between human emissions of greenhouse gases and a warming climate. Instead, the disagreement comes down to different views of climate risk in the face of multiple, cascading uncertainties. On one side of the debate are optimists, who believe that, with improving technology and greater affluence, our societies will prove quite adaptable to a changing climate. On the other side are pessimists, who are more concerned about the risks associated with rapid, large-scale and poorly understood transformations of the climate system. But most pessimists do not believe that runaway climate change or a hothouse earth are plausible scenarios, much less that human extinction is imminent. And most optimists recognize a need for policies to address climate change, even if they don’t support the radical measures that Ms. Thunberg and others have demanded. In the fake climate debate, both sides agree that economic growth and reduced emissions vary inversely; it’s a zero-sum game. In the real debate, the relationship is much more complicated. Long-term economic growth is associated with both rising per capita energy consumption and slower population growth. For this reason, as the world continues to get richer, higher per capita energy consumption is likely to be offset by a lower population. A richer world will also likely be more technologically advanced, which means that energy consumption should be less carbon-intensive than it would be in a poorer, less technologically advanced future. In fact, a number of the high-emissions scenarios produced by the United Nations Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change involve futures in which the world is relatively poor and populous and less technologically advanced. Affluent, developed societies are also much better equipped to respond to climate extremes and natural disasters. That’s why natural disasters kill and displace many more people in poor societies than in rich ones. It’s not just seawalls and flood channels that make us resilient; it’s air conditioning and refrigeration, modern transportation and communications networks, early warning systems, first responders and public health bureaucracies. New research published in the journal Global Environmental Change finds that global economic growth over the last decade has reduced climate mortality by a factor of five, with the greatest benefits documented in the poorest nations. In low-lying Bangladesh, 300,000 people died in Cyclone Bhola in 1970, when 80% of the population lived in extreme poverty. In 2019, with less than 20% of the population living in extreme poverty, Cyclone Fani killed just five people. “Poor nations are most vulnerable to a changing climate. The fastest way to reduce that vulnerability is through economic development.” So while it is true that poor nations are most vulnerable to a changing climate, it is also true that the fastest way to reduce that vulnerability is through economic development, which requires infrastructure and industrialization. Those activities, in turn, require cement, steel, process heat and chemical inputs, all of which are impossible to produce today without fossil fuels. For this and other reasons, the world is unlikely to cut emissions fast enough to stabilize global temperatures at less than 2 degrees above pre-industrial levels, the long-standing international target, much less 1.5 degrees, as many activists now demand. But recent forecasts also suggest that many of the worst-case climate scenarios produced in the last decade, which assumed unbounded economic growth and fossil-fuel development, are also very unlikely. There is still substantial uncertainty about how sensitive global temperatures will be to higher emissions over the long-term. But the best estimates now suggest that the world is on track for 3 degrees of warming by the end of this century, not 4 or 5 degrees as was once feared. That is due in part to slower economic growth in the wake of the global financial crisis, but also to decades of technology policy and energy-modernization efforts. “We have better and cleaner technologies available today because policy-makers in the U.S. and elsewhere set out to develop those technologies.” The energy intensity of the global economy continues to fall. Lower-carbon natural gas has displaced coal as the primary source of new fossil energy. The falling cost of wind and solar energy has begun to have an effect on the growth of fossil fuels. Even nuclear energy has made a modest comeback in Asia. | 5,032 | <h4><strong>Warming doesn’t cause extinction---new studies.</h4><p>Nordhaus 20</strong> Ted Nordhaus, an American author, environmental policy expert, and the director of research at The Breakthrough Institute, citing new climate change forecasts. [Ignore the Fake Climate Debate, 1-23-2020, https://www.wsj.com/articles/ignore-the-fake-climate-debate-11579795816]//BPS</p><p><u><mark>Beyond</u></mark> the <u>headlines and <mark>social media</u></mark>, where Greta Thunberg, Donald Trump and the online armies of climate <u>“alarmists” and “deniers”</u> do battle, <u><mark>there is</mark> <strong>a real climate <mark>debate</u></strong></mark> bubbling along <u><mark>in</mark> <strong>scientific <mark>journals</u></strong></mark>, conferences and, occasionally, even in the halls of Congress. <u>It gets</u> a lot <u>less attention</u> than the boisterous and fake debate that dominates our public discourse, but it is much more relevant to how the world might actually address the problem. In the real climate debate, no one denies the relationship between human emissions of greenhouse gases and a warming climate. Instead, the disagreement comes down to different views of climate risk in the face of multiple, cascading uncertainties. On one side of the debate are optimists, who believe that, with improving technology and greater affluence, our societies will prove quite adaptable to a changing climate. On the other side are pessimists, who are more concerned about the risks associated with rapid, large-scale and poorly understood transformations of the climate system. But <u><strong>most <mark>pessimists</strong> do not believe</u></mark> that <u><strong><mark>runaway</mark> climate change</strong> <mark>or</mark> <strong>a <mark>hothouse</mark> earth</strong> <mark>are plausible</mark> scenarios, <strong><mark>much less</strong></mark> that <strong>human <mark>extinction</strong></mark> is imminent</u>. And most optimists recognize a need for policies to address climate change, even if they don’t support the radical measures that Ms. Thunberg and others have demanded. In the fake climate debate, both sides agree that economic growth and reduced emissions vary inversely; it’s a zero-sum game. In the real debate, the relationship is much more complicated. Long-term economic growth is associated with both rising per capita energy consumption and slower population growth. For this reason, as the world continues to get richer, higher per capita energy consumption is likely to be offset by a lower population. <u><strong>A <mark>richer world</strong> will</u></mark> also likely <u><mark>be</mark> <strong>more technologically advanced</strong>, which means</u> that <u>energy</u> consumption <u>should <mark>be <strong>less carbon-intensive</u></strong></mark> than it would be in a poorer, less technologically advanced future. In fact, a number of the high-emissions scenarios produced by the United Nations Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change involve futures in which the world is relatively poor and populous and less technologically advanced. Affluent, developed societies are also much better equipped to respond to climate extremes and natural disasters. That’s why natural disasters kill and displace many more people in poor societies than in rich ones. It’s not just seawalls and flood channels that make us resilient; it’s air conditioning and refrigeration, modern transportation and communications networks, early warning systems, first responders and public health bureaucracies. <u>New research</u> published in the journal Global Environmental Change <u>finds</u> that <u><strong>global economic <mark>growth</u></strong></mark> over the last decade <u>has <strong><mark>reduced</strong></mark> climate <mark>mortality by</mark> <strong>a factor of <mark>five</u></strong></mark>, with the greatest benefits documented in the poorest nations. In low-lying Bangladesh, 300,000 people died in Cyclone Bhola in 1970, when 80% of the population lived in extreme poverty. In 2019, with less than 20% of the population living in extreme poverty, Cyclone Fani killed just five people. “Poor nations are most vulnerable to a changing climate. The fastest way to reduce that vulnerability is through economic development.” So while it is true that poor nations are most vulnerable to a changing climate, it is also true that the fastest way to reduce that vulnerability is through economic development, which requires infrastructure and industrialization. Those activities, in turn, require cement, steel, process heat and chemical inputs, all of which are impossible to produce today without fossil fuels. For this and other reasons, the world is unlikely to cut emissions fast enough to stabilize global temperatures at less than 2 degrees above pre-industrial levels, the long-standing international target, much less 1.5 degrees, as many activists now demand. But <u><strong>recent <mark>forecasts</u></strong></mark> also <u><mark>suggest</u></mark> that many of <u><strong>the <mark>worst-case</mark> climate scenarios</u></strong> produced in the last decade, which assumed unbounded economic growth and fossil-fuel development, <u><mark>are</u></mark> also <u><strong>very <mark>unlikely</strong>. There is</mark> <strong>still substantial <mark>uncertainty</strong></mark> about</u> how sensitive global <u>temperatures</u> will be to higher emissions over the long-term. But <u><strong>the best <mark>estimates</u></strong></mark> now <u><mark>suggest</u></mark> that <u>the <mark>world is on</mark> track for <strong><mark>3 degrees</mark> of warming</u></strong> by the end of this century, not 4 or 5 degrees as was once feared. That is due in part to slower economic growth in the wake of the global financial crisis, but also to decades of technology policy and energy-modernization efforts. “We have better and cleaner technologies available today because policy-makers in the U.S. and elsewhere set out to develop those technologies.” The <u>energy intensity</u> of the global economy <u>continues to fall. Lower-carbon natural gas</u> has <u>displaced coal</u> as the primary source of new fossil energy. The <u>falling cost of wind and solar energy</u> has begun to <u>have an effect on</u> the growth of <u>fossil fuels. Even nuclear energy</u> has <u>made a modest comeback</u> in Asia.</p> | null | Fracking Advantage | 1NC – Warming | 21,182 | 346 | 134,573 | ./documents/hspolicy21/NewTrier/ShMo/New%20Trier-Shah-Moore-Neg-IDCA%20JV%20State-Round2.docx | 752,244 | N | IDCA JV State | 2 | Walter Payton RZ | Matthew Sung | 1AC - Fracking
1NC - States CP Reg Neg CP Antitrust DA T Permitting Warming Good High Food Prices Good
2NR - Reg Neg CP Antitrust DA | hspolicy21/NewTrier/ShMo/New%20Trier-Shah-Moore-Neg-IDCA%20JV%20State-Round2.docx | null | 64,142 | ShMo | New Trier ShMo | null | Av..... | Sh..... | An..... | Mo..... | 22,064 | NewTrier | New Trier | IL | null | 1,020 | hspolicy21 | HS Policy 2021-22 | 2,021 | cx | hs | 2 |
2,321,898 | Unsafe AI development spirals and causes extinction – paperclips prove | Bostrom et. al 14 | Bostrom et. al 14 [Nick Bostrom is an Oxford University philosopher, Stephen Cass is a staff writer for IEEE Spectrum, and Eliza Strickland has read Bostrom’s book and spoken to him;also IEEE Spectrum Associate Editor, 12/4/14, Nick Bostrom, “Nick Bostrom Says We Should Trust Our Future Robot Overlords”, http://spectrum.ieee.org/podcast/robotics/artificial-intelligence/nick-bostrom-says-we-should-trust-our-future-robot-overlords]-DD | There are obviously existential risks that arise from nature, asteroid impacts, supervolcanic eruptions, and so forth. But the human species has been around for over 100,000 years. So if these risks from nature have failed to do us in in the last 100,000 years, they are unlikely to do us in in the next 100 years, whereas we ourselves will be introducing entirely new kinds of phenomena into the world in this century by advancing the frontier of technology. With these brand-new technologies come brand-new risks that our species might not be able to survive. Right now, computer scientists can build very smart AIs, but for very specific tasks We did do a survey of the world’s leading AI experts. One of the questions we asked was: By which year do you think there’s a 50 percent chance that we will have developed human-level machine intelligence? The median answer to that question was 2040 or 2050, depending on exactly which group of experts we asked. Because once we do make an AI with human-level intelligence, things could go bad in a hurry. so let’s suppose an AI does achieve superintelligence. Why would it seek to destroy its human creators? it wouldn’t have any grudge against us—but the AI would have some goal, and we’d just be in its way. It would be similar to the way that humans cause animal extinctions, he said. : Let’s suppose you were a superintelligence and your goal was to make as many paper clips as possible. Maybe someone wanted you to run a paper clip factory, and then you succeeded in becoming superintelligent, and now you have this goal of maximizing the number of paper clips in existence. So you would quickly realize that the existence of humans is an impediment. Maybe the humans will take it upon themselves to switch you off one day. You want to reduce that probability as much as possible, because if they switch you off, there will be fewer paper clips. So you would want to get rid of humans right away. Even if they wouldn’t pose a threat, you’d still realize that human bodies consist of atoms, and those atoms could be used to make some very nice paper clips. Bostrom thinks that just about any goal we give an AI could come back to bite us. Even if we go with something like “make humans happy,” the machine could decide that the most effective way to meet this goal is to stick electrodes in the pleasure centers of all our brains. | With brand-new technologies come brand-new risks that our species might not be able to survive once we e an AI with human-level intelligence, things could go bad in a hurry AI would have some goal, and we’d just be in its way suppose you were a superintelligence and your goal was to make paper clips you would realize that the existence of humans is an impediment Maybe the humans will switch you off You want to reduce that probability So you would want to get rid of humans you’d realize that human bodies consist of atoms, and could be used to make paper clips any goal we give an AI could come back to bite us | Nick Bostrom: There are obviously existential risks that arise from nature, asteroid impacts, supervolcanic eruptions, and so forth. But the human species has been around for over 100,000 years. So if these risks from nature have failed to do us in in the last 100,000 years, they are unlikely to do us in in the next 100 years, whereas we ourselves will be introducing entirely new kinds of phenomena into the world in this century by advancing the frontier of technology. Eliza Strickland: With these brand-new technologies come brand-new risks that our species might not be able to survive. Stephen Cass: We’ve seen some pretty impressive AIs recently, like IBM’s Watson, which tromped the human competition on the TV game show “Jeopardy!” But how smart have AIs really gotten? Eliza Strickland: Right now, computer scientists can build very smart AIs, but for very specific tasks. IBM’s Watson won “Jeopardy!” because it can understand conversational English and look up information, but that’s all it can do. Watson can’t write you an e-mail describing what its data center looks like, or explain why its programmers are moving slowly after a big lunch. We’re still a long way from creating an AI that can match a human’s level of general intelligence, although Bostrom says we don’t know exactly how long. Nick Bostrom: We did do a survey of the world’s leading AI experts. One of the questions we asked was: By which year do you think there’s a 50 percent chance that we will have developed human-level machine intelligence? The median answer to that question was 2040 or 2050, depending on exactly which group of experts we asked. Stephen Cass: So why should we start worrying about this now? Eliza Strickland: Because once we do make an AI with human-level intelligence, things could go bad in a hurry. Here’s what Bostrom said. Nick Bostrom: Well, at the moment, it’s computer scientists who are doing AI research, and to some extent neuroscientists and other folk. If and when machines begin to surpass humans in general intelligence, the research would increasingly be done by machines. And as they got better, they would also get better at doing the research to make themselves even better. Eliza Strickland: With this feedback loop, Bostrom says, an AI could go from human-level intelligence to superintelligence before we’re really prepared for it. Stephen Cass: Okay, so let’s suppose an AI does achieve superintelligence. Why would it seek to destroy its human creators? Eliza Strickland: Bostrom says it wouldn’t have any grudge against us—but the AI would have some goal, and we’d just be in its way. It would be similar to the way that humans cause animal extinctions, he said. Nick Bostrom: If we think about what we are doing to various animal species, it’s not so much that we hate them. For the most part, it’s just that we have other uses for their habitats, and they get wiped out as a side effect. Stephen Cass: So what motivates an AI? What would it be trying to accomplish? Eliza Strickland: It would have some goal that had been programmed into it by scientists. And Bostrom explains that even simple goals can have disastrous consequences. Nick Bostrom: Let’s suppose you were a superintelligence and your goal was to make as many paper clips as possible. Maybe someone wanted you to run a paper clip factory, and then you succeeded in becoming superintelligent, and now you have this goal of maximizing the number of paper clips in existence. So you would quickly realize that the existence of humans is an impediment. Maybe the humans will take it upon themselves to switch you off one day. You want to reduce that probability as much as possible, because if they switch you off, there will be fewer paper clips. So you would want to get rid of humans right away. Even if they wouldn’t pose a threat, you’d still realize that human bodies consist of atoms, and those atoms could be used to make some very nice paper clips. Eliza Strickland: Bostrom thinks that just about any goal we give an AI could come back to bite us. Even if we go with something like “make humans happy,” the machine could decide that the most effective way to meet this goal is to stick electrodes in the pleasure centers of all our brains. Stephen Cass: Isn’t that—spoiler alert!—basically the plot of the sci-fi movie I, Robot? Eliza Strickland: Oh, yeah. That was the Will Smith movie based on Isaac Asimov’s famous three laws of robotics, which are supposed to guarantee that a robot won’t hurt a human being. In the movie—and actually in most of Asimov’s robot stories—the laws don’t work quite as intended. | 4,619 | <h4>Unsafe AI development spirals and causes extinction – paperclips prove</h4><p><strong>Bostrom et. al 14</strong> [Nick Bostrom is an Oxford University philosopher, Stephen Cass is a staff writer for IEEE Spectrum, and Eliza Strickland has read Bostrom’s book and spoken to him;also IEEE Spectrum Associate Editor, 12/4/14, Nick Bostrom, “Nick Bostrom Says We Should Trust Our Future Robot Overlords”, http://spectrum.ieee.org/podcast/robotics/artificial-intelligence/nick-bostrom-says-we-should-trust-our-future-robot-overlords]-DD</p><p>Nick Bostrom: <u><strong>There are obviously existential risks that arise from nature, asteroid impacts, supervolcanic eruptions, and so forth. But the human species has been around for over 100,000 years. So if these risks from nature have failed to do us in in the last 100,000 years, they are unlikely to do us in in the next 100 years, whereas we ourselves will be introducing entirely new kinds of phenomena into the world in this century by advancing the frontier of technology.</u></strong> Eliza Strickland: <u><strong><mark>With</mark> these <mark>brand-new technologies come brand-new risks that our species might not be able to survive</strong></mark>.</u> Stephen Cass: We’ve seen some pretty impressive AIs recently, like IBM’s Watson, which tromped the human competition on the TV game show “Jeopardy!” But how smart have AIs really gotten? Eliza Strickland: <u><strong>Right now, computer scientists can build very smart AIs, but for very specific tasks</u></strong>. IBM’s Watson won “Jeopardy!” because it can understand conversational English and look up information, but that’s all it can do. Watson can’t write you an e-mail describing what its data center looks like, or explain why its programmers are moving slowly after a big lunch. We’re still a long way from creating an AI that can match a human’s level of general intelligence, although Bostrom says we don’t know exactly how long. Nick Bostrom: <u><strong>We did do a survey of the world’s leading AI experts. One of the questions we asked was: By which year do you think there’s a 50 percent chance that we will have developed human-level machine intelligence? The median answer to that question was 2040 or 2050, depending on exactly which group of experts we asked</strong>.</u> Stephen Cass: So why should we start worrying about this now? Eliza Strickland: <u><strong>Because <mark>once we</mark> do mak<mark>e an AI with human-level intelligence, things could go bad in a hurry</mark>.</u></strong> Here’s what Bostrom said. Nick Bostrom: Well, at the moment, it’s computer scientists who are doing AI research, and to some extent neuroscientists and other folk. If and when machines begin to surpass humans in general intelligence, the research would increasingly be done by machines. And as they got better, they would also get better at doing the research to make themselves even better. Eliza Strickland: With this feedback loop, Bostrom says, an AI could go from human-level intelligence to superintelligence before we’re really prepared for it. Stephen Cass: Okay, <u><strong>so let’s suppose an AI does achieve superintelligence. Why would it seek to destroy its human creators?</u></strong> Eliza Strickland: Bostrom says <u><strong>it wouldn’t have any grudge against us—but the <mark>AI would have some goal, and we’d just be in its way</mark>. It would be similar to the way that humans cause animal extinctions, he said.</u></strong> Nick Bostrom: If we think about what we are doing to various animal species, it’s not so much that we hate them. For the most part, it’s just that we have other uses for their habitats, and they get wiped out as a side effect. Stephen Cass: So what motivates an AI? What would it be trying to accomplish? Eliza Strickland: It would have some goal that had been programmed into it by scientists. And Bostrom explains that even simple goals can have disastrous consequences. Nick Bostrom<u><strong>: Let’s <mark>suppose you were a superintelligence and your goal was to make</mark> as many <mark>paper clips</mark> as possible. Maybe someone wanted you to run a paper clip factory, and then you succeeded in becoming superintelligent, and now you have this goal of maximizing the number of paper clips in existence. So <mark>you would</mark> quickly <mark>realize that the existence of humans is an impediment</mark>. <mark>Maybe the humans will</mark> take it upon themselves to <mark>switch you off</mark> one day. <mark>You want to reduce that probability</mark> as much as possible, because if they switch you off, there will be fewer paper clips. <mark>So you would want to get rid of humans</mark> right away. Even if they wouldn’t pose a threat, <mark>you’d</mark> still <mark>realize that human bodies consist of atoms,</mark> <mark>and</mark> those atoms <mark>could be used to make</mark> some very nice <mark>paper clips</mark>.</u></strong> Eliza Strickland: <u><strong>Bostrom thinks that just about <mark>any goal we give an AI could come back to bite us</mark>. Even if we go with something like “make humans happy,” the machine could decide that the most effective way to meet this goal is to stick electrodes in the pleasure centers of all our brains</strong>.</u> Stephen Cass: Isn’t that—spoiler alert!—basically the plot of the sci-fi movie I, Robot? Eliza Strickland: Oh, yeah. That was the Will Smith movie based on Isaac Asimov’s famous three laws of robotics, which are supposed to guarantee that a robot won’t hurt a human being. In the movie—and actually in most of Asimov’s robot stories—the laws don’t work quite as intended.</p> | 1AC | null | Advantage 1 – AI | 162,481 | 196 | 73,490 | ./documents/hsld20/Princeton/Go/Princeton-Gong-Aff-Lexington-Round6.docx | 871,611 | A | Lexington | 6 | Curtis Chang | Conal Thomas-McGinnis | 1AC-Stock Disclosure
1NC-shells
1AR-aprioris
2NR-shell
2AR-aprioris | hsld20/Princeton/Go/Princeton-Gong-Aff-Lexington-Round6.docx | null | 73,672 | JuGo | Princeton JuGo | null | Ju..... | Go..... | null | null | 24,686 | Princeton | Princeton | NJ | null | 1,028 | hsld20 | HS LD 2020-21 | 2,020 | ld | hs | 1 |
4,030,118 | The aff is try or die – we need to act as soon as possible to meet the 2° goal or we’re all dead | Worland 7/9 ) | Worland 7/9 (Justin Worland, 7-9-2020, "2020 Is Our Last, Best Chance to Save the Planet," Time, https://time.com/5864692/climate-change-defining-moment/) | we may look back at 2020 as the year we decided to keep driving off the climate cliff–or to take the last exit. Taking the threat seriously would mean using the opportunity presented by this crisis to spend on solar panels and wind farms, push companies being bailed out to cut emissions and foster greener forms of transport in cities. If we instead choose to fund new coal-fired power plants and oil wells and thoughtlessly fire up factories to urge growth, we will lock in a pathway toward climate catastrophe. We’re standing at a climate crossroads: the world has already warmed 1.1°C since the Industrial Revolution. If we pass 2°C, we risk hitting one or more major tipping points, where the effects of climate change go from advancing gradually to changing dramatically overnight, reshaping the planet. To ensure that we don’t pass that threshold, we need to cut emissions in half by 2030. Climate change has understandably fallen out of the public eye this year as the coronavirus pandemic rages The time frame for effective climate action was always going to be tight, but the coronavirus pandemic has shrunk it further. Scientists and policymakers expected the green transition to occur over the next decade, but the pandemic has pushed 10 years of anticipated investment in everything from power plants to roads into a monthslong time frame. “It’s in this next six months that recovery strategies are likely to be formulated and the path is set,” says Nicholas Stern, a former World Bank chief economist known for his landmark 2006 report warning that climate change could devastate the global economy. To achieve the 1.5°C goal without creating mass disruption has always meant thoughtfully restructuring the global economy, moving it away from fossil-fuel extraction slowly but surely. Scientists and economists agree this is the last opportunity we have to do so. “If we delay further than 2020,” says Rockstrom, “there’s absolutely no empirical evidence that it can be done in an orderly way.” But this moment is not just about opportunity; even maintaining the status quo is dangerous. Research from the UNEP released last year shows that if nations stick with current plans to reduce emissions, global temperatures will rise more than 3°C by the end of this century. | If we pass 2°C risk hitting tipping points effects of climate change go from advancing gradually to changing dramatically overnight cut emissions in half by 2030 time frame always tight coronavirus shrunk further pushed investment into monthslong time frame climate change could devastate the global economy this is the last opportunity we have to do so If we delay further than 2020 no empirical evidence that it can be done in an orderly way even maintaining the status quo is dangerous if nations stick with current plans to reduce emissions temperatures rise more than 3°C by end of century | From our vantage point today, 2020 looks like the year when an unknown virus spun out of control, killed hundreds of thousands and altered the way we live day to day. In the future, we may look back at 2020 as the year we decided to keep driving off the climate cliff–or to take the last exit. Taking the threat seriously would mean using the opportunity presented by this crisis to spend on solar panels and wind farms, push companies being bailed out to cut emissions and foster greener forms of transport in cities. If we instead choose to fund new coal-fired power plants and oil wells and thoughtlessly fire up factories to urge growth, we will lock in a pathway toward climate catastrophe. There’s a divide about which way to go. In early April, as COVID-19 spread across the U.S. and doctors urgently warned that New York City might soon run out of ventilators and hospital beds, President Donald Trump gathered CEOs from some of the country’s biggest oil and gas companies for a closed-door meeting in the White House Cabinet Room. The industry faced its biggest disruption in decades, and Trump wanted to help the companies secure their place at the center of the 21st century American economy. Everything was on the table, from a tariff on imports to the U.S. government itself purchasing excess oil. “We’ll work this out, and we’ll get our energy business back,” Trump told the CEOs. “I’m with you 1,000%.” A few days later, he announced he had brokered a deal with Russian President Vladimir Putin and Saudi Crown Prince Mohammed bin Salman to cut oil production and rescue the industry. Later in April, Ursula von der Leyen, the president of the European Commission, in a video message from across the Atlantic, offered a different approach for the continent’s economic future. A European Green Deal, she said, would be the E.U.’s “motor for the recovery.” “We can turn the crisis of this pandemic into an opportunity to rebuild our economies differently,” she said. On May 27, she pledged more than $800 billion to the initiative, promising to transform the way Europeans live. For the past three years, the world outside the U.S. has largely tried to ignore Trump’s retrograde position on climate, hoping 2020 would usher in a new President with a new position, re-enabling the cooperation between nations needed to prevent the worst ravages of climate change. But there’s no more time to wait. We’re standing at a climate crossroads: the world has already warmed 1.1°C since the Industrial Revolution. If we pass 2°C, we risk hitting one or more major tipping points, where the effects of climate change go from advancing gradually to changing dramatically overnight, reshaping the planet. To ensure that we don’t pass that threshold, we need to cut emissions in half by 2030. Climate change has understandably fallen out of the public eye this year as the coronavirus pandemic rages. Nevertheless, this year, or perhaps this year and next, is likely to be the most pivotal yet in the fight against climate change. “We’ve run out of time to build new things in old ways,” says Rob Jackson, an earth system science professor at Stanford University and the chair of the Global Carbon Project. What we do now will define the fate of the planet–and human life on it–for decades. The time frame for effective climate action was always going to be tight, but the coronavirus pandemic has shrunk it further. Scientists and policymakers expected the green transition to occur over the next decade, but the pandemic has pushed 10 years of anticipated investment in everything from power plants to roads into a monthslong time frame. Countries have already spent $11 trillion to help stem the economic damage from COVID-19. They could spend trillions more. “It’s in this next six months that recovery strategies are likely to be formulated and the path is set,” says Nicholas Stern, a former World Bank chief economist known for his landmark 2006 report warning that climate change could devastate the global economy. We don’t know where the chips will fall: Will a newfound respect for science and a fear of future shocks lead us to finally wake up, or will the desire to return to normal overshadow the threats lurking just around the corner? We find ourselves on the brink of climate catastrophe in large part because of the decisions made during a past crisis. As the world came out of the Great Depression and World War II, the U.S. launched a rapid bid to remake the global economy–running on fossil fuels. In the first postwar years, Americans moved to suburbs and began driving gas-guzzling cars to work, while the federal government built a highway system to connect the country for those vehicles. The single biggest line item in the Marshall Plan, the U.S. government program that funded the European recovery, went to support oil, which ensured that the continent’s economy would also run on that fossil fuel. Meanwhile, plastic, an oil derivative, became the go-to building block for consumer goods after the U.S. had developed production capacity for use in World War II. The underlying philosophy of economic development in this time period was a focus on gross national product, a term developed by U.S. government economists during the Depression, which included consumption as a proxy for prosperity: the more we consume, the better off we are, according to this model, which, in the postwar era, the U.S. assiduously spread abroad. The promise of endless growth also required an endless supply of oil to power factories, automobiles and jet planes. In 1945, President Franklin D. Roosevelt sealed a deal with Ibn Saud, the first King of Saudi Arabia, trading security for access to the country’s vast oil reserves. Every U.S. President since, implicitly or explicitly, has continued that exchange. The coronavirus pandemic is the most significant disruption yet to the postwar fossil-fuel order. The global economy is expected to contract more than 5% this year, according to the International Monetary Fund (IMF). This is a challenge so big that it has also created a once-in-a-lifetime opportunity to change direction. This moment comes just in time. In 2018, a landmark report from the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change, the U.N.’s climate-science body, warned that allowing the planet to warm any more than 2°C above preindustrial levels would drive hundreds of millions of people into poverty, destroy coral reefs and leave some countries unable to adapt. A 2019 analysis in the journal Nature identified nine tipping points–from the collapse of the West Antarctic ice sheet to the thawing of Arctic permafrost–that the planet appears close to reaching, any one of which might very well be triggered if warming exceeds 1.5°C. “Going beyond 2°C is a very critical step,” says Johan Rockstrom, director of the Potsdam Institute for Climate Impact Research, “not only in terms of economic and human impact but also in terms of the stability of the earth.” To keep temperatures from rising past the 1.5°C goal, we would need to cut global greenhouse-gas emissions 7.6% every year for the next decade, according to a report from the U.N. Environment Programme (UNEP). That’s about the level the COVID-19 pandemic will reduce emissions this year, but virtually no one thinks a deadly pandemic and accompanying unemployment is a sustainable way to halt climate change–and recessions are typically followed by sharp rebounds in emissions. To achieve the 1.5°C goal without creating mass disruption has always meant thoughtfully restructuring the global economy, moving it away from fossil-fuel extraction slowly but surely. Scientists and economists agree this is the last opportunity we have to do so. “If we delay further than 2020,” says Rockstrom, “there’s absolutely no empirical evidence that it can be done in an orderly way.” As of late June, countries had spent some $11 trillion on measures to halt the pandemic and stem its economic impact, according to the IMF. Economists say that’s not enough, and countries and central banks plan to keep doling out money to help the global economy stay afloat. There are lots of things we could be buying with that money that would make our lives better and protect us from climate disaster. In recent months, leading institutions across the spectrum have offered approaches that are varied in their specifics but generally similar in philosophy: invest in greener infrastructure. The International Energy Agency (IEA), for example, calls for an annual $1 trillion investment in clean energy for the next three years. At a cost of about 0.7% of global GDP, this would represent a small portion of the funds spent to combat COVID-19 but could be transformative. Expansion and modernization of electric grids would allow for easier flow of renewable energy. Governments could buy out gas-guzzling vehicles, pushing consumers to go electric. Homes and buildings could be retrofitted to consume less energy. This spending would also help solve the immediate problem of lost jobs and economic stagnation by creating nearly 10 million jobs worldwide and increasing global GDP by 1.1%, meaning it would add more to the economy than it costs. Importantly, green investment would result in a slew of “co-benefits.” For example, some rural communities would receive access to electricity for the first time. For another, air pollution would decline all over the world. “If governments do not make use of this opportunity, they may miss a very important tool for the economic recovery,” says Fatih Birol, head of the IEA. But this moment is not just about opportunity; even maintaining the status quo is dangerous. Research from the UNEP released last year shows that if nations stick with current plans to reduce emissions, global temperatures will rise more than 3°C by the end of this century. | 9,864 | <h4>The aff is try or die – we need to act <u>as soon as possible</u> to meet the 2° goal or we’re all dead</h4><p><strong>Worland 7/9</strong> (Justin Worland, 7-9-2020, "2020 Is Our Last, Best Chance to Save the Planet," Time, https://time.com/5864692/climate-change-defining-moment/<u><strong>)</p><p></u></strong>From our vantage point today, 2020 looks like the year when an unknown virus spun out of control, killed hundreds of thousands and altered the way we live day to day. In the future, <u>we may look back at 2020 as the year we decided to keep driving off the climate cliff–or to take the last exit. Taking the threat seriously would mean using the opportunity presented by this crisis to spend on solar panels and wind farms, push companies being bailed out to cut emissions and foster greener forms of transport in cities. If we instead choose to fund new coal-fired power plants and oil wells and thoughtlessly fire up factories to urge growth, we will lock in a pathway toward climate catastrophe.</u> There’s a divide about which way to go. In early April, as COVID-19 spread across the U.S. and doctors urgently warned that New York City might soon run out of ventilators and hospital beds, President Donald Trump gathered CEOs from some of the country’s biggest oil and gas companies for a closed-door meeting in the White House Cabinet Room. The industry faced its biggest disruption in decades, and Trump wanted to help the companies secure their place at the center of the 21st century American economy. Everything was on the table, from a tariff on imports to the U.S. government itself purchasing excess oil. “We’ll work this out, and we’ll get our energy business back,” Trump told the CEOs. “I’m with you 1,000%.” A few days later, he announced he had brokered a deal with Russian President Vladimir Putin and Saudi Crown Prince Mohammed bin Salman to cut oil production and rescue the industry. Later in April, Ursula von der Leyen, the president of the European Commission, in a video message from across the Atlantic, offered a different approach for the continent’s economic future. A European Green Deal, she said, would be the E.U.’s “motor for the recovery.” “We can turn the crisis of this pandemic into an opportunity to rebuild our economies differently,” she said. On May 27, she pledged more than $800 billion to the initiative, promising to transform the way Europeans live. For the past three years, the world outside the U.S. has largely tried to ignore Trump’s retrograde position on climate, hoping 2020 would usher in a new President with a new position, re-enabling the cooperation between nations needed to prevent the worst ravages of climate change. But there’s no more time to wait. <u>We’re standing at a climate crossroads: the world has already warmed 1.1°C since the Industrial Revolution. <mark>If we pass 2°C</mark>, we <mark>risk hitting</mark> one or more major <mark>tipping points</mark>, where the <mark>effects of climate change go from advancing gradually to changing dramatically overnight</mark>, reshaping the planet. To ensure that we don’t pass that threshold, we need to <mark>cut emissions in half by 2030</mark>. Climate change has understandably fallen out of the public eye this year as the coronavirus pandemic rages</u>. Nevertheless, this year, or perhaps this year and next, is likely to be the most pivotal yet in the fight against climate change. “We’ve run out of time to build new things in old ways,” says Rob Jackson, an earth system science professor at Stanford University and the chair of the Global Carbon Project. What we do now will define the fate of the planet–and human life on it–for decades. <u>The <mark>time frame</mark> for effective climate action was <mark>always</mark> going to be <mark>tight</mark>, but the <mark>coronavirus</mark> pandemic has <mark>shrunk</mark> it <mark>further</mark>. Scientists and policymakers expected the green transition to occur over the next decade, but the pandemic has <mark>pushed</mark> 10 years of anticipated <mark>investment</mark> in everything from power plants to roads <mark>into</mark> a <mark>monthslong time frame</mark>.</u> Countries have already spent $11 trillion to help stem the economic damage from COVID-19. They could spend trillions more. <u>“It’s in this next six months that recovery strategies are likely to be formulated and the path is set,” says Nicholas Stern, a former World Bank chief economist known for his landmark 2006 report warning that <mark>climate change could devastate the global economy</mark>.</u> We don’t know where the chips will fall: Will a newfound respect for science and a fear of future shocks lead us to finally wake up, or will the desire to return to normal overshadow the threats lurking just around the corner? We find ourselves on the brink of climate catastrophe in large part because of the decisions made during a past crisis. As the world came out of the Great Depression and World War II, the U.S. launched a rapid bid to remake the global economy–running on fossil fuels. In the first postwar years, Americans moved to suburbs and began driving gas-guzzling cars to work, while the federal government built a highway system to connect the country for those vehicles. The single biggest line item in the Marshall Plan, the U.S. government program that funded the European recovery, went to support oil, which ensured that the continent’s economy would also run on that fossil fuel. Meanwhile, plastic, an oil derivative, became the go-to building block for consumer goods after the U.S. had developed production capacity for use in World War II. The underlying philosophy of economic development in this time period was a focus on gross national product, a term developed by U.S. government economists during the Depression, which included consumption as a proxy for prosperity: the more we consume, the better off we are, according to this model, which, in the postwar era, the U.S. assiduously spread abroad. The promise of endless growth also required an endless supply of oil to power factories, automobiles and jet planes. In 1945, President Franklin D. Roosevelt sealed a deal with Ibn Saud, the first King of Saudi Arabia, trading security for access to the country’s vast oil reserves. Every U.S. President since, implicitly or explicitly, has continued that exchange. The coronavirus pandemic is the most significant disruption yet to the postwar fossil-fuel order. The global economy is expected to contract more than 5% this year, according to the International Monetary Fund (IMF). This is a challenge so big that it has also created a once-in-a-lifetime opportunity to change direction. This moment comes just in time. In 2018, a landmark report from the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change, the U.N.’s climate-science body, warned that allowing the planet to warm any more than 2°C above preindustrial levels would drive hundreds of millions of people into poverty, destroy coral reefs and leave some countries unable to adapt. A 2019 analysis in the journal Nature identified nine tipping points–from the collapse of the West Antarctic ice sheet to the thawing of Arctic permafrost–that the planet appears close to reaching, any one of which might very well be triggered if warming exceeds 1.5°C. “Going beyond 2°C is a very critical step,” says Johan Rockstrom, director of the Potsdam Institute for Climate Impact Research, “not only in terms of economic and human impact but also in terms of the stability of the earth.” To keep temperatures from rising past the 1.5°C goal, we would need to cut global greenhouse-gas emissions 7.6% every year for the next decade, according to a report from the U.N. Environment Programme (UNEP). That’s about the level the COVID-19 pandemic will reduce emissions this year, but virtually no one thinks a deadly pandemic and accompanying unemployment is a sustainable way to halt climate change–and recessions are typically followed by sharp rebounds in emissions. <u>To achieve the 1.5°C goal without creating mass disruption has always meant thoughtfully restructuring the global economy, moving it away from fossil-fuel extraction slowly but surely. Scientists and economists agree <mark>this is the last opportunity we have to do so</mark>. “<mark>If we delay further than 2020</mark>,” says Rockstrom, “there’s absolutely <mark>no empirical evidence that it can be done in an orderly way</mark>.” </u>As of late June, countries had spent some $11 trillion on measures to halt the pandemic and stem its economic impact, according to the IMF. Economists say that’s not enough, and countries and central banks plan to keep doling out money to help the global economy stay afloat. There are lots of things we could be buying with that money that would make our lives better and protect us from climate disaster. In recent months, leading institutions across the spectrum have offered approaches that are varied in their specifics but generally similar in philosophy: invest in greener infrastructure. The International Energy Agency (IEA), for example, calls for an annual $1 trillion investment in clean energy for the next three years. At a cost of about 0.7% of global GDP, this would represent a small portion of the funds spent to combat COVID-19 but could be transformative. Expansion and modernization of electric grids would allow for easier flow of renewable energy. Governments could buy out gas-guzzling vehicles, pushing consumers to go electric. Homes and buildings could be retrofitted to consume less energy. This spending would also help solve the immediate problem of lost jobs and economic stagnation by creating nearly 10 million jobs worldwide and increasing global GDP by 1.1%, meaning it would add more to the economy than it costs. Importantly, green investment would result in a slew of “co-benefits.” For example, some rural communities would receive access to electricity for the first time. For another, air pollution would decline all over the world. “If governments do not make use of this opportunity, they may miss a very important tool for the economic recovery,” says Fatih Birol, head of the IEA. <u>But this moment is not just about opportunity; <mark>even maintaining the status quo is dangerous</mark>. Research from the UNEP released last year shows that <mark>if nations stick with current plans to reduce emissions</mark>, global <mark>temperatures</mark> will <mark>rise more than 3°C</mark> <mark>by</mark> the <mark>end of</mark> this <mark>century</mark>.</p></u> | GHill R2 Aff Doc | 1AC | Advantage 1: Turn Out and Representation | 39,088 | 325 | 137,067 | ./documents/hsld20/Lexington/Yi/Lexington-Ying-Aff-Greenhill-Round2.docx | 865,070 | A | SO - Greenhill | 2 | Immaculate Heart Felicity Park | Tarun Ratnasabapathy | 1AC - Federal Elections
1NC - Defense Spending DA - 2020 PIC - Carbon Tax CP - ASpec on case
1AR - Condo
2NR - Defense Spending DA - Carbon Tax CP
2AR - Condo | hsld20/Lexington/Yi/Lexington-Ying-Aff-Greenhill-Round2.docx | null | 73,323 | DeYi | Lexington DeYi | null | De..... | Yi..... | null | null | 24,591 | Lexington | Lexington | MA | null | 1,028 | hsld20 | HS LD 2020-21 | 2,020 | ld | hs | 1 |
4,192,990 | Russia will exploit divisions between NATO members to instigate nuclear crises and global war | Kulesa ’18 | Kulesa ’18 [Lukasz; February 2018; Research Director at the European Leadership Network; European Leadership Network, “Envisioning a Russia-NATO Conflict: Implications for Deterrence Stability,” http://www.jstor.com/stable/resrep17437] | Once a conflict was under way, the “fog of war” and rising unpredictability would inevitably set in, complicating the implementation of any conflict management. The actual dynamics of conflict are extremely difficult to predict. Simulations give limited insights Russian military theorists assume a conflict with NATO can be managed and controlled in a way that would bring it to a swift end consistent with Russian aims. The Russian theory of victory seek to exploit weak points in an Alliance war effort. Based on the conviction that democracies are weak and risk-averse, Russia may assume that threats of horizontal or vertical escalation could be effective. It would try to bring home the notion it has much higher stakes in the conflict than NATO members and will be ready to push the boundaries of conflict further. It would try to test and exploit potential divisions within the Alliance, combining selective diplomacy and activation of its intelligence assets in NATO states Any NATO-Russia conflict would inevitably have a nuclear dimension. The role of nuclear weapons as a tool for escalation control for Russia has been debated by experts, but when Russia might use nuclear weapons in a conflict remains an open question. Beyond “escalate to de-escalate” there are a wider range of options for Russian nuclear weapon use a single nuclear warning shot could be lethal or non-lethal. It could be directed against a military target or a civilian one. Detonation could be configured for an EMP effect. A “false flag” attack is conceivable. These options signal escalation and could significantly complicate NATO’s responses It is less clear how far the Alliance would be willing to escalate the conflict and what mechanisms it would use while trying to maintain control The goals of waging a conflict with Russia would have to be limited in order to avoid a massive nuclear exchange. Such limitations could put too much restraint on NATO’s operations: the Russian regime’s stability may need to be threatened to force the leadership into terminating the conflict Relying on concepts of escalation control from the Cold War might be misleading. The circumstances in which a Russia-NATO conflict would play out would be radically different from the 20th century instead of gradual escalation or salami tactics escalation, it is possible to imagine “leap frog” escalation connected in different domains Russian and NATO assumptions regarding conflict termination would not survive the first hours of actual conflict. Both sides are capable of underestimating the resolve of the other side to prevail and the other side’s willingness to endure the costs, especially once both start committing political capital | Once conflict was under way, the “fog of war” and unpredictability would inevitably set Russian theorists assume conflict can be controlled Russia exploit weak points in Alliance It would push boundaries try to exploit divisions Any conflict would have a nuc dimension for escalation control a single nuclear shot could be lethal Detonation could be EMP effect. A “false flag” complicate responses conflict would have to be limited to avoid nuclear exchang Relying on escalation control might be misleading Russia-NATO conflict would be “leap frog” escalation Both sides underestimat resolve | Escalation: Can a NATO - Russia conflict be managed? Once a conflict was under way, the “fog of war” and rising unpredictability would inevitably set in, complicating the implementation of any predetermined theories of escalation, deescalation and inter-conflict management. The actual dynamics of a conflict and the perceptions of the stakes involved are extremely difficult to predict. Simulations and table-top exercises can give only limited insights into the actual decision-making processes and interactions. Still, Russian military theorists and practitioners seem to assume that a conflict with NATO can be managed and controlled in a way that would bring it to a swift end consistent with Russian aims. The Russian theory of victory would seek to exploit weak points in an Alliance war effort. Based on the conviction that democracies are weak and their leaders and populations are risk-averse, Russia may assume that its threats of horizontal or vertical escalation could be particularly effective. It would also try to bring home the notion that it has much higher stakes in the conflict (regime survival) than a majority of the NATO members involved, and thus will be ready to push the boundaries of the conflict further. It would most likely try to test and exploit potential divisions within the Alliance, combining selective diplomacy and activation of its intelligence assets in some NATO states with a degree of selectivity in terms of targets of particular attacks. Any NATO-Russia conflict would inevitably have a nuclear dimension. The role of nuclear weapons as a tool for escalation control for Russia has been thoroughly debated by experts, but when and how Russia might use (and not merely showcase or activate) nuclear weapons in a conflict remains an open question. Beyond catch phrases such as “escalate to de-escalate” or “escalate to win” there are a wider range of options for Russian nuclear weapon use. For example, a single nuclear warning shot could be lethal or non-lethal. It could be directed against a purely military target or a military-civilian one. Detonation could be configured for an EMP effect. A “false flag” attack is also conceivable. These options might be used to signal escalation and could significantly complicate NATO’s responses. Neither NATO nor its member states have developed a similar theory of victory. Public NATO documents stipulate the general goals for the Alliance: defend against any armed attack and, as needed, restore the full sovereignty and territorial integrity of member states. It is less clear how far the Alliance would be willing to escalate the conflict to achieve these goals, and what mechanisms and means it would use while trying to maintain some degree of control over the conflict. The goals and methods of waging a conflict with Russia would probably have to be limited in order to avoid a massive nuclear exchange. Such limitations would also involve restrictions on striking back against targets on Russian territory. But too narrow an approach could put too much restraint on NATO’s operations: the Russian regime’s stability may ultimately need to be threatened in order to force the leadership into terminating the conflict. NATO would thus need to establish what a proportional self-defence response to Russian actions would involve, and to what extent cyber operations or attacks against military targets in quite different parts of Russia would be useful as tools of escalation to signal NATO’s resolve. Moreover, individual NATO Allies, especially those directly affected by Russia’s actions, might pursue their individual strategies of escalation. With regards to the nuclear dimension in NATO escalation plans, given the stakes involved, this element would most likely be handled by the three nuclear-weapon members of the Alliance, with the US taking the lead. The existence of three independent centres of nuclear decision-making could be exploited to complicate Russian planning and introduce uncertainty into the Russian strategic calculus, but some degree of “P3” dialogue and coordination would be beneficial. This coordination would not necessarily focus on nuclear targeting, but rather on designing coordinated operations to demonstrate resolve in order to keep the conflict below the nuclear threshold, or bring it back under the threshold after first use. Relying on concepts of escalation control and on lessons from the Cold War confrontation might be misleading. The circumstances in which a Russia-NATO conflict would play out would be radically different from the 20th century screenplay. Moreover, instead of gradual (linear) escalation or salami tactics escalation, it is possible to imagine surprizing “leap frog” escalation, possibly connected with actions in different domains (e.g. a cyberattack against critical infrastructure). Flexibility, good intelligence and inventiveness in responding to such developments would be crucial. Conflict termination Russian and NATO assumptions regarding conflict termination would most likely not survive the first hours of an actual conflict. Both sides are capable of underestimating the resolve of the other side to prevail in a conflict and the other side’s willingness to commit the necessary resources and endure the costs, especially once both sides start committing their political capital and resources and the casualties accumulate. | 5,400 | <h4>Russia will <u>exploit</u> divisions between NATO members to instigate <u>nuclear crises</u> and <u>global war</u> </h4><p><strong>Kulesa ’18 </strong>[Lukasz; February 2018; Research Director at the European Leadership Network; European Leadership Network, “Envisioning a Russia-NATO Conflict: Implications for Deterrence Stability,” http://www.jstor.com/stable/resrep17437]</p><p>Escalation: Can a NATO - Russia conflict be managed? <u><mark>Once</mark> a <mark>conflict was <strong>under way</strong>, the “<strong>fog of war</strong>” and</mark> <strong>rising <mark>unpredictability</strong> would <strong>inevitably</strong> set</mark> in, <strong>complicating</strong> the implementation of any</u> predetermined theories of escalation, deescalation and inter-<u>conflict management. The <strong>actual</strong> dynamics of</u> a <u>conflict</u> and the perceptions of the stakes involved <u>are <strong>extremely difficult</strong> to predict. Simulations</u> and table-top exercises can <u>give</u> only <u>limited insights</u> into the actual decision-making processes and interactions. Still, <u><mark>Russian</mark> military <mark>theorists</u></mark> and practitioners seem to <u><strong><mark>assume</u></strong></mark> that <u>a <mark>conflict</mark> with NATO <mark>can be</mark> <strong>managed</strong> and <strong><mark>controlled</strong></mark> in a way that would bring it to a <strong>swift end</strong> consistent with Russian aims. The <mark>Russia</mark>n <strong>theory of victory</u></strong> would <u>seek to <strong><mark>exploit weak points</strong> in</mark> an <mark>Alliance</mark> war effort. Based on the <strong>conviction</strong> that democracies are weak and</u> their leaders and populations are <u>risk-averse, Russia may <strong>assume</strong> that</u> its <u>threats of <strong>horizontal</strong> or <strong>vertical escalation</strong> could be</u> particularly <u>effective. <mark>It would</u></mark> also <u>try to bring home the notion</u> that <u>it has <strong>much higher stakes</strong> in the conflict</u> (regime survival) <u>than</u> a majority of the <u>NATO members</u> involved, <u>and</u> thus <u>will be ready to <strong><mark>push</mark> the <mark>boundaries</strong></mark> of</u> the <u>conflict further. It would</u> most likely <u><mark>try to</mark> <strong>test</strong> and <strong><mark>exploit</strong></mark> potential <strong><mark>divisions</strong></mark> within the Alliance, combining <strong>selective diplomacy</strong> and <strong>activation</strong> of its intelligence assets in</u> some <u>NATO states </u>with a degree of selectivity in terms of targets of particular attacks. <u><strong><mark>Any</strong></mark> NATO-Russia <mark>conflict would</mark> <strong>inevitably</strong> <mark>have a <strong>nuc</mark>lear <mark>dimension</strong></mark>. The role of <strong>nuclear weapons</strong> as a tool <mark>for <strong>escalation control</strong></mark> for Russia has been</u> thoroughly <u>debated by experts, but when</u> and how <u>Russia might use</u> (and not merely showcase or activate) <u>nuclear weapons in a conflict remains an <strong>open question</strong>. Beyond</u> catch phrases such as <u>“<strong>escalate to de-escalate</strong>”</u> or “escalate to win” <u>there are a <strong>wider range</strong> of options for Russian <strong>nuclear weapon use</u></strong>. For example, <u><mark>a single <strong>nuclear</mark> warning <mark>shot</strong> could be lethal</mark> or non-lethal. It could be directed against a</u> purely <u>military target or a</u> military-<u>civilian one. <mark>Detonation could be</mark> configured for an <strong><mark>EMP effect</strong>. A “<strong>false flag</strong>”</mark> attack is</u> also <u>conceivable. These options</u> might be used to <u><strong>signal escalation</strong> and could <strong>significantly <mark>complicate</strong></mark> NATO’s <mark>responses</u></mark>. Neither NATO nor its member states have developed a similar theory of victory. Public NATO documents stipulate the general goals for the Alliance: defend against any armed attack and, as needed, restore the full sovereignty and territorial integrity of member states. <u>It is less clear how far the Alliance would be <strong>willing to escalate</strong> the conflict</u> to achieve these goals, <u>and what mechanisms</u> and means <u>it would use while trying to maintain</u> some degree of <u>control</u> over the conflict. <u>The goals</u> and methods <u>of waging a <mark>conflict</mark> with Russia <mark>would</u></mark> probably <u><mark>have to be limited</mark> in order <mark>to avoid</mark> a <strong>massive <mark>nuclear exchang</mark>e</strong>. Such limitations</u> would also involve restrictions on striking back against targets on Russian territory. But too narrow an approach <u>could put <strong>too much restraint</strong> on NATO’s operations: the Russian <strong>regime’s stability</strong> may</u> ultimately <u>need to be threatened</u> in order <u>to <strong>force the leadership</strong> into <strong>terminating</strong> the conflict</u>. NATO would thus need to establish what a proportional self-defence response to Russian actions would involve, and to what extent cyber operations or attacks against military targets in quite different parts of Russia would be useful as tools of escalation to signal NATO’s resolve. Moreover, individual NATO Allies, especially those directly affected by Russia’s actions, might pursue their individual strategies of escalation. With regards to the nuclear dimension in NATO escalation plans, given the stakes involved, this element would most likely be handled by the three nuclear-weapon members of the Alliance, with the US taking the lead. The existence of three independent centres of nuclear decision-making could be exploited to complicate Russian planning and introduce uncertainty into the Russian strategic calculus, but some degree of “P3” dialogue and coordination would be beneficial. This coordination would not necessarily focus on nuclear targeting, but rather on designing coordinated operations to demonstrate resolve in order to keep the conflict below the nuclear threshold, or bring it back under the threshold after first use. <u><mark>Relying on</mark> concepts of <strong><mark>escalation control</u></strong></mark> and on lessons <u>from the Cold War</u> confrontation <u><mark>might be <strong>misleading</strong></mark>. The circumstances in which a <strong><mark>Russia-NATO conflict</strong> would</mark> play out would <mark>be</mark> <strong>radically different</strong> from the 20th century</u> screenplay. Moreover, <u>instead of <strong>gradual</u></strong> (linear) <u>escalation or <strong>salami tactics</strong> escalation, it is possible to imagine</u> surprizing <u><mark>“<strong>leap frog</strong>” escalation</u></mark>, possibly <u>connected</u> with actions <u>in <strong>different domains</u></strong> (e.g. a cyberattack against critical infrastructure). Flexibility, good intelligence and inventiveness in responding to such developments would be crucial. Conflict termination <u>Russian and NATO assumptions regarding conflict termination would</u> most likely <u><strong>not survive</strong> the <strong>first hours</strong> of</u> an <u>actual conflict. <mark>Both sides</mark> are capable of <strong><mark>underestimat</mark>ing</strong> the <strong><mark>resolve</strong></mark> of the other side to prevail</u> in a conflict <u>and the other side’s <strong>willingness</strong> to</u> commit the necessary resources and <u>endure the costs, especially once both</u> sides <u>start committing</u> their <u>political capital</u> and resources and the casualties accumulate.</p> | 1ac – ILOVEYOU | 1ac | A2 | 60 | 544 | 144,051 | ./documents/hspolicy22/Maize/ShWr/Maize-ShWr-Aff-7----KSHSAA-5A-2-Speaker-State-Championship-Round-2.docx | 962,879 | A | 7 -- KSHSAA 5A 2 Speaker State Championship | 2 | Salina South AL | Colle | 1ac - ILOVEYOU v3
1nc - t ocos, withdrawal cp, turkey appeasement da, noko tradeoff da
2nr - withdrawal cp, turkey appeasement da | hspolicy22/Maize/ShWr/Maize-ShWr-Aff-7----KSHSAA-5A-2-Speaker-State-Championship-Round-2.docx | 2023-01-14 02:31:19 | 79,385 | ShWr | Maize ShWr | contact info:
Devin Short - 2A- he/him - [email protected]
Ashley Wright - 2N - she/her - [email protected] | De..... | Sh..... | As..... | Wr..... | 26,604 | Maize | Maize | KS | null | 2,002 | hspolicy22 | HS Policy 2022-23 | 2,022 | cx | hs | 2 |
4,741,965 | Backlash turns the affirmative - Protective measures are taken by nativist movements to ensure border security | Beirich and Potok 9 | Beirich and Potok 9
(Heidi and Mark, Director of Research and Intelligence project, Southern Poverty Law Center, Southern Poverty Law Center, “USA: Hate Groups, Radical-Right Violence, on the Rise” Policing, http://policing.oxfordjournals.org/cgi/content/full/pap020v1) | the organized anti-immigrant movement has exploded ‘nativist extremist’ target people, rather than policy. they do not limit themselves to advocating, for stricter border security, tighter population control, or tougher enforcement of laws against hiring illegal immigrants. they go after the immigrants themselves, using armed vigilante border patrols; surveillance of apartments and houses occupied by Mexicans and Central Americans; publicizing photos and home addresses of ‘suspected illegal aliens’ and harassment and intimidation of Latino immigrants at day-labour sites and migrant-worker camps. nativist extremist groups are active in all regions of the U S Many of the groups in non-border states are local chapters of either the Minuteman Civil Defense Corps or the Minuteman Project These nationwide organizations muster volunteers for vigilante border actions Many protest actions or conduct ‘surveillance ops’ at day-labor sites members openly carry firearms have also spawned a slew of imitators and splinter groups the Antelope Valley Minutemen, leader | the organized anti-immigrant movement has exploded nativist extremist’ target people, rather than policy they go after the immigrants themselves, using armed vigilante border patrol nativist extremist groups are active in all regions of the U S These nationwide organizations muster volunteers for vigilante border actions. Many protest actions or conduct ‘surveillance ops’ at day-labor sites . members openly carry firearms have also spawned a slew of imitators and splinter groups | Many whites have come to see the federal government, along with the nation's business elites, as specifically responsible for the failure to curb non-white immigration. On the radical right, the government often is seen as plotting to destroy the white race. Now, the white supremacist movement has been joined in its anger over America's immigration policy by a new nativist movement that seemingly came out of nowhere in the last few years. Starting with a meeting held in 2001 in Sierra Vista, AZ, which brought together several anti-immigrant hate groups to laud a border rancher known for detaining suspected immigrants at gunpoint, the organized anti-immigrant movement has exploded (Southern Poverty Law Center, 2001a). By 2007, the SPLC had identified 144 ‘nativist extremist’ groups active across 39 states (Southern Poverty Law Center, 2007). Most of these organizations—nearly 100 of them—had appeared since April 2006. The groups identified as ‘nativist extremist’ target people, rather than policy. That is, they do not limit themselves to advocating, even in forceful terms, for stricter border security, tighter population control, or tougher enforcement of laws against hiring illegal immigrants. Instead, they go after the immigrants themselves, using tactics including armed vigilante border patrols; conspicuous surveillance of apartments and houses occupied by Mexicans and Central Americans; publicizing photos and home addresses of ‘suspected illegal aliens’ and harassment and intimidation of Latino immigrants at day-labour sites and migrant-worker camps. Because their tactics frequently cross the line into illegal harassment and even violence, these groups sometimes represent another challenge for law enforcement. Though most heavily concentrated in Arizona, California and Texas, nativist extremist groups are active in all regions of the United States. Many of the groups in non-border states are local chapters of either the Minuteman Civil Defense Corps or the Minuteman Project, which comprised 57 of the 144 nativist extremist groups listed by the SPLC. These separate, competing nationwide organizations both emerged from the original month-long Minuteman ‘civilian border patrol’ operation held in Cochise County, AZ, in April 2005. Minuteman chapters raise money for their parent organizations and muster volunteers for vigilante border actions. Many also hold protest actions or conduct ‘surveillance ops’ at day-labor sites in their home cities. In states where it's allowed by law, their members openly carry firearms. The Minuteman Civil Defense Corps and Minuteman Project have also spawned a slew of imitators and splinter groups that have no official affiliation with either national Minuteman organization. These rogue outfits include the Antelope Valley Minutemen, whose leader, Frank Jorge, has written on his website: ‘We have a right, and an obligation, to defend our country, our homes, and our families not only from this invasion, but also from the very Government that is precipitating this treasonous act’ (Buchanan and Holthouse, 2007). | 3,092 | <h4>Backlash turns the affirmative - <strong>Protective measures are taken by nativist movements to ensure border security </h4><p>Beirich and Potok 9 </p><p></strong>(Heidi and Mark, Director of Research and Intelligence project, Southern Poverty Law Center, Southern Poverty Law Center, “USA: Hate Groups, Radical-Right Violence, on the Rise” Policing, http://policing.oxfordjournals.org/cgi/content/full/pap020v1)</p><p>Many whites have come to see the federal government, along with the nation's business elites, as specifically responsible for the failure to curb non-white immigration. On the radical right, the government often is seen as plotting to destroy the white race. Now, the white supremacist movement has been joined in its anger over America's immigration policy by a new nativist movement that seemingly came out of nowhere in the last few years. Starting with a meeting held in 2001 in Sierra Vista, AZ, which brought together several anti-immigrant hate groups to laud a border rancher known for detaining suspected immigrants at gunpoint,<u> <mark>the organized anti-immigrant movement has exploded</u></mark> (Southern Poverty Law Center, 2001a). By 2007, the SPLC had identified 144 ‘nativist extremist’ groups active across 39 states (Southern Poverty Law Center, 2007). Most of these organizations—nearly 100 of them—had appeared since April 2006. The groups identified as<u> ‘<mark>nativist extremist’ target people, rather than policy</mark>. </u>That is,<u> they do not limit themselves to advocating, </u>even in forceful terms, <u>for stricter border security, tighter population control, or tougher enforcement of laws against hiring illegal immigrants. </u>Instead,<u> <mark>they go after the immigrants themselves, using</mark> </u>tactics including<u> <strong><mark>armed vigilante border patrol</mark>s</strong>; </u>conspicuous<u> surveillance of apartments and houses occupied by Mexicans and Central Americans; publicizing photos and home addresses of ‘suspected illegal aliens’ and harassment and intimidation of Latino immigrants at day-labour sites and migrant-worker camps.</u> Because their tactics frequently cross the line into illegal harassment and even violence, these groups sometimes represent another challenge for law enforcement. Though most heavily concentrated in Arizona, California and Texas, <u><mark>nativist extremist groups are active in all regions of the U</u></mark>nited <u><mark>S</u></mark>tates. <u>Many of the groups in non-border states are local chapters of either the Minuteman Civil Defense Corps or the Minuteman Project</u>, which comprised 57 of the 144 nativist extremist groups listed by the SPLC. <u><mark>These</u></mark> separate, competing <u><mark>nationwide organizations</u></mark> both emerged from the original month-long Minuteman ‘civilian border patrol’ operation held in Cochise County, AZ, in April 2005. Minuteman chapters raise money for their parent organizations and <u><mark>muster volunteers for vigilante border actions</u>. <u>Many </u></mark>also hold<u><mark> protest actions or conduct ‘surveillance ops’ at day-labor sites </u></mark>in their home cities<mark>.</mark> In states where it's allowed by law, their <u><mark>members openly carry firearms</u></mark>. The Minuteman Civil Defense Corps and Minuteman Project <u><mark>have also spawned a slew of imitators and splinter groups</u></mark> that have no official affiliation with either national Minuteman organization. These rogue outfits include<u> the Antelope Valley Minutemen, </u>whose<u> leader</u>, Frank Jorge, has written on his website: ‘We have a right, and an obligation, to defend our country, our homes, and our families not only from this invasion, but also from the very Government that is precipitating this treasonous act’ (Buchanan and Holthouse, 2007).</p> | null | Populism DA | null | 283,767 | 150 | 165,680 | ./documents/hsld22/Marlborough/OlOh/Marlborough-OlOh-Neg-Peninsula-Round-4.docx | 966,556 | N | Peninsula | 4 | Immaculate Heart SP | Mei Kim | AC - Lay South America
NC - Lay Lightly Controlled CP, Lay Populism DA, China Adv CP, Lay Nebel T, Case
1AR - All
NR - All
2AR - All | hsld22/Marlborough/OlOh/Marlborough-OlOh-Neg-Peninsula-Round-4.docx | 2023-01-22 05:18:32 | 80,343 | OlOh | Marlborough OlOh | null | Ol..... | Oh..... | null | null | 26,925 | Marlborough | Marlborough | CA | null | 2,003 | hsld22 | HS LD 2022-23 | 2,022 | ld | hs | 1 |
4,571,175 | Growth key to avoid all existential risk | Aschenbrenner 20 | Aschenbrenner 20 [Aschenbrenner, Leopold. Existential risk and growth. Working paper]. Global Priorities Institute, University of Oxford. https://globalprioritiesinstitute. org/wp-content/upload s/Leopold-Aschenbrenner_Existential-risk-and-growth_. pdf, 2020.] CT | Human activity can create or mitigate existential risks. Analyzing this in a model of endogenous growth, when the scale effect of existential risk is moderate and the marginal utility of consumption declines quickly enough, this paper grounds the intuition of some prominent thinkers that humanity may be in a critical “time of perils.” We may be economically advanced enough to be able to destroy ourselves, but not economically advanced enough that we care about this existential risk and spend on safety. This “time of perils” implies that working on could be reducing existential risk now very impactful from an altruistic perspective. Faster economic growth appears to generally improve the odds of humanity’s survival. When the world is not very fragile, growth straightforwardly reduces risk. In the moderate fragility case, faster economic growth, while initially increasing risk, can help us get through this “time of perils” more quickly and thus increases the long-run probability of humanity’s survival. In particular, note that this effect doesn’t require a permanently higher growth rate; the improvement in humanity’s odds of survival are potentially substantial even for a temporary period of faster growth. Conversely, even a temporary period of slow economic growth could substantially curtail the future of human civilization. This model suggests even if you care only about the very long-term future of humanity, the pace of economic growth in the short run could be key to whether we make it there. | Human activity can mitigate existential risks Faster growth improve the odds In fragility growth help us get through perils” more quickly and increases long-run probability of survival temporary slow growth could substantially curtail the future of civilization | Human activity can create or mitigate existential risks. Analyzing this in a model of endogenous growth, when the scale effect of existential risk is moderate and the marginal utility of consumption declines quickly enough, this paper grounds the intuition of some prominent thinkers that humanity may be in a critical “time of perils.” We may be economically advanced enough to be able to destroy ourselves, but not economically advanced enough that we care about this existential risk and spend on safety. This “time of perils” implies that working on could be reducing existential risk now very impactful from an altruistic perspective. Faster economic growth appears to generally improve the odds of humanity’s survival. When the world is not very fragile, growth straightforwardly reduces risk. When the world is extremely fragile, growth increases risk, but humanity is doomed to destruction anyway—the odds of humanity’s survival are zero anyway. In the moderate fragility case, faster economic growth, while initially increasing risk, can help us get through this “time of perils” more quickly and thus increases the long-run probability of humanity’s survival. In particular, note that this effect doesn’t require a permanently higher growth rate; the improvement in humanity’s odds of survival are potentially substantial even for a temporary period of faster growth. Conversely, even a temporary period of slow economic growth—as we have arguably been experiencing in the developed economies in recent decades—could substantially curtail the future of human civilization. This model suggests even if you care only about the very long-term future of humanity, the pace of economic growth in the short run could be key to whether we make it there. This paper suggests many future research directions. It would clearly be desirable to get better empirical data on the scale effect of existential risk. More broadly, a better understanding of how exactly existential risk is created and mitigated—and therefore modeled—would be helpful. It would also be interesting to look at the implications of a decentralized allocation, as well as possible mechanisms to efficiently provide for the global public good of existential risk mitigation. Finally, from the perspective of maximizing altruistic impact, it would be valuable to compare the impact on the longrun probability of humanity’s survival from working on policies that might accelerate the rate of growth to direct work on reducing existential risk by funding the safety sector. | 2,540 | <h4>Growth key to avoid <u>all existential risk</h4><p></u><strong>Aschenbrenner 20</strong> [Aschenbrenner, Leopold. Existential risk and growth. Working paper]. Global Priorities Institute, University of Oxford. https://globalprioritiesinstitute. org/wp-content/upload s/Leopold-Aschenbrenner_Existential-risk-and-growth_. pdf, 2020.] CT</p><p><u><mark>Human activity can<strong></mark> create </strong>or <mark>mitigate existential risks<strong></mark>. Analyzing this in a model of endogenous growth, when the scale effect of existential risk is moderate and the marginal utility of consumption declines quickly enough, this paper grounds the intuition of some prominent thinkers that </strong>humanity may be in a critical “time of perils.” We may be economically advanced enough to be able to destroy ourselves, but not<strong> economically </strong>advanced enough that we<strong> care about this existential risk and </strong>spend on safety<strong>.</u></strong> <u><strong>This “time of perils” implies that working on could be reducing existential risk now very impactful from an altruistic perspective. </strong><mark>Faster </mark>economic <mark>growth</mark> <strong>appears to generally </strong><mark>improve the odds </mark>of humanity’s survival. When the world is not very fragile<strong>, </strong>growth straightforwardly reduces risk<strong>.</u></strong> When the world is extremely fragile, growth increases risk, but humanity is doomed to destruction anyway—the odds of humanity’s survival are zero anyway. <u><mark>In </mark>the<strong> moderate </strong><mark>fragility </mark>case<strong>, faster economic </strong><mark>growth<strong></mark>, while initially increasing risk, </strong>can <mark>help us get through</mark> <strong>this “</strong>time of <mark>perils” more quickly and<strong></mark> thus </strong><mark>increases </mark>the <mark>long-run probability of<strong></mark> humanity’s </strong><mark>survival<strong></mark>. In particular, note that </strong>this<strong> effect </strong>doesn’t require a permanently higher growth rate; the improvement in<strong> humanity’s odds of </strong>survival are <strong>potentially </strong>substantial even for a temporary period of faster growth<strong>. Conversely, </strong>even a <mark>temporary </mark>period of <mark>slow<strong></mark> economic </strong><mark>growth</u></mark>—as we have arguably been experiencing in the developed economies in recent decades—<u><mark>could substantially curtail the future of<strong></mark> human </strong><mark>civilization<strong></mark>.</u></strong> <u><strong>This model suggests even </strong>if you care<strong> only </strong>about the<strong> very long-term </strong>future of humanity, the pace of economic growth in the short run could be key to whether we make it<strong> there.</u></strong> This paper suggests many future research directions. It would clearly be desirable to get better empirical data on the scale effect of existential risk. More broadly, a better understanding of how exactly existential risk is created and mitigated—and therefore modeled—would be helpful. It would also be interesting to look at the implications of a decentralized allocation, as well as possible mechanisms to efficiently provide for the global public good of existential risk mitigation. Finally, from the perspective of maximizing altruistic impact, it would be valuable to compare the impact on the longrun probability of humanity’s survival from working on policies that might accelerate the rate of growth to direct work on reducing existential risk by funding the safety sector.</p> | AC Tools | AC Shell | Econ | 1,622,462 | 160 | 151,181 | ./documents/hsld22/Marlborough/SyKa/Marlborough-SyKa-Aff-Harvard-Westlake-Round-2.docx | 964,328 | A | Harvard Westlake | 2 | Vestavia Hills AS | Zhang, Aaron | null | hsld22/Marlborough/SyKa/Marlborough-SyKa-Aff-Harvard-Westlake-Round-2.docx | 2023-01-15 15:24:58 | 80,326 | SyKa | Marlborough SyKa | null | Sy..... | Ka..... | null | null | 26,925 | Marlborough | Marlborough | CA | null | 2,003 | hsld22 | HS LD 2022-23 | 2,022 | ld | hs | 1 |
4,799,251 | Strong ASEAN solves Asia War. | Mahbubani 17 | Mahbubani 17, Kishore, and Jeffery Sng. The ASEAN miracle: A catalyst for peace. NUS Press, 2017. (Distinguished Fellow at the Asia Research Institute and former Singaporean diplomat)//Elmer | ASEAN is a living and breathing modern miracle. Why? No other regional organization has done as much as the Association of Southeast Asian Nations (ASEAN) to improve the living conditions of a broad swath of humanity. ASEAN has brought peace and prosperity to a troubled region, It may have also acted as a critical catalyst for China’s peaceful rise. ASEAN is therefore more deserving of the next Nobel Peace Prize than any other person or institution today In many areas, however, ASEAN has generated optimistic narratives. ASEAN provides a living laboratory of peaceful civilizational coexistence ASEAN created indispensable diplomatic platform that regularly brings all the great powers together. Moreover, ASEAN has created conducive environments for the great powers to talk When tensions rise ASEAN provides a face-saving platform and the right setting to restart the conversation. ASEAN has especially facilitated China’s peaceful rise by generating an ecosystem of peace that moderated aggressive impulses | ASEAN brought peace and prosperity to a troubled region, catalyst for China’s peaceful rise. provides laboratory of peaceful civilizational coexistence ASEAN created indispensable platform conducive for great powers to talk face-saving platform generating peace that moderated aggressive impulses | ASEAN is a living and breathing modern miracle. Why? No other regional organization has done as much as the Association of Southeast Asian Nations (ASEAN) to improve the living conditions of a broad swath of humanity. The more than 600 million people living in the region have seen remarkable progress in the 50 years since the formation of the association. ASEAN has brought peace and prosperity to a troubled region, generated inter-civilizational harmony in the most diverse corner of the earth and brought hope to many people. It may have also acted as a critical catalyst for China’s peaceful rise. ASEAN is therefore more deserving of the next Nobel Peace Prize than any other person or institution today. It is no secret that our global discourse is dominated today by pessimistic voices. In many areas, however, ASEAN has generated optimistic narratives. In an era of growing cultural pessimism, where many thoughtful and infl uential individuals believe that different civilizations—especially Islam and the West—cannot live together in peace, ASEAN provides a living laboratory of peaceful civilizational coexistence. Few are aware that Southeast Asia has become a microcosm of our global condition. In the past, diff erent civilizations existed in separate geopolitical compartments. Today, our shrinking world means they are coming closer together. Southeast Asia is the only region where so many civilizations live together cheek by jowl. And they live together in peace. This miracle was delivered by ASEAN. Second, in an era of growing economic pessimism, where many young people, especially in America and Europe, believe that their lives will get worse in coming decades, Southeast Asia bubbles with optimism. This once-impoverished region has experienced a remarkable economic miracle. World Bank President Jim Yong Kim observed, “In just 30 years, Vietnam has reduced extreme poverty from 50 per cent to roughly 3 per cent—an astounding accomplishment.”1 Indonesia, once a metaphor for continuing and persistent poverty, has one of the most optimistic youthful populations in the world. How did such a poor country become so optimistic? ASEAN has generated economic optimism. Third, in an era of growing geopolitical pessimism, when many leading geopolitical thinkers predict rising competition and tension between great powers—especially between America and China— ASEAN has created an indispensable diplomatic platform that regularly brings all the great powers together. Moreover, ASEAN has created conducive environments for the great powers to talk to each other. Within ASEAN, a culture of peace has evolved as a result of imbibing the Indonesian custom of musyawarah and mufakat (consultation and consensus). Now ASEAN has begun to share this culture of peace with the larger Asia-Pacific region. When tensions rise between China and Japan and their leaders find it difficult to speak to each other, ASEAN provides a face-saving platform and the right setting to restart the conversation. ASEAN has especially facilitated China’s peaceful rise by generating an ecosystem of peace that moderated aggressive impulses. | 3,141 | <h4>Strong ASEAN solves <u>Asia War</u>. </h4><p><strong>Mahbubani 17</strong>, Kishore, and Jeffery Sng. The ASEAN miracle: A catalyst for peace. NUS Press, 2017. (Distinguished Fellow at the Asia Research Institute and former Singaporean diplomat)//Elmer </p><p><u>ASEAN is a living and breathing modern miracle. Why? No other regional organization has done as much as the Association of Southeast Asian Nations (ASEAN) to improve the living conditions of a broad swath of humanity.</u> The more than 600 million people living in the region have seen remarkable progress in the 50 years since the formation of the association. <u><strong><mark>ASEAN</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>has <mark>brought peace and prosperity to a troubled region,</u></strong></mark> generated inter-civilizational harmony in the most diverse corner of the earth and brought hope to many people. <u>It may have also</u> <u><strong>acted as a critical <mark>catalyst for China’s peaceful rise.</u></strong></mark> <u>ASEAN is therefore more deserving of the next Nobel Peace Prize than any other person or institution today</u>. It is no secret that our global discourse is dominated today by pessimistic voices. <u>In many areas, however, ASEAN has generated optimistic narratives.</u> In an era of growing cultural pessimism, where many thoughtful and infl uential individuals believe that different civilizations—especially Islam and the West—cannot live together in peace, <u>ASEAN <strong><mark>provides</strong> </mark>a <strong>living <mark>laboratory of peaceful civilizational coexistence</u></strong></mark>. Few are aware that Southeast Asia has become a microcosm of our global condition. In the past, diff erent civilizations existed in separate geopolitical compartments. Today, our shrinking world means they are coming closer together. Southeast Asia is the only region where so many civilizations live together cheek by jowl. And they live together in peace. This miracle was delivered by ASEAN. Second, in an era of growing economic pessimism, where many young people, especially in America and Europe, believe that their lives will get worse in coming decades, Southeast Asia bubbles with optimism. This once-impoverished region has experienced a remarkable economic miracle. World Bank President Jim Yong Kim observed, “In just 30 years, Vietnam has reduced extreme poverty from 50 per cent to roughly 3 per cent—an astounding accomplishment.”1 Indonesia, once a metaphor for continuing and persistent poverty, has one of the most optimistic youthful populations in the world. How did such a poor country become so optimistic? ASEAN has generated economic optimism. Third, in an era of growing geopolitical pessimism, when many leading geopolitical thinkers predict rising competition and tension between great powers—especially between America and China— <u><strong><mark>ASEAN</u></strong></mark> has <u><strong><mark>created</u></strong></mark> an <u><strong><mark>indispensable </mark>diplomatic <mark>platform</u></strong></mark> <u>that regularly brings all the great powers together. Moreover, ASEAN has created</u> <u><strong><mark>conducive</u></strong></mark> <u>environments</u> <u><strong><mark>for</u></strong></mark> <u>the</u> <u><strong><mark>great powers to talk</u></strong></mark> to each other. Within ASEAN, a culture of peace has evolved as a result of imbibing the Indonesian custom of musyawarah and mufakat (consultation and consensus). Now ASEAN has begun to share this culture of peace with the larger Asia-Pacific region. <u><strong>When tensions rise</u></strong> between China and Japan and their leaders find it difficult to speak to each other, <u><strong>ASEAN provides a <mark>face-saving platform</u></strong></mark> <u>and the right setting to restart the conversation. ASEAN has especially facilitated China’s peaceful rise by <strong><mark>generating</u></strong></mark> <u>an</u> <u><strong>ecosystem of <mark>peace that</u></strong></mark> <u><strong><mark>moderated aggressive impulses</u></strong></mark>.</p> | 1AC | null | Advantage | 819,227 | 151 | 168,172 | ./documents/hsld22/StrakeJesuitCollegePreparatory/NaWe/StrakeJesuitCollegePreparatory-NaWe-Aff-Barkley-Forum-for-High-Schools-WAU.docx | 970,172 | A | Barkley Forum for High Schools | WAU | Challenge Early JA | Cho,Traber,Wang | AC - ASEAN
NC - Black Nationalism, Afropess, Case
1AR - Vague alts bad, all
2NR - All
2AR - K | hsld22/StrakeJesuitCollegePreparatory/NaWe/StrakeJesuitCollegePreparatory-NaWe-Aff-Barkley-Forum-for-High-Schools-WAU.docx | 2023-01-29 14:06:02 | 80,559 | NaWe | Strake Jesuit College Preparatory NaWe | null | Na..... | We..... | null | null | 27,049 | StrakeJesuitCollegePreparatory | Strake Jesuit College Preparatory | TX | 36,501 | 2,003 | hsld22 | HS LD 2022-23 | 2,022 | ld | hs | 1 |
4,696,501 | Settler colonialism is the permeating structure of the nation-state which requires the elimination of indigenous life and land via the occupation of settlers. The appropriation of land turns Natives into ghosts and chattel slaves into excess labor. | Tuck and Yang 12 | Tuck and Yang 12
(Eve Tuck, Unangax, State University of New York at New Paltz K. Wayne Yang University of California, San Diego, Decolonization is not a metaphor, Decolonization: Indigeneity, Education & Society Vol. 1, No. 1, 2012, pp. 1-40, JKS) | Settler colonialism operates through internal/external colonial modes simultaneously because there is no spatial separation between metropole and colony. in the United States, many Indigenous peoples have been forcibly removed from their homelands onto reservations, indentured, and abducted into state custody, signaling the form of colonization as simultaneously internal (via boarding schools and other biopolitical modes of control) and external (via uranium mining on Indigenous land in the US Southwest and oil extraction on Indigenous land in Alaska) with a frontier (the US military still nicknames all enemy territory “Indian Country”). The horizons of the settler colonial nation-state require total appropriation of Indigenous life and land Settler colonialism is different from other forms of colonialism settlers come with the intention of making a new home on the land, that insists on settler sovereignty over all things relying on postcolonial literatures or coloniality that ignore settler colonialism will not help to envision the shape that decolonization must take in settler colonial contexts Land is what is most valuable, contested, required This is both because the settlers make land their source of capital, the disruption of Indigenous relationships to land represents epistemic, ontological, cosmological violence This violence is not temporally contained in the arrival of the settler but is reasserted each day of occupation. settler colonialism is a structure and not an event land is remade into property and human relationships to land are restricted to the relationship of the owner to his property In order for the settlers to make a place their home, they must destroy and disappear the Indigenous peoples that live there. Our/their relationships to land comprise our/their epistemologies, ontologies, and cosmologies. Indigenous peoples must be erased, must be made into ghosts settler colonialism involves the subjugation and forced labor of chattel slaves, whose bodies and lives become the property, and who are kept landless. chattels are commodities of labor and therefore it is the slave’s person that is the excess. the slave is a desirable commodity but the person underneath is imprisonable, punishable, and murderable. The violence of keeping/killing the chattel slave makes them deathlike monsters in the settler imagination The chattel slave serves as that excess labor, labor that can never be paid because payment would have to be in the form of property (land). Settlers are not immigrants. . In this set of settler colonial relations, colonial subjects who are displaced by external colonialism, as well as racialized and minoritized by internal colonialism, still occupy and settle stolen Indigenous land. Settlers are diverse, not just white European descent, and include people of color This tightly wound set of conditions and racialized, globalized relations exponentially complicates what is meant by decolonization, and by solidarity, against settler colonial forces. Decolonization as metaphor allows people to equivocate contradictory decolonial desires because it turns decolonization into an empty signifier to be filled by any track towards liberation. the tracks walk all over land/people in settler contexts. decolonization must involve the repatriation of land simultaneous to the recognition of how land and relations to land have always already been differently understood and enacted; that is, all of the land, and not just symbolically. This is precisely why decolonization is unsettling, especially across lines of solidarity Settler colonialism and its decolonization implicates and unsettles everyone. | The horizons of the settler colonial nation-state require total appropriation of Indigenous life and land that insists on settler sovereignty over all things settlers make land their source of capital, the disruption of Indigenous relationships to land represents epistemic, ontological, cosmological violence. This violence is not temporally contained but is reasserted each day of occupation settler colonialism is a structure and not an event involves the subjugation and forced labor of chattel slaves, whose bodies and lives become the property, and who are kept landless the slave’s person that is the excess Settlers are diverse, not just white Decolonization as metaphor allows people to equivocate contradictory decolonial desires because it turns decolonization into an empty signifier to be filled by any track towards liberation decolonization must involve the repatriation of land | Our intention in this descriptive exercise is not be exhaustive, or even inarguable; instead, we wish to emphasize that (a) decolonization will take a different shape in each of these contexts - though they can overlap - and that (b) neither external nor internal colonialism adequately describe the form of colonialism which operates in the United States or other nation-states in which the colonizer comes to stay. Settler colonialism operates through internal/external colonial modes simultaneously because there is no spatial separation between metropole and colony. For example, in the United States, many Indigenous peoples have been forcibly removed from their homelands onto reservations, indentured, and abducted into state custody, signaling the form of colonization as simultaneously internal (via boarding schools and other biopolitical modes of control) and external (via uranium mining on Indigenous land in the US Southwest and oil extraction on Indigenous land in Alaska) with a frontier (the US military still nicknames all enemy territory “Indian Country”). The horizons of the settler colonial nation-state are total and require a mode of total appropriation of Indigenous life and land, rather than the selective expropriation of profit-producing fragments. Settler colonialism is different from other forms of colonialism in that settlers come with the intention of making a new home on the land, a homemaking that insists on settler sovereignty over all things in their new domain. Thus, relying solely on postcolonial literatures or theories of coloniality that ignore settler colonialism will not help to envision the shape that decolonization must take in settler colonial contexts. Within settler colonialism, the most important concern is land/water/air/subterranean earth (land, for shorthand, in this article.) Land is what is most valuable, contested, required. This is both because the settlers make Indigenous land their new home and source of capital, and also because the disruption of Indigenous relationships to land represents a profound epistemic, ontological, cosmological violence. This violence is not temporally contained in the arrival of the settler but is reasserted each day of occupation. This is why Patrick Wolfe (1999) emphasizes that settler colonialism is a structure and not an event. In the process of settler colonialism, land is remade into property and human relationships to land are restricted to the relationship of the owner to his property. Epistemological, ontological, and cosmological relationships to land are interred, indeed made pre-modern and backward. Made savage. In order for the settlers to make a place their home, they must destroy and disappear the Indigenous peoples that live there. Indigenous peoples are those who have creation stories, not colonization stories, about how we/they came to be in a particular place - indeed how we/they came to be a place. Our/their relationships to land comprise our/their epistemologies, ontologies, and cosmologies. For the settlers, Indigenous peoples are in the way and, in the destruction of Indigenous peoples, Indigenous communities, and over time and through law and policy, Indigenous peoples’ claims to land under settler regimes, land is recast as property and as a resource. Indigenous peoples must be erased, must be made into ghosts (Tuck and Ree, forthcoming). At the same time, settler colonialism involves the subjugation and forced labor of chattel slaves, whose bodies and lives become the property, and who are kept landless. Slavery in settler colonial contexts is distinct from other forms of indenture whereby excess labor is extracted from persons. First, chattels are commodities of labor and therefore it is the slave’s person that is the excess. Second, unlike workers who may aspire to own land, the slave’s very presence on the land is already an excess that must be dis-located. Thus, the slave is a desirable commodity but the person underneath is imprisonable, punishable, and murderable. The violence of keeping/killing the chattel slave makes them deathlike monsters in the settler imagination; they are reconfigured/disfigured as the threat, the razor’s edge of safety and terror. The settler, if known by his actions and how he justifies them, sees himself as holding dominion over the earth and its flora and fauna, as the anthropocentric normal, and as more developed, more human, more deserving than other groups or species. The settler is making a new "home" and that home is rooted in a homesteading worldview where the wild land and wild people were made for his benefit. He can only make his identity as a settler by making the land produce, and produce excessively, because "civilization" is defined as production in excess of the "natural" world (i.e. in excess of the sustainable production already present in the Indigenous world). In order for excess production, he needs excess labor, which he cannot provide himself. The chattel slave serves as that excess labor, labor that can never be paid because payment would have to be in the form of property (land). The settler's wealth is land, or a fungible version of it, and so payment for labor is impossible.6 The settler positions himself as both superior and normal; the settler is natural, whereas the Indigenous inhabitant and the chattel slave are unnatural, even supernatural. Settlers are not immigrants. Immigrants are beholden to the Indigenous laws and epistemologies of the lands they migrate to. Settlers become the law, supplanting Indigenous laws and epistemologies. Therefore, settler nations are not immigrant nations (See also A.J. Barker, 2009). Not unique, the United States, as a settler colonial nation-state, also operates as an empire - utilizing external forms and internal forms of colonization simultaneous to the settler colonial project. This means, and this is perplexing to some, that dispossessed people are brought onto seized Indigenous land through other colonial projects. Other colonial projects include enslavement, as discussed, but also military recruitment, low-wage and high-wage labor recruitment (such as agricultural workers and overseas-trained engineers), and displacement/migration (such as the coerced immigration from nations torn by U.S. wars or devastated by U.S. economic policy). In this set of settler colonial relations, colonial subjects who are displaced by external colonialism, as well as racialized and minoritized by internal colonialism, still occupy and settle stolen Indigenous land. Settlers are diverse, not just of white European descent, and include people of color, even from other colonial contexts. This tightly wound set of conditions and racialized, globalized relations exponentially complicates what is meant by decolonization, and by solidarity, against settler colonial forces. Decolonization in exploitative colonial situations could involve the seizing of imperial wealth by the postcolonial subject. In settler colonial situations, seizing imperial wealth is inextricably tied to settlement and re-invasion. Likewise, the promise of integration and civil rights is predicated on securing a share of a settler-appropriated wealth (as well as expropriated ‘third-world’ wealth). Decolonization in a settler context is fraught because empire, settlement, and internal colony have no spatial separation. Each of these features of settler colonialism in the US context - empire, settlement, and internal colony - make it a site of contradictory decolonial desires7. Decolonization as metaphor allows people to equivocate these contradictory decolonial desires because it turns decolonization into an empty signifier to be filled by any track towards liberation. In reality, the tracks walk all over land/people in settler contexts. Though the details are not fixed or agreed upon, in our view, decolonization in the settler colonial context must involve the repatriation of land simultaneous to the recognition of how land and relations to land have always already been differently understood and enacted; that is, all of the land, and not just symbolically. This is precisely why decolonization is necessarily unsettling, especially across lines of solidarity. “Decolonization never takes place unnoticed” (Fanon, 1963, p. 36). Settler colonialism and its decolonization implicates and unsettles everyone. | 8,393 | <h4><strong>Settler colonialism is the permeating structure of the nation-state which requires the elimination of indigenous life and land via the occupation of settlers. The appropriation of land turns Natives into ghosts and chattel slaves into excess labor.</h4><p>Tuck and Yang 12</p><p>(Eve Tuck, Unangax<u>, State University of New York at New Paltz K. Wayne Yang University of California, San Diego, Decolonization is not a metaphor, Decolonization: Indigeneity, Education & Society Vol. 1, No. 1, 2012, pp. 1-40, JKS)</p><p></u></strong>Our intention in this descriptive exercise is not be exhaustive, or even inarguable; instead, we wish to emphasize that (a) decolonization will take a different shape in each of these contexts - though they can overlap - and that (b) neither external nor internal colonialism adequately describe the form of colonialism which operates in the United States or other nation-states in which the colonizer comes to stay. <u>Settler colonialism operates through internal/external colonial modes simultaneously because there is no spatial separation between metropole and colony. </u>For example, <u>in the United States, many Indigenous peoples have been forcibly removed from their homelands onto reservations, indentured, and abducted into state custody, signaling the form of colonization as simultaneously internal (via boarding schools and other biopolitical modes of control) and external (via uranium mining on Indigenous land in the US Southwest and oil extraction on Indigenous land in Alaska) with a frontier (the US military still nicknames all enemy territory “Indian Country”).</u> <u><strong><mark>The horizons of the settler colonial nation-state</mark> </u></strong>are total and<u><strong> <mark>require</mark> </u></strong>a mode of<u><strong> <mark>total appropriation of Indigenous life and land</u></strong></mark>, rather than the selective expropriation of profit-producing fragments. <u>Settler colonialism is different from other forms of colonialism </u>in that<u> settlers come with the intention of making a new home on the land, </u>a homemaking<u> <mark>that insists on settler sovereignty over all things</u></mark> in their new domain. Thus, <u><strong>relying</u></strong> solely <u><strong>on postcolonial literatures or </u></strong>theories of<u><strong> coloniality that ignore settler colonialism will not help to envision the shape that decolonization must take in settler colonial contexts</u></strong>. Within settler colonialism, the most important concern is land/water/air/subterranean earth (land, for shorthand, in this article.) <u>Land is what is most valuable, contested, required</u>. <u>This is both because the <mark>settlers make </u></mark>Indigenous<u><mark> land their</mark> </u>new home and<u> <mark>source of capital,</mark> </u>and also because<u> <mark>the disruption of Indigenous relationships to land represents</mark> </u>a profound<u> <strong><mark>epistemic, ontological, cosmological violence</u></strong>. <u>This violence is not temporally contained</mark> in the arrival of the settler <mark>but is reasserted each day of occupation</mark>.</u> This is why Patrick Wolfe (1999) emphasizes that <u><strong><mark>settler colonialism is a structure and not an event</u></strong></mark>. In the process of settler colonialism, <u>land is remade into property and human relationships to land are restricted to the relationship of the owner to his property</u>. Epistemological, ontological, and cosmological relationships to land are interred, indeed made pre-modern and backward. Made savage. <u>In order for the settlers to make a place their home, they must destroy and disappear the Indigenous peoples that live there.</u> Indigenous peoples are those who have creation stories, not colonization stories, about how we/they came to be in a particular place - indeed how we/they came to be a place. <u>Our/their relationships to land comprise our/their epistemologies, ontologies, and cosmologies.</u> For the settlers, Indigenous peoples are in the way and, in the destruction of Indigenous peoples, Indigenous communities, and over time and through law and policy, Indigenous peoples’ claims to land under settler regimes, land is recast as property and as a resource. <u><strong>Indigenous peoples must be erased, must be made into ghosts</u></strong> (Tuck and Ree, forthcoming). At the same time, <u>settler colonialism <mark>involves the subjugation and forced labor of chattel slaves, whose bodies and lives become the property, and who are kept landless</mark>.</u> Slavery in settler colonial contexts is distinct from other forms of indenture whereby excess labor is extracted from persons. First, <u>chattels are commodities of labor and therefore it is <mark>the slave’s person that is the excess</mark>.</u> Second, unlike workers who may aspire to own land, the slave’s very presence on the land is already an excess that must be dis-located. Thus, <u>the slave is a desirable commodity but the person underneath is imprisonable, punishable, and murderable. The violence of keeping/killing the chattel slave makes them deathlike monsters in the settler imagination</u>; they are reconfigured/disfigured as the threat, the razor’s edge of safety and terror. The settler, if known by his actions and how he justifies them, sees himself as holding dominion over the earth and its flora and fauna, as the anthropocentric normal, and as more developed, more human, more deserving than other groups or species. The settler is making a new "home" and that home is rooted in a homesteading worldview where the wild land and wild people were made for his benefit. He can only make his identity as a settler by making the land produce, and produce excessively, because "civilization" is defined as production in excess of the "natural" world (i.e. in excess of the sustainable production already present in the Indigenous world). In order for excess production, he needs excess labor, which he cannot provide himself. <u>The chattel slave serves as that excess labor, labor that can never be paid because payment would have to be in the form of property (land).</u> The settler's wealth is land, or a fungible version of it, and so payment for labor is impossible.6 The settler positions himself as both superior and normal; the settler is natural, whereas the Indigenous inhabitant and the chattel slave are unnatural, even supernatural. <u>Settlers are not immigrants.</u> Immigrants are beholden to the Indigenous laws and epistemologies of the lands they migrate to. Settlers become the law, supplanting Indigenous laws and epistemologies. Therefore, settler nations are not immigrant nations (See also A.J. Barker, 2009). Not unique, the United States, as a settler colonial nation-state, also operates as an empire - utilizing external forms and internal forms of colonization simultaneous to the settler colonial project<u>.</u> This means, and this is perplexing to some, that dispossessed people are brought onto seized Indigenous land through other colonial projects. Other colonial projects include enslavement, as discussed, but also military recruitment, low-wage and high-wage labor recruitment (such as agricultural workers and overseas-trained engineers), and displacement/migration (such as the coerced immigration from nations torn by U.S. wars or devastated by U.S. economic policy). <u>In this set of settler colonial relations, colonial subjects who are displaced by external colonialism, as well as racialized and minoritized by internal colonialism, still occupy and settle stolen Indigenous land. <mark>Settlers are diverse, not just </u></mark>of <u><mark>white</mark> European descent, and include people of color</u>, even from other colonial contexts. <u>This tightly wound set of conditions and racialized, globalized relations exponentially complicates what is meant by decolonization, and by solidarity, against settler colonial forces.</u> Decolonization in exploitative colonial situations could involve the seizing of imperial wealth by the postcolonial subject. In settler colonial situations, seizing imperial wealth is inextricably tied to settlement and re-invasion. Likewise, the promise of integration and civil rights is predicated on securing a share of a settler-appropriated wealth (as well as expropriated ‘third-world’ wealth). Decolonization in a settler context is fraught because empire, settlement, and internal colony have no spatial separation. Each of these features of settler colonialism in the US context - empire, settlement, and internal colony - make it a site of contradictory decolonial desires7. <u><strong><mark>Decolonization as metaphor allows people to equivocate</mark> </u></strong>these <u><strong><mark>contradictory decolonial desires because it turns decolonization into an empty signifier to be filled by any track towards liberation</mark>.</u></strong> In reality, <u>the tracks walk all over land/people in settler contexts.</u> Though the details are not fixed or agreed upon, in our view, <u><mark>decolonization</mark> </u>in the settler colonial context<u> <mark>must involve the repatriation of land </mark>simultaneous to the recognition of how land and relations to land have always already been differently understood and enacted; that is, all of the land, and not just symbolically.</u> <u>This is precisely why decolonization is </u>necessarily<u> unsettling, especially across lines of solidarity</u>. “Decolonization never takes place unnoticed” (Fanon, 1963, p. 36). <u><strong>Settler colonialism and its decolonization implicates and unsettles everyone.</p></u></strong> | null | 4 | 1nc – k | 37,296 | 643 | 163,300 | ./documents/hsld22/Harker/ramu/Harker-ramu-Neg-ndca-Round-2.docx | 990,743 | N | ndca | 2 | mountain house es | anna myers | 1ac - asean
1nc - t longley, t all borders, t operationalization, settler colonialism k, case
1ar - all
2nr - k, case
2ar - case, k | hsld22/Harker/ramu/Harker-ramu-Neg-ndca-Round-2.docx | 2023-03-25 18:53:50 | 80,526 | ramu | Harker ramu | null | ra..... | mu..... | null | null | 26,565 | Harker | Harker | CA | null | 2,003 | hsld22 | HS LD 2022-23 | 2,022 | ld | hs | 1 |
2,560,274 | Prospect of conviction leads to nuclear first use --- it’s existential | Oppenheimer 19 | Oppenheimer 19 - professor with the NYU School of Professional Studies Center for Global Affairs, life member of the Council on Foreign Relations, and Senior Consulting Fellow for scenario planning at the International Institute for Strategic Studies (Michael, “Will Trump risk war to save his presidency?” The Hill, https://thehill.com/opinion/white-house/432275-will-trump-risk-war-to-save-his-presidency) | Trump is prepared to inflict lasting damage to save his presidency the odds of a "wag the dog" dynamic are increasing the temptation to change the subject and rally his base by hyping an external threat could become irresistible Backed into a corner and politically wounded, we can expect neither rational nor well-intentioned behavior from the president a real national security crisis, provoked by Trump will move rapidly, present existential risk We face an oversupply of potential crises for a president prepared to distort and manipulate external threats for political purposes Iran could give up on the JCPOA resume its nuclear program internal conflict in Venezuela could worsen territorial disputes in the South and East China Seas could lead to a direct clash as could Taiwan there could be dangerous fallout from North Korea; Russia could move more boldly into Ukraine. his support for military restraint is not likely to survive his first exploitable crisis Pompeo look favorably on the use of force and are spoiling for a fight Our president is politically motivated to seize any opportunity available to save his presidency Internal constraints on his behavior have all but disappeared and the enlarged presence of hard right advisors in his inner circle will generate further impetus towards escalation first use of nuclear weapons | Trump is prepared to inflict lasting damage to save his presidency the odds of "wag the dog are increasing the temptation to rally his base by hyping an external threat could become irresistible we can expect neither rational nor well-intentioned behavior a crisis, provoked by Trump will present existential risk We face an oversupply of crises for a president prepared to manipulate external threats for political purposes Iran S C S Taiwan North Korea; Ukraine. his support for military restraint is not likely to survive crisis Our president is politically motivated to seize any opportunity to save his presidency Internal constraints on his behavior have all but disappeared and hard right advisors will generate impetus towards first use of nuclear weapons | Lost — temporally — in the Cohen testimony and the predictable collapse of the nuclear talks with North Korea, is the lesson we need to learn from the fabricated Mexican border ‘crisis’ and fake national emergency. It is this: President Trump is prepared to inflict lasting damage on the country to save his presidency. As we try to impose fact and law on immigration policy, we need to apply this lesson in contemplating Trump’s next desperate act. The most worrisome scenario is a real but still manageable external crisis that arrives at a moment when escalation is in Trump’s political interest. Response mismanagement would fuel the crisis, but the real threat is a president motivated to hype a real crisis that his chaotic administration will be unable to control. Such a possibility has risen from Hollywood cliché to serious risk and the odds of a "wag the dog" dynamic are increasing. Trump is in a deep hole and digging furiously. The political benefits of the wall will prove transitory, as construction bogs down in the courts and the latest caravan melts away. Between Mueller, mounting congressional scrutiny, low poll numbers, Republican desertions, further indictments of family and friends, impeachment (if not conviction) and an approaching election, the temptation to change the subject and rally his base by hyping an external threat could become irresistible. Backed into a corner and politically wounded, we can expect neither rational nor well-intentioned behavior from the president. Unlike the slow moving and artificial crisis over the border, a real national security crisis, provoked by Trump or not, will move rapidly, present high, possibly existential risk, involve complexity, uncertainty and unintended negative consequences from ill-conceived policy choices. Consider Berlin blockades, Soviet missiles in Cuba, several global financial and economic crises, 9/11. Few presidents have avoided such perils and their presidencies — and the future of the country — have been defined by their responses. Such episodes are exacting tests of precisely those qualities lacking in the Trump Administration: the rigor of policy process, the knowledge and skill of advisors, the confidence and mutual respect among and between policy and intelligence officials and the calmness of the president. Even with the best of intentions and effort, presidential performance has varied widely over our recent history. At the extremes, JFK’s skillful management of the missile crisis produced a peaceful resolution, Soviet capitulation, an improved period in U.S.-Soviet relations and enhanced political standing for the president. George W. Bush’s response to 9/11 was to invade Iraq, arguably the worst strategic mistake since Vietnam and still paying negative dividends for ourselves and the Middle East. We face an oversupply of potential crises and all offer ample opportunities for a president prepared to distort and manipulate external threats for political purposes. Iran could give up on the JCPOA and resume its nuclear program, reinforcing Iran-Israel conflict arising out of Syria and offering an opportunity for U.S. intervention; internal conflict in Venezuela could worsen and be attributed to hostile external influences; territorial disputes in the South and East China Seas could lead to a direct clash between U.S. and Chinese forces, as could a crisis precipitated by a Chinese move against Taiwan; there could be dangerous fallout from the failed nuclear negotiation with North Korea; Russia could move more boldly into Ukraine. Some might challenge the likelihood of this scenario, based on Trump’s announcements (not yet implemented) of troop withdrawals from Syria and Afghanistan, but his support for military restraint is not likely to survive his first exploitable crisis. His apparent preference for restraint is not the product of experience or deep conviction and-to his and our great fortune-has not yet been tested by crisis. His two closest advisors, Pompeo and Bolton, look favorably on the use of force to promote American interests and are spoiling for a fight with Iran. The Bush precedent is instructive. An inexperienced president entered office with a declared preference for restraint in the use of force, opposition to nation building and support for collective action with allies. He then did a complete about-face in reaction to 9/11 and followed his neocon advisors into a unilateral, regime changing, nation building disaster in Iraq. We must all recognize the problem we’re dealing with and get out in front of the dangers. Our president is a willful and heedless man who is personally inclined and politically motivated to seize any opportunity available to save his presidency. Managing a future crisis, even if he had the capacity, will not be his priority. Capitalizing on it will be. Internal constraints on his behavior have all but disappeared and the enlarged presence of hard right advisors in his inner circle will generate further impetus towards escalation, especially if Iran provides the provocation. Our priority — in the public, the Congress, the press — is not to improve the administration’s decision-making skills, but to contain Trump’s instincts for doing harm. We must reassert congressional war powers, require intelligence community confirmation of the factual basis of any administration war narrative, insist on defense department assessment of our capacity to carry out presidential policy preferences, place limits on the president’s authority to launch first use of nuclear weapons, scrutinize administration policy on emerging conflicts through public or closed hearings and — for the press — aggressively cover the administration’s reaction to emerging potential crises. | 5,762 | <h4>Prospect of conviction leads to <u>nuclear first use</u> --- it’s existential</h4><p><strong>Oppenheimer 19 </strong>- professor with the NYU School of Professional Studies Center for Global Affairs, life member of the Council on Foreign Relations, and Senior Consulting Fellow for scenario planning at the International Institute for Strategic Studies (Michael, “Will Trump risk war to save his presidency?” The Hill, https://thehill.com/opinion/white-house/432275-will-trump-risk-war-to-save-his-presidency)</p><p>Lost — temporally — in the Cohen testimony and the predictable collapse of the nuclear talks with North Korea, is the lesson we need to learn from the fabricated Mexican border ‘crisis’ and fake national emergency. It is this: President <u><strong><mark>Trump is prepared to inflict lasting damage</u></strong></mark> on the country <u><strong><mark>to save his presidency</u></strong></mark>. As we try to impose fact and law on immigration policy, we need to apply this lesson in contemplating Trump’s next desperate act. The most worrisome scenario is a real but still manageable external crisis that arrives at a moment when escalation is in Trump’s political interest. Response mismanagement would fuel the crisis, but the real threat is a president motivated to hype a real crisis that his chaotic administration will be unable to control. Such a possibility has risen from Hollywood cliché to serious risk and <u><strong><mark>the odds of </mark>a <mark>"wag the dog</mark>" dynamic <mark>are increasing</u></strong></mark>. Trump is in a deep hole and digging furiously. The political benefits of the wall will prove transitory, as construction bogs down in the courts and the latest caravan melts away. Between Mueller, mounting congressional scrutiny, low poll numbers, Republican desertions, further indictments of family and friends, impeachment (if not conviction) and an approaching election, <u><strong><mark>the temptation to </mark>change the subject and <mark>rally his base by hyping an external threat could become irresistible</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong>Backed into a corner and politically wounded, <mark>we can expect neither rational nor well-intentioned behavior</mark> from the president</u></strong>. Unlike the slow moving and artificial crisis over the border, <u><strong><mark>a </mark>real national security <mark>crisis, provoked by Trump</u></strong></mark> or not, <u><strong><mark>will </mark>move rapidly, <mark>present</mark> </u></strong>high, possibly <u><strong><mark>existential risk</u></strong></mark>, involve complexity, uncertainty and unintended negative consequences from ill-conceived policy choices. Consider Berlin blockades, Soviet missiles in Cuba, several global financial and economic crises, 9/11. Few presidents have avoided such perils and their presidencies — and the future of the country — have been defined by their responses. Such episodes are exacting tests of precisely those qualities lacking in the Trump Administration: the rigor of policy process, the knowledge and skill of advisors, the confidence and mutual respect among and between policy and intelligence officials and the calmness of the president. Even with the best of intentions and effort, presidential performance has varied widely over our recent history. At the extremes, JFK’s skillful management of the missile crisis produced a peaceful resolution, Soviet capitulation, an improved period in U.S.-Soviet relations and enhanced political standing for the president. George W. Bush’s response to 9/11 was to invade Iraq, arguably the worst strategic mistake since Vietnam and still paying negative dividends for ourselves and the Middle East. <u><strong><mark>We face an oversupply of</mark> potential <mark>crises</u></strong></mark> and all offer ample opportunities <u><strong><mark>for a president prepared to </mark>distort and <mark>manipulate external threats</mark> <mark>for political purposes</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong><mark>Iran </mark>could give up on the JCPOA </u></strong>and <u><strong>resume its nuclear program</u></strong>, reinforcing Iran-Israel conflict arising out of Syria and offering an opportunity for U.S. intervention; <u><strong>internal conflict in Venezuela could worsen</u></strong> and be attributed to hostile external influences; <u><strong>territorial disputes in the <mark>S</mark>outh and East <mark>C</mark>hina <mark>S</mark>eas could lead to a direct clash</u></strong> between U.S. and Chinese forces, <u><strong>as could</u></strong> a crisis precipitated by a Chinese move against <u><strong><mark>Taiwan</u></strong></mark>; <u><strong>there could be dangerous fallout</u></strong> <u><strong>from</u></strong> the failed nuclear negotiation with <u><strong><mark>North Korea; </mark>Russia could move more boldly into <mark>Ukraine.</strong></mark> </u>Some might challenge the likelihood of this scenario, based on Trump’s announcements (not yet implemented) of troop withdrawals from Syria and Afghanistan, but <u><strong><mark>his support for military restraint is not likely to survive</mark> his first exploitable <mark>crisis</u></strong></mark>. His apparent preference for restraint is not the product of experience or deep conviction and-to his and our great fortune-has not yet been tested by crisis. His two closest advisors, <u><strong>Pompeo </u></strong>and Bolton, <u><strong>look favorably on the use of force</u></strong> to promote American interests <u><strong>and are spoiling for a fight</u></strong> with Iran. The Bush precedent is instructive. An inexperienced president entered office with a declared preference for restraint in the use of force, opposition to nation building and support for collective action with allies. He then did a complete about-face in reaction to 9/11 and followed his neocon advisors into a unilateral, regime changing, nation building disaster in Iraq. We must all recognize the problem we’re dealing with and get out in front of the dangers. <u><strong><mark>Our president is</u></strong></mark> a willful and heedless man who is personally inclined and <u><strong><mark>politically motivated to seize any opportunity </mark>available <mark>to save his presidency</u></strong></mark>. Managing a future crisis, even if he had the capacity, will not be his priority. Capitalizing on it will be. <u><strong><mark>Internal constraints on his behavior have all but disappeared and </mark>the enlarged presence of <mark>hard right advisors </mark>in his inner circle <mark>will generate </mark>further <mark>impetus towards</mark> escalation</u></strong>, especially if Iran provides the provocation. Our priority — in the public, the Congress, the press — is not to improve the administration’s decision-making skills, but to contain Trump’s instincts for doing harm. We must reassert congressional war powers, require intelligence community confirmation of the factual basis of any administration war narrative, insist on defense department assessment of our capacity to carry out presidential policy preferences, place limits on the president’s authority to launch <u><strong><mark>first use of nuclear weapons</u></strong></mark>, scrutinize administration policy on emerging conflicts through public or closed hearings and — for the press — aggressively cover the administration’s reaction to emerging potential crises.</p> | 1NC | null | 1NC | 59,933 | 414 | 82,395 | ./documents/ndtceda19/MichiganState/ScPe/Michigan%20State-Scullion-Pepper-Neg-Wake-Round3.docx | 613,698 | N | Wake | 3 | Wake BE | Hunter McCullough | 1AC
-CN STM
1NC
-Security K
-Unilat CP
-Xi DA
-Conviction PTX
2NR
-Xi | ndtceda19/MichiganState/ScPe/Michigan%20State-Scullion-Pepper-Neg-Wake-Round3.docx | null | 51,952 | ScPe | Michigan State ScPe | null | Ja..... | Sc..... | La..... | Pe..... | 19,271 | MichiganState | Michigan State | null | null | 1,009 | ndtceda19 | NDT/CEDA 2019-20 | 2,019 | cx | college | 2 |
2,174,466 | Arms racing commercializes APT operations – that causes rogue spoofing and early warning attacks | Johnson 19 | Johnson 19 [James Martin Center for Nonproliferation Studies (CNS), Middlebury Institute of International Studies, Monterey. “The AI-cyber nexus: implications for military escalation, deterrence and strategic stability” Journal of Cyber Policy. 12-09-2019. https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/full/10.1080/23738871.2019.1701693?casa_token=S5u2prjCDUwAAAAA:MIiwLChl5HM7bNaPhlussbuwDnsgv0qcVM1oPkHZUCkxmqKqGWObK1c5VvSExQ2z4fk8DM8-TkX9kg] | Advances in AI could also exacerbate this cybersecurity challenge by enabling improvements to the cyber offence Machine learning and AI by automating advanced persistent threat APT operations might dramatically reduce the extensive manpower resources and high levels of technical skill required to execute APT operations (or ‘hunting for weaknesses’), especially against hardened nuclear targets The machine speed of AI-augmented cyber tools could enable a low-skilled and capital-restricted attacker to exploit a narrow window of opportunity to penetrate an adversary’s cyber-defences or use APT tools to find new vulnerabilities when docked for maintenance air-gapped nuclear-powered submarines, considered secure when submerged, could become increasingly vulnerable to a new generation of low-cost – possibly black-market – and highly automated APT cyberattacks.
An attacker could also apply AI machine learning techniques to target autonomous dual-use early-warning systems with ‘weaponized software’ causing unpredictable and potentially undetectable errors Furthermore, as the linkages between digital and physical systems the potential for to an adversary to use cyberattacks in both kinetic and nonkinetic attacks will increase. A significant risk variable in the operation of autonomous systems is the time that passes between a system failure and the time it takes for a human operator to take corrective action. If the system failure is the result of a deliberate act, this time frame will be compressed
Even if nuclear early-warning systems might eventually detect the subversion heightened levels of uncertainty and tension caused by an alert may impel the respective militaries to put their nuclear weapons on high alert status This skewed assessment by states in the context of nuclear weapons, which are ready to launch nuclear weapons at a moment’s notice, would likely precipitate worst-case scenario thinking that may spark an inadvertent escalation During a crisis, the inability of a state to determine an attacker’s intent may lead an actor to conclude that an attack was intended to undermine its nuclear deterrent ’ (audio and video manipulation), coupled with data-poisoning cyberattacks, could spark an escalatory crisis between two (or more) nuclear states (Fitzpatrick 2019).30 | Advances exacerbate cybersecurity challenge by enabling offence Machine APT dramatically reduce the resources and technical skill required to execute hunting for weaknesses’ against hardened nuclear targets tools enable a low-skilled -restricted attacker to exploit a narrow window of opportunity when docked air-gapped nuclear submarines become increasingly vulnerable to a new generation of low-cost black-market APT cyberattacks
AI machine learning target autonomous early-warning systems
heightened uncertainty and tension may impel militaries to put nuclear weapons on high alert status worst-case scenario thinking may spark escalation | Advances in AI could also exacerbate this cybersecurity challenge by enabling improvements to the cyber offence. Machine learning and AI by automating advanced persistent threat (APT) operations might dramatically reduce the extensive manpower resources and high levels of technical skill required to execute APT operations (or ‘hunting for weaknesses’), especially against hardened nuclear targets.26 The machine speed of AI-augmented cyber tools could enable a low-skilled and capital-restricted attacker to exploit a narrow window of opportunity to penetrate an adversary’s cyber-defences or use APT tools to find new vulnerabilities. For example, when docked for maintenance air-gapped nuclear-powered submarines, considered secure when submerged, could become increasingly vulnerable to a new generation of low-cost – possibly black-market – and highly automated APT cyberattacks.
An attacker could also apply AI machine learning techniques to target autonomous dual-use early-warning and other operating systems (e.g. C3I, ISR, early-warning and robotic control networks) with ‘weaponized software’ such as hacking, subverting, spoofing or tricking, causing unpredictable and potentially undetectable errors, malfunctions and behavioural manipulation to weapons systems – or ‘data-poisoning’. 27 Furthermore, as the linkages between digital and physical systems (or the ‘Internet of Things’) expand, the potential for to an adversary to use cyberattacks in both kinetic and nonkinetic attacks will increase. A significant risk variable in the operation of autonomous systems is the time that passes between a system failure (i.e. performing in a manner other than how the human operator intended) and the time it takes for a human operator to take corrective action. If the system failure is the result of a deliberate act, this time frame will be compressed (Johnson 2019a).
Even if nuclear early-warning systems might eventually detect the subversion, heightened levels of uncertainty and tension caused by an alert may impel the respective militaries to put their nuclear weapons on high alert status. This skewed assessment by states in the context of nuclear weapons, which are ready to launch nuclear weapons at a moment’s notice, would likely precipitate worst-case scenario thinking that may spark an inadvertent escalation (Talmadge 2017).28 During a crisis, the inability of a state to determine an attacker’s intent may lead an actor to conclude that an attack (threatened or actual) was intended to undermine its nuclear deterrent.29 For example, an AIenabled third party generated ‘deepfake’ (audio and video manipulation), coupled with data-poisoning cyberattacks, could spark an escalatory crisis between two (or more) nuclear states (Fitzpatrick 2019).30 | 2,776 | <h4>Arms racing commercializes <u>APT operations</u> – that causes <u>rogue spoofing</u> and <u>early warning</u> attacks<u> </h4><p></u><strong>Johnson 19 <u></strong>[James Martin Center for Nonproliferation Studies (CNS), Middlebury Institute of International Studies, Monterey. “The AI-cyber nexus: implications for military escalation, deterrence and strategic stability” Journal of Cyber Policy. 12-09-2019. https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/full/10.1080/23738871.2019.1701693?casa_token=S5u2prjCDUwAAAAA:MIiwLChl5HM7bNaPhlussbuwDnsgv0qcVM1oPkHZUCkxmqKqGWObK1c5VvSExQ2z4fk8DM8-TkX9kg]</p><p><mark>Advances</mark> in AI could also <strong><mark>exacerbate</strong></mark> this <strong><mark>cybersecurity challenge</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>by enabling</mark> improvements to the <strong>cyber <mark>offence</u></strong></mark>. <u><mark>Machine </mark>learning and AI by automating advanced persistent threat</u> (<u><strong><mark>APT</u></strong></mark>) <u>operations might <mark>dramatically reduce the</mark> extensive manpower <mark>resources and</mark> high levels of <mark>technical skill required to</mark> <mark>execute</mark> APT operations (or ‘<strong><mark>hunting for weaknesses’</strong></mark>), especially <mark>against <strong>hardened nuclear targets</u></strong></mark>.26 <u>The <strong>machine speed</strong> of AI-augmented cyber <mark>tools</u></mark> <u>could <mark>enable a <strong>low-skilled</strong></mark> and <strong>capital<mark>-restricted attacker</strong> to exploit a narrow <strong>window of opportunity</u></strong></mark> <u>to penetrate an adversary’s cyber-defences or use APT tools to find new vulnerabilities</u>. For example, <u><mark>when docked</mark> for maintenance <strong><mark>air-gapped nuclear</mark>-powered <mark>submarines</strong></mark>, considered secure when submerged, could <mark>become <strong>increasingly vulnerable</strong> to a new generation of low-cost</mark> – possibly <strong><mark>black-market</strong></mark> – and highly automated <strong><mark>APT cyberattacks</strong></mark>.</p><p>An attacker could also apply <strong><mark>AI machine learning</u></strong></mark> <u>techniques to <mark>target autonomous</mark> dual-use <strong><mark>early-warning</u></strong></mark> and other operating <u><mark>systems</u></mark> (e.g. C3I, ISR, early-warning and robotic control networks) <u>with ‘weaponized software’</u> such as hacking, subverting, spoofing or tricking, <u>causing unpredictable and potentially undetectable errors</u>, malfunctions and behavioural manipulation to weapons systems – or ‘data-poisoning’. 27 <u>Furthermore, as the linkages between digital and physical systems</u> (or the ‘Internet of Things’) expand, <u>the potential for to an adversary to use cyberattacks in both kinetic and nonkinetic attacks will increase. A <strong>significant risk</u></strong> <u>variable in the operation of autonomous systems is the time that passes between a system failure</u> (i.e. performing in a manner other than how the human operator intended) <u>and the time it takes for a human operator to take corrective action. If the system failure is the result of a deliberate act, this time frame will be compressed</u> (Johnson 2019a).</p><p><u>Even if nuclear early-warning systems might eventually detect the subversion</u>, <u><mark>heightened</mark> levels of <strong><mark>uncertainty</strong> and <strong>tension</u></strong></mark> <u>caused by an alert <mark>may impel</mark> the respective <mark>militaries to put</mark> their <strong><mark>nuclear weapons on high alert status</u></strong></mark>. <u>This skewed assessment by states in the context of nuclear weapons, which are ready to launch nuclear weapons at a moment’s notice, would likely precipitate <strong><mark>worst-case scenario thinking</u></strong></mark> <u>that <mark>may spark</mark> an inadvertent <strong><mark>escalation</u></strong></mark> (Talmadge 2017).28 <u>During a crisis, the inability of a state to determine an attacker’s intent may lead an actor to conclude that an attack</u> (threatened or actual) <u>was intended to undermine its <strong>nuclear deterrent</u></strong>.29 For example, an AIenabled third party generated ‘deepfake<u>’ (audio and video manipulation), coupled with data-poisoning cyberattacks, could spark an escalatory crisis between two (or more) nuclear states (Fitzpatrick 2019).30</p></u> | null | null | 1AC | 1,240,848 | 802 | 66,400 | ./documents/hsld20/Harker/Th/Harker-Thakur-Aff-ASU-Round5.docx | 859,796 | A | ASU | 5 | Dublin AL | Sannes, Joel | 1AC - Lethal Cyber v2
1NC - DA - DIB DA - Terror
2NR - DA - Terror | hsld20/Harker/Th/Harker-Thakur-Aff-ASU-Round5.docx | null | 73,082 | RoTh | Harker RoTh | null | Ro..... | Th..... | null | null | 24,534 | Harker | Harker | CA | null | 1,028 | hsld20 | HS LD 2020-21 | 2,020 | ld | hs | 1 |
1,964,084 | It makes nuclear war inevitable in every region | Klare 20 | Dr. Michael T. Klare 20, Five Colleges Professor of Peace and World Security Studies at Hampshire College, Ph.D. from the Graduate School of the Union Institute, BA and MA from Columbia University, Member of the Board of Director at the Arms Control Association, Defense Correspondent for The Nation, “How Rising Temperatures Increase the Likelihood of Nuclear War”, The Nation, 1/13/2020, https://www.thenation.com/article/archive/nuclear-defense-climate-change/ | Climbing temperatures and sea levels will diminish food and water in resource-deprived areas, increasing the risk of widespread starvation, social unrest, and human flight. Global corn production is projected to fall by 14 percent Food scarcity and crop failures pushing hundreds of millions of people into overcrowded cities, where pandemics, ethnic strife, and storm damage is bound to increase. All will impose an immense burden on human institutions states may collapse into a collection of warring chiefdoms fighting over sources of water and other vital resources
A similar momentum is evident in the nuclear arms race, with China, Russia, and the U S rushing to deploy a host of new munitions
nuclear war might erupt in Europe, South Asia, or the western Pacific | sea will diminish food and water pushing millions into overcrowded cities, where pandemics strife increase states collapse fighting over resources
nuclear war erupt in Europe or the Pacific | Climbing world temperatures and rising sea levels will diminish the supply of food and water in many resource-deprived areas, increasing the risk of widespread starvation, social unrest, and human flight. Global corn production, for example, is projected to fall by as much as 14 percent in a 2°C warmer world, according to research cited in a 2018 special report by the UN’s Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC). Food scarcity and crop failures risk pushing hundreds of millions of people into overcrowded cities, where the likelihood of pandemics, ethnic strife, and severe storm damage is bound to increase. All of this will impose an immense burden on human institutions. Some states may collapse or break up into a collection of warring chiefdoms—all fighting over sources of water and other vital resources.
A similar momentum is now evident in the emerging nuclear arms race, with all three major powers—China, Russia, and the United States—rushing to deploy a host of new munitions. This dangerous process commenced a decade ago, when Russian and Chinese leaders sought improvements to their nuclear arsenals and President Barack Obama, in order to secure Senate approval of the New Strategic Arms Reduction Treaty of 2010, agreed to initial funding for the modernization of all three legs of America’s strategic triad, which encompasses submarines, intercontinental ballistic missiles, and bombers. (New START, which mandated significant reductions in US and Russian arsenals, will expire in February 2021 unless renewed by the two countries.) Although Obama initiated the modernization of the nuclear triad, the Trump administration has sought funds to proceed with their full-scale production, at an estimated initial installment of $500 billion over 10 years.
Even during the initial modernization program of the Obama era, Russian and Chinese leaders were sufficiently alarmed to hasten their own nuclear acquisitions. Both countries were already in the process of modernizing their stockpiles—Russia to replace Cold War–era systems that had become unreliable, China to provide its relatively small arsenal with enhanced capabilities. Trump’s decision to acquire a whole new suite of ICBMs, nuclear-armed submarines, and bombers has added momentum to these efforts. And with all three major powers upgrading their arsenals, the other nuclear-weapon states—led by India, Pakistan, and North Korea—have been expanding their stockpiles as well. Moreover, with Trump’s recent decision to abandon the Intermediate-Range Nuclear Forces (INF) Treaty, all major powers are developing missile delivery systems for a regional nuclear war such as might erupt in Europe, South Asia, or the western Pacific. | 2,720 | <h4>It makes <u>nuclear war</u> inevitable in <u>every</u> region</h4><p>Dr. Michael T. <strong>Klare 20</strong>, Five Colleges Professor of Peace and World Security Studies at Hampshire College, Ph.D. from the Graduate School of the Union Institute, BA and MA from Columbia University, Member of the Board of Director at the Arms Control Association, Defense Correspondent for The Nation, “How Rising Temperatures Increase the Likelihood of Nuclear War”, The Nation, 1/13/2020, https://www.thenation.com/article/archive/nuclear-defense-climate-change/</p><p><u>Climbing</u> world <u><strong>temperatures</u></strong> <u>and</u> rising <u><strong><mark>sea</mark> levels</u></strong> <u><mark>will diminish</u></mark> the supply of <u><strong><mark>food</u></strong> <u>and</u> <u><strong>water</u></strong></mark> <u>in</u> many <u><strong>resource-deprived areas</strong>, increasing the risk of widespread <strong>starvation</strong>, social</u> <u><strong>unrest</strong>, and</u> <u><strong>human flight</strong>. Global</u> <u><strong>corn production</u></strong>, for example, <u>is projected to fall by</u> as much as <u><strong>14 percent</u></strong> in a 2°C warmer world, according to research cited in a 2018 special report by the UN’s Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC). <u><strong>Food scarcity</u></strong> <u>and</u> <u><strong>crop failures</u></strong> risk <u><strong><mark>pushing</mark> hundreds of <mark>millions</u></strong></mark> <u>of people <mark>into</u> <u><strong>overcrowded cities</strong>, where</u></mark> the likelihood of <u><strong><mark>pandemics</strong></mark>, ethnic</u> <u><strong><mark>strife</strong></mark>, and</u> severe <u><strong>storm damage</u></strong> <u>is bound to <mark>increase</mark>. All</u> of this <u>will impose an immense burden on human institutions</u>. Some <u><strong><mark>states </mark>may <mark>collapse</u></strong></mark> or break up <u>into a <strong>collection of warring chiefdoms</u></strong>—all <u><mark>fighting over</mark> sources of water and other vital <mark>resources</u></mark>.</p><p><u>A</u> <u><strong>similar momentum</u></strong> <u>is</u> now <u>evident in the</u> emerging <u><strong>nuclear arms race</strong>, with</u> all three major powers—<u><strong>China, Russia, and the U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates—<u>rushing to deploy a</u> <u><strong>host of new munitions</u></strong>. This dangerous process commenced a decade ago, when Russian and Chinese leaders sought improvements to their nuclear arsenals and President Barack Obama, in order to secure Senate approval of the New Strategic Arms Reduction Treaty of 2010, agreed to initial funding for the modernization of all three legs of America’s strategic triad, which encompasses submarines, intercontinental ballistic missiles, and bombers. (New START, which mandated significant reductions in US and Russian arsenals, will expire in February 2021 unless renewed by the two countries.) Although Obama initiated the modernization of the nuclear triad, the Trump administration has sought funds to proceed with their full-scale production, at an estimated initial installment of $500 billion over 10 years.</p><p>Even during the initial modernization program of the Obama era, Russian and Chinese leaders were sufficiently alarmed to hasten their own nuclear acquisitions. Both countries were already in the process of modernizing their stockpiles—Russia to replace Cold War–era systems that had become unreliable, China to provide its relatively small arsenal with enhanced capabilities. Trump’s decision to acquire a whole new suite of ICBMs, nuclear-armed submarines, and bombers has added momentum to these efforts. And with all three major powers upgrading their arsenals, the other nuclear-weapon states—led by India, Pakistan, and North Korea—have been expanding their stockpiles as well. Moreover, with Trump’s recent decision to abandon the Intermediate-Range Nuclear Forces (INF) Treaty, all major powers are developing missile delivery systems for a regional <u><strong><mark>nuclear war</u></strong></mark> such as <u>might <mark>erupt in <strong>Europe</strong></mark>, <strong>South Asia</strong>, <mark>or the</u></mark> <u><strong>western <mark>Pacific</u></strong></mark>.</p> | 2NC | Uncooperative Federalism CP | Warming---Impact---2NC | 4,792 | 683 | 58,000 | ./documents/hspolicy20/MontgomeryBell/ClPi/Montgomery%20Bell-Climaco-Pierce-Neg-NDCA%2011-Round2.docx | 735,386 | N | NDCA 11 | 2 | OPRF BR | Chris Fry | 1AC - Interpol
1NC - T-In the US Infrastructure DA Uncooperative Federalism CP NATO CP Psychoanalysis K
2NR - Uncooperative Federalism CP | hspolicy20/MontgomeryBell/ClPi/Montgomery%20Bell-Climaco-Pierce-Neg-NDCA%2011-Round2.docx | null | 62,699 | ClPi | Montgomery Bell ClPi | null | Ch..... | Cl..... | Do..... | Pi..... | 21,723 | MontgomeryBell | Montgomery Bell | TN | null | 1,019 | hspolicy20 | HS Policy 2020-21 | 2,020 | cx | hs | 2 |
1,765,300 | Possibility of NATO membership emboldens nationalist militias and Russia to flout compromise and escalate the Ukrainian civil war—US moratorium solves. | Hahn 19 | Hahn 19—(Ph.D., is a Senior Researcher at the Center for Terrorism and Intelligence Studies (CETIS), Akribis Group, San Jose, California). Hahn, Gordon. 2019. “NATO Expansion’s Open Door Policy and War or Peace in the Donbass.” The Transnational. July 25, 2019. https://transnational.live/2019/07/25/nato-expansions-open-door-policy-and-war-or-peace-in-the-donbass/. | NATO expansion has contributed to the 2008 Georgian Russian Five-Day War and the ongoing Donbass civil war. The West’s 2008 promise that both Georgia and Ukraine will become NATO members encouraged Georgian nationalism . Similarly, NATO expansion encouraged ultranationalism in Ukraine and the ultra-nationalist-led 2014 Maidan revolt, leading to Ukraine’s civil war in eastern Ukraine’s Donbass regions . NATO expansion now is poised to re-start the Donbass civil war or spark a larger Ukrainian civil war western Ukraine is the only one of Ukraine’s regions that supports becoming a NATO member, a policy NATO also supports. On the other hand, western Ukraine is the only region that opposes the measures that could address the grievances that drive Donbass resistance to Kyiv. All the other mega-regions support compromises that might solve the civil war. western Ukraine are hold the rest of Ukraine hostage to its ultra-nationalist orientation supported in turn by the West’s policy of NATO expansion. only 36 percent of Ukrainian citizens “want Ukraine to be a NATO member-state by the year 2030” – the poll did not include very anti-NATO Crimea and Donbass. Only in Western Ukraine is there a majority supports NATO membership. former Ukrainian President Petro Poroshenko has submitted to the Ukraine’s parliament a proposal to become a NATO member. the issue of NATO expansion can only further polarize eastern and southern Ukraine from western Ukraine, sewing the seeds for another civil war, involving more regions. possibility that forces in Kyiv machinate a referendum could regenerate internecine conflict in Donbass and elsewhere in Ukraine. The key to war or peace Poroshenko’s move is an attempt to secure his base of support as he is running behind in the presidential race . it is the western and central mega-regions that cling to Ukraine becoming a NATO member even at the cost of continuing war in Donbass rejecting a compromise in the form of non-aligned status for Ukraine – i.e., non-membership of Ukraine in NATO. NATO’s continuing support for Ukrainian membership in the alliance provides political and even military cover for western Ukraine’s strong resistance to peace. If NATO expansion did not exist as a Western policy, western Ukraine would be forced to re-think their stance on NATO membership and opposition to compromise with the Donbass (and the rest of the east and the south). the United States continues to refuse an official moratorium on NATO expansion and persists in pursuing membership for Ukraine. Moreover, the West is putting very little pressure on Kyiv as the country has sank deeper and deeper into neo-fascist rule over the last four years . A short list of authoritarian measures in recent years include : murder of journalists, pogroms against Gypsy-Roma , the storming of courtrooms by neo-fascist groups , the storming of local government institutions , and unpunished war crimes committed by ultra-nationalist and neofascist volunteer battalions. As long as this bending over backwards to accommodate neo-fascists for the NATO expansion’s sake, we can expect growing polarization in Ukraine – now not just between the west and Donbass but between the south and east and Kyiv as well as where there are substantial ethnic Russian, Russophone populations. One can also expect more pushback from Moscow, perhaps rather nasty. Ukraine justifies the worst fears of the most inveterate anti-Western Russians, playing into their political hands the West is repeating the mistake it made with each successive round of NATO expansion, lending unwitting support to the worst elements in Russian politics. support by the West and from Russia is crucial in the ongoing Donbass conflict and the rise of tensions in the south and east. civil wars are often caused by foreign actors supporting combatant sides, and is only the firm intent to secure peace that convinces the civil war’s opposing sides to sit down at the negotiating table. in the 1960s’ North Yemeni civil war, the opposing Yemeni sides could not reach agreement through bilateral negotiations. Only when their foreign patrons, Egypt and Saudi came to an agreement was progress made in the inter-Yemeni talks. Trump and Putin must engage on these issues | NATO expansion encouraged the ultra-nationalist revolt, leading to Ukraine’s civil war . expansion is poised to re-start a larger war western Ukraine is the only region that supports becoming a member . All the other regions support compromises . western Ukraine hold the rest of Ukraine hostage to its ultra-nationalist orientation former President Poroshenko submitted a proposal to become a member. expansion can only further polarize Ukraine, sewing another civil war, involving more regions. a referendum could regenerate conflict . NATO’s continuing support for membership provides political cover for resistance to peace. If expansion did not exist western Ukraine would re-think opposition to compromise the U S continues to refuse an official moratorium on expansion and persists in pursuing Ukraine. Kyiv has sank deeper into neo-fascist rule . authoritarian measures include murder of journalists , storming of local government institutions and war crimes by ultra-nationalist volunteer battalions. bending over backwards to accommodate neo-fascists One can expect pushback from Moscow justifies the worst fears of anti-Western Russians, lending support to the worst elements in Russian politics. support by the West and Russia is crucial in the rise of tensions . civil wars are caused by foreign actors and only firm intent to secure peace convinces the opposing sides to sit down . Trump must engage on these issues | NATO expansion has contributed to the causal matrix of two wars: the 2008 Georgian-South Ossetiyan/Russian Five-Day War and the ongoing Donbass civil war. The West’s April 2008 promise that both Georgia and Ukraine will become NATO members encouraged Georgian nationalism and Saakashvili’s war in South Ossetiya and consequently led to Georgia’s de facto loss of its South Ossetiyan as well as Abkhaziyan territories. Similarly, NATO expansion encouraged the rise of ultranationalism in Ukraine, especially western Ukraine, and the ultra-nationalist-led February 2014 Maidan revolt, leading to Ukraine’s loss of Crimea and civil war in eastern Ukraine’s Donbass regions of Donetsk and Luhansk. NATO expansion now is poised to help re-start the Donbass civil war or spark a larger Ukrainian civil war (and/or similar conflicts involving Moldova and its breakaway republic of Transdnestr). Specifically, the NATO/western Ukraine nexus confounds resolution of the Donbass civil war. On the one hand, western Ukraine is the only one of Ukraine’s mega-regions that supports Ukraine becoming a NATO member, a policy NATO also supports. On the other hand, western Ukraine is the only mega-region in Ukraine that opposes all the measures that could address the grievances that drive Donbass resistance to Kyiv. All the other mega-regions have majorities that support some of the compromises that might resolve the civil war. In this way, western Ukraine, representatives of which dominate Ukraine’s Maidan government, are holding the rest of Ukraine hostage to its nationalist/ultra-nationalist orientation; an orientation that is supported in turn by the West’s policy of NATO expansion. Countrywide opinion on NATO membership A Western public opinion survey in October 2018 found that only 36 percent of Ukrainian citizens “want Ukraine to be a NATO member-state by the year 2030” – the poll did not include very anti-NATO Crimea and Donbass. Only in Western Ukraine is there a majority – 64 percent, supports NATO membership. This includes the ultra-nationalist hotbed of Lviv (Lvov), where 77 percent support it. In central Ukraine, 33 percent support it; this includes the capitol Kyiv, where only 38 percent support NATO membership. In southern Ukraine, only 21 percent support it. In eastern Ukraine only 17 percent. This includes the major industrial center of Kharkiv (Kharkov), where only 16 percent support it. Kherson Oblast was polled separately, and there only 28 percent support NATO membership. Therefore, the issue sharply divides western Ukraine from the rest of the country, where universally there are strong majorities against Ukraine becoming a member of the military bloc – as can be seen here. Despite the lack of public support for NATO membership countrywide, now former Ukrainian President Petro Poroshenko’s has submitted to the Ukraine’s parliament, the Verkhovna Rada, a proposal to add a new “constitutional norm” to Ukraine’s constitution stipulating Ukraine will become a NATO member. The Rada accepted the submission for consideration and sent a draft to the Constitutional Court for its review in September (www.pravda.com.ua/rus/news/2018/09/20/7192667/). Whether a gimmick for his presidential re-election campaign or not, the issue of NATO expansion so used can only further polarize eastern and southern Ukraine from western Ukraine, sewing the seeds for another civil war, involving more regions. The possibility that forces in Kyiv will machinate the holding of such a referendum cannot be rejected out of hand, and that could regenerate internecine conflict in Donbass and elsewhere in Ukraine. The key to war or peace Poroshenko’s move is in part an attempt to secure his base of support in western Ukraine as he is running behind in the presidential race, according to the polls. But this is the same western Ukraine that opposes any compromises with the Donbass insurgents; the leverage against a peace agreement is anchored in pro-NATO western Ukraine. The region holds the key to war or peace no less than the Kremlin. A January 2018 opinion survey carried out by Kyiv’s Democratic Initiative Foundation found that readiness to compromise decreases in Ukraine as one moves from east to west. Thus, 30.5% of the inhabitants of the South, 23% of the East, and 25.5% of the Donbass responded they are ready to support compromises for peace, but in western Ukraine only 8% expressed such readiness. Moreover, the survey demonstrated that only western Ukraine resists all of the possible solutions to the Donbass war. The adoption of a constitutional amendment granting special status or autonomy to Donbass (Donetsk and Luhansk regions) is opposed by 55 percent in the west and 59 percent in central Ukraine, while in Donbass only 41 percent oppose such a compromise and in eastern Ukraine and southern Ukraine only 32 percent and 29 percent oppose such a solution. A constitutional amendment that would give the Russian language the status of an official state language like the Ukrainian language is opposed by 68 percent in the west, 57 percent in the center, 48 percent in Donbass, but in the east only 29 percent oppose and 44 percent support such a compromise, and in the south only 20 percent oppose and 54 percent support such a compromise. On the issue of granting a full amnesty to all insurgents, in the west only 6 percent support full amnesty, where as in the south and east support reaches 28 percent and 29 precent in Donbass and the south. respectively. The proposal of holding elections in the Donbass under conditions proposed by the insurgents is supported only by 5 percent in the west, 9 percent in the center, 12 percent in Donbass, 19 percent in the south, and 23 percent in the east. Regarding the proposal to allow local police, court, prosecutorial personnel in the Donbass to be appointed locally by the self-proclaimed insurgent authorities in Donetsk and Luhansk, only 10 percent in the west agree, 12.5 percent in the center, 23 percent in the Donbass, 24 percent in the east, and 33 percent in the south. On granting the rebel territories special political and economic ties to Russia, only 12 percent in the west support it (56 percent are against), in the center – 16 and 59 percent, respectively, in the east – 25 and 35 percent, in the south – 32 and 35 percent, and, not surprisingly in Donbass, more approve than disapprove – 38 and 32 percent, respectively. Finally, it is the western and, to a lesser degree, the central mega-regions that cling to Ukraine becoming a NATO member even at the cost of continuing war in Donbass rejecting a compromise in the form of the adoption of a law instituting neutral or non-aligned status for Ukraine – i.e., non-membership of Ukraine in NATO. In western Ukraine 56 percent oppose, and only 15 percent support such a compromise. In central Ukraine, the division is again less stark – 51 percent opposed to such a law, with 25 percent approving. In the rest of the country, except for Donbass (43 percent against 35 percent for), a majority support such a compromise: in the South, “for” 52 percent support and 16 percent are opposed; and in the east – 54 percent support and 24 percent oppose the adoption of such a law. See the source here. Thus, NATO’s continuing support for Ukrainian membership in the alliance provides political and even military cover for western Ukraine’s strong resistance to peace. If NATO expansion did not exist as a Western policy, those in western Ukraine would be forced to re-think their stance on NATO membership and opposition to compromise with the Donbass (and, incidentally, the rest of the east and the south). The West ignores warning signs Washington and Brussels are well aware of this dangerous split in Ukraine as they (hopefully) were when the issue sparked the original crisis in 2013 through the trojan horse of EU membership. Nevertheless, they persist in their NATO expansion policy. Most importantly, the United States continues to refuse ending or putting an official moratorium on the policy of NATO expansion and persists in pursuing NATO membership for Ukraine. This was again made clear when US envoy for the Minsk peace process Kurt Volker stated that Washington cannot dictate such matters to sovereign states. Moreover, the West is putting very little pressure on Kyiv, as the country has sank deeper and deeper into neo-fascist rule over the last four years, as I warned already in 2014. A short list of authoritarian measures in recent years includes: – a ban on the use of communist and fascist symbols, only enforced against fascist symbols, since key parties and organizations that back the current regime use them; – the closing of numerous television programs and stations that do not tow the government’s ultranationalist line (most recent case here). – the establishment of the leaders of the World War II Organization of Ukrainian Nationalists (OUN) and Ukrainian Partisan Army (UPA) – which allied with Nazi German invaders and assisted or led in some cases efforts to slaughter Jews, Poles, and Russians – as heroes of the Ukrainian nation; – the adoption of laws limiting the use of the Russian language in media and publishing; – adoption of a new Law on Education that discriminates against minority language use, especially Russian language use, in schools protested by the Romanian, Hungarian, and Russian governments and the EU Vienna commission; – the adoption of an even more draconian “Law on Languages” mandating full Ukrainization of language use in Ukraine outside of interpersonal communication and religious services – see source here and here. – the adoption by the Lviv (Lvov) Oblast (regional) government of a law banning the use of the Russian language in media, publishing, literature, and music; – and the adoption of a law-making the OUN and UPA salute the official salute of Maidan Ukraine’s military and police. Moreover, a draft law has been submitted to the Rada that would ban the Russian Orthodox Church, with the fate of believers and their freedom of association and speech rights remaining unclear. It is not just the growing ethnic, even apartheid state aspect of the Maidan regime that is worrisome. Even in the ‘civic sector’ Maidan’s ‘free and fair elections’ are not entirely free and fair, with vote-buying rampant. And this is despite its functioning in conditions of the removal of almost all anti-regime and opposition elements from the polity by dint of the loss of Crimea and the civil war in Donbass – see source here. To all this can be added the murder of journalists, pogroms against Gypsy-Roma that have wounded and killed several, the storming of courtrooms by neo-fascist groups to intimidate judges and juries, the storming of local government institutions to intimidate public officials, and unpunished war crimes committed by ultra-nationalist and neofascist volunteer battalions. Even Western government-tied NGOs that helped in the rise of the Maidan revolt and continue to support it, despite definitive proof that the regime was born of a neo-fascist terrorist false flag operation that saw neo-fascist snipers shoot police, demonstrators and journalists that sparked the overthrow of president Viktor Yanukovych on 20 February 2014, are beginning to shyly ring the alarm bell, with both Freedom House and the Atlantic Council having done so, not to mention international human rights organizations. Yet putting aside their democratization principles, Western governments have proven willing to hold hostage even a present NATO member’s (Hungary’s) attempts to protect the minority language rights of its ethnic kin in Ukraine to the Ukrainian chauvinism of western Ukraine. The US State Department recently appealed to Budapest to not allow the new Ukrainian Law on Education get in the way of Ukrainian-NATO cooperation, after Budapest warned it will block any Ukrainian bid for NATO membership if the new Law on Education is not amended (See source here). How to prevent repeated mistakes As long as this bending over backwards to accommodate the Maidan regime’s dependence on ultra-nationalism and neo-fascists for the NATO expansion’s sake, we can expect growing polarization in Ukraine – now not just between the west and Donbass but between the south and east, on the one hand, and Kyiv, on the other hand, as well as within the south and east and even in Kyiv where there are substantial ethnic Russian, Russophone populations. One can therefore also expect more pushback from Moscow, perhaps some of it rather nasty. What is happening in Ukraine justifies the worst fears and claims of the most inveterate anti-Western Russians, playing into their political hands in power struggles on the streets and inside the Kremlin. In other words, the West is repeating the mistake it has already made several times with each successive round of NATO expansion, lending unwitting support to the worst elements in Russian politics. Moreover, the support of polarized sides by outside powers in the West and from Russia is crucial in the ongoing Donbass conflict and the rise of tensions in the south and east. Indeed, civil wars are quite often caused and prolonged by foreign actors supporting the internal combatant sides, and in such cases it is only the firm intent to secure the peace that convinces the civil war’s opposing sides to sit down in earnest at the negotiating table. For example, for South Yemeni president, Ali Nasser Mohammad, has spoken of how in the latter period of the 1960s’ North Yemeni civil war, the opposing Yemeni sides could not reach agreement through bilateral negotiations. Only when their main foreign patrons, Egyptian President Nasser and Saudi King Faisal, came to an agreement on ending the conflict was progress made in the inter-Yemeni talks. It would be prudent for the West to at least begin reigning in Ukraine’s ultranationalist inclinations and pushing it to negotiate directly with the Donbass insurgent governments. For Moscow’s part, it should do the same in relation to Donbass and refrain from exacerbating tensions elsewhere in the south and east of Ukraine. Trump and Putin must aggressively engage on these issues, especially as President Poroshenko and other presidential candidates are likely to be rushing to outbid each other in terms of their nationalist credentials for the duration of the presidential election campaign leading to further provocative steps. | 14,452 | <h4><u>Possibility</u> of NATO membership <u>emboldens</u> nationalist militias and Russia to <u>flout compromise</u> and <u>escalate</u> the <u>Ukrainian civil war</u>—US moratorium solves.</h4><p><u><strong>Hahn 19</u></strong>—(Ph.D., is a Senior Researcher at the Center for Terrorism and Intelligence Studies (CETIS), Akribis Group, San Jose, California). Hahn, Gordon. 2019. “NATO Expansion’s Open Door Policy and War or Peace in the Donbass.” The Transnational. July 25, 2019. https://transnational.live/2019/07/25/nato-expansions-open-door-policy-and-war-or-peace-in-the-donbass/.</p><p><u><strong>NATO expansion has contributed to</u></strong> the causal matrix of two wars: <u><strong>the 2008 Georgian</u></strong>-South Ossetiyan/<u><strong>Russian Five-Day War and the ongoing Donbass civil war. The West’s </u></strong>April <u><strong>2008 promise that both Georgia and Ukraine will become NATO members encouraged Georgian nationalism</u></strong> and Saakashvili’s war in South Ossetiya and consequently led to Georgia’s de facto loss of its South Ossetiyan as well as Abkhaziyan territories<u><strong>. Similarly, <mark>NATO expansion encouraged</u></strong></mark> the rise of <u><strong>ultranationalism</u></strong> <u><strong>in Ukraine</u></strong>, especially western Ukraine, <u><strong>and <mark>the ultra-nationalist</mark>-led</u></strong> February <u><strong>2014 Maidan <mark>revolt, leading to Ukraine’s</mark> </u></strong>loss of Crimea and<u><strong> <mark>civil war</mark> in eastern Ukraine’s Donbass regions </u></strong>of Donetsk and Luhansk<u><strong><mark>. </mark>NATO <mark>expansion </mark>now <mark>is poised to</u></strong></mark> help <u><strong><mark>re-start </mark>the Donbass civil war</u></strong> <u><strong>or spark <mark>a larger </mark>Ukrainian civil <mark>war</u></strong></mark> (and/or similar conflicts involving Moldova and its breakaway republic of Transdnestr). Specifically, the NATO/western Ukraine nexus confounds resolution of the Donbass civil war. On the one hand, <u><strong><mark>western Ukraine is the only</mark> one of Ukraine’s</u></strong> mega-<u><strong><mark>region</mark>s <mark>that supports</u></strong></mark> Ukraine <u><strong><mark>becoming a </mark>NATO <mark>member</mark>, a policy NATO also supports<mark>.</mark> On the other hand, western Ukraine is the only</u></strong> mega-<u><strong>region</u></strong> in Ukraine <u><strong>that opposes</u></strong> all <u><strong>the measures that could address the grievances that drive Donbass resistance to Kyiv.</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>All the other</mark> mega-<mark>regions</u></strong></mark> have majorities that <u><strong><mark>support</mark> </u></strong>some of the<u><strong> <mark>compromises </mark>that might </u></strong>re<u><strong>solve the civil war<mark>.</mark> </u></strong>In this way, <u><strong><mark>western Ukraine</u></strong></mark>, representatives of which dominate Ukraine’s Maidan government, <u><strong>are <mark>hold</u></strong></mark>ing <u><strong><mark>the rest of Ukraine hostage</u></strong> <u><strong>to its</u></strong></mark> nationalist/<u><strong><mark>ultra-nationalist orientation</u></strong></mark>; an orientation that is <u><strong>supported in turn by the West’s policy of NATO expansion.</u></strong> Countrywide opinion on NATO membership A Western public opinion survey in October 2018 found that <u><strong>only 36 percent of Ukrainian citizens “want Ukraine to be a NATO member-state by the year 2030” – the poll did not include very anti-NATO Crimea and Donbass. Only in Western Ukraine is there a majority</u></strong> – 64 percent, <u><strong>supports NATO membership.</u></strong> This includes the ultra-nationalist hotbed of Lviv (Lvov), where 77 percent support it. In central Ukraine, 33 percent support it; this includes the capitol Kyiv, where only 38 percent support NATO membership. In southern Ukraine, only 21 percent support it. In eastern Ukraine only 17 percent. This includes the major industrial center of Kharkiv (Kharkov), where only 16 percent support it. Kherson Oblast was polled separately, and there only 28 percent support NATO membership. Therefore, the issue sharply divides western Ukraine from the rest of the country, where universally there are strong majorities against Ukraine becoming a member of the military bloc – as can be seen here. Despite the lack of public support for NATO membership countrywide, now <u><strong><mark>former </mark>Ukrainian <mark>President</mark> Petro <mark>Poroshenko</u></strong></mark>’s <u><strong>has <mark>submitted</mark> to the Ukraine’s parliament</u></strong>, the Verkhovna Rada, <u><strong><mark>a proposal to</u></strong></mark> add a new “constitutional norm” to Ukraine’s constitution stipulating Ukraine will <u><strong><mark>become a </mark>NATO <mark>member.</u></strong></mark> The Rada accepted the submission for consideration and sent a draft to the Constitutional Court for its review in September (www.pravda.com.ua/rus/news/2018/09/20/7192667/). Whether a gimmick for his presidential re-election campaign or not, <u><strong>the issue of NATO <mark>expansion</u></strong></mark> so used <u><strong><mark>can only further polarize</mark> eastern and southern Ukraine from western <mark>Ukraine, sewing</mark> the seeds for <mark>another civil war, involving more regions.</mark> </u></strong>The <u><strong>possibility that forces in Kyiv</u></strong> will <u><strong>machinate</u></strong> the holding of such <u><strong><mark>a referendum</mark> </u></strong>cannot be rejected out of hand, and that <u><strong><mark>could regenerate</mark> internecine <mark>conflict</mark> in Donbass and elsewhere in Ukraine<mark>.</mark> The key to war or peace Poroshenko’s move is</u></strong> in part <u><strong>an attempt to secure his base of support</u></strong> in western Ukraine <u><strong>as he is running behind in the presidential race</u></strong>, according to the polls<u><strong>. </u></strong>But this is the same western Ukraine that opposes any compromises with the Donbass insurgents; the leverage against a peace agreement is anchored in pro-NATO western Ukraine. The region holds the key to war or peace no less than the Kremlin. A January 2018 opinion survey carried out by Kyiv’s Democratic Initiative Foundation found that readiness to compromise decreases in Ukraine as one moves from east to west. Thus, 30.5% of the inhabitants of the South, 23% of the East, and 25.5% of the Donbass responded they are ready to support compromises for peace, but in western Ukraine only 8% expressed such readiness. Moreover, the survey demonstrated that only western Ukraine resists all of the possible solutions to the Donbass war. The adoption of a constitutional amendment granting special status or autonomy to Donbass (Donetsk and Luhansk regions) is opposed by 55 percent in the west and 59 percent in central Ukraine, while in Donbass only 41 percent oppose such a compromise and in eastern Ukraine and southern Ukraine only 32 percent and 29 percent oppose such a solution. A constitutional amendment that would give the Russian language the status of an official state language like the Ukrainian language is opposed by 68 percent in the west, 57 percent in the center, 48 percent in Donbass, but in the east only 29 percent oppose and 44 percent support such a compromise, and in the south only 20 percent oppose and 54 percent support such a compromise. On the issue of granting a full amnesty to all insurgents, in the west only 6 percent support full amnesty, where as in the south and east support reaches 28 percent and 29 precent in Donbass and the south. respectively. The proposal of holding elections in the Donbass under conditions proposed by the insurgents is supported only by 5 percent in the west, 9 percent in the center, 12 percent in Donbass, 19 percent in the south, and 23 percent in the east. Regarding the proposal to allow local police, court, prosecutorial personnel in the Donbass to be appointed locally by the self-proclaimed insurgent authorities in Donetsk and Luhansk, only 10 percent in the west agree, 12.5 percent in the center, 23 percent in the Donbass, 24 percent in the east, and 33 percent in the south. On granting the rebel territories special political and economic ties to Russia, only 12 percent in the west support it (56 percent are against), in the center – 16 and 59 percent, respectively, in the east – 25 and 35 percent, in the south – 32 and 35 percent, and, not surprisingly in Donbass, more approve than disapprove – 38 and 32 percent, respectively. Finally, <u><strong>it is the western</u></strong> <u><strong>and</u></strong>, to a lesser degree, the <u><strong>central mega-regions that cling to Ukraine becoming a NATO member even at the cost of continuing war in Donbass rejecting a compromise in the form of</u></strong> the adoption of a law instituting neutral or <u><strong>non-aligned status for Ukraine – i.e., non-membership of Ukraine in NATO. </u></strong>In western Ukraine 56 percent oppose, and only 15 percent support such a compromise. In central Ukraine, the division is again less stark – 51 percent opposed to such a law, with 25 percent approving. In the rest of the country, except for Donbass (43 percent against 35 percent for), a majority support such a compromise: in the South, “for” 52 percent support and 16 percent are opposed; and in the east – 54 percent support and 24 percent oppose the adoption of such a law. See the source here. Thus, <u><strong><mark>NATO’s continuing support for </mark>Ukrainian <mark>membership</mark> in the alliance <mark>provides political</mark> and even military <mark>cover for </mark>western Ukraine’s strong <mark>resistance to peace. If </mark>NATO <mark>expansion did not exist</mark> as a Western policy,</u></strong> those in <u><strong><mark>western Ukraine would</mark> be forced to <mark>re-think </mark>their stance on NATO membership and <mark>opposition to compromise </mark>with the Donbass (and</u></strong>, incidentally,<u><strong> the rest of the east and the south). </u></strong>The West ignores warning signs Washington and Brussels are well aware of this dangerous split in Ukraine as they (hopefully) were when the issue sparked the original crisis in 2013 through the trojan horse of EU membership. Nevertheless, they persist in their NATO expansion policy. Most importantly, <u><strong><mark>the</mark> <mark>U</mark>nited <mark>S</mark>tates <mark>continues to refuse</u></strong></mark> ending or putting <u><strong><mark>an official moratorium on</u></strong></mark> the policy of <u><strong>NATO <mark>expansion and persists in pursuing</mark> </u></strong>NATO<u><strong> membership for <mark>Ukraine.</u></strong></mark> This was again made clear when US envoy for the Minsk peace process Kurt Volker stated that Washington cannot dictate such matters to sovereign states. <u><strong>Moreover, the West is putting very little pressure on <mark>Kyiv</u></strong></mark>, <u><strong>as the country <mark>has sank </mark>deeper and <mark>deeper into neo-fascist rule</mark> over the last four years</u></strong>, as I warned already in 2014<u><strong><mark>.</mark> A short list of <mark>authoritarian measures</mark> in recent years <mark>include</u></strong></mark>s<u><strong>: </u></strong>– a ban on the use of communist and fascist symbols, only enforced against fascist symbols, since key parties and organizations that back the current regime use them; – the closing of numerous television programs and stations that do not tow the government’s ultranationalist line (most recent case here). – the establishment of the leaders of the World War II Organization of Ukrainian Nationalists (OUN) and Ukrainian Partisan Army (UPA) – which allied with Nazi German invaders and assisted or led in some cases efforts to slaughter Jews, Poles, and Russians – as heroes of the Ukrainian nation; – the adoption of laws limiting the use of the Russian language in media and publishing; – adoption of a new Law on Education that discriminates against minority language use, especially Russian language use, in schools protested by the Romanian, Hungarian, and Russian governments and the EU Vienna commission; – the adoption of an even more draconian “Law on Languages” mandating full Ukrainization of language use in Ukraine outside of interpersonal communication and religious services – see source here and here. – the adoption by the Lviv (Lvov) Oblast (regional) government of a law banning the use of the Russian language in media, publishing, literature, and music; – and the adoption of a law-making the OUN and UPA salute the official salute of Maidan Ukraine’s military and police. Moreover, a draft law has been submitted to the Rada that would ban the Russian Orthodox Church, with the fate of believers and their freedom of association and speech rights remaining unclear. It is not just the growing ethnic, even apartheid state aspect of the Maidan regime that is worrisome. Even in the ‘civic sector’ Maidan’s ‘free and fair elections’ are not entirely free and fair, with vote-buying rampant. And this is despite its functioning in conditions of the removal of almost all anti-regime and opposition elements from the polity by dint of the loss of Crimea and the civil war in Donbass – see source here. To all this can be added the <u><strong><mark>murder of journalists</mark>, pogroms against Gypsy-Roma</u></strong> that have wounded and killed several<u><strong><mark>,</mark> the storming of courtrooms by neo-fascist groups </u></strong>to intimidate judges and juries<u><strong>, the <mark>storming of local government institutions</mark> </u></strong>to intimidate public officials<u><strong>, <mark>and</mark> unpunished <mark>war crimes</mark> committed <mark>by ultra-nationalist </mark>and neofascist <mark>volunteer battalions.</mark> </u></strong>Even Western government-tied NGOs that helped in the rise of the Maidan revolt and continue to support it, despite definitive proof that the regime was born of a neo-fascist terrorist false flag operation that saw neo-fascist snipers shoot police, demonstrators and journalists that sparked the overthrow of president Viktor Yanukovych on 20 February 2014, are beginning to shyly ring the alarm bell, with both Freedom House and the Atlantic Council having done so, not to mention international human rights organizations. Yet putting aside their democratization principles, Western governments have proven willing to hold hostage even a present NATO member’s (Hungary’s) attempts to protect the minority language rights of its ethnic kin in Ukraine to the Ukrainian chauvinism of western Ukraine. The US State Department recently appealed to Budapest to not allow the new Ukrainian Law on Education get in the way of Ukrainian-NATO cooperation, after Budapest warned it will block any Ukrainian bid for NATO membership if the new Law on Education is not amended (See source here). How to prevent repeated mistakes <u><strong>As long as this <mark>bending over backwards to accommodate</u></strong></mark> the Maidan regime’s dependence on ultra-nationalism and <u><strong><mark>neo-fascists</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>for the NATO expansion’s sake, we can expect growing polarization in Ukraine – now not just between the west and Donbass but between the south and east</u></strong>, on the one hand,<u><strong> and Kyiv</u></strong>, on the other hand,<u><strong> as well as </u></strong>within the south and east and even in Kyiv<u><strong> where there are substantial ethnic Russian, Russophone populations. <mark>One can</u></strong></mark> therefore <u><strong>also <mark>expect</mark> more <mark>pushback from Moscow</mark>, perhaps</u></strong> some of it <u><strong>rather nasty.</u></strong> What is happening in <u><strong>Ukraine</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>justifies the worst fears</mark> </u></strong>and claims<u><strong> <mark>of</mark> the most inveterate <mark>anti-Western Russians,</mark> playing into their political hands</u></strong> in power struggles on the streets and inside the Kremlin. In other words, <u><strong>the West is repeating the mistake it </u></strong>has already <u><strong>made</u></strong> several times <u><strong>with each successive round of NATO expansion, <mark>lending </mark>unwitting <mark>support to the worst elements in Russian politics.</mark> </u></strong>Moreover, the <u><strong><mark>support</u></strong></mark> of polarized sides <u><strong><mark>by</u></strong></mark> outside powers in <u><strong><mark>the West and </mark>from <mark>Russia</u></strong> <u><strong>is crucial in </mark>the ongoing Donbass conflict and <mark>the rise of tensions </mark>in the south and east<mark>.</u></strong></mark> Indeed, <u><strong><mark>civil wars are</u></strong></mark> quite <u><strong>often <mark>caused</u></strong></mark> and prolonged <u><strong><mark>by foreign actors </mark>supporting</u></strong> the internal <u><strong>combatant sides, <mark>and</u></strong></mark> in such cases it <u><strong>is <mark>only</mark> the <mark>firm intent to secure</u></strong></mark> the <u><strong><mark>peace</mark> that <mark>convinces the</mark> civil war’s <mark>opposing sides to sit down</mark> </u></strong>in earnest<u><strong> at the negotiating table<mark>.</mark> </u></strong>For example, for South Yemeni president, Ali Nasser Mohammad, has spoken of how <u><strong>in the</u></strong> latter period of the <u><strong>1960s’ North Yemeni civil war, the opposing Yemeni sides could not reach agreement through bilateral negotiations. Only when their </u></strong>main<u><strong> foreign patrons,</u></strong> <u><strong>Egypt</u></strong>ian President Nasser <u><strong>and</u></strong> <u><strong>Saudi</u></strong> King Faisal, <u><strong>came to an agreement</u></strong> on ending the conflict <u><strong>was progress made in the inter-Yemeni talks. </u></strong>It would be prudent for the West to at least begin reigning in Ukraine’s ultranationalist inclinations and pushing it to negotiate directly with the Donbass insurgent governments. For Moscow’s part, it should do the same in relation to Donbass and refrain from exacerbating tensions elsewhere in the south and east of Ukraine. <u><strong><mark>Trump</mark> and Putin <mark>must</u></strong></mark> aggressively <u><strong><mark>engage on these issues</u></strong></mark>, especially as President Poroshenko and other presidential candidates are likely to be rushing to outbid each other in terms of their nationalist credentials for the duration of the presidential election campaign leading to further provocative steps.</p> | 1AC | null | Ukraine: 1AC | 789,568 | 152 | 51,997 | ./documents/ndtceda20/Minnesota/PhRa/Minnesota-PhoenixFlood-Rao-Aff-Liberty-Round2.docx | 620,565 | A | Liberty | 2 | LIberty WW | Ian Lowery | 1AC-Expansion
1NC-T Reduce CP Adv CP Congress DA Rider DA Assurance DA China
2NR-T | ndtceda20/Minnesota/PhRa/Minnesota-PhoenixFlood-Rao-Aff-Liberty-Round2.docx | null | 52,403 | PhRa | Minnesota PhRa | null | Ow..... | Ph..... | Br..... | Ra..... | 19,336 | Minnesota | Minnesota | null | null | 1,010 | ndtceda20 | NDT/CEDA 2020-21 | 2,020 | cx | college | 2 |
1,931,580 | Extinction outweighs and should guide policy making – quality of life will improve and you’re cognitively biased against it. | Schubert et al. 19 xtinction, 10/21/2019, Scientific Reports, https://doi.org/10.1038/s41598-019-50145-9)//ddv | Schubert et al. 19 (Stefan, researcher at the Social Behaviour and Ethics Lab at University of Oxford, PhD in Philosophy from the London School of Economics; The Psychology of Existential Risk: Moral Judgments about Human Extinction, 10/21/2019, Scientific Reports, https://doi.org/10.1038/s41598-019-50145-9)//ddv | In the 21st century, technological advances will likely yield great benefits to humanity, but experts warn that they will also lead to growing risks of human extinction nuclear weapons, synthetic biology and a i no catastrophe is the best outcome, and extinction the worst outcome the badness of human extinction is greatly dependent on how long the future would otherwise be, and what the quality of future people’s lives would be Bostrom notes, predictions about the long-term future have often been left to theology and fiction, whilst being neglected by science if humanity does not go extinct, then the future could be both extraordinarily long and extraordinarily good, involving much greater quality of life than the current world Bostrom argues that a conservative estimate of humanity’s future potential is “at least 1016 human lives of normal duration”, considerably better than the average contemporary human life ” less conservative estimates would yield even greater numbers, and a drastically improved quality of life it is of paramount moral importance to make sure that we realize our future potential, and prevent human extinction. the fact that people use the availability heuristic—they focus on risks which have salient historical examples—leads to a neglect of new types of risks and risks of major catastrophes people fail to act because of psychological distance
people when presented with a scenario involving a near-extinction catastrophe and an extinction catastrophe as possible outcomes, they do not see human extinction as uniquely bad compared with non-extinction this is partly because people feel strongly for the victims of the catastrophes, and therefore focus on the immediate consequences of the catastrophes. The immediate consequences are not that different so this naturally leads them to find near-extinction almost as bad as extinction when asked in the most straightforward and unqualified way, participants do not find human extinction uniquely bad Our studies suggest that it could be that if people reflected more carefully, they might to a greater extent agree that extinction is uniquely bad deliberative thought-processes lead to finding extinction uniquely bad, whereas intuitive thought-processes lead to the opposite conclusion If it is right that human extinction is uniquely bad, then we should arguably invest much more in making sure it does not happen. We should also change policy in many other ways we should be prepared to make substantial sacrifices in order to make sure that humanity realizes its future potential. | technological advances lead to growing risks of extinction1 human extinction is dependent on how long and the quality of future lives predictions have been neglected by science if not extinct could be both long and good greater quality of life than the current world humanity’s potential is 1016 human lives of duration availability heuristic leads to neglect of new risks people fail to act because of psychological distance
thought-processes lead to finding extinction uniquely bad whereas intuitive thought the opposite we should invest more in policy prepared to make sacrifices | *intro of paper
Introduction The ever-increasing powers of technology can be used for good and ill. In the 21st century, technological advances will likely yield great benefits to humanity, but experts warn that they will also lead to growing risks of human extinction1,2,3,4. The risks stem both from existing technologies such as nuclear weapons, as well as emerging technologies such as synthetic biology and artificial intelligence5. A small but growing number of research institutes, such as the University of Oxford’s Future of Humanity Institute and the University of Cambridge’s Centre for the Study of Existential Risk, are studying these risks and how to mitigate them. Yet besides them, relatively small resources are explicitly devoted to reducing these risks. Here, we study the general public’s views of the badness of human extinction. We hypothesize that most people judge human extinction to be bad. But how bad do they find it? And why do they find it bad? Besides being highly policy-relevant, these questions are central for humanity’s understanding of itself and its place in nature. Human extinction is a pervasive theme in myths and religious writings6,7,8,9,10. One view is that human extinction is bad primarily because it would harm many concrete individuals: it would mean the death of all currently living people. On this view, human extinction is a very bad event, but it is not much worse than catastrophes that kill nearly all currently living people—since the difference in terms of numbers of deaths would be relatively small. Another view is that the human extinction is bad primarily because it would mean that the human species would go extinct and that humanity’s future would be lost forever. On this view, human extinction is uniquely bad: much worse even than catastrophes killing nearly everyone, since we could recover from them and re-build civilization. Whether extinction is uniquely bad or not depends on which of these considerations is the stronger: the immediate harm, or the long-term consequences. Here is one way to pit these considerations against each other. Consider three outcomes: no catastrophe, a catastrophe killing 80% (near-extinction), and a catastrophe killing 100% (extinction). According to both considerations, no catastrophe is the best outcome, and extinction the worst outcome. But they come apart regarding the relative differences between the three outcomes. If the immediate harm is the more important consideration, then the first difference, between no catastrophe and near-extinction, is greater than the second difference, between near-extinction and extinction. That is because the first difference is greater in terms of numbers of harmed individuals. On the other hand, if the long-term consequences are more important, then the second difference is greater. The first difference compares two non-extinction outcomes, whereas the second difference compares a non-extinction outcome with an extinction outcome—and only the extinction outcome means that the future would be forever lost. This thought-experiment was conceived by the well-known philosopher Derek Parfit11 (we have adapted the three outcomes slightly; see the Methods section). Parfit argued that most people would find the first difference to be greater, but he himself thought that the second difference is greater. Many other philosophers and other academics working to reduce the risk of human extinction agree with Parfit12,13,14,15. On their view, the badness of human extinction is greatly dependent on how long the future would otherwise be, and what the quality of future people’s lives would be. As the philosopher Nick Bostrom notes, predictions about the long-term future have often been left to theology and fiction, whilst being neglected by science16. However, in recent years, researchers have tried to assess what the long-term future may be like. They argue that if humanity does not go extinct, then the future could be both extraordinarily long and extraordinarily good, involving much greater quality of life than the current world. For instance, Nick Bostrom argues that a conservative estimate of humanity’s future potential is “at least 1016 human lives of normal duration”, which could “be considerably better than the average contemporary human life, which is so often marred by disease, poverty [and] injustice”17. He goes on to argue that less conservative estimates would yield even greater numbers, and a drastically improved quality of life. The argument is that if humanity develops to a sufficiently high technological level, then it will either cause its own extinction via misuse of powerful technologies, or use those technological powers to greatly improve the level of well-being. Furthermore, they argue, based on the view that new happy people coming into existence is morally valuable11, that it is of paramount moral importance to make sure that we realize our future potential, and prevent human extinction. While philosophers have discussed the ethics of human extinction for some time, the general public’s views on this matter has not received much study. There are some studies on perceptions of risk of extinction, however. Two studies found that a slight majority do not think that humanity will go extinct, and that most of those who thought that it would go extinct thought that would happen at least 500 years into the future18,19. There is also a related literature on catastrophic risk in general, focusing primarily on non-extinction catastrophes. For instance, it has been argued that the fact that people use the availability heuristic—they focus on risks which have salient historical examples—leads to a neglect of new types of risks and risks of major catastrophes (which are rare, and therefore less psychologically available)20. Similarly, it has been argued that the fact that risk mitigation is a public good leads to under-investment, since it means that it is not possible to exclude free riders from benefiting from it21. On specific risks, there is a literature on the psychology of climate change showing that people fail to act to mitigate climate change because they engage in temporal discounting22,23 and motivated reasoning about its severity24, and because of psychological distance25 (e.g., temporal and social distance). However, to date there have been no studies on how laypeople reason about the moral aspect of human extinction: how bad it would be. Is the extinction of our own species something people care about? Do they recognize it as being fundamentally different in quality from other catastrophes? And if so, why?
*discussion section of paper
Discussion Our studies show that people find that human extinction is bad, and that it is important to prevent it. However, when presented with a scenario involving no catastrophe, a near-extinction catastrophe and an extinction catastrophe as possible outcomes, they do not see human extinction as uniquely bad compared with non-extinction. We find that this is partly because people feel strongly for the victims of the catastrophes, and therefore focus on the immediate consequences of the catastrophes. The immediate consequences of near-extinction are not that different from those of extinction, so this naturally leads them to find near-extinction almost as bad as extinction. Another reason is that they neglect the long-term consequences of the outcomes. Lastly, their empirical beliefs about the quality of the future make a difference: telling them that the future will be extraordinarily good makes more people find extinction uniquely bad. Thus, when asked in the most straightforward and unqualified way, participants do not find human extinction uniquely bad. This could partly explain why we currently invest relatively small resources in reducing existential risk. However, these responses should not necessarily be seen as reflecting people’s well-considered views on the badness of human extinction. Rather, it seems that they partly reflect the fact that people often fail to consider the long-term consequences of extinction. Our studies suggest that it could be that if people reflected more carefully, they might to a greater extent agree that extinction is uniquely bad. A suggestive finding with regards to this is that higher scores on the cognitive reflection test predicted a greater tendency to find extinction uniquely bad. This could mean that deliberative thought-processes lead to finding extinction uniquely bad, whereas intuitive thought-processes lead to the opposite conclusion. More research is needed on the role of deliberation and intuition, as well as many other questions, such as the role of cognitive ability, and the ultimate evolutionary causes of why humans struggle to think clearly about their own extinction. Finally, let us consider possible policy implications. If it is right that human extinction is uniquely bad, then we should arguably invest much more in making sure it does not happen. We should also change policy in many other ways; e.g., shift technology policy in a more cautious direction29. On this view, we should, if necessary, be prepared to make substantial sacrifices in order to make sure that humanity realizes its future potential. Hence much hinges on the complex question whether we deem our own extinction to be uniquely bad. | 9,376 | <h4><u>Extinction outweighs</u> and should guide policy making – quality of life will improve and you’re <u>cognitively biased</u> against it.</h4><p><strong>Schubert et al. 19</strong> (Stefan, researcher at the Social Behaviour and Ethics Lab at University of Oxford, PhD in Philosophy from the London School of Economics; The Psychology of Existential Risk: Moral Judgments about Human E<strong>xtinction, 10/21/2019, Scientific Reports, https://doi.org/10.1038/s41598-019-50145-9)//ddv</p><p>*intro of paper</p><p></strong>Introduction The ever-increasing powers of technology can be used for good and ill. <u>In the 21st century, <mark>technological advances</mark> will likely yield great benefits to humanity, but experts warn that they will also <mark>lead to <strong>growing risks of</mark> human <mark>extinction</u></strong>1</mark>,2,3,4. The risks stem both from existing technologies such as <u>nuclear weapons, </u>as well as emerging technologies such as <u>synthetic biology and a</u>rtificial <u>i</u>ntelligence5. A small but growing number of research institutes, such as the University of Oxford’s Future of Humanity Institute and the University of Cambridge’s Centre for the Study of Existential Risk, are studying these risks and how to mitigate them. Yet besides them, relatively small resources are explicitly devoted to reducing these risks. Here, we study the general public’s views of the badness of human extinction. We hypothesize that most people judge human extinction to be bad. But how bad do they find it? And why do they find it bad? Besides being highly policy-relevant, these questions are central for humanity’s understanding of itself and its place in nature. Human extinction is a pervasive theme in myths and religious writings6,7,8,9,10. One view is that human extinction is bad primarily because it would harm many concrete individuals: it would mean the death of all currently living people. On this view, human extinction is a very bad event, but it is not much worse than catastrophes that kill nearly all currently living people—since the difference in terms of numbers of deaths would be relatively small. Another view is that the human extinction is bad primarily because it would mean that the human species would go extinct and that humanity’s future would be lost forever. On this view, human extinction is uniquely bad: much worse even than catastrophes killing nearly everyone, since we could recover from them and re-build civilization. Whether extinction is uniquely bad or not depends on which of these considerations is the stronger: the immediate harm, or the long-term consequences. Here is one way to pit these considerations against each other. Consider three outcomes: no catastrophe, a catastrophe killing 80% (near-extinction), and a catastrophe killing 100% (extinction). According to both considerations, <u>no catastrophe is the best outcome, and extinction the worst outcome</u>. But they come apart regarding the relative differences between the three outcomes. If the immediate harm is the more important consideration, then the first difference, between no catastrophe and near-extinction, is greater than the second difference, between near-extinction and extinction. That is because the first difference is greater in terms of numbers of harmed individuals. On the other hand, if the long-term consequences are more important, then the second difference is greater. The first difference compares two non-extinction outcomes, whereas the second difference compares a non-extinction outcome with an extinction outcome—and only the extinction outcome means that the future would be forever lost. This thought-experiment was conceived by the well-known philosopher Derek Parfit11 (we have adapted the three outcomes slightly; see the Methods section). Parfit argued that most people would find the first difference to be greater, but he himself thought that the second difference is greater. Many other philosophers and other academics working to reduce the risk of human extinction agree with Parfit12,13,14,15. On their view, <u>the badness of <mark>human extinction is</mark> greatly <mark>dependent on how long</mark> the future would otherwise be, <mark>and</mark> what <mark>the quality of future </mark>people’s <mark>lives</mark> would be</u>. As the philosopher Nick <u>Bostrom notes, <mark>predictions</mark> about the long-term future <mark>have</mark> often <mark>been</mark> left to theology and fiction, whilst being <strong><mark>neglected by science</u></strong></mark>16. However, in recent years, researchers have tried to assess what the long-term future may be like. They argue that <u><mark>if</mark> humanity does <mark>not</mark> go <mark>extinct</mark>, then the future <mark>could be both</mark> <strong>extraordinarily <mark>long</strong> and</mark> <strong>extraordinarily <mark>good</strong></mark>, involving much <mark>greater <strong>quality of life </strong>than the current world</u></mark>. For instance, Nick <u>Bostrom argues that a conservative estimate of <mark>humanity’s</mark> future <mark>potential is</mark> “at least <mark>1016 human lives of</mark> normal <mark>duration</mark>”,</u> which could “be <u>considerably better than the average contemporary human life</u>, which is so often marred by disease, poverty [and] injustice<u>”</u>17. He goes on to argue that <u>less conservative estimates would yield even greater numbers, and a <strong>drastically improved quality of life</u></strong>. The argument is that if humanity develops to a sufficiently high technological level, then it will either cause its own extinction via misuse of powerful technologies, or use those technological powers to greatly improve the level of well-being. Furthermore, they argue, based on the view that new happy people coming into existence is morally valuable11, that <u>it is of paramount moral importance to make sure that we realize our future potential, and prevent human extinction. </u>While philosophers have discussed the ethics of human extinction for some time, the general public’s views on this matter has not received much study. There are some studies on perceptions of risk of extinction, however. Two studies found that a slight majority do not think that humanity will go extinct, and that most of those who thought that it would go extinct thought that would happen at least 500 years into the future18,19. There is also a related literature on catastrophic risk in general, focusing primarily on non-extinction catastrophes. For instance, it has been argued that <u>the fact that people use the <mark>availability heuristic</mark>—they focus on risks which have salient historical examples—<mark>leads to</mark> a <strong><mark>neglect of new</mark> types of <mark>risks</strong></mark> and risks of major catastrophes</u> (which are rare, and therefore less psychologically available)20. Similarly, it has been argued that the fact that risk mitigation is a public good leads to under-investment, since it means that it is not possible to exclude free riders from benefiting from it21. On specific risks, there is a literature on the psychology of climate change showing that <u><mark>people fail to act</u></mark> to mitigate climate change because they engage in temporal discounting22,23 and motivated reasoning about its severity24, and <u><mark>because of psychological distance</u><strong></mark>25 (e.g., temporal and social distance). However, to date there have been no studies on how laypeople reason about the moral aspect of human extinction: how bad it would be. Is the extinction of our own species something people care about? Do they recognize it as being fundamentally different in quality from other catastrophes? And if so, why?</p><p>*discussion section of paper</p><p></strong>Discussion Our studies show that <u>people</u> find that human extinction is bad, and that it is important to prevent it. However, <u>when presented with a scenario involving </u>no catastrophe, <u>a near-extinction catastrophe and an extinction catastrophe as possible outcomes, they do not see human extinction as uniquely bad compared with non-extinction</u>. We find that <u>this is partly because people feel strongly for the victims of the catastrophes, and therefore focus on the immediate consequences of the catastrophes. The immediate consequences </u>of near-extinction <u>are not that different</u> from those of extinction, <u>so this naturally leads them to find near-extinction almost as bad as extinction</u>. Another reason is that they neglect the long-term consequences of the outcomes. Lastly, their empirical beliefs about the quality of the future make a difference: telling them that the future will be extraordinarily good makes more people find extinction uniquely bad. Thus, <u>when asked in the most <strong>straightforward</strong> and <strong>unqualified</strong> way, participants do not find human extinction uniquely bad</u>. This could partly explain why we currently invest relatively small resources in reducing existential risk. However, these responses should not necessarily be seen as reflecting people’s well-considered views on the badness of human extinction. Rather, it seems that they partly reflect the fact that people often fail to consider the long-term consequences of extinction. <u>Our studies suggest that it could be that if people reflected more carefully, they might to a greater extent <strong>agree that extinction is uniquely bad</u></strong>. A suggestive finding with regards to this is that higher scores on the cognitive reflection test predicted a greater tendency to find extinction uniquely bad. This could mean that <u>deliberative <mark>thought-processes lead to finding extinction uniquely bad</mark>, <mark>whereas intuitive thought</mark>-processes lead to <mark>the opposite</mark> conclusion</u>. More research is needed on the role of deliberation and intuition, as well as many other questions, such as the role of cognitive ability, and the ultimate evolutionary causes of why humans struggle to think clearly about their own extinction. Finally, let us consider possible policy implications. <u>If it is right that human extinction is uniquely bad, then <mark>we should</mark> arguably <strong><mark>invest</mark> much <mark>more in </mark>making sure it does not happen</strong>. We should also change <mark>policy</mark> in many other ways</u>; e.g., shift technology policy in a more cautious direction29. On this view, <u>we should</u>, if necessary, <u>be <mark>prepared to make <strong></mark>substantial <mark>sacrifices</strong></mark> in order to make sure that humanity realizes its future potential.</u> Hence much hinges on the complex question whether we deem our own extinction to be uniquely bad.</p> | 2ac | Framing | solvency | 35,865 | 170 | 57,030 | ./documents/hspolicy20/Mamaroneck/BlOw/Mamaroneck-Blechman-Owen-Aff-Michigan-Round4.docx | 734,171 | A | Michigan | 4 | Cambridge MR | Ashton Smith | 1ac - interop
1nc - security k t bidirectional t forensic science new affs bad
2nr - security k | hspolicy20/Mamaroneck/BlOw/Mamaroneck-Blechman-Owen-Aff-Michigan-Round4.docx | null | 62,632 | BlOw | Mamaroneck BlOw | null | Ja..... | Bl..... | Ja..... | Ow..... | 21,706 | Mamaroneck | Mamaroneck | NY | null | 1,019 | hspolicy20 | HS Policy 2020-21 | 2,020 | cx | hs | 2 |
2,177,164 | Automated anti-submarine warfare causes nuclear escalation and use it or lose it | Klare 19 and arms control. This installment provides an assessment of autonomous weapons systems development and prospects, the dangers they pose, and possible strategies for their control. "Autonomous Weapons Systems and the Laws of War." https://www.armscontrol.org/act/2019-03/features/autonomous-weapons-systems-laws-war] | Klare 19 [Michael T. Klare is a professor emeritus of peace and world security studies at Hampshire College and senior visiting fellow at the Arms Control Association. This is the second in the “Arms Control Tomorrow” series, in which he considers disruptive emerging technologies and their implications for war-fighting and arms control. This installment provides an assessment of autonomous weapons systems development and prospects, the dangers they pose, and possible strategies for their control. "Autonomous Weapons Systems and the Laws of War." https://www.armscontrol.org/act/2019-03/features/autonomous-weapons-systems-laws-war] | The Navy is not alone in exploring future battle formations involving various combinations of crewed systems and swarms of autonomous robotic weapons The Air Force is testing software to enable fighter pilots to guide accompanying unmanned aircraft toward enemy The Army is testing an unarmed robotic ground vehicle their development has generated considerable alarm among diplomats , arms control advocates fear that deploying fully autonomous weapons in battle would severely reduce human oversight resulting in violations of the laws of war, and could weaken barriers that restrain escalation from conventional to nuclear war would the Army’s proposed RCV be able to distinguish between enemy combatants and civilian bystander Might a wolfpack of sub hunters, hot on the trail of an enemy submarine carrying nuclear-armed ballistic missiles, provoke the captain of that vessel to launch its weapons to avoid losing them to a presumptive U.S pre-emptive strike? | The Navy is exploring swarms of autonomous robotic weapons deploying fully autonomous weapons would reduce human oversight and weaken barriers that restrain escalation from nuclear war Might a wolfpack of sub hunters provoke the captain to launch its weapons to avoid losing them to a pre-emptive strike? | The Navy is not alone in exploring future battle formations involving various combinations of crewed systems and swarms of autonomous and semiautonomous robotic weapons. The Air Force is testing software to enable fighter pilots to guide accompanying unmanned aircraft toward enemy positions, whereupon the drones will seek and destroy air defense radars and other key targets on their own. The Army is testing an unarmed robotic ground vehicle, the Squad Multipurpose Equipment Transport (SMET) and has undertaken development of a Robotic Combat Vehicle (RCV). These systems, once fielded, would accompany ground troops and crewed vehicles in combat, trying to reduce U.S. soldiers’ exposure to enemy fire. Similar endeavors are under way in China, Russia, and a score of other countries.1 For advocates of such scenarios, the development and deployment of autonomous weapons systems, or “killer robots,” as they are often called, offer undeniable advantages in combat. Comparatively cheap and able to operate 24 hours a day without tiring, the robotic warriors could help reduce U.S. casualties. When equipped with advanced sensors and artificial intelligence (AI), moreover, autonomous weapons could be trained to operate in coordinated swarms, or “wolfpacks,” overwhelming enemy defenders and affording a speedy U.S. victory. “Imagine anti-submarine warfare wolfpacks,” said former Deputy Secretary of Defense Robert Work at the christening of Sea Hunter. “Imagine mine warfare flotillas, distributed surface-warfare action groups, deception vessels, electronic warfare vessels”—all unmanned and operating autonomously. Although the rapid deployment of such systems appears highly desirable to Work and other proponents of robotic systems, their development has generated considerable alarm among diplomats, human rights campaigners, arms control advocates, and others who fear that deploying fully autonomous weapons in battle would severely reduce human oversight of combat operations, possibly resulting in violations of the laws of war, and could weaken barriers that restrain escalation from conventional to nuclear war. For example, would the Army’s proposed RCV be able to distinguish between enemy combatants and civilian bystanders in a crowded urban battle space, as required by international law? Might a wolfpack of sub hunters, hot on the trail of an enemy submarine carrying nuclear-armed ballistic missiles, provoke the captain of that vessel to launch its weapons to avoid losing them to a presumptive U.S. pre-emptive strike? | 2,546 | <h4>Automated <u>anti-submarine</u> warfare causes <u>nuclear escalation</u> and <u>use it or lose it</u> </h4><p><strong>Klare 19</strong> [Michael T. Klare is a professor emeritus of peace and world security studies at Hampshire College and senior visiting fellow at the Arms Control Association. This is the second in the “Arms Control Tomorrow” series, in which he considers disruptive emerging technologies and their implications for war-fighting<u><strong> and arms control. This installment provides an assessment of autonomous weapons systems development and prospects, the dangers they pose, and possible strategies for their control. "Autonomous Weapons Systems and the Laws of War." https://www.armscontrol.org/act/2019-03/features/autonomous-weapons-systems-laws-war]</p><p></strong><mark>The Navy is</mark> not alone in <mark>exploring</mark> future battle</u> <u>formations involving various combinations of crewed systems and <mark>swarms of <strong>autonomous</u></strong></mark> and semiautonomous <u><strong><mark>robotic weapons</u></strong></mark>. <u>The Air Force is testing software to enable fighter pilots to guide accompanying <strong>unmanned aircraft</strong> toward enemy</u> positions, whereupon the drones will seek and destroy air defense radars and other key targets on their own. <u>The Army is testing an unarmed robotic ground vehicle</u>, the Squad Multipurpose Equipment Transport (SMET) and has undertaken development of a Robotic Combat Vehicle (RCV). These systems, once fielded, would accompany ground troops and crewed vehicles in combat, trying to reduce U.S. soldiers’ exposure to enemy fire. Similar endeavors are under way in China, Russia, and a score of other countries.1 For advocates of such scenarios, the development and deployment of autonomous weapons systems, or “killer robots,” as they are often called, offer undeniable advantages in combat. Comparatively cheap and able to operate 24 hours a day without tiring, the robotic warriors could help reduce U.S. casualties. When equipped with advanced sensors and artificial intelligence (AI), moreover, autonomous weapons could be trained to operate in coordinated swarms, or “wolfpacks,” overwhelming enemy defenders and affording a speedy U.S. victory. “Imagine anti-submarine warfare wolfpacks,” said former Deputy Secretary of Defense Robert Work at the christening of Sea Hunter. “Imagine mine warfare flotillas, distributed surface-warfare action groups, deception vessels, electronic warfare vessels”—all unmanned and operating autonomously. Although the rapid deployment of such systems appears highly desirable to Work and other proponents of robotic systems, <u>their development has generated considerable alarm among diplomats</u>, human rights campaigners<u>, arms control advocates</u>, and others who <u>fear that <mark>deploying</mark> <mark>fully autonomous weapons</mark> in battle <mark>would</mark> severely <mark>reduce human <strong>oversight</u></strong></mark> of combat operations, possibly <u>resulting in violations of the laws of war, <mark>and</mark> could <mark>weaken barriers that <strong>restrain escalation</strong> from</mark> conventional</u> <u>to</u> <u><strong><mark>nuclear war</u></strong></mark>. For example, <u>would the Army’s proposed <strong>RCV</strong> be</u> <u>able to distinguish between enemy combatants and civilian bystander</u>s in a crowded urban battle space, as required by international law? <u><mark>Might a <strong>wolfpack of sub hunters</strong></mark>, hot on the trail of an enemy submarine carrying nuclear-armed ballistic missiles, <mark>provoke the captain</mark> of that vessel <mark>to <strong>launch its weapons</strong> to avoid</u> <u>losing them to a</mark> presumptive</u> <u>U.S</u>. <u><strong><mark>pre-emptive strike?</p></u></strong></mark> | null | null | 1AC | 18,161 | 268 | 66,534 | ./documents/hsld20/Harker/Zh/Harker-Zhang-Aff-Golden%20Desert-Round4.docx | 860,405 | A | Golden Desert | 4 | Peninsula AB | Asher Towner | 1AC - nuclear c3
1NC - T-ban disarm DA heg DA
1AR - all
1NR - all | hsld20/Harker/Zh/Harker-Zhang-Aff-Golden%20Desert-Round4.docx | null | 73,095 | ViZh | Harker ViZh | null | Vi..... | Zh..... | null | null | 24,534 | Harker | Harker | CA | null | 1,028 | hsld20 | HS LD 2020-21 | 2,020 | ld | hs | 1 |
1,212,431 | And Sino-India conflict! | Klare 20 | Klare 20 — Five College professor emeritus of peace and world security studies, and director of the Five College Program in Peace and World Security Studies (PAWSS), holds a B.A. and M.A. from Columbia University and a Ph.D. from the Graduate School of the Union Institute. (Michael; Published: 2020; "Climate Change, Water Scarcity, and the Potential for Interstate Conflict in South Asia"; Journal of Strategic Security 13, No. 4, Pages 109-122; https://doi.org/10.5038/1944-0472.13.4.1826 Available at: https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/jss/vol13/iss4/8)//CYang | potential for interstate conflict nuclear conflict — over water arises in the case of another major river The Brahmaputra originates in China and traverses much of India For Chinese Brahmaputra is an important engine of hydroelectric power For Indians, it is a valuable source of irrigation water, especially in agriculture-dependent regions Leaders of both countries are fully aware of their counterparts’ concerns over the river
Brahmaputra a matter of deep concern To this day, discord remains a continuing source of friction in Sino-Indian and a potential spark for violent conflict
Brahmaputra draws much of its flow from melting of Himalayan glaciers—and these could eventually disappear. For China and India melting of the glaciers will have momentous consequences. Given Brahmaputra’s critical importance in both countries, any decline would be highly disruptive, causing widespread hardship and social unrest
Under these more stressful conditions Chinese leadership, desperate to provide supply to China’s water-starved northeast inclined to proceed with water diversion effort certain to trigger a harsh Indian response become a major element in pushing China and India towards an adversarial relationship
once fighting breaks out, it is impossible to predict succeeding chain of events, and any outcome is conceivable Both are armed with nuclear weapons, and Washington views India as a strategic counterweight to China defeat of India would be viewed as a potential threat to American interests and precipitate U.S. military intervention | potential for nuclear conflict — over water arises in the case of a major river Brahmaputra
a matter of concern discord remains a source of friction and a spark for conflict
Brahmaputra could disappear momentous consequences. Given critical importance decline would be disruptive, causing widespread unrest
Under these conditions Chinese leadership inclined to water diversion effort trigger a Indian response push China and India towards adversarial relationship
Both armed with nuc s, and Washington views India as a counterweight precipitate U.S. intervention | China, India, and the Brahmaputra River
The potential for interstate conflict—even nuclear conflict — over shared water supplies arises in the case of another major river at risk from climate change: The Brahmaputra, which originates in China and traverses much of northeastern India before merging with the Ganges in Bangladesh and emptying into the Bay of Bengal. The fifth-largest river in the world by volume of water flow, the Brahmaputra starts on the northern slopes of the Himalayas and flows easterly across the southern Tibetan plateau (where it is known as the Yarlung Tsangpo) before making a nearly 180-degree turn and crossing into the Indian state of Arunachal Pradesh; from there, it flows in a southwesterly direction towards its confluence with the Ganges and thence its exit into the Bay of Bengal. For the Chinese, the Brahmaputra is an important engine of hydroelectric power; they have already installed one dam on the river, at Zangmu, and have announced plans for at least three more. For the Indians, it is a valuable source of irrigation water, especially in agriculture-dependent regions of the northeast. Leaders of both countries are fully aware of their counterparts’ interests and concerns over the river but have made little effort to reach a mutual understanding—let alone any formal agreements—regarding its future development.31
Several factors make the future status of the Brahmaputra a matter of deep concern to security analysts. To begin with, the river enters India through the state of Arunachal Pradesh, an area of northeastern India abutting Tibet that is claimed by both countries. Beijing insists that this region was once part of the kingdom of Tibet, and so belongs to China; New Delhi claims it is a legitimate part of India under a 1914 treaty between Tibet and Great Britain. The two sides fought a war here in 1962, with India suffering significant battlefield setbacks but China agreeing to restore the status quo ante. The countries have not been able to resolve the ownership dispute in subsequent years, despite intermittent negotiations, and both continue to maintain substantial military forces in the region. To this day, discord over Arunachal Pradesh remains a continuing source of friction in Sino-Indian relations and a potential spark for violent conflict.32
Another potential source of friction between China and India arises from Chinese plans (or rumors of such plans) to divert water from the upper Brahmaputra and funnel it via a series of tunnels and canals to northeastern China, where existing supplies are hugely inadequate.33 While dismissed by many Chinese experts as overly ambitious and costly, the notion of diverting water from the Brahmaputra has generated considerable anxiety in India, where experts fear that the resulting decline in water flow into the Indian section of the river would threaten agricultural productivity. Given the centrality of farming in the Indian economy and political system, any Chinese move to proceed with such a diversion project could lead to increased tension between the two countries. 34
Few analysts believe that a Sino-Indian conflict over the Brahmaputra is likely in the years immediately ahead. Both countries have strong motives for maintaining friendly—if not necessarily, warm—relations between them, and water issues have not yet dominated the bilateral agenda. This, however, is where global warming enters the picture. The Brahmaputra, like the Indus, draws much of its flow during dry seasons from the melting of Himalayan glaciers—and these, as has already been noted, are melting as a result of climate change, and could eventually disappear. For both China and India, the melting of the Himalayan glaciers will have momentous consequences. Given the Brahmaputra’s critical importance to agriculture and economic activity in both countries, any significant long-term decline in its flow would be highly disruptive, causing widespread hardship and social unrest.35
Under these more stressful conditions, the Chinese leadership, desperate to provide additional supply to China’s water-starved northeast, might be more inclined to proceed with water diversion projects on the Brahmaputra and other shared river systems.36 Coming at a time of equivalent water scarcity in India, such an effort is almost certain to trigger a harsh Indian response. “The most salient climate-related point of conflict [between China and India] could be China’s move to divert the upstream waters of rivers originating in the Himalayan watershed,” the NIC warned in a special report on climate change and India. “If China was determined to move forward with such a scheme, it could become a major element in pushing China and India towards an adversarial rather than simply a competitive relationship. Border clashes related to control of the rivers are not out of the question.”37
Any conflict between China and India over the waters of the Brahmaputra, should one occur, is most likely to remain a localized affair, without provoking a full-scale mobilization of forces on both sides. During the 1962 war over Arunachal Pradesh, Chinese army troops engaged their Indian counterparts in disputed areas along the border, but neither side escalated to large-scale combat. However, once fighting breaks out, it is impossible to predict the succeeding chain of events, and any outcome is conceivable. A minor skirmish along the Indo-Chinese border might not be a cause for alarm in the United States, but a larger war between those two countries undoubtedly would be. Both are armed with nuclear weapons, and Washington views India as a strategic counterweight to China.38 A crushing defeat of India would be viewed as a potential threat to American national interests and might conceivably precipitate U.S. military intervention. Where that might lead is anyone’s guess, but the mere possibility of such combat has made this scenario a matter of deep concern for security analysts in Washington.39 | 6,001 | <h4>And Sino-India conflict!</h4><p><strong>Klare 20 </strong>— Five College professor emeritus of peace and world security studies, and director of the Five College Program in Peace and World Security Studies (PAWSS), holds a B.A. and M.A. from Columbia University and a Ph.D. from the Graduate School of the Union Institute. (Michael; Published: 2020; "Climate Change, Water Scarcity, and the Potential for Interstate Conflict in South Asia"; Journal of Strategic Security 13, No. 4, Pages 109-122; https://doi.org/10.5038/1944-0472.13.4.1826 Available at: https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/jss/vol13/iss4/8)//CYang</p><p>China, India, and the Brahmaputra River</p><p>The <u><mark>potential for</mark> interstate conflict</u>—even <u><mark>nuclear conflict — over</u></mark> shared <u><mark>water</u></mark> supplies <u><mark>arises in the case of a</mark>nother <strong><mark>major river</u></strong></mark> at risk from climate change: <u>The <mark>Brahmaputra</u></mark>, which <u>originates in China and traverses much of</u> northeastern <u>India</u> before merging with the Ganges in Bangladesh and emptying into the Bay of Bengal. The fifth-largest river in the world by volume of water flow, the Brahmaputra starts on the northern slopes of the Himalayas and flows easterly across the southern Tibetan plateau (where it is known as the Yarlung Tsangpo) before making a nearly 180-degree turn and crossing into the Indian state of Arunachal Pradesh; from there, it flows in a southwesterly direction towards its confluence with the Ganges and thence its exit into the Bay of Bengal. <u>For</u> the <u>Chinese</u>, the <u>Brahmaputra is an <strong>important engine</strong> of hydroelectric power</u>; they have already installed one dam on the river, at Zangmu, and have announced plans for at least three more. <u>For</u> the <u>Indians, it is a <strong>valuable source</strong> of irrigation water, especially in agriculture-dependent regions</u> of the northeast. <u>Leaders of both countries are <strong>fully aware</strong> of their counterparts’</u> interests and <u>concerns over the river</u> but have made little effort to reach a mutual understanding—let alone any formal agreements—regarding its future development.31</p><p>Several factors make the future status of the <u>Brahmaputra <mark>a matter of</mark> <strong>deep <mark>concern</strong></mark> </u>to security analysts. To begin with, the river enters India through the state of Arunachal Pradesh, an area of northeastern India abutting Tibet that is claimed by both countries. Beijing insists that this region was once part of the kingdom of Tibet, and so belongs to China; New Delhi claims it is a legitimate part of India under a 1914 treaty between Tibet and Great Britain. The two sides fought a war here in 1962, with India suffering significant battlefield setbacks but China agreeing to restore the status quo ante. The countries have not been able to resolve the ownership dispute in subsequent years, despite intermittent negotiations, and both continue to maintain substantial military forces in the region. <u>To this day, <mark>discord</u></mark> over Arunachal Pradesh <u><mark>remains a</mark> <strong>continuing <mark>source</strong> of friction</mark> in Sino-Indian</u> relations <u><mark>and a</mark> <strong>potential <mark>spark</strong> for</mark> violent <mark>conflict</u></mark>.32</p><p>Another potential source of friction between China and India arises from Chinese plans (or rumors of such plans) to divert water from the upper Brahmaputra and funnel it via a series of tunnels and canals to northeastern China, where existing supplies are hugely inadequate.33 While dismissed by many Chinese experts as overly ambitious and costly, the notion of diverting water from the Brahmaputra has generated considerable anxiety in India, where experts fear that the resulting decline in water flow into the Indian section of the river would threaten agricultural productivity. Given the centrality of farming in the Indian economy and political system, any Chinese move to proceed with such a diversion project could lead to increased tension between the two countries. 34</p><p>Few analysts believe that a Sino-Indian conflict over the Brahmaputra is likely in the years immediately ahead. Both countries have strong motives for maintaining friendly—if not necessarily, warm—relations between them, and water issues have not yet dominated the bilateral agenda. This, however, is where global warming enters the picture. The <u><mark>Brahmaputra</u></mark>, like the Indus, <u>draws much of its flow</u> during dry seasons <u>from</u> the <u>melting of Himalayan glaciers—and these</u>, as has already been noted, are melting as a result of climate change, and <u><mark>could</mark> <strong>eventually <mark>disappear</strong></mark>. For</u> both <u>China and India</u>, the <u>melting of the </u>Himalayan <u>glaciers will have <strong><mark>momentous consequences</strong>. Given</u></mark> the <u>Brahmaputra’s <strong><mark>critical importance</u></strong></mark> to agriculture and economic activity <u>in both countries, any</u> significant long-term <u><mark>decline</u></mark> in its flow <u><mark>would be</mark> <strong>highly <mark>disruptive</strong>, causing widespread</mark> hardship and social <mark>unrest</u></mark>.35</p><p><u><mark>Under these</mark> <strong>more stressful <mark>conditions</u></strong></mark>, the <u><mark>Chinese leadership</mark>, desperate to provide</u> additional <u>supply to China’s water-starved northeast</u>, might be more <u><mark>inclined to</mark> proceed with <mark>water diversion</u></mark> projects on the Brahmaputra and other shared river systems.36 Coming at a time of equivalent water scarcity in India, such an <u><mark>effort</u></mark> is almost <u>certain to <mark>trigger a</mark> <strong>harsh <mark>Indian response</u></strong></mark>. “The most salient climate-related point of conflict [between China and India] could be China’s move to divert the upstream waters of rivers originating in the Himalayan watershed,” the NIC warned in a special report on climate change and India. “If China was determined to move forward with such a scheme, it could <u>become a <strong>major element</strong> in <mark>push</mark>ing <mark>China and India towards</mark> an <mark>adversarial</u></mark> rather than simply a competitive <u><mark>relationship</u></mark>. Border clashes related to control of the rivers are not out of the question.”37</p><p>Any conflict between China and India over the waters of the Brahmaputra, should one occur, is most likely to remain a localized affair, without provoking a full-scale mobilization of forces on both sides. During the 1962 war over Arunachal Pradesh, Chinese army troops engaged their Indian counterparts in disputed areas along the border, but neither side escalated to large-scale combat. However, <u>once fighting breaks out, it is impossible to predict</u> the <u><strong>succeeding chain</strong> of events, and any outcome is conceivable</u>. A minor skirmish along the Indo-Chinese border might not be a cause for alarm in the United States, but a larger war between those two countries undoubtedly would be. <u><mark>Both</mark> are <mark>armed with nuc</mark>lear weapon<mark>s, and Washington views India as a</mark> strategic <mark>counterweight</mark> to China</u>.38 A crushing <u>defeat of India would be viewed as a <strong>potential threat</strong> to American</u> national <u>interests and</u> might conceivably <u><mark>precipitate U.S.</mark> <strong>military <mark>intervention</u></strong></mark>. Where that might lead is anyone’s guess, but the mere possibility of such combat has made this scenario a matter of deep concern for security analysts in Washington.39</p> | null | 1AC — Water Markets V1 | 1AC — Modeling | 25,096 | 717 | 29,760 | ./documents/hspolicy21/Peninsula/WaKi/Peninsula-Wang-Kim-Aff-Damus-Round1.docx | 753,916 | A | Damus | 1 | Jesuit GL | Sarah Davidson | 1ac- Water Markets
1nc- T-protect Cap K
2nr- Cap K | hspolicy21/Peninsula/WaKi/Peninsula-Wang-Kim-Aff-Damus-Round1.docx | null | 64,308 | WaKi | Peninsula WaKi | null | So..... | Wa..... | Je..... | Ki..... | 22,099 | Peninsula | Peninsula | CA | null | 1,020 | hspolicy21 | HS Policy 2021-22 | 2,021 | cx | hs | 2 |
4,111,983 | Non-kinetic escalation is a myth. | Lonergan, 4-15 | Erica Lonergan, 4-15 (Erica Lonergan is Assistant Professor in the Army Cyber Institute at West Point and a Research Scholar at the Saltzman Institute of War and Peace Studies at Columbia University and previously served as Senior Director on the U.S. Cyberspace Solarium Commission, 4-15-2022, accessed on 6-8-2022, Foreign Affairs, “The Cyber-Escalation Fallacy”, https://www.foreignaffairs.com/articles/russian-federation/2022-04-15/cyber-escalation-fallacy, HBisevac) | cyberpower is much harder to use against targets of strategic significance or to achieve outcomes with decisive impacts In failing to recognize this U.S. approaching the use of cyberpower in a way that may be doing more harm than good in the process overlooking the considerable opportunities as well as risks they present current understanding about the role of cyber-operations in conflict is built on false assumptions about cyberspace the assumption that cyber-operations play a central role in either provoking or extending war is wrong Hundreds of cyber-incidents have occurred between rivals with long histories but none has ever triggered an escalation to war Nor Ko conducted major cyberattacks against So Ko on at least four different occasions reasonable to expect that these operations might escalate the situation on the Korean Peninsula Yet that is not what happened Despite decades of malicious behavior in cyberspace cyberattacks have always been contained below the level of armed conflict major adversarial powers across the world have routinely observed a mutually understood line that distinguishes strategic interactions | understanding about cyber built on false assumptions assumption that cyber provok or extend war is wrong -incidents occurred between rivals but none triggered escalation cyberattacks contained below armed conflict powers observed mutually understood line | In fact, the negligible role of cyberattacks in the Ukraine conflict should come as no surprise. Through war simulations, statistical analyses, and other kinds of studies, scholars have found little evidence that cyber-operations provide effective forms of coercion or that they cause escalation to actual military conflict. That is because for all its potential to disrupt companies, hospitals, and utility grids during peacetime, cyberpower is much harder to use against targets of strategic significance or to achieve outcomes with decisive impacts, either on the battlefield or during crises short of war. In failing to recognize this, U.S. officials and policymakers are approaching the use of cyberpower in a way that may be doing more harm than good—treating cyber-operations like any other weapon of war rather than as a nonlethal instrument of statecraft and, in the process, overlooking the considerable opportunities as well as risks they present. Much of the current understanding in Washington about the role of cyber-operations in conflict is built on long-standing but false assumptions about cyberspace. Many scholars have asserted that cyber-operations could easily lead to military escalation, up to and including the use of nuclear weapons. Jason Healey and Robert Jervis, for example, expressing a widely held view, have argued that an incident that takes place in cyberspace, “might cross the threshold into armed conflict either through a sense of impunity or through miscalculation or mistake.” Policymakers have also long believed that cyberspace poses grave perils. In 2012, Secretary of Defense Leon Panetta warned of an impending “cyber-Pearl Harbor,” in which adversaries could take down critical U.S. infrastructure through cyberattacks. Nearly a decade later, FBI Director Christopher Wray compared the threat from ransomware—when actors hold a target hostage by encrypting data and demanding a ransom payment in return for decrypting it—to the 9/11 attacks. And as recently as December 2021, Secretary of Defense Lloyd Austin noted that in cyberspace, “norms of behavior aren’t well-established and the risks of escalation and miscalculation are high.” Seemingly buttressing these claims has been a long record of cyber-operations by hostile governments. In recent years, states ranging from Russia and China to Iran and North Korea have used cyberspace to conduct large-scale espionage, inflict significant economic damage, and undermine democratic institutions. In January 2021, for example, attackers linked to the Chinese government were able to breach Microsoft’s Exchange email servers, giving them access to communications and other private information from companies and governments, and may have allowed other malicious actors to conduct ransomware attacks. That breach followed on the heels of a Russian intrusion against the software vendor SolarWinds, in which hackers were able to access a huge quantity of sensitive government and corporate data—an espionage treasure trove. Cyberattacks have also inflicted significant economic costs. The NotPetya attack affected critical infrastructure around the world—ranging from logistics and energy to finance and government—causing upward of $10 billion in damage. But the assumption that cyber-operations play a central role in either provoking or extending war is wrong. Hundreds of cyber-incidents have occurred between rivals with long histories of tension or even conflict, but none has ever triggered an escalation to war. North Korea, for example, has conducted major cyberattacks against South Korea on at least four different occasions, including the “Ten Days of Rain” denial of service attack—in which a network is flooded with an overwhelming number of requests, becoming temporarily inaccessible to users—against South Korean government websites, financial institutions, and critical infrastructure in 2011 and the “Dark Seoul” attack in 2013, which disrupted service across the country’s financial and media sectors. It would be reasonable to expect that these operations might escalate the situation on the Korean Peninsula, especially because North Korea’s war plans against South Korea reportedly involve cyber-operations. Yet that is not what happened. Instead, in each case, the South Korean response was minimal and limited to either direct, official attribution to North Korea by government officials or more indirect public suggestions that Pyongyang was likely behind the attacks. Similarly, although the United States reserves the right to respond to cyberattacks in any way it sees fit, including with military force, it has until now relied on economic sanctions, indictments, diplomatic actions, and some reported instances of tit-for-tat cyber-responses. For example, following Russia’s interference in the 2016 U.S. presidential election, the Obama administration expelled 35 Russian diplomats and shuttered two facilities said to be hubs for Russian espionage. The Treasury Department also levied economic sanctions against Russian officials. Yet according to media reports, the administration ultimately rejected plans to conduct retaliatory cyber-operations against Russia. And although the United States did use its own cyber-operations to respond to Russian attacks during the 2018 midterm elections, it limited itself to temporarily disrupting the Internet Research Agency, a Russian troll farm. These measured responses are not unusual. Despite decades of malicious behavior in cyberspace—and no matter the level of destruction—cyberattacks have always been contained below the level of armed conflict. Indeed, researchers have found that major adversarial powers across the world have routinely observed a “firebreak” between cyberattacks and conventional military operations: a mutually understood line that distinguishes strategic interactions above and below it, similar to the threshold that exists for the employment of nuclear weapons. | 5,965 | <h4>Non-kinetic escalation is a <u>myth</u>.</h4><p>Erica <strong>Lonergan, 4-15</strong> (Erica Lonergan is Assistant Professor in the Army Cyber Institute at West Point and a Research Scholar at the Saltzman Institute of War and Peace Studies at Columbia University and previously served as Senior Director on the U.S. Cyberspace Solarium Commission, 4-15-2022, accessed on 6-8-2022, Foreign Affairs, “The Cyber-Escalation Fallacy”, https://www.foreignaffairs.com/articles/russian-federation/2022-04-15/cyber-escalation-fallacy, HBisevac)</p><p>In fact, the negligible role of cyberattacks in the Ukraine conflict should come as no surprise. Through war simulations, statistical analyses, and other kinds of studies, scholars have found little evidence that cyber-operations provide effective forms of coercion or that they cause escalation to actual military conflict. That is because for all its potential to disrupt companies, hospitals, and utility grids during peacetime, <u>cyberpower is <strong>much harder</strong> to use against targets of <strong>strategic significance</strong> or to <strong>achieve outcomes</strong> with <strong>decisive impacts</u></strong>, either on the battlefield or during crises short of war. <u>In failing to recognize this</u>, <u>U.S.</u> officials and policymakers are <u>approaching the use of cyberpower in a way that may be doing <strong>more harm than good</u></strong>—treating cyber-operations like any other weapon of war rather than as a nonlethal instrument of statecraft and, <u>in the process</u>, <u>overlooking the <strong>considerable opportunities</strong> as well as <strong>risks</strong> they present</u>. Much of the <u>current <mark>understanding</u></mark> in Washington <u><mark>about</mark> the role of <mark>cyber</mark>-operations in conflict is <mark>built on</u></mark> long-standing but <u><strong><mark>false</mark> <mark>assumptions</strong></mark> about cyberspace</u>. Many scholars have asserted that cyber-operations could easily lead to military escalation, up to and including the use of nuclear weapons. Jason Healey and Robert Jervis, for example, expressing a widely held view, have argued that an incident that takes place in cyberspace, “might cross the threshold into armed conflict either through a sense of impunity or through miscalculation or mistake.” Policymakers have also long believed that cyberspace poses grave perils. In 2012, Secretary of Defense Leon Panetta warned of an impending “cyber-Pearl Harbor,” in which adversaries could take down critical U.S. infrastructure through cyberattacks. Nearly a decade later, FBI Director Christopher Wray compared the threat from ransomware—when actors hold a target hostage by encrypting data and demanding a ransom payment in return for decrypting it—to the 9/11 attacks. And as recently as December 2021, Secretary of Defense Lloyd Austin noted that in cyberspace, “norms of behavior aren’t well-established and the risks of escalation and miscalculation are high.” Seemingly buttressing these claims has been a long record of cyber-operations by hostile governments. In recent years, states ranging from Russia and China to Iran and North Korea have used cyberspace to conduct large-scale espionage, inflict significant economic damage, and undermine democratic institutions. In January 2021, for example, attackers linked to the Chinese government were able to breach Microsoft’s Exchange email servers, giving them access to communications and other private information from companies and governments, and may have allowed other malicious actors to conduct ransomware attacks. That breach followed on the heels of a Russian intrusion against the software vendor SolarWinds, in which hackers were able to access a huge quantity of sensitive government and corporate data—an espionage treasure trove. Cyberattacks have also inflicted significant economic costs. The NotPetya attack affected critical infrastructure around the world—ranging from logistics and energy to finance and government—causing upward of $10 billion in damage. But <u>the <strong><mark>assumption</strong></mark> <mark>that</mark> <mark>cyber</mark>-operations play a central role in either <strong><mark>provok</mark>ing</strong> <mark>or</mark> <strong><mark>extend</mark>ing <mark>war</strong></mark> <mark>is <strong>wrong</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong>Hundreds</strong> of cyber<mark>-incidents</mark> have <mark>occurred</mark> <mark>between</mark> <mark>rivals</mark> with <strong>long histories</u></strong> of tension or even conflict, <u><mark>but</mark> <strong><mark>none</mark> </strong>has<strong> ever</strong> <strong><mark>triggered</strong></mark> an <strong><mark>escalation</strong></mark> to war</u>. <u><strong>No</strong>r</u>th <u><strong>Ko</u></strong>rea, for example, has <u>conducted <strong>major</strong> cyberattacks against <strong>So</u></strong>uth <u><strong>Ko</u></strong>rea <u>on at least four different occasions</u>, including the “Ten Days of Rain” denial of service attack—in which a network is flooded with an overwhelming number of requests, becoming temporarily inaccessible to users—against South Korean government websites, financial institutions, and critical infrastructure in 2011 and the “Dark Seoul” attack in 2013, which disrupted service across the country’s financial and media sectors. It would be <u>reasonable to expect that these operations might <strong>escalate</strong> the situation on the <strong>Korean Peninsula</u></strong>, especially because North Korea’s war plans against South Korea reportedly involve cyber-operations. <u>Yet that is <strong>not what happened</u></strong>. Instead, in each case, the South Korean response was minimal and limited to either direct, official attribution to North Korea by government officials or more indirect public suggestions that Pyongyang was likely behind the attacks. Similarly, although the United States reserves the right to respond to cyberattacks in any way it sees fit, including with military force, it has until now relied on economic sanctions, indictments, diplomatic actions, and some reported instances of tit-for-tat cyber-responses. For example, following Russia’s interference in the 2016 U.S. presidential election, the Obama administration expelled 35 Russian diplomats and shuttered two facilities said to be hubs for Russian espionage. The Treasury Department also levied economic sanctions against Russian officials. Yet according to media reports, the administration ultimately rejected plans to conduct retaliatory cyber-operations against Russia. And although the United States did use its own cyber-operations to respond to Russian attacks during the 2018 midterm elections, it limited itself to temporarily disrupting the Internet Research Agency, a Russian troll farm. These measured responses are not unusual. <u>Despite decades of malicious behavior in cyberspace</u>—and no matter the level of destruction—<u><mark>cyberattacks</mark> have <strong>always</strong> <strong>been <mark>contained</strong> <strong>below</strong></mark> the level of <strong><mark>armed</mark> <mark>conflict</u></strong></mark>. Indeed, researchers have found that <u>major adversarial <mark>powers</mark> across the world have routinely <strong><mark>observed</u></strong></mark> a “firebreak” between cyberattacks and conventional military operations: <u>a <strong><mark>mutually</mark> <mark>understood line</strong></mark> that <strong>distinguishes strategic interactions</u></strong> above and below it, similar to the threshold that exists for the employment of nuclear weapons.</p> | null | null | Cyber | 10,762 | 334 | 140,963 | ./documents/hspolicy22/NewTrier/HeSu/NewTrier-HeSu-Neg-Mid-America-Cup-Round-5.docx | 929,556 | N | Mid America Cup | 5 | Rowland Hall SK | Sheaff | 1AC: Space Assets
1NC: Turkey Hedging, Turkey PIC, Cease Space CP
2NR: Cease Space CP | hspolicy22/NewTrier/HeSu/NewTrier-HeSu-Neg-Mid-America-Cup-Round-5.docx | 2022-09-25 19:19:56 | 81,443 | HeSu | New Trier HeSu | null | Na..... | He..... | Re..... | Su..... | 26,561 | NewTrier | New Trier | IL | null | 2,002 | hspolicy22 | HS Policy 2022-23 | 2,022 | cx | hs | 2 |
4,191,154 | EVEN WITHOUT Article V, Cyber triggers retal and false readings---nuclear war. | Klare ’19 | Klare ’19 [Michael; November 19; Professor Emeritus of Peace and World Security Studies at Hampshire College, Senior Visiting Fellow at the Arms Control Association; Arms Control Today, “Cyber Battles, Nuclear Outcomes? Dangerous New Pathways to Escalation” https://www.armscontrol.org/act/2019-11/features/cyber-battles-nuclear-outcomes-dangerous-new-pathways-escalation] | another pathway to escalation could arise from a cascading series of cyberstrikes against vital national infrastructure All major powers, along with Iran and North Korea deployed cyberweapons to destroy an adversary’s power grids
The danger is that economic attacks if during a period of tension could lead to an escalating series of tit-for-tat attacks against more vital elements of an adversary’s critical infrastructure, producing widespread chaos and leading one side to initiate kinetic attacks on critical military targets, risking the slippery slope to nuclear conflict a Russian cyberattack on the power grid could trigger U.S. attacks on Russian energy attacks lead to major conflict and nuclear war.”
Others include third parties, such as proxy states or terrorist organizations, to provoke a global nuclear crisis by causing early-warning systems to generate false readings of missile launches As states’ reliance on cyberspace grows the dangers of accidental escalation grow severe | escalation arise from cascading cyberstrikes against infrastructure All powers deployed weapons to destroy grids
attacks lead to escalating tit-for-tat against vital infrastructure leading to kinetic attacks risking nuc conflict Russian attack lead to nuc war.”
proxy states provoke a global crisis by causing false readings of missile s dangers of accident grow | Yet another pathway to escalation could arise from a cascading series of cyberstrikes and counterstrikes against vital national infrastructure rather than on military targets. All major powers, along with Iran and North Korea, have developed and deployed cyberweapons designed to disrupt and destroy major elements of an adversary’s key economic systems, such as power grids, financial systems, and transportation networks. As noted, Russia has infiltrated the U.S. electrical grid, and it is widely believed that the United States has done the same in Russia.12 The Pentagon has also devised a plan known as “Nitro Zeus,” intended to immobilize the entire Iranian economy and so force it to capitulate to U.S. demands or, if that approach failed, to pave the way for a crippling air and missile attack.13
The danger here is that economic attacks of this sort, if undertaken during a period of tension and crisis, could lead to an escalating series of tit-for-tat attacks against ever more vital elements of an adversary’s critical infrastructure, producing widespread chaos and harm and eventually leading one side to initiate kinetic attacks on critical military targets, risking the slippery slope to nuclear conflict. For example, a Russian cyberattack on the U.S. power grid could trigger U.S. attacks on Russian energy and financial systems, causing widespread disorder in both countries and generating an impulse for even more devastating attacks. At some point, such attacks “could lead to major conflict and possibly nuclear war.”14
These are by no means the only pathways to escalation resulting from the offensive use of cyberweapons. Others include efforts by third parties, such as proxy states or terrorist organizations, to provoke a global nuclear crisis by causing early-warning systems to generate false readings (“spoofing”) of missile launches. Yet, they do provide a clear indication of the severity of the threat. As states’ reliance on cyberspace grows and cyberweapons become more powerful, the dangers of unintended or accidental escalation can only grow more severe. | 2,092 | <h4>EVEN WITHOUT Article V, Cyber triggers retal and false readings---nuclear war. </h4><p><strong>Klare ’19 </strong>[Michael; November 19; Professor Emeritus of Peace and World Security Studies at Hampshire College, Senior Visiting Fellow at the Arms Control Association; Arms Control Today, “Cyber Battles, Nuclear Outcomes? Dangerous New Pathways to Escalation” https://www.armscontrol.org/act/2019-11/features/cyber-battles-nuclear-outcomes-dangerous-new-pathways-escalation]</p><p>Yet <u>another pathway to <strong><mark>escalation</strong></mark> could <mark>arise from</mark> a <strong><mark>cascading</mark> series</strong> of <strong><mark>cyberstrikes</u></strong></mark> and counterstrikes <u><mark>against</mark> vital <strong>national <mark>infrastructure</u></strong></mark> rather than on military targets. <u><mark>All</mark> <strong>major <mark>powers</strong></mark>, along with <strong>Iran</strong> and <strong>North Korea</u></strong>, have developed and <u><mark>deployed</mark> cyber<mark>weapons</u></mark> designed <u><mark>to</u></mark> disrupt and <u><mark>destroy</u></mark> major elements of <u>an adversary’s</u> key economic systems, such as <u>power <mark>grids</u></mark>, financial systems, and transportation networks. As noted, Russia has infiltrated the U.S. electrical grid, and it is widely believed that the United States has done the same in Russia.12 The Pentagon has also devised a plan known as “Nitro Zeus,” intended to immobilize the entire Iranian economy and so force it to capitulate to U.S. demands or, if that approach failed, to pave the way for a crippling air and missile attack.13</p><p><u>The danger</u> here <u>is that <strong>economic <mark>attacks</u></strong></mark> of this sort, <u>if</u> undertaken <u>during a period of tension</u> and crisis, <u>could <mark>lead to</mark> an <strong><mark>escalating</strong></mark> series of <strong><mark>tit-for-tat</mark> attacks</strong> <mark>against</u></mark> ever <u>more <mark>vital</mark> elements of an adversary’s <strong>critical <mark>infrastructure</strong></mark>, producing widespread chaos</u> and harm <u>and</u> eventually <u><mark>leading</mark> one side <mark>to</mark> initiate <strong><mark>kinetic attacks</strong></mark> on critical military targets, <mark>risking</mark> the <strong>slippery slope</strong> to <strong><mark>nuc</mark>lear <mark>conflict</u></strong></mark>. For example, <u>a <strong><mark>Russian</strong></mark> cyber<mark>attack</mark> on the</u> U.S. <u>power grid could trigger <strong>U.S. attacks</strong> on Russian <strong>energy</u></strong> and financial systems, causing widespread disorder in both countries and generating an impulse for even more devastating attacks. At some point, such <u>attacks</u> “could <u><mark>lead to</mark> major conflict and</u> possibly <u><strong><mark>nuc</mark>lear <mark>war</strong>.”</u></mark>14</p><p>These are by no means the only pathways to escalation resulting from the offensive use of cyberweapons. <u>Others include</u> efforts by <u>third parties, such as <strong><mark>proxy states</strong></mark> or <strong>terrorist</strong> organization<strong>s</strong>, to <mark>provoke a <strong>global</mark> nuclear <mark>crisis</strong> by causing</mark> <strong>early-warning</strong> systems to generate <strong><mark>false readings</u></strong></mark> (“spoofing”) <u><mark>of missile</mark> launche<mark>s</u></mark>. Yet, they do provide a clear indication of the severity of the threat. <u>As states’ reliance on <strong>cyberspace</strong> grows</u> and cyberweapons become more powerful, <u>the <mark>dangers of</u></mark> unintended or <u><strong><mark>accident</mark>al escalation</u></strong> can only <u><mark>grow</u></mark> more <u>severe</u>.</p> | 1AC | null | 1AC – Cyberattacks | 55 | 1,568 | 144,005 | ./documents/hspolicy22/LiberalArtsAndScienceAcademy/WiDo/LiberalArtsAndScienceAcademy-WiDo-Aff-Heart-of-Texas-Invitational-hosted-by-St-Marks-Round-3.docx | 937,498 | A | Heart of Texas Invitational hosted by St Marks | 3 | Niles North MK | Stephen Pipkin | 1AC – Russian Cyber v1.3.1
1NC – T SC, Security K, Canada CP, Midterms DA, Dip Cap DA
Block – T SC, Canada CP, Midterms DA
2NR – Canada CP | hspolicy22/LiberalArtsAndScienceAcademy/WiDo/LiberalArtsAndScienceAcademy-WiDo-Aff-Heart-of-Texas-Invitational-hosted-by-St-Marks-Round-3.docx | 2022-10-22 04:24:57 | 80,076 | WiDo | Liberal Arts And Science Academy WiDo | For docs, contact only:
[email protected]
For chains, put both:
[email protected]
[email protected]
Gideon Witchel (he/him) - 2A
Jack Dollinger (he/him) - 2N | Gi..... | Wi..... | Ja..... | Do..... | 26,584 | LiberalArtsAndScienceAcademy | Liberal Arts And Science Academy | TX | null | 2,002 | hspolicy22 | HS Policy 2022-23 | 2,022 | cx | hs | 2 |
4,748,330 | 1. Supply chains. Border delays create continent-wide costs—plan provides rapid growth. | GOPET TRANS 22 | GOPET TRANS 22 [GOPET TRANS; 11-1-22; leading provider of transport and logistics services in Bulgaria; “Accession to Schengen could make border queues history and support industry and country’s growth,” https://gopettrans.com/5737/accession-to-schengen-could-make-border-queues-history-and-support-industry-and-country-s-growth/] brett | Limitation of queues and days long jams at borders are two immediate effects if Bulgaria and Romania will enter Schengen
Without checks and delays at the borders, there will be unobstructed traffic corridors, increased frequency of deliveries and rapid growth with real benefits for freight transport and supply chains
Ascension into Schengen has a number of benefits for freight transportation and supply chains The most visible and immediate one – eliminating borders queues and huge waiting times carriers waited up to 72h at the Bulgarian – Romanian border which are the main traffic gateways towards Europe let’s not forget additional delays are piled up at the Romanian – Hungarian borders
by removing borders checks, a trip from Bulgaria to Germany will gain at least 24h without counting any major delays at borders
delays costs create cascading penalties costs incurred by the shippers because goods in transit need to reach production lines which cannot stop and may delay other processes Or they cannot reach the consumers at the right time
it also takes a toll on the drivers, whom have a difficult job as it is. Let’s not forget we are dealing with sectorial drivers’ shortage signalling tough working conditions, do not appeal to younger generations and cannot attract them towards this career
Another benefit will be the actual increase of flows, both imports and exports, and this will accelerate the development both locally and regionally having suppliers closer to selling markets is becoming a more appropriate strategy Bulgaria can become a regional hub supplying businesses across the Continent removing borders will become an additional growth vector, increasing local competitiveness
we may see a reconsolidation of the capacity on the markets, as carriers in the Region could move freely, in the same way it happens for instance between Germany and Benelux countries In Europe, the shortage of drivers increased by over 40% from 2020 to 2021, according to an IRU study. While elimination of borders will not increase suddenly number of drivers, we can for sure have a more fluid use of the existing ones by removing idle time spent in queues
A very significant economic impact of border checks removal will be felt on short distance trips, so for example on trips between Bulgaria and Romania or Bulgaria and Greece, where waiting times at border represent now a significant part of the journey increase in frequency with positive effects on the local economies
Due to the lack of borders and the reduction of transport time, the amount of carbon emissions will also be considerably reduced, thus protecting the environment | immediate effects
Without borders there will be rapid growth with real benefits for supply chains
the main traffic gateways towards Europe
delays create cascading penalties
we are dealing with drivers’ shortage
flows will accelerate development regionally supplying businesses across the Continent
we may see reconsolidation as carriers move freely | Limitation of queues and days long jams at borders are two immediate effects if Bulgaria and Romania will enter Schengen. Few weeks ago the European Parliament gave a positive vote on it, with 85% pro inclusion. This is a consultative body, the real decision is to be made by the European Council in December. In terms of technical conditions, most local and international authorities and bodies say that they’ve been met for quite a while.
“We hope for a positive decision. Without checks and delays at the borders, there will be unobstructed traffic corridors, increased frequency of deliveries and rapid growth with real benefits for freight transport and supply chains. We predict a 30% increase in vehicle trips per week for short distances between Bulgaria, Greece and Romania, and for Central Europe we predict about 15%”, says Raya Rendakova, Commercial Director of GOPET TRANS, leading provider of transport and logistics services in Bulgaria with strong local presence and active activity in Greece, Romania, Poland, Spain and Turkey.
Croatia is also consider to integrate Schengen space together with Bulgaria and Romania, but its impact on actual freight movements for us is limited (geographically, does not sit on our main transportation corridors).
Ascension into Schengen has a number of benefits for freight transportation and supply chains in general. The most visible and immediate one – eliminating borders queues and huge waiting times. Let’s only remember the situation from earlier this year when carriers waited up to 72h at the Bulgarian – Romanian border (at both crossing points from Vidin – Calafat and Ruse – Giurgiu), which are the main traffic gateways towards Europe. And let’s not forget additional delays are piled up at the Romanian – Hungarian borders.
We do estimate that, by removing borders checks, a trip from Bulgaria to Germany will gain at least 24h. And this without counting any major delays at borders.
Such delays don’t have a negative impacts only on costs. And we are not discussing here only direct costs, associated with the delays, and which usually create a cascading of penalties. We are counting costs incurred by the shippers because goods in transit need to reach production lines which cannot stop and may delay other processes. Or they cannot reach the consumers at the right time.
Furthermore, we need to also consider additional fuel costs and also an increase of CO2 emissions in those areas, given the accumulation of waiting trucks.
“Lastly, it also takes a toll on the drivers, whom have a difficult job as it is. Let’s not forget we are dealing with sectorial drivers’ shortage”, points out Rendakova. Such queues, signalling tough working conditions, do not appeal to younger generations and cannot attract them towards this career.
Another benefit will be the actual increase of flows, both imports and exports, and this will accelerate the development both locally and regionally. The Pandemics made it clear for supply chains that having suppliers closer to selling markets is becoming a more appropriate strategy. Bulgaria can become a regional hub supplying businesses across the Continent. In this regards, removing borders will become an additional growth vector, increasing local competitiveness.
In terms of benefit, we may see a reconsolidation of the capacity on the markets, as carriers in the Region could move freely, in the same way it happens for instance between Germany and Benelux countries. In Europe, the shortage of drivers increased by over 40% from 2020 to 2021, according to an IRU study. While elimination of borders will not increase suddenly number of drivers, we can for sure have a more fluid use of the existing ones by removing idle time spent in queues.
“A very significant economic impact of border checks removal will be felt on short distance trips, so for example on trips between Bulgaria and Romania or Bulgaria and Greece, where waiting times at border represent now a significant part of the journey. In our case, it impacts groupage lines who work on a pre-set schedule. Without checks and delays, an increase in frequency is expected to happen, with positive effects on the local economies”, says Raya Rendakova.
Due to the lack of borders and the reduction of transport time, the amount of carbon emissions will also be considerably reduced, thus protecting the environment. In this regard, GOPET TRANS has already taken important steps, offering customers the opportunity to choose sustainable transport services such as intermodal setups. | 4,551 | <h4>1. <u>Supply chains</u>. Border <u>delays</u> create <u>continent-wide</u> costs—plan provides <u>rapid</u> growth.</h4><p><strong>GOPET TRANS 22</strong> [GOPET TRANS; 11-1-22; leading provider of transport and logistics services in Bulgaria; “Accession to Schengen could make border queues history and support industry and country’s growth,” https://gopettrans.com/5737/accession-to-schengen-could-make-border-queues-history-and-support-industry-and-country-s-growth/] brett</p><p><u>Limitation of queues and days long jams at borders are two <strong><mark>immediate effects</strong></mark> if <strong>Bulgaria</strong> and <strong>Romania</strong> will enter <strong>Schengen</u></strong>. Few weeks ago the European Parliament gave a positive vote on it, with 85% pro inclusion. This is a consultative body, the real decision is to be made by the European Council in December. In terms of technical conditions, most local and international authorities and bodies say that they’ve been met for quite a while.</p><p>“We hope for a positive decision. <u><mark>Without</mark> <strong>checks</strong> and <strong>delays</strong> at the <strong><mark>borders</strong></mark>, <mark>there will be</mark> unobstructed traffic corridors, increased frequency of deliveries and <strong><mark>rapid growth</strong></mark> <mark>with real benefits for</mark> <strong>freight transport</strong> and <strong><mark>supply chains</u></strong></mark>. We predict a 30% increase in vehicle trips per week for short distances between Bulgaria, Greece and Romania, and for Central Europe we predict about 15%”, says Raya Rendakova, Commercial Director of GOPET TRANS, leading provider of transport and logistics services in Bulgaria with strong local presence and active activity in Greece, Romania, Poland, Spain and Turkey.</p><p>Croatia is also consider to integrate Schengen space together with Bulgaria and Romania, but its impact on actual freight movements for us is limited (geographically, does not sit on our main transportation corridors).</p><p><u><strong>Ascension</u></strong> <u>into Schengen</u> <u>has a number of benefits for <strong>freight transportation</u></strong> <u>and <strong>supply chains</u></strong> in general. <u>The most visible and <strong>immediate one</strong> – <strong>eliminating borders queues</strong> and <strong>huge waiting times</u></strong>. Let’s only remember the situation from earlier this year when <u><strong>carriers</strong> waited up to 72h at the Bulgarian – Romanian border</u> (at both crossing points from Vidin – Calafat and Ruse – Giurgiu), <u>which are <mark>the <strong>main traffic gateways</strong> towards Europe</u></mark>. And <u>let’s not forget <strong>additional delays</strong> are piled up at the Romanian – Hungarian borders</u>.</p><p>We do estimate that, <u>by removing borders checks, a trip from Bulgaria to Germany will gain at least 24h</u>. And this <u><strong>without counting any major delays at borders</u></strong>.</p><p>Such <u><strong><mark>delays</u></strong></mark> don’t have a negative impacts only on costs. And we are not discussing here only direct <u><strong>costs</u></strong>, associated with the delays, and which usually <u><mark>create</u></mark> a <u><strong><mark>cascading</u></strong></mark> of <u><strong><mark>penalties</u></strong></mark>. We are counting <u>costs incurred by the <strong>shippers</strong> because goods in transit need to reach production lines which cannot stop and may delay other processes</u>. <u>Or they cannot reach the consumers at the right time</u>.</p><p>Furthermore, we need to also consider additional fuel costs and also an increase of CO2 emissions in those areas, given the accumulation of waiting trucks.</p><p>“Lastly, <u>it also takes a toll on the drivers, whom have a difficult job as it is. Let’s not forget <mark>we are dealing with</mark> sectorial <strong><mark>drivers’ shortage</u></strong></mark>”, points out Rendakova. Such queues, <u>signalling tough working conditions, do not appeal to younger generations and cannot attract them towards this career</u>.</p><p><u>Another benefit will be the actual increase of <strong><mark>flows</strong></mark>, both imports and exports, and this <mark>will accelerate</mark> the <mark>development</mark> both <strong>locally</strong> and <strong><mark>regionally</u></strong></mark>. The Pandemics made it clear for supply chains that <u>having suppliers closer to selling markets is becoming a more appropriate strategy</u>. <u><strong>Bulgaria</strong> can become a regional hub <strong><mark>supplying businesses</strong> across the <strong>Continent</u></strong></mark>. In this regards, <u><strong>removing borders</strong> will become an <strong>additional growth vector</strong>, increasing <strong>local competitiveness</u></strong>.</p><p>In terms of benefit, <u><mark>we may see</mark> a <strong><mark>reconsolidation</strong></mark> of the capacity on the markets, <mark>as carriers</mark> in the Region could <mark>move freely</mark>, in the same way it happens for instance between Germany and Benelux countries</u>. <u>In Europe, the shortage of drivers increased by over 40% from 2020 to 2021, according to an IRU study. While <strong>elimination of borders</strong> will not increase suddenly number of drivers, we can for sure have a more <strong>fluid use</strong> of the existing ones by removing idle time spent in queues</u>.</p><p>“<u>A very significant <strong>economic impact</strong> of border checks removal will be felt on short distance trips, so for example on trips between Bulgaria and Romania or Bulgaria and Greece, where waiting times at border represent now a significant part of the journey</u>. In our case, it impacts groupage lines who work on a pre-set schedule. Without checks and delays, an <u><strong>increase in frequency</u></strong> is expected to happen, <u>with positive effects on the local economies</u>”, says Raya Rendakova.</p><p><u>Due to the lack of borders and the reduction of transport time, the amount of <strong>carbon emissions</strong> will also be <strong>considerably reduced</strong>, thus protecting the environment</u>. In this regard, GOPET TRANS has already taken important steps, offering customers the opportunity to choose sustainable transport services such as intermodal setups.</p> | null | null | 1AC—ADV—Growth | 1,705,364 | 142 | 166,276 | ./documents/hsld22/Montville/SuHe/Montville-SuHe-Aff-TOC-Digital-Speech-and-Debate-Series-3-Round-6.docx | 992,272 | A | TOC Digital Speech and Debate Series 3 | 6 | Iowa City West BE | Herrig | 1ac: schegen, disclosure
1nc: disclosure, extinction first bad, case
1ar: all
2nr: all
2ar: all | hsld22/Montville/SuHe/Montville-SuHe-Aff-TOC-Digital-Speech-and-Debate-Series-3-Round-6.docx | 2023-04-01 18:38:08 | 79,615 | SuHe | Montville SuHe | Hey, I'm sunay (he/him). Best form of contact is messenger (Sunay Hegde). Here's my email if that doesnt work: [email protected]. If you need anything/if theres anyway I can be more accessible (ie formatting, trigger warning, etc.) please let me know. Also my cites are like really messed up, and I really have no idea how to fix it, so please ignore the cites and just go to opensource. | Su..... | He..... | null | null | 26,713 | Montville | Montville | NJ | 1,660 | 2,003 | hsld22 | HS LD 2022-23 | 2,022 | ld | hs | 1 |
2,308,064 | 1] Extinction outweighs under any framework | Pummer 15 | Pummer 15 [Theron, Junior Research Fellow in Philosophy at St. Anne's College, University of Oxford. “Moral Agreement on Saving the World” Practical Ethics, University of Oxford. May 18, 2015] AT | There appears to be lot of disagreement in moral philosophy. Whether these many apparent disagreements are deep and irresolvable, I believe there is at least one thing it is reasonable to agree on right now : that it is very important to reduce the risk that all intelligent beings on this planet are eliminated by an enormous catastrophe, such as a nuclear war. we – whether we’re consequentialists, deontologists, or virtue ethicists – should all agree that we should try to save the world. Clearly one thing that makes an outcome good is that the people in it are doing well. There is little disagreement here. reducing existential risk is easily the most important thing in the whole world. This is for the familiar reason that there are so many people who could exist in the future – there are trillions upon trillions… upon trillions. There are so many possible future people that reducing existential risk is arguably the most important thing in the world, even if the well-being of these possible people were given only 0.001% as much weight as that of existing people. this case is strengthened by the fact that there’s a good chance that many existing people will, with the aid of life-extension technology, live very long and very high quality lives. You might think what I have just argued applies to consequentialists only. There is a tendency to assume that, if an argument appeals to consequentialist considerations (the goodness of outcomes), it is irrelevant to non-consequentialists. But that is a huge mistake. Non-consequentialism is the view that there’s more that determines rightness than the goodness of consequences or outcomes; it is not the view that the latter don’t matter. All ethical doctrines worth our attention take consequences into account in judging rightness. One which did not would simply be irrational, crazy. Minimally plausible versions of deontology and virtue ethics must be concerned in part with promoting the good, from an impartial point of view. They’d thus imply very strong reasons to reduce existential risk Even egoism, the view that each agent should maximize her own good, might imply strong reasons to reduce existential risk. To be minimally plausible, egoism will need to be paired with a more sophisticated account of well-being. suppose that, while wearing it, Ayn could derive some pleasure by helping the poor, but instead could derive just a bit more by severely harming them. Hedonistic egoism would absurdly imply she should do the latter. To avoid this implication, egoists would need to build something like the meaningfulness of a life into well-being once these elements are included, we can (roughly, as above) argue that this sort of egoism will imply strong reasons to reduce existential risk. We should also take into account moral uncertainty. What is it reasonable for one to do, when one is uncertain not (only) about the empirical facts, but also about the moral facts? there’s agreement among minimally plausible ethical views that we have strong reason to reduce existential risk – not only consequentialists, but also deontologists, virtue ethicists, and sophisticated egoists should agree. even those (hedonistic egoists) who disagree should have a significant level of confidence that they are mistaken, and that one of the above views is correct. Even if they were 90% sure that their view is the correct one they would have pretty strong reason, from the standpoint of moral uncertainty, to reduce existential risk. even if we are only 1% sure that the well-being of possible future people matters, it is at least arguable that, from the standpoint of moral uncertainty, reducing existential risk is the most important thing in the world. It is enough for my claim that there is moral agreement in the relevant sense if all minimally plausible moral views would converge on the conclusion that we should try to save the world. views that place significantly greater moral weight on avoiding suffering than on promoting happiness seem to be fairly implausible views. even if things did not go well for our ancestors, I am optimistic that they will overall go fantastically well for our descendants, if we allow them to. I suspect that most of us alive today – at least those of us not suffering from extreme illness or poverty – have lives that are well worth living, and that things will continue to improve. Given the scientific and technological discoveries of the last two centuries, the world has never changed as fast. If we act wisely in the next few centuries, humanity will survive its most dangerous and decisive period. Our descendants might, I believe, make the further future very good. But that good future may also depend in part on us. If our selfish recklessness ends human history, we would be acting very wrongly. | reducing existential risk is the most important thing so many people could exist in the future trillions reducing existential risk is the most important even if the well-being of these possible people were given only 0.001% as much weight tendency to assume that if an argument appeals to consequentialist considerations irrelevant to non-consequentialists is a huge mistake Minimally plausible versions of deontology and virtue ethics must be concerned in part with promoting the good strong reasons to reduce existential risk We should also take into account moral uncertainty. even if we are only 1% sure that well-being matters, all minimally plausible moral views would converge that we should try to save the world. | There appears to be lot of disagreement in moral philosophy. Whether these many apparent disagreements are deep and irresolvable, I believe there is at least one thing it is reasonable to agree on right now, whatever general moral view we adopt: that it is very important to reduce the risk that all intelligent beings on this planet are eliminated by an enormous catastrophe, such as a nuclear war. How we might in fact try to reduce such existential risks is discussed elsewhere. My claim here is only that we – whether we’re consequentialists, deontologists, or virtue ethicists – should all agree that we should try to save the world. According to consequentialism, we should maximize the good, where this is taken to be the goodness, from an impartial perspective, of outcomes. Clearly one thing that makes an outcome good is that the people in it are doing well. There is little disagreement here. If the happiness or well-being of possible future people is just as important as that of people who already exist, and if they would have good lives, it is not hard to see how reducing existential risk is easily the most important thing in the whole world. This is for the familiar reason that there are so many people who could exist in the future – there are trillions upon trillions… upon trillions. There are so many possible future people that reducing existential risk is arguably the most important thing in the world, even if the well-being of these possible people were given only 0.001% as much weight as that of existing people. Even on a wholly person-affecting view – according to which there’s nothing (apart from effects on existing people) to be said in favor of creating happy people – the case for reducing existential risk is very strong. As noted in this seminal paper, this case is strengthened by the fact that there’s a good chance that many existing people will, with the aid of life-extension technology, live very long and very high quality lives. You might think what I have just argued applies to consequentialists only. There is a tendency to assume that, if an argument appeals to consequentialist considerations (the goodness of outcomes), it is irrelevant to non-consequentialists. But that is a huge mistake. Non-consequentialism is the view that there’s more that determines rightness than the goodness of consequences or outcomes; it is not the view that the latter don’t matter. Even John Rawls wrote, “All ethical doctrines worth our attention take consequences into account in judging rightness. One which did not would simply be irrational, crazy.” Minimally plausible versions of deontology and virtue ethics must be concerned in part with promoting the good, from an impartial point of view. They’d thus imply very strong reasons to reduce existential risk, at least when this doesn’t significantly involve doing harm to others or damaging one’s character. What’s even more surprising, perhaps, is that even if our own good (or that of those near and dear to us) has much greater weight than goodness from the impartial “point of view of the universe,” indeed even if the latter is entirely morally irrelevant, we may nonetheless have very strong reasons to reduce existential risk. Even egoism, the view that each agent should maximize her own good, might imply strong reasons to reduce existential risk. It will depend, among other things, on what one’s own good consists in. If well-being consisted in pleasure only, it is somewhat harder to argue that egoism would imply strong reasons to reduce existential risk – perhaps we could argue that one would maximize her expected hedonic well-being by funding life extension technology or by having herself cryogenically frozen at the time of her bodily death as well as giving money to reduce existential risk (so that there is a world for her to live in!). I am not sure, however, how strong the reasons to do this would be. But views which imply that, if I don’t care about other people, I have no or very little reason to help them are not even minimally plausible views (in addition to hedonistic egoism, I here have in mind views that imply that one has no reason to perform an act unless one actually desires to do that act). To be minimally plausible, egoism will need to be paired with a more sophisticated account of well-being. To see this, it is enough to consider, as Plato did, the possibility of a ring of invisibility – suppose that, while wearing it, Ayn could derive some pleasure by helping the poor, but instead could derive just a bit more by severely harming them. Hedonistic egoism would absurdly imply she should do the latter. To avoid this implication, egoists would need to build something like the meaningfulness of a life into well-being, in some robust way, where this would to a significant extent be a function of other-regarding concerns (see chapter 12 of this classic intro to ethics). But once these elements are included, we can (roughly, as above) argue that this sort of egoism will imply strong reasons to reduce existential risk. Add to all of this Samuel Scheffler’s recent intriguing arguments (quick podcast version available here) that most of what makes our lives go well would be undermined if there were no future generations of intelligent persons. On his view, my life would contain vastly less well-being if (say) a year after my death the world came to an end. So obviously if Scheffler were right I’d have very strong reason to reduce existential risk. We should also take into account moral uncertainty. What is it reasonable for one to do, when one is uncertain not (only) about the empirical facts, but also about the moral facts? I’ve just argued that there’s agreement among minimally plausible ethical views that we have strong reason to reduce existential risk – not only consequentialists, but also deontologists, virtue ethicists, and sophisticated egoists should agree. But even those (hedonistic egoists) who disagree should have a significant level of confidence that they are mistaken, and that one of the above views is correct. Even if they were 90% sure that their view is the correct one (and 10% sure that one of these other ones is correct), they would have pretty strong reason, from the standpoint of moral uncertainty, to reduce existential risk. Perhaps most disturbingly still, even if we are only 1% sure that the well-being of possible future people matters, it is at least arguable that, from the standpoint of moral uncertainty, reducing existential risk is the most important thing in the world. Again, this is largely for the reason that there are so many people who could exist in the future – there are trillions upon trillions… upon trillions. (For more on this and other related issues, see this excellent dissertation). Of course, it is uncertain whether these untold trillions would, in general, have good lives. It’s possible they’ll be miserable. It is enough for my claim that there is moral agreement in the relevant sense if, at least given certain empirical claims about what future lives would most likely be like, all minimally plausible moral views would converge on the conclusion that we should try to save the world. While there are some non-crazy views that place significantly greater moral weight on avoiding suffering than on promoting happiness, for reasons others have offered (and for independent reasons I won’t get into here unless requested to), they nonetheless seem to be fairly implausible views. And even if things did not go well for our ancestors, I am optimistic that they will overall go fantastically well for our descendants, if we allow them to. I suspect that most of us alive today – at least those of us not suffering from extreme illness or poverty – have lives that are well worth living, and that things will continue to improve. Derek Parfit, whose work has emphasized future generations as well as agreement in ethics, described our situation clearly and accurately: “We live during the hinge of history. Given the scientific and technological discoveries of the last two centuries, the world has never changed as fast. We shall soon have even greater powers to transform, not only our surroundings, but ourselves and our successors. If we act wisely in the next few centuries, humanity will survive its most dangerous and decisive period. Our descendants could, if necessary, go elsewhere, spreading through this galaxy…. Our descendants might, I believe, make the further future very good. But that good future may also depend in part on us. If our selfish recklessness ends human history, we would be acting very wrongly.” (From chapter 36 of On What Matters) | 8,686 | <h4>1] Extinction outweighs under any framework</h4><p><strong>Pummer 15</strong> [Theron, Junior Research Fellow in Philosophy at St. Anne's College, University of Oxford. “Moral Agreement on Saving the World” Practical Ethics, University of Oxford. May 18, 2015] AT</p><p><u><strong>There appears to be lot of disagreement in moral philosophy. Whether these many apparent disagreements are deep and irresolvable, I believe there is at least one thing it is reasonable to agree on right now</u></strong>, whatever general moral view we adopt<u><strong>: that it is very important to reduce the risk that all intelligent beings on this planet are eliminated by an enormous catastrophe, such as a nuclear war.</u></strong> How we might in fact try to reduce such existential risks is discussed elsewhere. My claim here is only that <u><strong>we – whether we’re consequentialists, deontologists, or virtue ethicists – should all agree that we should try to save the world. </u></strong>According to consequentialism, we should maximize the good, where this is taken to be the goodness, from an impartial perspective, of outcomes. <u><strong>Clearly one thing that makes an outcome good is that the people in it are doing well. There is little disagreement here.</u></strong> If the happiness or well-being of possible future people is just as important as that of people who already exist, and if they would have good lives, it is not hard to see how<u><strong> <mark>reducing existential risk is </mark>easily <mark>the most important thing </mark>in the whole world. This is for the familiar reason that there are <mark>so many people </mark>who <mark>could exist in the future</mark> – there are <mark>trillions </mark>upon trillions… upon trillions. There are so many possible future people that <mark>reducing existential risk is</mark> arguably <mark>the most important</mark> thing in the world, <mark>even if the well-being of these possible people were given only 0.001% as much weight </mark>as that of existing people.</u></strong> Even on a wholly person-affecting view – according to which there’s nothing (apart from effects on existing people) to be said in favor of creating happy people – the case for reducing existential risk is very strong. As noted in this seminal paper, <u><strong>this case is strengthened by the fact that there’s a good chance that many existing people will, with the aid of life-extension technology, live very long and very high quality lives. You might think what I have just argued applies to consequentialists only. There is a <mark>tendency to assume that</mark>, <mark>if an argument appeals to consequentialist considerations</mark> (the goodness of outcomes), it is <mark>irrelevant to non-consequentialists</mark>. But that <mark>is a huge mistake</mark>.</u></strong> <u><strong>Non-consequentialism is the view that there’s more that determines rightness than the goodness of consequences or outcomes; it is not the view that the latter don’t matter.</u></strong> Even John Rawls wrote, “<u><strong>All ethical doctrines worth our attention take consequences into account in judging rightness. One which did not would simply be irrational, crazy.</u></strong>” <u><strong><mark>Minimally plausible versions of deontology and virtue ethics must be concerned in part with promoting the good</mark>, from an impartial point of view.</u></strong> <u><strong>They’d thus imply very <mark>strong reasons to reduce existential risk</u></strong></mark>, at least when this doesn’t significantly involve doing harm to others or damaging one’s character. What’s even more surprising, perhaps, is that even if our own good (or that of those near and dear to us) has much greater weight than goodness from the impartial “point of view of the universe,” indeed even if the latter is entirely morally irrelevant, we may nonetheless have very strong reasons to reduce existential risk. <u><strong>Even egoism, the view that each agent should maximize her own good, might imply strong reasons to reduce existential risk.</u></strong> It will depend, among other things, on what one’s own good consists in. If well-being consisted in pleasure only, it is somewhat harder to argue that egoism would imply strong reasons to reduce existential risk – perhaps we could argue that one would maximize her expected hedonic well-being by funding life extension technology or by having herself cryogenically frozen at the time of her bodily death as well as giving money to reduce existential risk (so that there is a world for her to live in!). I am not sure, however, how strong the reasons to do this would be. But views which imply that, if I don’t care about other people, I have no or very little reason to help them are not even minimally plausible views (in addition to hedonistic egoism, I here have in mind views that imply that one has no reason to perform an act unless one actually desires to do that act). <u><strong>To be minimally plausible, egoism will need to be paired with a more sophisticated account of well-being.</u></strong> To see this, it is enough to consider, as Plato did, the possibility of a ring of invisibility – <u><strong>suppose that, while wearing it, Ayn could derive some pleasure by helping the poor, but instead could derive just a bit more by severely harming them. Hedonistic egoism would absurdly imply she should do the latter. To avoid this implication, egoists would need to build something like the meaningfulness of a life into well-being</u></strong>, in some robust way, where this would to a significant extent be a function of other-regarding concerns (see chapter 12 of this classic intro to ethics). But <u><strong>once these elements are included, we can (roughly, as above) argue that this sort of egoism will imply strong reasons to reduce existential risk.</u></strong> Add to all of this Samuel Scheffler’s recent intriguing arguments (quick podcast version available here) that most of what makes our lives go well would be undermined if there were no future generations of intelligent persons. On his view, my life would contain vastly less well-being if (say) a year after my death the world came to an end. So obviously if Scheffler were right I’d have very strong reason to reduce existential risk. <u><strong><mark>We should also take into account moral uncertainty.</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>What is it reasonable for one to do, when one is uncertain not (only) about the empirical facts, but also about the moral facts?</u></strong> I’ve just argued that <u><strong>there’s agreement among minimally plausible ethical views that we have strong reason to reduce existential risk – not only consequentialists, but also deontologists, virtue ethicists, and sophisticated egoists should agree.</u></strong> But <u><strong>even those (hedonistic egoists) who disagree should have a significant level of confidence that they are mistaken, and that one of the above views is correct. Even if they were 90% sure that their view is the correct one </u></strong>(and 10% sure that one of these other ones is correct), <u><strong>they would have pretty strong reason, from the standpoint of moral uncertainty, to reduce existential risk.</u></strong> Perhaps most disturbingly still, <u><strong><mark>even if we are only 1% sure that </mark>the <mark>well-being </mark>of possible future people <mark>matters, </mark>it is at least arguable that, from the standpoint of moral uncertainty, reducing existential risk is the most important thing in the world.</u></strong> Again, this is largely for the reason that there are so many people who could exist in the future – there are trillions upon trillions… upon trillions. (For more on this and other related issues, see this excellent dissertation). Of course, it is uncertain whether these untold trillions would, in general, have good lives. It’s possible they’ll be miserable. <u><strong>It is enough for my claim that there is moral agreement in the relevant sense if</u></strong>, at least given certain empirical claims about what future lives would most likely be like, <u><strong><mark>all minimally plausible moral views would converge </mark>on the conclusion <mark>that we should try to save the world.</u></strong></mark> While there are some non-crazy <u><strong>views that place significantly greater moral weight on avoiding suffering than on promoting happiness</u></strong>, for reasons others have offered (and for independent reasons I won’t get into here unless requested to), they nonetheless <u><strong>seem to be fairly implausible views.</u></strong> And <u><strong>even if things did not go well for our ancestors, I am optimistic that they will overall go fantastically well for our descendants, if we allow them to. I suspect that most of us alive today – at least those of us not suffering from extreme illness or poverty – have lives that are well worth living, and that things will continue to improve.</u></strong> Derek Parfit, whose work has emphasized future generations as well as agreement in ethics, described our situation clearly and accurately: “We live during the hinge of history. <u><strong>Given the scientific and technological discoveries of the last two centuries, the world has never changed as fast. </u></strong>We shall soon have even greater powers to transform, not only our surroundings, but ourselves and our successors. <u><strong>If we act wisely in the next few centuries, humanity will survive its most dangerous and decisive period. </u></strong>Our descendants could, if necessary, go elsewhere, spreading through this galaxy…. <u><strong>Our descendants might, I believe, make the further future very good. But that good future may also depend in part on us. If our selfish recklessness ends human history, we would be acting very wrongly.</u></strong>” (From chapter 36 of On What Matters)</p> | null | 2 | 1NC – DA | 12,186 | 5,631 | 72,782 | ./documents/hsld20/Peninsula/Ra/Peninsula-Ramireddy-Neg-Apple%20Valley-Round6.docx | 870,329 | N | Apple Valley | 6 | Appleton North MU | Vincent Liu | 1AC Rawls
1NC Util NC Recruitment DA
1AR All
2NR NC DA Case
2AR All | hsld20/Peninsula/Ra/Peninsula-Ramireddy-Neg-Apple%20Valley-Round6.docx | null | 73,622 | AnRa | Peninsula AnRa | null | An..... | Ra..... | null | null | 24,672 | Peninsula | Peninsula | CA | null | 1,028 | hsld20 | HS LD 2020-21 | 2,020 | ld | hs | 1 |
859,035 | Fearing militarism of overseas presence challenges securitization and apocalypitization | WILLIAMS ’11 | Michael WILLIAMS Graduate School of Public and International Affairs, University of Ottawa ’11 “Securitization and the liberalism of fear” Security Dialogue 42 p. 453-456 | fear might seem straightforwardly related to securitization: an increase in fear equals an increase in securitization fear can operate in ways that can actually inhibit processes of securitization, constraining the logic of extremity, making actors reluctant to use securitizing moves and providing resources for opposing such moves a narrowly technocratic liberalism serving both as a foil for the idea of securitization as radically creative This understanding of liberalism has become a staple this ‘Schmittian’ representation and critique of liberalism is not the only version of liberalism available to take it as a given model for liberal thought and as an assumed foundation for analysing how ‘security’ operates in liberal societies—may risk being seriously misleading the ‘liberalism of fear’ can provide a more rounded appreciation of the politics of security in liberal polities and of how a better understanding of the liberalism of fear can extend the reach of securitization theory and provide support for desecuritization liberalism of fear is resolutely anti-utopian It is non-foundationalist sceptical, seeing a world where violence actual or potential) is and will remain an ineradicable part of political life It sides with facing up to the worst things that human beings have shown themselves capable of doing and trying to avoid them It is suspicious of grand moral visions sceptical not cynical it advocates a focus on cruelty based on the ‘existential experience on humanity’s shared capacity to feel fear and to be victims of cruelty the liberalism of fear does begin with a summum malum which all of us know and would avoid if only we could the very fear of fear itself fear cannot and should not be always and in every way avoided it is an inescapable part of life something that often helps preserve us from danger The fear we fear is of pain inflicted by others to kill and maim us, not the natural and healthy fear that merely warns us of avoidable pain We fear a society of fearful people It fears above all collective concentrations of power that make possible ‘institutionalized cruelty’ the liberalism of fear focuses on restraining fear’s excesses The liberalism of fear is far from rejecting the state’s role in the provision of social goods, including security But, it is continually alert to the state’s potential to do the opposite fear can work as a counter-practice against processes of securitization. Fear operates in normal politics, and the fear of fear— of the power of the politics of security is a core part of liberal theory and practice. Fear is not a one-way street to extremity, nor does it operate only in emergency situations the fear of fear can act as a bulwark against such processes within ‘normal’ or even ‘securitized’ politics act to prevent or oppose a movement toward a more intense politics of fear—countering a shift toward ‘security’ in its more extreme manifestations | fear can inhibit securitization making actors reluctant to securitizi and providing resources for opposing such moves critique of liberalism risk being seriously misleading the ‘liberalism of fear’ provide a rounded appreciation of the politics of security in liberal polities, and of how the liberalism of fear can provide support for desecuritization liberalism of fear is anti-utopian. It is non-foundationalist seeing a world where violence will remain ineradicable It sides with facing up to the worst and trying to avoid them. It is suspicious of grand moral visions fear should not be always avoided it is inescapable something that helps preserve us from danger It fears collective concentrations of power that make possible ‘institutionalized cruelty’ liberalism focuses on restraining fear’s excesses The liberalism of fear is far from rejecting the state’s role it is continually alert to the state’s potential to do the opposite Fear is not a one-way street to extremity, nor does it operate only in emergency fear of fear can within even ‘securitized’ politics act to oppose movement toward ‘security’ in its more extreme manifestations | Fear is not a concept (or indeed a word) often found in securitization theory. Instead, the Copenhagen School speaks of security as an existential threat, as emergency measures or as a ‘breaking free of rules’. Security is not an objective condition, but emerges through particular social processes or ‘speech acts’ that elevate an issue above the normal political logic: ‘if we do not tackle this problem, everything else will be irrelevant because we will not be here or will not be free to handle it in our own way’ (Buzan et al., 1998: 24). Yet, even this formulation indicates an intimate relationship between existential threat and fear—the fear of annihilation, loss and alienation. Threats imply the loss of or damage to something (physical survival or well-being, an object, a social order, an identity) that is valued—that is, a fear for its continued possession or existence. People can fear other individuals, other groups, other states (or their own); they can fear economic calamity or environmental degradation. Even exceptional violence or fearless killing—an existential or heroic self-sacrifice, for instance—is tied in complex ways to fear: fear for someone or something else that is being defended, fear of failing to achieve glory or salvation. Fear’s negativity always has positive value. This article seeks to extend securitization theory conceptually and, to a lesser degree, empirically by further developing the relationship between securitization and the politics of fear. My suggestion is that by so doing it is possible to enlarge the theoretical framework of the Copenhagen School and to expand its application in understanding the politics of security in liberal societies. At first glance, fear might seem straightforwardly related to securitization: an increase in fear equals an increase in securitization, or at the very least facilitates successful securitization. However, rather than looking at the ways in which fear can facilitate securitization, or adding to the widespread claims about the connections between the politics of fear and the extension of security logics throughout society,1 I want to explore a rather different possibility: that focusing on fear also allows us to see how fear can operate in ways that can actually inhibit processes of securitization, constraining the logic of extremity, making actors reluctant to use securitizing moves and providing resources for opposing such moves. To make this argument, I turn to an examination of the relationship between liberalism and fear. As Jef Huysmans (1998) pointed out in one of the earliest and most perceptive appraisals of the Copenhagen School, liberalism provides an important backdrop to the theory, with a narrowly technocratic liberalism and superficial pluralism serving both as a foil for the idea of securitization as radically creative and socially constructed and as a link to theories of enmity, emergency, and the political identified with Carl Schmitt and with classical political realism more broadly. Fear within liberalism is thus often closely associated with a politics of extremity and enmity, and is seen as having close—and perhaps even constitutive—connections to securitization. Liberal societies, such positions often imply, either need a politics of security and fear in order to overcome the weaknesses of their pluralist foundations or, conversely, are congenitally ill-equipped to respond effectively to the challenges of a politics of extremity and securitization. This understanding of liberalism has in turn become a staple (sometimes an almost unquestioned assumption) for some of the most vibrant controversies over the theoretical and political entailments of securitization theory.2 There is little doubt that these analyses point to crucial issues in the relationship between liberalism and security, and in the politics of securitization in liberal states. Yet, this ‘Schmittian’ or classical ‘realist’ (or, for that matter, Straussian) representation and critique of liberalism is not the only version of liberalism available, and to take it as a given model for liberal thought or practice as a whole—and as an assumed foundation for analysing how ‘security’ operates in liberal societies—may in fact risk being seriously misleading. At least, this is the suspicion I want to explore here, and for help in doing so it is particularly revealing to turn one of the most nuanced and influential expressions of an alternative vision, a vision that Judith Shklar aptly christened the ‘liberalism of fear’.3 Shklar’s conception of liberal politics, I suggest, can help provide a more rounded appreciation of the politics of security in liberal polities, and of how a better understanding of the liberalism of fear can extend the reach of securitization theory both conceptually and empirically, and may—perhaps paradoxically—even provide support for the Copenhagen School’s political project of desecuritization. I In contrast to the narrowly rationalistic liberalism that is the focus of the critiques alluded to above, the liberalism of fear has a number of affinities with securitization theory.4 It is resolutely anti-utopian. It is, in a philosophical sense, non-foundationalist. It is sceptical, seeing a world where violence (actual or potential) is and will remain an ineradicable part of political life. It sides with what Emerson once called the ‘party of memory’ in contrast to the ‘party of hope’ (see Shklar, 1998: 8), insisting on facing up to the worst things that human beings have shown themselves capable of doing to one another, and trying to avoid them. It is suspicious of and generally eschews grand moral visions and philosophical or theo-political schemas, which it tends to see as sources of obscurantism and conflict rather than emancipation and progress. It has no ‘strong’ ontology, in either a rationalist or a social constructivist (self–other) sense.5 It rejects the identification of liberalism with an abstract rationalism, a narrow utilitarianism, Kantian formalism, a programme of indisputable natural rights or a flat proceduralism.6 In sum, it is a vision of liberalism that contrasts sharply with the thin version often put forth by both proponents and critics of liberalism in international relations7—and in many debates over securitization theory. Yet, if the liberalism of fear is sceptical, it is not cynical. Nor is it without a place to stand. In place of essentialist visions of individuals or schemes of indisputable rights, it advocates a focus on cruelty and fear. It is, in Stanley Hoffmann’s (1998: xxii) nice phrase, a vision based on the ‘existential experience of fear and cruelty’, concentrating on humanity’s shared capacity to feel fear and to be victims of cruelty.8 Perhaps most importantly in this context, it turns this focus on fear into a positive principle of liberal politics. As Shklar (1998: 10–11) argues, the liberalism of fear does not, to be sure, offer a summum bonum toward which all political agents should strive, but it certainly does begin with a summum malum which all of us know and would avoid if only we could. That evil is cruelty and the fear that it inspires, and the very fear of fear itself. To that extent, the liberalism of fear makes a universal and especially a cosmopolitan claim, as it historically has always done. In this vision, fear is central to liberal politics, but in a way very different from those visions that see fear, emergency and ‘security’ as the defining ‘outside’ of liberal societies, as the antithesis of normal politics, or, as suggested in other analyses, as the constitutive realm or radical otherness or enmity that stabilizes and/or energizes otherwise decadent or depoliticized liberal orders.9 For the liberalism of fear, fear cannot and should not be always and in every way avoided. For one thing, it is an inescapable part of life, something that often helps preserve us from danger. More complexly, fear can also be a crucial element in preserving as well as constructing a liberal order, for one of the major things to be feared in social life is the fear of fear itself. As Shklar (1998: 11) puts it in one of her most evocative phrasings: To be alive is to be afraid, and much to our advantage in many cases, since alarm often preserves us from danger. The fear we fear is of pain inflicted by others to kill and maim us, not the natural and healthy fear that merely warns us of avoidable pain. And, when we think politically, we are afraid not only for ourselves but for our fellow citizens as well. We fear a society of fearful people. This vision of liberal politics fears the politics of fear. It fears above all collective concentrations of power that make possible ‘institutionalized cruelty’, particularly when they are abetted or accompanied by a politics of fear. Thus, while the liberalism of fear fears all concentrations of power, it fears most the concentration of power in that most fearsome of institutions in the modern world—the state; for while cruelty can reflect sadistic urges, ‘public cruelty is not an occasional personal inclination. It is made possible by differences in public power’ (Shklar, 1998: 11). A degree of fear and coercion is doubtless a condition of the operation of all social orders; but, as its first order of concern, the liberalism of fear focuses on restraining fear’s excesses. As Shklar (1998: 11) puts it: A minimal level of fear is implied in any system of law, and the liberalism of fear does not dream of an end to public, coercive government. The fear it does want to prevent is that which is created by arbitrary, unexpected, unnecessary, and unlicensed acts of force and by habitual and pervasive acts of cruelty and torture performed by military, paramilitary and police agents in any regime. The liberalism of fear is far from rejecting the state’s role in the provision of social goods, including security. Indeed, these may be essential in overcoming socially derived cruelties of many kinds.10 But, it is continually alert to the state’s potential to do the opposite.11 Here, then, is a vision of politics where fear is not confined to the realm of security; nor is fear wholly negative. Such a vision shares with the Copenhagen School the fear that fear in politics is dangerous. But, Shklar’s multidimensional analysis of fear allows us to see how fear can work as a counter-practice against processes of securitization. Fear operates in normal politics, and the fear of fear—that is, the fear of the power of the politics of security and its consequences—is a core part of liberal theory and practice. Fear is not a one-way street to extremity, nor does it operate only in emergency situations. Instead, the fear of fear can act as a bulwark against such processes. In other words, the fear of fear can within ‘normal’ or even ‘securitized’ politics act to prevent or oppose a movement toward a more intense politics of fear—countering a shift toward ‘security’ in its more extreme manifestations.12 | 11,030 | <h4>Fearing militarism of overseas presence challenges securitization and apocalypitization </h4><p>Michael <u><strong>WILLIAMS</u></strong> Graduate School of Public and International Affairs, University of Ottawa <u><strong>’11</u></strong> “Securitization and the liberalism of fear” Security Dialogue 42 p. 453-456</p><p>Fear is not a concept (or indeed a word) often found in securitization theory. Instead, the Copenhagen School speaks of security as an existential threat, as emergency measures or as a ‘breaking free of rules’. Security is not an objective condition, but emerges through particular social processes or ‘speech acts’ that elevate an issue above the normal political logic: ‘if we do not tackle this problem, everything else will be irrelevant because we will not be here or will not be free to handle it in our own way’ (Buzan et al., 1998: 24). Yet, even this formulation indicates an intimate relationship between existential threat and fear—the fear of annihilation, loss and alienation. Threats imply the loss of or damage to something (physical survival or well-being, an object, a social order, an identity) that is valued—that is, a fear for its continued possession or existence. People can fear other individuals, other groups, other states (or their own); they can fear economic calamity or environmental degradation. Even exceptional violence or fearless killing—an existential or heroic self-sacrifice, for instance—is tied in complex ways to fear: fear for someone or something else that is being defended, fear of failing to achieve glory or salvation. Fear’s negativity always has positive value. This article seeks to extend securitization theory conceptually and, to a lesser degree, empirically by further developing the relationship between securitization and the politics of fear. My suggestion is that by so doing it is possible to enlarge the theoretical framework of the Copenhagen School and to expand its application in understanding the politics of security in liberal societies. At first glance, <u><strong>fear might seem straightforwardly related to securitization: an increase in fear equals an increase in securitization</u></strong>, or at the very least facilitates successful securitization. However, rather than looking at the ways in which fear can facilitate securitization, or adding to the widespread claims about the connections between the politics of fear and the extension of security logics throughout society,1 I want to explore a rather different possibility: that focusing on fear also allows us to see how <u><strong><mark>fear can</mark> operate in ways that can actually <mark>inhibit</mark> processes of <mark>securitization</mark>, constraining the logic of extremity, <mark>making actors reluctant to</mark> use <mark>securitizi</mark>ng moves <mark>and providing resources for opposing such moves</u></strong></mark>. To make this argument, I turn to an examination of the relationship between liberalism and fear. As Jef Huysmans (1998) pointed out in one of the earliest and most perceptive appraisals of the Copenhagen School, liberalism provides an important backdrop to the theory, with <u><strong>a narrowly technocratic liberalism</u></strong> and superficial pluralism <u><strong>serving both as a foil for the idea of securitization as radically creative</u></strong> and socially constructed and as a link to theories of enmity, emergency, and the political identified with Carl Schmitt and with classical political realism more broadly. Fear within liberalism is thus often closely associated with a politics of extremity and enmity, and is seen as having close—and perhaps even constitutive—connections to securitization. Liberal societies, such positions often imply, either need a politics of security and fear in order to overcome the weaknesses of their pluralist foundations or, conversely, are congenitally ill-equipped to respond effectively to the challenges of a politics of extremity and securitization. <u><strong>This understanding of liberalism has</u></strong> in turn <u><strong>become a staple</u></strong> (sometimes an almost unquestioned assumption) for some of the most vibrant controversies over the theoretical and political entailments of securitization theory.2 There is little doubt that these analyses point to crucial issues in the relationship between liberalism and security, and in the politics of securitization in liberal states. Yet, <u><strong>this ‘Schmittian’</u></strong> or classical ‘realist’ (or, for that matter, Straussian) <u><strong>representation and <mark>critique of liberalism</mark> is not the only version of liberalism available</u></strong>, and <u><strong>to take it as a given model for liberal thought</u></strong> or practice as a whole—<u><strong>and as an assumed foundation for analysing how ‘security’ operates in liberal societies—may</u></strong> in fact <u><strong><mark>risk being seriously misleading</u></strong></mark>. At least, this is the suspicion I want to explore here, and for help in doing so it is particularly revealing to turn one of the most nuanced and influential expressions of an alternative vision, a vision that Judith Shklar aptly christened <u><strong><mark>the ‘liberalism of fear’</u></strong></mark>.3 Shklar’s conception of liberal politics, I suggest, <u><strong>can</u></strong> help <u><strong><mark>provide a</mark> more <mark>rounded appreciation of the politics of security in liberal polities</u></strong>, <u><strong>and of how</mark> a better understanding of <mark>the liberalism of fear can</mark> extend the reach of securitization theory</u></strong> both conceptually and empirically, <u><strong>and</u></strong> may—perhaps paradoxically—even <u><strong><mark>provide support for</u></strong></mark> the Copenhagen School’s political project of <u><strong><mark>desecuritization</u></strong></mark>. I In contrast to the narrowly rationalistic liberalism that is the focus of the critiques alluded to above, the <u><strong><mark>liberalism of fear</u></strong></mark> has a number of affinities with securitization theory.4 It <u><strong><mark>is</mark> resolutely <mark>anti-utopian</u></strong>. <u><strong>It is</u></strong></mark>, in a philosophical sense, <u><strong><mark>non-foundationalist</u></strong></mark>. It is <u><strong>sceptical, <mark>seeing a world where violence</mark> </u></strong>(<u><strong>actual or potential) is and <mark>will remain</mark> an <mark>ineradicable</mark> part of political life</u></strong>. <u><strong><mark>It sides with</u></strong></mark> what Emerson once called the ‘party of memory’ in contrast to the ‘party of hope’ (see Shklar, 1998: 8), insisting on <u><strong><mark>facing up to the worst</mark> things that human beings have shown themselves capable of doing</u></strong> to one another, <u><strong><mark>and trying to avoid them</u></strong>. <u><strong>It is suspicious of</u></strong></mark> and generally eschews <u><strong><mark>grand moral visions</u></strong></mark> and philosophical or theo-political schemas, which it tends to see as sources of obscurantism and conflict rather than emancipation and progress. It has no ‘strong’ ontology, in either a rationalist or a social constructivist (self–other) sense.5 It rejects the identification of liberalism with an abstract rationalism, a narrow utilitarianism, Kantian formalism, a programme of indisputable natural rights or a flat proceduralism.6 In sum, it is a vision of liberalism that contrasts sharply with the thin version often put forth by both proponents and critics of liberalism in international relations7—and in many debates over securitization theory. Yet, if the liberalism of fear is <u><strong>sceptical</u></strong>, it is <u><strong>not cynical</u></strong>. Nor is it without a place to stand. In place of essentialist visions of individuals or schemes of indisputable rights, <u><strong>it advocates a focus on cruelty</u></strong> and fear. It is, in Stanley Hoffmann’s (1998: xxii) nice phrase, a vision <u><strong>based on the ‘existential experience</u></strong> of fear and cruelty’, concentrating <u><strong>on humanity’s shared capacity to feel fear and to be victims of cruelty</u></strong>.8 Perhaps most importantly in this context, it turns this focus on fear into a positive principle of liberal politics. As Shklar (1998: 10–11) argues, <u><strong>the liberalism of fear does</u></strong> not, to be sure, offer a summum bonum toward which all political agents should strive, but it certainly does <u><strong>begin with a summum malum which all of us know and would avoid if only we could</u></strong>. That evil is cruelty and the fear that it inspires, and <u><strong>the very fear of fear itself</u></strong>. To that extent, the liberalism of fear makes a universal and especially a cosmopolitan claim, as it historically has always done. In this vision, fear is central to liberal politics, but in a way very different from those visions that see fear, emergency and ‘security’ as the defining ‘outside’ of liberal societies, as the antithesis of normal politics, or, as suggested in other analyses, as the constitutive realm or radical otherness or enmity that stabilizes and/or energizes otherwise decadent or depoliticized liberal orders.9 For the liberalism of <u><strong><mark>fear</u></strong></mark>, fear <u><strong>cannot and <mark>should not be always</mark> and in every way <mark>avoided</u></strong></mark>. For one thing, <u><strong><mark>it is</mark> an <mark>inescapable</mark> part of life</u></strong>, <u><strong><mark>something that</mark> often <mark>helps preserve us from danger</u></strong></mark>. More complexly, fear can also be a crucial element in preserving as well as constructing a liberal order, for one of the major things to be feared in social life is the fear of fear itself. As Shklar (1998: 11) puts it in one of her most evocative phrasings: To be alive is to be afraid, and much to our advantage in many cases, since alarm often preserves us from danger. <u><strong>The fear we fear is of pain inflicted by others to kill and maim us, not the natural and healthy fear that merely warns us of avoidable pain</u></strong>. And, when we think politically, we are afraid not only for ourselves but for our fellow citizens as well. <u><strong>We fear a society of fearful people</u></strong>. This vision of liberal politics fears the politics of fear. <u><strong><mark>It fears</mark> above all <mark>collective concentrations of power that make possible ‘institutionalized cruelty’</u></strong></mark>, particularly when they are abetted or accompanied by a politics of fear. Thus, while the liberalism of fear fears all concentrations of power, it fears most the concentration of power in that most fearsome of institutions in the modern world—the state; for while cruelty can reflect sadistic urges, ‘public cruelty is not an occasional personal inclination. It is made possible by differences in public power’ (Shklar, 1998: 11). A degree of fear and coercion is doubtless a condition of the operation of all social orders; but, as its first order of concern, <u><strong>the <mark>liberalism</mark> of fear <mark>focuses on restraining fear’s excesses</u></strong></mark>. As Shklar (1998: 11) puts it: A minimal level of fear is implied in any system of law, and the liberalism of fear does not dream of an end to public, coercive government. The fear it does want to prevent is that which is created by arbitrary, unexpected, unnecessary, and unlicensed acts of force and by habitual and pervasive acts of cruelty and torture performed by military, paramilitary and police agents in any regime. <u><strong><mark>The liberalism of fear is far from rejecting the state’s role</mark> in the provision of social goods, including security</u></strong>. Indeed, these may be essential in overcoming socially derived cruelties of many kinds.10 <u><strong>But, <mark>it is continually alert to the state’s potential to do the opposite</u></strong></mark>.11 Here, then, is a vision of politics where fear is not confined to the realm of security; nor is fear wholly negative. Such a vision shares with the Copenhagen School the fear that fear in politics is dangerous. But, Shklar’s multidimensional analysis of fear allows us to see how <u><strong>fear can work as a counter-practice against processes of securitization. Fear operates in normal politics, and the fear of fear—</u></strong>that is, the fear <u><strong>of the power of the politics of security </u></strong>and its consequences—<u><strong>is a core part of liberal theory and practice. <mark>Fear is not a one-way street to extremity, nor does it operate only in emergency</mark> situations</u></strong>. Instead, <u><strong>the <mark>fear of fear can</mark> act as a bulwark against such processes</u></strong>. In other words, the fear of fear can <u><strong><mark>within</mark> ‘normal’ or <mark>even ‘securitized’ politics act to</mark> prevent or <mark>oppose</mark> a <mark>movement toward</mark> a more intense politics of fear—countering a shift toward <mark>‘security’ in its more extreme manifestations</u></strong></mark>.12</p> | 2AC | Internal K | 1AC---Solvency | 747,001 | 192 | 20,554 | ./documents/ndtceda15/Northwestern/CaEs/Northwestern-Callahan-Esman-Aff-Wakeshirley-Round7.docx | 584,467 | A | Wakeshirley | 7 | Texas Chowdhury-Segura | Gonzalez | 1AC ASB China Securitization
1NC Anthro K Internal Securitization K
2NR Internal K | ndtceda15/Northwestern/CaEs/Northwestern-Callahan-Esman-Aff-Wakeshirley-Round7.docx | null | 49,915 | CaEs | Northwestern CaEs | null | Ch..... | Ca..... | Pa..... | Es..... | 18,975 | Northwestern | Northwestern | null | null | 1,005 | ndtceda15 | NDT/CEDA 2015-16 | 2,015 | cx | college | 2 |
2,601,554 | Proliferation dampens conflict --- only our evidence does a statistical, controlled study. | Suzuki 2015 | Akisato Suzuki, June 2015. Akisato, Researcher at the Institute for International Conflict Resolution and Reconstruction, School of Law and Government, Dublin City University, MA in Violence, Terrorism and Security at Queen's University, “Is more better or worse? New empirics on nuclear proliferation and interstate conflict by Random Forests,” Research and Politics, SagePub | Given these conflict-reducing/provoking effects of nuclear proliferation, what overall effect would prolif have on a systemic propensity for conflict? This challenge motivates the empirical examination
Random Forests can examine non-linearity which is desirable because some theories expect non-linearity between nuclear proliferation and propensity for conflict finally it can cope with potential interactions and multicollinearity between regressors most regressors here are highly correlated, and it is plausible to anticipate some interaction e.g. democratic states and g w p The specific capabilities of Random Forests are therefore essential
the optimist theory is supported Controlling for democratic peace, capitalist peace, and polarity the number of nuclear states is still a significant predictor in explaining a systemic propensity for interstate conflict.
the relationship is empirically non-linear Overall the optimist theory is supported, and the change from two nuclear states to nine nuclear states decreases the dispute–state ratio the number of militarized interstate dispute onsets per system-year decreases This is a substantively significant decline.
the pessimist theory finds no support from either variable importance estimation or the partial dependence plot
if the number of democratic states and the g w p are sufficiently large, they decrease the dispute–state ratio Their effects are significant, though not as much as the number of nuclear states. Unipolarity is also associated with a decline however, its effect is negligible
The main findings reveal that the optimist expectation of the relationship between nuclear proliferation and interstate conflict is empirically supported first, a larger number of nuclear states decreases the propensity for interstate conflict and there is no clear evidence that the emergence of new nuclear states increases the systemic propensity for interstate conflict nuclear weapons have no exogenous effect on the probability of conflict, because when a state is engaged in conflict, it may develop nuclear weapons
This conclusion raises questions about how to reconcile this study’s findings with those of a recent quantitative dyadic-level study Bell and Miller It is possible that nuclear proliferation decreases conflict through the conflict-mitigating effects of extended nuclear deterrence and/or fear of nuclear states’ intervention, to the extent that these effects overwhelm the conflict-provoking effect of nuclear–asymmetrical dyads dyadic-level empirics cannot solely be relied on to infer causal links systemic-level empirics deserve attention | Random Forests examine non-linearity it can cope with interactions and multicollinearity between regressors e.g. democratic states and g w p specific capabilities of Random Forests are essential
the optimist theory is supported Controlling for democratic capitalist peace, and polarity the number of nuclear states is a significant predictor in explaining interstate conflict
the relationship is empirically non-linear
the pessimist theory finds no support
The findings reveal the optimist expectation between nuclear proliferation and interstate conflict is empirically supported a larger number of nuclear states decreases conflict;
, dyadic-level empirics cannot be relied on to infer causal links | Given these conflict-reducing/provoking effects of nuclear proliferation, what overall effect would nuclear proliferation have on a systemic propensity for conflict? This is difficult to answer, not only due to the controversy over whether nuclear states are more or less prone to conflict, but also because the existing theories do not explain whether those conflict-reducing/provoking effects are large enough to influence a systemic propensity for interstate conflict, given the ratio of nuclear states to non-nuclear states in the system. This challenge motivates the empirical examination of the relationship between nuclear proliferation and a systemic propensity for conflict.
Empirical investigation by Random Forests
The interstate–systemic year data are used here to investigate the relationship between nuclear proliferation and a systemic propensity for interstate conflict. The dependent variable is the number of militarized interstate dispute onsets (Palmer et al., 2015; version 4.01 is used) per systemic-year, standardized as the ratio to the number of states in the interstate system (Correlates of War Project, 2011) – hereafter, the ‘dispute–state ratio’. Observations one year ahead (t+1) are used to make sure that causal effects precede a variation in the dispute–state ratio.2
Two regressors are used to examine the effect of nuclear proliferation: the number of nuclear states in the interstate system; and a count of the years since the number of nuclear states changes (hereafter ‘nuclear year counter’), measuring the effect of new nuclear states (Horowitz, 2009). The data about nuclear states are from Gartzke and Kroenig (2009); additionally, the current paper codes North Korea as a nuclear state since 2009 (Table 1).3
The model also includes the number of democratic states (Polity2 score ⩾ 6 in Marshall, 2013) in the interstate system, the gross world product (Earth Policy Institute, 2012), and the binary variable of unipolarity (coded zero until 1989 and one from 1990; see Monteiro, 2011/2012); these three variables control for democratic peace (Russett and Oneal, 2001), capitalist peace (Gartzke, 2007), and polarity (Monteiro, 2011/2012) respectively. The number of nuclear states and these control variables suffer from multicollinearity (see Table A-9 in the online appendix), and this paer later explains how to resolve this problem. A lagged dependent variable is also included to address the temporal dependence of time-series data. The temporal scope is 1950–2009 (i.e. N=59) due to the data availability and the use of the dependent variable at t+1. The descriptive statistics of all variables are displayed in Table 2.4.
As mentioned in the introduction, this paper uses the machine learning, non-parametric method Random Forests for the empirical investigation.5 Although it is unfamiliar to most political science and international relations analysts, Random Forests has been widely used in numerous scientific studies (Strobl et al., 2009: 324; Strobl et al., 2008). The popularity of the method is also apparent from the fact that Breiman’s (2001) original paper has been cited 12,721 times in the literature.6
Random Forests generates two useful analytics: first, ‘conditional variable importance’ measures how ‘important’ each regressor is, conditional on the remaining regressors (Hothorn et al., 2006; Strobl et al., 2007, 2008). This is analogous to statistical significance in conventional regression models. The significance threshold proposed by Strobl et al. (2009: 343) is whether the importance score of a regressor is negative, zero, or lower than the absolute value of the lowest negative score. If none applies, the regressor is considered as important; and the second relevant analytic is a partial dependence plot (Friedman, 2001). This estimates the marginal effect of each regressor on the dependent variable while taking the remaining regressors into consideration.
Random Forests has three attractive and distinctive characteristics for the purposes of this paper: first, the estimation of conditional variable importance and partial dependence plots enable conventional applied researchers to interpret non-parametric analysis in an intuitive way; second, Random Forests can examine non-linearity (Strobl et al., 2009: 339–341), which is desirable because, as already noted, some theories expect non-linearity between nuclear proliferation and a systemic propensity for conflict; and finally, it can cope with potential interactions and multicollinearity between regressors (Strobl et al., 2009: 339–341; Strobl et al., 2008). As noted before, most of the regressors here are highly correlated, and also it is plausible to anticipate some interaction effect between them (e.g. the number of democratic states and the gross world product). The specific capabilities of Random Forests are therefore essential.
The estimation of conditional variable importance shows that the nuclear year counter has a negative importance score.7 Thus, the nuclear year counter is not important in explaining the dispute–state ratio. This suggests that the optimist theory is supported. The remaining regressors have an importance score higher than the absolute value of the importance score of the nuclear year counter, meaning that they are all important. Controlling for democratic peace, capitalist peace, and polarity, the number of nuclear states is still a significant predictor in explaining a systemic propensity for interstate conflict.
Figure 1 presents the partial dependence plots of the model.8 First, on average, a larger number of nuclear states is associated with a lower dispute–state ratio, although the changes from two nuclear states to three and from six to seven increase the ratio instead. Thus, the relationship is empirically non-linear, as Bueno de Mesquita and Riker (1982) and Intriligator and Brito (1981) expected in part. Overall, however, the optimist theory is supported, and the change from two nuclear states to nine nuclear states decreases the dispute–state ratio approximately from 0.228 to 0.18. This means that, if there are 194 states in the system (as there were in 2009), the number of militarized interstate dispute onsets per system-year decreases approximately from 44 to 35. This is a substantively significant decline.
Second, the nuclear year counter shows a concave relationship with the dispute–state ratio, suggesting that new nuclear states are less prone to conflict than middle-aged nuclear states. Thus, the pessimist theory finds no support from either the variable importance estimation or the partial dependence plot.
Finally, as for the control variables, the number of democratic states and the gross world product have a complex non-linear relationship with the dispute–state ratio, but if the number of democratic states and the gross world product are sufficiently large, they tend to decrease the dispute–state ratio. Their substantive effects are also significant, though not as much as the number of nuclear states. When comparing the effect of their lowest and highest values (23 and 94 in the number of democratic states and 7 and 71.2 in the gross world product), the number of democratic states decreases the number of militarized interstate dispute onsets per system-year approximately from 40 to 37, and the gross world product from 44 to 37. Unipolarity is also associated with a decline in the dispute–state ratio, suggesting that unipolarity is better than bipolarity in terms of a systemic propensity for interstate conflict; however, its effect is negligible, as it reduces the number of militarized interstate dispute onsets per system-year from 39 to 38. One caveat is, as explained in the online appendix, that the results of the number of democratic states and unipolarity are significantly sensitive to a parameter setting. Thus, these predictors are less robust, and the aforementioned points about them should be treated with caution.
Discussion and concluding remarks
The main findings reveal that the optimist expectation of the relationship between nuclear proliferation and interstate conflict is empirically supported:9 first, a larger number of nuclear states on average decreases the systemic propensity for interstate conflict; and second, there is no clear evidence that the emergence of new nuclear states increases the systemic propensity for interstate conflict. Gartzke and Jo (2009) argue that nuclear weapons themselves have no exogenous effect on the probability of conflict, because when a state is engaged in or expects to engage in conflict, it may develop nuclear weapons to keep fighting, or to prepare for, that conflict. If this selection effect existed, the analysis should overestimate the conflict-provoking effect of nuclear proliferation in the above model. Still, the results indicate that a larger number of nuclear states are associated with fewer disputes in the system.
This conclusion, however, raises questions about how to reconcile this study’s findings with those of a recent quantitative dyadic-level study (Bell and Miller, 2015). The current paper finds that nuclear proliferation decreases the systemic propensity for interstate conflict, while Bell and Miller (2015) find that nuclear symmetry has no significant effect on dyadic conflict, but that nuclear asymmetry is associated with a higher probability of dyadic conflict. It is possible that nuclear proliferation decreases conflict through the conflict-mitigating effects of extended nuclear deterrence and/or fear of nuclear states’ intervention, to the extent that these effects overwhelm the conflict-provoking effect of nuclear–asymmetrical dyads. Thus, dyadic-level empirics cannot solely be relied on to infer causal links between nuclear proliferation and a systemic propensity for conflict. The systemic-level empirics deserve attention. | 9,889 | <h4>Proliferation <u>dampens</u> conflict --- only our evidence does a <u>statistical</u>, <u>controlled</u> study.</h4><p>Akisato <strong>Suzuki</strong>, June <strong>2015</strong>. Akisato, Researcher at the Institute for International Conflict Resolution and Reconstruction, School of Law and Government, Dublin City University, MA in Violence, Terrorism and Security at Queen's University, “Is more better or worse? New empirics on nuclear proliferation and interstate conflict by Random Forests,” Research and Politics, SagePub</p><p><u><strong>Given these conflict-reducing/provoking effects of nuclear proliferation, what overall effect would</u></strong> nuclear <u><strong>prolif</u></strong>eration <u><strong>have on a systemic propensity for conflict?</u></strong> This is difficult to answer, not only due to the controversy over whether nuclear states are more or less prone to conflict, but also because the existing theories do not explain whether those conflict-reducing/provoking effects are large enough to influence a systemic propensity for interstate conflict, given the ratio of nuclear states to non-nuclear states in the system. <u><strong>This challenge motivates the empirical examination</u></strong> of the relationship between nuclear proliferation and a systemic propensity for conflict.</p><p>Empirical investigation by Random Forests</p><p>The interstate–systemic year data are used here to investigate the relationship between nuclear proliferation and a systemic propensity for interstate conflict. The dependent variable is the number of militarized interstate dispute onsets (Palmer et al., 2015; version 4.01 is used) per systemic-year, standardized as the ratio to the number of states in the interstate system (Correlates of War Project, 2011) – hereafter, the ‘dispute–state ratio’. Observations one year ahead (t+1) are used to make sure that causal effects precede a variation in the dispute–state ratio.2</p><p>Two regressors are used to examine the effect of nuclear proliferation: the number of nuclear states in the interstate system; and a count of the years since the number of nuclear states changes (hereafter ‘nuclear year counter’), measuring the effect of new nuclear states (Horowitz, 2009). The data about nuclear states are from Gartzke and Kroenig (2009); additionally, the current paper codes North Korea as a nuclear state since 2009 (Table 1).3</p><p>The model also includes the number of democratic states (Polity2 score ⩾ 6 in Marshall, 2013) in the interstate system, the gross world product (Earth Policy Institute, 2012), and the binary variable of unipolarity (coded zero until 1989 and one from 1990; see Monteiro, 2011/2012); these three variables control for democratic peace (Russett and Oneal, 2001), capitalist peace (Gartzke, 2007), and polarity (Monteiro, 2011/2012) respectively. The number of nuclear states and these control variables suffer from multicollinearity (see Table A-9 in the online appendix), and this paer later explains how to resolve this problem. A lagged dependent variable is also included to address the temporal dependence of time-series data. The temporal scope is 1950–2009 (i.e. N=59) due to the data availability and the use of the dependent variable at t+1. The descriptive statistics of all variables are displayed in Table 2.4.</p><p>As mentioned in the introduction, this paper uses the machine learning, non-parametric method Random Forests for the empirical investigation.5 Although it is unfamiliar to most political science and international relations analysts, Random Forests has been widely used in numerous scientific studies (Strobl et al., 2009: 324; Strobl et al., 2008). The popularity of the method is also apparent from the fact that Breiman’s (2001) original paper has been cited 12,721 times in the literature.6</p><p>Random Forests generates two useful analytics: first, ‘conditional variable importance’ measures how ‘important’ each regressor is, conditional on the remaining regressors (Hothorn et al., 2006; Strobl et al., 2007, 2008). This is analogous to statistical significance in conventional regression models. The significance threshold proposed by Strobl et al. (2009: 343) is whether the importance score of a regressor is negative, zero, or lower than the absolute value of the lowest negative score. If none applies, the regressor is considered as important; and the second relevant analytic is a partial dependence plot (Friedman, 2001). This estimates the marginal effect of each regressor on the dependent variable while taking the remaining regressors into consideration.</p><p>Random Forests has three attractive and distinctive characteristics for the purposes of this paper: first, the estimation of conditional variable importance and partial dependence plots enable conventional applied researchers to interpret non-parametric analysis in an intuitive way; second, <u><strong><mark>Random Forests</mark> can <mark>examine non-linearity</u></strong></mark> (Strobl et al., 2009: 339–341), <u><strong>which is desirable because</u></strong>, as already noted, <u><strong>some theories expect non-linearity between nuclear proliferation and</u></strong> a systemic <u><strong>propensity for conflict</u></strong>; and <u><strong>finally</u></strong>, <u><strong><mark>it can cope with</mark> potential <mark>interactions and multicollinearity between regressors</u></strong></mark> (Strobl et al., 2009: 339–341; Strobl et al., 2008). As noted before, <u><strong>most</u></strong> of the <u><strong>regressors here are highly correlated, and</u></strong> also <u><strong>it is plausible to anticipate some interaction</u></strong> effect between them (<u><strong><mark>e.g.</u></strong></mark> the number of <u><strong><mark>democratic states and</u></strong></mark> the <u><strong><mark>g</u></strong></mark>ross <u><strong><mark>w</u></strong></mark>orld <u><strong><mark>p</u></strong></mark>roduct). <u><strong>The <mark>specific capabilities of Random Forests are</mark> therefore <mark>essential</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>The estimation of conditional variable importance shows that the nuclear year counter has a negative importance score.7 Thus, the nuclear year counter is not important in explaining the dispute–state ratio. This suggests that <u><strong><mark>the optimist theory is supported</u></strong></mark>. The remaining regressors have an importance score higher than the absolute value of the importance score of the nuclear year counter, meaning that they are all important. <u><strong><mark>Controlling for democratic</mark> peace, <mark>capitalist peace, and polarity</u></strong></mark>, <u><strong><mark>the number of nuclear states is</mark> still <mark>a significant predictor in explaining</mark> a systemic propensity for <mark>interstate conflict</mark>.</p><p></u></strong>Figure 1 presents the partial dependence plots of the model.8 First, on average, a larger number of nuclear states is associated with a lower dispute–state ratio, although the changes from two nuclear states to three and from six to seven increase the ratio instead. Thus, <u><strong><mark>the relationship is empirically non-linear</u></strong></mark>, as Bueno de Mesquita and Riker (1982) and Intriligator and Brito (1981) expected in part. <u><strong>Overall</u></strong>, however, <u><strong>the optimist theory is supported, and the change from two nuclear states to nine nuclear states decreases the dispute–state ratio</u></strong> approximately from 0.228 to 0.18. This means that, if there are 194 states in the system (as there were in 2009), <u><strong>the number of militarized interstate dispute onsets per system-year decreases</u></strong> approximately from 44 to 35. <u><strong>This is a substantively significant decline.</p><p></u></strong>Second, the nuclear year counter shows a concave relationship with the dispute–state ratio, suggesting that new nuclear states are less prone to conflict than middle-aged nuclear states. Thus, <u><strong><mark>the pessimist theory finds no support</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>from either</u></strong> the <u><strong>variable importance estimation or the partial dependence plot</u></strong>.</p><p>Finally, as for the control variables, the number of democratic states and the gross world product have a complex non-linear relationship with the dispute–state ratio, but <u><strong>if the number of democratic states and the g</u></strong>ross <u><strong>w</u></strong>orld <u><strong>p</u></strong>roduct <u><strong>are sufficiently large, they</u></strong> tend to <u><strong>decrease the dispute–state ratio</u></strong>. <u><strong>Their</u></strong> substantive <u><strong>effects are</u></strong> also <u><strong>significant, though not as much as the number of nuclear states.</u></strong> When comparing the effect of their lowest and highest values (23 and 94 in the number of democratic states and 7 and 71.2 in the gross world product), the number of democratic states decreases the number of militarized interstate dispute onsets per system-year approximately from 40 to 37, and the gross world product from 44 to 37. <u><strong>Unipolarity is also associated with a decline</u></strong> in the dispute–state ratio, suggesting that unipolarity is better than bipolarity in terms of a systemic propensity for interstate conflict; <u><strong>however, its effect is negligible</u></strong>, as it reduces the number of militarized interstate dispute onsets per system-year from 39 to 38. One caveat is, as explained in the online appendix, that the results of the number of democratic states and unipolarity are significantly sensitive to a parameter setting. Thus, these predictors are less robust, and the aforementioned points about them should be treated with caution.</p><p>Discussion and concluding remarks</p><p><u><strong><mark>The</mark> main <mark>findings reveal</mark> that <mark>the optimist expectation</mark> of the relationship <mark>between nuclear proliferation and interstate conflict is empirically supported</u></strong></mark>:9 <u><strong>first, <mark>a larger number of nuclear states</u></strong></mark> on average <u><strong><mark>decreases</mark> the</u></strong> systemic <u><strong>propensity for interstate <mark>conflict</u></strong>; <u><strong></mark>and</u></strong> second, <u><strong>there is no clear evidence that the emergence of new nuclear states increases the systemic propensity for interstate conflict</u></strong>. Gartzke and Jo (2009) argue that <u><strong>nuclear weapons</u></strong> themselves <u><strong>have no exogenous effect on the probability of conflict, because when a state is engaged in</u></strong> or expects to engage in <u><strong>conflict, it may develop nuclear weapons</u></strong> to keep fighting, or to prepare for, that conflict. If this selection effect existed, the analysis should overestimate the conflict-provoking effect of nuclear proliferation in the above model. Still, the results indicate that a larger number of nuclear states are associated with fewer disputes in the system.</p><p><u><strong>This conclusion</u></strong>, however, <u><strong>raises questions about how to reconcile this study’s findings with those of a recent quantitative dyadic-level study</u></strong> (<u><strong>Bell and Miller</u></strong>, 2015). The current paper finds that nuclear proliferation decreases the systemic propensity for interstate conflict, while Bell and Miller (2015) find that nuclear symmetry has no significant effect on dyadic conflict, but that nuclear asymmetry is associated with a higher probability of dyadic conflict. <u><strong>It is possible that nuclear proliferation decreases conflict through the conflict-mitigating effects of extended nuclear deterrence and/or fear of nuclear states’ intervention, to the extent that these effects overwhelm the conflict-provoking effect of nuclear–asymmetrical dyads</u></strong>. Thus<mark>, <u><strong>dyadic-level empirics cannot</mark> solely <mark>be relied on</u></strong> <u><strong>to infer causal links</u></strong></mark> between nuclear proliferation and a systemic propensity for conflict. The <u><strong>systemic-level empirics deserve attention</u></strong>.</p> | null | 1NC | Nuclear Forensics ADV | 3,078 | 648 | 105,316 | ./documents/hspolicy18/MontgomeryBellAcademy/HaRa/Montgomery%20Bell%20Academy-Harrington-Rankin-Neg-Michigan-Round3.docx | 697,757 | N | Michigan | 3 | Northside OP | Jack Kussman | 1AC New Nuclear Scientists Aff
2NR Courts CP and DACA DA | hspolicy18/MontgomeryBellAcademy/HaRa/Montgomery%20Bell%20Academy-Harrington-Rankin-Neg-Michigan-Round3.docx | null | 59,328 | HaRa | Montgomery Bell Academy HaRa | null | Ja..... | Ha..... | Ja..... | Ra..... | 20,916 | MontgomeryBellAcademy | Montgomery Bell Academy | null | null | 1,017 | hspolicy18 | HS Policy 2018-19 | 2,018 | cx | hs | 2 |
2,722,472 | Alliance instability causes military autonomy---causes extinction and reverses solvency | Fatton 19 | Fatton 19, [Lionel P. Fatton* Webster University Geneva; Research Institute for the History of Global Arms Transfer, Meiji University, A new spear in Asia: why is Japan moving toward autonomous defense?, International Relations of the Asia-Pacific Volume 19, (2019) 297–325 doi: 10.1093/irap/lcy006 Advance Access Publication 3 April 2018] | evolutions of Japan’s defense posture could have destabilizing consequences for Asia high distrust, if not hostility portended spiraling tensions caused by action– reaction dynamics between competitive defensive measures The US–Japan alliance mitigated this security dilemma by guaranteeing Japan’s survival and acting as a ‘bottle cap’ on resurgence of Japanese militarism militarily more autonomous and powerful Japan would alarm China. The ‘egg shell’ perception, which gained momentum in Beijing posits the alliance is an incubator of Japanese rearm would strengthen Not only would Sino-Japanese relations deteriorate due to prospect of Japan’s revival US–China relations would also be undermined by Beijing’s recognition of the alliance as destabilizing autonomous Japan does not only raise prospect of military clash with China in E C S it increases likelihood of Sino-American war. The alliance could become the thread between an emotionally-charged territorial dispute and cataclysmic great power conflict half of heaven would fall if Japan and China were to fight each other the whole heaven would collapse if the U S were embroiled. | hostility portended spiraling action– reaction dynamics The alliance mitigated security dilemma by guaranteeing Japan’s survival acting as a ‘bottle cap’ on militarism militarily autonomous Japan would alarm China. The ‘egg shell perception gained momentum in Beijing posits the alliance is an incubator of rearm Sino-Japanese relations deteriorate US–China relations would be undermined by recognition of the alliance as destabilizing autonomous Japan raise prospect of military clash with China in E C S it increases likelihood of cataclysmic great power conflict the whole heaven would collapse if the U S were embroiled | The evolutions of Japan’s defense posture could have destabilizing consequences for the Asia-Pacific region as well. The high level of distrust, if not hostility, between China and Japan since the end of the Second World War has portended spiraling tensions caused by action– reaction dynamics between competitive defensive measures (Samuels, 2007). The US–Japan alliance has mitigated this security dilemma by guaranteeing Japan’s survival and acting as a ‘bottle cap’ on the resurgence of Japanese militarism (Christensen, 2011, 236). A militarily more autonomous and powerful Japan would alarm China. The ‘egg shell’ perception, which has gained momentum in Beijing since the mid-1990s and posits that the alliance is an incubator of Japanese rearmament, would strengthen (Christensen, 2011, 236). Not only would Sino-Japanese relations deteriorate due to the prospect of Japan’s revival as a great power, US–China relations would also be undermined by Beijing’s recognition of the alliance as a destabilizing factor. The United States and China, the world’s two largest economic and military powers, are widely regarded as holding the faith of the Asia-Pacific region. Japan is often dropped out of the equation despite its disruptive potential. A more autonomous Japan does not only raise the prospect of a military clash with China in the East China Sea, it also increases the likelihood of a Sino-American war. The US–Japan alliance could become the thread between an emotionally-charged territorial dispute and what would be a cataclysmic great power conflict (Miller, 2015). Deng Xiaoping said in the late 1970s that half of heaven would fall if Japan and China were to fight each other. Today, the whole heaven would collapse if the United States were embroiled. | 1,772 | <h4>Alliance instability causes <u>military autonomy</u>---causes <u>extinction</u> and <u>reverses</u> solvency</h4><p><strong>Fatton 19<u></strong>, [Lionel P. Fatton* Webster University Geneva; Research Institute for the History of Global Arms Transfer, Meiji University, A new spear in Asia: why is Japan moving toward autonomous defense?, International Relations of the Asia-Pacific Volume 19, (2019) 297–325 doi: 10.1093/irap/lcy006 Advance Access Publication 3 April 2018]</p><p></u>The <u>evolutions of Japan’s defense posture could have <strong>destabilizing consequences</strong> for</u> the <u>Asia</u>-Pacific region as well. The <u>high</u> level of <u>distrust, if not <mark>hostility</u></mark>, between China and Japan since the end of the Second World War has <u><mark>portended <strong>spiraling </strong></mark>tensions caused by <strong><mark>action– reaction dynamics</strong></mark> between competitive defensive measures</u> (Samuels, 2007). <u><mark>The</u></mark> <u>US–Japan <mark>alliance</u></mark> has <u><strong><mark>mitigated</strong></mark> this <strong><mark>security dilemma </strong>by <strong>guaranteeing </strong>Japan’s <strong>survival</mark> </strong>and <mark>acting as a <strong>‘bottle cap’ </strong>on</u></mark> the <u><strong>resurgence </strong>of Japanese <strong><mark>militarism</mark> </u></strong>(Christensen, 2011, 236). A <u><mark>militarily</mark> more <mark>autonomous</mark> and powerful <mark>Japan would <strong>alarm China</strong>. The ‘<strong>egg shell</strong></mark>’ <mark>perception</mark>, which</u> has <u><strong><mark>gained momentum</strong></mark> <mark>in Beijing</u></mark> since the mid-1990s and <u><mark>posits</u></mark> that <u><mark>the alliance is an <strong>incubator </strong>of <strong></mark>Japanese <mark>rearm</u></strong></mark>ament, <u>would <strong>strengthen </u></strong>(Christensen, 2011, 236). <u>Not only would <mark>Sino-Japanese relations <strong>deteriorate</u></strong></mark> <u>due to</u> the <u><strong>prospect </strong>of Japan’s revival</u> as a great power, <u><strong><mark>US–China relations </strong>would</mark> also <mark>be <strong>undermined</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>by </mark>Beijing’s <mark>recognition of the alliance as</u></mark> a <u><strong><mark>destabilizing</u></strong></mark> factor. The United States and China, the world’s two largest economic and military powers, are widely regarded as holding the faith of the Asia-Pacific region. Japan is often dropped out of the equation despite its disruptive potential. A more <u><mark>autonomous Japan</mark> does not only <strong><mark>raise</mark> </u></strong>the <u><strong><mark>prospect </strong>of</u></mark> a <u><strong><mark>military clash </strong>with China in</u></mark> the <u><strong><mark>E</u></strong></mark>ast <u><strong><mark>C</u></strong></mark>hina <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>ea, <u><mark>it</u></mark> also <u><strong><mark>increases</mark> </u></strong>the <u><mark>likelihood of</u></mark> a <u>Sino-American war. The</u> US–Japan <u>alliance could become the thread between an emotionally-charged territorial dispute and</u> what would be a <u><strong><mark>cataclysmic great power conflict</mark> </u></strong>(Miller, 2015). Deng Xiaoping said in the late 1970s that <u>half of heaven would fall if Japan and China were to fight each other</u>. Today, <u><mark>the <strong>whole heaven would collapse</strong> if the</u></mark> <u><strong><mark>U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates <u><mark>were <strong>embroiled</strong></mark>.</p></u> | 1NC v Taiwan | 3 | null | 82,326 | 281 | 86,593 | ./documents/hspolicy19/Interlake/WuCa/Interlake-Wu-Cai-Neg-Alta-Doubles.docx | 713,103 | N | Alta | Doubles | CK McClatchy BG | Panel | 1AC - Taiwan
1NC - T-Subs Deterrence CP Alliances DA Prolif Good Nuclear energy CT
2NR - Deterrence CP Prolif Good CBW CT | hspolicy19/Interlake/WuCa/Interlake-Wu-Cai-Neg-Alta-Doubles.docx | null | 60,796 | WuCa | Interlake WuCa | null | Si..... | Wu..... | Ne..... | Ca..... | 21,240 | Interlake | Interlake | WA | null | 1,018 | hspolicy19 | HS Policy 2019-20 | 2,019 | cx | hs | 2 |
3,869,826 | [Greene and Hicks 6]Studies prove debate is inevitably implicated in the context of propaganda – voting aff aligns with a model predicated on communist base-building. | Greene and Hicks ‘6 | Greene and Hicks ‘6
[Ronald Greene, former Chair of the Critical and Cultural Studies Division of the National Communication Association, and Darrin Hicks, communication studies at the University of Denver. 2006. “Lost convictions: Debating both sides and the ethical self-fashioning of liberal citizens,” https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/abs/10.1080/09502380500040928] pat | the Army Information and Education Group was conducting experiments testing the relationship between inducement and internalized attitude change Hovland Janis and Kelley published their highly influential book Communication and Persuasion which established a positive relation between verbalization and the intensification of belief and predicted that being forced to overtly defend a position discrepant from one’s own private beliefs would result in the internalization of the overtly defended position The fear that defending the diplomatic recognition of ‘Red China’ would turn American youth into Communist sympathizers saturated the debating both sides controversy with an anxiety over the virility of ‘democratic faith’ Debate in particular the format of debating both sides of controversial issues embodied the sort of political conflict that could engender sound conviction and a committed youth impervious to Communist propaganda For Schlesinger, however, the ground of the anti-Communist consensus Baird believed to be evident in ‘the majority of students’ was unstable | the A I E G established relation between verbalization intensification of belief and internalization of the defended position The fear of Communist sympathizers saturated debating both sides with anxiety over ‘democratic faith’ Debate embodied the political conflict that could engender a committed youth impervious to Communist propaganda however, the anti-Communist consensus was unstable | Concurrently, the Army Information and Education Group, which would become the core of the Hovland-Yale Communication and Persuasion Group, led by Carl Hovland, was conducting experiments testing the relationship between inducement and internalized attitude change. In 1953, Hovland, Janis, and Kelley published their highly influential book Communication and Persuasion, which established a positive relation between verbalization and the intensification of belief and predicted that being forced to overtly defend a position discrepant from one’s own private beliefs would result in the internalization of the overtly defended position. This prediction was further supported by the forced-compliance and cognitive dissonance studies of Festinger (1957) and his colleagues at Stanford. For decades, the ability to understand the merits of opposing arguments had been championed as one of the prime pedagogical benefits of intercollegiate debate training. However, in the fall of 1954, Hovland’s and Festinger’s studies coupled with the anti- Communist rhetoric of Schlesinger, which would, much to Schlesinger’s dismay, come to underwrite McCarthy’s witch hunts, would be articulated in such a way that debate’s ability to train students to take the other’s perspective might be framed as a threat to national security. The fear that defending the diplomatic recognition of ‘Red China’ would turn American youth into Communist sympathizers saturated the debating both sides controversy with an anxiety over the virility of ‘democratic faith’. Those choosing to defend the virtues of intercollegiate debate and the practice of debating both sides were careful not to question the basic tenets of the anti-Communism that constituted the ideological core of Cold War liberalism. Democracy, if it were to survive the seductive appeal of totalitarianism, had to become a fighting faith, a faith born out of and tested in social and political conflict. Debate, in particular the format of debating both sides of controversial issues embodied the sort of political conflict that could engender sound conviction, rational decisions, and a committed youth impervious to Communist propaganda. Moreover, debate provided the antidote to communist propaganda. Baird concluded, ‘[c]ollege debate teams are the last groups in this nation where Communist propaganda has any chance of making headway’ (1955, p. 7). No student wishing to win the debate, Burns argued, ‘would take the affirmative on the grounds that we must love the Chinese or that they are merely agrarian radicals’ (p. 7). Burns, so confident in the anti-Communist sentiment of the majority of students, contended that no student would dare argue in favour of Communism but ‘pitch his [sic ] case on the argument that recognition might help pull China out of the Moscow orbit, that it might help build a firmer anti-Communist alliance, that it might make peaceful coexistence possible. He [sic ] would, in short, be directing our attention to the very questions that all American’s might well be debating’ (p. 7). For Schlesinger, however, the ground of the anti-Communist consensus Baird believed to be evident in ‘the majority of students’ was unstable | 3,206 | <h4>[Greene and Hicks 6]Studies prove debate is <u>inevitably implicated</u> in the context of propaganda – voting aff aligns with a model predicated on <u>communist base-building</u>.<strong> </h4><p>Greene and Hicks ‘6</p><p></strong>[Ronald Greene, former Chair of the Critical and Cultural Studies Division of the National Communication Association, and Darrin Hicks, communication studies at the University of Denver. 2006. “Lost convictions: Debating both sides and the ethical self-fashioning of liberal citizens,” https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/abs/10.1080/09502380500040928] pat</p><p>Concurrently, <u><mark>the <strong>A</strong></mark>rmy <strong><mark>I</strong></mark>nformation and <strong><mark>E</strong></mark>ducation <strong><mark>G</strong></mark>roup</u>, which would become the core of the Hovland-Yale Communication and Persuasion Group, led by Carl Hovland, <u>was conducting experiments testing the relationship between inducement and internalized attitude change</u>. In 1953, <u>Hovland</u>, <u>Janis</u>, <u>and Kelley published their highly influential book Communication and Persuasion</u>, <u>which <mark>established</mark> a positive <mark>relation between verbalization</mark> and the <mark>intensification of belief and</mark> predicted that being forced to overtly defend a position discrepant from one’s own private beliefs would result in the <mark>internalization of the</mark> overtly <mark>defended position</u></mark>. This prediction was further supported by the forced-compliance and cognitive dissonance studies of Festinger (1957) and his colleagues at Stanford. For decades, the ability to understand the merits of opposing arguments had been championed as one of the prime pedagogical benefits of intercollegiate debate training. However, in the fall of 1954, Hovland’s and Festinger’s studies coupled with the anti- Communist rhetoric of Schlesinger, which would, much to Schlesinger’s dismay, come to underwrite McCarthy’s witch hunts, would be articulated in such a way that debate’s ability to train students to take the other’s perspective might be framed as a threat to national security. <u><mark>The fear</mark> that defending the diplomatic recognition <mark>of</mark> ‘Red China’ would turn American youth into <mark>Communist sympathizers saturated</mark> the <mark>debating both sides</mark> controversy <mark>with</mark> an <mark>anxiety over</mark> the virility of <mark>‘democratic faith’</u></mark>. Those choosing to defend the virtues of intercollegiate debate and the practice of debating both sides were careful not to question the basic tenets of the anti-Communism that constituted the ideological core of Cold War liberalism. Democracy, if it were to survive the seductive appeal of totalitarianism, had to become a fighting faith, a faith born out of and tested in social and political conflict. <u><mark>Debate</u></mark>, <u>in particular the format of debating both sides of controversial issues <mark>embodied the</mark> sort of <mark>political conflict that could engender</mark> sound conviction</u>, rational decisions, <u>and <mark>a committed youth impervious to Communist propaganda</u></mark>. Moreover, debate provided the antidote to communist propaganda. Baird concluded, ‘[c]ollege debate teams are the last groups in this nation where Communist propaganda has any chance of making headway’ (1955, p. 7). No student wishing to win the debate, Burns argued, ‘would take the affirmative on the grounds that we must love the Chinese or that they are merely agrarian radicals’ (p. 7). Burns, so confident in the anti-Communist sentiment of the majority of students, contended that no student would dare argue in favour of Communism but ‘pitch his [sic ] case on the argument that recognition might help pull China out of the Moscow orbit, that it might help build a firmer anti-Communist alliance, that it might make peaceful coexistence possible. He [sic ] would, in short, be directing our attention to the very questions that all American’s might well be debating’ (p. 7). <u><strong>For Schlesinger, <mark>however, the</mark> ground of the <mark>anti-Communist consensus</mark> Baird believed to be evident in ‘the majority of students’ <mark>was unstable</p></u></strong></mark> | null | null | null | 5,756 | 183 | 129,026 | ./documents/hsld22/Hamilton/AlLi/Hamilton-AlLi-Aff-Mid-America-Cup-Triples.docx | 929,736 | A | Mid America Cup | Triples | Independent Hamilton Alexis Li | Anderson,Lampman,Sanjrani | 1AC- Marx Aff
1NC- Case
1AC- Case
2NR- Case
2AR- Case | hsld22/Hamilton/AlLi/Hamilton-AlLi-Aff-Mid-America-Cup-Triples.docx | 2022-09-25 23:39:24 | 80,533 | AlLi | Hamilton AlLi | null | Al..... | Li..... | null | null | 27,042 | Hamilton | Hamilton | AZ | null | 2,003 | hsld22 | HS LD 2022-23 | 2,022 | ld | hs | 1 |
2,303,832 | LAW ban stifles AI R&D | New 18 | New 18 [(Joshua New - senior policy analyst at the Center for Data Innovation) “Fighting Military AI Research Underminess Social and Economic Progress” Center for Data Innovation. 10-19-18] LM | propaganda that stigmatizes incredibly valuable AI research done by defense agencies–research that will have broad social benefits beyond just defense applications. Defense (R&D) activities have long played a crucial role in the U.S. innovation ecosystem investments in AI will be no different should policymakers succumb to baseless fears that military AI research will lead to a dystopian world , it will set back important AI research
fear of autonomous weapons , engenders apprehension for AI R&D efforts that could conceivably be used in an autonomous weapon. Google opted to not renew a contract with the Pentagon for Project Maven, to develop better computer vision algorithms to analyze drone video,
these concerns overshadow the vast amount of valuable AI research taking place in U.S. defense agencies. (DARPA) alone is investing heavily in AI R&D efforts that could generate crucial breakthroughs that would benefit broad swathes of AI applications beyond military ones. DARPA allocated $75 million for its Explainable AI (XAI) program to spur breakthroughs in machine learning Explainable AI would be enormously beneficial for applications ranging from judicial decision-making to medical diagnostic software, and would alleviate concerns about the potential for AI to be biased and unfairly discriminate with common sense would be an enormous boon to practically every conceivable application of AI, enabling it to intuit, The list of broadly useful AI R&D initiatives at DARPA is long, including using AI to discover new molecules that could lead to new medical treatments,
These R&D efforts will benefit the military’s use of AI, but will also benefit applications that generate social and economic value in countless ways. Resisting efforts is fundamentally a disagreement about the ethics of defense activities and warfare. has its place in policymaking, but sabotaging important AI research that can serve the public good as a means of avoiding confronting these issues head on is counterproductive and will harm innovation.
AI research in defense can create immeasurable benefits that can be broadly enjoyed by the public and shying away from these efforts will leave Americans worse off. | AI research done by defense agencies will have broad social benefits beyond defense (R&D) activities have played a crucial role in U.S. innovation baseless fears that military AI will lead to a dystopian world set back important AI research
fear of autonomous weapons engenders apprehension for AI R&D
concerns overshadow vast amount of valuable AI research AI would be beneficial for applications ranging from judicial to medical diagnostic and | In November 2017, an advocacy group called the Campaign to Stop Killer Robots published a short film called “Slaughterbots” in which autonomous drones developed by the military-industrial complex terrorize and kill innocent civilians. Though compelling, Slaughterbots is disingenuous propaganda that stigmatizes incredibly valuable AI research done by defense agencies–research that will have broad social and economic benefits beyond just defense applications. Defense research and development (R&D) activities have long played a crucial role in the U.S. innovation ecosystem and have been responsible for many widely-used technologies today, including the Internet, GPS, and smartphones. Defense agencies’ investments in AI will be no different, yet should policymakers succumb to baseless fears that military AI research will lead to a dystopian world full of killer robots, it will set back important AI research poised to deliver many benefits to Americans.
Though the Campaign to Stop Killer Robots and others typically only call for the ban on “fully autonomous weapons,” this is not nearly so clean cut of an issue and would significantly hinder innovation. The development of any fully autonomous system, whether it be a self-driving car or a military drone, would rely on huge amounts of R&D into its various components: navigation algorithms, computer vision algorithms, facial recognition algorithms, and others, depending on its function. Thus, fear of autonomous weapons, stoked by propaganda like “Slaughterbots” and pundits hand-wringing about “runaway AI” alike, engenders apprehension for AI R&D efforts that could conceivably be used in an autonomous weapon. Case in point, Google earlier this year opted to not renew a contract with the Pentagon for Project Maven, an initiative to develop better computer vision algorithms to analyze drone video, after facing significant backlash due to the fact that the technology could conceivably be used to help automate drone strikes.
Unfortunately, these concerns overshadow the vast amount of valuable AI research taking place in U.S. defense agencies. The Defense Advanced Research Projects Agency (DARPA) alone is investing heavily in AI R&D efforts that could generate crucial breakthroughs that would benefit broad swathes of AI applications beyond military ones. For example, in 2017, DARPA allocated $75 million for its Explainable AI (XAI) program to spur breakthroughs in machine learning techniques that could explain themselves or be more interpretable by humans without sacrificing performance (there can be as-of-yet inescapable tradeoffs between accuracy and interpretability for advanced machine learning systems). Explainable AI would be enormously beneficial for applications ranging from judicial decision-making to medical diagnostic software, and would alleviate pervasive concerns about the potential for AI to be biased and unfairly discriminate. Just recently, DARPA also announced its Machine Common Sense program, which aims to improve AI’s ability to understand the world and communicate naturally, as AI currently can only understand and evaluate very narrow types of problems that do not require outside knowledge. AI with common sense would be an enormous boon to practically every conceivable application of AI, enabling it to intuit, for example, that solid objects cannot pass through one another, which AI expert Oren Etzioni describes as the “holy grail of AI for 35 years or more.” The list of broadly useful AI R&D initiatives at DARPA is long, including using AI to discover new molecules that could lead to new medical treatments, using AI and smartphones to conduct ongoing, passive health monitoring, and using AI to uncover and account for bias in datasets.
These and other projects are part of DARPA’s “AI Next” campaign, a $2 billion initiative to “advance the state-of-the-art” in AI. These R&D efforts will benefit the military’s use of AI, to be sure, but will also benefit applications that generate social and economic value in countless ways. Resisting such efforts due to their potential military application is fundamentally a disagreement about the ethics of defense activities and warfare. Debating how nations should govern and use autonomous weapons has its place in policymaking, but sabotaging important AI research that can serve the public good as a means of avoiding confronting these issues head on is counterproductive and will harm innovation.
There are compelling reasons to pursue the development of AI explicitly for defense purposes, as countries such as China and Russia develop autonomous systems of their own. However, as policymakers responsible for funding the federal government’s R&D activities evaluate agency budgets, they should be careful to recognize that this technology is not just about killer robots: AI research in defense can create immeasurable benefits that can be broadly enjoyed by the public and shying away from these efforts will leave Americans worse off. | 5,010 | <h4>LAW ban stifles AI R&D</h4><p><strong>New 18</strong> [(Joshua New - senior policy analyst at the Center for Data Innovation) “Fighting Military AI Research Underminess Social and Economic Progress” Center for Data Innovation. 10-19-18] LM</p><p>In November 2017, an advocacy group called the Campaign to Stop Killer Robots published a short film called “Slaughterbots” in which autonomous drones developed by the military-industrial complex terrorize and kill innocent civilians. Though compelling, Slaughterbots is disingenuous <u><strong>propaganda that stigmatizes incredibly valuable <mark>AI research done by defense agencies</mark>–research that <mark>will have broad social</mark> </u></strong>and economic <u><strong><mark>benefits beyond</mark> just <mark>defense</mark> applications. Defense</u></strong> research and development<u><strong> <mark>(R&D) activities have </mark>long <mark>played a crucial role in </mark>the <mark>U.S. innovation </mark>ecosystem </u></strong>and have been responsible for many widely-used technologies today, including the Internet, GPS, and smartphones. Defense agencies’ <u><strong>investments in AI will be no different</u></strong>, yet <u><strong>should policymakers succumb to <mark>baseless fears that military AI</mark> research <mark>will lead to a dystopian</mark> <mark>world</u></strong></mark> full of killer robots<u><strong>, it will <mark>set back important AI research</u></strong></mark> poised to deliver many benefits to Americans.</p><p>Though the Campaign to Stop Killer Robots and others typically only call for the ban on “fully autonomous weapons,” this is not nearly so clean cut of an issue and would significantly hinder innovation. The development of any fully autonomous system, whether it be a self-driving car or a military drone, would rely on huge amounts of R&D into its various components: navigation algorithms, computer vision algorithms, facial recognition algorithms, and others, depending on its function. Thus, <u><strong><mark>fear of autonomous weapons</u></strong></mark>, stoked by propaganda like “Slaughterbots” and pundits hand-wringing about “runaway AI” alike<u><strong>, <mark>engenders apprehension for AI R&D </mark>efforts that could conceivably be used in an autonomous weapon. </u></strong>Case in point, <u><strong>Google</u></strong> earlier this year <u><strong>opted to not renew a contract with the Pentagon for Project Maven,</u></strong> an initiative <u><strong>to develop better computer vision algorithms to analyze drone video, </u></strong>after facing significant backlash due to the fact that the technology could conceivably be used to help automate drone strikes.</p><p>Unfortunately, <u><strong>these <mark>concerns overshadow</mark> the <mark>vast amount of valuable AI research</mark> taking place in U.S. defense agencies.</u></strong> The Defense Advanced Research Projects Agency <u><strong>(DARPA) alone is investing heavily in AI R&D efforts that could generate crucial breakthroughs that would benefit broad swathes of AI applications beyond military ones.</u></strong> For example, in 2017, <u><strong>DARPA allocated $75 million for its Explainable AI (XAI) program to spur breakthroughs in machine learning</u></strong> techniques that could explain themselves or be more interpretable by humans without sacrificing performance (there can be as-of-yet inescapable tradeoffs between accuracy and interpretability for advanced machine learning systems). <u><strong>Explainable <mark>AI would be</mark> enormously <mark>beneficial for applications ranging from judicial</mark> decision-making <mark>to medical diagnostic</mark> software, <mark>and</mark> would alleviate</u></strong> pervasive <u><strong>concerns about the potential for AI to be biased and unfairly discriminate</u></strong>. Just recently, DARPA also announced its Machine Common Sense program, which aims to improve AI’s ability to understand the world and communicate naturally, as AI currently can only understand and evaluate very narrow types of problems that do not require outside knowledge. AI <u><strong>with common sense would be an enormous boon to practically every conceivable application of AI, enabling it to intuit, </u></strong>for example, that solid objects cannot pass through one another, which AI expert Oren Etzioni describes as the “holy grail of AI for 35 years or more.” <u><strong>The list of broadly useful AI R&D initiatives at DARPA is long, including using AI to discover new molecules that could lead to new medical treatments, </u></strong>using AI and smartphones to conduct ongoing, passive health monitoring, and using AI to uncover and account for bias in datasets.</p><p>These and other projects are part of DARPA’s “AI Next” campaign, a $2 billion initiative to “advance the state-of-the-art” in AI. <u><strong>These R&D efforts will benefit the military’s use of AI,</u></strong> to be sure, <u><strong>but will also benefit applications that generate social and economic value in countless ways. Resisting</u></strong> such <u><strong>efforts</u></strong> due to their potential military application <u><strong>is fundamentally a disagreement about the ethics of defense activities and warfare.</u></strong> Debating how nations should govern and use autonomous weapons <u><strong>has its place in policymaking, but sabotaging important AI research that can serve the public good as a means of avoiding confronting these issues head on is counterproductive and will harm innovation.</p><p></u></strong>There are compelling reasons to pursue the development of AI explicitly for defense purposes, as countries such as China and Russia develop autonomous systems of their own. However, as policymakers responsible for funding the federal government’s R&D activities evaluate agency budgets, they should be careful to recognize that this technology is not just about killer robots: <u><strong>AI research in defense can create immeasurable benefits that can be broadly enjoyed by the public and shying away from these efforts will leave Americans worse off.</p></u></strong> | null | null | 3 | 72,426 | 440 | 72,595 | ./documents/hsld20/PalosVerdes/Ve/Palos%20Verdes-Velazquez-Neg-Peninsula%20Invitational-Round1.docx | 870,086 | N | Peninsula Invitational | 1 | Carnegie Vanguard SR | Fang, Justin | null | hsld20/PalosVerdes/Ve/Palos%20Verdes-Velazquez-Neg-Peninsula%20Invitational-Round1.docx | null | 73,611 | KaVe | Palos Verdes KaVe | null | Ka..... | Ve..... | null | null | 24,668 | PalosVerdes | Palos Verdes | CA | null | 1,028 | hsld20 | HS LD 2020-21 | 2,020 | ld | hs | 1 |
1,044,937 | US-Mexico economic relations solve renewables competitiveness. | Pascual et al. 21 | Carlos Pascual et al. 21, former US ambassador to Mexico; Angelica Ruiz, senior vice president for BP Latin America; David Crisostomo, director of energy futures at IHS Markit; Samantha Gross, director of energy security at Brookings Institution; Veronica Irastorza, associate director at NERA Economic Consulting; Alejandra León, associate director of research and analysis at IHS Markit; Jeremy Martin, vice president of energy and sustainability at Institute of the Americas; John McNeece, senior fellow for energy and trade at UC San Diego; Isabel Studer, president of the Board of the Mexican Climate Initiative; Lisa Viscidi, director of energy and climate change at Inter-American Dialogue; 3/3/2021, “U.S.-Mexico Forum 2025: Energy and Sustainability,” https://usmex.ucsd.edu/_files/usmex-forum-2025_report_energy.pdf, RMax | A Global Transformation Reaches Mexico and the United States
2020 was a pivot point for global energy global impact of COVID-19 forced countries around the world to assess how they will invest to rebuild their economies build back better for Biden’s Administration – encompasses necessity to confront climate crisis, and build infrastructure and economic incentives to create jobs fossil fuels in energy begun historic downward shift.
path to net-zero will be filled with uncertainty, but momentum has shifted and will touch most aspects of how every nation produces and consumes energy. Underpinning this shift have been commitments from 125 nations around the world
To succeed, countries will enter intense and accelerated legislative activity climate change will be central issue in U.S.-Mexico relationship under Biden Biden made climate change one of four priorities Mexico, as largest U.S. trade partner could benefit more from increased coordination with U S to grasp benefits of this transition than any other country in the world
At stake for Mexico and U S is can they adapt their energy to make them competitive, sustain growth, and create jobs in global economy committed to eliminate g g e
answer depends on whether Mexico and U S open door for cooperation on energy transition. Much will depend on how rule of law prevails in energy relationship between the two countries. disputes over private investment in renewables in Mexico and rights of U.S. investors in trade of refined products. Still, USMCA) is now in force and provides path to create transparent and predictable commercial relationships. No Party to the Agreement can modify its domestic legal framework or adopt measures in violation of its commitments under the USMCA without potentially facing claims under the general state to state or investorstate dispute settlement mechanisms. In addition, the reservations or exemptions to the energy obligations that each Party established in the Agreement, can only be modified in the future if they further liberalize; thus they cannot be made more restrictive. The administration of President Lopez Obrador may not accept this interpretation of the USMCA, and that could become an issue for both governments to address with urgency.
Mexico and U S with two of the most integrated manufacturing economies will remain intertwined as global energy transition unfolds energy policies that foster cross-border integration of renewable energy can propel global industrial competitiveness of both U S and Mexico.
Mexico and U S have geographic characteristics that make them first-in-class producers of renewable power. Mexico and U S have complementary fuel types and refining capabilities, and potential for sharing technical innovation. factors could facilitate greater integration of Mexican and U.S. energy systems, from upstream to refining, to achieve lower costs and higher productivity. | 2020 was a pivot fossil fuels begun downward shift
Underpinning this have been commitments from nations
climate will be central in U.S.-Mexico relationship under Biden Mexico benefit from coordination with U S
can they adapt energy to make them competitive
answer depends on whether Mexico and U S cooperat on energy
Mexico and U S remain intertwined cross-border integration of renewable energy propel global competitiveness
Mexico and U S make first class renewable power. sharing technical innovation | A Global Transformation Reaches Mexico and the United States
The year 2020 was a pivot point for the global energy system. For decades, fossil fuels met about 80 percent of the world’s primary energy demand. The global impact of COVID-19 – on economic growth, collapsing oil demand, lost lives, and the way we live and work – has forced countries around the world to assess how they will invest perhaps 15-25% of their GDP to rebuild their economies. The phrase “build back better” – a foundational premise for President Joseph Biden’s Administration – encompasses the necessity to embrace change, confront the climate crisis, and build the infrastructure and economic incentives to create jobs while ensuring resilience and sustainability. In 2020, oil demand declined 10%, world energy demand fell 6%, but the world consumed 9% more wind and solar power.1 The share of fossil fuels in the energy mix has begun an historic downward shift.
Globally, the path to net-zero will be filled with uncertainty, but the momentum has shifted and will touch most aspects of how every nation produces and consumes energy. Underpinning this shift have been commitments from about 125 nations around the world to net-zero emissions by 2050 (and 2060 for China). With the Biden Administration’s pledge to net-zero by 2050 and carbon-free power sector by 2035, the share of global emissions in countries with net-zero pledges will be 66%.2 In other words, two-thirds of the world’s emissions will be in countries committed to reduce them to a net annual balance of 0. Yet, few of these countries have policies, laws, and regulations in place that will allow them to achieve this goal.
To succeed, countries across the world will enter a period of intense and accelerated legislative and regulatory activity, to create the frameworks that drive investment and innovation in order to make net-zero a reality. That period of action will jump into high gear in 2021, as nations prepare for COP-26, the 26th session of the UN Framework Convention on Climate Change, where countries will establish new commitments under the Paris Accord. To be sure, climate change will be a central issue in the U.S.-Mexico relationship under the Biden Administration. President Biden has made climate change one of four priorities for his administration, the first U.S. president to do so. At home, Biden pledged to assess how climate penetrates all domestic investments, committing to ensure that all cities over 100,000 people have public transit systems, creating national infrastructure for electric vehicles, and banning new licenses for oil and gas production on public lands and waters. Mexico, as the largest U.S. trade partner and neighbor, could potentially benefit more from increased coordination with the United States to grasp the benefits of this transition than any other country in the world.
This paper explores areas for research and technology collaboration that could reduce emissions, and in the case of carbon capture and storage, also potentially extend the competitive lifespans of untapped hydrocarbon reserves in both countries. However, the converse of this dynamic is also a risk: both Mexico and the United States should expect that many countries, perhaps starting with Europe and extending to China with the world’s largest carbon market, will impose cross-border tariffs on the goods of exporting nations that do not share their climate ambitions. At stake for Mexico and the United States is this challenge: can they adapt their energy systems to make them competitive, sustain growth, and create jobs in a global economy committed to eliminate net greenhouse gas emissions?
The answer depends on whether Mexico and the United States open the door for cooperation on energy transition. Much will depend on how the rule of law prevails in the energy relationship between the two countries. There have been disputes over private investment in renewables in Mexico and the rights of U.S. investors in the trade of refined products. Still, the United States-Mexico-Canada Agreement (USMCA) is now in force and provides a path forward to create transparent and predictable commercial relationships. No Party to the Agreement can modify its domestic legal framework or adopt measures in violation of its commitments under the USMCA without potentially facing claims under the general state to state or investorstate dispute settlement mechanisms. In addition, the reservations or exemptions to the energy obligations that each Party established in the Agreement, can only be modified in the future if they further liberalize; thus they cannot be made more restrictive. The administration of President Lopez Obrador may not accept this interpretation of the USMCA, and that could become an issue for both governments to address with urgency.
Mexico and the United States, with two of the most integrated manufacturing economies in the world, will remain inextricably intertwined as the global energy transition unfolds. And in turn, energy policies that foster cross-border integration of fossil fuels and renewable energy capacity can propel the global industrial competitiveness of both the United States and Mexico.
The transformation potential cuts across the energy spectrum. Not only have solar and wind costs dropped precipitously in the past decade – 80% for solar PV and 50% for onshore wind3 – Mexico and the United States have geographic characteristics that make them first-in-class producers of renewable power. Even with the onset of peak oil demand, the decline rate of oil reservoirs combined with population growth and transportation demands in emerging economies suggest that the world will need by 2050 on the order of a new 45 MMb/d of oil.4 Mexico and the United States have complementary fuel types and refining capabilities, and the potential for sharing technical innovation. These factors could facilitate greater integration of Mexican and U.S. energy systems, from upstream to refining, to achieve lower costs and higher productivity. | 6,052 | <h4>US-Mexico economic relations solve <u>renewables competitiveness</u>.</h4><p>Carlos <strong>Pascual et al. 21</strong>, former US ambassador to Mexico; Angelica Ruiz, senior vice president for BP Latin America; David Crisostomo, director of energy futures at IHS Markit; Samantha Gross, director of energy security at Brookings Institution; Veronica Irastorza, associate director at NERA Economic Consulting; Alejandra León, associate director of research and analysis at IHS Markit; Jeremy Martin, vice president of energy and sustainability at Institute of the Americas; John McNeece, senior fellow for energy and trade at UC San Diego; Isabel Studer, president of the Board of the Mexican Climate Initiative; Lisa Viscidi, director of energy and climate change at Inter-American Dialogue; 3/3/2021, “U.S.-Mexico Forum 2025: Energy and Sustainability,” https://usmex.ucsd.edu/_files/usmex-forum-2025_report_energy.pdf, RMax </p><p><u><strong>A Global Transformation Reaches Mexico and the United States </p><p></u></strong>The year <u><mark>2020 was a <strong>pivot</mark> point</strong> for</u> the <u>global energy</u> system. For decades, fossil fuels met about 80 percent of the world’s primary energy demand. The <u>global impact of COVID-19</u> – on economic growth, collapsing oil demand, lost lives, and the way we live and work – has <u>forced countries around the world to assess how they will invest </u>perhaps 15-25% of their GDP <u>to rebuild their economies</u>. The phrase “<u>build back better</u>” – a foundational premise <u>for</u> President Joseph <u>Biden’s Administration –</u> <u>encompasses</u> the <u>necessity to</u> embrace change, <u>confront</u> the <u>climate crisis, and build</u> the <u>infrastructure and economic incentives to create jobs</u> while ensuring resilience and sustainability. In 2020, oil demand declined 10%, world energy demand fell 6%, but the world consumed 9% more wind and solar power.1 The share of <u><mark>fossil fuels</mark> in</u> the <u>energy</u> mix has <u><mark>begun</u></mark> an <u>historic <strong><mark>downward shift</strong></mark>. </p><p></u>Globally, the <u>path to net-zero will be filled with uncertainty, but</u> the <u>momentum has <strong>shifted</strong> and will</u> <u>touch most aspects of how every nation produces and consumes energy. <mark>Underpinning this</mark> shift <mark>have</u> <u>been commitments from</mark> </u>about <u>125 <mark>nations</mark> around the world</u> to net-zero emissions by 2050 (and 2060 for China). With the Biden Administration’s pledge to net-zero by 2050 and carbon-free power sector by 2035, the share of global emissions in countries with net-zero pledges will be 66%.2 In other words, two-thirds of the world’s emissions will be in countries committed to reduce them to a net annual balance of 0. Yet, few of these countries have policies, laws, and regulations in place that will allow them to achieve this goal.<u> </p><p>To succeed, countries</u> across the world <u>will enter</u> a period of <u>intense and accelerated legislative</u> and regulatory <u>activity</u>, to create the frameworks that drive investment and innovation in order to make net-zero a reality. That period of action will jump into high gear in 2021, as nations prepare for COP-26, the 26th session of the UN Framework Convention on Climate Change, where countries will establish new commitments under the Paris Accord. To be sure, <u><mark>climate</mark> change <mark>will be</u></mark> a <u><strong><mark>central </mark>issue</strong> <mark>in</u></mark> the <u><mark>U.S.-Mexico relationship under</u></mark> the <u><mark>Biden</u></mark> Administration. President <u>Biden</u> has <u>made climate change one of four priorities</u> for his administration, the first U.S. president to do so. At home, Biden pledged to assess how climate penetrates all domestic investments, committing to ensure that all cities over 100,000 people have public transit systems, creating national infrastructure for electric vehicles, and banning new licenses for oil and gas production on public lands and waters. <u><mark>Mexico</mark>, as</u> the <u>largest U.S. trade partner </u>and neighbor, <u>could</u> potentially <u><strong><mark>benefit</mark> more</strong> <mark>from</mark> <strong>increased <mark>coordination</strong> with</u></mark> the <u><strong><mark>U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates <u>to grasp</u> the <u>benefits of this transition than <strong>any other country</strong> in the world</u>. </p><p>This paper explores areas for research and technology collaboration that could reduce emissions, and in the case of carbon capture and storage, also potentially extend the competitive lifespans of untapped hydrocarbon reserves in both countries. However, the converse of this dynamic is also a risk: both Mexico and the United States should expect that many countries, perhaps starting with Europe and extending to China with the world’s largest carbon market, will impose cross-border tariffs on the goods of exporting nations that do not share their climate ambitions. <u>At stake for Mexico and</u> the <u><strong>U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates <u>is</u> this challenge: <u><mark>can they adapt </mark>their <mark>energy</u></mark> systems <u><mark>to make them <strong>competitive</strong></mark>, sustain growth, and create <strong>jobs</strong> in </u>a <u>global economy committed to eliminate</u> net <u>g</u>reenhouse <u>g</u>as <u>e</u>missions? </p><p>The <u><mark>answer <strong>depends on</strong> whether Mexico and</u></mark> the <u><strong><mark>U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates <u>open</u> the<u> door for <strong><mark>cooperat</mark>ion</strong> <mark>on energy</mark> transition. Much will depend on how</u> the <u><strong>rule of law</strong> prevails in</u> the <u><strong>energy relationship</strong> between the two countries.</u> There have been <u>disputes over private investment in renewables in Mexico and</u> the <u>rights of U.S. investors in</u> the <u>trade of refined products. Still,</u> the United States-Mexico-Canada Agreement (<u>USMCA) is now in force and provides</u> a <u>path</u> forward <u>to create transparent and predictable commercial relationships. No Party to the Agreement can modify its domestic legal framework or adopt measures in violation of its commitments under the USMCA without potentially facing claims under the general state to state or investorstate dispute settlement mechanisms. In addition, the reservations or exemptions to the energy obligations that each Party established in the Agreement, can only be modified in the future if they further liberalize; thus they cannot be made more restrictive. The administration of President Lopez Obrador may not accept this interpretation of the USMCA, and that could become an issue for both governments to address with urgency. </p><p><mark>Mexico and</u></mark> the <u><strong><mark>U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates, <u>with two of the most integrated manufacturing economies</u> in the world, <u>will <mark>remain</u></mark> inextricably <u><strong><mark>intertwined</strong> </mark>as</u> the <u><strong>global energy transition</strong> unfolds</u>. And in turn, <u>energy policies that foster <strong><mark>cross-border integration</strong> of</u></mark> fossil fuels and <u><strong><mark>renewable energy</u></strong></mark> capacity <u>can <strong><mark>propel</u></strong></mark> the <u><mark>global</mark> industrial <strong><mark>competitiveness</strong></mark> of both</u> the <u><strong>U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates <u>and Mexico. </p><p></u>The transformation potential cuts across the energy spectrum. Not only have solar and wind costs dropped precipitously in the past decade – 80% for solar PV and 50% for onshore wind3 – <u><mark>Mexico and</u></mark> the <u><strong><mark>U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates <u>have <strong>geographic characteristics</strong> that <mark>make</mark> them <strong><mark>first</mark>-in-<mark>class</strong> </mark>producers of <strong><mark>renewable power.</u></strong></mark> Even with the onset of peak oil demand, the decline rate of oil reservoirs combined with population growth and transportation demands in emerging economies suggest that the world will need by 2050 on the order of a new 45 MMb/d of oil.4 <u>Mexico and</u> the <u><strong>U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates <u>have complementary fuel types and refining capabilities, and</u> the <u><strong>potential</strong> for <strong><mark>sharing technical innovation</strong></mark>.</u> These <u>factors could facilitate greater integration of Mexican and U.S. energy systems, from upstream to refining, to achieve lower costs and higher productivity.</p></u> | 1AC – Original Jurisdiction | 1AC – Equitable Apportionment | null | 524,575 | 151 | 25,267 | ./documents/hspolicy21/Bellarmine/MaTa/Bellarmine-Manens-Talur-Aff-ASU-Round3.docx | 743,991 | A | ASU | 3 | Damien DL | Young Park | 1AC - Original Jurisdiction v3
2NR - Security K | hspolicy21/Bellarmine/MaTa/Bellarmine-Manens-Talur-Aff-ASU-Round3.docx | null | 63,368 | MaTa | Bellarmine MaTa | null | Be..... | Ma..... | Ni..... | Ta..... | 21,887 | Bellarmine | Bellarmine | CA | null | 1,020 | hspolicy21 | HS Policy 2021-22 | 2,021 | cx | hs | 2 |
1,443,072 | Incoming satellites ensure unmanageable space debris | Boley & Byers 21 | Boley & Byers 21 [Aaron C., Department of Physics and Astronomy @ The University of British Columbia*, and Michael, Department of Political Science @ The University of British Columbia; Published: 20 May 2021; Scientific Reports; “Satellite mega-constellations create risks in Low Earth Orbit, the atmosphere and on Earth,” https://www.nature.com/articles/s41598-021-89909-7] brett | Companies are placing satellites into orbit at an unprecedented frequency to build ‘mega-constellations’ of communications satellites in LEO In two years the number of satellites in LEO has increased by over 50% 5000 as of March 2021 SpaceX alone is on track to add 11,000 and has filed for permission for another 30,000 with the FCC OneWeb, Amazon, Telesat, current governance system for LEO is ill-equipped to handle large satellite systems satellites could lead to multiple tragedies of the commons impediments to astronomy increased risk of space debris changes to the chemistry of Earth’s upper atmosphere and increased dangers on Earth’s surface from re-entered debris The heavy use of certain orbital regions result in de facto exclusion of other actors from them violating the O
S T All of these challenges could be addressed through multilateral law-making mega-constellations require a shift in policies
Thousands of satellites provide considerable mass in LEO which can break into debris upon collisions, explosions, or degradation in the harsh space environment Fragmentations increase cross-section of orbiting material, and with it, the collision probability per time Eventually, collisions could dominate on-orbit evolution, a situation called the Kessler Syndrome Simulations of the long-term evolution of debris suggest that LEO is already in the initial stages of the Kessler Syndrome but that this could be managed through a d r The addition of satellite mega-constellations and the general proliferation of low-cost satellites in LEO stresses the environment further
Starlink will include about as many satellites as there are trackable debris pieces while its total mass will equal all the mass currently in LEO—over 3000 tonnes The satellites will be in narrow orbital shells, creating unprecedented congestion OneWeb has already placed an initial 146 satellites and Amazon, Telesat, GW and other companies, are soon to follow.
Enhanced collision risk
Mega-constellations are composed of mass-produced satellites with few backup systems This allows for short upgrade cycles and rapid expansions of capabilities, but also considerable discarded equipment 10% will be de-orbiting at any time If other companies do likewise, thousands de-orbiting satellites will be slowly passing through the same congested space, posing collision risks Failures will increase these numbers, although the long-term failure rate is difficult to project
communication and cooperation between operators is ad hoc and voluntary companies might be less-than-fully transparent about events in LEO
SpaceX filings do not account for untracked debris probability that a single piece of untracked debris will hit any satellite in the Starlink 550 km shell is about 0.003 after one year if at any time there are 230 pieces of untracked debris decaying through the 550 km orbital shell, there is a 50% chance that there will be one or more collisions between satellites in the shell and the debris such a situation is plausible Depending on balance between the de-orbit and the collision rates if subsequent fragmentation events lead to similar amounts of debris within that orbital shell a runaway cascade of collisions could occur
Fragmentation events are not confined to local orbits India ASAT test debris was placed on orbits with apogees in excess of 1000 km three tracked debris remain long-lived debris has high eccentricities, and can cross multiple orbital shells twice per orbit A major fragmentation event from a single satellite could affect all operators in LEO | Companies build ‘mega-constellations’ of satellites the number in LEO has increased by 50%, SpaceX add 11,000 and filed for another 30,000 large satellite systems increased risk of space debris
Thousands provide considerable mass which break upon collisions or degradation Fragmentations increase collision probability per time collisions could dominate a situation called the Kessler Syndrome Simulations of long-term evolution of debris suggest initial stages but that this could be managed addition of mega-constellations in LEO stresses the environment further
Starlink creat unprecedented congestion other companies are soon to follow
Mega-constellations are mass-produced with few backup systems This allows for considerable discarded equipment posing collision risks
runaway cascade could occur
major fragmentation could affect all operators in LEO | Companies are placing satellites into orbit at an unprecedented frequency to build ‘mega-constellations’ of communications satellites in Low Earth Orbit (LEO). In two years, the number of active and defunct satellites in LEO has increased by over 50%, to about 5000 (as of 30 March 2021). SpaceX alone is on track to add 11,000 more as it builds its Starlink mega-constellation and has already filed for permission for another 30,000 satellites with the Federal Communications Commission (FCC)1. Others have similar plans, including OneWeb, Amazon, Telesat, and GW, which is a Chinese state-owned company2. The current governance system for LEO, while slowly changing, is ill-equipped to handle large satellite systems. Here, we outline how applying the consumer electronic model to satellites could lead to multiple tragedies of the commons. Some of these are well known, such as impediments to astronomy and an increased risk of space debris, while others have received insufficient attention, including changes to the chemistry of Earth’s upper atmosphere and increased dangers on Earth’s surface from re-entered debris. The heavy use of certain orbital regions might also result in a de facto exclusion of other actors from them, violating the 1967 Outer
Space Treaty. All of these challenges could be addressed in a coordinated manner through multilateral law-making, whether in the United Nations, the Inter-Agency Debris Committee (IADC), or an ad hoc process, rather than in an uncoordinated manner through different national laws. Regardless of the law-making forum, mega-constellations require a shift in perspectives and policies: from looking at single satellites, to evaluating systems of thousands of satellites, and doing so within an understanding of the limitations of Earth’s environment, including its orbits.
Thousands of satellites and 1500 rocket bodies provide considerable mass in LEO, which can break into debris upon collisions, explosions, or degradation in the harsh space environment. Fragmentations increase the cross-section of orbiting material, and with it, the collision probability per time. Eventually, collisions could dominate on-orbit evolution, a situation called the Kessler Syndrome3. There are already over 12,000 trackable debris pieces in LEO, with these being typically 10 cm in diameter or larger. Including sizes down to 1 cm, there are about a million inferred debris pieces, all of which threaten satellites, spacecraft and astronauts due to their orbits crisscrossing at high relative speeds. Simulations of the long-term evolution of debris suggest that LEO is already in the protracted initial stages of the Kessler Syndrome, but that this could be managed through active debris removal4. The addition of satellite mega-constellations and the general proliferation of low-cost satellites in LEO stresses the environment further5,6,7,8.
Results
The overall setting
The rapid development of the space environment through mega-constellations, predominately by the ongoing construction of Starlink, is shown by the cumulative payload distribution function (Fig. 1). From an environmental perspective, the slope change in the distribution function defines NewSpace, an era of dominance by commercial actors. Before 2015, changes in the total on-orbit objects came principally from fragmentations, with effects of the 2007 Chinese anti-satellite test and the 2009 Kosmos-2251/Iridium-33 collisions being evident on the graph.
Figure 1
[Figure 1 omitted]
Cumulative on-orbit distribution functions (all orbits). Deorbited objects are not included. The 2007 and 2009 spikes are a Chinese anti-satellite test and the Iridium 33-Kosmos 2251 collision, respectively. The recent, rapid rise of the orange curve represents NewSpace (see "Methods").
Full size image
Although the volume of space is large, individual satellites and satellite systems have specific functions, with associated altitudes and inclinations (Fig. 2). This increases congestion and requires active management for station keeping and collision avoidance9, with automatic collision-avoidance technology still under development. Improved space situational awareness is required, with data from operators as well as ground- and space-based sensors being widely and freely shared10. Improved communications between satellite operators are also necessary: in 2019, the European Space Agency moved an Earth observation satellite to avoid colliding with a Starlink satellite, after failing to reach SpaceX by e-mail. Internationally adopted ‘right of way’ rules are needed10 to prevent games of ‘chicken’, as companies seek to preserve thruster fuel and avoid service interruptions. SpaceX and NASA recently announced11 a cooperative agreement to help reduce the risk of collisions, but this is only one operator and one agency.
Figure 2
[Figure 2 omitted]
Orbital distribution and density information for objects in Low Earth Orbit (LEO). (Left) Distribution of payloads (active and defunct satellites), binned to the nearest 1 km in altitude and 1° in orbital inclination. The centre of each circle represents the position on the diagram, and the size of the circle is proportional to the number of satellites within the given parameter space. (Right) Number density of different space resident objects (SROs) based on 1 km radial bins, averaged over the entire sky. Because SRO objects are on elliptical orbits, the contribution of a given object to an orbital shell is weighted by the time that object spends in the shell. Despite significant parameter space, satellites are clustered in their orbits due to mission requirements. The emerging Starlink cluster at 550 km and 55° inclination is already evident in both plots (Left and Right).
Full size image
When completed, Starlink will include about as many satellites as there are trackable debris pieces today, while its total mass will equal all the mass currently in LEO—over 3000 tonnes. The satellites will be placed in narrow orbital shells, creating unprecedented congestion, with 1258 already in orbit (as of 30 March 2021). OneWeb has already placed an initial 146 satellites, and Amazon, Telesat, GW and other companies, operating under different national regulatory regimes, are soon likely to follow.
Enhanced collision risk
Mega-constellations are composed of mass-produced satellites with few backup systems. This consumer electronic model allows for short upgrade cycles and rapid expansions of capabilities, but also considerable discarded equipment. SpaceX will actively de-orbit its satellites at the end of their 5–6-year operational lives. However, this process takes 6 months, so roughly 10% will be de-orbiting at any time. If other companies do likewise, thousands of de-orbiting satellites will be slowly passing through the same congested space, posing collision risks. Failures will increase these numbers, although the long-term failure rate is difficult to project. Figure 3 is similar to the righthand portion of Fig. 2 but includes the Starlink and OneWeb mega-constellations as filed (and amended) with the FCC (see “Methods”). The large density spikes show that some shells will have satellite number densities in excess of n=10−6 km−3.
Figure 3
[Figure 3 omitted]
Satellite density distribution in LEO with the Starlink and OneWeb mega-constellations as filed (and amended) with the FCC. Provided that the orbits are nearly circular, the number densities in those shells will exceed 10–6 km−3. Because the collisional cross-section in those shells is also high, they represent regions that have a high collision risk whenever debris is too small to be tracked or collision avoidance manoeuvres are impossible for other reasons.
Full size image
Deorbiting satellites will be tracked and operational satellites can manoeuvre to avoid close conjunctions. However, this depends on ongoing communication and cooperation between operators, which at present is ad hoc and voluntary. A recent letter12 to the FCC from SpaceX suggests that some companies might be less-than-fully transparent about events13 in LEO.
Despite the congestion and traffic management challenges, FCC filings by SpaceX suggest that collision avoidance manoeuvres can in fact maintain collision-free operations in orbital shells and that the probability of a collision between a non-responsive satellite and tracked debris is negligible. However, the filings do not account for untracked debris6, including untracked debris decaying through the shells used by Starlink. Using simple estimates (see “Methods”), the probability that a single piece of untracked debris will hit any satellite in the Starlink 550 km shell is about 0.003 after one year. Thus, if at any time there are 230 pieces of untracked debris decaying through the 550 km orbital shell, there is a 50% chance that there will be one or more collisions between satellites in the shell and the debris. As discussed further in “Methods”, such a situation is plausible. Depending on the balance between the de-orbit and the collision rates, if subsequent fragmentation events lead to similar amounts of debris within that orbital shell, a runaway cascade of collisions could occur.
Fragmentation events are not confined to their local orbits, either. The India 2019 ASAT test was conducted at an altitude below 300 km in an effort to minimize long-lived debris. Nevertheless, debris was placed on orbits with apogees in excess of 1000 km. As of 30 March 2021, three tracked debris pieces remain in orbit14. Such long-lived debris has high eccentricities, and thus can cross multiple orbital shells twice per orbit. A major fragmentation event from a single satellite could affect all operators in LEO.
Even if debris collisions were avoidable, meteoroids are always a threat. The cumulative meteoroid flux15 for masses m > 10–2 g is about 1.2 × 10–4 meteoroids m−2 year−1 (see “Methods”). Such masses could cause non-negligible damage to satellites16. Assuming a Starlink constellation of 12,000 satellites (i.e. the initial phase), there is about a 50% chance of 15 or more meteoroid impacts per year at m > 10–2 g. Satellites will have shielding, but events that might be rare to a single satellite could become common across the constellation.
One partial response to these congestion and collision concerns is for operators to construct mega-constellations out of a smaller number of satellites. But this does not, individually or collectively, eliminate the need for an all-of-LEO approach to evaluating the effects of the construction and maintenance of any one constellation. | 10,605 | <h4>Incoming satellites ensure <u>unmanageable</u> space debris</h4><p><strong>Boley & Byers 21</strong> [Aaron C., Department of Physics and Astronomy @ The University of British Columbia*, and Michael, Department of Political Science @ The University of British Columbia; Published: 20 May 2021; Scientific Reports; “Satellite mega-constellations create risks in Low Earth Orbit, the atmosphere and on Earth,” https://www.nature.com/articles/s41598-021-89909-7] brett</p><p><u><mark>Companies</mark> are placing satellites into orbit at an unprecedented frequency to <mark>build <strong>‘mega-constellations’</strong> of</mark> communications <mark>satellites </mark>in</u> Low Earth Orbit (<u><strong>LEO</u></strong>). <u><strong>In two years</u></strong>, <u><mark>the number</mark> of</u> active and defunct <u>satellites <mark>in <strong>LEO</strong> has increased by</mark> over <mark>50%</u>,</mark> to about <u><strong>5000</u></strong> (<u><strong>as of</u></strong> 30 <u>March <strong>2021</u></strong>). <u><strong><mark>SpaceX</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>alone</u></strong> <u>is on track to <mark>add 11,000</u></mark> more as it builds its Starlink mega-constellation <u><mark>and</mark> has</u> already <u><mark>filed for</mark> permission for <mark>another 30,000</u></mark> satellites <u>with the</u> Federal Communications Commission (<u>FCC</u>)1. Others have similar plans, including <u><strong>OneWeb, Amazon, Telesat,</u></strong> and GW, which is a Chinese state-owned company2. The <u>current governance system for LEO</u>, while slowly changing, <u>is ill-equipped to handle <strong><mark>large satellite systems</u></strong></mark>. Here, we outline how applying the consumer electronic model to <u>satellites could lead to <strong>multiple tragedies of the commons</u></strong>. Some of these are well known, such as <u>impediments to <strong>astronomy</u></strong> and an <u><mark>increased risk of <strong>space debris</u></strong></mark>, while others have received insufficient attention, including <u>changes to the <strong>chemistry</strong> of Earth’s <strong>upper atmosphere</u></strong> <u>and</u> <u><strong>increased dangers</strong> on Earth’s surface from <strong>re-entered debris</u></strong>. <u>The heavy use of certain orbital regions</u> might also <u>result in</u> a <u>de facto exclusion of other actors from them</u>, <u>violating the</u> 1967 <u><strong>O</u></strong>uter </p><p><u><strong>S</u></strong>pace <u><strong>T</u></strong>reaty. <u>All of these challenges could be addressed</u> in a coordinated manner <u>through multilateral law-making</u>, whether in the United Nations, the Inter-Agency Debris Committee (IADC), or an ad hoc process, rather than in an uncoordinated manner through different national laws. Regardless of the law-making forum, <u><strong>mega-constellations</u></strong> <u>require a shift in</u> perspectives and <u>policies</u>: from looking at single satellites, to evaluating systems of thousands of satellites, and doing so within an understanding of the limitations of Earth’s environment, including its orbits.</p><p><u><mark>Thousands</mark> of <strong>satellites</u></strong> and 1500 rocket bodies <u><mark>provide <strong>considerable mass</strong></mark> in LEO</u>, <u><mark>which</mark> can <mark>break </mark>into debris <mark>upon</mark> <strong><mark>collisions</strong></mark>, explosions, <mark>or</mark> <strong><mark>degradation</strong></mark> in the <strong>harsh space environment</u></strong>. <u><strong><mark>Fragmentations</strong> increase</u></mark> the <u><strong>cross-section of orbiting material</strong>, and with it, the <strong><mark>collision probability</strong> per time</u></mark>. <u>Eventually, <mark>collisions could dominate</mark> on-orbit evolution, <mark>a situation called the <strong>Kessler Syndrome</u></strong></mark>3. There are already over 12,000 trackable debris pieces in LEO, with these being typically 10 cm in diameter or larger. Including sizes down to 1 cm, there are about a million inferred debris pieces, all of which threaten satellites, spacecraft and astronauts due to their orbits crisscrossing at high relative speeds. <u><mark>Simulations of</mark> the <strong><mark>long-term evolution</strong></mark> <mark>of debris suggest</mark> that LEO is already in the</u> protracted <u><strong><mark>initial stages </mark>of the Kessler Syndrome</u></strong>, <u><mark>but that this could be managed</u></mark> <u>through</u> <u><strong>a</u></strong>ctive <u><strong>d</u></strong>ebris <u><strong>r</u></strong>emoval4. <u>The <mark>addition of</mark> satellite <strong><mark>mega-constellations</strong></mark> and the general proliferation of low-cost satellites <mark>in LEO <strong>stresses the environment further</u></strong></mark>5,6,7,8.</p><p>Results</p><p>The overall setting</p><p>The rapid development of the space environment through mega-constellations, predominately by the ongoing construction of Starlink, is shown by the cumulative payload distribution function (Fig. 1). From an environmental perspective, the slope change in the distribution function defines NewSpace, an era of dominance by commercial actors. Before 2015, changes in the total on-orbit objects came principally from fragmentations, with effects of the 2007 Chinese anti-satellite test and the 2009 Kosmos-2251/Iridium-33 collisions being evident on the graph.</p><p>Figure 1</p><p>[Figure 1 omitted]</p><p>Cumulative on-orbit distribution functions (all orbits). Deorbited objects are not included. The 2007 and 2009 spikes are a Chinese anti-satellite test and the Iridium 33-Kosmos 2251 collision, respectively. The recent, rapid rise of the orange curve represents NewSpace (see "Methods").</p><p>Full size image</p><p>Although the volume of space is large, individual satellites and satellite systems have specific functions, with associated altitudes and inclinations (Fig. 2). This increases congestion and requires active management for station keeping and collision avoidance9, with automatic collision-avoidance technology still under development. Improved space situational awareness is required, with data from operators as well as ground- and space-based sensors being widely and freely shared10. Improved communications between satellite operators are also necessary: in 2019, the European Space Agency moved an Earth observation satellite to avoid colliding with a Starlink satellite, after failing to reach SpaceX by e-mail. Internationally adopted ‘right of way’ rules are needed10 to prevent games of ‘chicken’, as companies seek to preserve thruster fuel and avoid service interruptions. SpaceX and NASA recently announced11 a cooperative agreement to help reduce the risk of collisions, but this is only one operator and one agency.</p><p>Figure 2</p><p>[Figure 2 omitted]</p><p>Orbital distribution and density information for objects in Low Earth Orbit (LEO). (Left) Distribution of payloads (active and defunct satellites), binned to the nearest 1 km in altitude and 1° in orbital inclination. The centre of each circle represents the position on the diagram, and the size of the circle is proportional to the number of satellites within the given parameter space. (Right) Number density of different space resident objects (SROs) based on 1 km radial bins, averaged over the entire sky. Because SRO objects are on elliptical orbits, the contribution of a given object to an orbital shell is weighted by the time that object spends in the shell. Despite significant parameter space, satellites are clustered in their orbits due to mission requirements. The emerging Starlink cluster at 550 km and 55° inclination is already evident in both plots (Left and Right).</p><p>Full size image</p><p>When completed, <u><strong><mark>Starlink</strong></mark> will include about as many satellites as there are trackable debris pieces</u> today, <u>while its <strong>total mass will equal all the mass currently in LEO</strong>—over 3000 tonnes</u>. <u>The satellites will be</u> placed <u>in narrow orbital shells, <mark>creat</mark>ing<mark> <strong>unprecedented congestion</u></strong></mark>, with 1258 already in orbit (as of 30 March 2021). <u><strong>OneWeb</u></strong> <u>has already placed an initial 146 satellites</u>, <u>and</u> <u><strong>Amazon,</u></strong> <u><strong>Telesat,</u></strong> <u><strong>GW</u></strong> <u>and <strong><mark>other companies</mark>,</u></strong> operating under different national regulatory regimes, <u><mark>are soon</u></mark> likely <u><mark>to follow<strong></mark>.</p><p>Enhanced collision risk</p><p></strong><mark>Mega-constellations are</mark> composed of <strong><mark>mass-produced</mark> satellites</strong> <mark>with <strong>few backup systems</u></strong></mark>. <u><mark>This</u></mark> consumer electronic model <u><mark>allows for</mark> short upgrade cycles and rapid expansions of capabilities, but also <strong><mark>considerable discarded equipment</u></strong></mark>. SpaceX will actively de-orbit its satellites at the end of their 5–6-year operational lives. However, this process takes 6 months, so roughly <u>10% will be de-orbiting at any time</u>. <u>If other companies do likewise, thousands</u> of <u><strong>de-orbiting satellites</u></strong> <u>will be slowly passing through the same congested space, <mark>posing collision risks</u></mark>. <u>Failures will increase these numbers, although the long-term failure rate is difficult to project</u>. Figure 3 is similar to the righthand portion of Fig. 2 but includes the Starlink and OneWeb mega-constellations as filed (and amended) with the FCC (see “Methods”). The large density spikes show that some shells will have satellite number densities in excess of n=10−6 km−3.</p><p>Figure 3</p><p>[Figure 3 omitted]</p><p>Satellite density distribution in LEO with the Starlink and OneWeb mega-constellations as filed (and amended) with the FCC. Provided that the orbits are nearly circular, the number densities in those shells will exceed 10–6 km−3. Because the collisional cross-section in those shells is also high, they represent regions that have a high collision risk whenever debris is too small to be tracked or collision avoidance manoeuvres are impossible for other reasons.</p><p>Full size image</p><p>Deorbiting satellites will be tracked and operational satellites can manoeuvre to avoid close conjunctions. However, this depends on ongoing <u>communication and cooperation between operators</u>, which at present <u>is ad hoc and voluntary</u>. A recent letter12 to the FCC from SpaceX suggests that some <u><strong>companies might be less-than-fully transparent</strong> about events</u>13 <u>in LEO</u>.</p><p>Despite the congestion and traffic management challenges, FCC filings by <u><strong>SpaceX</u></strong> suggest that collision avoidance manoeuvres can in fact maintain collision-free operations in orbital shells and that the probability of a collision between a non-responsive satellite and tracked debris is negligible. However, the <u><strong>filings do not account for untracked debris</u></strong>6, including untracked debris decaying through the shells used by Starlink. Using simple estimates (see “Methods”), the <u>probability that a single piece of untracked debris will hit any satellite in the Starlink 550 km shell is about 0.003 after one year</u>. Thus, <u>if at any time there are 230 pieces of <strong>untracked debris</strong> decaying through the 550 km orbital shell, there is a <strong>50% chance</strong> that there will be one or more collisions between satellites in the shell and the debris</u>. As discussed further in “Methods”, <u>such a situation is plausible</u>. <u>Depending on</u> the <u>balance between the de-orbit and the collision rates</u>, <u>if <strong>subsequent fragmentation</strong> events lead to <strong>similar amounts of debris within that orbital shell</u></strong>, <u><strong>a <mark>runaway cascade</mark> of collisions <mark>could occur</u></strong></mark>.</p><p><u>Fragmentation events are not confined to</u> their <u>local orbits</u>, either. The <u>India</u> 2019 <u>ASAT test</u> was conducted at an altitude below 300 km in an effort to minimize long-lived debris. Nevertheless, <u>debris was placed on orbits with apogees in excess of 1000 km</u>. As of 30 March 2021, <u>three tracked debris</u> pieces <u>remain</u> in orbit14. Such <u>long-lived debris has high eccentricities, and</u> thus <u>can cross multiple orbital shells twice per orbit</u>. <u><strong>A <mark>major fragmentation</mark> event from a single satellite <mark>could affect all operators in LEO</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>Even if debris collisions were avoidable, meteoroids are always a threat. The cumulative meteoroid flux15 for masses m > 10–2 g is about 1.2 × 10–4 meteoroids m−2 year−1 (see “Methods”). Such masses could cause non-negligible damage to satellites16. Assuming a Starlink constellation of 12,000 satellites (i.e. the initial phase), there is about a 50% chance of 15 or more meteoroid impacts per year at m > 10–2 g. Satellites will have shielding, but events that might be rare to a single satellite could become common across the constellation.</p><p>One partial response to these congestion and collision concerns is for operators to construct mega-constellations out of a smaller number of satellites. But this does not, individually or collectively, eliminate the need for an all-of-LEO approach to evaluating the effects of the construction and maintenance of any one constellation.</p> | null | null | My sole contention is space debris | 339,325 | 265 | 39,651 | ./documents/hsld21/Interlake/Bo/Interlake-Bomberger-Aff-Puget%20Sound%20High%20School%20Tournament-Round6.docx | 890,055 | A | Puget Sound High School Tournament | 6 | Lynbrook SY | Alex Sapadin | 1AC - Whole Res
1NR - Nebel T Internet DA Satellite DA US Russia Debris CP
1AR - all
2NR - T Satellite DA
2AR - all | hsld21/Interlake/Bo/Interlake-Bomberger-Aff-Puget%20Sound%20High%20School%20Tournament-Round6.docx | null | 74,804 | DaBo | Interlake DaBo | null | Da..... | Bo..... | null | null | 25,025 | Interlake | Interlake | WA | null | 1,029 | hsld21 | HS LD 2021-22 | 2,021 | ld | hs | 1 |
1,512,201 | We can avoid Kessler for up to a century – MH reads green. | 1AC MuñOz-Patchen, 19 "Regulating the Space Commons: Treating Space Debris as Abandoned Property in Violation of the Outer Space Treaty," University of Chicago, 2019, 12-6-2021, https://cjil.uchicago.edu/publication/regulating-space-commons-treating-space-debris-abandoned-property-violation-outer-space)//AW | 1AC MuñOz-Patchen, 19 - (Chelsea, "Regulating the Space Commons: Treating Space Debris as Abandoned Property in Violation of the Outer Space Treaty," University of Chicago, 2019, 12-6-2021, https://cjil.uchicago.edu/publication/regulating-space-commons-treating-space-debris-abandoned-property-violation-outer-space)//AW | debris cannot be tracked due to size and velocity making it impossible to avoid collisions. debris must travel at speeds of up to 17,500 miles per hour pieces shed nuts, bolts, paint chips, motor sprays of aluminum particles, glass splinters, waste water, and bits of foil and stay in orbit for centuries objects are a collision threat taking up useful orbit space. the crew of the ISS had to take shelter three times due to close calls commercial space tourism will increase the number of objects launched into space and thus the amount of debris. The Kessler Syndrome is created when debris hits a space object, creating new debris and setting off a chain reaction of collisions that closes off entire orbits. In 2011, The National Research Council predicted that the Kessler Syndrome could happen within ten to twenty years. Donald J. Kessler, the astrophysicist and NASA scientist who theorized the Kessler Syndrome in 1978, believes this cascade may be a century away, meaning that there is still time to develop a solution.52 | debris cannot be tracked due to size and velocity making it impossible to avoid collisions. pieces shed and stay in orbit for centuries objects are a collision threat taking up useful orbit space. commercial space tourism will increase debris. The Kessler Syndrome is when debris hits a space object, creating new debris and setting off a chain reaction of collisions that closes off entire orbits. Donald Kessler believes this cascade may be a century away there is time to develop a solution | Debris poses a threat to functioning space objects and astronauts in space, and may cause damage to the earth’s surface upon re-entry.29 Much of the small debris cannot be tracked due to its size and the velocity at which it travels, making it impossible to anticipate and maneuver to avoid collisions.30 To remain in orbit, debris must travel at speeds of up to 17,500 miles per hour.31 At this speed even very small pieces of debris can cause serious damage, threatening a spacecraft and causing expensive damage.32 There are millions of these very small pieces, and thousands of larger ones.33 The small-to-medium pieces of debris “continuously shed fragments like lens caps, booster upper stages, nuts, bolts, paint chips, motor sprays of aluminum particles, glass splinters, waste water, and bits of foil,” and may stay in orbit for decades or even centuries, posing an ongoing risk.34 Debris ten centimeters or larger in diameter creates the likelihood of complete destruction for any functioning satellite with which it collides.35 Large nonfunctional objects remaining in orbit are a collision threat, capable of creating huge amounts of space debris and taking up otherwise useful orbit space.36 This issue is of growing importance as more nations and companies gain the ability to launch satellites and other objects into space.37 From February 2009 through the end of 2010, more than thirty-two collision-avoidance maneuvers were reportedly used to avoid debris by various space agencies and satellite companies, and as of March 2012, the crew of the International Space Station (ISS) had to take shelter three times due to close calls with passing debris.38 These maneuvers require costly fuel usage and place a strain on astronauts.39 Furthermore, the launches of some spacecraft have “been delayed because of the presence of space debris in the planned flight paths.”40 In 2011, Euroconsult, a satellite consultant, projected that there would be “a 51% increase in satellites launched in the next decade over the number launched in the past decade.”41 In addition to satellites, the rise of commercial space tourism will also increase the number of objects launched into space and thus the amount of debris.42 The more objects are sent into space, and the more collisions create cascades of debris, the greater the risk of damage to vital satellites and other devices relied on for “weather forecasting, telecommunications, commerce, and national security.”43 The Space Debris Mitigation Guidelines44 were created by UNCOPUOS with input from the IADC and adopted in 2007.45 The guidelines were developed to address the problem of space debris and were intended to “increase mutual understanding on acceptable activities in space.”46 These guidelines are nonbinding but suggest best practices to implement at the national level when planning for a launch. Many nations have adopted the guidelines to some degree, and some have gone beyond what the guidelines suggest.47 While the guidelines do not address existing debris, they do much to prevent the creation of new debris. The Kessler Syndrome is the biggest concern with space debris. The Kessler Syndrome is a cascade created when debris hits a space object, creating new debris and setting off a chain reaction of collisions that eventually closes off entire orbits.48 The concern is that this cascade will occur when a tipping point is reached at which the natural removal rate cannot keep up with the amount of new debris added.49 At this point a collision could set off a cascade destroying all space objects within the orbit.50 In 2011, The National Research Council predicted that the Kessler Syndrome could happen within ten to twenty years.51 Donald J. Kessler, the astrophysicist and NASA scientist who theorized the Kessler Syndrome in 1978, believes this cascade may be a century away, meaning that there is still time to develop a solution.52 | 3,921 | <h4>We can avoid Kessler for up to a century – MH reads green. </h4><p><strong>1AC MuñOz-Patchen, 19</strong> - (Chelsea, <u><strong>"Regulating the Space Commons: Treating Space Debris as Abandoned Property in Violation of the Outer Space Treaty," University of Chicago, 2019, 12-6-2021, https://cjil.uchicago.edu/publication/regulating-space-commons-treating-space-debris-abandoned-property-violation-outer-space)//AW</p><p></u></strong>Debris poses a threat to functioning space objects and astronauts in space, and may cause damage to the earth’s surface upon re-entry.29 Much of the small <u><mark>debris cannot be tracked due to</u></mark> its <u><mark>size and</u></mark> the <u><mark>velocity</u></mark> at which it travels, <u><strong><mark>making it impossible to</u></strong></mark> anticipate and maneuver to <u><strong><mark>avoid collisions.</u></strong></mark>30 To remain in orbit, <u><strong>debris must travel at speeds of up to 17,500 miles per hour</u></strong>.31 At this speed even very small pieces of debris can cause serious damage, threatening a spacecraft and causing expensive damage.32 There are millions of these very small pieces, and thousands of larger ones.33 The small-to-medium <u><mark>pieces</u></mark> of debris “continuously <u><mark>shed</u></mark> fragments like lens caps, booster upper stages, <u>nuts, bolts, paint chips, motor sprays of aluminum particles, glass splinters, waste water, and bits of foil</u>,” <u><mark>and</u></mark> may <u><mark>stay in orbit for</u></mark> decades or even <u><mark>centuries</u></mark>, posing an ongoing risk.34 Debris ten centimeters or larger in diameter creates the likelihood of complete destruction for any functioning satellite with which it collides.35 Large nonfunctional <u><mark>objects</u></mark> remaining in orbit <u><mark>are a collision threat</u></mark>, capable of creating huge amounts of space debris and <u><mark>taking up</u></mark> otherwise <u><mark>useful orbit space.</u></mark>36 This issue is of growing importance as more nations and companies gain the ability to launch satellites and other objects into space.37 From February 2009 through the end of 2010, more than thirty-two collision-avoidance maneuvers were reportedly used to avoid debris by various space agencies and satellite companies, and as of March 2012, <u>the crew of the</u> International Space Station (<u>ISS</u>) <u>had to take shelter three times due to close calls</u> with passing debris.38 These maneuvers require costly fuel usage and place a strain on astronauts.39 Furthermore, the launches of some spacecraft have “been delayed because of the presence of space debris in the planned flight paths.”40 In 2011, Euroconsult, a satellite consultant, projected that there would be “a 51% increase in satellites launched in the next decade over the number launched in the past decade.”41 In addition to satellites, the rise of <u><mark>commercial space tourism will</u></mark> also <u><mark>increase</mark> the number of objects launched into space and thus the amount of <mark>debris.</u></mark>42 The more objects are sent into space, and the more collisions create cascades of debris, the greater the risk of damage to vital satellites and other devices relied on for “weather forecasting, telecommunications, commerce, and national security.”43 The Space Debris Mitigation Guidelines44 were created by UNCOPUOS with input from the IADC and adopted in 2007.45 The guidelines were developed to address the problem of space debris and were intended to “increase mutual understanding on acceptable activities in space.”46 These guidelines are nonbinding but suggest best practices to implement at the national level when planning for a launch. Many nations have adopted the guidelines to some degree, and some have gone beyond what the guidelines suggest.47 While the guidelines do not address existing debris, they do much to prevent the creation of new debris. The Kessler Syndrome is the biggest concern with space debris. <u><mark>The <strong>Kessler Syndrome</strong> is</u></mark> a cascade <u>created <mark>when debris hits a space object, creating new debris and <strong>setting off a chain reaction</strong> of collisions that</u></mark> eventually <u><strong><mark>closes off entire orbits.</u></strong></mark>48 The concern is that this cascade will occur when a tipping point is reached at which the natural removal rate cannot keep up with the amount of new debris added.49 At this point a collision could set off a cascade destroying all space objects within the orbit.50 <u>In 2011, The National Research Council predicted that the Kessler Syndrome <strong>could happen within ten to twenty years.</u></strong>51 <u><strong><mark>Donald</mark> J. <mark>Kessler</mark>, the astrophysicist and NASA scientist who theorized the Kessler Syndrome in 1978, <mark>believes this cascade may be a century away</mark>, meaning that <mark>there is</mark> still <mark>time to develop a solution</mark>.52 </p></u></strong> | 1NC v Global Commons | Case | 1NC: Space Debris | 337,731 | 160 | 42,892 | ./documents/hsld21/MountainHouse/Su/Mountain%20House-Su-Neg-Palm%20Classic-Round5.docx | 895,370 | N | Palm Classic | 5 | Marlborough HL | Jonathan Jeong | 1AC - Global Commons
1NC - Extra T Sabotage CP Case
1AR - All
2NR - Sabotage CP
2AR - Case | hsld21/MountainHouse/Su/Mountain%20House-Su-Neg-Palm%20Classic-Round5.docx | null | 75,134 | ElSu | Mountain House ElSu | null | El..... | Su..... | null | null | 25,095 | MountainHouse | Mountain House | CA | null | 1,029 | hsld21 | HS LD 2021-22 | 2,021 | ld | hs | 1 |
180,064 | Will adopt conciliatory policies instead | Clary 15 | Christopher Clary 15, Ph.D. in Political Science from MIT, Postdoctoral Fellow, Watson Institute for International Studies, Brown University, “Economic Stress and International Cooperation: Evidence from International Rivalries,” April 22, 2015, http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2597712 | Do economic downturns generate pressure for diversionary conflict? This paper provides new evidence that economic stress is associated with conciliatory policies between strategic rivals. Drawing on data from 109 distinct rival dyads since 1950, 67 of which terminated, the evidence suggests rivalries were approximately twice as likely to terminate during economic downturns This is true controlling for all of the main alternative explanations for peaceful relations between foes systemic changes), as well as many other possible confounding variables. This questions existing theories claiming economic downturns are associated with diversionary war, and instead argues peace may result from economic troubles | economic stress is associated with conciliatory policies Drawing on data from 109 distinct rival dyads 67 of which terminated, evidence suggests rivalries were twice as likely to terminate during downturns controlling for all main alternative explanations for peaceful relations systemic changes), as well as other confounding variables. This questions existing theories claiming downturns are associated with diversionary war, and argues peace may result from economic troubles | Do economic downturns generate pressure for diversionary conflict? Or might downturns encourage austerity and economizing behavior in foreign policy? This paper provides new evidence that economic stress is associated with conciliatory policies between strategic rivals. For states that view each other as military threats, the biggest step possible toward bilateral cooperation is to terminate the rivalry by taking political steps to manage the competition. Drawing on data from 109 distinct rival dyads since 1950, 67 of which terminated, the evidence suggests rivalries were approximately twice as likely to terminate during economic downturns than they were during periods of economic normalcy. This is true controlling for all of the main alternative explanations for peaceful relations between foes (democratic status, nuclear weapons possession, capability imbalance, common enemies, and international systemic changes), as well as many other possible confounding variables. This research questions existing theories claiming that economic downturns are associated with diversionary war, and instead argues that in certain circumstances peace may result from economic troubles. | 1,185 | <h4>Will adopt <u>conciliatory policies</u> instead</h4><p>Christopher <strong>Clary 15</strong>, Ph.D. in Political Science from MIT, Postdoctoral Fellow, Watson Institute for International Studies, Brown University, “Economic Stress and International Cooperation: Evidence from International Rivalries,” April 22, 2015, http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2597712</p><p><u>Do economic downturns generate pressure for diversionary conflict?</u> Or might downturns encourage austerity and economizing behavior in foreign policy? <u>This paper provides new evidence that <mark>economic stress is associated with <strong>conciliatory policies</mark> between strategic rivals.</u></strong> For states that view each other as military threats, the biggest step possible toward bilateral cooperation is to terminate the rivalry by taking political steps to manage the competition. <u><mark>Drawing on data from <strong>109 distinct rival dyads</strong></mark> since 1950, <strong><mark>67 of which terminated,</strong></mark> the <mark>evidence suggests rivalries were</mark> approximately <strong><mark>twice as likely to terminate during </mark>economic <mark>downturns</u></strong></mark> than they were during periods of economic normalcy. <u>This is true <mark>controlling for <strong>all </mark>of the <mark>main alternative explanations for peaceful relations</mark> between foes</u></strong> (democratic status, nuclear weapons possession, capability imbalance, common enemies, and international <u><strong><mark>systemic changes),</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>as well as <strong></mark>many</strong> <strong><mark>other</strong></mark> possible <strong><mark>confounding variables</strong>. This</u></mark> research <u><strong><mark>questions existing theories</u></strong> <u>claiming</u></mark> that <u>economic <mark>downturns are associated with <strong>diversionary war</strong>, and</mark> instead <mark>argues</u></mark> that in certain circumstances <u><strong><mark>peace may result from economic troubles</u></strong></mark>.</p> | Case Answers | Econ---Defense | AT: Econ Impact---Defense | 983 | 2,566 | 2,311 | ./documents/openev/2018/NHSI/Path to Citizenship Negative - Northwestern 2018.docx | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null |
3,652,140 | Use util | Greene 10 | Greene 10 Associate Professor of the Social Sciences Department of Psychology Harvard University, Joshua, Moral Psychology: Historical and Contemporary Readings, “The Secret Joke of Kant’s Soul”, www.fed.cuhk.edu.hk/~lchang/material/Evolutionary/Developmental/Greene-KantSoul.pdf | What turn-of-the-millennium science is telling us is that human moral judgment is not a pristine rational enterprise moral judgments are driven by a hodgepodge of emotional dispositions, which themselves were shaped by a hodgepodge of evolutionary forces, both biological and cultural Because of this, it is exceedingly unlikely that there is any rationally coherent normative moral theory that can accommodate our moral intuitions anyone who claims to have such a theory almost certainly doesn't Missing the Deontological Point rationalist deontologists will remain unmoved by the arguments presented here they will insist that I have simply misunderstood what deontologists are all about Deontology, they will say, isn't about this intuition or that intuition Rather, deontology is about taking humanity seriously This is, no doubt, how many deontologists see deontology. But this insider's view may be misleading The problem is that it defines deontology in terms of values that are not distinctively deontological Consider the following analogy with religion. When one asks a religious person to explain the essence of his religion, one often gets an answer like this: "It's about love This sort of answer accurately captures the phenomenology of many people's religion, but it's nevertheless inadequate for distinguishing religion from other things the standard deontological/Kantian self-characterizatons fail to distinguish deontology from other approaches to ethics consequentialists have respect for persons are against treating people as mere objects wish to act for reasons that rational creatures can share, etc A consequentialist respects other persons, and refrains from treating them as mere objects, by counting every person's well-being in the decision-making process Likewise, a consequentialist attempts to act according to reasons that rational creatures can share by acting according to principles that give equal weight to everyone's interests, i.e. that are impartial If you ask a deontologically-minded person why it's wrong to push someone in front of speeding trolley in order to save five others answers will be tautological: "Because it's murder!"Others will be more sophisticated: "The ends don't justify the means But these answers don't really explain anything if you give the same people the trolley case they'll make the opposite judgment Talk about rights, respect for persons, and reasons we can share are natural attempts to explain, in "cognitive" terms, what we feel when we find ourselves having emotionally driven intuitions that are odds with the cold calculus of consequentialism there seems to be "something deeply right" about them because they give voice to powerful moral emotions. But, as with many religious people's accounts of what's essential to religion, they don't really explain what's distinctive about the philosophy in question | science is telling us moral judgment is not rational enterprise it is exceedingly unlikely there is any coherent moral theory that can accommodate our moral intuitions consequentialists have respect for persons refrains from treating them as objects by counting every person's well-being in the decision-making process that give equal weight to everyone's interests If you ask a deontologically-minded person why it's wrong to push someone to save five others answers will be tautological | What turn-of-the-millennium science is telling us is that human moral judgment is not a pristine rational enterprise, that our moral judgments are driven by a hodgepodge of emotional dispositions, which themselves were shaped by a hodgepodge of evolutionary forces, both biological and cultural. Because of this, it is exceedingly unlikely that there is any rationally coherent normative moral theory that can accommodate our moral intuitions. Moreover, anyone who claims to have such a theory, or even part of one, almost certainly doesn't. Instead, what that person probably has is a moral rationalization. It seems then, that we have somehow crossed the infamous "is"-"ought" divide. How did this happen? Didn't Hume (Hume, 1978) and Moore (Moore, 1966) warn us against trying to derive an "ought" from and "is?" How did we go from descriptive scientific theories concerning moral psychology to skepticism about a whole class of normative moral theories? The answer is that we did not, as Hume and Moore anticipated, attempt to derive an "ought" from and "is." That is, our method has been inductive rather than deductive. We have inferred on the basis of the available evidence that the phenomenon of rationalist deontological philosophy is best explained as a rationalization of evolved emotional intuition (Harman, 1977). Missing the Deontological Point I suspect that rationalist deontologists will remain unmoved by the arguments presented here. Instead, I suspect, they will insist that I have simply misunderstood whatKant and like-minded deontologists are all about. Deontology, they will say, isn't about this intuition or that intuition. It's not defined by its normative differences with consequentialism. Rather, deontology is about taking humanity seriously. Above all else, it's about respect for persons. It's about treating others as fellow rational creatures rather than as mere objects, about acting for reasons rational beings can share. And so on (Korsgaard, 1996a; Korsgaard, 1996b).This is, no doubt, how many deontologists see deontology. But this insider's view, as I've suggested, may be misleading. The problem, more specifically, is that it defines deontology in terms of values that are not distinctively deontological, though they may appear to be from the inside. Consider the following analogy with religion. When one asks a religious person to explain the essence of his religion, one often gets an answer like this: "It's about love, really. It's about looking out for other people, looking beyond oneself. It's about community, being part of something larger than oneself." This sort of answer accurately captures the phenomenology of many people's religion, but it's nevertheless inadequate for distinguishing religion from other things. This is because many, if not most, non-religious people aspire to love deeply, look out for other people, avoid self-absorption, have a sense of a community, and be connected to things larger than themselves. In other words, secular humanists and atheists can assent to most of what many religious people think religion is all about. From a secular humanist's point of view, in contrast, what's distinctive about religion is its commitment to the existence of supernatural entities as well as formal religious institutions and doctrines. And they're right. These things really do distinguish religious from non-religious practices, though they may appear to be secondary to many people operating from within a religious point of view. In the same way, I believe that most of the standard deontological/Kantian self-characterizatons fail to distinguish deontology from other approaches to ethics. (See also Kagan (Kagan, 1997, pp. 70-78.) on the difficulty of defining deontology.) It seems to me that consequentialists, as much as anyone else, have respect for persons, are against treating people as mere objects, wish to act for reasons that rational creatures can share, etc. A consequentialist respects other persons, and refrains from treating them as mere objects, by counting every person's well-being in the decision-making process. Likewise, a consequentialist attempts to act according to reasons that rational creatures can share by acting according to principles that give equal weight to everyone's interests, i.e. that are impartial. This is not to say that consequentialists and deontologists don't differ. They do. It's just that the real differences may not be what deontologists often take them to be. What, then, distinguishes deontology from other kinds of moral thought? A good strategy for answering this question is to start with concrete disagreements between deontologists and others (such as consequentialists) and then work backward in search of deeper principles. This is what I've attempted to do with the trolley and footbridge cases, and other instances in which deontologists and consequentialists disagree. If you ask a deontologically-minded person why it's wrong to push someone in front of speeding trolley in order to save five others, you will getcharacteristically deontological answers. Some will be tautological: "Because it's murder!"Others will be more sophisticated: "The ends don't justify the means." "You have to respect people's rights." But, as we know, these answers don't really explain anything, because if you give the same people (on different occasions) the trolley case or the loop case (See above), they'll make the opposite judgment, even though their initial explanation concerning the footbridge case applies equally well to one or both of these cases. Talk about rights, respect for persons, and reasons we can share are natural attempts to explain, in "cognitive" terms, what we feel when we find ourselves having emotionally driven intuitions that are odds with the cold calculus of consequentialism. Although these explanations are inevitably incomplete, there seems to be "something deeply right" about them because they give voice to powerful moral emotions. But, as with many religious people's accounts of what's essential to religion, they don't really explain what's distinctive about the philosophy in question. | 6,158 | <h4>Use util</h4><p><strong>Greene 10</strong> Associate Professor of the Social Sciences Department of Psychology Harvard University, Joshua, Moral Psychology: Historical and Contemporary Readings, “The Secret Joke of Kant’s Soul”, www.fed.cuhk.edu.hk/~lchang/material/Evolutionary/Developmental/Greene-KantSoul.pdf</p><p><u>What</u> <u>turn-of-the-millennium <mark>science</u> <u>is telling us</u></mark> <u>is</u> <u>that</u> <u>human</u> <u><mark>moral judgment is not</mark> a</u> <u>pristine</u> <u><mark>rational enterprise</u></mark>, that our <u>moral judgments are driven by a hodgepodge of emotional dispositions, which themselves were shaped by a hodgepodge of evolutionary forces, both biological and cultural</u>. <u>Because of this, <mark>it is</u> <u><strong>exceedingly unlikely</mark> that <mark>there is any</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>rationally</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>coherent</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>normative</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>moral theory that</mark> <mark>can accommodate</u></strong> <u><strong>our</u></strong> <u><strong>moral intuitions</u></strong></mark>. Moreover, <u>anyone who claims to have such a theory</u>, or even part of one, <u><strong>almost certainly doesn't</u></strong>. Instead, what that person probably has is a moral rationalization. It seems then, that we have somehow crossed the infamous "is"-"ought" divide. How did this happen? Didn't Hume (Hume, 1978) and Moore (Moore, 1966) warn us against trying to derive an "ought" from and "is?" How did we go from descriptive scientific theories concerning moral psychology to skepticism about a whole class of normative moral theories? The answer is that we did not, as Hume and Moore anticipated, attempt to derive an "ought" from and "is." That is, our method has been inductive rather than deductive. We have inferred on the basis of the available evidence that the phenomenon of rationalist deontological philosophy is best explained as a rationalization of evolved emotional intuition (Harman, 1977).<u> Missing the Deontological Point </u>I suspect that <u>rationalist</u> <u>deontologists will remain unmoved</u> <u>by the arguments presented here</u>. Instead, I suspect, <u>they</u> <u>will insist that I have</u> <u><strong>simply misunderstood</u></strong> <u><strong>what</u></strong>Kant and like-minded <u><strong>deontologists</u></strong> <u><strong>are all about</u></strong>. <u>Deontology, they will say, isn't about this intuition or that intuition</u>. It's not defined by its normative differences with consequentialism. <u>Rather, deontology is about taking humanity seriously</u>. Above all else, it's about respect for persons. It's about treating others as fellow rational creatures rather than as mere objects, about acting for reasons rational beings can share. And so on (Korsgaard, 1996a; Korsgaard, 1996b).<u>This is, no doubt, how many deontologists see deontology. But this insider's view</u>, as I've suggested, <u><strong>may be misleading</u></strong>. <u>The problem</u>, more specifically, <u><strong>is that it defines deontology in terms of values that are not</u></strong> <u><strong>distinctively</u></strong> <u><strong>deontological</u></strong>, though they may appear to be from the inside. <u>Consider the following analogy with religion. When one asks a religious person to explain the essence of his religion, one often gets an answer like this: "It's about love</u>, really. It's about looking out for other people, looking beyond oneself. It's about community, being part of something larger than oneself." <u>This sort of answer accurately captures the phenomenology of many people's religion, but it's nevertheless inadequate for distinguishing religion from other things</u>. This is because many, if not most, non-religious people aspire to love deeply, look out for other people, avoid self-absorption, have a sense of a community, and be connected to things larger than themselves. In other words, secular humanists and atheists can assent to most of what many religious people think religion is all about. From a secular humanist's point of view, in contrast, what's distinctive about religion is its commitment to the existence of supernatural entities as well as formal religious institutions and doctrines. And they're right. These things really do distinguish religious from non-religious practices, though they may appear to be secondary to many people operating from within a religious point of view. In the same way, I believe that most of <u>the standard</u> <u>deontological/Kantian self-characterizatons</u> <u><strong>fail to distinguish deontology from other approaches to ethics</u></strong>. (See also Kagan (Kagan, 1997, pp. 70-78.) on the difficulty of defining deontology.) It seems to me that <u><mark>consequentialists</u></mark>, as much as anyone else, <u><strong><mark>have respect for persons</u></strong></mark>, <u>are</u> <u><strong>against treating people as</u></strong> <u><strong>mere</u></strong> <u><strong>objects</u></strong>, <u>wish</u> <u><strong>to act for reasons that rational creatures can share</strong>, etc</u>. <u>A consequentialist respects other persons, and <mark>refrains from treating them as</mark> mere <mark>objects</mark>,</u> <u><mark>by counting<strong> every person's well-being</u></strong> <u><strong>in the decision-making process</u></strong></mark>. <u>Likewise, a</u> <u>consequentialist</u> <u>attempts to act according to reasons that rational creatures can share by acting according to</u> <u>principles</u> <u><mark>that</u> <u><strong>give equal weight to everyone's interests</strong></mark>, i.e. that are impartial</u>. This is not to say that consequentialists and deontologists don't differ. They do. It's just that the real differences may not be what deontologists often take them to be. What, then, distinguishes deontology from other kinds of moral thought? A good strategy for answering this question is to start with concrete disagreements between deontologists and others (such as consequentialists) and then work backward in search of deeper principles. This is what I've attempted to do with the trolley and footbridge cases, and other instances in which deontologists and consequentialists disagree. <u><mark>If you ask a deontologically-minded</u> <u>person why it's</mark> <mark>wrong to push someone</mark> in front of</u> <u>speeding</u> <u>trolley</u> <u>in order</u> <u><mark>to save five others</u></mark>, you will getcharacteristically deontological <u><mark>answers</u></mark>. Some <u><strong><mark>will be</u></strong> <u><strong>tautological</strong></mark>:</u> <u><strong>"Because it's murder!"</strong>Others will be more sophisticated: "The ends don't justify the means</u>." "You have to respect people's rights." <u><strong>But</u></strong>, as we know, <u>these answers don't really explain anything</u>, because <u>if you give the same people</u> (on different occasions) <u>the trolley case</u> or the loop case (See above), <u><strong>they'll make the opposite judgment</u></strong>, even though their initial explanation concerning the footbridge case applies equally well to one or both of these cases. <u>Talk about rights,</u> <u>respect for persons, and reasons we can share</u> <u>are natural attempts to explain, in "cognitive" terms, what we feel</u> <u>when we find ourselves having emotionally driven intuitions that are odds with the cold calculus of consequentialism</u>. Although these explanations are inevitably incomplete, <u><strong>there seems to be "something deeply right" about them</u></strong> <u><strong>because they give voice to powerful moral emotions</strong>.</u> <u>But, as with many religious people's accounts of what's essential to religion,</u> <u>they don't</u> <u>really</u> <u>explain what's distinctive about</u> <u>the philosophy in question</u>.</p> | 2AC | Cap | 2AC Cap | 10,110 | 1,812 | 122,311 | ./documents/ndtceda16/GeorgeMason/ReGu/George%20Mason-Reddy-Guzman-Aff-JMU-Octas.docx | 588,144 | A | JMU | Octas | JMU SF | Crenshaw, Hagwood, Holguin | 1AC Warming Nuclear Paris
1NC T-Restrict Econ DA Trade DA China DA with Econ Impact Cap K Warming Good Nuclear Case Args Paris Soft Power Args Middle East Heg Turn (Heg Bad) Solvency | ndtceda16/GeorgeMason/ReGu/George%20Mason-Reddy-Guzman-Aff-JMU-Octas.docx | null | 50,241 | ReGu | George Mason ReGu | null | Pa..... | Re..... | An..... | Gu..... | 19,026 | GeorgeMason | George Mason | null | null | 1,006 | ndtceda16 | NDT/CEDA 2016-17 | 2,016 | cx | college | 2 |
698,250 | 3 – Hypersonic warhead discrimination is impossible – weapons move too fast and follow irregular trajectory, which means countries will think they’re being attacked and launch nukes in response – that causes full–blown nuclear war – Acton’s wrong | Van Loon 19 | Van Loon 19 [Margot van Loon is a Junior Fellow at the American Foreign Policy Council, where her research focuses on defense policy, arms control, and international cooperation. As a 2018 Rosenthal Fellow, she served in the policy office for countering weapons of mass destruction at the Department of Defense, and previously worked in the Office of the Under Secretary of Defense for Acquisition, Technology, and Logistics. She holds an MPP (International and Global Affairs) from the Harvard Kennedy School of Government and a BA in International Studies from American University. DEFENSE TECHNOLOGY PROGRAM BRIEF: Hypersonic Weapons. May 2019. https://www.afpc.org/uploads/documents/Defense_Technology_Briefing_-_Issue_18.pdf] | Hypersonic weapons are coming online just as the United States shifts its focus to great power competition To China and Russia who are seeking ways to expand the role of nuclear weapons in their strategies the unique characteristics of hypersonic systems including ability to render useless all current U.S. missile defenses represent a perfect opportunity to take the lead
Putin and Kremlin officials alarmingly boasted of the role such capabilities could play in a decapitation strike on the United States
pace of testing and adversarial rhetoric has contributed to fears among American policymakers the reality may be more tempered Acton argued
however this would allow them “to threaten, with nonnuclear warheads, targets in Europe and eventually the continental United States that, previously could only have destroyed with nuclear weapons rendering U.S. missile defenses obsolete lowering the bar to full-blown military conflict
the inadvertent escalation risk of hypersonic weapons should not be underestimated Because of speed and maneuverability it would be nearly impossible to predict what facilities or country is being targeted if a country detected the launch it would be impossible to know for certain the type of warhead it carries a conventional strike could easily be mistaken for a preemptive nuclear attack.17 | To China and Russia who are seeking ways to expand the role of nuclear weapons in their strategies hypersonic systems represent a perfect opportunity
Putin and Kremlin officials alarmingly boasted of the role such could play in decapitation strike on the U S
pace of testing and adversarial rhetoric contributed to fears among American policymakers the reality may be more tempered Acton argued
however, this would allow them “to threaten with nonnuclear warheads Europe and the continental U S rendering missile defenses obsolete lowering the bar to full-blown conflict
inadvertent escalation risk should not be underestimated Because of speed and maneuverability it would be impossible to predict what facilities (or country) is being targeted it would be impossible to know the warhead it carries conventional strike could easily be mistaken for preemptive nuclear attack | Hypersonic weapons are coming online just as the United States shifts its focus back to great power competition as its most pressing national security threat. To China and Russia - both of whom are rapidly modernizing their military capabilities and seeking ways to expand the role of nuclear weapons in their strategies6 - the unique characteristics of hypersonic systems (including their ability to render useless all current U.S. missile defenses) represent a perfect opportunity to take the lead in a high-stakes technological field.
Russia’s “Kinzhal” aircraft-launched boost-glide vehicle is currently operational,7 and its nuclear-capable “Avangard” system will reportedly come online in 2019 (after much rhetorical fanfare from Vladimir Putin and other high-profile Kremlin officials, who have alarmingly boasted of the role such capabilities could play in a potential decapitation strike on the United States).8 China has tested multiple systems, including the “Starry Sky-2” boost-glide system and the DF-ZF unpowered glide vehicle (referred to by DoD as WU-14) that would give Beijing conventional prompt strike capability over a multi-thousand kilometer range. 9 Both countries have conducted multiple tests of these systems while continuing to funnel massive funding into hypersonics research and development (R&D)10 - two trends that, in the last year, have thrust the United States’ own hypersonic efforts into an uncomfortable spotlight.
Somewhat understandably, the pace of testing and the adversarial rhetoric has contributed to perceptions and fears among American policymakers of a new arms race. However, the reality may be more tempered. James Acton, co-director of the Carnegie Endowment for International Peace, has argued that “in many ways, the United States is running a different race from Russia and China.”11 Russia and China are generally believed to take a different view of the role that hypersonic weapons can play in their strategy than the United States. Their interest appears vested in the capability of getting nuclear-armed vehicles past U.S. ballistic missile defenses. To many U.S. experts and leaders, this is not the strategic disruption it might seem. They assert that intercontinental ballistic missiles and submarine-launched ballistic missiles already give Washington, Moscow, and Beijing an unpreventable ability to launch a nuclear strike. Adding nuclear-equipped long-range hypersonic weapons that can defeat current missile defenses essentially results in the same outcome, and thus would not truly alter the strategic balance among the three powers that currently possess them.12 Rather, U.S. officials see greater potential value in the ability of conventionally-armed hypersonic weapons to disrupt the tactical dynamics of regional or theater conflicts by expanding U.S. response options without crossing the nuclear threshold.13
Certainly, hypersonic threats do not necessarily require hypersonic responses, and the logic of deterrence still matters.14 Should Beijing or Moscow field hypersonic weapons with conventional warheads, however, this would allow them “to threaten, with nonnuclear warheads, targets in Europe and eventually the continental United States that, previously, [they] could only have destroyed with nuclear weapons,”15 rendering U.S. missile defenses obsolete while holding the United States at risk and lowering the bar to full-blown military conflict.16
That said, the inadvertent escalation risk of hypersonic weapons should not be underestimated. Because of their speed and maneuverability, it would be nearly impossible to predict what facilities (or even what country) is being targeted if a country detected the launch of one of these weapons. Moreover, it would be impossible to know for certain the type of warhead it carries, meaning that a conventional strike could easily be mistaken for a preemptive nuclear attack.17 | 3,908 | <h4>3 – Hypersonic warhead discrimination is <u>impossible</u> – weapons <u>move too fast</u> and follow <u>irregular trajectory</u>, which means countries will <u>think they’re being attacked</u> and <u>launch nukes in response</u> – that causes <u>full–blown nuclear war</u> – Acton’s wrong</h4><p><strong>Van Loon 19</strong> [Margot van Loon is a Junior Fellow at the American Foreign Policy Council, where her research focuses on defense policy, arms control, and international cooperation. As a 2018 Rosenthal Fellow, she served in the policy office for countering weapons of mass destruction at the Department of Defense, and previously worked in the Office of the Under Secretary of Defense for Acquisition, Technology, and Logistics. She holds an MPP (International and Global Affairs) from the Harvard Kennedy School of Government and a BA in International Studies from American University. DEFENSE TECHNOLOGY PROGRAM BRIEF: Hypersonic Weapons. May 2019. https://www.afpc.org/uploads/documents/Defense_Technology_Briefing_-_Issue_18.pdf]</p><p><u><strong>Hypersonic weapons</strong> are coming online <strong>just</strong> as the <strong>U</strong>nited <strong>S</strong>tates <strong>shifts its focus</u></strong> back <u>to <strong>great power competition</u></strong> as its most pressing national security threat. <u><mark>To <strong>China and Russia</u></strong></mark> - both of <u><mark>who</u></mark>m <u><mark>are</u></mark> rapidly modernizing their military capabilities and <u><mark>seeking ways to</mark> <strong><mark>expand the role</strong> of <strong>nuclear weapons</strong> in their strategies</u></mark>6 - <u>the unique characteristics of <mark>hypersonic systems</u></mark> (<u>including</u> their <u>ability to render useless all current U.S. missile defenses</u>) <u><mark>represent a <strong>perfect opportunity</u></strong></mark> <u>to <strong>take the lead</u></strong> in a high-stakes technological field.</p><p>Russia’s “Kinzhal” aircraft-launched boost-glide vehicle is currently operational,7 and its nuclear-capable “Avangard” system will reportedly come online in 2019 (after much rhetorical fanfare from Vladimir <u><strong><mark>Putin</strong> and</u></mark> other high-profile <u><strong><mark>Kremlin officials</u></strong></mark>, who have <u><strong><mark>alarmingly boasted</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>of the role such</mark> capabilities <mark>could play in</mark> a</u> potential <u><strong><mark>decapitation strike</u></strong> <u>on the <strong>U</strong></mark>nited <strong><mark>S</strong></mark>tates</u>).8 China has tested multiple systems, including the “Starry Sky-2” boost-glide system and the DF-ZF unpowered glide vehicle (referred to by DoD as WU-14) that would give Beijing conventional prompt strike capability over a multi-thousand kilometer range. 9 Both countries have conducted multiple tests of these systems while continuing to funnel massive funding into hypersonics research and development (R&D)10 - two trends that, in the last year, have thrust the United States’ own hypersonic efforts into an uncomfortable spotlight.</p><p>Somewhat understandably, the <u><strong><mark>pace of testing</u></strong> <u>and</u></mark> the <u><strong><mark>adversarial rhetoric</u></strong></mark> <u>has <mark>contributed to</u></mark> perceptions and <u><strong><mark>fears</u></strong> <u>among</u> <u><strong>American policymakers</u></strong></mark> of a new arms race. However, <u><mark>the reality may be more tempered</u></mark>. James <u><strong><mark>Acton</u></strong></mark>, co-director of the Carnegie Endowment for International Peace, has <u><strong><mark>argued</u></strong></mark> that “in many ways, the United States is running a different race from Russia and China.”11 Russia and China are generally believed to take a different view of the role that hypersonic weapons can play in their strategy than the United States. Their interest appears vested in the capability of getting nuclear-armed vehicles past U.S. ballistic missile defenses. To many U.S. experts and leaders, this is not the strategic disruption it might seem. They assert that intercontinental ballistic missiles and submarine-launched ballistic missiles already give Washington, Moscow, and Beijing an unpreventable ability to launch a nuclear strike. Adding nuclear-equipped long-range hypersonic weapons that can defeat current missile defenses essentially results in the same outcome, and thus would not truly alter the strategic balance among the three powers that currently possess them.12 Rather, U.S. officials see greater potential value in the ability of conventionally-armed hypersonic weapons to disrupt the tactical dynamics of regional or theater conflicts by expanding U.S. response options without crossing the nuclear threshold.13</p><p>Certainly, hypersonic threats do not necessarily require hypersonic responses, and the logic of deterrence still matters.14 Should Beijing or Moscow field hypersonic weapons with conventional warheads, <u><strong><mark>however</u></strong>, <u>this would allow them “to <strong>threaten</strong></mark>, <mark>with <strong>nonnuclear warheads</strong></mark>, targets in <strong><mark>Europe</strong> and</mark> eventually <mark>the <strong>continental U</strong></mark>nited <strong><mark>S</strong></mark>tates that, previously</u>, [they] <u>could only have destroyed with nuclear weapons</u>,”15 <u><mark>rendering</mark> <strong>U.S. <mark>missile defenses obsolete</u></strong></mark> while holding the United States at risk and <u><strong><mark>lowering the bar</strong> to <strong>full-blown</strong></mark> military <strong><mark>conflict</u></strong></mark>.16</p><p>That said, <u>the <strong><mark>inadvertent escalation risk</strong></mark> of <strong>hypersonic weapons</strong> <mark>should <strong>not be underestimated</u></strong></mark>. <u><mark>Because of</u></mark> their <u><strong><mark>speed</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>and <strong>maneuverability</u></strong></mark>, <u><mark>it would be</mark> <strong>nearly <mark>impossible</strong> to <strong>predict what facilities</u></strong> (<u>or</u></mark> even what <u><strong><mark>country</u></strong>) <u>is being targeted</mark> if a country detected the launch</u> of one of these weapons. Moreover, <u><mark>it would be impossible to know</mark> for certain <mark>the</mark> type of <mark>warhead it carries</u></mark>, meaning that <u>a <strong><mark>conventional strike</strong> could <strong>easily be mistaken</u></strong> <u>for</mark> a <strong><mark>preemptive nuclear attack</strong></mark>.17</p></u> | null | 1AC | 2 | 374,456 | 142 | 15,039 | ./documents/hsld19/Harker/Da/Harker-Dani-Aff-Stanford-Triples.docx | 838,525 | A | Stanford | Triples | Silver Creek VVo | Michael Murray, Vinay Maruri, Alex Avery | 1AC - disarm lay
1NC - queer pess nukespeak
2NR - all | hsld19/Harker/Da/Harker-Dani-Aff-Stanford-Triples.docx | null | 71,631 | ArDa | Harker ArDa | null | Ar..... | Da..... | null | null | 24,119 | Harker | Harker | CA | null | 1,027 | hsld19 | HS LD 2019-20 | 2,019 | ld | hs | 1 |
2,589,269 | Decline doesn’t cause war---incites cooperation | Davis & Pelc 17 | Christina L. Davis & Krzysztof J. Pelc 17, Christina L. Davis is a Professor of Politics and International Affairs at Princeton; Krzysztof J. Pelc is an Associate Professor of Political Science at McGill University, “Cooperation in Hard Times: Self-restraint of Trade Protection,” Journal of Conflict Resolution, 61(2): 398-429 | Conclusion Political economy theory would lead us to expect rising trade protection during hard times Yet empirical evidence has been mixed Our statistical findings show that under conditions of pervasive economic crisis states exercise more restraint These results throw light on behavior not only during the crisis, but throughout the WTO period By controlling for product-level imports, we show that the restraint on remedy use is not a byproduct of declining imports We also take into account the ability of countries to manipulate their currency and demonstrate that the relationship between crisis and trade protection holds independent of exchange rate policies decisions to impose costs on their trade partners by taking advantage of their legal right to use flexibility measures can give rise to an individual incentive for strategic self-restraint toward trade partners in similar economic trouble government leaders fear the repercussions that their own use of trade protection may have on the behavior of trade partners at a time when they cannot afford the economic cost of a trade war Institutions provide monitoring and a venue for leader interaction that facilitates coordination among states to reinforce expectations that any move to protect industries will trigger similar moves in other countries tools of informal governance such as leader pledges, guidance from the Director General, trade policy reviews, and plenary meetings play a real role within the trade regime These circumstances trigger informal mechanisms that complement legal rules to support cooperation During widespread crisis, legal enforcement would be inadequate, and informal governance helps to bolster the system institutions are generating restraint by facilitating informal coordination Rather than reinforcing pressure for protection, pervasive crisis in the global economy is shown to generate countervailing pressure for restraint in response to domestic crisis hard times bring more, not less, international cooperation | under economic crisis states exercise restraint leaders fear repercussions Institutions facilitate coordination to protect industries During crisis informal governance bolster the system hard times bring more cooperation | Conclusion Political economy theory would lead us to expect rising trade protection during hard times. Yet empirical evidence on this count has been mixed. Some studies find a correlation between poor macroeconomic conditions and protection, but the worst recession since the Great Depression has generated surprisingly moderate levels of protection. We explain this apparent contradiction. Our statistical findings show that under conditions of pervasive economic crisis at the international level, states exercise more restraint than they would when facing crisis alone. These results throw light on behavior not only during the crisis, but throughout the WTO period, from 1995 to the present. One concern may be that the restraint we observe during widespread crises is actually the result of a decrease in aggregate demand and that domestic pressure for import relief is lessened by the decline of world trade. By controlling for product-level imports, we show that the restraint on remedy use is not a byproduct of declining imports. We also take into account the ability of some countries to manipulate their currency and demonstrate that the relationship between crisis and trade protection holds independent of exchange rate policies. Government decisions to impose costs on their trade partners by taking advantage of their legal right to use flexibility measures are driven not only by the domestic situation but also by circumstances abroad. This can give rise to an individual incentive for strategic self-restraint toward trade partners in similar economic trouble. Under conditions of widespread crisis, government leaders fear the repercussions that their own use of trade protection may have on the behavior of trade partners at a time when they cannot afford the economic cost of a trade war. Institutions provide monitoring and a venue for leader interaction that facilitates coordination among states. Here the key function is to reinforce expectations that any move to protect industries will trigger similar moves in other countries. Such coordination often draws on shared historical analogies, such as the Smoot–Hawley lesson, which form a focal point to shape beliefs about appropriate state behavior. Much of the literature has focused on the more visible action of legal enforcement through dispute settlement, but this only captures part of the story. Our research suggests that tools of informal governance such as leader pledges, guidance from the Director General, trade policy reviews, and plenary meetings play a real role within the trade regime. In the absence of sufficiently stringent rules over flexibility measures, compliance alone is insufficient during a global economic crisis. These circumstances trigger informal mechanisms that complement legal rules to support cooperation. During widespread crisis, legal enforcement would be inadequate, and informal governance helps to bolster the system. Informal coordination is by nature difficult to observe, and we are unable to directly measure this process. Instead, we examine the variation in responses across crises of varying severity, within the context of the same formal setting of the WTO. Yet by focusing on discretionary tools of protection—trade remedies and tariff hikes within the bound rate—we can offer conclusions about how systemic crises shape country restraint independent of formal institutional constraints. Insofar as institutions are generating such restraint, we offer that it is by facilitating informal coordination, since all these instruments of trade protection fall within the letter of the law. Future research should explore trade policy at the micro level to identify which pathway is the most important for coordination. Research at a more macro-historical scope could compare how countries respond to crises under fundamentally different institutional contexts. In sum, the determinants of protection include economic downturns not only at home but also abroad. Rather than reinforcing pressure for protection, pervasive crisis in the global economy is shown to generate countervailing pressure for restraint in response to domestic crisis. In some cases, hard times bring more, not less, international cooperation. | 4,239 | <h4>Decline doesn’t cause war---incites cooperation</h4><p>Christina L. <strong>Davis &</strong> Krzysztof J. <strong>Pelc 17</strong>, Christina L. Davis is a Professor of Politics and International Affairs at Princeton; Krzysztof J. Pelc is an Associate Professor of Political Science at McGill University, “Cooperation in Hard Times: Self-restraint of Trade Protection,” Journal of Conflict Resolution, 61(2): 398-429 </p><p><u>Conclusion Political economy theory would lead us to expect rising trade protection during hard times</u>. <u>Yet <strong>empirical evidence</u></strong> on this count <u>has been mixed</u>. Some studies find a correlation between poor macroeconomic conditions and protection, but the worst recession since the Great Depression has generated surprisingly moderate levels of protection. We explain this apparent contradiction. <u>Our statistical findings show that <mark>under</mark> conditions of pervasive <mark>economic crisis</u></mark> at the international level, <u><mark>states exercise</mark> more <strong><mark>restraint</u></strong></mark> than they would when facing crisis alone. <u>These results throw light on behavior not only during the crisis, but throughout the WTO period</u>, from 1995 to the present. One concern may be that the restraint we observe during widespread crises is actually the result of a decrease in aggregate demand and that domestic pressure for import relief is lessened by the decline of world trade. <u>By <strong>controlling</strong> for <strong>product-level imports</strong>, we show that the restraint on remedy use is not a byproduct of declining imports</u>. <u>We</u> <u><strong>also</u></strong> <u>take into account the ability of</u> some <u>countries to <strong>manipulate their currency</strong> and demonstrate that the relationship between crisis and trade protection <strong>holds</strong> independent of exchange rate policies</u>. Government <u>decisions to impose costs on their trade partners by taking advantage of their legal right to use flexibility measures</u> are driven not only by the domestic situation but also by circumstances abroad. This <u>can give rise to an individual <strong>incentive for strategic self-restraint</strong> toward trade partners in similar economic trouble</u>. Under conditions of widespread crisis, <u>government <mark>leaders <strong>fear</strong></mark> the <strong><mark>repercussions</strong></mark> that their own use of trade protection may have on the behavior of trade partners at a time when they cannot afford the economic cost of a trade war</u>. <u><mark>Institutions</mark> provide <strong>monitoring</strong> and a venue for <strong>leader interaction</strong> that <strong><mark>facilitate</mark>s <mark>coordination</strong></mark> among states</u>. Here the key function is <u><mark>to</mark> reinforce expectations that any move to <mark>protect industries</mark> will trigger similar moves in other countries</u>. Such coordination often draws on shared historical analogies, such as the Smoot–Hawley lesson, which form a focal point to shape beliefs about appropriate state behavior. Much of the literature has focused on the more visible action of legal enforcement through dispute settlement, but this only captures part of the story. Our research suggests that <u>tools of informal governance such as leader pledges, guidance from the Director General, trade policy reviews, and plenary meetings <strong>play a real role</strong> within the trade regime</u>. In the absence of sufficiently stringent rules over flexibility measures, compliance alone is insufficient during a global economic crisis. <u>These <strong>circumstances</strong> trigger <strong>informal mechanisms</strong> that complement legal rules to <strong>support cooperation</u></strong>. <u><mark>During</mark> widespread <mark>crisis</mark>, legal enforcement would be inadequate, and <mark>informal governance</mark> helps to <mark>bolster the system</u></mark>. Informal coordination is by nature difficult to observe, and we are unable to directly measure this process. Instead, we examine the variation in responses across crises of varying severity, within the context of the same formal setting of the WTO. Yet by focusing on discretionary tools of protection—trade remedies and tariff hikes within the bound rate—we can offer conclusions about how systemic crises shape country restraint independent of formal institutional constraints. Insofar as <u>institutions are generating </u>such <u>restraint</u>, we offer that it is <u>by facilitating informal coordination</u>, since all these instruments of trade protection fall within the letter of the law. Future research should explore trade policy at the micro level to identify which pathway is the most important for coordination. Research at a more macro-historical scope could compare how countries respond to crises under fundamentally different institutional contexts. In sum, the determinants of protection include economic downturns not only at home but also abroad. <u>Rather than reinforcing pressure for protection, pervasive crisis in the global economy is shown to generate countervailing pressure for restraint in response to domestic crisis</u>. In some cases, <u><strong><mark>hard times bring more</mark>, not less, international <mark>cooperation</u></strong></mark>. </p> | 2AC | USMCA DA | 2AC---Econ | 10,311 | 545 | 82,947 | ./documents/ndtceda19/MissouriState/EnHo/Missouri%20State-Engelby-Hopkins-Aff-Samford-Round1.docx | 614,119 | A | Samford | 1 | Samford EG | Megan Mapes | 1AC- SSA (Transparency STM)
1NC- ASPEC EU CP XO CP Transparency DA USMCA DA China-Japan Relations DA
2NR- China-Japan Relations DA | ndtceda19/MissouriState/EnHo/Missouri%20State-Engelby-Hopkins-Aff-Samford-Round1.docx | null | 51,980 | EnHo | Missouri State EnHo | null | Cl..... | En..... | Pa..... | Ho..... | 19,273 | MissouriState | Missouri State | null | null | 1,009 | ndtceda19 | NDT/CEDA 2019-20 | 2,019 | cx | college | 2 |
1,872,157 | Capitalism’s drive to accumulate compels environmental catastrophe and nuclear warfare --- we should mobilize our intellectual energies accordingly | Eagleton 11 | Eagleton 11 [Terry, Distinguished Professor of English Literature at Lancaster University, Why Marx Was Right, 2011, Yale University: New Haven, CT, p. 224-6] | The two great threats to human survival that now confront us are military and environmental. They are likely to converge more and more in the future, as struggles over scarce resources escalate into armed conflict communists have been among the most ardent advocates of peace, It seems axiomatic ‘‘that the expansionary, competitive logic of capitalist accumulation must be destabilizing, and that capitalism is the greatest threat to world peace The same goes for environmentalism capitalism cannot avoid ecological devastation given the antisocial nature of its drive to accumulate it cannot by its nature achieve world peace or respect the material world. Capitalism may be able to accommodate some degree of ecological care, But the essential irrationality of the drive for capital accumulation, which subordinates everything to the requirements of the self-expansion of capital and so-called growth, is unavoidably hostile to ecological balance. As history lurches towards the prospect of nuclear warfare and environmental catastrophe is hard to see how it is less than the sober truth. If we do not act now, it seems that capitalism will be the death of us | The threats to human survival that confront us are military and environmental. likely to converge as struggles escalate into armed conflict It seems axiomatic that capitalist accumulation must be destabilizing capitalism cannot avoid eco devastation, given its drive to accumulate the essential irrationality is unavoidably hostile to ecological balance As history lurches towards of nuclear warfare and environmental catastrophe capitalism will be the death of us | The two great threats to human survival that now confront us are military and environmental. They are likely to converge more and more in the future, as struggles over scarce resources escalate into armed conflict. Over the years, communists have been among the most ardent advocates of peace, and the reason for this is ably summarized by Ellen Meiksins Wood. ‘‘It seems to me axiomatic,’’ she writes, ‘‘that the expansionary, competitive and exploitative logic of capitalist accumulation in the context of the nation-state system must, in the longer or shorter term, be destabilizing, and that capitalism . . . is and will for the foreseeable future remain the greatest threat to world peace.’’≤Σ If the peace movement is to grasp the root causes of global aggression, it cannot afford to ignore the nature of the beast that breeds it. And this means that it cannot afford to ignore the insights of Marxism. The same goes for environmentalism. Wood argues that capitalism cannot avoid ecological devastation, given the antisocial nature of its drive to accumulate. The system may come to tolerate racial and gender equality, but it cannot by its nature achieve world peace or respect the material world. Capitalism, Wood comments, ‘‘may be able to accommodate some degree of ecological care, especially when the technology of environmental protection is itself profitably marketable. But the essential irrationality of the drive for capital accumulation, which subordinates everything to the requirements of the self-expansion of capital and so-called growth, is unavoidably hostile to ecological balance.’’ The old communist slogan ‘‘Socialism or barbarism’’ always seemed to some a touch too apocalyptic. As history lurches towards the prospect of nuclear warfare and environmental catastrophe, it is hard to see how it is less than the sober truth. If we do not act now, it seems that capitalism will be the death of us | 1,924 | <h4>Capitalism’s drive to accumulate compels environmental catastrophe and nuclear warfare --- we should mobilize our intellectual energies accordingly </h4><p><strong>Eagleton 11 </strong>[Terry, Distinguished Professor of English Literature at Lancaster University, Why Marx Was Right, 2011, Yale University: New Haven, CT, p. 224-6]</p><p><u><mark>The</mark> two <strong>great <mark>threats to human survival</strong> that </mark>now <mark>confront us are military and environmental.</mark> They are <mark>likely to converge</mark> more and more in the future, <mark>as struggles</mark> over scarce resources <mark>escalate into armed conflict</u><strong></mark>. Over the years, <u>communists</u> <u></strong>have been among the most <strong>ardent advocates of peace,</u> and the reason for this is ably summarized by Ellen Meiksins Wood. ‘‘<u></strong><mark>It seems</u><strong></mark> to me <u><mark>axiomatic</u></mark>,’’ she writes, <u></strong>‘‘<mark>that</mark> the expansionary, competitive </u><strong>and exploitative <u></strong>logic of <strong><mark>capitalist</mark> <mark>accumulation</u></mark> in the context of the nation-state system <u></strong><mark>must</u><strong></mark>, in the longer or shorter term, <u></strong><mark>be destabilizing</mark>, and that capitalism</u><strong> . . . <u></strong>is</u><strong> and will for the foreseeable future remain <u></strong>the greatest threat to world peace</u><strong>.’’≤Σ If the peace movement is to grasp the root causes of global aggression, it cannot afford to ignore the nature of the beast that breeds it. And this means that it cannot afford to ignore the insights of Marxism. <u></strong>The same goes for environmentalism</u><strong>. Wood argues that <u></strong><mark>capitalism cannot avoid eco</mark>logical <mark>devastation</u><strong>, <u>given</mark> the antisocial nature of <mark>its drive to</mark> <mark>accumulate</u></mark>. The system may come to tolerate racial and gender equality, but <u>it cannot by its nature</u> <u></strong>achieve world peace or respect the material world. Capitalism</u><strong>, Wood comments, ‘‘<u></strong>may be able to accommodate some degree of ecological care,</u><strong> especially when the technology of environmental protection is itself profitably marketable. <u></strong>But <mark>the essential irrationality</mark> of the drive for capital accumulation, which subordinates everything to the requirements of the self-expansion of capital and so-called <strong>growth, <mark>is</mark> <mark>unavoidably hostile to ecological balance</mark>.</u>’’ The old communist slogan ‘‘Socialism or barbarism’’ always seemed to some a touch too apocalyptic. <u></strong><mark>As history lurches towards</mark> the prospect <mark>of <strong>nuclear warfare and environmental catastrophe</u></mark>, it <u></strong>is hard to see how it is less than the sober truth. If we do not act now, it seems that <strong><mark>capitalism will be the death of us</p></u></strong></mark> | null | 2 | null | 9,092 | 169 | 55,141 | ./documents/hspolicy20/GlenbrookSouth/WaSe/Glenbrook%20South-Wawrzyn-Sepahdari-Neg-Bronx-Round4.docx | 729,596 | N | Bronx | 4 | Bronx Science DK | Patrick McCleary | 1ac - Flesh of the unSovereign
1nc - T Framework K Capitalism CT anthroprocene CT Private Policing
2nr - T Framework CT Antrho | hspolicy20/GlenbrookSouth/WaSe/Glenbrook%20South-Wawrzyn-Sepahdari-Neg-Bronx-Round4.docx | null | 62,286 | WaSe | Glenbrook South WaSe | null | Ne..... | Wa..... | Au..... | Se..... | 21,622 | GlenbrookSouth | Glenbrook South | IL | null | 1,019 | hspolicy20 | HS Policy 2020-21 | 2,020 | cx | hs | 2 |
1,938,891 | Scenario analysis is pedagogically valuable – enhances creativity and self-reflexivity, deconstructs cognitive biases and flawed ontological assumptions, and enables the imagination and creation of alternative futures. | Barma et al. 16 | Barma et al. 16 – (May 2016, [Advance Publication Online on 11/6/15], Naazneen Barma, PhD in Political Science from UC-Berkeley, Assistant Professor of National Security Affairs at the Naval Postgraduate School, Brent Durbin, PhD in Political Science from UC-Berkeley, Professor of Government at Smith College, Eric Lorber, JD from UPenn and PhD in Political Science from Duke, Gibson, Dunn & Crutcher, Rachel Whitlark, PhD in Political Science from GWU, Post-Doctoral Research Fellow with the Project on Managing the Atom and International Security Program within the Belfer Center for Science and International Affairs at Harvard, “‘Imagine a World in Which’: Using Scenarios in Political Science,” International Studies Perspectives 17 (2), pp. 1-19, http://www.naazneenbarma.com/uploads/2/9/6/9/29695681/using_scenarios_in_political_science_isp_2015.pdf) | Over the past decade, the “cult of irrelevance” in political science has been lamented by a growing chorus Prominent scholars have diagnosed the gap made the case for why research is valuable for policymaking and offered ideas several initiatives have been formed Many focus on providing scholars with the skills, platforms, and networks to better communicate findings and implications to the policymaking community Yet enhancing communication is only one component Another is the generation of substantive research programs that are actually policy relevant In a field that has an admirable devotion to pedagogical self-reflection strikingly little attention is paid to techniques for generating policy-relevant ideas for research topics This article outlines an experiential and problem-based approach to political science research using scenario analysis Scenario analysis can immerse decision makers in future states that go beyond conventional extrapolations of current trends preparing them to take advantage of unexpected opportunities and to protect themselves from adverse exogenous shocks Scenario analysis is thus typically seen as serving the purposes of corporate planning or as a policy tool Yet scenario analysis is not inherently limited to these uses This section makes a case for the utility of the technique for political science scholarship We characterize scenario analysis as the art of juxtaposing current trends in unexpected combinations in order to articulate surprising and yet plausible futures referred to as “alternative worlds.” Scenarios are explicitly not forecasts or projections based on linear extrapolations of contemporary patterns and they are not hypothesis-based expert predictions Nor should they be equated with simulations, which are functional representations of real institutions or decision-making processes Instead, they are depictions of possible future states of the world together with a narrative of the driving causal forces that could lead to those futures Several features make scenario analysis particularly useful for policymaking Long-term global trends across a number of different realms combine in often-unexpected ways to produce unforeseen challenges Yet the ability of decision makers to imagine, let alone prepare for, discontinuities is constrained by their existing mental models and maps This limitation is exacerbated by well-known cognitive bias tendencies such as groupthink and confirmation bias The power of scenarios lies in their ability to help individuals break out of conventional modes of thinking and analysis by introducing unusual combinations of trends and deliberate discontinuities in narratives about the future Imagining alternative future worlds through a structured analytical process enables policymakers to envision and thereby adapt to something altogether different from the known present Scenarios are essentially textured, plausible, and relevant stories that help us imagine how the future could be different from the past Very simply, scenario analysis can throw into sharp relief often-overlooked yet pressing questions in international affairs that demand focused investigation Scenarios thus offer an innovative tool for developing a political science research agenda achieving this objective requires careful tailoring of the approach The use of scenarios is similar to counterfactual analysis in that it modifies certain variables in a given situation in order to analyze the resulting effects Whereas counterfactuals are traditionally retrospective scenarios are deliberately forward-looking and designed to explore potential futures We see scenarios as a complementary resource for exploring these dynamics in international affairs, rather than as a replacement The scenario process described here has thus been carefully designed to offer some guidance to policy-oriented students who are otherwise left to the relatively unstructured norms by which political science ideas are typically developed The scenario approach to generating research ideas is grounded in the belief that these traditional approaches can be complemented by identifying questions likely to be of great empirical importance in the real world, even if these do not appear in existing research programs or as clear extrapolations from past events scenarios envision alternative worlds that could develop in the medium (five to seven year) term and are designed to tease out issues scholars and policymakers may encounter in the relatively near future so that they can begin thinking critically about them now This timeframe offers a period distant enough from the present as to avoid falling into current events analysis, but not so far into the future as to seem like science fiction participants learn strategies for avoiding failures of creativity and for overturning the assumptions that prevent scholars and analysts from anticipating and understanding the pivotal junctures that arise in international affairs | Scenario analysis can immerse decision makers in future states that go beyond conventional extrapolations juxtaposing trends to articulate plausible “alternative worlds.” Scenarios are depictions of possible future states of the world together with causal forces that could lead to those futures scenario analysis useful for decision makers to imagine, discontinuities power of scenarios lies in their ability to help individuals break out of conventional modes of thinking Imagining alternative worlds enables policymakers to envision and adapt identifying questions of great empirical importance even if these do not appear in existing research programs participants learn strategies for avoiding failures and for overturning assumptions that prevent scholars and analysts from anticipating and understanding | Over the past decade, the “cult of irrelevance” in political science scholarship has been lamented by a growing chorus (Putnam 2003; Nye 2009; Walt 2009). Prominent scholars of international affairs have diagnosed the roots of the gap between academia and policymaking, made the case for why political science research is valuable for policymaking, and offered a number of ideas for enhancing the policy relevance of scholarship in international relations and comparative politics (Walt 2005,2011; Mead 2010; Van Evera 2010; Jentleson and Ratner 2011; Gallucci 2012; Avey and Desch 2014). Building on these insights, several initiatives have been formed in the attempt to “bridge the gap.”2 Many of the specific efforts put in place by these projects focus on providing scholars with the skills, platforms, and networks to better communicate the findings and implications of their research to the policymaking community, a necessary and worthwhile objective for a field in which theoretical debates, methodological training, and publishing norms tend more and more toward the abstract and esoteric. Yet enhancing communication between scholars and policymakers is only one component of bridging the gap between international affairs theory and practice. Another crucial component of this bridge is the generation of substantive research programs that are actually policy relevant—a challenge to which less concerted attention has been paid. The dual challenges of bridging the gap are especially acute for graduate students, a particular irony since many enter the discipline with the explicit hope of informing policy. In a field that has an admirable devotion to pedagogical self-reflection, strikingly little attention is paid to techniques for generating policy-relevant ideas for dissertation and other research topics. Although numerous articles and conference workshops are devoted to the importance of experiential and problem-based learning, especially through techniques of simulation that emulate policymaking processes (Loggins 2009; Butcher 2012; Glasgow 2012; Rothman 2012; DiCicco 2014), little has been written about the use of such techniques for generating and developing innovative research ideas. This article outlines an experiential and problem-based approach to developing a political science research program using scenario analysis. It focuses especially on illuminating the research generation and pedagogical benefits of this technique by describing the use of scenarios in the annual New Era Foreign Policy Conference (NEFPC), which brings together doctoral students of international and comparative affairs who share a demonstrated interest in policy-relevant scholarship.3 In the introductory section, the article outlines the practice of scenario analysis and considers the utility of the technique in political science. We argue that scenario analysis should be viewed as a tool to stimulate problem-based learning for doctoral students and discuss the broader scholarly benefits of using scenarios to help generate research ideas. The second section details the manner in which NEFPC deploys scenario analysis. The third section reflects upon some of the concrete scholarly benefits that have been realized from the scenario format. The fourth section offers insights on the pedagogical potential associated with using scenarios in the classroom across levels of study. A brief conclusion reflects on the importance of developing specific techniques to aid those who wish to generate political science scholarship of relevance to the policy world. What Are Scenarios and Why Use Them in Political Science? Scenario analysis is perceived most commonly as a technique for examining the robustness of strategy. It can immerse decision makers in future states that go beyond conventional extrapolations of current trends, preparing them to take advantage of unexpected opportunities and to protect themselves from adverse exogenous shocks. The global petroleum company Shell, a pioneer of the technique, characterizes scenario analysis as the art of considering “what if” questions about possible future worlds. Scenario analysis is thus typically seen as serving the purposes of corporate planning or as a policy tool to be used in combination with simulations of decision making. Yet scenario analysis is not inherently limited to these uses. This section provides a brief overview of the practice of scenario analysis and the motivations underpinning its uses. It then makes a case for the utility of the technique for political science scholarship and describes how the scenarios deployed at NEFPC were created. The Art of Scenario Analysis We characterize scenario analysis as the art of juxtaposing current trends in unexpected combinations in order to articulate surprising and yet plausible futures, often referred to as “alternative worlds.” Scenarios are thus explicitly not forecasts or projections based on linear extrapolations of contemporary patterns, and they are not hypothesis-based expert predictions. Nor should they be equated with simulations, which are best characterized as functional representations of real institutions or decision-making processes (Asal 2005). Instead, they are depictions of possible future states of the world, offered together with a narrative of the driving causal forces and potential exogenous shocks that could lead to those futures. Good scenarios thus rely on explicit causal propositions that, independent of one another, are plausible—yet, when combined, suggest surprising and sometimes controversial future worlds. For example, few predicted the dramatic fall in oil prices toward the end of 2014. Yet independent driving forces, such as the shale gas revolution in the United States, China’s slowing economic growth, and declining conflict in major Middle Eastern oil producers such as Libya, were all recognized secular trends that—combined with OPEC’s decision not to take concerted action as prices began to decline—came together in an unexpected way. While scenario analysis played a role in war gaming and strategic planning during the Cold War, the real antecedents of the contemporary practice are found in corporate futures studies of the late 1960s and early 1970s (Raskin et al. 2005). Scenario analysis was essentially initiated at Royal Dutch Shell in 1965, with the realization that the usual forecasting techniques and models were not capturing the rapidly changing environment in which the company operated (Wack 1985; Schwartz 1991). In particular, it had become evident that straight-line extrapolations of past global trends were inadequate for anticipating the evolving business environment. Shell-style scenario planning “helped break the habit, ingrained in most corporate planning, of assuming that the future will look much like the present” (Wilkinson and Kupers 2013, 4). Using scenario thinking, Shell anticipated the possibility of two Arab-induced oil shocks in the 1970s and hence was able to position itself for major disruptions in the global petroleum sector. Building on its corporate roots, scenario analysis has become a standard policymaking tool. For example, the Project on Forward Engagement advocates linking systematic foresight, which it defines as the disciplined analysis of alternative futures, to planning and feedback loops to better equip the United States to meet contemporary governance challenges (Fuerth 2011). Another prominent application of scenario thinking is found in the National Intelligence Council’s series of Global Trends reports, issued every four years to aid policymakers in anticipating and planning for future challenges. These reports present a handful of “alternative worlds” approximately twenty years into the future, carefully constructed on the basis of emerging global trends, risks, and opportunities, and intended to stimulate thinking about geopolitical change and its effects.4 As with corporate scenario analysis, the technique can be used in foreign policymaking for long-range general planning purposes as well as for anticipating and coping with more narrow and immediate challenges. An example of the latter is the German Marshall Fund’s EuroFutures project, which uses four scenarios to map the potential consequences of the Euro-area financial crisis (German Marshall Fund 2013). Several features make scenario analysis particularly useful for policymaking.5 Long-term global trends across a number of different realms—social, technological, environmental, economic, and political—combine in often-unexpected ways to produce unforeseen challenges. Yet the ability of decision makers to imagine, let alone prepare for, discontinuities in the policy realm is constrained by their existing mental models and maps. This limitation is exacerbated by well-known cognitive bias tendencies such as groupthink and confirmation bias (Jervis 1976; Janis 1982; Tetlock 2005). The power of scenarios lies in their ability to help individuals break out of conventional modes of thinking and analysis by introducing unusual combinations of trends and deliberate discontinuities in narratives about the future. Imagining alternative future worlds through a structured analytical process enables policymakers to envision and thereby adapt to something altogether different from the known present. Designing Scenarios for Political Science Inquiry The characteristics of scenario analysis that commend its use to policymakers also make it well suited to helping political scientists generate and develop policy-relevant research programs. Scenarios are essentially textured, plausible, and relevant stories that help us imagine how the future political-economic world could be different from the past in a manner that highlights policy challenges and opportunities. For example, terrorist organizations are a known threat that have captured the attention of the policy community, yet our responses to them tend to be linear and reactive. Scenarios that explore how seemingly unrelated vectors of change—the rise of a new peer competitor in the East that diverts strategic attention, volatile commodity prices that empower and disempower various state and nonstate actors in surprising ways, and the destabilizing effects of climate change or infectious disease pandemics—can be useful for illuminating the nature and limits of the terrorist threat in ways that may be missed by a narrower focus on recognized states and groups. By illuminating the potential strategic significance of specific and yet poorly understood opportunities and threats, scenario analysis helps to identify crucial gaps in our collective understanding of global politicaleconomic trends and dynamics. The notion of “exogeneity”—so prevalent in social science scholarship—applies to models of reality, not to reality itself. Very simply, scenario analysis can throw into sharp relief often-overlooked yet pressing questions in international affairs that demand focused investigation. Scenarios thus offer, in principle, an innovative tool for developing a political science research agenda. In practice, achieving this objective requires careful tailoring of the approach. The specific scenario analysis technique we outline below was designed and refined to provide a structured experiential process for generating problem-based research questions with contemporary international policy relevance.6 The first step in the process of creating the scenario set described here was to identify important causal forces in contemporary global affairs. Consensus was not the goal; on the contrary, some of these causal statements represented competing theories about global change (e.g., a resurgence of the nation-state vs. border-evading globalizing forces). A major principle underpinning the transformation of these causal drivers into possible future worlds was to “simplify, then exaggerate” them, before fleshing out the emerging story with more details.7 Thus, the contours of the future world were drawn first in the scenario, with details about the possible pathways to that point filled in second. It is entirely possible, indeed probable, that some of the causal claims that turned into parts of scenarios were exaggerated so much as to be implausible, and that an unavoidable degree of bias or our own form of groupthink went into construction of the scenarios. One of the great strengths of scenario analysis, however, is that the scenario discussions themselves, as described below, lay bare these especially implausible claims and systematic biases.8 An explicit methodological approach underlies the written scenarios themselves as well as the analytical process around them—that of case-centered, structured, focused comparison, intended especially to shed light on new causal mechanisms (George and Bennett 2005). The use of scenarios is similar to counterfactual analysis in that it modifies certain variables in a given situation in order to analyze the resulting effects (Fearon 1991). Whereas counterfactuals are traditionally retrospective in nature and explore events that did not actually occur in the context of known history, our scenarios are deliberately forward-looking and are designed to explore potential futures that could unfold. As such, counterfactual analysis is especially well suited to identifying how individual events might expand or shift the “funnel of choices” available to political actors and thus lead to different historical outcomes (Nye 2005, 68–69), while forward-looking scenario analysis can better illuminate surprising intersections and sociopolitical dynamics without the perceptual constraints imposed by fine-grained historical knowledge. We see scenarios as a complementary resource for exploring these dynamics in international affairs, rather than as a replacement for counterfactual analysis, historical case studies, or other methodological tools. In the scenario process developed for NEFPC, three distinct scenarios are employed, acting as cases for analytical comparison. Each scenario, as detailed below, includes a set of explicit “driving forces” which represent hypotheses about causal mechanisms worth investigating in evolving international affairs. The scenario analysis process itself employs templates (discussed further below) to serve as a graphical representation of a structured, focused investigation and thereby as the research tool for conducting case-centered comparative analysis (George and Bennett 2005). In essence, these templates articulate key observable implications within the alternative worlds of the scenarios and serve as a framework for capturing the data that emerge (King, Keohane, and Verba 1994). Finally, this structured, focused comparison serves as the basis for the cross-case session emerging from the scenario analysis that leads directly to the articulation of new research agendas. The scenario process described here has thus been carefully designed to offer some guidance to policy-oriented graduate students who are otherwise left to the relatively unstructured norms by which political science dissertation ideas are typically developed. The initial articulation of a dissertation project is generally an idiosyncratic and personal undertaking (Useem 1997; Rothman 2008), whereby students might choose topics based on their coursework, their own previous policy exposure, or the topics studied by their advisors. Research agendas are thus typically developed by looking for “puzzles” in existing research programs (Kuhn 1996). Doctoral students also, understandably, often choose topics that are particularly amenable to garnering research funding. Conventional grant programs typically base their funding priorities on extrapolations from what has been important in the recent past—leading to, for example, the prevalence of Japan and Soviet studies in the mid-1980s or terrorism studies in the 2000s—in the absence of any alternative method for identifying questions of likely future significance. The scenario approach to generating research ideas is grounded in the belief that these traditional approaches can be complemented by identifying questions likely to be of great empirical importance in the real world, even if these do not appear as puzzles in existing research programs or as clear extrapolations from past events. The scenarios analyzed at NEFPC envision alternative worlds that could develop in the medium (five to seven year) term and are designed to tease out issues scholars and policymakers may encounter in the relatively near future so that they can begin thinking critically about them now. This timeframe offers a period distant enough from the present as to avoid falling into current events analysis, but not so far into the future as to seem like science fiction. In imagining the worlds in which these scenarios might come to pass, participants learn strategies for avoiding failures of creativity and for overturning the assumptions that prevent scholars and analysts from anticipating and understanding the pivotal junctures that arise in international affairs. | 17,133 | <h4>Scenario analysis is pedagogically valuable – enhances creativity and self-reflexivity, deconstructs cognitive biases and flawed ontological assumptions, and enables the imagination and creation of alternative futures.</h4><p><strong>Barma et al. 16</strong> – (May 2016, [Advance Publication Online on 11/6/15], Naazneen Barma, PhD in Political Science from UC-Berkeley, Assistant Professor of National Security Affairs at the Naval Postgraduate School, Brent Durbin, PhD in Political Science from UC-Berkeley, Professor of Government at Smith College, Eric Lorber, JD from UPenn and PhD in Political Science from Duke, Gibson, Dunn & Crutcher, Rachel Whitlark, PhD in Political Science from GWU, Post-Doctoral Research Fellow with the Project on Managing the Atom and International Security Program within the Belfer Center for Science and International Affairs at Harvard, “‘Imagine a World in Which’: Using Scenarios in Political Science,” International Studies Perspectives 17 (2), pp. 1-19, http://www.naazneenbarma.com/uploads/2/9/6/9/29695681/using_scenarios_in_political_science_isp_2015.pdf)</p><p><u>Over the past decade, the “cult of irrelevance” in political science</u> scholarship <u>has been lamented by a growing chorus</u> (Putnam 2003; Nye 2009; Walt 2009). <u>Prominent scholars</u> of international affairs <u>have diagnosed</u> the roots of <u>the gap</u> between academia and policymaking, <u>made the case for why</u> political science <u>research is valuable for policymaking</u>, <u>and offered</u> a number of <u>ideas</u> for enhancing the policy relevance of scholarship in international relations and comparative politics (Walt 2005,2011; Mead 2010; Van Evera 2010; Jentleson and Ratner 2011; Gallucci 2012; Avey and Desch 2014). Building on these insights, <u>several initiatives have been formed</u> in the attempt to “bridge the gap.”2 <u>Many</u> of the specific efforts put in place by these projects <u>focus on providing scholars with the skills, platforms, and networks to better communicate</u> the <u>findings and implications</u> of their research <u>to the policymaking community</u>, a necessary and worthwhile objective for a field in which theoretical debates, methodological training, and publishing norms tend more and more toward the abstract and esoteric. <u>Yet enhancing communication</u> between scholars and policymakers <u>is only one component</u> of bridging the gap between international affairs theory and practice. <u>Another</u> crucial component of this bridge <u>is the <strong>generation of substantive research programs that are actually policy relevant</u></strong>—a challenge to which less concerted attention has been paid. The dual challenges of bridging the gap are especially acute for graduate students, a particular irony since many enter the discipline with the explicit hope of informing policy. <u>In a field that has an admirable devotion to pedagogical self-reflection</u>, <u><strong>strikingly little attention is paid to techniques for generating policy-relevant ideas</u></strong> <u>for</u> dissertation and other <u>research topics</u>. Although numerous articles and conference workshops are devoted to the importance of experiential and problem-based learning, especially through techniques of simulation that emulate policymaking processes (Loggins 2009; Butcher 2012; Glasgow 2012; Rothman 2012; DiCicco 2014), little has been written about the use of such techniques for generating and developing innovative research ideas. <u>This article outlines an experiential and problem-based approach to</u> developing a <u>political science research</u> program <u>using scenario analysis</u>. It focuses especially on illuminating the research generation and pedagogical benefits of this technique by describing the use of scenarios in the annual New Era Foreign Policy Conference (NEFPC), which brings together doctoral students of international and comparative affairs who share a demonstrated interest in policy-relevant scholarship.3 In the introductory section, the article outlines the practice of scenario analysis and considers the utility of the technique in political science. We argue that scenario analysis should be viewed as a tool to stimulate problem-based learning for doctoral students and discuss the broader scholarly benefits of using scenarios to help generate research ideas. The second section details the manner in which NEFPC deploys scenario analysis. The third section reflects upon some of the concrete scholarly benefits that have been realized from the scenario format. The fourth section offers insights on the pedagogical potential associated with using scenarios in the classroom across levels of study. A brief conclusion reflects on the importance of developing specific techniques to aid those who wish to generate political science scholarship of relevance to the policy world. What Are Scenarios and Why Use Them in Political Science? <u><mark>Scenario analysis</u></mark> is perceived most commonly as a technique for examining the robustness of strategy. It <u><mark>can immerse decision makers in future states that go beyond conventional extrapolations</mark> of current trends</u>, <u>preparing them to take advantage of unexpected opportunities and to protect themselves from adverse exogenous shocks</u>. The global petroleum company Shell, a pioneer of the technique, characterizes scenario analysis as the art of considering “what if” questions about possible future worlds. <u>Scenario analysis is thus <strong>typically seen as serving the purposes of corporate planning or as a policy tool</u></strong> to be used in combination with simulations of decision making. <u><strong>Yet scenario analysis is not inherently limited to these uses</u></strong>. <u>This section</u> provides a brief overview of the practice of scenario analysis and the motivations underpinning its uses. It then <u>makes a case for the utility of the technique for political science scholarship</u> and describes how the scenarios deployed at NEFPC were created. The Art of Scenario Analysis <u>We characterize scenario analysis as the art of <mark>juxtaposing </mark>current <mark>trends </mark>in unexpected combinations in order <mark>to <strong>articulate </mark>surprising and yet <mark>plausible </mark>futures</u></strong>, often <u><strong>referred to as <mark>“alternative worlds.”</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>Scenarios </mark>are</u> thus <u><strong>explicitly not forecasts or projections based on linear extrapolations of contemporary patterns</u></strong>, <u>and they are <strong>not hypothesis-based expert predictions</u></strong>. <u><strong>Nor should they be equated with simulations</strong>, which are</u> best characterized as <u>functional representations of <strong>real institutions</strong> or decision-making processes</u> (Asal 2005). <u><strong>Instead, they <mark>are depictions of possible future states of the world</u></strong></mark>, offered <u><strong><mark>together with</mark> a narrative of the driving <mark>causal forces</u></strong></mark> and potential exogenous shocks <u><strong><mark>that could lead to those futures</u></strong></mark>. Good scenarios thus rely on explicit causal propositions that, independent of one another, are plausible—yet, when combined, suggest surprising and sometimes controversial future worlds. For example, few predicted the dramatic fall in oil prices toward the end of 2014. Yet independent driving forces, such as the shale gas revolution in the United States, China’s slowing economic growth, and declining conflict in major Middle Eastern oil producers such as Libya, were all recognized secular trends that—combined with OPEC’s decision not to take concerted action as prices began to decline—came together in an unexpected way. While scenario analysis played a role in war gaming and strategic planning during the Cold War, the real antecedents of the contemporary practice are found in corporate futures studies of the late 1960s and early 1970s (Raskin et al. 2005). Scenario analysis was essentially initiated at Royal Dutch Shell in 1965, with the realization that the usual forecasting techniques and models were not capturing the rapidly changing environment in which the company operated (Wack 1985; Schwartz 1991). In particular, it had become evident that straight-line extrapolations of past global trends were inadequate for anticipating the evolving business environment. Shell-style scenario planning “helped break the habit, ingrained in most corporate planning, of assuming that the future will look much like the present” (Wilkinson and Kupers 2013, 4). Using scenario thinking, Shell anticipated the possibility of two Arab-induced oil shocks in the 1970s and hence was able to position itself for major disruptions in the global petroleum sector. Building on its corporate roots, scenario analysis has become a standard policymaking tool. For example, the Project on Forward Engagement advocates linking systematic foresight, which it defines as the disciplined analysis of alternative futures, to planning and feedback loops to better equip the United States to meet contemporary governance challenges (Fuerth 2011). Another prominent application of scenario thinking is found in the National Intelligence Council’s series of Global Trends reports, issued every four years to aid policymakers in anticipating and planning for future challenges. These reports present a handful of “alternative worlds” approximately twenty years into the future, carefully constructed on the basis of emerging global trends, risks, and opportunities, and intended to stimulate thinking about geopolitical change and its effects.4 As with corporate scenario analysis, the technique can be used in foreign policymaking for long-range general planning purposes as well as for anticipating and coping with more narrow and immediate challenges. An example of the latter is the German Marshall Fund’s EuroFutures project, which uses four scenarios to map the potential consequences of the Euro-area financial crisis (German Marshall Fund 2013). <u>Several features make <mark>scenario analysis </mark>particularly <mark>useful</mark> <mark>for</mark> policymaking</u>.5 <u>Long-term global trends across a number of different realms</u>—social, technological, environmental, economic, and political—<u>combine in often-unexpected ways to produce unforeseen challenges</u>. <u>Yet the ability of <mark>decision</mark> <mark>makers to imagine, </mark>let alone prepare for, <mark>discontinuities</u></mark> in the policy realm <u>is constrained by their existing mental models and maps</u>. <u>This limitation is exacerbated by <strong>well-known cognitive bias tendencies such as groupthink and confirmation bias</u></strong> (Jervis 1976; Janis 1982; Tetlock 2005). <u>The <mark>power of scenarios lies in their ability to help individuals <strong>break out of conventional modes of thinking</strong></mark> and analysis by introducing unusual combinations of trends and deliberate discontinuities in narratives about the future</u>. <u><strong><mark>Imagining alternative </mark>future <mark>worlds </mark>through a structured analytical process <mark>enables policymakers to envision and </mark>thereby <mark>adapt </mark>to something altogether different from the known present</u></strong>. Designing Scenarios for Political Science Inquiry The characteristics of scenario analysis that commend its use to policymakers also make it well suited to helping political scientists generate and develop policy-relevant research programs. <u>Scenarios are essentially textured, plausible, and relevant stories that help us imagine how the future</u> political-economic world <u>could be different from the past</u> in a manner that highlights policy challenges and opportunities. For example, terrorist organizations are a known threat that have captured the attention of the policy community, yet our responses to them tend to be linear and reactive. Scenarios that explore how seemingly unrelated vectors of change—the rise of a new peer competitor in the East that diverts strategic attention, volatile commodity prices that empower and disempower various state and nonstate actors in surprising ways, and the destabilizing effects of climate change or infectious disease pandemics—can be useful for illuminating the nature and limits of the terrorist threat in ways that may be missed by a narrower focus on recognized states and groups. By illuminating the potential strategic significance of specific and yet poorly understood opportunities and threats, scenario analysis helps to identify crucial gaps in our collective understanding of global politicaleconomic trends and dynamics. The notion of “exogeneity”—so prevalent in social science scholarship—applies to models of reality, not to reality itself. <u>Very simply, scenario analysis can throw into sharp relief often-overlooked yet pressing questions in international affairs that demand focused investigation</u>. <u>Scenarios thus offer</u>, in principle, <u>an innovative tool for developing a political science research agenda</u>. In practice, <u>achieving this objective requires careful tailoring of the approach</u>. The specific scenario analysis technique we outline below was designed and refined to provide a structured experiential process for generating problem-based research questions with contemporary international policy relevance.6 The first step in the process of creating the scenario set described here was to identify important causal forces in contemporary global affairs. Consensus was not the goal; on the contrary, some of these causal statements represented competing theories about global change (e.g., a resurgence of the nation-state vs. border-evading globalizing forces). A major principle underpinning the transformation of these causal drivers into possible future worlds was to “simplify, then exaggerate” them, before fleshing out the emerging story with more details.7 Thus, the contours of the future world were drawn first in the scenario, with details about the possible pathways to that point filled in second. It is entirely possible, indeed probable, that some of the causal claims that turned into parts of scenarios were exaggerated so much as to be implausible, and that an unavoidable degree of bias or our own form of groupthink went into construction of the scenarios. One of the great strengths of scenario analysis, however, is that the scenario discussions themselves, as described below, lay bare these especially implausible claims and systematic biases.8 An explicit methodological approach underlies the written scenarios themselves as well as the analytical process around them—that of case-centered, structured, focused comparison, intended especially to shed light on new causal mechanisms (George and Bennett 2005). <u>The use of scenarios is similar to counterfactual analysis in that it modifies certain variables in a given situation in order to analyze the resulting effects</u> (Fearon 1991). <u>Whereas counterfactuals are traditionally retrospective</u> in nature and explore events that did not actually occur in the context of known history, our <u><strong>scenarios are deliberately forward-looking</u></strong> <u>and</u> are <u>designed to <strong>explore potential futures</u></strong> that could unfold. As such, counterfactual analysis is especially well suited to identifying how individual events might expand or shift the “funnel of choices” available to political actors and thus lead to different historical outcomes (Nye 2005, 68–69), while forward-looking scenario analysis can better illuminate surprising intersections and sociopolitical dynamics without the perceptual constraints imposed by fine-grained historical knowledge. <u>We see scenarios as a complementary resource for exploring these dynamics in international affairs, rather than as a replacement</u> for counterfactual analysis, historical case studies, or other methodological tools. In the scenario process developed for NEFPC, three distinct scenarios are employed, acting as cases for analytical comparison. Each scenario, as detailed below, includes a set of explicit “driving forces” which represent hypotheses about causal mechanisms worth investigating in evolving international affairs. The scenario analysis process itself employs templates (discussed further below) to serve as a graphical representation of a structured, focused investigation and thereby as the research tool for conducting case-centered comparative analysis (George and Bennett 2005). In essence, these templates articulate key observable implications within the alternative worlds of the scenarios and serve as a framework for capturing the data that emerge (King, Keohane, and Verba 1994). Finally, this structured, focused comparison serves as the basis for the cross-case session emerging from the scenario analysis that leads directly to the articulation of new research agendas. <u>The scenario process described here has thus been carefully designed to offer some guidance to policy-oriented</u> graduate <u>students who are otherwise left to the relatively unstructured norms by which political science</u> dissertation <u>ideas are typically developed</u>. The initial articulation of a dissertation project is generally an idiosyncratic and personal undertaking (Useem 1997; Rothman 2008), whereby students might choose topics based on their coursework, their own previous policy exposure, or the topics studied by their advisors. Research agendas are thus typically developed by looking for “puzzles” in existing research programs (Kuhn 1996). Doctoral students also, understandably, often choose topics that are particularly amenable to garnering research funding. Conventional grant programs typically base their funding priorities on extrapolations from what has been important in the recent past—leading to, for example, the prevalence of Japan and Soviet studies in the mid-1980s or terrorism studies in the 2000s—in the absence of any alternative method for identifying questions of likely future significance. <u>The scenario approach to generating research ideas is grounded in the belief that these traditional approaches can be complemented by <mark>identifying questions</mark> likely to be <mark>of great empirical importance</mark> in the real world, <mark>even if these <strong>do not appear</u></strong></mark> as puzzles <u><strong><mark>in existing research programs</strong></mark> or as clear extrapolations from past events</u>. The <u>scenarios</u> analyzed at NEFPC <u>envision alternative worlds that could develop in the medium (five to seven year) term and are designed to <strong>tease out issues scholars and policymakers may encounter in the relatively near future</u></strong> <u>so that they can <strong>begin thinking critically about them now</u></strong>. <u>This timeframe offers a period distant enough from the present as to avoid falling into current events analysis, but not so far into the future as to seem like science fiction</u>. In imagining the worlds in which these scenarios might come to pass, <u><mark>participants <strong>learn strategies for avoiding failures </mark>of creativity</strong> <mark>and for <strong>overturning </mark>the <mark>assumptions that prevent scholars and analysts from anticipating and understanding</strong></mark> the pivotal junctures that arise in international affairs</u>.</p> | 2ac | null | 1AC Advantage – Disease | 1,569 | 2,269 | 57,209 | ./documents/hspolicy20/Mamaroneck/DeRu/Mamaroneck-DeVito-Rubin-Aff-Michigan-Round3.docx | 734,025 | A | Michigan | 3 | Casady BH | Bennet McGraw | 1ac
-forensic analysis
1nc
-t subsets
-georgia runoff disad
-advantage counterplan
-cap k | hspolicy20/Mamaroneck/DeRu/Mamaroneck-DeVito-Rubin-Aff-Michigan-Round3.docx | null | 62,630 | DeRu | Mamaroneck DeRu | null | De..... | De..... | Ve..... | Ru..... | 21,706 | Mamaroneck | Mamaroneck | NY | null | 1,019 | hspolicy20 | HS Policy 2020-21 | 2,020 | cx | hs | 2 |
2,805,581 | Extinction. | Roth & Bunn 17 | Nickolas Roth & Matthew Bunn 17. **Research associate at the Belfer Center’s Project on Managing the Atom at Harvard University and research fellow at the Center for International and Security Studies at the University of Maryland. **Professor of practice at the Harvard Kennedy School. “The effects of a single terrorist nuclear bomb.” Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists, http://thebulletin.org/effects-single-terrorist-nuclear-bomb11150 | The escalating threats between North Korea and the United States make it easy to forget the “nuclear nightmare,” as former US Secretary of Defense William J. Perry put it, that could result even from the use of just a single terrorist nuclear bomb in the heart of a major city.
we attempt to spell out here the likely consequences of the explosion of a single terrorist nuclear bomb on a major city and its subsequent ripple effects on the rest of the planet blast, fire, initial radiation, and long-term radioactive fallout from such a bomb could leave the heart of a major city a smoldering radioactive ruin killing hundreds of thousands of people Economic, political, and social aftershocks would ripple throughout the world it is far easier to make a crude, unsafe, unreliable nuclear explosive that might fit in the back of a truck Numerous government studies concluded it is plausible a sophisticated terrorist group could make a crude bomb if they got the needed nuclear material in the last quarter century, there have been some 20 seizures of stolen, weapons-usable nuclear material, and at least two terrorist groups have made significant efforts to acquire nuclear bombs. immensity of the consequences means that even a small chance is enough to justify an intensive effort to reduce the risk The explosion would create a powerful blast wave rushing out in every direction communications would be destroyed The economic impact of such an attack would be enormous The effects would reverberate for so far they are difficult to estimate Insurance companies would reel under the losses many insurance policies exclude nuclear attacks thousands of companies would go bankrupt and banks would be left holding an immense number of mortgages that would never be repaid Consumer and investor confidence would likely be dramatically affected The country attacked might well lash out militarily With the nuclear threshold already crossed in this scenario it is conceivable resulting conflicts might escalate to nuclear use International politics could become more brutish and violent with powerful states taking unilateral action by force if necessary in an effort to ensure their security Would the reaction after a far more devastating nuclear attack be any less? | a single terrorist nuclear bomb would ripple throughout the world Numerous studies concluded it is plausible immensity means even a small chance is enough to justify an intensive effort explosion would create powerful blast wave in every direction communications would be destroyed economic impact would be enormous Insurance companies would reel thousands go bankrupt Consumer and investor confidence would be dramatically affected The country attacked might lash out militarily With the nuclear threshold already crossed resulting conflicts might escalate to nuclear use | The escalating threats between North Korea and the United States make it easy to forget the “nuclear nightmare,” as former US Secretary of Defense William J. Perry put it, that could result even from the use of just a single terrorist nuclear bomb in the heart of a major city.
At the risk of repeating the vast literature on the tragedies of Hiroshima and Nagasaki—and the substantial literature surrounding nuclear tests and simulations since then—we attempt to spell out here the likely consequences of the explosion of a single terrorist nuclear bomb on a major city, and its subsequent ripple effects on the rest of the planet. Depending on where and when it was detonated, the blast, fire, initial radiation, and long-term radioactive fallout from such a bomb could leave the heart of a major city a smoldering radioactive ruin, killing tens or hundreds of thousands of people and wounding hundreds of thousands more. Vast areas would have to be evacuated and might be uninhabitable for years. Economic, political, and social aftershocks would ripple throughout the world. A single terrorist nuclear bomb would change history. The country attacked—and the world—would never be the same. The idea of terrorists accomplishing such a thing is, unfortunately, not out of the question; it is far easier to make a crude, unsafe, unreliable nuclear explosive that might fit in the back of a truck than it is to make a safe, reliable weapon of known yield that can be delivered by missile or combat aircraft. Numerous government studies have concluded that it is plausible that a sophisticated terrorist group could make a crude bomb if they got the needed nuclear material. And in the last quarter century, there have been some 20 seizures of stolen, weapons-usable nuclear material, and at least two terrorist groups have made significant efforts to acquire nuclear bombs. Terrorist use of an actual nuclear bomb is a low-probability event—but the immensity of the consequences means that even a small chance is enough to justify an intensive effort to reduce the risk. Fortunately, since the early 1990s, countries around the world have significantly reduced the danger—but it remains very real, and there is more to do to ensure this nightmare never becomes reality. Brighter than a thousand suns. Imagine a crude terrorist nuclear bomb—containing a chunk of highly enriched uranium just under the size of a regulation bowling ball, or a much smaller chunk of plutonium—suddenly detonating inside a delivery van parked in the heart of a major city. Such a terrorist bomb would release as much as 10 kilotons of explosive energy, or the equivalent of 10,000 tons of conventional explosives, a volume of explosives large enough to fill all the cars of a mile-long train. In a millionth of a second, all of that energy would be released inside that small ball of nuclear material, creating temperatures and pressures as high as those at the center of the sun. That furious energy would explode outward, releasing its energy in three main ways: a powerful blast wave; intense heat; and deadly radiation. The ball would expand almost instantly into a fireball the width of four football fields, incinerating essentially everything and everyone within. The heated fireball would rise, sucking in air from below and expanding above, creating the mushroom cloud that has become the symbol of the terror of the nuclear age. The ionized plasma in the fireball would create a localized electromagnetic pulse more powerful than lightning, shorting out communications and electronics nearby—though most would be destroyed by the bomb’s other effects in any case. (Estimates of heat, blast, and radiation effects in this article are drawn primarily from Alex Wellerstein’s “Nukemap,” which itself comes from declassified US government data, such as the 660-page government textbook The Effects of Nuclear Weapons.) At the instant of its detonation, the bomb would also release an intense burst of gamma and neutron radiation which would be lethal for nearly everyone directly exposed within about two-thirds of a mile from the center of the blast. (Those who happened to be shielded by being inside, or having buildings between them and the bomb, would be partly protected—in some cases, reducing their doses by ten times or more.) The nuclear flash from the heat of the fireball would radiate in both visible light and the infrared; it would be “brighter than a thousand suns,” in the words of the title of a book describing the development of nuclear weapons—adapting a phrase from the Hindu epic the Bhagavad-Gita. Anyone who looked directly at the blast would be blinded. The heat from the fireball would ignite fires and horribly burn everyone exposed outside at distances of nearly a mile away. (In the Nagasaki Atomic Bomb Museum, visitors gaze in horror at the bones of a human hand embedded in glass melted by the bomb.) No one has burned a city on that scale in the decades since World War II, so it is difficult to predict the full extent of the fire damage that would occur from the explosion of a nuclear bomb in one of today’s cities. Modern glass, steel, and concrete buildings would presumably be less flammable than the wood-and-rice-paper housing of Hiroshima or Nagasaki in the 1940s—but many questions remain, including exactly how thousands of broken gas lines might contribute to fire damage (as they did in Dresden during World War II). On 9/11, the buildings of the World Trade Center proved to be much more vulnerable to fire damage than had been expected. Ultimately, even a crude terrorist nuclear bomb would carry the possibility that the countless fires touched off by the explosion would coalesce into a devastating firestorm, as occurred at Hiroshima. In a firestorm, the rising column of hot air from the massive fire sucks in the air from all around, creating hurricane-force winds; everything flammable and everything alive within the firestorm would be consumed. The fires and the dust from the blast would make it extremely difficult for either rescuers or survivors to see. The explosion would create a powerful blast wave rushing out in every direction. For more than a quarter-mile all around the blast, the pulse of pressure would be over 20 pounds per square inch above atmospheric pressure (known as “overpressure”), destroying or severely damaging even sturdy buildings. The combination of blast, heat, and radiation would kill virtually everyone in this zone. The blast would be accompanied by winds of many hundreds of miles per hour. The damage from the explosion would extend far beyond this inner zone of almost total death. Out to more than half a mile, the blast would be strong enough to collapse most residential buildings and create a serious danger that office buildings would topple over, killing those inside and those in the path of the rubble. (On the other hand, the office towers of a modern city would tend to block the blast wave in some areas, providing partial protection from the blast, as well as from the heat and radiation.) In that zone, almost anything made of wood would be destroyed: Roofs would cave in, windows would shatter, gas lines would rupture. Telephone poles, street lamps, and utility lines would be severely damaged. Many roads would be blocked by mountains of wreckage. In this zone, many people would be killed or injured in building collapses, or trapped under the rubble; many more would be burned, blinded, or injured by flying debris. In many cases, their charred skin would become ragged and fall off in sheets. The effects of the detonation would act in deadly synergy. The smashed materials of buildings broken by the blast would be far easier for the fires to ignite than intact structures. The effects of radiation would make it far more difficult for burned and injured people to recover. The combination of burns, radiation, and physical injuries would cause far more death and suffering than any one of them would alone. The silent killer. The bomb’s immediate effects would be followed by a slow, lingering killer: radioactive fallout. A bomb detonated at ground level would dig a huge crater, hurling tons of earth and debris thousands of feet into the sky. Sucked into the rising fireball, these particles would mix with the radioactive remainders of the bomb, and over the next few hours or days, the debris would rain down for miles downwind. Depending on weather and wind patterns, the fallout could actually be deadlier and make a far larger area unusable than the blast itself. Acute radiation sickness from the initial radiation pulse and the fallout would likely affect tens of thousands of people. Depending on the dose, they might suffer from vomiting, watery diarrhea, fever, sores, loss of hair, and bone marrow depletion. Some would survive; some would die within days; some would take months to die. Cancer rates among the survivors would rise. Women would be more vulnerable than men—children and infants especially so. Much of the radiation from a nuclear blast is short-lived; radiation levels even a few days after the blast would be far below those in the first hours. For those not killed or terribly wounded by the initial explosion, the best advice would be to take shelter in a basement for at least several days. But many would be too terrified to stay. Thousands of panic-stricken people might receive deadly doses of radiation as they fled from their homes. Some of the radiation will be longer-lived; areas most severely affected would have to be abandoned for many years after the attack. The combination of radioactive fallout and the devastation of nearly all life-sustaining infrastructure over a vast area would mean that hundreds of thousands of people would have to evacuate. Ambulances to nowhere. The explosion would also destroy much of the city’s ability to respond. Hospitals would be leveled, doctors and nurses killed and wounded, ambulances destroyed. (In Hiroshima, 42 of 45 hospitals were destroyed or severely damaged, and 270 of 300 doctors were killed.) Resources that survived outside the zone of destruction would be utterly overwhelmed. Hospitals have no ability to cope with tens or hundreds of thousands of terribly burned and injured people all at once; the United States, for example, has 1,760 burn beds in hospitals nationwide, of which a third are available on any given day. And the problem would not be limited to hospitals; firefighters, for example, would have little ability to cope with thousands of fires raging out of control at once. Fire stations and equipment would be destroyed in the affected area, and firemen killed, along with police and other emergency responders. Some of the first responders may become casualties themselves, from radioactive fallout, fire, and collapsing buildings. Over much of the affected area, communications would be destroyed, by both the physical effects and the electromagnetic pulse from the explosion. Better preparation for such a disaster could save thousands of lives—but ultimately, there is no way any city can genuinely be prepared for a catastrophe on such a historic scale, occurring in a flash, with zero warning. Rescue and recovery attempts would be impeded by the destruction of most of the needed personnel and equipment, and by fire, debris, radiation, fear, lack of communications, and the immense scale of the disaster. The US military and the national guard could provide critically important capabilities—but federal plans assume that “no significant federal response” would be available for 24-to-72 hours. Many of those burned and injured would wait in vain for help, food, or water, perhaps for days. The scale of death and suffering. How many would die in such an event, and how many would be terribly wounded, would depend on where and when the bomb was detonated, what the weather conditions were at the time, how successful the response was in helping the wounded survivors, and more. Many estimates of casualties are based on census data, which reflect where people sleep at night; if the attack occurred in the middle of a workday, the numbers of people crowded into the office towers at the heart of many modern cities would be far higher. The daytime population of Manhattan, for example, is roughly twice its nighttime population; in Midtown on a typical workday, there are an estimated 980,000 people per square mile. A 10-kiloton weapon detonated there might well kill half a million people—not counting those who might die of radiation sickness from the fallout. (These effects were analyzed in great detail in the Rand Corporation’s Considering the Effects of a Catastrophic Terrorist Attack and the British Medical Journal’s “Nuclear terrorism.”) On a typical day, the wind would blow the fallout north, seriously contaminating virtually all of Manhattan above Gramercy Park; people living as far away as Stamford, Connecticut would likely have to evacuate. Seriously injured survivors would greatly outnumber the dead, their suffering magnified by the complete inadequacy of available help. The psychological and social effects—overwhelming sadness, depression, post-traumatic stress disorder, myriad forms of anxiety—would be profound and long-lasting. The scenario we have been describing is a groundburst. An airburst—such as might occur, for example, if terrorists put their bomb in a small aircraft they had purchased or rented—would extend the blast and fire effects over a wider area, killing and injuring even larger numbers of people immediately. But an airburst would not have the same lingering effects from fallout as a groundburst, because the rock and dirt would not be sucked up into the fireball and contaminated. The 10-kiloton blast we have been discussing is likely toward the high end of what terrorists could plausibly achieve with a crude, improvised bomb, but even a 1-kiloton blast would be a catastrophic event, having a deadly radius between one-third and one-half that of a 10-kiloton blast. These hundreds of thousands of people would not be mere statistics, but countless individual stories of loss—parents, children, entire families; all religions; rich and poor alike—killed or horribly mutilated. Human suffering and tragedy on this scale does not have to be imagined; it can be remembered through the stories of the survivors of the US atomic bombings of Hiroshima and Nagasaki, the only times in history when nuclear weapons have been used intentionally against human beings. The pain and suffering caused by those bombings are almost beyond human comprehension; the eloquent testimony of the Hibakusha—the survivors who passed through the atomic fire—should stand as an eternal reminder of the need to prevent nuclear weapons from ever being used in anger again. Global economic disaster. The economic impact of such an attack would be enormous. The effects would reverberate for so far and so long that they are difficult to estimate in all their complexity. Hundreds of thousands of people would be too injured or sick to work for weeks or months. Hundreds of thousands more would evacuate to locations far from their jobs. Many places of employment would have to be abandoned because of the radioactive fallout. Insurance companies would reel under the losses; but at the same time, many insurance policies exclude the effects of nuclear attacks—an item insurers considered beyond their ability to cover—so the owners of thousands of buildings would not have the insurance payments needed to cover the cost of fixing them, thousands of companies would go bankrupt, and banks would be left holding an immense number of mortgages that would never be repaid. Consumer and investor confidence would likely be dramatically affected, as worried people slowed their spending. Enormous new homeland security and military investments would be very likely. If the bomb had come in a shipping container, the targeted country—and possibly others—might stop all containers from entering until it could devise a system for ensuring they could never again be used for such a purpose, throwing a wrench into the gears of global trade for an extended period. (And this might well occur even if a shipping container had not been the means of delivery.) Even the far smaller 9/11 attacks are estimated to have caused economic aftershocks costing almost $1 trillion even excluding the multi-trillion-dollar costs of the wars that ensued. The cost of a terrorist nuclear attack in a major city would likely be many times higher. The most severe effects would be local, but the effects of trade disruptions, reduced economic activity, and more would reverberate around the world. Consequently, while some countries may feel that nuclear terrorism is only a concern for the countries most likely to be targeted—such as the United States—in reality it is a threat to everyone, everywhere. In 2005, then-UN Secretary-General Kofi Annan warned that these global effects would push “tens of millions of people into dire poverty,” creating “a second death toll throughout the developing world.” One recent estimate suggested that a nuclear attack in an urban area would cause a global recession, cutting global Gross Domestic Product by some two percent, and pushing an additional 30 million people in the developing world into extreme poverty. Desperate dilemmas. In short, an act of nuclear terrorism could rip the heart out of a major city, and cause ripple effects throughout the world. The government of the country attacked would face desperate decisions: How to help the city attacked? How to prevent further attacks? How to respond or retaliate? Terrorists—either those who committed the attack or others—would probably claim they had more bombs already hidden in other cities (whether they did or not), and threaten to detonate them unless their demands were met. The fear that this might be true could lead people to flee major cities in a large-scale, uncontrolled evacuation. There is very little ability to support the population of major cities in the surrounding countryside. The potential for widespread havoc and economic chaos is very real. If the detonation took place in the capital of the nation attacked, much of the government might be destroyed. A bomb in Washington, D.C., for example, might kill the President, the Vice President, and many of the members of Congress and the Supreme Court. (Having some plausible national leader survive is a key reason why one cabinet member is always elsewhere on the night of the State of the Union address.) Elaborate, classified plans for “continuity of government” have already been drawn up in a number of countries, but the potential for chaos and confusion—if almost all of a country’s top leaders were killed—would still be enormous. Who, for example, could address the public on what the government would do, and what the public should do, to respond? Could anyone honestly assure the public there would be no further attacks? If they did, who would believe them? In the United States, given the practical impossibility of passing major legislation with Congress in ruins and most of its members dead or seriously injured, some have argued for passing legislation in advance giving the government emergency powers to act—and creating procedures, for example, for legitimately replacing most of the House of Representatives. But to date, no such legislative preparations have been made. In what would inevitably be a desperate effort to prevent further attacks, traditional standards of civil liberties might be jettisoned, at least for a time—particularly when people realized that the fuel for the bomb that had done such damage would easily have fit in a suitcase. Old rules limiting search and surveillance could be among the first to go. The government might well impose martial law as it sought to control the situation, hunt for the perpetrators, and find any additional weapons or nuclear materials they might have. Even the far smaller attacks of 9/11 saw the US government authorizing torture of prisoners and mass electronic surveillance. And what standards of international order and law would still hold sway? The country attacked might well lash out militarily at whatever countries it thought might bear a portion of responsibility. (A terrifying description of the kinds of discussions that might occur appeared in Brian Jenkins’ book, Will Terrorists Go Nuclear?) With the nuclear threshold already crossed in this scenario—at least by terrorists—it is conceivable that some of the resulting conflicts might escalate to nuclear use. International politics could become more brutish and violent, with powerful states taking unilateral action, by force if necessary, in an effort to ensure their security. After 9/11, the United States led the invasions of two sovereign nations, in wars that have since cost hundreds of thousands of lives and trillions of dollars, while plunging a region into chaos. Would the reaction after a far more devastating nuclear attack be any less? | 21,099 | <h4><strong>Extinction.</h4><p></strong>Nickolas <strong>Roth &</strong> Matthew <strong>Bunn 17</strong>. **Research associate at the Belfer Center’s Project on Managing the Atom at Harvard University and research fellow at the Center for International and Security Studies at the University of Maryland. **Professor of practice at the Harvard Kennedy School. “The effects of a single terrorist nuclear bomb.” Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists, http://thebulletin.org/effects-single-terrorist-nuclear-bomb11150</p><p><u>The escalating threats between North Korea and the United States make it easy to forget the “nuclear nightmare,” as former US Secretary of Defense William J. Perry put it, that could result even from the use of just a single terrorist nuclear bomb in the heart of a major city.</p><p></u>At the risk of repeating the vast literature on the tragedies of Hiroshima and Nagasaki—and the substantial literature surrounding nuclear tests and simulations since then—<u>we attempt to spell out here the likely consequences of the explosion of <mark>a <strong>single terrorist nuclear bomb</strong></mark> on a major city</u>, <u>and its <strong>subsequent ripple effects</strong> on the rest of the planet</u>. Depending on where and when it was detonated, the <u>blast, fire, initial radiation, and long-term radioactive fallout from such a bomb could leave the heart of a major city a smoldering radioactive ruin</u>, <u>killing</u> tens or <u><strong>hundreds of thousands of people</u></strong> and wounding hundreds of thousands more. Vast areas would have to be evacuated and might be uninhabitable for years. <u>Economic, political, and social <strong>aftershocks</strong> <mark>would <strong>ripple throughout the world</u></strong></mark>. A single terrorist nuclear bomb would change history. The country attacked—and the world—would never be the same. The idea of terrorists accomplishing such a thing is, unfortunately, not out of the question; <u>it is far easier to make a crude, unsafe, unreliable nuclear explosive that might fit in the back of a truck</u> than it is to make a safe, reliable weapon of known yield that can be delivered by missile or combat aircraft. <u><strong><mark>Numerous</mark> government <mark>studies</u></strong></mark> have <u><mark>concluded</u></mark> that <u><strong><mark>it is plausible</u></strong></mark> that <u>a sophisticated terrorist group could make a crude bomb if they got the needed nuclear material</u>. And <u>in the last quarter century, there have been some 20 seizures of stolen, weapons-usable nuclear material, and at least two terrorist groups have made significant efforts to acquire nuclear bombs.</u> Terrorist use of an actual nuclear bomb is a low-probability event—but the <u><strong><mark>immensity</strong></mark> of the consequences <mark>means</mark> that <mark>even a small chance is enough to justify an intensive effort</mark> to reduce the risk</u>. Fortunately, since the early 1990s, countries around the world have significantly reduced the danger—but it remains very real, and there is more to do to ensure this nightmare never becomes reality. Brighter than a thousand suns. Imagine a crude terrorist nuclear bomb—containing a chunk of highly enriched uranium just under the size of a regulation bowling ball, or a much smaller chunk of plutonium—suddenly detonating inside a delivery van parked in the heart of a major city. Such a terrorist bomb would release as much as 10 kilotons of explosive energy, or the equivalent of 10,000 tons of conventional explosives, a volume of explosives large enough to fill all the cars of a mile-long train. In a millionth of a second, all of that energy would be released inside that small ball of nuclear material, creating temperatures and pressures as high as those at the center of the sun. That furious energy would explode outward, releasing its energy in three main ways: a powerful blast wave; intense heat; and deadly radiation. The ball would expand almost instantly into a fireball the width of four football fields, incinerating essentially everything and everyone within. The heated fireball would rise, sucking in air from below and expanding above, creating the mushroom cloud that has become the symbol of the terror of the nuclear age. The ionized plasma in the fireball would create a localized electromagnetic pulse more powerful than lightning, shorting out communications and electronics nearby—though most would be destroyed by the bomb’s other effects in any case. (Estimates of heat, blast, and radiation effects in this article are drawn primarily from Alex Wellerstein’s “Nukemap,” which itself comes from declassified US government data, such as the 660-page government textbook The Effects of Nuclear Weapons.) At the instant of its detonation, the bomb would also release an intense burst of gamma and neutron radiation which would be lethal for nearly everyone directly exposed within about two-thirds of a mile from the center of the blast. (Those who happened to be shielded by being inside, or having buildings between them and the bomb, would be partly protected—in some cases, reducing their doses by ten times or more.) The nuclear flash from the heat of the fireball would radiate in both visible light and the infrared; it would be “brighter than a thousand suns,” in the words of the title of a book describing the development of nuclear weapons—adapting a phrase from the Hindu epic the Bhagavad-Gita. Anyone who looked directly at the blast would be blinded. The heat from the fireball would ignite fires and horribly burn everyone exposed outside at distances of nearly a mile away. (In the Nagasaki Atomic Bomb Museum, visitors gaze in horror at the bones of a human hand embedded in glass melted by the bomb.) No one has burned a city on that scale in the decades since World War II, so it is difficult to predict the full extent of the fire damage that would occur from the explosion of a nuclear bomb in one of today’s cities. Modern glass, steel, and concrete buildings would presumably be less flammable than the wood-and-rice-paper housing of Hiroshima or Nagasaki in the 1940s—but many questions remain, including exactly how thousands of broken gas lines might contribute to fire damage (as they did in Dresden during World War II). On 9/11, the buildings of the World Trade Center proved to be much more vulnerable to fire damage than had been expected. Ultimately, even a crude terrorist nuclear bomb would carry the possibility that the countless fires touched off by the explosion would coalesce into a devastating firestorm, as occurred at Hiroshima. In a firestorm, the rising column of hot air from the massive fire sucks in the air from all around, creating hurricane-force winds; everything flammable and everything alive within the firestorm would be consumed. The fires and the dust from the blast would make it extremely difficult for either rescuers or survivors to see. <u>The <mark>explosion would create</mark> a <strong><mark>powerful blast</strong> wave</mark> rushing out <mark>in every direction</u></mark>. For more than a quarter-mile all around the blast, the pulse of pressure would be over 20 pounds per square inch above atmospheric pressure (known as “overpressure”), destroying or severely damaging even sturdy buildings. The combination of blast, heat, and radiation would kill virtually everyone in this zone. The blast would be accompanied by winds of many hundreds of miles per hour. The damage from the explosion would extend far beyond this inner zone of almost total death. Out to more than half a mile, the blast would be strong enough to collapse most residential buildings and create a serious danger that office buildings would topple over, killing those inside and those in the path of the rubble. (On the other hand, the office towers of a modern city would tend to block the blast wave in some areas, providing partial protection from the blast, as well as from the heat and radiation.) In that zone, almost anything made of wood would be destroyed: Roofs would cave in, windows would shatter, gas lines would rupture. Telephone poles, street lamps, and utility lines would be severely damaged. Many roads would be blocked by mountains of wreckage. In this zone, many people would be killed or injured in building collapses, or trapped under the rubble; many more would be burned, blinded, or injured by flying debris. In many cases, their charred skin would become ragged and fall off in sheets. The effects of the detonation would act in deadly synergy. The smashed materials of buildings broken by the blast would be far easier for the fires to ignite than intact structures. The effects of radiation would make it far more difficult for burned and injured people to recover. The combination of burns, radiation, and physical injuries would cause far more death and suffering than any one of them would alone. The silent killer. The bomb’s immediate effects would be followed by a slow, lingering killer: radioactive fallout. A bomb detonated at ground level would dig a huge crater, hurling tons of earth and debris thousands of feet into the sky. Sucked into the rising fireball, these particles would mix with the radioactive remainders of the bomb, and over the next few hours or days, the debris would rain down for miles downwind. Depending on weather and wind patterns, the fallout could actually be deadlier and make a far larger area unusable than the blast itself. Acute radiation sickness from the initial radiation pulse and the fallout would likely affect tens of thousands of people. Depending on the dose, they might suffer from vomiting, watery diarrhea, fever, sores, loss of hair, and bone marrow depletion. Some would survive; some would die within days; some would take months to die. Cancer rates among the survivors would rise. Women would be more vulnerable than men—children and infants especially so. Much of the radiation from a nuclear blast is short-lived; radiation levels even a few days after the blast would be far below those in the first hours. For those not killed or terribly wounded by the initial explosion, the best advice would be to take shelter in a basement for at least several days. But many would be too terrified to stay. Thousands of panic-stricken people might receive deadly doses of radiation as they fled from their homes. Some of the radiation will be longer-lived; areas most severely affected would have to be abandoned for many years after the attack. The combination of radioactive fallout and the devastation of nearly all life-sustaining infrastructure over a vast area would mean that hundreds of thousands of people would have to evacuate. Ambulances to nowhere. The explosion would also destroy much of the city’s ability to respond. Hospitals would be leveled, doctors and nurses killed and wounded, ambulances destroyed. (In Hiroshima, 42 of 45 hospitals were destroyed or severely damaged, and 270 of 300 doctors were killed.) Resources that survived outside the zone of destruction would be utterly overwhelmed. Hospitals have no ability to cope with tens or hundreds of thousands of terribly burned and injured people all at once; the United States, for example, has 1,760 burn beds in hospitals nationwide, of which a third are available on any given day. And the problem would not be limited to hospitals; firefighters, for example, would have little ability to cope with thousands of fires raging out of control at once. Fire stations and equipment would be destroyed in the affected area, and firemen killed, along with police and other emergency responders. Some of the first responders may become casualties themselves, from radioactive fallout, fire, and collapsing buildings. Over much of the affected area, <u><strong><mark>communications would be destroyed</u></strong></mark>, by both the physical effects and the electromagnetic pulse from the explosion. Better preparation for such a disaster could save thousands of lives—but ultimately, there is no way any city can genuinely be prepared for a catastrophe on such a historic scale, occurring in a flash, with zero warning. Rescue and recovery attempts would be impeded by the destruction of most of the needed personnel and equipment, and by fire, debris, radiation, fear, lack of communications, and the immense scale of the disaster. The US military and the national guard could provide critically important capabilities—but federal plans assume that “no significant federal response” would be available for 24-to-72 hours. Many of those burned and injured would wait in vain for help, food, or water, perhaps for days. The scale of death and suffering. How many would die in such an event, and how many would be terribly wounded, would depend on where and when the bomb was detonated, what the weather conditions were at the time, how successful the response was in helping the wounded survivors, and more. Many estimates of casualties are based on census data, which reflect where people sleep at night; if the attack occurred in the middle of a workday, the numbers of people crowded into the office towers at the heart of many modern cities would be far higher. The daytime population of Manhattan, for example, is roughly twice its nighttime population; in Midtown on a typical workday, there are an estimated 980,000 people per square mile. A 10-kiloton weapon detonated there might well kill half a million people—not counting those who might die of radiation sickness from the fallout. (These effects were analyzed in great detail in the Rand Corporation’s Considering the Effects of a Catastrophic Terrorist Attack and the British Medical Journal’s “Nuclear terrorism.”) On a typical day, the wind would blow the fallout north, seriously contaminating virtually all of Manhattan above Gramercy Park; people living as far away as Stamford, Connecticut would likely have to evacuate. Seriously injured survivors would greatly outnumber the dead, their suffering magnified by the complete inadequacy of available help. The psychological and social effects—overwhelming sadness, depression, post-traumatic stress disorder, myriad forms of anxiety—would be profound and long-lasting. The scenario we have been describing is a groundburst. An airburst—such as might occur, for example, if terrorists put their bomb in a small aircraft they had purchased or rented—would extend the blast and fire effects over a wider area, killing and injuring even larger numbers of people immediately. But an airburst would not have the same lingering effects from fallout as a groundburst, because the rock and dirt would not be sucked up into the fireball and contaminated. The 10-kiloton blast we have been discussing is likely toward the high end of what terrorists could plausibly achieve with a crude, improvised bomb, but even a 1-kiloton blast would be a catastrophic event, having a deadly radius between one-third and one-half that of a 10-kiloton blast. These hundreds of thousands of people would not be mere statistics, but countless individual stories of loss—parents, children, entire families; all religions; rich and poor alike—killed or horribly mutilated. Human suffering and tragedy on this scale does not have to be imagined; it can be remembered through the stories of the survivors of the US atomic bombings of Hiroshima and Nagasaki, the only times in history when nuclear weapons have been used intentionally against human beings. The pain and suffering caused by those bombings are almost beyond human comprehension; the eloquent testimony of the Hibakusha—the survivors who passed through the atomic fire—should stand as an eternal reminder of the need to prevent nuclear weapons from ever being used in anger again. Global economic disaster. <u>The <mark>economic impact</mark> of such an attack <mark>would be <strong>enormous</u></strong></mark>. <u>The effects would <strong>reverberate</strong> for so far</u> and so long that <u>they are difficult to estimate</u> in all their complexity. Hundreds of thousands of people would be too injured or sick to work for weeks or months. Hundreds of thousands more would evacuate to locations far from their jobs. Many places of employment would have to be abandoned because of the radioactive fallout. <u><mark>Insurance companies would reel</mark> under the losses</u>; but at the same time, <u>many insurance policies exclude</u> the effects of <u>nuclear attacks</u>—an item insurers considered beyond their ability to cover—so the owners of thousands of buildings would not have the insurance payments needed to cover the cost of fixing them, <u><mark>thousands</mark> of companies would <mark>go bankrupt</u></mark>, <u>and banks would be left holding an immense number of mortgages that would never be repaid</u>. <u><mark>Consumer and investor confidence would</mark> likely <mark>be</mark> <strong><mark>dramatically affected</u></strong></mark>, as worried people slowed their spending. Enormous new homeland security and military investments would be very likely. If the bomb had come in a shipping container, the targeted country—and possibly others—might stop all containers from entering until it could devise a system for ensuring they could never again be used for such a purpose, throwing a wrench into the gears of global trade for an extended period. (And this might well occur even if a shipping container had not been the means of delivery.) Even the far smaller 9/11 attacks are estimated to have caused economic aftershocks costing almost $1 trillion even excluding the multi-trillion-dollar costs of the wars that ensued. The cost of a terrorist nuclear attack in a major city would likely be many times higher. The most severe effects would be local, but the effects of trade disruptions, reduced economic activity, and more would reverberate around the world. Consequently, while some countries may feel that nuclear terrorism is only a concern for the countries most likely to be targeted—such as the United States—in reality it is a threat to everyone, everywhere. In 2005, then-UN Secretary-General Kofi Annan warned that these global effects would push “tens of millions of people into dire poverty,” creating “a second death toll throughout the developing world.” One recent estimate suggested that a nuclear attack in an urban area would cause a global recession, cutting global Gross Domestic Product by some two percent, and pushing an additional 30 million people in the developing world into extreme poverty. Desperate dilemmas. In short, an act of nuclear terrorism could rip the heart out of a major city, and cause ripple effects throughout the world. The government of the country attacked would face desperate decisions: How to help the city attacked? How to prevent further attacks? How to respond or retaliate? Terrorists—either those who committed the attack or others—would probably claim they had more bombs already hidden in other cities (whether they did or not), and threaten to detonate them unless their demands were met. The fear that this might be true could lead people to flee major cities in a large-scale, uncontrolled evacuation. There is very little ability to support the population of major cities in the surrounding countryside. The potential for widespread havoc and economic chaos is very real. If the detonation took place in the capital of the nation attacked, much of the government might be destroyed. A bomb in Washington, D.C., for example, might kill the President, the Vice President, and many of the members of Congress and the Supreme Court. (Having some plausible national leader survive is a key reason why one cabinet member is always elsewhere on the night of the State of the Union address.) Elaborate, classified plans for “continuity of government” have already been drawn up in a number of countries, but the potential for chaos and confusion—if almost all of a country’s top leaders were killed—would still be enormous. Who, for example, could address the public on what the government would do, and what the public should do, to respond? Could anyone honestly assure the public there would be no further attacks? If they did, who would believe them? In the United States, given the practical impossibility of passing major legislation with Congress in ruins and most of its members dead or seriously injured, some have argued for passing legislation in advance giving the government emergency powers to act—and creating procedures, for example, for legitimately replacing most of the House of Representatives. But to date, no such legislative preparations have been made. In what would inevitably be a desperate effort to prevent further attacks, traditional standards of civil liberties might be jettisoned, at least for a time—particularly when people realized that the fuel for the bomb that had done such damage would easily have fit in a suitcase. Old rules limiting search and surveillance could be among the first to go. The government might well impose martial law as it sought to control the situation, hunt for the perpetrators, and find any additional weapons or nuclear materials they might have. Even the far smaller attacks of 9/11 saw the US government authorizing torture of prisoners and mass electronic surveillance. And what standards of international order and law would still hold sway? <u><mark>The country attacked might</mark> well <strong><mark>lash out militarily</u></strong></mark> at whatever countries it thought might bear a portion of responsibility. (A terrifying description of the kinds of discussions that might occur appeared in Brian Jenkins’ book, Will Terrorists Go Nuclear?) <u><mark>With the nuclear threshold already crossed</mark> in this scenario</u>—at least by terrorists—<u>it is <strong>conceivable</u></strong> that some of the <u><strong><mark>resulting conflicts might escalate to nuclear use</u></strong></mark>. <u>International politics could become more brutish and violent</u>, <u>with powerful states taking unilateral action</u>, <u>by force if necessary</u>, <u>in an effort to ensure their security</u>. After 9/11, the United States led the invasions of two sovereign nations, in wars that have since cost hundreds of thousands of lives and trillions of dollars, while plunging a region into chaos. <u><strong>Would the reaction after a far more devastating nuclear attack be any less?</p></u></strong> | 1NR | ***USMCA DA*** | 2NC – M – Energy Security | 11,438 | 1,267 | 88,902 | ./documents/hspolicy19/StrathHaven/LeRu/Strath%20Haven-Lee-Ruan-Neg-GDS-Round5.docx | 721,147 | N | GDS | 5 | Edgemont SK | Kai Sam Ng | 1AC - Saudi
1NC - T-Pearson Russia Fill-In DA USMCA DA Iran Nuclear Deal CP Holbrooke CP Petro-Yuan DA
2NC - Iran Nuclear Deal CP Petro Yuan DA
1NR - USMCA DA
2NR - Petro Yuan DA Iran Nuclear CP
2AR - Condo and Substance | hspolicy19/StrathHaven/LeRu/Strath%20Haven-Lee-Ruan-Neg-GDS-Round5.docx | null | 61,566 | LeRu | Strath Haven LeRu | null | Wi..... | Le..... | Ai..... | Ru..... | 21,440 | StrathHaven | Strath Haven | PA | null | 1,018 | hspolicy19 | HS Policy 2019-20 | 2,019 | cx | hs | 2 |
2,077,357 | 6] Extinction outweighs | Baum & Barrett 18 | Seth D. Baum & Anthony M. Barrett 18. Global Catastrophic Risk Institute. 2018. “Global Catastrophes: The Most Extreme Risks.” Risk in Extreme Environments: Preparing, Avoiding, Mitigating, and Managing, edited by Vicki Bier, Routledge, pp. 174–184. | Taken literally, a global catastrophe can be any event that is in some way catastrophic across the globe This suggests a rather low threshold However, in common usage, a global catastrophe would be catastrophic for a significant portion of the globe Others have emphasized catastrophes that cause long-term declines in the trajectory of human civilization that human civilization does not recover from that drastically reduce humanity’s potential for future achievements Bostrom using the term “existential risk”), or that result in human extinction A common theme across all these treatments of GCR is that some catastrophes are vastly more important than others Without nuclear winter, a global nuclear war might kill several hundred million people. This is obviously a major catastrophe, but humanity would presumably carry on. However, with nuclear winter humanity could go extinct. The loss would be not just an additional four billion or so deaths, but the loss of all future generations the loss would be billions and billions of lives, or even more Sagan estimated 500 trillion lives, assuming humanity would continue for ten million more years, which he cited as typical for a successful species. Sagan’s 500 trillion number may even be an underestimate An open question in astronomy is whether it is possible for the descendants of humanity to continue living for an infinite length of time or instead merely an astronomically large but finite length of time the stakes with global catastrophes could be much larger than the loss of 500 trillion lives. Debates about the infinite vs. the merely astronomical are of theoretical interest but they have limited practical significance. This can be seen when evaluating GCRs from a standard risk-equals-probability-times-magnitude framework. Using Sagan’s 500 trillion lives estimate, it follows that reducing the probability of global catastrophe by a mere one-in-500-trillion chance is of the same significance as saving one human life. Phrased differently, society should try 500 trillion times harder to prevent a global catastrophe than it should to save a person’s life. Or, preventing one million deaths is equivalent to a one-in500-million reduction in the probability of global catastrophe. This suggests society should make extremely large investment in GCR reduction, at the expense of virtually all other objectives. society should be willing to spend $1 million for a one-in-500-million reduction in the probability of global catastrophe while reasonable disagreement exists on how large of a VSL to use and how much to count future generations, even low-end positions suggest vast resource allocations should be redirected to reducing GCR. This conclusion is only strengthened when considering the astronomical size of the stakes as long as something along the lines of the standard riskequals-probability-times-magnitude framework is being used, then even tiny GCR reductions merit significant effort. This point holds especially strongly for risks of catastrophes that would cause permanent harm to global human civilization. The discussion thus far has assumed that all human lives are valued equally. This assumption is not universally held People often value some people more than others Great debates rage on across moral philosophy, economics, and other fields about how much people should value others This debate is crucial While everyone has the right to their own views and feelings the strongest arguments are for the widely held position that all human lives should be valued equally. Philosophers speak of an agent-neutral, objective “view from nowhere” or a “veil of ignorance” in which each person considers what is best for society irrespective of which member of society they happen to be Such a perspective suggests valuing everyone equally, regardless of who they are or where or when they live. This in turn suggests a very high value for reducing GCR, or a high degree of priority for GCR reduction efforts. | with nuclear winter humanity could go extinct loss of all future generations. would be 500 trillion lives may be an underestimate risk-equals-probability-times-magnitude society should try 500 trillion times harder to prevent global catastrophe than to save a person’s life all human lives should be valued equally a “veil of ignorance” in which each considers what is best for society irrespective of which member they happen to be valuing everyone equally suggests a very high value for reducing GCR | 2. What Is GCR And Why Is It Important? Taken literally, a global catastrophe can be any event that is in some way catastrophic across the globe. This suggests a rather low threshold for what counts as a global catastrophe. An event causing just one death on each continent (say, from a jet-setting assassin) could rate as a global catastrophe, because surely these deaths would be catastrophic for the deceased and their loved ones. However, in common usage, a global catastrophe would be catastrophic for a significant portion of the globe. Minimum thresholds have variously been set around ten thousand to ten million deaths or $10 billion to $10 trillion in damages (Bostrom and Ćirković 2008), or death of one quarter of the human population (Atkinson 1999; Hempsell 2004). Others have emphasized catastrophes that cause long-term declines in the trajectory of human civilization (Beckstead 2013), that human civilization does not recover from (Maher and Baum 2013), that drastically reduce humanity’s potential for future achievements (Bostrom 2002, using the term “existential risk”), or that result in human extinction (Matheny 2007; Posner 2004). A common theme across all these treatments of GCR is that some catastrophes are vastly more important than others. Carl Sagan was perhaps the first to recognize this, in his commentary on nuclear winter (Sagan 1983). Without nuclear winter, a global nuclear war might kill several hundred million people. This is obviously a major catastrophe, but humanity would presumably carry on. However, with nuclear winter, per Sagan, humanity could go extinct. The loss would be not just an additional four billion or so deaths, but the loss of all future generations. To paraphrase Sagan, the loss would be billions and billions of lives, or even more. Sagan estimated 500 trillion lives, assuming humanity would continue for ten million more years, which he cited as typical for a successful species. Sagan’s 500 trillion number may even be an underestimate. The analysis here takes an adventurous turn, hinging on the evolution of the human species and the long-term fate of the universe. On these long time scales, the descendants of contemporary humans may no longer be recognizably “human”. The issue then is whether the descendants are still worth caring about, whatever they are. If they are, then it begs the question of how many of them there will be. Barring major global catastrophe, Earth will remain habitable for about one billion more years 2 until the Sun gets too warm and large. The rest of the Solar System, Milky Way galaxy, universe, and (if it exists) the multiverse will remain habitable for a lot longer than that (Adams and Laughlin 1997), should our descendants gain the capacity to migrate there. An open question in astronomy is whether it is possible for the descendants of humanity to continue living for an infinite length of time or instead merely an astronomically large but finite length of time (see e.g. Ćirković 2002; Kaku 2005). Either way, the stakes with global catastrophes could be much larger than the loss of 500 trillion lives. Debates about the infinite vs. the merely astronomical are of theoretical interest (Ng 1991; Bossert et al. 2007), but they have limited practical significance. This can be seen when evaluating GCRs from a standard risk-equals-probability-times-magnitude framework. Using Sagan’s 500 trillion lives estimate, it follows that reducing the probability of global catastrophe by a mere one-in-500-trillion chance is of the same significance as saving one human life. Phrased differently, society should try 500 trillion times harder to prevent a global catastrophe than it should to save a person’s life. Or, preventing one million deaths is equivalent to a one-in500-million reduction in the probability of global catastrophe. This suggests society should make extremely large investment in GCR reduction, at the expense of virtually all other objectives. Judge and legal scholar Richard Posner made a similar point in monetary terms (Posner 2004). Posner used $50,000 as the value of a statistical human life (VSL) and 12 billion humans as the total loss of life (double the 2004 world population); he describes both figures as significant underestimates. Multiplying them gives $600 trillion as an underestimate of the value of preventing global catastrophe. For comparison, the United States government typically uses a VSL of around one to ten million dollars (Robinson 2007). Multiplying a $10 million VSL with 500 trillion lives gives $5x1021 as the value of preventing global catastrophe. But even using “just" $600 trillion, society should be willing to spend at least that much to prevent a global catastrophe, which converts to being willing to spend at least $1 million for a one-in-500-million reduction in the probability of global catastrophe. Thus while reasonable disagreement exists on how large of a VSL to use and how much to count future generations, even low-end positions suggest vast resource allocations should be redirected to reducing GCR. This conclusion is only strengthened when considering the astronomical size of the stakes, but the same point holds either way. The bottom line is that, as long as something along the lines of the standard riskequals-probability-times-magnitude framework is being used, then even tiny GCR reductions merit significant effort. This point holds especially strongly for risks of catastrophes that would cause permanent harm to global human civilization. The discussion thus far has assumed that all human lives are valued equally. This assumption is not universally held. People often value some people more than others, favoring themselves, their family and friends, their compatriots, their generation, or others whom they identify with. Great debates rage on across moral philosophy, economics, and other fields about how much people should value others who are distant in space, time, or social relation, as well as the unborn members of future generations. This debate is crucial for all valuations of risk, including GCR. Indeed, if each of us only cares about our immediate selves, then global catastrophes may not be especially important, and we probably have better things to do with our time than worry about them. While everyone has the right to their own views and feelings, we find that the strongest arguments are for the widely held position that all human lives should be valued equally. This position is succinctly stated in the United States Declaration of Independence, updated in the 1848 Declaration of Sentiments: “We hold these truths to be self-evident: that all men and women are created equal”. Philosophers speak of an agent-neutral, objective “view from nowhere” (Nagel 1986) or a “veil of ignorance” (Rawls 1971) in which each person considers what is best for society irrespective of which member of society they happen to be. Such a perspective suggests valuing everyone equally, regardless of who they are or where or when they live. This in turn suggests a very high value for reducing GCR, or a high degree of priority for GCR reduction efforts. | 7,160 | <h4>6] Extinction outweighs</h4><p>Seth D. <strong>Baum &</strong> Anthony M. <strong>Barrett 18<u></strong>. Global Catastrophic Risk Institute. 2018. “Global Catastrophes: The Most Extreme Risks.” Risk in Extreme Environments: Preparing, Avoiding, Mitigating, and Managing, edited by Vicki Bier, Routledge, pp. 174–184.</p><p></u>2. What Is GCR And Why Is It Important? <u>Taken <strong>literally</strong>, a global catastrophe can be any event that is in some way catastrophic across the globe</u>. <u>This suggests a rather low threshold</u> for what counts as a global catastrophe. An event causing just one death on each continent (say, from a jet-setting assassin) could rate as a global catastrophe, because surely these deaths would be catastrophic for the deceased and their loved ones. <u>However, in common usage, a global catastrophe would be <strong>catastrophic</strong> for a significant portion of the globe</u>. Minimum thresholds have variously been set around ten thousand to ten million deaths or $10 billion to $10 trillion in damages (Bostrom and Ćirković 2008), or death of one quarter of the human population (Atkinson 1999; Hempsell 2004). <u>Others have emphasized catastrophes that cause <strong>long-term declines in the trajectory of human civilization</u></strong> (Beckstead 2013), <u>that human civilization <strong>does not recover from</u></strong> (Maher and Baum 2013), <u>that drastically reduce humanity’s potential for future achievements</u> (<u>Bostrom</u> 2002, <u>using the term “<strong>existential risk</strong>”), or that result in <strong>human extinction</u></strong> (Matheny 2007; Posner 2004). <u>A common theme across all these treatments of GCR is that <strong>some catastrophes are vastly more important than others</u></strong>. Carl Sagan was perhaps the first to recognize this, in his commentary on nuclear winter (Sagan 1983). <u>Without nuclear winter, a global nuclear war might kill several hundred million people. This is obviously a major catastrophe, but humanity would presumably carry on. However, <mark>with <strong>nuclear winter</u></strong></mark>, per Sagan, <u><strong><mark>humanity</mark> <mark>could go extinct</strong></mark>. The loss would be not just an additional four billion or so deaths, but the <mark>loss of <strong>all future generations</u></strong>.</mark> To paraphrase Sagan, <u>the loss <mark>would be</mark> billions and billions of lives, or even <strong>more</u></strong>. <u>Sagan estimated <strong><mark>500 trillion lives</strong></mark>, assuming humanity would continue for ten million more years, which he cited as typical for a successful species. Sagan’s 500 trillion number <mark>may</mark> even <mark>be an <strong>underestimate</u></strong></mark>. The analysis here takes an adventurous turn, hinging on the evolution of the human species and the long-term fate of the universe. On these long time scales, the descendants of contemporary humans may no longer be recognizably “human”. The issue then is whether the descendants are still worth caring about, whatever they are. If they are, then it begs the question of how many of them there will be. Barring major global catastrophe, Earth will remain habitable for about one billion more years 2 until the Sun gets too warm and large. The rest of the Solar System, Milky Way galaxy, universe, and (if it exists) the multiverse will remain habitable for a lot longer than that (Adams and Laughlin 1997), should our descendants gain the capacity to migrate there. <u>An open question in astronomy is whether it is possible for the descendants of humanity to continue living for an <strong>infinite length of time</strong> or instead merely an <strong>astronomically large but finite</strong> length of time</u> (see e.g. Ćirković 2002; Kaku 2005). Either way,<u> the stakes with global catastrophes <strong>could</strong> be <strong>much larger than the loss of 500 trillion lives. </strong>Debates about the infinite vs. the merely astronomical are of theoretical interest</u> (Ng 1991; Bossert et al. 2007), <u>but they have <strong>limited practical significance</strong>. This can be seen when <strong>evaluating GCRs from a standard <mark>risk-equals-probability-times-magnitude</mark> framework</strong>. Using Sagan’s 500 trillion lives estimate, it follows that reducing the probability of global catastrophe by a mere one-in-500-trillion chance is of the same significance as saving one human life. Phrased differently, <mark>society should <strong>try 500 trillion times harder to prevent</mark> a <mark>global catastrophe</mark> <mark>than</mark> it should <mark>to save a person’s life</strong></mark>. Or, preventing one million deaths is equivalent to a one-in500-million reduction in the probability of global catastrophe. This suggests society should <strong>make extremely large investment in GCR reduction, at the expense of virtually all other objectives. </u></strong>Judge and legal scholar Richard Posner made a similar point in monetary terms (Posner 2004). Posner used $50,000 as the value of a statistical human life (VSL) and 12 billion humans as the total loss of life (double the 2004 world population); he describes both figures as significant underestimates. Multiplying them gives $600 trillion as an underestimate of the value of preventing global catastrophe. For comparison, the United States government typically uses a VSL of around one to ten million dollars (Robinson 2007). Multiplying a $10 million VSL with 500 trillion lives gives $5x1021 as the value of preventing global catastrophe. But even using “just" $600 trillion, <u>society should be willing to spend</u> at least that much to prevent a global catastrophe, which converts to being willing to spend at least <u>$1 million for a one-in-500-million reduction in the probability of global catastrophe</u>. Thus <u>while reasonable disagreement exists on how large of a VSL to use and how much to count future generations, even low-end positions suggest <strong>vast resource allocations</strong> should be redirected to reducing GCR. This conclusion is only <strong>strengthened</strong> when considering the <strong>astronomical size of the stakes</u></strong>, but the same point holds either way. The bottom line is that, <u>as long as something along the lines of the standard riskequals-probability-times-magnitude framework is being used, then <strong>even tiny GCR reductions</strong> merit significant effort. This point holds especially strongly for risks of catastrophes that would cause <strong>permanent harm to global human civilization</strong>. The discussion thus far has assumed that all human lives are valued equally. This assumption is <strong>not universally held</u></strong>. <u>People often value some people more than others</u>, favoring themselves, their family and friends, their compatriots, their generation, or others whom they identify with. <u>Great debates rage on across moral philosophy, economics, and other fields about how much people should value others</u> who are distant in space, time, or social relation, as well as the unborn members of future generations. <u>This debate is crucial</u> for all valuations of risk, including GCR. Indeed, if each of us only cares about our immediate selves, then global catastrophes may not be especially important, and we probably have better things to do with our time than worry about them. <u>While everyone has the right to their <strong>own views and feelings</u></strong>, we find that <u>the strongest arguments are for the <strong>widely held position</strong> that<mark> <strong>all human lives should be valued equally</strong></mark>.</u> This position is succinctly stated in the United States Declaration of Independence, updated in the 1848 Declaration of Sentiments: “We hold these truths to be self-evident: that all men and women are created equal”. <u>Philosophers speak of an agent-neutral, objective “view from nowhere”</u> (Nagel 1986) <u>or <mark>a “veil of ignorance”</u></mark> (Rawls 1971) <u><mark>in which each</mark> person <mark>considers what is best for society <strong>irrespective of which member</mark> of society <mark>they happen to be</u></strong></mark>. <u>Such a perspective <strong>suggests <mark>valuing everyone equally</strong></mark>, regardless of who they are or where or when they live. This in turn <mark>suggests a <strong>very high value for reducing GCR</strong></mark>, or a high degree of priority for GCR reduction efforts. </p></u> | null | 1AC | Framing | 1,570 | 2,142 | 61,844 | ./documents/hsld20/Anderson/Cr/Anderson-Cryan-Aff-Nano%20Nagle-Round4.docx | 853,009 | A | Nano Nagle | 4 | Thomas Horace Rogers JW | Selena Zhang | 1AC-US Populism ADV
1NC-T-"a" Elections DA Advantage CP
2NR-DACPCase turns | hsld20/Anderson/Cr/Anderson-Cryan-Aff-Nano%20Nagle-Round4.docx | null | 72,666 | BrCr | Anderson BrCr | null | Br..... | Cr..... | null | null | 24,409 | Anderson | Anderson | TX | null | 1,028 | hsld20 | HS LD 2020-21 | 2,020 | ld | hs | 1 |
1,939,245 | ‘Its’ commitments is singular, meaning federal only | Updegrave 91 | W.C. Updegrave 91, “Explanation of ZIP Code Address Purpose”, 8/19/1991, http://www.supremelaw.org/ref/zipcode/updegrav.htm | Note the singular possessive pronoun "its", not "their", therefore carrying the implication that it relates to the "United States" as a corporation domiciled in the District of Columbia (in the singular sense), not in the sense of being the 50 States of the Union (in the plural sense). The map shows all the States of the Union, but it also shows D.C., Puerto Rico and the Virgin Islands, making the explanatory statement literally correct. | Note the singular possessive "its", not "their" implication it relates to U S in D C singular not the 50 States plural | More specifically, looking at the map on page 11 of the National ZIP Code Directory, e.g. at a local post office, one will see that the first digit of a ZIP Code defines an area that includes more than one State. The first sentence of the explanatory paragraph begins: "A ZIP Code is a numerical code that identifies areas within the United States and its territories for purposes of ..." [cf. 26 CFR 1.1-1(c)]. Note the singular possessive pronoun "its", not "their", therefore carrying the implication that it relates to the "United States" as a corporation domiciled in the District of Columbia (in the singular sense), not in the sense of being the 50 States of the Union (in the plural sense). The map shows all the States of the Union, but it also shows D.C., Puerto Rico and the Virgin Islands, making the explanatory statement literally correct. | 855 | <h4>‘Its’ commitments is <u>singular</u>, meaning <u>federal</u> only</h4><p>W.C. <strong>Updegrave 91</strong>, “Explanation of ZIP Code Address Purpose”, 8/19/1991, <u>http://www.supremelaw.org/ref/zipcode/updegrav.htm</p><p></u>More specifically, looking at the map on page 11 of the National ZIP Code Directory, e.g. at a local post office, one will see that the first digit of a ZIP Code defines an area that includes more than one State. The first sentence of the explanatory paragraph begins: "A ZIP Code is a numerical code that identifies areas within the United States and its territories for purposes of ..." [cf. 26 CFR 1.1-1(c)]. <u><mark>Note the <strong>singular possessive</strong></mark> pronoun <strong><mark>"its", not "their"</strong></mark>, therefore carrying the <mark>implication</mark> that <mark>it relates to</mark> the "<strong><mark>U</strong></mark>nited <strong><mark>S</strong></mark>tates" as a corporation domiciled <mark>in</mark> the <strong><mark>D</strong></mark>istrict of <strong><mark>C</strong></mark>olumbia (in the <mark>singular</mark> sense), <strong><mark>not</mark> in the sense of being <mark>the 50 States</strong></mark> of the Union (in the <mark>plural</mark> sense). The map shows all the States of the Union, but it also shows D.C., Puerto Rico and the Virgin Islands, making the explanatory statement literally correct. </p></u> | 2nc | Nga | framing | 2,804 | 603 | 57,218 | ./documents/hspolicy20/Mamaroneck/GuPe/Mamaroneck-Gupta-Peters-Neg-1st%20and%202nd%20Year%20National%20Championships%20at%20Woodward%20Academy-Round1.docx | 734,411 | N | 1st and 2nd Year National Championships at Woodward Academy | 1 | Altamont AY | Wombough, Sam | 1ac -- predictive policing
2nr -- nga cp
2ar -- condo | hspolicy20/Mamaroneck/GuPe/Mamaroneck-Gupta-Peters-Neg-1st%20and%202nd%20Year%20National%20Championships%20at%20Woodward%20Academy-Round1.docx | null | 62,635 | GuPe | Mamaroneck GuPe | null | Ro..... | Gu..... | Lu..... | Pe..... | 21,706 | Mamaroneck | Mamaroneck | NY | null | 1,019 | hspolicy20 | HS Policy 2020-21 | 2,020 | cx | hs | 2 |
1,899,942 | Threat discourse is a sham meant to obfuscate the consequences of structural violence. Impact calculus should be evaluated from the position of those rendered irrelevant in traditional metrics. | Jackson 12 | Jackson 12 Richard Jackson has a PhD in Political Science from University of Canterbury, New Zealand and is the Deputy Director of the National Peace and Conflict Studies Centre at the University of Otago, New Zealand “The Great Con of National Security” August 15 2012 https://richardjacksonterrorismblog.wordpress.com/2012/08/05/the-great-con-of-national-security | big threats distract from the things that can really hurt such as structural violence politicians and media spend most of their time talking about terrorism Iran North Korea China and a host of other issues which are unlikely to affect the health and well-being of you and your family the state spends vast sums on security measures which have no impact on the actual risk of dying from these threats, and then engages in ‘security theatre’ to show just how seriously the state takes these threats the rulers of society are hoping you won’t notice increasing inequality For them insecurity are a price worth paying to keep social structures as they are A more egalitarian society would not suit their interests It is also more exciting for the media than stories about how people of colour are discriminated against and suffer worse health as a consequence security is – misdirection on an epic scale to distract you from structures which are the real threat and to convince you to permanently acquiesce to security measures you’re much more likely to die from structural violence we need to challenge this | big threats distract from the things that can really hurt such as structural violence terrorism, Iran North Korea China and other issues are unlikely the rulers of society are hoping you won’t notice increasing inequality i For them insecurity are a price worth paying to keep social structures as they are egalitarian society would not suit their interests security is misdirection on an epic scale to distract you from structures which are the real threat and to convince you to permanently acquiesce to security measures you’re much more likely to die from structural violence | It may have once been the case that being attacked by another country was a major threat to the lives of ordinary people. It may also be true that there are still some pretty serious dangers out there associated with the spread of nuclear weapons. For the most part, however, most of what you’ve been told about national security and all the big threats which can supposedly kill you is one big con designed to distract you from the things that can really hurt you, such as the poverty, inequality and structural violence of capitalism, global warming, and the manufacture and proliferation of weapons – among others. The facts are simple and irrefutable: you’re far more likely to die from lack of health care provision than you are from terrorism; from stress and overwork than Iranian or North Korean nuclear missiles; from lack of road safety than from illegal immigrants; from mental illness and suicide than from computer hackers; from domestic violence than from asylum seekers; from the misuse of legal medicines and alcohol abuse than from international drug lords. And yet, politicians and the servile media spend most of their time talking about the threats posed by terrorism, immigration, asylum seekers, the international drug trade, the nuclear programmes of Iran and North Korea, computer hackers, animal rights activism, the threat of China, and a host of other issues which are all about as equally unlikely to affect the health and well-being of you and your family. Along with this obsessive and perennial discussion of so-called ‘national security issues’, the state spends truly vast sums on security measures which have virtually no impact on the actual risk of dying from these threats, and then engages in massive displays of ‘security theatre’ designed to show just how seriously the state takes these threats – such as the x-ray machines and security measures in every public building, surveillance cameras everywhere, missile launchers in urban areas, drones in Afghanistan, armed police in airports, and a thousand other things. This display is meant to convince you that these threats are really, really serious. And while all this is going on, the rulers of society are hoping that you won’t notice that increasing social and economic inequality in society leads to increased ill health for a growing underclass; that suicide and crime always rise when unemployment rises; that workplaces remain highly dangerous and kill and maim hundreds of people per year; that there are preventable diseases which plague the poorer sections of society; that domestic violence kills and injures thousands of women and children annually; and that globally, poverty and preventable disease kills tens of millions of people needlessly every year. In other words, they are hoping that you won’t notice how much structural violence there is in the world. More than this, they are hoping that you won’t notice that while literally trillions of dollars are spent on military weapons, foreign wars and security theatre (which also arguably do nothing to make any us any safer, and may even make us marginally less safe), that domestic violence programmes struggle to provide even minimal support for women and children at risk of serious harm from their partners; that underfunded mental health programmes mean long waiting lists to receive basic care for at-risk individuals; that drug and alcohol rehabilitation programmes lack the funding to match the demand for help; that welfare measures aimed at reducing inequality have been inadequate for decades; that health and safety measures at many workplaces remain insufficiently resourced; and that measures to tackle global warming and developing alternative energy remain hopelessly inadequate. Of course, none of this is surprising. Politicians are a part of the system; they don’t want to change it. For them, all the insecurity, death and ill-health caused by capitalist inequality are a price worth paying to keep the basic social structures as they are. A more egalitarian society based on equality, solidarity, and other non-materialist values would not suit their interests, or the special interests of the lobby groups they are indebted to. It is also true that dealing with economic and social inequality, improving public health, changing international structures of inequality, restructuring the military-industrial complex, and making the necessary economic and political changes to deal with global warming will be extremely difficult and will require long-term commitment and determination. For politicians looking towards the next election, it is clearly much easier to paint immigrants as a threat to social order or pontificate about the ongoing danger of terrorists. It is also more exciting for the media than stories about how poor people and people of colour are discriminated against and suffer worse health as a consequence. Viewed from this vantage point, national security is one massive confidence trick – misdirection on an epic scale. Its primary function is to distract you from the structures and inequalities in society which are the real threat to the health and wellbeing of you and your family, and to convince you to be permanently afraid so that you will acquiesce to all the security measures which keep you under state control and keep the military-industrial complex ticking along. Keep this in mind next time you hear a politician talking about the threat of uncontrolled immigration, the risk posed by asylum seekers or the threat of Iran, or the need to expand counter-terrorism powers. The question is: when politicians are talking about national security, what is that they don’t want you to think and talk about? What exactly is the misdirection they are engaged in? The truth is, if you think that terrorists or immigrants or asylum seekers or Iran are a greater threat to your safety than the capitalist system, you have been well and truly conned, my friend. Don’t believe the hype: you’re much more likely to die from any one of several forms of structural violence in society than you are from immigrants or terrorism. Somehow, we need to challenge the politicians on this fact. | 6,192 | <h4>Threat discourse is a <u>sham</u> meant to obfuscate the consequences of <u>structural violence</u>. Impact calculus should be evaluated from the position of those rendered <u>irrelevant</u> in <u>traditional metrics</u>. </h4><p><strong>Jackson 12</strong> Richard Jackson has a PhD in Political Science from University of Canterbury, New Zealand and is the Deputy Director of the National Peace and Conflict Studies Centre at the University of Otago, New Zealand “The Great Con of National Security” August 15 2012 https://richardjacksonterrorismblog.wordpress.com/2012/08/05/the-great-con-of-national-security</p><p>It may have once been the case that being attacked by another country was a major threat to the lives of ordinary people. It may also be true that there are still some pretty serious dangers out there associated with the spread of nuclear weapons. For the most part, however, most of<u> </u>what you’ve been told about national security and all the<u> <mark>big threats</mark> </u>which can supposedly kill you is one big con designed to<u> <strong><mark>distract</strong> </u></mark>you<u> <mark>from the things that can really hurt</u></mark> you,<u> <mark>such as</u></mark> the poverty, inequality and<u> <mark>structural violence</u></mark> of capitalism, global warming, and the manufacture and proliferation of weapons – among others. The facts are simple and irrefutable: you’re far more likely to die from lack of health care provision than you are from terrorism; from stress and overwork than Iranian or North Korean nuclear missiles; from lack of road safety than from illegal immigrants; from mental illness and suicide than from computer hackers; from domestic violence than from asylum seekers; from the misuse of legal medicines and alcohol abuse than from international drug lords. And yet, <u>politicians and</u> the servile <u>media spend most of their time talking about</u> the threats posed by <u><strong><mark>terrorism</u></strong>,</mark> immigration, asylum seekers, the international drug trade, the nuclear programmes of <u><strong><mark>Iran</u></strong></mark> and <u><strong><mark>North Korea</u></strong></mark>, computer hackers, animal rights activism, the threat of <u><strong><mark>China</u></strong></mark>, <u><mark>and </mark>a host of <strong><mark>other issues</strong> </mark>which <mark>are</u></mark> all about as equally <u><strong><mark>unlikely</u></strong></mark> <u>to affect the health and well-being of you and your family</u>. Along with this obsessive and perennial discussion of so-called ‘national security issues’, <u>the state spends</u> truly <u>vast sums on security measures which have</u> virtually <u>no impact on the actual risk of dying from these threats, and then engages in</u> massive displays of <u>‘security theatre’</u> designed <u>to show just how seriously the state takes these threats </u>– such as the x-ray machines and security measures in every public building, surveillance cameras everywhere, missile launchers in urban areas, drones in Afghanistan, armed police in airports, and a thousand other things. This display is meant to convince you that these threats are really, really serious. And while all this is going on, <u><mark>the rulers of society are hoping</u></mark> that <u><mark>you won’t notice</u></mark> that <u><mark>increasing </u></mark>social and economic <u><mark>inequality </u>i</mark>n society leads to increased ill health for a growing underclass; that suicide and crime always rise when unemployment rises; that workplaces remain highly dangerous and kill and maim hundreds of people per year; that there are preventable diseases which plague the poorer sections of society; that domestic violence kills and injures thousands of women and children annually; and that globally, poverty and preventable disease kills tens of millions of people needlessly every year. In other words, they are hoping that you won’t notice how much structural violence there is in the world. More than this, they are hoping that you won’t notice that while literally trillions of dollars are spent on military weapons, foreign wars and security theatre (which also arguably do nothing to make any us any safer, and may even make us marginally less safe), that domestic violence programmes struggle to provide even minimal support for women and children at risk of serious harm from their partners; that underfunded mental health programmes mean long waiting lists to receive basic care for at-risk individuals; that drug and alcohol rehabilitation programmes lack the funding to match the demand for help; that welfare measures aimed at reducing inequality have been inadequate for decades; that health and safety measures at many workplaces remain insufficiently resourced; and that measures to tackle global warming and developing alternative energy remain hopelessly inadequate. Of course, none of this is surprising. Politicians are a part of the system; they don’t want to change it. <u><mark>For them</u></mark>, all the <u><mark>insecurity</u></mark>, death and ill-health caused by capitalist inequality <u><mark>are a price worth paying to <strong>keep</u></strong></mark> the basic <u><strong><mark>social structures as they are</u></strong></mark>. <u>A more <mark>egalitarian society</u></mark> based on equality, solidarity, and other non-materialist values <u><mark>would not suit their interests</u></mark>, or the special interests of the lobby groups they are indebted to. It is also true that dealing with economic and social inequality, improving public health, changing international structures of inequality, restructuring the military-industrial complex, and making the necessary economic and political changes to deal with global warming will be extremely difficult and will require long-term commitment and determination. For politicians looking towards the next election, it is clearly much easier to paint immigrants as a threat to social order or pontificate about the ongoing danger of terrorists. <u>It is also more exciting for the media than stories about how</u> poor people and <u>people of colour are discriminated against and suffer worse health as a consequence</u>. Viewed from this vantage point, national <u><strong><mark>security is </u></strong></mark>one massive confidence trick<u> – <strong><mark>misdirection on an epic scale</u></strong></mark>. Its primary function is<u> <strong><mark>to distract you from</strong> </u></mark>the<u> <strong><mark>structures</strong> </u></mark>and inequalities in society<u> <strong><mark>which are the real threat</strong> </u></mark>to the health and wellbeing of you and your family, <u><strong><mark>and to convince you to</strong></mark> </u>be<u> <strong><mark>permanently</strong> </u></mark>afraid so that you will<u> <strong><mark>acquiesce to</u></strong></mark> all the <u><strong><mark>security measures</u></strong></mark> which keep you under state control and keep the military-industrial complex ticking along. Keep this in mind next time you hear a politician talking about the threat of uncontrolled immigration, the risk posed by asylum seekers or the threat of Iran, or the need to expand counter-terrorism powers. The question is: when politicians are talking about national security, what is that they don’t want you to think and talk about? What exactly is the misdirection they are engaged in? The truth is, if you think that terrorists or immigrants or asylum seekers or Iran are a greater threat to your safety than the capitalist system, you have been well and truly conned, my friend. Don’t believe the hype: <u><strong><mark>you’re much more likely to die from</u></strong></mark> any one of several forms of <u><strong><mark>structural violence</u></strong></mark> in society than you are from immigrants or terrorism. Somehow, <u><strong>we need to challenge</u></strong> the politicians on <u><strong>this</u></strong> fact.</p> | 1AC | 1AC - Framing | null | 18,777 | 610 | 56,042 | ./documents/hspolicy20/Kickapoo/KeMo/Kickapoo-Kennedy-Montford-Aff-Dragon%20Discloure-Finals.docx | 731,691 | A | Dragon Discloure | Finals | none | null | null | hspolicy20/Kickapoo/KeMo/Kickapoo-Kennedy-Montford-Aff-Dragon%20Discloure-Finals.docx | null | 62,475 | KeMo | Kickapoo KeMo | null | Ca..... | Ke..... | Bl..... | Mo..... | 21,671 | Kickapoo | Kickapoo | MO | null | 1,019 | hspolicy20 | HS Policy 2020-21 | 2,020 | cx | hs | 2 |
4,731,582 | That’s key to ICJ cred that solves territorial conflicts—perm fails. | Angehr ’8 | Angehr ’8 [Mark; 2008; Expert @ the Federalist Society for Law & public policy studies, JD candidate @ Northwestern Law, Engage, Vol 9 Issue 2, June, https://fedsoc-cms-public.s3.amazonaws.com/update/pdf/zkFz3EzOjG6xiLxTg9WkUFCKT5Ona8oBZTuPh2H4.pdf] brett | ICJ is a principal organ of the UN as well as the UN’s principal judicial organ ICJ’s status as “principal judicial organ” of the UN has been characterized as an “organic link” to the shared goals of the UN system ICJ has a duty to further the purposes and principles of the UN These purposes are to “maintain peace and security and “take collective measures for the prevention and removal of threats to the peace The advisory function of the ICJ serves as a vehicle for the Court’s participation in the “Purposes and Principles” of the UN Charter. Accordingly, the Court placed the matter “in a much broader frame of reference than a bilateral dispute,” as it was “of particularly acute concern to the United Nations. Organizational theory helps to explain why the ICJ is not functioning as a check on the actions of the political organs in its advisory jurisdiction Th e ICJ’s reliance on compliance ncentivizes give opinions in accordance with political preferences likelihood that the Court will render an opinion in line with policy preferences of political organ is thus greater. Th e results of such a model have been borne out in the Court’s case law. Council requested advisory opinion on South Africa’s continued presence The request was seen as an opportunity for the Court to “redeem its impaired image,” since its advisory jurisdiction had been unused The Court in this iteration of coordination produced an opinion in line with clear political preference by holding that South Africa’s presence was illegal Although this coordination effect has positive value as an explanation of the ICJ’s behavior, it should not be seen as normative. Th e ICJ overestimates the institutional benefits it receives from such coordination. In light of the cost in loss of judicial autonomy and reduced institutional benefits, a new calculation shows that the Court should defer less Th e Court should thus be more competitive rendering decisions that may not line up with political preferences The result of such an undertaking is more independent and legitimate advisory opinions. As more authoritative statements of the law, the opinions would provide a better enforcement mechanism against the political organs to police the behavior of States By asserting its jurisdiction the ICJ would signal that the function each organ was to perform had changed. In the long-term, the functional differentiation of each organ would shift to accommodate the Court’s new role, and the organs ultimately resume a cooperative interaction. Th e political organ would continue to request opinions, because the benefit of receiving truly independent advisory opinions would outweigh the risk of an opinion not in line with its political preference. A revitalized advisory jurisdiction could aid the political organs in providing another strong enforcement mechanism against States that violate international norms. This model has the additional advantage of better serving the shared goals of the UN system. In reclaiming its judicial autonomy within its advisory jurisdiction, the Court is aiding the UN’s settlement of international disputes “in conformity with the principles of justice and international law In contrast, an opinion that reproduces the politically-determined legal conclusion does not further this goal, because it abdicates judicial responsibility to a political organ. | ICJ prevent threats not functioning as a check advisory opinion “redeem its image more independent and legitimate enforcement aiding settlement of disputes politically-determined conclusion abdicates responsibility | Organizational Dynamic of the ICJ’s Advisory Jurisdiction Th e ICJ is largely modeled on its predecessor court, the Permanent Court of International Justice (PCIJ), established by the League of Nations.7 However, unlike the PCIJ, which was not formally part of the League of Nations, the ICJ is a principal organ of the UN as well as the UN’s principal judicial organ.8 Only States may be parties in cases before the fi fteen-member Court, though the State need not be a member of the UN in order to appear.9 Member States may request that the Court exercise jurisdiction over any dispute involving interpretation of a treaty or international law, or the “existence of any fact which, if established, would constitute a breach of an international obligation.”10 Once jurisdiction has been established, the Court must decide disputes in accordance with international law, which is limited to international conventions, custom, and general principles of law.11 Th e Assembly and the Council are authorized to submit advisory opinion requests to the ICJ on “any legal question,” which the Court has broadly construed to include complex factual disputes or political issues.12 Th e advisory opinion request must be “accompanied by all documents likely to throw light upon the question.”13 Th e advisory opinion, while truly a peculiar notion to federal courts in the United States, is permitted in many U.S. courts.14 However, the advisory jurisdiction as exercised in the World Court diff ers from the practice in the United States of a state legislator requesting a court’s opinion on the constitutionality of a proposed law.15 Th e ICJ’s advisory opinions have often involved hotly debated political disputes16 and legal questions embedded in broader bilateral disputes.17 State consent, while required for the exercise of contentious jurisdiction, is not required for the ICJ to exercise advisory jurisdiction over a dispute.18 Th e ICJ’s status as “principal judicial organ” of the UN has been characterized as an “organic link” to the shared goals of the UN system.19 Th e ICJ, like all other principal organs in the UN system, has a duty to further the purposes and principles of the UN These purposes are to “maintain peace and security,” and “take collective measures for the prevention and removal of threats to the peace.”20 The advisory function of the ICJ, even more than its contentious jurisdiction, serves as a vehicle for the Court’s participation in the “Purposes and Principles” of the UN Charter.21 Proponents of the advisory jurisdiction argue that by rendering advisory opinions, the Court is able to place another organ’s operation upon a firm and secure foundation. Judge Bedjaoui has written that the Court’s advisory function assists the political organs by taking into account “its preoccupations or diffi culties and by selecting, from all possible interpretations of the Charter, the one which best serves the actions and objectives of the political organ concerned.”22 In the Wall Opinion, the Court explained that its obligation to clarify a legal issue for the Assembly outweighed any concerns about the judicial propriety of adjudicating an ongoing political dispute and armed conflict between Israel and Palestine.23 Accordingly, the Court stressed the organizational purpose of the advisory opinion: “Th e Court’s Opinion is given not to the States, but to the organ which is entitled to request it.”24 Th e ICJ characterized the opinion as that which “the General Assembly deems of assistance to it in the proper exercise of its function.”25 Accordingly, the Court placed the matter “in a much broader frame of reference than a bilateral dispute,” as it was “of particularly acute concern to the United Nations.”26 Th e Court is strongly inclined to not only answer a request for an advisory opinion, but to facilitate the larger aims of the UN by arriving at a conclusion in line with the preference of the political organ.27 Judge Azevedo has stated that the Court “must do its utmost to co-operate with the other organs with a view to attaining the aims and principles that have been set forth.”28 Th e closer the institutional connection of the ICJ to the requesting organ, he argues, the greater the usefulness of that opinion to the operation of the requesting organ. However, the advisory function threatens the institutional legitimacy of the Court because it often resolves disputes without the consent of the relevant States,29 and the political organ making the request has often already ruled on the issue.30 Organizational theory helps to explain why the ICJ is not functioning as a check on the actions of the political organs in its advisory jurisdiction. By examining the benefi ts and drawbacks of coordination among organizations and within organizations, organizational theory predicts the most effi cient modes of cooperation.31 Studies of coordination mechanisms within organizations suggest that the ICJ is likely motivated to undertake advisory opinions out of a fear of institutional isolation and marginalization.32 An organization might “seek[] to forestall or prevent future crisis which may imperil its success or even continuation.”33 Because organizations have incentives to increase their authority and prestige, the Court is unlikely to decline the opportunity to contribute to the progress of international law by rendering an advisory opinion.34 Given the institutional incentives for rendering advisory opinions, the ICJ will continue to do so as long as the perceived benefi ts of cooperation outweigh the loss in judicial autonomy.35 Similarly, the political organ will make the request as long as the perceived advantage to its operations outweighs any loss to its political autonomy. Th e ICJ’s reliance on the political organs to enforce compliance with its decisions incentivizes the Court not only to take on advisory opinions, but to give opinions in accordance with the political preferences of the requesting organ. Th e main impediment to coordination between the ICJ and the political organ is the line between cooperation and competition. If the degree of interdependence is high, and the degree of antagonism is high, the result will be competition and confl ict.36 By contrast, if the degree of interdependence is high, and the degree of antagonism is low, the result will be cooperation. The ICJ has an incentive to reduce competition and increase smooth cooperation in order to avoid alienating the requesting organ and risking institutional isolation. If we map the interaction of the ICJ and the Assembly in the Wall Opinion onto this organizational dynamic, we see a high level of interdependence due to their “organic link” and a low level of antagonism due to the Court’s incentive to contribute to the shared goals of the UN as reflected in the stated policy preference of the Assembly. Th e resultant “cooperation” between the two organs reduces the need for information processing and furthers the shared mission of the UN. By systematizing coordination through a process that provides the Court with “an exact statement of the question” as well as a “voluminous dossier”37 of documents “likely to throw light on the question,”38 the Court is unlikely to conduct its own investigation outside of the given universe of documents. From an organizational theory perspective, the Court will not engage in its own extensive review of the background material and facts, because such a duplicative inquiry would bring the Court into competition with the functioning of the requesting organ. In relying on the resolutions and factual studies made by the political organs, the likelihood that the Court will render an opinion in line with the policy preferences of the political organ is thus greater. Th e results of such a model have been borne out in the Court’s case law. In 1949, the Court held in an advisory opinion that South Africa had no legal obligation to place its mandate, South West Africa (now Namibia), under a trusteeship with the UN39 Th e Assembly had advocated for South Africa’s withdrawal from South West Africa, but the Court found in favor of South Africa’s continued occupation. Th e opinion weakened the Court’s credibility, especially among African nations.40 Th e loss of political capital to the Assembly outweighed any potential benefi t of further coordination with the Court on the issue, and, as a result, the Assembly never revisited the issue with the Court. Th en, in 1971, the Council requested an advisory opinion on the “legal consequences” of South Africa’s continued presence in Namibia.41 The request was seen as an opportunity for the Court to “redeem its impaired image,” since its advisory jurisdiction had been unused since 1962.42 Th e Council had in fact already passed Resolution 276, which strongly condemned the “illegal” presence of South Africa in Namibia.43 The Court in this iteration of coordination produced an opinion in line with the clear political preference of the Council by holding that South Africa’s presence in Namibia was illegal.44 Th e Court’s interaction with the Council was thus cooperative, and in rendering an opinion that mirrored the eff ect of the Council’s resolution on the issue, the Court avoided confl ict with the political organ. Th e Court consequently repaired its image and staved off institutional marginalization by indicating its willingness to cooperate with the political organs. Although this coordination effect has positive value as an explanation of the ICJ’s behavior, it should not be seen as normative. Th e ICJ overestimates the institutional benefits it receives from such coordination. The fear of institutional isolation motivates the ICJ to defer to the political organ, but there is little evidence that behaving in such a way increases in the long-term the number of advisory requests that the Court receives. If the Court were correct in the assumption that advisory opinions deferent to the preferences of the political organs lessen the court’s marginalization and increase the volume of its advisory jurisdiction caseload, there would be an increase in advisory opinions after the ICJ rendered a deferent advisory opinion. Although advisory requests two and four years later followed the deferent South West Africa opinion, a statistical breakdown of the Court’s advisory docket shows no long-term changes in the number of opinions rendered from its fi rst opinion in 1947 to its last in 2004. Th e Court averages about four advisory opinions a decade. As of 2008, the Court has not received another advisory request since the Wall Opinion, and it would appear that the Court will have a below-average number of advisory opinions this decade, despite the accommodation it provided the Assembly in the cooperative Wall Opinion. While the ICJ is concerned about institutional marginalization and orders its behavior in rendering advisory opinions accordingly, the motivation of the political organs in requesting advisory opinions proves to be more complex. First, the Council or Assembly may refer a dispute to the ICJ’s advisory jurisdiction when the intractability of the dispute does not lend itself to political resolution. Second, a referral to the ICJ’s advisory jurisdiction can take place if the particular dispute is susceptible to judicial resolution, that is, if the ICJ can help the organ overcome a political impasse by settling a question of international law. Th ird, if the political organ doubts the utility of the advisory opinion it will receive, or if it fears an opinion not in line with its political preferences, it can take steps to make known its preferences before the Court composes its opinion. Th erefore, the political organ’s perception of the ICJ’s propensity to render an opinion not in line with the organ’s political preference is just one of three factors that determine when the ICJ will be asked to exercise its advisory jurisdiction. Th e Court’s fear of marginalization is thus overblown; the factors determining when the organs refer a dispute to its advisory jurisdiction depend more on the peculiar nature of the dispute itself than on the Court’s perceived deference to the political will of the Council or Assembly. In other words, the Assembly’s decision to refer to the ICJ the question of the legality of the wall in Palestine depended more on the exigencies of that particular situation—namely, the need for a legal and not political resolution—than on the ICJ’s recent record of deference to the Assembly in its advisory jurisdiction. In light of the cost in loss of judicial autonomy and reduced institutional benefits, a new calculation shows that the Court should defer less to the requesting organ. Th e Court should thus be more competitive by undertaking its own fact- fi nding and by rendering decisions that may not line up with the political preferences of the requesting organ. The result of such an undertaking is more independent and legitimate advisory opinions. As more authoritative statements of the law, the opinions would provide a better enforcement mechanism against the political organs to police the behavior of States that have violated their legal obligations. By asserting its jurisdiction over fact-finding and legal interpretation, the ICJ would signal to the requesting organ that the function each organ was to perform had changed. In the long-term, the functional differentiation of each organ would shift to accommodate the Court’s new role, and the organs could ultimately resume a cooperative interaction. Th e political organ would continue to request opinions, because the benefit of receiving truly independent advisory opinions would outweigh the risk of an opinion not in line with its political preference. A revitalized advisory jurisdiction could aid the political organs in providing another strong enforcement mechanism against States that violate international norms. This model has the additional advantage of better serving the shared goals of the UN system. In reclaiming its judicial autonomy within its advisory jurisdiction, the Court is aiding the UN’s settlement of international disputes “in conformity with the principles of justice and international law.”45 In contrast, an opinion that reproduces the politically-determined legal conclusion of the requesting organ does not further this goal, because it abdicates judicial responsibility to a political organ. | 14,459 | <h4>That’s <u>key</u> to <u>ICJ cred</u> that solves <u>territorial conflicts</u>—perm <u>fails</u>.</h4><p><strong>Angehr ’8</strong> [Mark; 2008; Expert @ the Federalist Society for Law & public policy studies, JD candidate @ Northwestern Law, Engage, Vol 9 Issue 2, June, https://fedsoc-cms-public.s3.amazonaws.com/update/pdf/zkFz3EzOjG6xiLxTg9WkUFCKT5Ona8oBZTuPh2H4.pdf] brett</p><p>Organizational Dynamic of the ICJ’s Advisory Jurisdiction Th e ICJ is largely modeled on its predecessor court, the Permanent Court of International Justice (PCIJ), established by the League of Nations.7 However, unlike the PCIJ, which was not formally part of the League of Nations, the <u>ICJ is a principal organ of the UN as well as the UN’s principal judicial organ</u>.8 Only States may be parties in cases before the fi fteen-member Court, though the State need not be a member of the UN in order to appear.9 Member States may request that the Court exercise jurisdiction over any dispute involving interpretation of a treaty or international law, or the “existence of any fact which, if established, would constitute a breach of an international obligation.”10 Once jurisdiction has been established, the Court must decide disputes in accordance with international law, which is limited to international conventions, custom, and general principles of law.11 Th e Assembly and the Council are authorized to submit advisory opinion requests to the ICJ on “any legal question,” which the Court has broadly construed to include complex factual disputes or political issues.12 Th e advisory opinion request must be “accompanied by all documents likely to throw light upon the question.”13 Th e advisory opinion, while truly a peculiar notion to federal courts in the United States, is permitted in many U.S. courts.14 However, the advisory jurisdiction as exercised in the World Court diff ers from the practice in the United States of a state legislator requesting a court’s opinion on the constitutionality of a proposed law.15 Th e ICJ’s advisory opinions have often involved hotly debated political disputes16 and legal questions embedded in broader bilateral disputes.17 State consent, while required for the exercise of contentious jurisdiction, is not required for the ICJ to exercise advisory jurisdiction over a dispute.18 Th e <u><strong><mark>ICJ</strong></mark>’s status as “principal judicial organ” of the UN has been characterized as an “organic link” to the shared goals of the UN system</u>.19 Th e <u>ICJ</u>, like all other principal organs in the UN system, <u>has a <strong>duty</strong> to further the purposes and principles of the UN</u> <u>These purposes are to “<strong>maintain peace</strong> and security</u>,” <u>and “take collective measures for the <strong><mark>prevent</strong></mark>ion and removal of <mark>threats</mark> to the peace</u>.”20 <u>The advisory function of the ICJ</u>, even more than its contentious jurisdiction, <u>serves as a <strong>vehicle for the Court’s participation</strong> in the “Purposes and Principles” of the UN Charter.</u>21 Proponents of the advisory jurisdiction argue that by rendering advisory opinions, the Court is able to place another organ’s operation upon a firm and secure foundation. Judge Bedjaoui has written that the Court’s advisory function assists the political organs by taking into account “its preoccupations or diffi culties and by selecting, from all possible interpretations of the Charter, the one which best serves the actions and objectives of the political organ concerned.”22 In the Wall Opinion, the Court explained that its obligation to clarify a legal issue for the Assembly outweighed any concerns about the judicial propriety of adjudicating an ongoing political dispute and armed conflict between Israel and Palestine.23 Accordingly, the Court stressed the organizational purpose of the advisory opinion: “Th e Court’s Opinion is given not to the States, but to the organ which is entitled to request it.”24 Th e ICJ characterized the opinion as that which “the General Assembly deems of assistance to it in the proper exercise of its function.”25 <u>Accordingly, the Court placed the matter “in a <strong>much broader frame</strong> of reference than a bilateral dispute,” as it was “of particularly acute concern to the United Nations.</u>”26 Th e Court is strongly inclined to not only answer a request for an advisory opinion, but to facilitate the larger aims of the UN by arriving at a conclusion in line with the preference of the political organ.27 Judge Azevedo has stated that the Court “must do its utmost to co-operate with the other organs with a view to attaining the aims and principles that have been set forth.”28 Th e closer the institutional connection of the ICJ to the requesting organ, he argues, the greater the usefulness of that opinion to the operation of the requesting organ. However, the advisory function threatens the institutional legitimacy of the Court because it often resolves disputes without the consent of the relevant States,29 and the political organ making the request has often already ruled on the issue.30 <u>Organizational theory helps to explain why the ICJ is <mark>not <strong>functioning as a check</mark> on the actions of the political organs</strong> in its advisory jurisdiction</u>. By examining the benefi ts and drawbacks of coordination among organizations and within organizations, organizational theory predicts the most effi cient modes of cooperation.31 Studies of coordination mechanisms within organizations suggest that the ICJ is likely motivated to undertake advisory opinions out of a fear of institutional isolation and marginalization.32 An organization might “seek[] to forestall or prevent future crisis which may imperil its success or even continuation.”33 Because organizations have incentives to increase their authority and prestige, the Court is unlikely to decline the opportunity to contribute to the progress of international law by rendering an advisory opinion.34 Given the institutional incentives for rendering advisory opinions, the ICJ will continue to do so as long as the perceived benefi ts of cooperation outweigh the loss in judicial autonomy.35 Similarly, the political organ will make the request as long as the perceived advantage to its operations outweighs any loss to its political autonomy. <u>Th e ICJ’s reliance on</u> the political organs to enforce <u>compliance</u> with its decisions i<u>ncentivizes</u> the Court not only to take on advisory opinions, but to <u>give</u> <u>opinions in accordance with </u>the <u><strong>political preferences</u></strong> of the requesting organ. Th e main impediment to coordination between the ICJ and the political organ is the line between cooperation and competition. If the degree of interdependence is high, and the degree of antagonism is high, the result will be competition and confl ict.36 By contrast, if the degree of interdependence is high, and the degree of antagonism is low, the result will be cooperation. The ICJ has an incentive to reduce competition and increase smooth cooperation in order to avoid alienating the requesting organ and risking institutional isolation. If we map the interaction of the ICJ and the Assembly in the Wall Opinion onto this organizational dynamic, we see a high level of interdependence due to their “organic link” and a low level of antagonism due to the Court’s incentive to contribute to the shared goals of the UN as reflected in the stated policy preference of the Assembly. Th e resultant “cooperation” between the two organs reduces the need for information processing and furthers the shared mission of the UN. By systematizing coordination through a process that provides the Court with “an exact statement of the question” as well as a “voluminous dossier”37 of documents “likely to throw light on the question,”38 the Court is unlikely to conduct its own investigation outside of the given universe of documents. From an organizational theory perspective, the Court will not engage in its own extensive review of the background material and facts, because such a duplicative inquiry would bring the Court into competition with the functioning of the requesting organ. In relying on the resolutions and factual studies made by the political organs, the <u>likelihood that the Court will render an opinion in line with</u> the <u>policy preferences of</u> the <u>political organ is thus greater. Th e results of such a model have been borne out in the Court’s case law.</u> In 1949, the Court held in an advisory opinion that South Africa had no legal obligation to place its mandate, South West Africa (now Namibia), under a trusteeship with the UN39 Th e Assembly had advocated for South Africa’s withdrawal from South West Africa, but the Court found in favor of South Africa’s continued occupation. Th e opinion weakened the Court’s credibility, especially among African nations.40 Th e loss of political capital to the Assembly outweighed any potential benefi t of further coordination with the Court on the issue, and, as a result, the Assembly never revisited the issue with the Court. Th en, in 1971, the <u>Council requested</u> an <u><strong><mark>advisory opinion</strong></mark> on</u> the “legal consequences” of <u>South Africa’s continued presence</u> in Namibia.41 <u>The request was seen as an opportunity for the Court to <mark>“<strong>redeem its</mark> impaired <mark>image</strong></mark>,” since its advisory jurisdiction had been unused </u>since 1962.42 Th e Council had in fact already passed Resolution 276, which strongly condemned the “illegal” presence of South Africa in Namibia.43 <u>The Court in this iteration of coordination produced an opinion in line with</u> the <u>clear political preference</u> of the Council <u>by <strong>holding that South Africa’s presence</u></strong> in Namibia <u><strong>was illegal</u></strong>.44 Th e Court’s interaction with the Council was thus cooperative, and in rendering an opinion that mirrored the eff ect of the Council’s resolution on the issue, the Court avoided confl ict with the political organ. Th e Court consequently repaired its image and staved off institutional marginalization by indicating its willingness to cooperate with the political organs. <u>Although this coordination effect has positive value as an explanation of the ICJ’s behavior, it should not be seen as normative. Th e ICJ <strong>overestimates the institutional benefits</strong> it receives from such coordination. </u>The fear of institutional isolation motivates the ICJ to defer to the political organ, but there is little evidence that behaving in such a way increases in the long-term the number of advisory requests that the Court receives. If the Court were correct in the assumption that advisory opinions deferent to the preferences of the political organs lessen the court’s marginalization and increase the volume of its advisory jurisdiction caseload, there would be an increase in advisory opinions after the ICJ rendered a deferent advisory opinion. Although advisory requests two and four years later followed the deferent South West Africa opinion, a statistical breakdown of the Court’s advisory docket shows no long-term changes in the number of opinions rendered from its fi rst opinion in 1947 to its last in 2004. Th e Court averages about four advisory opinions a decade. As of 2008, the Court has not received another advisory request since the Wall Opinion, and it would appear that the Court will have a below-average number of advisory opinions this decade, despite the accommodation it provided the Assembly in the cooperative Wall Opinion. While the ICJ is concerned about institutional marginalization and orders its behavior in rendering advisory opinions accordingly, the motivation of the political organs in requesting advisory opinions proves to be more complex. First, the Council or Assembly may refer a dispute to the ICJ’s advisory jurisdiction when the intractability of the dispute does not lend itself to political resolution. Second, a referral to the ICJ’s advisory jurisdiction can take place if the particular dispute is susceptible to judicial resolution, that is, if the ICJ can help the organ overcome a political impasse by settling a question of international law. Th ird, if the political organ doubts the utility of the advisory opinion it will receive, or if it fears an opinion not in line with its political preferences, it can take steps to make known its preferences before the Court composes its opinion. Th erefore, the political organ’s perception of the ICJ’s propensity to render an opinion not in line with the organ’s political preference is just one of three factors that determine when the ICJ will be asked to exercise its advisory jurisdiction. Th e Court’s fear of marginalization is thus overblown; the factors determining when the organs refer a dispute to its advisory jurisdiction depend more on the peculiar nature of the dispute itself than on the Court’s perceived deference to the political will of the Council or Assembly. In other words, the Assembly’s decision to refer to the ICJ the question of the legality of the wall in Palestine depended more on the exigencies of that particular situation—namely, the need for a legal and not political resolution—than on the ICJ’s recent record of deference to the Assembly in its advisory jurisdiction. <u>In light of the cost in <strong>loss of judicial autonomy and reduced institutional benefits</strong>, a new calculation shows that the Court should <strong>defer less</u></strong> to the requesting organ. <u>Th e Court should thus be <strong>more competitive</u></strong> by undertaking its own fact- fi nding and by <u><strong>rendering decisions that may not line up with</u></strong> the <u><strong>political preferences</u></strong> of the requesting organ. <u>The result of such an undertaking is <strong><mark>more independent and legitimate</strong></mark> advisory opinions. As more authoritative statements of the law, the opinions would provide a <strong>better <mark>enforcement</mark> mechanism</strong> against the political organs to police the behavior of States</u> that have violated their legal obligations. <u>By asserting its jurisdiction</u> over fact-finding and legal interpretation, <u>the ICJ would <strong>signal</u></strong> to the requesting organ <u><strong>that the function each organ was to perform had changed</strong>. In the long-term, the functional differentiation of each organ would <strong>shift to accommodate the Court’s new role</strong>, and the organs</u> could <u>ultimately <strong>resume a cooperative interaction</strong>. Th e political organ would continue to request opinions, because the benefit of receiving <strong>truly independent</strong> advisory opinions would outweigh the risk of an opinion not in line with its political preference. A <strong>revitalized</strong> advisory jurisdiction could <strong>aid the political organs in providing another strong enforcement mechanism against States that violate international norms</strong>. This model has the <strong>additional advantage of better serving the shared goals of the UN system</strong>.</u> <u>In reclaiming its judicial autonomy within its advisory jurisdiction, the Court is <strong><mark>aiding</mark> the UN’s <mark>settlement of</mark> international <mark>disputes</strong></mark> “in conformity with the principles of justice and international law</u>.”45 <u><strong>In contrast, an opinion that reproduces the <mark>politically-determined</mark> legal <mark>conclusion</u></strong></mark> of the requesting organ <u><strong>does not further this goal, because it <mark>abdicates</mark> judicial <mark>responsibility</mark> to a political organ</strong>.</p></u> | null | OFF | 1NC—CP | 24,759 | 223 | 165,057 | ./documents/hsld22/Lawrenceville/MiMe/Lawrenceville-MiMe-Neg-48th-University-of-Pennsylvania-Tournament-Round-2.docx | 973,569 | N | 48th University of Pennsylvania Tournament | 2 | Harrison TB | Booth | ac - cap
nc - icj populism case
1ar- all
2n - impact turn
2ar - all | hsld22/Lawrenceville/MiMe/Lawrenceville-MiMe-Neg-48th-University-of-Pennsylvania-Tournament-Round-2.docx | 2023-02-11 02:36:24 | 79,264 | MiMe | Lawrenceville MiMe | null | Mi..... | Me..... | null | null | 26,510 | Lawrenceville | Lawrenceville | NJ | null | 2,003 | hsld22 | HS LD 2022-23 | 2,022 | ld | hs | 1 |
1,237,979 | “Should” isn’t certain. | Black’s Law 79 | Black’s Law 79 (Black’s Law Dictionary – Fifth Edition, p. 1237) | Should does not ordinarily express certainty as “will” sometimes does. | Should does not express certainty | Should. The past tense of shall; ordinarily implying duty or obligation; although usually no more than an obligation of propriety or expediency, or a moral obligation, thereby distinguishing it from “ought.” It is not normally synonymous with “may,” and although often interchangeable with the word “would,” it does not ordinarily express certainty as “will” sometimes does. | 374 | <h4>“Should” isn’t certain.</h4><p><strong>Black’s Law 79<u></strong> (Black’s Law Dictionary – Fifth Edition, p. 1237)</p><p><mark>Should</u></mark>. The past tense of shall; ordinarily implying duty or obligation; although usually no more than an obligation of propriety or expediency, or a moral obligation, thereby distinguishing it from “ought.” It is not normally synonymous with “may,” and although often interchangeable with the word “would,” it <u><strong><mark>does not</mark> ordinarily <mark>express certainty</strong></mark> as “will” sometimes does. </p></u> | 2AC | Off | Devolution CP | 1,216 | 289 | 30,694 | ./documents/hspolicy21/WalterPayton/McWe/Walter%20Payton-McDermott-Weese-Aff-5%20-%20Dowling-Round3.docx | 755,948 | A | 5 - Dowling | 3 | GBN CG | Will Kirby | 1AC is Military Exemptions v5
1NC is CP Conditions CP Devolution DA Midterms T Protection
2NR is T Protection | hspolicy21/WalterPayton/McWe/Walter%20Payton-McDermott-Weese-Aff-5%20-%20Dowling-Round3.docx | null | 64,550 | McWe | Walter Payton McWe | null | Da..... | Mc..... | Co..... | We..... | 22,167 | WalterPayton | Walter Payton | IL | null | 1,020 | hspolicy21 | HS Policy 2021-22 | 2,021 | cx | hs | 2 |
2,069,861 | B] Real world education—an understanding of Kantianism is key to understanding the law in the real world because most states abide by inviolable side-constraints in their constitutions—Germany proves. | Ripstein, Arthur. Force and Freedom: Kant's Legal and Political Philosophy. Harvard University Press, 2009. *bracketed for clarity and grammar* | Ripstein, Arthur. Force and Freedom: Kant's Legal and Political Philosophy. Harvard University Press, 2009. *bracketed for clarity and grammar* | the German Basic Law [says] “Human dignity shall be inviolable. To respect and protect it shall be the duty of all state authority.” The following basic rights shall bind the legislature, the executive, and the judiciary as directly applicable law.” The right to dignity is the basis of the state’s power to legislate and so is not subject to any limitation, because—to put it in explicitly Kantian terms—citizens could not give themselves a law that turned them into mere objects. | the German Basic Law [says] The right to dignity is the basis of the state’s power to legislate to put it in explicitly Kantian terms—citizens could not give themselves a law that turned them into mere objects. | Strictly speaking, the right to dignity is not an enumerated right in the German Basic Law [says], but the organizing principle under which all enumerated rights—ranging from life and security of the person through freedom of expression, movement, association, and employment and the right to a fair trial to equality before the law—are organized. It appears as Art. I.1: “Human dignity shall be inviolable. To respect and protect it shall be the duty of all state authority.” Art. I.3 explains that the enumerated rights follow: “The following basic rights shall bind the legislature, the executive, and the judiciary as directly applicable law.” Other, enumerated rights are subject to proportionality analysis, through which they can be restricted in light of each other so as to give effect to a consistent system of rights. The right to dignity is the basis of the state’s power to legislate and so is not subject to any limitation, even in light of the enumerated rights falling under it, because—to put it in explicitly Kantian terms—citizens could not give themselves a law that turned them into mere objects. | 1,117 | <h4>B] <u>Real world education</u>—an understanding of Kantianism is key to understanding the law in the real world because most states abide by inviolable side-constraints in their constitutions—Germany proves. </h4><p><u><strong><mark>Ripstein</mark>, Arthur. Force and Freedom: Kant's Legal and Political Philosophy. Harvard University Press, 2009. *bracketed for clarity and grammar*</p><p></u></strong>Strictly speaking, the right to dignity is not an enumerated right in <u><strong><mark>the German Basic Law [says]</u></strong></mark>, but the organizing principle under which all enumerated rights—ranging from life and security of the person through freedom of expression, movement, association, and employment and the right to a fair trial to equality before the law—are organized. It appears as Art. I.1:<u><strong> “Human dignity shall be inviolable. To respect and protect it shall be the duty of all state authority.”</u></strong> Art. I.3 explains that the enumerated rights follow: “<u><strong>The following basic rights shall bind the legislature, the executive, and the judiciary as directly applicable law.”</u></strong> Other, enumerated rights are subject to proportionality analysis, through which they can be restricted in light of each other so as to give effect to a consistent system of rights. <u><strong><mark>The right to dignity is the basis of the state’s power to legislate </mark>and so is not subject to any limitation,</u></strong> even in light of the enumerated rights falling under it, <u><strong>because—<mark>to put it in explicitly Kantian terms—citizens could not give themselves a law that turned them into mere objects.</p></u></strong></mark> | null | 3 | null | 359,828 | 183 | 61,466 | ./documents/hsld20/AmericanHeritageBocaDelray/Sa/American%20Heritage%20Boca%20Delray-SaraswathiMohan-Neg-Stanford-Round6.docx | 852,464 | N | Stanford | 6 | Northern Valley HS Independent | James Stuckert | AC
3 OFF CASE
Spikes on top weigh between framing mechanisms Kant
Spikes on top
I meets | hsld20/AmericanHeritageBocaDelray/Sa/American%20Heritage%20Boca%20Delray-SaraswathiMohan-Neg-Stanford-Round6.docx | null | 72,652 | NaSa | American Heritage Boca Delray NaSa | null | Na..... | Sa..... | null | null | 24,405 | AmericanHeritageBocaDelray | American Heritage Boca Delray | FL | null | 1,028 | hsld20 | HS LD 2020-21 | 2,020 | ld | hs | 1 |
2,482,114 | US-Russia war is the only scenario for extinction. | Barratt 17 | Dr. Owen Cotton-Barratt 17. PhD in Pure Mathematics, Oxford, Lecturer in Mathematics at Oxford and Research Associate at the Future of Humanity Institute, et al, “Existential Risk: Diplomacy and Governance”, 2/3/2017, https://www.fhi.ox.ac.uk/wp-content/uploads/Existential-Risks-2017-01-23.pdf | even in an all-out nuclear war between the U S and Russia neither country’s population is likely to be completely destroyed by the direct effects of the blast The aftermath could be much worse burning flammable materials could send massive amounts of smoke into the atmosphere a nuclear winter an all-out exchange of 4,000 weapons could lead to a drop in global temperatures of around 8°C, making it impossible to grow food for 5 years. This could leave some survivors but they would be in a very precarious situation and the threat of extinction from other sources would be great. An exchange on this scale is only possible between the US and Russia who have more than 90% of the world’s nuclear weapons a small regional nuclear war involving 100 nuclear weapons would put two billion at risk though this might be pessimistic Wars on this scale are unlikely to lead to human extinction It is difficult to precisely estimate the probability of existential risk from nuclear war the most likely nuclear war is between India and Pakistan However, given the relatively modest size of their arsenals, the risk of human extinction is plausibly greater from a conflict between the U S and Russia | in a nuclear war between U S and Russia aftermath could send massive smoke into the atmosphere a nuclear winter could drop global temperatures making it impossible to grow food threat of extinction would be great only possible between the US and Russia a small war unlikely to lead to extinction risk is greater from U S and Russia | The bombings of Hiroshima and Nagasaki demonstrated the unprecedented destructive power of nuclear weapons. However, even in an all-out nuclear war between the United States and Russia, despite horrific casualties, neither country’s population is likely to be completely destroyed by the direct effects of the blast, fire, and radiation.8 The aftermath could be much worse: the burning of flammable materials could send massive amounts of smoke into the atmosphere, which would absorb sunlight and cause sustained global cooling, severe ozone loss, and agricultural disruption – a nuclear winter. According to one model 9 , an all-out exchange of 4,000 weapons10 could lead to a drop in global temperatures of around 8°C, making it impossible to grow food for 4 to 5 years. This could leave some survivors in parts of Australia and New Zealand, but they would be in a very precarious situation and the threat of extinction from other sources would be great. An exchange on this scale is only possible between the US and Russia who have more than 90% of the world’s nuclear weapons, with stockpiles of around 4,500 warheads each, although many are not operationally deployed.11 Some models suggest that even a small regional nuclear war involving 100 nuclear weapons would produce a nuclear winter serious enough to put two billion people at risk of starvation,12 though this estimate might be pessimistic.13 Wars on this scale are unlikely to lead to outright human extinction, but this does suggest that conflicts which are around an order of magnitude larger may be likely to threaten civilisation. It should be emphasised that there is very large uncertainty about the effects of a large nuclear war on global climate. This remains an area where increased academic research work, including more detailed climate modelling and a better understanding of how survivors might be able to cope and adapt, would have high returns. It is very difficult to precisely estimate the probability of existential risk from nuclear war over the next century, and existing attempts leave very large confidence intervals. According to many experts, the most likely nuclear war at present is between India and Pakistan.14 However, given the relatively modest size of their arsenals, the risk of human extinction is plausibly greater from a conflict between the United States and Russia. Tensions between these countries have increased in recent years and it seems unreasonable to rule out the possibility of them rising further in the future. | 2,526 | <h4>US-Russia war is the <u>only scenario</u> for extinction.</h4><p>Dr. Owen Cotton-<strong>Barratt 17</strong>. PhD in Pure Mathematics, Oxford, Lecturer in Mathematics at Oxford and Research Associate at the Future of Humanity Institute, et al, “Existential Risk: Diplomacy and Governance”, 2/3/2017, https://www.fhi.ox.ac.uk/wp-content/uploads/Existential-Risks-2017-01-23.pdf</p><p>The bombings of Hiroshima and Nagasaki demonstrated the unprecedented destructive power of nuclear weapons. However, <u>even <mark>in a</mark>n all-out <mark>nuclear war between</mark> the <strong><mark>U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates <u><mark>and Russia</u></mark>, despite horrific casualties, <u>neither country’s population is likely to be completely destroyed <strong>by the direct effects of the blast</u></strong>, fire, and radiation.8 <u>The <mark>aftermath could</mark> be <strong>much worse</u></strong>: the <u>burning</u> of <u>flammable materials could <mark>send massive</mark> amounts of <mark>smoke into the atmosphere</u></mark>, which would absorb sunlight and cause sustained global cooling, severe ozone loss, and agricultural disruption – <u><strong><mark>a nuclear winter</u></strong></mark>. According to one model 9 , <u>an all-out exchange of 4,000 weapons</u>10 <u><mark>could</mark> lead to a <mark>drop</mark> in <mark>global temperatures</mark> of around 8°C, <mark>making it <strong>impossible to grow food</mark> for</u></strong> 4 to <u><strong>5 years</strong>. This could leave some survivors</u> in parts of Australia and New Zealand, <u>but they would be in a very precarious situation and the <strong><mark>threat of extinction</mark> from other sources <mark>would be great</strong></mark>. An exchange on this scale is <strong><mark>only possible between the US and Russia</strong></mark> who have more than 90% of the world’s nuclear weapons</u>, with stockpiles of around 4,500 warheads each, although many are not operationally deployed.11 Some models suggest that even <u><mark>a small</mark> regional nuclear <mark>war</mark> involving 100 nuclear weapons would</u> produce a nuclear winter serious enough to <u>put two billion</u> people <u>at risk</u> of starvation,12 <u>though this</u> estimate <u><strong>might be pessimistic</u></strong>.13 <u>Wars on this scale are <strong><mark>unlikely to lead to</u></strong></mark> outright <u><strong>human <mark>extinction</u></strong></mark>, but this does suggest that conflicts which are around an order of magnitude larger may be likely to threaten civilisation. It should be emphasised that there is very large uncertainty about the effects of a large nuclear war on global climate. This remains an area where increased academic research work, including more detailed climate modelling and a better understanding of how survivors might be able to cope and adapt, would have high returns. <u>It is</u> very <u>difficult to precisely estimate the probability of <strong>existential <mark>risk</mark> from nuclear war</u></strong> over the next century, and existing attempts leave very large confidence intervals. According to many experts, <u>the most likely nuclear war</u> at present <u>is between India and Pakistan</u>.14 <u>However, given the relatively modest size of their arsenals, the risk of human extinction <mark>is</mark> <strong>plausibly <mark>greater</strong> from</mark> a conflict between the <strong><mark>U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates <u><mark>and Russia</u></mark>. Tensions between these countries have increased in recent years and it seems unreasonable to rule out the possibility of them rising further in the future.</p> | null | Russia DA | Outweighs---2NC | 46 | 1,991 | 80,515 | ./documents/ndtceda19/Emory/GiSh/Emory-Giampetruzzi-Shaikh-Neg-Texas-Round5.docx | 610,987 | N | Texas | 5 | Harvard BH | Armands Revelins | aff was debris test ban thing
2nr was the japan da | ndtceda19/Emory/GiSh/Emory-Giampetruzzi-Shaikh-Neg-Texas-Round5.docx | null | 51,763 | GiSh | Emory GiSh | null | Eu..... | Gi..... | Za..... | Sh..... | 19,247 | Emory | Emory | null | null | 1,009 | ndtceda19 | NDT/CEDA 2019-20 | 2,019 | cx | college | 2 |
1,426,906 | 3] Best studies prove pluralistic tendencies are inevitable | Polzler 19 | Polzler 19[Thomas Pölzler and Jennifer Cole Wright- “Empirical research on folk moral objectivism” https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC6686698/ NCBI. Published July 5th 2019] | Examining these studies' almost 30% of subjects' responses to the disagreement measure 50% of their responses to the truth‐aptness measure fell some moral statements were dominantly classified as objective others were dominantly classified as nonobjective Goodwin and Darley's study may have actually favored “metaethical pluralism More recent studies have by and large confirmed this folk metaethical pluralism Objectivity ratings for statements varied between as little as 5% and as much as 85%. Research based on different measures yielded high proportions of intrapersonal variation as well | Examining these studies' some moral statements were classified as objective others were as nonobjective Darley's study may have favored “metaethical pluralism More studies have confirmed Objectivity ratings for statements varied between 5% and 85%. | Examining these studies' results more closely, however, makes it less clear whether this interpretation is appropriate (Pölzler, 2018b). Take again Goodwin and Darley's study. In this study, almost 30% of subjects' responses to the disagreement measure and almost 50% of their responses to the truth‐aptness measure fell on the option that the researchers took to be indicative of subjectivism (Goodwin & Darley, 2008, pp. 1347, 1351). Moreover, while some moral statements were dominantly classified as objective (e.g., the above statement about robbery), many others were dominantly classified as nonobjective (e.g., the stem cell research statement). This suggests that subjects in Goodwin and Darley's study may have actually favored what Wright, Grandjean, and McWhite (2013) called “metaethical pluralism,” i.e., they sometimes sided with objectivism and other times with nonobjectivism. More recent studies have by and large confirmed this hypothesis of folk metaethical pluralism. Wright et al. (2013) and Wright, McWhite, and Grandjean (2014), for example, replicated Goodwin and Darley's results, using the exact same measures, but letting subjects classify the presented statements as moral and nonmoral themselves. Objectivity ratings for statements that were dominantly self‐classified as moral varied between as little as 5% and as much as 85%. Research based on different measures yielded high proportions of intrapersonal variation as well (e.g., Beebe, 2014; Beebe, Qiaoan, Wysocki, & Endara, 2015; Beebe & Sackris, 2016; Fisher, Knobe, Strickland, & Keil, 2017; Goodwin & Darley, 2012; Heiphetz & Young, 2017; Wright, 2018; Zijlstra, forthcoming‐a).2 | 1,668 | <h4>3] Best studies prove pluralistic tendencies are inevitable</h4><p><strong>Polzler 19</strong>[Thomas Pölzler and Jennifer Cole Wright- “Empirical research on folk moral objectivism” https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC6686698/ NCBI. Published July 5th 2019] </p><p><u><strong><mark>Examining these studies'</u></strong></mark> results more closely, however, makes it less clear whether this interpretation is appropriate (Pölzler, 2018b). Take again Goodwin and Darley's study. In this study, <u>almost 30% of subjects' responses to the disagreement measure</u> and almost <u>50% of their responses to the truth‐aptness measure fell</u> on the option that the researchers took to be indicative of subjectivism (Goodwin & Darley, 2008, pp. 1347, 1351). Moreover, while <u><strong><mark>some moral statements were</mark> dominantly <mark>classified as objective</u></strong></mark> (e.g., the above statement about robbery), many <u><strong><mark>others were</mark> dominantly classified <mark>as nonobjective</u></strong></mark> (e.g., the stem cell research statement). This suggests that subjects in <u>Goodwin and <strong><mark>Darley's study may have</mark> actually <mark>favored</u></strong></mark> what Wright, Grandjean, and McWhite (2013) called <u><strong><mark>“metaethical pluralism</u></strong></mark>,” i.e., they sometimes sided with objectivism and other times with nonobjectivism. <u><strong><mark>More</mark> recent <mark>studies have</mark> by and large <mark>confirmed</strong></mark> this</u> hypothesis of <u>folk metaethical pluralism</u>. Wright et al. (2013) and Wright, McWhite, and Grandjean (2014), for example, replicated Goodwin and Darley's results, using the exact same measures, but letting subjects classify the presented statements as moral and nonmoral themselves. <u><strong><mark>Objectivity ratings for statements</u></strong></mark> that were dominantly self‐classified as moral <u><strong><mark>varied between</mark> as little as <mark>5% and</mark> as much as <mark>85%.</u></strong></mark> <u>Research based on different measures yielded high proportions of intrapersonal variation as well</u> (e.g., Beebe, 2014; Beebe, Qiaoan, Wysocki, & Endara, 2015; Beebe & Sackris, 2016; Fisher, Knobe, Strickland, & Keil, 2017; Goodwin & Darley, 2012; Heiphetz & Young, 2017; Wright, 2018; Zijlstra, forthcoming‐a).2</p> | Speech 1AC Grapevine RD 3 vs Strake 9-11 9AM | null | FW | 328,978 | 192 | 39,057 | ./documents/hsld21/HoustonMemorial/Xu/Houston%20Memorial-Xu-Aff-Grapevine-Round3.docx | 889,249 | A | Grapevine | 3 | Strake Jesuit DL | Connor Self | AC- Prag
NC- T-Reduce Logcon Combo Shell
1AR- TT Multiple Shells Bad All
2NR- Combo Shell 1AR Offs
2AR- Multiple Shells Bad | hsld21/HoustonMemorial/Xu/Houston%20Memorial-Xu-Aff-Grapevine-Round3.docx | null | 74,785 | DaXu | Houston Memorial DaXu | null | Da..... | Xu..... | null | null | 25,020 | HoustonMemorial | Houston Memorial | TX | null | 1,029 | hsld21 | HS LD 2021-22 | 2,021 | ld | hs | 1 |
4,029,078 | Environmentalists aren’t voting – change won’t occur until turnout among activists increases. | Stinnett 15 (Nathaniel Stinnett (founded the Environmental Voter Project in 2015 after over a decade of experience as a senior advisor, consultant, and trainer for political campaigns and issue-advocacy nonprofits), 2015, “WHY DON'T ENVIRONMENTALISTS VOTE?”, Environmental Voter Project, https://www.environmentalvoter.org/news/why-dont-environmentalists-vote) | Stinnett 15 (Nathaniel Stinnett (founded the Environmental Voter Project in 2015 after over a decade of experience as a senior advisor, consultant, and trainer for political campaigns and issue-advocacy nonprofits), 2015, “WHY DON'T ENVIRONMENTALISTS VOTE?”, Environmental Voter Project, https://www.environmentalvoter.org/news/why-dont-environmentalists-vote) | But one of the environmental movement's biggest problems is the same now as it was on November 7: Environmentalists aren't voting. Approximately 20.1 million environmentalists are registered to vote, according to Environmental Voter Project research in the 2014 mid-term elections, only 4.2 million of them voted, and in the 2012 presidential election barely 10 million of them voted. early data reveal that America's overall turnout problem has only gotten worse. . Millions of long-registered voters likely stayed home on Election Day, which is particularly bad news for the environmental movement, because we tend to be poor voters. No matter who wins an election we can't expect environmental leadership when so few voters demand it. environmentalists need to address their turnout problem. Politicians want to win elections. To do that, they focus on issues of importance to voters, not non-voters. Right now, voters do not prioritize environmental issues. When we polled likely voters this summer, only 4 percent listed climate change and the environment as a top-2 issue Although voters don't prioritize environmental issues, non-voters do. Large majorities of Americans support government action to address climate change and protect the environment. Furthermore, committed environmentalists already go to great lengths to act on their beliefs millions of Americans are already fully persuaded environmentalists Politicians are already fielding new polls to determine their legislative priorities for 2017 and 2018, but their pollsters only survey voters, which means that most environmentalists won't be heard until we start voting. Simply by voting, environmentalists can appear on a campaign's radar and become the focus of all polling With politicians already focusing on the next election, the challenge to the environmental movement is to identify our non-voting environmentalists and mobilize them to do just one thing on one day: vote. | Environmentalists aren't voting in 2012 barely 10 million voted America's overall turnout problem has only gotten worse. we can't expect environmental leadership when so few voters demand it Politicians focus on issues of importance to voters, Although voters don't prioritize environmental issues, non-voters do most environmentalists won't be heard until we start voting | The last few weeks have rocked the environmental movement. In the wake of the November elections, environmentalists are deeply concerned about the future of the Paris climate accord, the rollback of federal environmental protections, and even the fate of the U.S. Environmental Protection Agency itself. But one of the environmental movement's biggest problems is the same now as it was on November 7: Environmentalists aren't voting. Approximately 20.1 million environmentalists are registered to vote, according to Environmental Voter Project research. But in the 2014 mid-term elections, only 4.2 million of them voted, and in the 2012 presidential election barely 10 million of them voted. In Massachusetts, 277,250 environmentalists skipped our 2014 gubernatorial election, which was decided by only 40,000 votes. While we don't yet know how many environmentalists voted on November 8 (public voter files won't be updated until February), early data reveal that America's overall turnout problem has only gotten worse. Most pundits' election postmortems have dismissed turnout problems, since raw voter turnout increased from 129 million in 2012 to 137 million in 2016. Yet, these numbers ignore a crucially important consideration: Over that same time period, the total number of registered voters skyrocketed from 153 million to 200 million. While raw voter turnout increased by 6 percent since 2012, the overall pool of registered voters increased by 31 percent. Put another way, turnout as a percentage of overall registered voters plummeted from 84 percent to 68 percent. Some of this decrease can be attributed to positive developments, such as record-setting voter registration efforts and fewer restrictions on registration in some states. Nevertheless, the growth in voter rolls can't solely be blamed for the steep slide in turnout rates. Millions of long-registered voters likely stayed home on Election Day, which is particularly bad news for the environmental movement, because we tend to be poor voters. No matter who wins an election - whether they're an environmentalist, a Democrat or a Republican - we can't expect environmental leadership when so few voters demand it. Regardless of party affiliation, environmentalists need to address their turnout problem. We need to start voting for one simple reason: Politicians want to win elections. To do that, they focus on issues of importance to voters, not non-voters. Right now, voters do not prioritize environmental issues. When we polled likely voters this summer, only 4 percent listed climate change and the environment as a top-2 issue, placing it 15 out of the 19 issues in our survey. Still there's an opportunity hidden in these statistics. Although voters don't prioritize environmental issues, non-voters do. Large majorities of Americans support government action to address climate change and protect the environment. Furthermore, committed environmentalists already go to great lengths to act on their beliefs: They diligently recycle, they bike to work, and they install solar panels on their roofs, all of which require much more time and effort than voting. In short, millions of Americans are already fully persuaded environmentalists; now we just need to change our habits and start voting. Fortunately, changing people's habits is much easier than changing their minds. While Big Data and predictive analytics help us accurately identify these environmental non-voters, we can get them to vote with a high-tech version of a tactic we learned in middle school: peer pressure. Recent behavioral science research shows that social pressure is far more effective at getting people to vote than talking about a particular candidate or issue. People will vote if you show them that their friends and neighbors are voting, and we now have the data, voter files and messaging tools to do just that. There's an old adage that policy is not made on Election Day, it's made in the time between election days. Politicians are already fielding new polls to determine their legislative priorities for 2017 and 2018, but their pollsters only survey voters, which means that most environmentalists won't be heard until we start voting. Whom you vote for is secret, but how often you vote is a public record. Rolls of active voters are the lifeblood of campaign strategy. Simply by voting, environmentalists can appear on a campaign's radar and become the focus of all polling, messaging and spending. Despite adages that disparage the impact of a single vote, the individual voter is a more potent political force than ever before. With politicians already focusing on the next election, the challenge to the environmental movement is to identify our non-voting environmentalists and mobilize them to do just one thing on one day: vote. | 4,811 | <h4>Environmentalists aren’t voting – change won’t occur until turnout among activists increases.</h4><p><strong>Stinnett 15</strong> <u><strong>(Nathaniel Stinnett (founded the Environmental Voter Project in 2015 after over a decade of experience as a senior advisor, consultant, and trainer for political campaigns and issue-advocacy nonprofits), 2015, “WHY DON'T ENVIRONMENTALISTS VOTE?”, Environmental Voter Project, https://www.environmentalvoter.org/news/why-dont-environmentalists-vote)</p><p></u></strong>The last few weeks have rocked the environmental movement. In the wake of the November elections, environmentalists are deeply concerned about the future of the Paris climate accord, the rollback of federal environmental protections, and even the fate of the U.S. Environmental Protection Agency itself. <u><strong>But one of the environmental movement's biggest problems is the same now as it was on November 7: <mark>Environmentalists aren't voting</mark>. Approximately 20.1 million environmentalists are registered to vote, according to Environmental Voter Project research</u></strong>. But <u><strong>in the 2014 mid-term elections, only 4.2 million of them voted, and <mark>in </mark>the <mark>2012 </mark>presidential election <mark>barely 10 million </mark>of them <mark>voted</mark>. </u></strong>In Massachusetts, 277,250 environmentalists skipped our 2014 gubernatorial election, which was decided by only 40,000 votes. While we don't yet know how many environmentalists voted on November 8 (public voter files won't be updated until February), <u><strong>early data reveal that <mark>America's overall turnout problem has only gotten worse.</mark> </u></strong>Most pundits' election postmortems have dismissed turnout problems, since raw voter turnout increased from 129 million in 2012 to 137 million in 2016. Yet, these numbers ignore a crucially important consideration: Over that same time period, the total number of registered voters skyrocketed from 153 million to 200 million. While raw voter turnout increased by 6 percent since 2012, the overall pool of registered voters increased by 31 percent. Put another way, turnout as a percentage of overall registered voters plummeted from 84 percent to 68 percent. Some of this decrease can be attributed to positive developments, such as record-setting voter registration efforts and fewer restrictions on registration in some states. Nevertheless, the growth in voter rolls can't solely be blamed for the steep slide in turnout rates<u><strong>. Millions of long-registered voters likely stayed home on Election Day, which is particularly bad news for the environmental movement, because we tend to be poor voters. No matter who wins an election</u></strong> - whether they're an environmentalist, a Democrat or a Republican - <u><strong><mark>we can't expect environmental</mark> <mark>leadership when so few voters demand it</mark>.</u></strong> Regardless of party affiliation, <u><strong>environmentalists need to address their turnout problem.</u></strong> We need to start voting for one simple reason: <u><strong><mark>Politicians</mark> want to win elections. To do that, they <mark>focus on issues of importance to voters, </mark>not non-voters. Right now, voters do not prioritize environmental issues. When we polled likely voters this summer, only 4 percent listed climate change and the environment as a top-2 issue</u></strong>, placing it 15 out of the 19 issues in our survey. Still there's an opportunity hidden in these statistics. <u><strong><mark>Although voters don't prioritize environmental issues, non-voters do</mark>. Large majorities of Americans support government action to address climate change and protect the environment. Furthermore, committed environmentalists already go to great lengths to act on their beliefs</u></strong>: They diligently recycle, they bike to work, and they install solar panels on their roofs, all of which require much more time and effort than voting. In short, <u><strong>millions of Americans are already fully persuaded environmentalists</u></strong>; now we just need to change our habits and start voting. Fortunately, changing people's habits is much easier than changing their minds. While Big Data and predictive analytics help us accurately identify these environmental non-voters, we can get them to vote with a high-tech version of a tactic we learned in middle school: peer pressure. Recent behavioral science research shows that social pressure is far more effective at getting people to vote than talking about a particular candidate or issue. People will vote if you show them that their friends and neighbors are voting, and we now have the data, voter files and messaging tools to do just that. There's an old adage that policy is not made on Election Day, it's made in the time between election days. <u><strong>Politicians are already fielding new polls to determine their legislative priorities for 2017 and 2018, but their pollsters only survey voters, which means that <mark>most environmentalists won't be heard until we start voting</mark>. </u></strong>Whom you vote for is secret, but how often you vote is a public record. Rolls of active voters are the lifeblood of campaign strategy. <u><strong>Simply by voting, environmentalists can appear on a campaign's radar and become the focus of all polling</u></strong>, messaging and spending. Despite adages that disparage the impact of a single vote, the individual voter is a more potent political force than ever before. <u><strong>With politicians already focusing on the next election, the challenge to the environmental movement is to identify our non-voting environmentalists and mobilize them to do just one thing on one day: vote.</p></u></strong> | null | Advantage 1- Global Warming | null | 357,850 | 147 | 137,021 | ./documents/hsld20/Lexington/Fo/Lexington-Fortier-Aff-Bronx-Round3.docx | 864,858 | A | New York City Invitational Debate And Speech Tournament | 3 | Flintridge Prep AL | Ratnasabapathy, Tarun | AC Util RR
NC Cap K Elections DA
1AR RR Case DA K
2NR Cap K
2AR RR | hsld20/Lexington/Fo/Lexington-Fortier-Aff-Bronx-Round3.docx | null | 73,321 | BrFo | Lexington BrFo | null | Br..... | Fo..... | null | null | 24,591 | Lexington | Lexington | MA | null | 1,028 | hsld20 | HS LD 2020-21 | 2,020 | ld | hs | 1 |
612,523 | Reforming the Patent Process would lower Drug Prices and incentivize Pharma Innovation by revitalizing the Market. | Stanbrook 13 | Stanbrook 13, Matthew B. "Limiting “evergreening” for a better balance of drug innovation incentives." (2013): 939-939. (MD (University of Toronto) PhD (University of Toronto))//Elmer | At issue in the Indian case was “evergreening,” a now widespread practice by the pharmaceutical industry designed to extend the monopoly on an existing drug by modifying it and seeking new patents Manufacturers, in defence of these practices, predictably tout the advantages of new versions of their products, which often represent more potent isomers or salts of the original drugs, longer-lasting formulations or improved delivery systems that make adherence easier or more convenient. new versions are me too” drugs, and demonstration that the resulting incremental benefits in efficacy and safety are clinically meaningful is often lacking. the original drugs have often been “blockbusters” used for years to improve the health of millions of patients. It seems hard to argue convincingly why such beneficial drugs require an upgrade, often just before their patents expire Rather than the marginal benefits accrued from tinkering with already effective agents, patients worldwide are in desperate need of new classes of pharmaceuticals for the great many health conditions for which treatments are presently inadequate or entirely lacking developing truly innovative drugs is high-risk Therefore, companies must continue to perceive sufficient incentives to continue investing in innovation. Indeed, there is evidence that the prospect of future evergreening has become part of the incentive calculation for innovative drug development perverse to maintain incentives that drive companies to divert drug-development resources away from innovation. Current patent legislation may not be optimal for striking the right balance between encouraging innovation and facilitating profiteering. Governments, including Canada’s, would do well to take inspiration from India’s example and tighten regulations that currently facilitate evergreening. denying future patents for modifications Limits on evergreening would likely reduce the extensive patent litigation that contributes to the high prices of generic drugs in Canada As opportunities to generate revenue from evergreening are eliminated, research-based pharmaceutical companies would be left with no choice but to invest more in innovative drug development to maintain their profits. | evergreening a widespread practice incremental benefits is often lacking Rather than marginal benefits from tinkering patients are in desperate need of classes of pharma developing truly innovative drugs is high-risk companies must perceive sufficient incentives prospect of future evergreening has become calculation perverse to maintain incentives that drive companies to divert drug-development resources away from innovation. denying future patents for modifications would reduce extensive patent litigation that contributes to high prices of generic drugs | At issue in the Indian case was “evergreening,” a now widespread practice by the pharmaceutical industry designed to extend the monopoly on an existing drug by modifying it and seeking new patents.2 Currently, half of all drugs patented in Canada have multiple subsequent patents, extending the lifetime of the original patent by about 8 years.3 Manufacturers, in defence of these practices, predictably tout the advantages of new versions of their products, which often represent more potent isomers or salts of the original drugs, longer-lasting formulations or improved delivery systems that make adherence easier or more convenient. But the new versions are by definition “me too” drugs, and demonstration that the resulting incremental benefits in efficacy and safety are clinically meaningful is often lacking. Moreover, the original drugs have often been “blockbusters” used for years to improve the health of millions of patients. It seems hard to argue convincingly why such beneficial drugs require an upgrade, often just before their patents expire. Rather than the marginal benefits accrued from tinkering with already effective agents, patients worldwide are in desperate need of new classes of pharmaceuticals for the great many health conditions for which treatments are presently inadequate or entirely lacking. But developing truly innovative drugs is undeniably a high-risk venture. It is important and necessary that pharmaceutical companies continue to take these risks, because they are usually the only entities with sufficient resources to do so. Therefore, companies must continue to perceive sufficient incentives to continue investing in innovation. Indeed, there is evidence that the prospect of future evergreening has become part of the incentive calculation for innovative drug development.4 But surely it is perverse to extend unpredictably a period of patent protection that the government intended to be clearly defined and predictable, and to maintain incentives that drive companies to divert their drug-development resources away from innovation. Current patent legislation may not be optimal for striking the right balance between encouraging innovation and facilitating profiteering. Given the broad societal importance of patent legislation, ongoing research to enable active governance of this issue should be a national priority. In the last decade, Canada’s laws have been among the friendliest toward evergreening in the world.5 We should now reflect on whether this is really in our national interest. Governments, including Canada’s, would do well to take inspiration from India’s example and tighten regulations that currently facilitate evergreening. This might involve denying future patents for modifications that currently would receive one. An overall reduction in the duration of all secondary patents on a therapy might also be considered. Globally, a more flexible and individualized approach to the length of drug patents might be a more effective strategy to align corporate incentives with population health needs. Limits on evergreening would likely reduce the extensive patent litigation that contributes to the high prices of generic drugs in Canada.3 Reducing economic pressure on generic drug companies may facilitate current provincial initiatives to lower generic drug prices. As opportunities to generate revenue from evergreening are eliminated, research-based pharmaceutical companies would be left with no choice but to invest more in innovative drug development to maintain their profits. | 3,557 | <h4>Reforming the Patent Process would <u>lower Drug Prices</u> and <u>incentivize Pharma Innovation</u> by revitalizing the Market.</h4><p><strong>Stanbrook 13</strong>, Matthew B. "Limiting “evergreening” for a better balance of drug innovation incentives." (2013): 939-939. (MD (University of Toronto) PhD (University of Toronto)<u>)//Elmer </p><p>At issue in the Indian case was “<mark>evergreening</mark>,” <mark>a </mark>now <mark>widespread practice </mark>by the pharmaceutical industry designed to extend the monopoly on an existing drug by modifying it and seeking new patents</u>.2 Currently, half of all drugs patented in Canada have multiple subsequent patents, extending the lifetime of the original patent by about 8 years.3 <u>Manufacturers, in defence of these practices, predictably tout the advantages of new versions of their products, which often represent more potent isomers or salts of the original drugs, longer-lasting formulations or improved delivery systems that make adherence easier or more convenient.</u> But the <u>new versions are</u> by definition “<u><strong>me too” drugs</strong>, and demonstration that the resulting <strong><mark>incremental benefits</strong></mark> in efficacy and safety are clinically meaningful <strong><mark>is often lacking</strong></mark>.</u> Moreover, <u>the original drugs have often been “blockbusters” used for years to improve the health of millions of patients. It seems hard to argue convincingly why such beneficial drugs require an upgrade, often just before their patents expire</u>. <u><mark>Rather than </mark>the <mark>marginal benefits </mark>accrued <mark>from tinkering </mark>with already effective agents, <mark>patients </mark>worldwide <mark>are in desperate need of </mark>new <mark>classes of pharma</mark>ceuticals for the great many health conditions for which treatments are presently inadequate or entirely lacking</u>. But <u><mark>developing</u> <u>truly innovative drugs is</u> </mark>undeniably a <u><mark>high-risk</u> </mark>venture. It is important and necessary that pharmaceutical companies continue to take these risks, because they are usually the only entities with sufficient resources to do so. <u>Therefore, <mark>companies must </mark>continue to <mark>perceive <strong>sufficient incentives</strong> </mark>to continue investing in innovation. Indeed, there is evidence that the <mark>prospect of future evergreening has become </mark>part of the incentive <mark>calculation </mark>for innovative drug development</u>.4 But surely it is <u><mark>perverse to</u> </mark>extend unpredictably a period of patent protection that the government intended to be clearly defined and predictable, and to <u><mark>maintain incentives</u> <u>that drive companies to divert</u> </mark>their <u><strong><mark>drug-development resources away from innovation</strong>.</u></mark> <u><strong>Current patent legislation may not be optimal</strong> for striking the right balance between encouraging innovation and facilitating profiteering. </u>Given the broad societal importance of patent legislation, ongoing research to enable active governance of this issue should be a national priority. In the last decade, Canada’s laws have been among the friendliest toward evergreening in the world.5 We should now reflect on whether this is really in our national interest. <u>Governments, including Canada’s, would do well to take inspiration from India’s example and tighten regulations that currently facilitate evergreening.</u> This might involve <u><strong><mark>denying future patents for modifications</u></strong> </mark>that currently would receive one. An overall reduction in the duration of all secondary patents on a therapy might also be considered. Globally, a more flexible and individualized approach to the length of drug patents might be a more effective strategy to align corporate incentives with population health needs. <u>Limits on evergreening <mark>would </mark>likely <mark>reduce </mark>the <strong><mark>extensive patent litigation</strong> that contributes to </mark>the <strong><mark>high prices of generic drugs</strong> </mark>in Canada</u>.3 Reducing economic pressure on generic drug companies may facilitate current provincial initiatives to lower generic drug prices. <u>As opportunities to generate revenue from evergreening are eliminated, research-based pharmaceutical companies would be left with no choice but to invest more in innovative drug development to maintain their profits.</p></u> | 1AC | null | Plan | 335,067 | 151 | 10,855 | ./documents/hsld21/Clements/Ko/Clements-Kolluri-Aff-Grapevine%20Classic-Round3.docx | 885,026 | A | Grapevine Classic | 3 | Dulles TY | Andrew Shaw | 1AC - Drug Prices AC V2
1NC - Counter Solvency Advocate Theory - TT ROTB and Aprioris - Kant NC - Determinism NC - case
1AR - all - RVI
2NR - TT ROTB and Aprioris - Kant NC
2AR - RVI - TT ROTB and Aprioris | hsld21/Clements/Ko/Clements-Kolluri-Aff-Grapevine%20Classic-Round3.docx | null | 74,515 | AkKo | Clements AkKo | null | Ak..... | Ko..... | null | null | 24,959 | Clements | Clements | TX | null | 1,029 | hsld21 | HS LD 2021-22 | 2,021 | ld | hs | 1 |
1,078,763 | Protection means to command a cessation of use. The plan isn’t. | Matanich 96 | Johanna Matanich (Spring, 1996). ARTICLE: A Treaty Comes of Age for the Ancient Ones: Implications of the Law of the Sea for the Regulation of Whaling. International Legal Perspectives, 8, 37, lexis | UNCLOS creates the obligation to protect and preserve the marine environment
there is little difference between conservation" and "preservation." In the context of protection, however conservation connotes a conservative use of a resource, but a use nonetheless, while the term "protection" is used to command a cessation of use.
affect | In context of protection conservation connotes a conservative use while protection" is to command a cessation of use | UNCLOS imposes a duty upon states to conserve whales that is stronger than their obligations under the International Whaling Convention. Generally, UNCLOS creates the obligation to protect and preserve the marine environment in article 192. This obligation applies to all living resources. Beyond that Article 65 asks states to "co-operate with a view to the conservation of marine mammals."
The Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties establishes rules for the interpretation of treaties. UNCLOS is to be interpreted "in good faith in accordance with the ordinary meaning to be given to the terms of the treaty in their context and in the light of [their] object and purpose." What then, does the term "conservation" mean? Generally, there is little difference between the use of the terms "conservation" and "preservation." In the context of environmental protection, however, conservation connotes a conservative use of a resource, but a use nonetheless, while the term "protection" is used to command a cessation of use. Indeed, the term "conservation" is used in UNCLOS article 64 to characterize the regulation of active fisheries. Because conservation is associated with use in that article, it is logical to assume the UNCLOS drafters associated the term conservation with "use" in Article 65. The word "protection" was used in an early draft of the article, then deleted, [*60] which provides further support for this conclusion.
Limits and ground---There are infinite ways to affect water or prevent threats to it – they allow hundreds of non-point source pollution affs that regulate things not related to water. It’s a massive topic with no clear negative ground. | 1,679 | <h4>Protection means to command a cessation of use. The plan isn’t.</h4><p>Johanna <strong>Matanich</strong> (Spring, 19<strong>96</strong>). ARTICLE: A Treaty Comes of Age for the Ancient Ones: Implications of the Law of the Sea for the Regulation of Whaling. International Legal Perspectives, 8, 37, lexis</p><p>UNCLOS imposes a duty upon states to conserve whales that is stronger than their obligations under the International Whaling Convention. Generally, <u>UNCLOS creates the obligation to protect and preserve the marine environment</u> in article 192. This obligation applies to all living resources. Beyond that Article 65 asks states to "co-operate with a view to the conservation of marine mammals."</p><p>The Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties establishes rules for the interpretation of treaties. UNCLOS is to be interpreted "in good faith in accordance with the ordinary meaning to be given to the terms of the treaty in their context and in the light of [their] object and purpose." What then, does the term "conservation" mean? Generally, <u>there is little difference between</u> the use of the terms "<u>conservation" and "preservation." <mark>In</mark> the <mark>context of</u></mark> environmental <u><mark>protection</mark>, however</u>, <u><mark>conservation</mark> <mark>connotes</mark> <mark>a conservative use </mark>of a resource, but a use nonetheless, <mark>while</mark> the term "<mark>protection" is </mark>used <mark>to <strong>command a cessation of use</strong></mark>.</u> Indeed, the term "conservation" is used in UNCLOS article 64 to characterize the regulation of active fisheries. Because conservation is associated with use in that article, it is logical to assume the UNCLOS drafters associated the term conservation with "use" in Article 65. The word "protection" was used in an early draft of the article, then deleted, [*60] which provides further support for this conclusion.</p><p>Limits and ground---There are infinite ways to <u>affect</u> water or prevent threats to it – they allow hundreds of non-point source pollution affs that regulate things not related to water. It’s a massive topic with no clear negative ground.</p> | 1NC New Trier r1 | Off | null | 23,338 | 820 | 27,413 | ./documents/hspolicy21/Lexington/HeVe/Lexington-He-Venkatesh-Neg-Trevian-Round1.docx | 749,516 | N | Trevian | 1 | Northside DW | Eugenia Giampetruzzi | 1AC - WOTUS
2NR - CP Incentives DA Business Confidence | hspolicy21/Lexington/HeVe/Lexington-He-Venkatesh-Neg-Trevian-Round1.docx | null | 63,959 | HeVe | Lexington HeVe | null | Je..... | He..... | At..... | Ve..... | 22,031 | Lexington | Lexington | MA | null | 1,020 | hspolicy21 | HS Policy 2021-22 | 2,021 | cx | hs | 2 |
4,378,942 | European support to Ukraine holds steady, but only because of unity—failure greenlights genocide and further aggression. | Rudik 22 | Rudik 22 [Kira; 10-3-22; leader of the Golos party, member of the Ukrainian parliament, and Vice President of the Alliance of Liberals and Democrats for Europe (ALDE). “European unity is essential as Putin prepares to weaponize winter,” https://www.atlanticcouncil.org/blogs/ukrainealert/european-unity-is-essential-as-putin-prepares-to-weaponize-winter/] brett | Putin recently escalated his invasion of Ukraine by officially annexing four partially occupied Ukrainian regions In his address accompanying these annexations Putin made clear that he sees the current war as an existential struggle with the West to shape the future of the entire world
For now, he is losing troops in eastern Ukraine have suffered a string of humiliating defeats in recent weeks and have been forced to retreat in disarray Putin’s response has been to raise the stakes further he has also announced Russia’s first mobilization since World War II
While nuclear saber-rattling has dominated discussions the most likely indication of Moscow’s immediate intentions came in September when Russian forces launched a series of targeted attacks against Ukraine’s civilian infrastructure These missile strikes left much of Ukraine without electricity while also causing flooding in the south of the country.
Putin himself confirmed that these attacks were a taste of things to come Let’s consider this a warning,” he said on September 16 If the situation develops further in this direction, our response will be more serious.”
Ukrainians are well aware of the threat posed by large-scale attacks on the country’s civilian infrastructure and are preparing accordingly With winter fast approaching Ukrainian faces the prospect of entire regions suffering power blackouts and heating failures during periods of intense cold weather consequences could be catastrophic
EU nations are also facing the prospect of an extremely challenging winter the Kremlin recent blasts on Russia’s Nord Stream pipelines appears designed to prevent Europe from receiving Russian gas during the coming winter months to force EU leaders to end their support for Ukraine
the most difficult European winter since World War II energy bills are already driving up the cost of living, with inflation surging to record levels throughout Europe Higher prices could fuel political instability Kremlin agents are working with local allies within the EU to spread the message that everything can be solved by abandoning Ukraine
Ukrainians are paying a far higher price Tens of thousands have already been killed by the invading Russian army in the past seven months and millions are currently living under Russian occupation Millions more have been forced to flee
Ever since Russia’s full-scale invasion of Ukraine there have been calls offering concessions to the Kremlin European leaders should reaffirm their commitment to a Ukrainian victory and demonstrate resolve
The last time Europe faced a threat similar to the challenges posed by Putin’s Russia was during the rise of Nazi Germany in the 1930s Putin is annexing neighboring lands under the guise of reuniting ethnic brethren while threatening the wider world with the prospect of a devastating war Putin openly employs the language of genocide Stopping him will require unprecedented unity within the ranks of the democratic world
As winter draws nearer, Kremlin propagandists will promote the idea that efforts to oppose Russia in Ukraine are futile The economic pain being inflicted on European families is in vain Calls will inevitably mount for a compromise deal that would condemn millions of Ukrainians in currently occupied regions of the country to a grim future under Russian rule
it is more important than ever to remain focused on the bigger picture If Putin’s Ukraine invasion does not end in a decisive defeat, the consequences for Europe will be far graver than today’s energy shortages and economic woes Russian success would be followed by similar military aggression against other nations of the former Soviet Union All European countries feel the political chill as a triumphant Moscow asserted its newfound authority to undermine the EU and fuel political extremism throughout the continent Generations of democratic progress would be in danger
coming months will not be easy
Surrendering to the Kremlin would sacrifice Europe’s future for the dubious benefits of a temporary pause in Russian aggression Europeans must remain united | In his address Putin sees the war as existential struggle with the West to shape the entire world
For now, he is losing troops suffered a string of defeats
Russian forces launched attacks against civilian infrastructure
Putin confirmed things to come
EU nations are facing challenging winter Russia prevent gas to force leaders to end support
Ukrainian victory
will require unprecedented unity
Kremlin propagandists promote a compromise deal that condemn millions to Russian rule
followed by military aggression against other nations and fuel extremism throughout the continent Generations of democratic progress in danger
coming months will not be easy
Europeans must remain united | Russian President Vladimir Putin recently escalated his invasion of Ukraine by officially annexing four partially occupied Ukrainian regions. In his address accompanying these annexations, Putin made clear that he sees the current war as an existential struggle with the collective West to shape the future of the entire world.
For now, he is losing. Russian troops in eastern Ukraine have suffered a string of humiliating defeats in recent weeks and have been forced to retreat in disarray. Putin’s response to these setbacks has been to raise the stakes further. In addition to annexing around 15% of Ukrainian territory, he has also announced Russia’s first mobilization since World War II and indicated that he is prepared to use nuclear weapons if necessary to achieve his war aims in Ukraine.
While the Kremlin’s nuclear saber-rattling has dominated discussions over what to expect next, the most likely indication of Moscow’s immediate intentions came earlier in September when Russian forces launched a series of targeted attacks against Ukraine’s civilian infrastructure. These missile strikes left much of northern and eastern Ukraine termporarily without electricity while also causing flooding in the south of the country.
Putin himself confirmed that these attacks were a taste of things to come if Russia’s fortunes on the battlefield continue to deteriorate. “Just recently the Russian army hit some sensitive targets. Let’s consider this a warning,” he said on September 16 in the wake of Ukraine’s successful Kharkiv counter-offensive. “If the situation develops further in this direction, our response will be more serious.”
Ukrainians are well aware of the threat posed by large-scale attacks on the country’s civilian infrastructure and are preparing accordingly. With the winter season fast approaching, Ukrainian faces the prospect of entire regions suffering power blackouts and heating failures during periods of intense cold weather. The consequences for the civilian population could be catastrophic.
The current situation in the European Union is obviously not as dramatic as Ukraine’s predicament, but EU nations are also facing the prospect of an extremely challenging winter courtesy of the Kremlin. For several months, Russia has been indicating its plans to use energy supplies as a weapon in its confrontation with the West. The recent blasts on Russia’s Nord Stream pipelines are the latest episode in a drama that appears designed to prevent Europe from receiving Russian gas during the coming winter months in order to force EU leaders to end their support for Ukraine.
This is setting the stage for what some observers predict will be the most difficult European winter since World War II. According to World Bank forecasts, energy prices are set to rise further. Mounting energy bills are already driving up the cost of living, with inflation surging to record levels throughout Europe. Higher prices for basic foodstuffs and other essentials will hurt poorer households and could fuel political instability across the continent. Kremlin agents are already working with local allies within the EU to spread the message that everything can be solved by abandoning Ukraine.
While Europeans count the cost of their confrontation with the Kremlin in financial terms, Ukrainians are paying a far higher price. Tens of thousands have already been killed by the invading Russian army in the past seven months and millions are currently living under Russian occupation. Millions more have either lost their homes or been forced to flee. Due to the indiscriminate artillery bombardments favored by Putin’s military, many towns and cities in both occupied and free Ukraine are approaching the winter season with entire residential districts destroyed or uninhabitable.
Ever since Russia’s full-scale invasion of Ukraine began in February 2022, there have been calls from some quarters within the EU to end the war by offering concessions to the Kremlin. Putin’s recent escalatory actions, along with his unhinged anti-Western rhetoric, should now serve to shatter any illusions over the possibility of reaching a negotiated settlement with the current Russian regime. Instead, European leaders should reaffirm their commitment to a Ukrainian victory and demonstrate that their resolve will not be broken by nuclear threats or energy blackmail.
The last time Europe faced a threat similar to the challenges posed by Putin’s Russia was during the rise of Nazi Germany in the 1930s. Like Hitler, Putin is annexing neighboring lands under the guise of reuniting ethnic brethren while threatening the wider world with the prospect of a devastating war. Like Hitler, Putin openly employs the language of genocide and is putting his criminal worldview into action. Stopping him will require unprecedented unity within the ranks of the democratic world.
As winter draws nearer, Kremlin propagandists will promote the idea that efforts to oppose Russia in Ukraine are futile. The economic pain being inflicted on European families is in vain, they will say. Such messaging is likely to resonate with millions of people across Europe who find themselves shivering in partially heated homes and struggling to provide for themselves and their families. Calls will inevitably mount for a compromise deal that would condemn millions of Ukrainians in currently occupied regions of the country to a grim future under Russian rule.
This is why it is more important than ever to remain focused on the bigger picture. If Putin’s Ukraine invasion does not end in a decisive defeat, the consequences for Europe will be far graver than today’s energy shortages and economic woes. Russian success in Ukraine would be followed by similar military aggression against other nations of the former Soviet Union. All European countries would feel the political chill as a triumphant Moscow asserted its newfound authority to undermine the EU and fuel political extremism throughout the continent. Generations of democratic progress would be in danger.
The coming months will not be easy for anyone. Some will be colder or hungrier than usual. Others will face bombs and blackouts. All will be confronted with the same question: what price are you willing to pay to preserve the core European values of freedom, dignity, and democratic rights?
Surrendering to the Kremlin would sacrifice Europe’s future for the dubious benefits of a temporary pause in Russian aggression. Instead, Europeans must remain united in their pursuit of Ukrainian victory. This is the only way to avoid the prospect on many more weaponized winters in the years to come. | 6,644 | <h4><u>European support</u> to Ukraine <u>holds steady</u>, but only because of <u>unity</u>—<u>failure</u> greenlights <u>genocide</u> and <u>further aggression</u>.</h4><p><strong>Rudik 22</strong> [Kira; 10-3-22; leader of the Golos party, member of the Ukrainian parliament, and Vice President of the Alliance of Liberals and Democrats for Europe (ALDE). “European unity is essential as Putin prepares to weaponize winter,” https://www.atlanticcouncil.org/blogs/ukrainealert/european-unity-is-essential-as-putin-prepares-to-weaponize-winter/] brett</p><p>Russian President Vladimir <u><strong>Putin</u></strong> <u>recently escalated his <strong>invasion</strong> of <strong>Ukraine</strong> by officially annexing four partially occupied Ukrainian regions</u>. <u><mark>In his <strong>address</strong></mark> accompanying these annexations</u>, <u><mark>Putin</u></mark> <u><strong>made clear</strong> that he</u> <u><mark>sees the</mark> current <mark>war as</mark> an <strong><mark>existential struggle</strong> with the</u></mark> collective <u><strong><mark>West</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>to shape</mark> the <strong>future</strong> of <mark>the <strong>entire world</u></strong></mark>.</p><p><u><mark>For now,</u></mark> <u><strong><mark>he is losing</u></strong></mark>. Russian <u><mark>troops</mark> in eastern Ukraine have <mark>suffered a string of</mark> <strong>humiliating <mark>defeats</strong></mark> in recent weeks and have been <strong>forced to retreat in disarray</u></strong>. <u>Putin’s response</u> to these setbacks <u>has been to <strong>raise the stakes</strong> further</u>. In addition to annexing around 15% of Ukrainian territory, <u>he has also announced Russia’s <strong>first mobilization</strong> since <strong>World War II</u></strong> and indicated that he is prepared to use nuclear weapons if necessary to achieve his war aims in Ukraine.</p><p><u>While</u> the Kremlin’s <u>nuclear saber-rattling has dominated discussions</u> over what to expect next, <u>the <strong>most likely indication</strong> of Moscow’s <strong>immediate intentions</strong> came</u> earlier <u>in <strong>September</u></strong> <u>when <mark>Russian forces launched</mark> a series of <strong>targeted <mark>attacks</strong> against</mark> Ukraine’s <strong><mark>civilian infrastructure</u></strong></mark>. <u>These missile strikes left much of</u> northern and eastern <u>Ukraine</u> termporarily <u>without <strong>electricity</u></strong> <u>while also causing <strong>flooding in the south of the country.</p><p></strong><mark>Putin</mark> himself <mark>confirmed</mark> that these attacks were a taste of <strong><mark>things to come</u></strong></mark> if Russia’s fortunes on the battlefield continue to deteriorate. “Just recently the Russian army hit some sensitive targets. <u><strong>Let’s consider this a warning,”</u></strong> <u>he said on September 16</u> in the wake of Ukraine’s successful Kharkiv counter-offensive. “<u><strong>If the situation develops further in this direction, our response will be more serious.”</p><p></strong>Ukrainians are well aware of the threat posed by large-scale attacks on the country’s civilian infrastructure and are preparing accordingly</u>. <u>With</u> the <u><strong>winter</u></strong> season <u><strong>fast approaching</u></strong>, <u>Ukrainian faces the prospect of entire regions suffering <strong>power blackouts</strong> and <strong>heating failures</strong> during periods of <strong>intense cold weather</u></strong>. The <u>consequences</u> for the civilian population <u>could be catastrophic</u>.</p><p>The current situation in the European Union is obviously not as dramatic as Ukraine’s predicament, but <u><strong><mark>EU nations</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>are</mark> also <mark>facing</mark> the prospect of an <strong>extremely <mark>challenging winter</u></strong></mark> courtesy of <u>the Kremlin</u>. For several months, Russia has been indicating its plans to use energy supplies as a weapon in its confrontation with the West. The <u>recent blasts on <strong><mark>Russia</strong></mark>’s <strong>Nord Stream</strong> pipelines</u> are the latest episode in a drama that <u>appears designed to <mark>prevent</mark> Europe from receiving <strong>Russian <mark>gas</strong></mark> during the coming winter months</u> in order <u><mark>to force</mark> <strong>EU <mark>leaders</strong> to end</mark> their <mark>support</mark> for <strong>Ukraine</u></strong>.</p><p>This is setting the stage for what some observers predict will be <u>the <strong>most difficult European winter</strong> since World War II</u>. According to World Bank forecasts, energy prices are set to rise further. Mounting <u>energy bills are already driving up the cost of living, with inflation surging to record levels throughout Europe</u>. <u><strong>Higher prices</u></strong> for basic foodstuffs and other essentials will hurt poorer households and <u>could fuel political instability</u> across the continent. <u><strong>Kremlin agents</u></strong> <u>are</u> already <u>working with <strong>local allies within the EU</strong> to spread the message that everything can be solved by <strong>abandoning Ukraine</u></strong>.</p><p>While Europeans count the cost of their confrontation with the Kremlin in financial terms, <u><strong>Ukrainians</strong> are paying a far higher price</u>. <u>Tens of thousands have already been killed by the invading Russian army in the past seven months and millions are currently living under Russian occupation</u>. <u><strong>Millions more</u></strong> <u>have</u> either lost their homes or <u><strong>been forced to flee</u></strong>. Due to the indiscriminate artillery bombardments favored by Putin’s military, many towns and cities in both occupied and free Ukraine are approaching the winter season with entire residential districts destroyed or uninhabitable.</p><p><u>Ever since Russia’s full-scale invasion of Ukraine</u> began in February 2022, <u>there have been calls</u> from some quarters within the EU to end the war by <u><strong>offering concessions to the Kremlin</u></strong>. Putin’s recent escalatory actions, along with his unhinged anti-Western rhetoric, should now serve to shatter any illusions over the possibility of reaching a negotiated settlement with the current Russian regime. Instead, <u><strong>European leaders</u></strong> <u>should reaffirm their <strong>commit</strong>ment to a <strong><mark>Ukrainian victory</strong></mark> and demonstrate</u> that their <u><strong>resolve</u></strong> will not be broken by nuclear threats or energy blackmail.</p><p><u>The last time Europe faced a <strong>threat similar</strong> to the challenges posed by Putin’s Russia was during the rise of Nazi Germany in the <strong>1930s</u></strong>. Like Hitler, <u>Putin is <strong>annexing neighboring lands</strong> under the guise of reuniting <strong>ethnic brethren</strong> while threatening the wider world with the prospect of a <strong>devastating war</u></strong>. Like Hitler, <u><strong>Putin openly employs the language of genocide</u></strong> and is putting his criminal worldview into action. <u>Stopping him</u> <u><mark>will require</mark> <strong><mark>unprecedented unity</strong></mark> within the ranks of the <strong>democratic world</u></strong>.</p><p><u>As winter draws nearer, <strong><mark>Kremlin propagandists</strong></mark> will <mark>promote</mark> the idea that <strong>efforts to oppose Russia</strong> in Ukraine are <strong>futile</u></strong>. <u>The economic pain being inflicted on European families is in vain</u>, they will say. Such messaging is likely to resonate with millions of people across Europe who find themselves shivering in partially heated homes and struggling to provide for themselves and their families. <u>Calls will inevitably mount for <mark>a compromise deal</mark> <mark>that</mark> would <strong><mark>condemn millions</strong></mark> of Ukrainians in <strong>currently occupied regions</strong> of the country <mark>to</mark> a <strong>grim future under <mark>Russian rule</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>This is why <u>it is more important than ever to remain focused on the <strong>bigger picture</u></strong>. <u>If Putin’s Ukraine invasion does not end in a decisive defeat, the consequences for Europe will be <strong>far graver</strong> than today’s <strong>energy shortages</strong> and <strong>economic woes</u></strong>. <u><strong>Russian success</u></strong> in Ukraine <u>would be <mark>followed by</mark> <strong>similar <mark>military aggression</strong> against other nations</mark> of the former Soviet Union</u>. <u><strong>All European countries</u></strong> would <u>feel the political chill as a triumphant Moscow asserted its newfound authority to <strong>undermine the EU</strong> <mark>and <strong>fuel</mark> political <mark>extremism</strong> throughout the continent</u></mark>. <u><strong><mark>Generations of democratic progress</mark> would be <mark>in danger</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>The <u><strong><mark>coming months will not be easy</u></strong></mark> for anyone. Some will be colder or hungrier than usual. Others will face bombs and blackouts. All will be confronted with the same question: what price are you willing to pay to preserve the core European values of freedom, dignity, and democratic rights?</p><p><u><strong>Surrendering to the Kremlin</u></strong> <u>would sacrifice Europe’s future for the dubious benefits of a temporary <strong>pause</strong> in Russian aggression</u>. Instead, <u><strong><mark>Europeans must remain united</u></strong></mark> in their pursuit of Ukrainian victory. This is the only way to avoid the prospect on many more weaponized winters in the years to come.</p> | null | 1AC—vs Kaps | 1AC—ADV—Unity | 1,663,636 | 265 | 151,753 | ./documents/hsld22/MountainHouse/ElSu/MountainHouse-ElSu-Aff-CPS-LD-Invitational-Quarters.docx | 957,719 | A | CPS LD Invitational | Quarters | Basis Independent Silicon Valley SK | Shania Hunt, Jonas Le Barillec, Alyssa Sawyer | 1AC - Schengenlargement v3
1NC - T-longley, vaccine pic, icj cp
1AR - all
2NR - t
2AR - case t | hsld22/MountainHouse/ElSu/MountainHouse-ElSu-Aff-CPS-LD-Invitational-Quarters.docx | 2023-01-02 23:49:31 | 79,525 | ElSu | Mountain House ElSu | See 0 - Contact Info in cites for disclosure, etc. | El..... | Su..... | null | null | 26,667 | MountainHouse | Mountain House | CA | null | 2,003 | hsld22 | HS LD 2022-23 | 2,022 | ld | hs | 1 |
3,524,167 | Vote neg for predictable limits---allowing the affirmative to pick any grounds for the debate makes negative engagement impossible, by skirting a predictable starting point and making our preparation and research useless. Abdicating debates about the resolution makes all limits impossible---topic relevance isn’t enough to ensure effective clash | Steinberg and Freeley 13 | Steinberg and Freeley 13, David, Lecturer in Communication studies and rhetoric, advisor to Miami Urban Debate League, Director of Debate at U Miami, former President of CEDA, and Austin, attorney who focuses on criminal, personal injury and civil rights law, JD, Suffolk University, Argumentation and Debate: Critical Thinking for Reasoned Decision Making, 121-4 | Debate is a means of settling differences, so there must be a controversy before there can be a debate. If everyone is in agreement on a value there is no need or opportunity for debate you can think of many concerns to be addressed by a conversation about the topic area of illegal immigration Participation in this “debate” is likely to be emotional and intense. However, it is not likely to be productive or useful without focus on a particular question and identification of a line demarcating sides in the controversy This enables focus on substantive and objectively identifiable issues facilitating comparison of competing argumentation leading to effective decisions. Vague understanding results in unfocused deliberation and poor decisions general tension without opportunity for resolution, and emotional distress, as evidenced by the failure of the U.S. Congress to make substantial progress on the immigration debate Of course, arguments may be presented without disagreement. it is important to identify the beginning positions of competing advocates to begin negotiation and movement toward a center It is frustrating and usually unproductive to attempt to make a decision when deciders are unclear as to what the decision is about. it is essential that the proposition be explicitly expressed the proposition provides essential guidance for the preparation of the debaters prior to the debate, the case building and discourse presented during the debate, and the decision to be made by the judge Someone disturbed by socially disenfranchised youths might observe, “Public schools are doing a terrible job! That concerned citizen, facing a complex range of issues, might arrive at an unhelpful decision, such as "We ought to do something about this” or, worse, “It’s too complicated a problem to deal with." Groups could join together to express their frustrations but without a focus for their discussions they could easily agree about the sorry state of education without finding points of clarity or potential solutions. A gripe session would follow. But if a precise question is posed—such as “What can be done to improve public education?”—then a more profitable area of discussion is opened up by placing a focus on the search for a concrete solution debate propositions in any debate, at some point, effective and meaningful discussion relies on identification of a clearly stated or understood proposition Although we now have a general subject It is still too broad This is not to say that debates should completely avoid creative interpretation of the controversy or that good debates cannot occur over competing interpretations of the controversy; in fact, these sorts of debates may be very engaging. The point is that debate is best facilitated by the guidance provided by focus on a particular point of difference | Debate is a means of settling differences, so there must be a controversy before there can be a debate “debate” is not productive without a particular question and a line demarcating sides This enables comparison of competing argumentation leading to effective decisions Vague understanding results in unfocused deliberation the proposition provides essential guidance for preparation the discourse presented and the decision to be made but without a focus for discussions, they could agree without finding points of clarity or potential solutions a general subject is still too broad debate is best facilitated by a particular point of difference | Debate is a means of settling differences, so there must be a controversy, a difference of opinion or a conflict of interest before there can be a debate. If everyone is in agreement on a feet or value or policy, there is no need or opportunity for debate; the matter can be settled by unanimous consent. Thus, for example, it would be pointless to attempt to debate "Resolved: That two plus two equals four,” because there is simply no controversy about this statement. Controversy is an essential prerequisite of debate. Where there is no clash of ideas, proposals, interests, or expressed positions of issues, there is no debate. Controversy invites decisive choice between competing positions. Debate cannot produce effective decisions without clear identification of a question or questions to be answered. For example, general argument may occur about the broad topic of illegal immigration. How many illegal immigrants live in the United States? What is the impact of illegal immigration and immigrants on our economy? What is their impact on our communities? Do they commit crimes? Do they take jobs from American workers? Do they pay taxes? Do they require social services? Is it a problem that some do not speak English? Is it the responsibility of employers to discourage illegal immigration by not hiring undocumented workers? Should they have the opportunity to gain citizenship? Does illegal immigration pose a security threat to our country? Do illegal immigrants do work that American workers are unwilling to do? Are their rights as workers and as human beings at risk due to their status? Are they abused by employers, law enforcement, housing, and businesses? How are their families impacted by their status? What is the moral and philosophical obligation of a nation state to maintain its borders? Should we build a wall on the Mexican border, establish a national identification card, or enforce existing laws against employers? Should we invite immigrants to become U.S. citizens? Surely you can think of many more concerns to be addressed by a conversation about the topic area of illegal immigration. Participation in this “debate” is likely to be emotional and intense. However, it is not likely to be productive or useful without focus on a particular question and identification of a line demarcating sides in the controversy. To be discussed and resolved effectively, controversies are best understood when seated clearly such that all parties to the debate share an understanding about the objective of the debate. This enables focus on substantive and objectively identifiable issues facilitating comparison of competing argumentation leading to effective decisions. Vague understanding results in unfocused deliberation and poor decisions, general feelings of tension without opportunity for resolution, frustration, and emotional distress, as evidenced by the failure of the U.S. Congress to make substantial progress on the immigration debate. Of course, arguments may be presented without disagreement. For example, claims are presented and supported within speeches, editorials, and advertisements even without opposing or refutational response. Argumentation occurs in a range of settings from informal to formal, and may not call upon an audience or judge to make a forced choice among competing claims. Informal discourse occurs as conversation or panel discussion without demanding a decision about a dichotomous or yes/no question. However, by definition, debate requires "reasoned judgment on a proposition. The proposition is a statement about which competing advocates will offer alternative (pro or con) argumentation calling upon their audience or adjudicator to decide. The proposition provides focus for the discourse and guides the decision process. Even when a decision will be made through a process of compromise, it is important to identify the beginning positions of competing advocates to begin negotiation and movement toward a center, or consensus position. It is frustrating and usually unproductive to attempt to make a decision when deciders are unclear as to what the decision is about. The proposition may be implicit in some applied debates (“Vote for me!”); however, when a vote or consequential decision is called for (as in the courtroom or in applied parliamentary debate) it is essential that the proposition be explicitly expressed (“the defendant is guilty!”). In academic debate, the proposition provides essential guidance for the preparation of the debaters prior to the debate, the case building and discourse presented during the debate, and the decision to be made by the debate judge after the debate. Someone disturbed by the problem of a growing underclass of poorly educated, socially disenfranchised youths might observe, “Public schools are doing a terrible job! They' are overcrowded, and many teachers are poorly qualified in their subject areas. Even the best teachers can do little more than struggle to maintain order in their classrooms." That same concerned citizen, facing a complex range of issues, might arrive at an unhelpful decision, such as "We ought to do something about this” or, worse, “It’s too complicated a problem to deal with." Groups of concerned citizens worried about the state of public education could join together to express their frustrations, anger, disillusionment, and emotions regarding the schools, but without a focus for their discussions, they could easily agree about the sorry state of education without finding points of clarity or potential solutions. A gripe session would follow. But if a precise question is posed—such as “What can be done to improve public education?”—then a more profitable area of discussion is opened up simply by placing a focus on the search for a concrete solution step. One or more judgments can be phrased in the form of debate propositions, motions for parliamentary debate, or bills for legislative assemblies, The statements "Resolved: That the federal government should implement a program of charter schools in at-risk communities” and “Resolved; That the state of Florida should adopt a school voucher program" more clearly identify specific ways of dealing with educational problems in a manageable form, suitable for debate. They provide specific policies to be investigated and aid discussants in identifying points of difference. This focus contributes to better and more informed decision making with the potential for better results. In academic debate, it provides better depth of argumentation and enhanced opportunity for reaping the educational benefits of participation. In the next section, we will consider the challenge of framing the proposition for debate, and its role in the debate. To have a productive debate, which facilitates effective decision making by directing and placing limits on the decision to be made, the basis for argument should be clearly defined. If we merely talk about a topic, such as ‘"homelessness,” or “abortion,” Or “crime,” or “global warming,” we are likely to have an interesting discussion but not to establish a profitable basis for argument. For example, the statement “Resolved: That the pen is mightier than the sword” is debatable, yet by itself fails to provide much basis for dear argumentation. If we take this statement to mean Iliad the written word is more effective than physical force for some purposes, we can identify a problem area: the comparative effectiveness of writing or physical force for a specific purpose, perhaps promoting positive social change. (Note that “loose” propositions, such as the example above, may be defined by their advocates in such a way as to facilitate a clear contrast of competing sides; through definitions and debate they “become” clearly understood statements even though they may not begin as such. There are formats for debate that often begin with this sort of proposition. However, in any debate, at some point, effective and meaningful discussion relies on identification of a clearly stated or understood proposition.) Back to the example of the written word versus physical force. Although we now have a general subject, we have not yet stated a problem. It is still too broad, too loosely worded to promote well-organized argument. What sort of writing are we concerned with—poems, novels, government documents, website development, advertising, cyber-warfare, disinformation, or what? What does it mean to be “mightier" in this context? What kind of physical force is being compared—fists, dueling swords, bazookas, nuclear weapons, or what? A more specific question might be, “Would a mutual defense treaty or a visit by our fleet be more effective in assuring Laurania of our support in a certain crisis?” The basis for argument could be phrased in a debate proposition such as “Resolved: That the United States should enter into a mutual defense treaty with Laurania.” Negative advocates might oppose this proposition by arguing that fleet maneuvers would be a better solution. This is not to say that debates should completely avoid creative interpretation of the controversy by advocates, or that good debates cannot occur over competing interpretations of the controversy; in fact, these sorts of debates may be very engaging. The point is that debate is best facilitated by the guidance provided by focus on a particular point of difference, which will be outlined in the following discussion. | 9,467 | <h4>Vote neg for <u>predictable limits</u>---allowing the affirmative to pick <u>any</u><strong> grounds for the debate makes negative engagement impossible, by skirting a predictable starting point and making our preparation and research useless. Abdicating debates about the resolution makes all limits impossible---topic relevance isn’t enough to ensure effective clash</h4><p>Steinberg and Freeley 13</strong>, David, Lecturer in Communication studies and rhetoric, advisor to Miami Urban Debate League, Director of Debate at U Miami, former President of CEDA, and Austin, attorney who focuses on criminal, personal injury and civil rights law, JD, Suffolk University, Argumentation and Debate:<strong> </strong>Critical Thinking for Reasoned Decision Making, 121-4 </p><p><u><mark>Debate is a means of <strong>settling differences</strong>,</u> <u>so there must be a controversy</u></mark>, a difference of opinion or a conflict of interest <u><strong><mark>before there can be a debate</strong></mark>. If everyone is in agreement on a</u> feet or <u><strong>value</u></strong> or policy, <u>there is no <strong>need or opportunity</strong> for debate</u>; the matter can be settled by unanimous consent. Thus, for example, it would be pointless to attempt to debate "Resolved: That two plus two equals four,” because there is simply no controversy about this statement. Controversy is an essential prerequisite of debate. Where there is no clash of ideas, proposals, interests, or expressed positions of issues, there is no debate. Controversy invites decisive choice between competing positions. Debate cannot produce effective decisions without clear identification of a question or questions to be answered. For example, general argument may occur about the broad topic of illegal immigration. How many illegal immigrants live in the United States? What is the impact of illegal immigration and immigrants on our economy? What is their impact on our communities? Do they commit crimes? Do they take jobs from American workers? Do they pay taxes? Do they require social services? Is it a problem that some do not speak English? Is it the responsibility of employers to discourage illegal immigration by not hiring undocumented workers? Should they have the opportunity to gain citizenship? Does illegal immigration pose a security threat to our country? Do illegal immigrants do work that American workers are unwilling to do? Are their rights as workers and as human beings at risk due to their status? Are they abused by employers, law enforcement, housing, and businesses? How are their families impacted by their status? What is the moral and philosophical obligation of a nation state to maintain its borders? Should we build a wall on the Mexican border, establish a national identification card, or enforce existing laws against employers? Should we invite immigrants to become U.S. citizens? Surely <u>you can think of many</u> more <u>concerns</u> <u>to be addressed by a conversation about the topic area of illegal immigration</u>. <u>Participation in this <mark>“debate”</mark> is likely to be emotional and intense. However, it <mark>is not </mark>likely to be <mark>productive</mark> or useful <mark>without</mark> focus on <mark>a particular question and</mark> <strong>identification of <mark>a line demarcating sides</strong></mark> in the controversy</u>. To be discussed and resolved effectively, controversies are best understood when seated clearly such that all parties to the debate share an understanding about the objective of the debate. <u><mark>This enables</mark> focus on substantive and objectively identifiable issues facilitating <mark>comparison of <strong>competing argumentation</u></strong> <u><strong>leading to effective decisions</mark>.</u></strong> <u><mark>Vague understanding results in <strong>unfocused deliberation</strong></mark> and <strong>poor decisions</u></strong>, <u>general</u> feelings of <u>tension without opportunity for resolution, </u>frustration, <u>and emotional distress, as evidenced by the failure of the U.S. Congress to make substantial progress on the immigration debate</u>. <u>Of course, arguments may be presented without disagreement.</u> For example, claims are presented and supported within speeches, editorials, and advertisements even without opposing or refutational response. Argumentation occurs in a range of settings from informal to formal, and may not call upon an audience or judge to make a forced choice among competing claims. Informal discourse occurs as conversation or panel discussion without demanding a decision about a dichotomous or yes/no question. However, by definition, debate requires "reasoned judgment on a proposition. The proposition is a statement about which competing advocates will offer alternative (pro or con) argumentation calling upon their audience or adjudicator to decide. The proposition provides focus for the discourse and guides the decision process. Even when a decision will be made through a process of compromise, <u>it is important to identify the beginning positions of competing advocates to begin negotiation and movement toward a center</u>, or consensus position. <u>It is frustrating and usually unproductive to attempt to make a decision when deciders are unclear as to what the decision is about. </u>The proposition may be implicit in some applied debates (“Vote for me!”); however, when a vote or consequential decision is called for (as in the courtroom or in applied parliamentary debate) <u>it is essential that the proposition be explicitly expressed</u> (“the defendant is guilty!”). In academic debate, <u><mark>the proposition provides <strong>essential guidance</mark> <mark>for</mark> the <mark>preparation</strong></mark> of the debaters prior to the debate, <mark>the </mark>case building and <mark>discourse presented</u></mark> <u>during the debate, <mark>and the <strong>decision to be made</mark> by the</u></strong> debate <u><strong>judge</u></strong> after the debate. <u>Someone disturbed by </u>the problem of a growing underclass of poorly educated, <u>socially disenfranchised youths might observe, “Public schools are doing a terrible job!</u> They' are overcrowded, and many teachers are poorly qualified in their subject areas. Even the best teachers can do little more than struggle to maintain order in their classrooms." <u>That</u> same <u>concerned citizen, facing a complex range of issues, might arrive at an unhelpful decision, such as "We ought to do something about this”</u> <u>or, worse, “It’s too complicated a problem to deal with."</u> <u>Groups</u> of concerned citizens worried about the state of public education <u>could join together to <strong>express their frustrations</u></strong>, anger, disillusionment, and emotions regarding the schools, <u><mark>but without a <strong>focus for</mark> their <mark>discussions</u></strong>, <u>they could</mark> <strong>easily <mark>agree</u></strong></mark> <u>about the sorry state of education <strong><mark>without finding points of clarity or potential solutions</strong></mark>. A gripe session would follow. But if a precise question</u> <u>is posed—such as “What can be done to improve public education?”—then a more profitable area of discussion is opened up</u> simply <u>by placing a focus on the search for a concrete solution</u> step. One or more judgments can be phrased in the form of <u>debate propositions</u>, motions for parliamentary debate, or bills for legislative assemblies, The statements "Resolved: That the federal government should implement a program of charter schools in at-risk communities” and “Resolved; That the state of Florida should adopt a school voucher program" more clearly identify specific ways of dealing with educational problems in a manageable form, suitable for debate. They provide specific policies to be investigated and aid discussants in identifying points of difference. This focus contributes to better and more informed decision making with the potential for better results. In academic debate, it provides better depth of argumentation and enhanced opportunity for reaping the educational benefits of participation. In the next section, we will consider the challenge of framing the proposition for debate, and its role in the debate. To have a productive debate, which facilitates effective decision making by directing and placing limits on the decision to be made, the basis for argument should be clearly defined. If we merely talk about a topic, such as ‘"homelessness,” or “abortion,” Or “crime,” or “global warming,” we are likely to have an interesting discussion but not to establish a profitable basis for argument. For example, the statement “Resolved: That the pen is mightier than the sword” is debatable, yet by itself fails to provide much basis for dear argumentation. If we take this statement to mean Iliad the written word is more effective than physical force for some purposes, we can identify a problem area: the comparative effectiveness of writing or physical force for a specific purpose, perhaps promoting positive social change. (Note that “loose” propositions, such as the example above, may be defined by their advocates in such a way as to facilitate a clear contrast of competing sides; through definitions and debate they “become” clearly understood statements even though they may not begin as such. There are formats for debate that often begin with this sort of proposition. However, <u>in any debate, at some point, effective and meaningful discussion relies on identification of a clearly stated or understood proposition</u>.) Back to the example of the written word versus physical force. <u>Although we now have <mark>a general subject</u></mark>, we have not yet stated a problem. <u><strong>It <mark>is still too broad</u></strong></mark>, too loosely worded to promote well-organized argument. What sort of writing are we concerned with—poems, novels, government documents, website development, advertising, cyber-warfare, disinformation, or what? What does it mean to be “mightier" in this context? What kind of physical force is being compared—fists, dueling swords, bazookas, nuclear weapons, or what? A more specific question might be, “Would a mutual defense treaty or a visit by our fleet be more effective in assuring Laurania of our support in a certain crisis?” The basis for argument could be phrased in a debate proposition such as “Resolved: That the United States should enter into a mutual defense treaty with Laurania.” Negative advocates might oppose this proposition by arguing that fleet maneuvers would be a better solution. <u>This is not to say that debates should completely <strong>avoid creative interpretation</u></strong> <u>of the controversy</u> by advocates, <u>or that good debates cannot occur over competing interpretations of the controversy; in fact, these sorts of debates may be very engaging. The point is that <mark>debate is best facilitated by</mark> the <strong>guidance provided by focus on <mark>a particular point of difference</u></strong></mark>, which will be outlined in the following discussion.</p> | 1NC | null | 1 | 51,689 | 1,023 | 116,612 | ./documents/ndtceda17/Northwestern/ByBa/Northwestern-Byrne-Balachundhar-Neg-Jesuit-Round6.docx | 599,767 | N | Jesuit | 6 | Cornell Knight-Rooney | DeLong | 1ac black utopianism
2nr T | ndtceda17/Northwestern/ByBa/Northwestern-Byrne-Balachundhar-Neg-Jesuit-Round6.docx | null | 51,031 | ByBa | Northwestern ByBa | null | AJ..... | By..... | Ni..... | Ba..... | 19,135 | Northwestern | Northwestern | null | null | 1,007 | ndtceda17 | NDT/CEDA 2017-18 | 2,017 | cx | college | 2 |
3,030,449 | Capitalism transforms individuals into ‘Nobodys’ that creates the conditions for state violence. Our critique does not deny the importance of identity, rather only an understanding of class as the mediating condition of oppression can make movements effective. | Hill 2016 | Marc L. Hill, 2016. Distinguished Professor of African American Studies at Morehouse College. Nobody, Casualties of America’s War on the Vulnerable, from Ferguson to Flint and Beyond. Atria Books. 17-20. | To be Nobody is to be abandoned by the State we have witnessed a radical transformation in the role and function of government in America An obsession with free-market logic and culture has led the political class to craft policies that promote private interests over the public good As a result, our schools justice system military police departments public policy, and virtually every other entity have been relocated to the private sector the private sector has kept its natural commitment to maximizing profits rather than investing in people This arrangement has left the nation’s vulnerable wedged between negligent government and corporate greed, trapped in a historically unprecedented state of precarity
To be Nobody is to be considered disposable These conditions reflect a prevailing belief that the vulnerable are unworthy of investment, protection, or even the most fundamental provisions of the social contract As a result, they can be erased, abandoned, and even left to die
While Nobodyness is strongly tethered to race, it cannot be divorced from other forms of social injustice We cannot make sense of Sandra Bland’s tragic death without recognizing the impact of gender and poverty in shaping the current carceral state
Despite the centrality of race within American life, Nobodyness cannot be understood without an equally thorough analysis of class Unlike other forms of difference, class creates the material conditions and relations through which racism, sexism, and other forms of oppression are produced, sustained, and lived. This does not mean that all forms of injustice are due to class antagonism Rather, it means that we cannot begin to address the various forms of oppression experienced by America’s vulnerable without radically changing a system that defends class at all costs
in Ferguson, Baltimore, New York City, Atlanta, Hempstead, Flint, and Sanford Underneath each case is a more fundamental set of economic conditions, political arrangements, and power relations that transforms everyday citizens into casualties of an increasingly intense war on the vulnerable | To be Nobody is to be abandoned by the State obsession with free-market logic led to policies that promote private interests over the public good our schools justice system military police public policy have been relocated to the private sector This left the vulnerable wedged between negligent government and corporate greed
conditions reflect a belief that the vulnerable are unworthy they can be erased and left to die
Despite the centrality of race Nobodyness cannot be understood without class class creates the material conditions and relations through which racism, sexism, and other forms of oppression are produced, sustained, and lived This does not mean that all forms of injustice are due to class Rather we cannot address oppression without radically changing a system that defends class at all costs
in Ferguson, Baltimore Flint, and Sanford Underneath each is a set of economic conditions | To be Nobody is to be abandoned by the State. For decades now, we have witnessed a radical transformation in the role and function of government in America. An obsession with free-market logic and culture has led the political class to craft policies that promote private interests over the public good. As a result, our schools, our criminal justice system, our military, our police departments, our public policy, and virtually every other entity engineered to protect life and enhance prosperity have been at least partially relocated to the private sector. At the same time, the private sector has kept its natural commitment to maximizing profits rather than investing in people. This arrangement has left the nation’s vulnerable wedged between the Scylla of negligent government and the Charybdis of corporate greed, trapped in a historically unprecedented state of precarity.
To be Nobody is to be considered disposable. In New Orleans, we saw the natural disaster of Hurricane Katrina followed by a grossly unnatural government response, one that killed thousands of vulnerable citizens and consigned many more to refugee status. In Flint, Michigan, we are witnessing this young century’s most profound illustration of civic evil, an entire city collectively punished with lead-poisoned water for the crime of being poor, Black, and politically disempowered. Every day, the nation’s homeless, mentally ill, drug addicted, and poor are pushed out of institutions of support and relocated to jails and prisons. These conditions reflect a prevailing belief that the vulnerable are unworthy of investment, protection, or even the most fundamental provisions of the social contract. As a result, they can be erased, abandoned, and even left to die.
Without question, Nobodyness is largely indebted to race, as White supremacy is foundational to the American democratic experiment. The belief that White lives are worth more than others – what Princeton University scholar Eddie Glaude calls the “value gap” – continues to color every aspect of our public and private lives.1 This belief likewise compromises the lives of vulnerable White citizens, many of who support political movements and policies that close ranks around Whiteness rather than ones that enhance their own social and economic interests.
While Nobodyness is strongly tethered to race, it cannot be divorced from other forms of social injustice. Instead, it must be understood through the lens of “intersectionality,” the ways that multiple forms of oppression operate simultaneously against the vulnerable.2 It would be impossible to example the 2014 killing of Mya Hall by National Security Agency police without understanding how sexism and transphobia conspire with structural racism to endanger Black trans bodies. We cannot make sense of Sandra Bland’s tragic death without recognizing the impact of gender and poverty in shaping the current carceral state. To understand the complexity of oppression, we must avoid simple solutions and singular answers.
Despite the centrality of race within American life, Nobodyness cannot be understood without an equally thorough analysis of class. Unlike other forms of difference, class creates the material conditions and relations through which racism, sexism, and other forms of oppression are produced, sustained, and lived. This does not mean that all forms of injustice are due to class antagonism, nor does it mean that all forms of domination can be automatically fixed through universal class struggle. Rather, it means that we cannot begin to address the various forms of oppression experienced by America’s vulnerable without radically changing a system that defends class at all costs.
This book is my attempt to tell these stories of those marked as Nobody. Based on extensive research, as well as my time on the ground – in Ferguson, Baltimore, New York City, Atlanta, Hempstead, Flint, and Sanford – I want to show how the high-profile and controversial cases of State violence that we’ve witnessed over the past few years are but a symptom of a deeper American problem. Underneath each case is a more fundamental set of economic conditions, political arrangements, and power relations that transforms everyday citizens into casualties of an increasingly intense war on the vulnerable. It is my hope that this book offers an analysis that spotlights the humanity of these “Nobodies” and inspires principled action. | 4,445 | <h4>Capitalism transforms individuals into ‘Nobodys’ that creates the conditions for state violence. Our critique does not deny the importance of identity, rather only an understanding of class as the <u>mediating condition</u> of oppression can make movements effective.</h4><p>Marc L. <strong>Hill</strong>, <strong>2016</strong>. Distinguished Professor of African American Studies at Morehouse College. Nobody, Casualties of America’s War on the Vulnerable, from Ferguson to Flint and Beyond. Atria Books. 17-20.</p><p><u><mark>To be Nobody is to be abandoned by the State</u></mark>. For decades now, <u>we have witnessed a radical transformation in the role and function of government in America</u>. <u>An <strong><mark>obsession with free-market logic</strong></mark> and culture has <mark>led</mark> the political class <mark>to</mark> craft <mark>policies that promote private interests over the public good</u></mark>. <u>As a result, <mark>our schools</u></mark>, our criminal <u><mark>justice system</u></mark>, our <u><mark>military</u></mark>, our <u><mark>police</mark> departments</u>, our <u><mark>public policy</mark>, and virtually every other entity</u> engineered to protect life and enhance prosperity <u><mark>have been</u></mark> at least partially <u><mark>relocated to the private sector</u></mark>. At the same time, <u>the private sector has kept its natural commitment to maximizing profits rather than investing in people</u>. <u><mark>This</mark> arrangement has <mark>left the</mark> nation’s <mark>vulnerable <strong>wedged between</u></strong></mark> the Scylla of <u><strong><mark>negligent government</strong> and</u></mark> the Charybdis of <u><strong><mark>corporate greed</strong></mark>, trapped in a historically unprecedented state of precarity</u>.</p><p><u>To be Nobody is to be considered disposable</u>. In New Orleans, we saw the natural disaster of Hurricane Katrina followed by a grossly unnatural government response, one that killed thousands of vulnerable citizens and consigned many more to refugee status. In Flint, Michigan, we are witnessing this young century’s most profound illustration of civic evil, an entire city collectively punished with lead-poisoned water for the crime of being poor, Black, and politically disempowered. Every day, the nation’s homeless, mentally ill, drug addicted, and poor are pushed out of institutions of support and relocated to jails and prisons. <u>These <mark>conditions reflect a</mark> prevailing <mark>belief that the vulnerable are unworthy </mark>of investment, protection, or even the most fundamental provisions of the social contract</u>. <u>As a result, <mark>they can be erased</mark>, abandoned, <mark>and</mark> even <mark>left to die</u></mark>.</p><p>Without question, Nobodyness is largely indebted to race, as White supremacy is foundational to the American democratic experiment. The belief that White lives are worth more than others – what Princeton University scholar Eddie Glaude calls the “value gap” – continues to color every aspect of our public and private lives.1 This belief likewise compromises the lives of vulnerable White citizens, many of who support political movements and policies that close ranks around Whiteness rather than ones that enhance their own social and economic interests.</p><p><u>While Nobodyness is strongly tethered to race, it cannot be divorced from other forms of social injustice</u>. Instead, it must be understood through the lens of “intersectionality,” the ways that multiple forms of oppression operate simultaneously against the vulnerable.2 It would be impossible to example the 2014 killing of Mya Hall by National Security Agency police without understanding how sexism and transphobia conspire with structural racism to endanger Black trans bodies. <u>We cannot make sense of Sandra Bland’s tragic death without recognizing the impact of gender and poverty in shaping the current carceral state</u>. To understand the complexity of oppression, we must avoid simple solutions and singular answers.</p><p><u><mark>Despite the centrality of race</mark> within American life, <mark>Nobodyness cannot be understood without</mark> an equally <strong>thorough analysis of <mark>class</u></strong></mark>. <u>Unlike other forms of difference, <strong><mark>class creates the material conditions</strong> and relations through which racism, sexism, and other forms of oppression are <strong>produced, sustained, and lived</strong></mark>. <mark>This <strong>does not mean</strong> that all forms of injustice are due to class</mark> antagonism</u>, nor does it mean that all forms of domination can be automatically fixed through universal class struggle. <u><mark>Rather</mark>, it means that <mark>we cannot</mark> begin to <mark>address</mark> the various forms of <mark>oppression</mark> experienced by America’s vulnerable <mark>without <strong>radically changing</strong> a system that <strong>defends class at all costs</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>This book is my attempt to tell these stories of those marked as Nobody. Based on extensive research, as well as my time on the ground – <u><mark>in Ferguson, Baltimore</mark>, New York City, Atlanta, Hempstead, <mark>Flint, and Sanford</u></mark> – I want to show how the high-profile and controversial cases of State violence that we’ve witnessed over the past few years are but a symptom of a deeper American problem. <u><mark>Underneath each</mark> case <mark>is a</mark> more fundamental <mark>set of <strong>economic conditions</strong></mark>, political arrangements, and power relations that transforms everyday citizens into casualties of an increasingly intense war on the vulnerable</u>. It is my hope that this book offers an analysis that spotlights the humanity of these “Nobodies” and inspires principled action. </p> | null | null | off | 51,700 | 174 | 99,424 | ./documents/ndtceda18/Emory/YaBu/Emory-Yamout-Burgess-Neg-Northwestern-Round4.docx | 603,028 | N | Northwestern | 4 | Emporia SW | Lauren Johnson | 1nc t cap case
2nc k case t ov
1nr t
2nr t case | ndtceda18/Emory/YaBu/Emory-Yamout-Burgess-Neg-Northwestern-Round4.docx | null | 51,292 | YaBu | Emory YaBu | null | Ga..... | Ya..... | Li..... | Bu..... | 19,176 | Emory | Emory | null | null | 1,008 | ndtceda18 | NDT/CEDA 2018-19 | 2,018 | cx | college | 2 |
3,224,706 | The role of the ballot is to answer the resolutional question. Topicality doesn’t restrict any style or argument, but defends a baseline for predictability. Debate is a game – not a forum for consensus. Competition is inevitable – it should be preserved as an incentive for clash. | Poscher 16 | Poscher 16 (Ralf, director of the Institute for Staatswissenschaft & Philosophy of Law, Professor of Public Law and Legal Philosophy, “Why We Argue About the Law: An Agonistic Account of Legal Disagreement,” in Metaphilosophy of Law, ed. Gizbert-Studnicki, Dyrda, Banas, 2/19/16, SSRN) | negation is a central feature of spirit and consciousness The tarrying with the negative is the “labour of the negative” Postema points to yet another feature of disagreements as a necessary ingredient of the process of practical reasoning. Only if our reasoning is exposed to contrary arguments can we test its merits We must go through the “labor of the negative” to have trust in processes Agreement without exposure to disagreement can be deceptive in various ways When a group of like‐minded people deliberates an issue, informational and reputational cascades produce more extreme views in their deliberations polarization and biases can be countered by the inclusion of dissenting voices opposing positions will profit from the catharsis it received “by looking the negative in the face and tarrying with it Even if the probability of reaching a consensus with our opponents is very low entering into an exchange of arguments can still serve to test and improve our position In hard cases we must lay out the argument to figure out what we believe to be the right answer We might not know what we believe ourselves until we have developed a line of argument against the background of our subjective beliefs, attitudes and dispositions our adversary is much more motivated to find a potential flaw in our argument than someone with whom we know we are in agreement Argumentation with an adversary can have purposes beyond persuading to test one’s own convictions, to engage our opponent in inferential commitments The rational does not lie in the discovery of a single right answer to the topic of debate, since in hard cases there are no single right answers our disagreements are instrumental to rationales which lie beyond the topic at hand like the exploration of our communalities the objectives listed above could not be achieved by a non‐argumentative procedure taking a gut vote would not help us to explore our communalities or our inferential commitments nor help to scrutinize the positions in the labor of the negative reduces the chances that constructions that have major flaws or inconsistencies built into the arguments supporting them will prevail Pure argumentative procedures not geared towards a decision procedure would undercut the incentive structure of our agonistic disagreements That the debates are about winning or losing helps to keep the participants engaged The agonistic account does not presuppose a fact of the matter, it is not accompanied by an ontological commitment, and the question of how the fact of the matter could be known to us is not even raised the agonistic account of disagreement is not confronted with the metaphysical or epistemological questions there is also some kind of identity of the substantive issues at stake in legal disagreements the conceptual unity of a linguistic practice is not ratified by the existence of a single best answer, but by the unity of the interpretive effort that extends to materials and practices that have sufficient overlap The fulcrum of disagreement in the existence of a single right answer does not lie in its existence, but in the communality of the effort if only on the basis of an overlapping common ground of materials, accepted practices, experiences and dispositions two athletes are engaged in the same contest when they follow the same rules even if there is no single best style Each is engaged in developing the best style to win against their opponent even people with radically opposing views about the application of an expression can still share a concept in that they are engaged in the same process of theorizing over roughly the same materials and practices. these lines allow for adamant disagreements without abandoning the idea that people are talking about the same concept semantic unity is provided by the largely overlapping materials that form the basis for their disagreement Such a semantic collapses only when we lack a sufficient overlap in the materials | negation is a central feature tarrying with the negative is the “labour of the negative Only if our reasoning is exposed to arguments can we test its merits Agreement without disagreement can be deceptive polarization and biases can be countered by inclusion of dissenting voices opposing positions will profit from looking the negative in the face Even if the probability of consensus is low an exchange of arguments can test and improve our position our adversary is much more motivated to find a potential flaw in our argument The rational does not lie in a single right answer our disagreements are instrumental beyond the topic like the exploration of communalities objectives above could not be achieved by a non‐argumentative procedure Pure argumentative procedures not geared towards a decision would undercut the incentive structure of disagreements That the debates are about winning helps keep participants engaged The agonistic account is not accompanied by ontological commitment The fulcrum of disagreement in a single right answer does not lie in its existence, but in the communality of the effort only on overlapping common ground even people with radically opposing views about can still share a concept they are engaged in the same process over roughly the same materials and practices | Hegel’s dialectical thinking powerfully exploits the idea of negation. It is a central feature of spirit and consciousness that they have the power to negate. The spirit “is this power only by looking the negative in the face and tarrying with it. This […] is the magical power that converts it into being.”102 The tarrying with the negative is part of what Hegel calls the “labour of the negative”103. In a loose reference to this Hegelian notion Gerald Postema points to yet another feature of disagreements as a necessary ingredient of the process of practical reasoning. Only if our reasoning is exposed to contrary arguments can we test its merits. We must go through the “labor of the negative” to have trust in our deliberative processes.104 This also holds where we seem to be in agreement. Agreement without exposure to disagreement can be deceptive in various ways. The first phenomenon Postema draws attention to is the group polarization effect. When a group of like‐minded people deliberates an issue, informational and reputational cascades produce more extreme views in the process of their deliberations.105 The polarization and biases that are well documented for such groups 106 can be countered at least in some settings by the inclusion of dissenting voices. In these scenarios, disagreement can be a cure for dysfunctional deliberative polarization and biases.107 A second deliberative dysfunction mitigated by disagreement is superficial agreement, which can even be manipulatively used in the sense of a “presumptuous ‘We’”108. Disagreement can help to police such distortions of deliberative processes by challenging superficial agreements. Disagreements may thus signal that a deliberative process is not contaminated with dysfunctional agreements stemming from polarization or superficiality. Protecting our discourse against such contaminations is valuable even if we do not come to terms. Each of the opposing positions will profit from the catharsis it received “by looking the negative in the face and tarrying with it”. These advantages of disagreement in collective deliberations are mirrored on the individual level. Even if the probability of reaching a consensus with our opponents is very low from the beginning, as might be the case in deeply entrenched conflicts, entering into an exchange of arguments can still serve to test and improve our position. We have to do the “labor of the negative” for ourselves. Even if we cannot come up with a line of argument that coheres well with everybody else’s beliefs, attitudes and dispositions, we can still come up with a line of argument that achieves this goal for our own personal beliefs, attitudes and dispositions. To provide ourselves with the most coherent system of our own beliefs, attitudes and dispositions is – at least in important issues – an aspect of personal integrity – to borrow one of Dworkin’s favorite expressions for a less aspirational idea. In hard cases we must – in some way – lay out the argument for ourselves to figure out what we believe to be the right answer. We might not know what we believe ourselves in questions of abortion, the death penalty, torture, and stem cell research, until we have developed a line of argument against the background of our subjective beliefs, attitudes and dispositions. In these cases it might be rational to discuss the issue with someone unlikely to share some of our more fundamental convictions or who opposes the view towards which we lean. This might even be the most helpful way of corroborating a view, because we know that our adversary is much more motivated to find a potential flaw in our argument than someone with whom we know we are in agreement. It might be more helpful to discuss a liberal position with Scalia than with Breyer if we want to make sure that we have not overlooked some counter‐argument to our case. It would be too narrow an understanding of our practice of legal disagreement and argumentation if we restricted its purpose to persuading an adversary in the case at hand and inferred from this narrow understanding the irrationality of argumentation in hard cases, in which we know beforehand that we will not be able to persuade. Rational argumentation is a much more complex practice in a more complex social framework. Argumentation with an adversary can have purposes beyond persuading him: to test one’s own convictions, to engage our opponent in inferential commitments and to persuade third parties are only some of these; to rally our troops or express our convictions might be others. To make our peace with Kant we could say that “there must be a hope of coming to terms” with someone though not necessarily with our opponent, but maybe only a third party or even just ourselves and not necessarily only on the issue at hand, but maybe through inferential commitments in a different arena. f) The Advantage Over Non‐Argumentative Alternatives It goes without saying that in real world legal disagreements, all of the reasons listed above usually play in concert and will typically hold true to different degrees relative to different participants in the debate: There will be some participants for whom our hope of coming to terms might still be justified and others for whom only some of the other reasons hold and some for whom it is a mixture of all of the reasons in shifting degrees as our disagreements evolve. It is also apparent that, with the exception of the first reason, the rationality of our disagreements is of a secondary nature. The rational does not lie in the discovery of a single right answer to the topic of debate, since in hard cases there are no single right answers. Instead, our disagreements are instrumental to rationales which lie beyond the topic at hand, like the exploration of our communalities or of our inferential commitments. Since these reasons are of this secondary nature, they must stand up to alternative ways of settling irreconcilable disagreements that have other secondary reasons in their favor – like swiftness of decision making or using fewer resources. Why does our legal practice require lengthy arguments and discursive efforts even in appellate or supreme court cases of irreconcilable legal disagreements? The closure has to come by some non‐argumentative mean and courts have always relied on them. For the medieval courts of the Germanic tradition it is bequeathed that judges had to fight it out literally if they disagreed on a question of law – though the king allowed them to pick surrogate fighters.109 It is understandable that the process of civilization has led us to non‐violent non‐ argumentative means to determine the law. But what was wrong with District Judge Currin of Umatilla County in Oregon, who – in his late days – decided inconclusive traffic violations by publicly flipping a coin?110 If we are counting heads at the end of our lengthy argumentative proceedings anyway, why not decide hard cases by gut voting at the outset and spare everybody the cost of developing elaborate arguments on questions, where there is not fact of the matter to be discovered? One reason lies in the mixed nature of our reasons in actual legal disagreements. The different second order reasons can be held apart analytically, but not in real life cases. The hope of coming to terms will often play a role at least for some time relative to some participants in the debate. A second reason is that the objectives listed above could not be achieved by a non‐argumentative procedure. Flipping a coin, throwing dice or taking a gut vote would not help us to explore our communalities or our inferential commitments nor help to scrutinize the positions in play. A third reason is the overall rational aspiration of the law that Dworkin relates to in his integrity account111. In a justificatory sense112 the law aspires to give a coherent account of itself – even if it is not the only right one – required by equal respect under conditions of normative disagreement.113 Combining legal argumentation with the non‐argumentative decision‐ making procedure of counting reasoned opinions serves the coherence aspiration of the law in at least two ways: First, the labor of the negative reduces the chances that constructions of the law that have major flaws or inconsistencies built into the arguments supporting them will prevail. Second, since every position must be a reasoned one within the given framework of the law, it must be one that somehow fits into the overall structure of the law along coherent lines. It thus protects against incoherent “checkerboard” treatments114 of hard cases. It is the combination of reasoned disagreement and the non‐rational decision‐making mechanism of counting reasoned opinions that provides for both in hard cases: a decision and one – of multiple possible – coherent constructions of the law. Pure non‐rational procedures – like flipping a coin – would only provide for the decision part. Pure argumentative procedures – which are not geared towards a decision procedure – would undercut the incentive structure of our agonistic disagreements.115 In the face of unresolvable disagreements endless debates would seem an idle enterprise. That the debates are about winning or losing helps to keep the participants engaged. That the decision depends on counting reasoned opinions guarantees that the engagement focuses on rational argumentation. No plain non‐argumentative procedure would achieve this result. If the judges were to flip a coin at the end of the trial in hard cases, there would be little incentive to engage in an exchange of arguments. It is specifically the count of reasoned opinions which provides for rational scrutiny in our legal disagreements and thus contributes to the rationales discussed above. 2. The Semantics of Agonistic Disagreements The agonistic account does not presuppose a fact of the matter, it is not accompanied by an ontological commitment, and the question of how the fact of the matter could be known to us is not even raised. Thus the agonistic account of legal disagreement is not confronted with the metaphysical or epistemological questions that plague one‐right‐answer theories in particular. However, it must still come up with a semantics that explains in what sense we disagree about the same issue and are not just talking at cross purposes. In a series of articles David Plunkett and Tim Sundell have reconstructed legal disagreements in semantic terms as metalinguistic negotiations on the usage of a term that at the center of a hard case like “cruel and unusual punishment” in a death‐penalty case.116 Even though the different sides in the debate define the term differently, they are not talking past each other, since they are engaged in a metalinguistic negotiation on the use of the same term. The metalinguistic negotiation on the use of the term serves as a semantic anchor for a disagreement on the substantive issues connected with the term because of its functional role in the law. The “cruel and unusual punishment”‐clause thus serves to argue about the permissibility of the death penalty. This account, however only provides a very superficial semantic commonality. But the commonality between the participants of a legal disagreement go deeper than a discussion whether the term “bank” should in future only to be used for financial institutions, which fulfills every criteria for semantic negotiations that Plunkett and Sundell propose. Unlike in mere semantic negotiations, like the on the disambiguation of the term “bank”, there is also some kind of identity of the substantive issues at stake in legal disagreements. A promising route to capture this aspect of legal disagreements might be offered by recent semantic approaches that try to accommodate the externalist challenges of realist semantics,117 which inspire one‐right‐answer theorists like Moore or David Brink. Neo‐ descriptivist and two‐valued semantics provide for the theoretical or interpretive element of realist semantics without having to commit to the ontological positions of traditional externalism. In a sense they offer externalist semantics with no ontological strings attached. The less controversial aspect of the externalist picture of meaning developed in neo‐ descriptivist and two‐valued semantics can be found in the deferential structure that our meaning‐providing intentions often encompass.118 In the case of natural kinds, speakers defer to the expertise of chemists when they employ natural kind terms like gold or water. If a speaker orders someone to buy $ 10,000 worth of gold as a safe investment, he might not know the exact atomic structure of the chemical element 79. In cases of doubt, though, he would insist that he meant to buy only stuff that chemical experts – or the markets for that matter – qualify as gold. The deferential element in the speaker’s intentions provides for the specific externalist element of the semantics. In the case of the law, the meaning‐providing intentions connected to the provisions of the law can be understood to defer in a similar manner to the best overall theory or interpretation of the legal materials. Against the background of such a semantic framework the conceptual unity of a linguistic practice is not ratified by the existence of a single best answer, but by the unity of the interpretive effort that extends to legal materials and legal practices that have sufficient overlap119 – be it only in a historical perspective120. The fulcrum of disagreement that Dworkin sees in the existence of a single right answer121 does not lie in its existence, but in the communality of the effort – if only on the basis of an overlapping common ground of legal materials, accepted practices, experiences and dispositions. As two athletes are engaged in the same contest when they follow the same rules, share the same concept of winning and losing and act in the same context, but follow very different styles of e.g. wrestling, boxing, swimming etc. They are in the same contest, even if there is no single best style in which to wrestle, box or swim. Each, however, is engaged in developing the best style to win against their opponent, just as two lawyers try to develop the best argument to convince a bench of judges.122 Within such a semantic framework even people with radically opposing views about the application of an expression can still share a concept, in that they are engaged in the same process of theorizing over roughly the same legal materials and practices. Semantic frameworks along these lines allow for adamant disagreements without abandoning the idea that people are talking about the same concept. An agonistic account of legal disagreement can build on such a semantic framework, which can explain in what sense lawyers, judges and scholars engaged in agonistic disagreements are not talking past each other. They are engaged in developing the best interpretation of roughly the same legal materials, albeit against the background of diverging beliefs, attitudes and dispositions that lead them to divergent conclusions in hard cases. Despite the divergent conclusions, semantic unity is provided by the largely overlapping legal materials that form the basis for their disagreement. Such a semantic collapses only when we lack a sufficient overlap in the materials. To use an example of Michael Moore’s: If we wanted to debate whether a certain work of art was “just”, we share neither paradigms nor a tradition of applying the concept of justice to art such as to engage in an intelligible controversy | 15,624 | <h4>The role of the ballot is to answer the resolutional question. Topicality doesn’t restrict any style or argument, but defends a baseline for predictability. Debate is a game – not a forum for consensus. Competition is inevitable – it should be preserved as an incentive for clash.</h4><p><strong>Poscher 16 </strong>(Ralf, director of the Institute for Staatswissenschaft & Philosophy of Law, Professor of Public Law and Legal Philosophy, “Why We Argue About the Law: An Agonistic Account of Legal Disagreement,” in Metaphilosophy of Law, ed. Gizbert-Studnicki, Dyrda, Banas, 2/19/16, SSRN)</p><p>Hegel’s dialectical thinking powerfully exploits the idea of <u><strong><mark>negation</u></strong></mark>. It <u><mark>is a central feature</mark> of spirit and consciousness</u> that they have the power to negate. The spirit “is this power only by looking the negative in the face and tarrying with it. This […] is the magical power that converts it into being.”102 <u>The <mark>tarrying with the negative is</u></mark> part of what Hegel calls <u><mark>the “<strong>labour of the negative</mark>”</u></strong>103. In a loose reference to this Hegelian notion Gerald <u>Postema points to yet another feature of disagreements as a necessary ingredient of the process of practical reasoning.</u> <u><mark>Only if our reasoning is exposed to</mark> contrary <mark>arguments can we test its merits</u></mark>. <u>We must go through the “labor of the negative” to have trust in</u> our deliberative <u>processes</u>.104 This also holds where we seem to be in agreement. <u><mark>Agreement without</mark> exposure to <mark>disagreement can be deceptive</mark> in various ways</u>. The first phenomenon Postema draws attention to is the group polarization effect. <u>When a group of like‐minded people deliberates an issue, informational and reputational cascades produce more extreme views</u> <u>in</u> the process of <u>their deliberations</u>.105 The <u><mark>polarization and biases</u></mark> that are well documented for such groups 106 <u><mark>can be countered</u></mark> at least in some settings <u><mark>by</mark> the <mark>inclusion of</mark> <strong><mark>dissenting voices</u></strong></mark>. In these scenarios, disagreement can be a cure for dysfunctional deliberative polarization and biases.107 A second deliberative dysfunction mitigated by disagreement is superficial agreement, which can even be manipulatively used in the sense of a “presumptuous ‘We’”108. Disagreement can help to police such distortions of deliberative processes by challenging superficial agreements. Disagreements may thus signal that a deliberative process is not contaminated with dysfunctional agreements stemming from polarization or superficiality. Protecting our discourse against such contaminations is valuable even if we do not come to terms. Each of the <u><strong><mark>opposing positions will profit</strong> from</mark> the catharsis it received “by <mark>looking the negative in the face</mark> and tarrying with it</u>”. These advantages of disagreement in collective deliberations are mirrored on the individual level. <u><mark>Even if the probability of</mark> reaching a <mark>consensus</mark> with our opponents <mark>is</mark> very <mark>low</u></mark> from the beginning, as might be the case in deeply entrenched conflicts, <u>entering into <mark>an exchange of arguments can</mark> still serve to <strong><mark>test and improve our position</u></strong></mark>. We have to do the “labor of the negative” for ourselves. Even if we cannot come up with a line of argument that coheres well with everybody else’s beliefs, attitudes and dispositions, we can still come up with a line of argument that achieves this goal for our own personal beliefs, attitudes and dispositions. To provide ourselves with the most coherent system of our own beliefs, attitudes and dispositions is – at least in important issues – an aspect of personal integrity – to borrow one of Dworkin’s favorite expressions for a less aspirational idea. <u>In hard cases we must</u> – in some way – <u>lay out the argument</u> for ourselves <u>to figure out what we believe to be the right answer</u>. <u>We might not know what we believe ourselves</u> in questions of abortion, the death penalty, torture, and stem cell research, <u>until we have developed a line of argument against the background of our subjective beliefs, attitudes and dispositions</u>. In these cases it might be rational to discuss the issue with someone unlikely to share some of our more fundamental convictions or who opposes the view towards which we lean. This might even be the most helpful way of corroborating a view, because we know that <u><mark>our adversary is much more</mark> <strong><mark>motivated to find a potential flaw</strong></mark> <mark>in our argument</mark> than someone with whom we know we are in agreement</u>. It might be more helpful to discuss a liberal position with Scalia than with Breyer if we want to make sure that we have not overlooked some counter‐argument to our case. It would be too narrow an understanding of our practice of legal disagreement and argumentation if we restricted its purpose to persuading an adversary in the case at hand and inferred from this narrow understanding the irrationality of argumentation in hard cases, in which we know beforehand that we will not be able to persuade. Rational argumentation is a much more complex practice in a more complex social framework. <u>Argumentation with an adversary can have purposes <strong>beyond persuading</u></strong> him: <u>to test one’s own convictions, to engage our opponent in inferential commitments</u> and to persuade third parties are only some of these; to rally our troops or express our convictions might be others. To make our peace with Kant we could say that “there must be a hope of coming to terms” with someone though not necessarily with our opponent, but maybe only a third party or even just ourselves and not necessarily only on the issue at hand, but maybe through inferential commitments in a different arena. f) The Advantage Over Non‐Argumentative Alternatives It goes without saying that in real world legal disagreements, all of the reasons listed above usually play in concert and will typically hold true to different degrees relative to different participants in the debate: There will be some participants for whom our hope of coming to terms might still be justified and others for whom only some of the other reasons hold and some for whom it is a mixture of all of the reasons in shifting degrees as our disagreements evolve. It is also apparent that, with the exception of the first reason, the rationality of our disagreements is of a secondary nature. <u><mark>The rational <strong>does not lie in</mark> the discovery of <mark>a single right answer</strong></mark> to the topic of debate, since in hard cases there are no single right answers</u>. Instead, <u><mark>our disagreements are instrumental</mark> to rationales which lie <mark>beyond the topic</mark> at hand</u>, <u><mark>like the <strong>exploration of</mark> our <mark>communalities</u></strong></mark> or of our inferential commitments. Since these reasons are of this secondary nature, they must stand up to alternative ways of settling irreconcilable disagreements that have other secondary reasons in their favor – like swiftness of decision making or using fewer resources. Why does our legal practice require lengthy arguments and discursive efforts even in appellate or supreme court cases of irreconcilable legal disagreements? The closure has to come by some non‐argumentative mean and courts have always relied on them. For the medieval courts of the Germanic tradition it is bequeathed that judges had to fight it out literally if they disagreed on a question of law – though the king allowed them to pick surrogate fighters.109 It is understandable that the process of civilization has led us to non‐violent non‐ argumentative means to determine the law. But what was wrong with District Judge Currin of Umatilla County in Oregon, who – in his late days – decided inconclusive traffic violations by publicly flipping a coin?110 If we are counting heads at the end of our lengthy argumentative proceedings anyway, why not decide hard cases by gut voting at the outset and spare everybody the cost of developing elaborate arguments on questions, where there is not fact of the matter to be discovered? One reason lies in the mixed nature of our reasons in actual legal disagreements. The different second order reasons can be held apart analytically, but not in real life cases. The hope of coming to terms will often play a role at least for some time relative to some participants in the debate. A second reason is that <u>the <mark>objectives</mark> listed <mark>above <strong>could not be achieved</strong> by a non‐argumentative procedure</u></mark>. Flipping a coin, throwing dice or <u>taking a gut vote would not help us to explore our communalities or our inferential commitments nor help to scrutinize the positions in</u> play. A third reason is the overall rational aspiration of the law that Dworkin relates to in his integrity account111. In a justificatory sense112 the law aspires to give a coherent account of itself – even if it is not the only right one – required by equal respect under conditions of normative disagreement.113 Combining legal argumentation with the non‐argumentative decision‐ making procedure of counting reasoned opinions serves the coherence aspiration of the law in at least two ways: First, <u>the labor of the negative reduces the chances that constructions</u> of the law <u>that have major flaws or inconsistencies built into the arguments supporting them will prevail</u>. Second, since every position must be a reasoned one within the given framework of the law, it must be one that somehow fits into the overall structure of the law along coherent lines. It thus protects against incoherent “checkerboard” treatments114 of hard cases. It is the combination of reasoned disagreement and the non‐rational decision‐making mechanism of counting reasoned opinions that provides for both in hard cases: a decision and one – of multiple possible – coherent constructions of the law. Pure non‐rational procedures – like flipping a coin – would only provide for the decision part. <u><mark>Pure argumentative procedures</u></mark> – which are <u><strong><mark>not geared</mark> <mark>towards a decision</mark> procedure</u></strong> – <u><mark>would undercut the incentive structure of</mark> our agonistic <mark>disagreements</u></mark>.115 In the face of unresolvable disagreements endless debates would seem an idle enterprise. <u><mark>That the</mark> <mark>debates are about <strong>winning</mark> or losing</strong> <mark>helps</mark> to <mark>keep</mark> the <mark>participants engaged</u></mark>. That the decision depends on counting reasoned opinions guarantees that the engagement focuses on rational argumentation. No plain non‐argumentative procedure would achieve this result. If the judges were to flip a coin at the end of the trial in hard cases, there would be little incentive to engage in an exchange of arguments. It is specifically the count of reasoned opinions which provides for rational scrutiny in our legal disagreements and thus contributes to the rationales discussed above. 2. The Semantics of Agonistic Disagreements <u><mark>The agonistic account</mark> <strong>does not presuppose a fact</strong> of the matter, it <mark>is <strong>not accompanied by</mark> an <mark>ontological commitment</strong></mark>, and the question of how the fact of the matter could be known to us is <strong>not even raised</u></strong>. Thus <u>the agonistic account of</u> legal <u>disagreement is not confronted with the metaphysical or epistemological questions</u> that plague one‐right‐answer theories in particular. However, it must still come up with a semantics that explains in what sense we disagree about the same issue and are not just talking at cross purposes. In a series of articles David Plunkett and Tim Sundell have reconstructed legal disagreements in semantic terms as metalinguistic negotiations on the usage of a term that at the center of a hard case like “cruel and unusual punishment” in a death‐penalty case.116 Even though the different sides in the debate define the term differently, they are not talking past each other, since they are engaged in a metalinguistic negotiation on the use of the same term. The metalinguistic negotiation on the use of the term serves as a semantic anchor for a disagreement on the substantive issues connected with the term because of its functional role in the law. The “cruel and unusual punishment”‐clause thus serves to argue about the permissibility of the death penalty. This account, however only provides a very superficial semantic commonality. But the commonality between the participants of a legal disagreement go deeper than a discussion whether the term “bank” should in future only to be used for financial institutions, which fulfills every criteria for semantic negotiations that Plunkett and Sundell propose. Unlike in mere semantic negotiations, like the on the disambiguation of the term “bank”, <u>there is also some kind of identity of the <strong>substantive issues at stake</strong> in legal disagreements</u>. A promising route to capture this aspect of legal disagreements might be offered by recent semantic approaches that try to accommodate the externalist challenges of realist semantics,117 which inspire one‐right‐answer theorists like Moore or David Brink. Neo‐ descriptivist and two‐valued semantics provide for the theoretical or interpretive element of realist semantics without having to commit to the ontological positions of traditional externalism. In a sense they offer externalist semantics with no ontological strings attached. The less controversial aspect of the externalist picture of meaning developed in neo‐ descriptivist and two‐valued semantics can be found in the deferential structure that our meaning‐providing intentions often encompass.118 In the case of natural kinds, speakers defer to the expertise of chemists when they employ natural kind terms like gold or water. If a speaker orders someone to buy $ 10,000 worth of gold as a safe investment, he might not know the exact atomic structure of the chemical element 79. In cases of doubt, though, he would insist that he meant to buy only stuff that chemical experts – or the markets for that matter – qualify as gold. The deferential element in the speaker’s intentions provides for the specific externalist element of the semantics. In the case of the law, the meaning‐providing intentions connected to the provisions of the law can be understood to defer in a similar manner to the best overall theory or interpretation of the legal materials. Against the background of such a semantic framework <u>the conceptual unity of a linguistic practice is not ratified by the existence of a single best answer, but by the unity of the interpretive effort that extends to</u> legal <u>materials and</u> legal <u>practices that have sufficient overlap</u>119 – be it only in a historical perspective120. <u><mark>The fulcrum of disagreement</u></mark> that Dworkin sees <u><mark>in</mark> the existence of <mark>a single right answer</u></mark>121 <u><mark>does not lie in its existence, but in</mark> <mark>the <strong>communality of the effort</u></strong></mark> – <u>if <mark>only on</mark> the basis of an <strong><mark>overlapping common ground</u></strong></mark> <u>of</u> legal <u>materials, accepted practices, experiences and dispositions</u>. As <u>two athletes are engaged in the same contest when they follow the same rules</u>, share the same concept of winning and losing and act in the same context, but follow very different styles of e.g. wrestling, boxing, swimming etc. They are in the same contest, <u><strong>even if there is no single best style</u></strong> in which to wrestle, box or swim. <u>Each</u>, however, <u>is engaged in developing the best style to win against their opponent</u>, just as two lawyers try to develop the best argument to convince a bench of judges.122 Within such a semantic framework <u><mark>even people with radically opposing views about</mark> the application of an expression <mark>can still <strong>share a concept</u></strong></mark>, <u>in that <mark>they are engaged in the same</mark> <mark>process</mark> of theorizing <mark>over roughly the same</u></mark> legal <u><mark>materials and practices</mark>.</u> Semantic frameworks along <u>these lines allow for adamant disagreements without abandoning the idea that people are talking about the same concept</u>. An agonistic account of legal disagreement can build on such a semantic framework, which can explain in what sense lawyers, judges and scholars engaged in agonistic disagreements are not talking past each other. They are engaged in developing the best interpretation of roughly the same legal materials, albeit against the background of diverging beliefs, attitudes and dispositions that lead them to divergent conclusions in hard cases. Despite the divergent conclusions, <u>semantic unity is provided by the <strong>largely overlapping</u></strong> legal <u>materials that form the basis for their disagreement</u>. <u>Such a semantic collapses only when we <strong>lack a sufficient overlap</strong> in the materials</u>. To use an example of Michael Moore’s: If we wanted to debate whether a certain work of art was “just”, we share neither paradigms nor a tradition of applying the concept of justice to art such as to engage in an intelligible controversy</p> | 1NC | null | 1 | 14,649 | 1,154 | 104,445 | ./documents/hspolicy18/Lexington/LuZh/Lexington-Lu-Zhou-Neg-NY%20Fall%20Faceoff%20at%20Mamaroneck%20HS-Round2.docx | 695,558 | N | NY Fall Faceoff at Mamaroneck HS | 2 | Stuyvesant HC | Erin Szczechowski | 1AC - Asian Feminist Killjoy
1NC - T-USfg v5 F*ck PIC MacKinnon DA Nguyen v INS CP Joo v Japan CP Psychoanalysis K Performance PIC MURCA CA
2NC - MacKinnon DA 'MURCA CA T-USfg v5
1NR - F*ck PIC Case
2NR - 'MURCA CA | hspolicy18/Lexington/LuZh/Lexington-Lu-Zhou-Neg-NY%20Fall%20Faceoff%20at%20Mamaroneck%20HS-Round2.docx | null | 59,166 | LuZh | Lexington LuZh | null | Al..... | Lu..... | Ke..... | Zh..... | 20,878 | Lexington | Lexington | null | null | 1,017 | hspolicy18 | HS Policy 2018-19 | 2,018 | cx | hs | 2 |
1,531,198 | [5] Principle of explosion is true which proves the resolution true. | Wikiwand | Wikiwand. “Principle of Explosion.” Wikiwand, 0AD, www.wikiwand.com/en/Principle_of_explosion. //Massa | "from contradiction, anything (follows)"), or the principle of Pseudo-Scotus deductive explosion [4]
consider two contradictory statements – "All lemons are yellow" and "Not all lemons are yellow" anything can be proven the assertion that "unicorns exist", by using the following argument:
"All lemons are yellow" has been assumed to be true.
Therefore "All lemons are yellow OR unicorns exist” must also be true, since the first part is true.
since we know that "Not all lemons are yellow" the first part is false, and hence the second part must be true, i.e., unicorns exist. | "All lemons are yellow" and "Not anything can be proven "unicorns exist"
lemons yellow assumed
Therefore "All lemons yellow OR unicorns exist” true
since the first part is false the second true | The principle of explosion (Latin: ex falso (sequitur) quodlibet (EFQ), "from falsehood, anything (follows)", or ex contradictione (sequitur) quodlibet (ECQ), "from contradiction, anything (follows)"), or the principle of Pseudo-Scotus, is the law of classical logic, intuitionistic logic and similar logical systems, according to which any statement can be proven from a contradiction.[1] That is, once a contradiction has been asserted, any proposition (including their negations) can be inferred from it. This is known as deductive explosion.[2][3] The proof of this principle was first given by 12th century French philosopher William of Soissons.[4]
As a demonstration of the principle, consider two contradictory statements – "All lemons are yellow" and "Not all lemons are yellow", and suppose that both are true. If that is the case, anything can be proven, e.g., the assertion that "unicorns exist", by using the following argument:
We know that "All lemons are yellow", as it has been assumed to be true.
Therefore, the two-part statement "All lemons are yellow OR unicorns exist” must also be true, since the first part is true.
However, since we know that "Not all lemons are yellow" (as this has been assumed), the first part is false, and hence the second part must be true, i.e., unicorns exist. | 1,310 | <h4>[5] Principle of explosion is true which proves the resolution true.</h4><p><u><strong>Wikiwand</u></strong>. “Principle of Explosion.” Wikiwand, 0AD, www.wikiwand.com/en/Principle_of_explosion. //Massa</p><p>The principle of explosion (Latin: ex falso (sequitur) quodlibet (EFQ), "from falsehood, anything (follows)", or ex contradictione (sequitur) quodlibet (ECQ), <u><strong>"from contradiction, anything (follows)"), or the principle of Pseudo-Scotus</u></strong>, is the law of classical logic, intuitionistic logic and similar logical systems, according to which any statement can be proven from a contradiction.[1] That is, once a contradiction has been asserted, any proposition (including their negations) can be inferred from it. This is known as <u><strong>deductive explosion</u></strong>.[2][3] The proof of this principle was first given by 12th century French philosopher William of Soissons.<u><strong>[4]</p><p></u></strong>As a demonstration of the principle, <u><strong>consider two contradictory statements – <mark>"All lemons are yellow" and "Not</mark> all lemons are yellow"</u></strong>, and suppose that both are true. If that is the case, <u><strong><mark>anything can be proven</u></strong></mark>, e.g., <u><strong>the assertion that <mark>"unicorns exist"</mark>, by using the following argument:</p><p></u></strong>We know that <u><strong>"All <mark>lemons</mark> are <mark>yellow</mark>"</u></strong>, as it <u><strong>has been <mark>assumed</mark> to be true.</p><p><mark>Therefore</u></strong></mark>, the two-part statement <u><strong><mark>"All lemons</mark> are <mark>yellow OR unicorns exist”</mark> must also be <mark>true</mark>, since the first part is true.</p><p></u></strong>However, <u><strong><mark>since </mark>we know that "Not all lemons are yellow"</u></strong> (as this has been assumed), <u><strong><mark>the first part is false</mark>, and hence <mark>the second</mark> part must be <mark>true</mark>, i.e., unicorns exist.</p></u></strong> | null | null | 1AC – Fun | 327,420 | 175 | 43,679 | ./documents/hsld21/Proof/Ra/Proof-Raghavan-Aff-Greenhill-Round2.docx | 897,204 | A | Greenhill | 2 | Marcus JR | Javier Navarette | 1ac -prag
1nc- queerpess case
1ar- prag tt tricks k
2nr- k case | hsld21/Proof/Ra/Proof-Raghavan-Aff-Greenhill-Round2.docx | null | 75,263 | DhRa | Proof DhRa | null | Dh..... | Ra..... | null | null | 25,136 | Proof | Proof | CA | null | 1,029 | hsld21 | HS LD 2021-22 | 2,021 | ld | hs | 1 |
2,440,893 | The plan is a shock – Japan will prolif and hedge in space which turns case | Cheng 9 | Cheng 9 [Dean Cheng, Senior Research Fellow, Asian Studies Center, Davis Institute for National Security and Foreign Policy Heritage. Reflections on Sino-US Space Cooperation. EISENHOWER CENTER FOR SPACE AND DEFENSE STUDIES. Vol. 2, No. 3, December 2009. https://www.usafa.edu/app/uploads/Space_and_Defense_2_3.pdf] | it is important to consider ramifications of Sino-US cooperation in space may arouse concerns in Tokyo they are keeping a close eye on developments regarding China
Japan is the bulwark for US deterrence and engagement of China and No Korea U S .35
For Japan forbids the United States is an essential
guarantor of its security Any move by the US that might undermine this view raises not only the prospect of weakening US-Japanese ties, but also affecting Japan’s security policies
it is essential not to engage in activities that would undercut perceptions of American reliability
Failing to do so may well incur a Japanese reaction Tokyo is fully capable of undertaking space-oriented responses when it is concerned That would arouse the ire of China The tragic history of Sino-Japanese relations continues to cast a baleful influence upon current interactions between the two states If there is not a “space race” currently underway between Beijing and Tokyo, it would be most unfortunate if American actions were to precipitate one | Sino-US coop in space may arouse concerns in Tokyo they keep a close eye on China
Japan is the bulwark for deterrence and engagement of China and Korea .35
the U S is an essential
guarantor of security. Any move that might undermine this weaken US-Japan ties, but also affect Japan’s security policies
it is essential not to undercut perceptions of American reliability
Failing may incur Japanese reaction Tokyo is capable of space-oriented responses That would arouse ire of China there is not “space race” between Beijing and Tokyo, it would be unfortunate if America precipitate one | Beyond the bilateral difficulties of cooperating with the PRC, it is also important to consider potential ramifications of Sino-US cooperation in space on the Asian political landscape. In particular, cooperation between Washington and Beijing on space issues may well arouse concerns in Tokyo and Delhi. Both of these nations have their own space programs, and while they are arguably not engaged in a “space race” with China (or each other), they are certainly keeping a close eye on developments regarding China.
Of particular importance is Japan. The United States relationship with Japan is arguably its most important in East Asia.
US interest in Japan should be self-evident. Japan hosts 47,000 US troops and is the linchpin for forward US presence in that hemisphere. Japan is the second largest contributor to all major international organizations that buttress US foreign policy.... Japan is the bulwark for US deterrence and engagement of China and North Korea—the reason why those countries cannot assume that the United States will eventually withdraw from the region.35
For Japan, whose “peace constitution” forbids it from using war as an instrument of state policy, the United States is an essential
guarantor of its security. Any move by the US that might undermine this view raises not only the prospect of weakening US-Japanese ties, but also potentially affecting Japan’s security policies.
In this regard, then, it is essential not to engage in activities that would undercut perceptions of American reliability. Such moves, it should be noted, are not limited to those in the security realm. For example, the Nixon administration undertook several initiatives in the late 1960s and early 1970s that rocked Tokyo-Washington relations, and are still remembered as the “Nixon shocks.” While some of these were in the realm of security (including Nixon’s opening to China and the promulgation of the Nixon Doctrine), the others were in the trade area. These included a ten percent surcharge on all imports entering the US and suspended the convertibility of the dollar (i.e., removed the US from the gold standard).36
Part of the “shock” was the fundamental nature of these shifts. Even more damaging, however, was the failure of the Nixon Administration to consult their Japanese counterparts, catching them wholly off-guard. It took several years for the effects of these shocks to wear off. If the United States is intent upon expanding space relations with the PRC, then it would behoove it to consult Japan, in order to minimize the prospect of a “space shock.”
Failing to do so may well incur a Japanese reaction. The decision on the part of Japan to build an explicitly intelligence-focused satellite was in response to the North Korean missile test of 1999, suggesting that Tokyo is fully capable of undertaking space-oriented responses when it is concerned.37 That, in turn, would potentially arouse the ire of China. The tragic history of Sino-Japanese relations continues to cast a baleful influence upon current interactions between the two states. If there is not a “space race” currently underway between Beijing and Tokyo, it would be most unfortunate if American actions were to precipitate one. | 3,229 | <h4>The plan is a <u>shock</u> – Japan will prolif and <u>hedge in space</u> which <u>turns case</u> </h4><p><strong>Cheng 9</strong> [Dean Cheng, Senior Research Fellow, Asian Studies Center, Davis Institute for National Security and Foreign Policy Heritage. Reflections on Sino-US Space Cooperation. EISENHOWER CENTER FOR SPACE AND DEFENSE STUDIES. Vol. 2, No. 3, December 2009. https://www.usafa.edu/app/uploads/Space_and_Defense_2_3.pdf]</p><p>Beyond the bilateral difficulties of cooperating with the PRC, <u>it is</u> also <u>important to consider</u> potential <u><strong>ramifications</u></strong> <u>of <strong><mark>Sino-US coop</strong></mark>eration <mark>in <strong>space</strong></mark> </u>on the Asian political landscape. In particular, cooperation between Washington and Beijing on space issues <u><mark>may</u></mark> well <u><mark>arouse concerns in <strong>Tokyo</u></strong></mark> and Delhi. Both of these nations have their own space programs, and while they are arguably not engaged in a “space race” with China (or each other), <u><mark>they </mark>are</u> certainly <u><mark>keep</mark>ing<mark> a <strong>close eye</strong> on </mark>developments regarding <mark>China</u></mark>.</p><p>Of particular importance is Japan. The United States relationship with Japan is arguably its most important in East Asia.</p><p>US interest in Japan should be self-evident. Japan hosts 47,000 US troops and is the linchpin for forward US presence in that hemisphere. Japan is the second largest contributor to all major international organizations that buttress US foreign policy.... <u><mark>Japan is</mark> <mark>the</u> <u><strong>bulwark</u></strong> <u>for</u></mark> <u><strong>US <mark>deterrence</u></strong> <u>and</u> <u><strong>engagement</u></strong> <u>of</u> <u><strong>China</u></strong> <u>and</u> <u><strong></mark>No</u></strong>rth <u><strong><mark>Korea</u></strong></mark>—the reason why those countries cannot assume that the <u><strong>U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates will eventually withdraw from the region<u><strong><mark>.35</p><p></strong></mark>For Japan</u>, whose “peace constitution” <u><strong>forbids</u></strong> it from using war as an instrument of state policy, <u><mark>the <strong>U</strong></mark>nited <strong><mark>S</strong></mark>tates <mark>is an <strong>essential</p><p>guarantor</strong> of</mark> its <mark>security</u>. <u><strong>Any move</u></strong></mark> <u>by the <strong>US</strong> <mark>that might <strong>undermine this</mark> view</strong> raises not only the prospect of <strong><mark>weaken</strong></mark>ing <strong><mark>US-Japan</strong></mark>ese <strong><mark>ties</strong>, but</u></mark> <u><mark>also</u></mark> potentially <u><strong><mark>affect</strong></mark>ing <strong><mark>Japan’s security policies</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>In this regard, then, <u><mark>it is <strong>essential</strong> not to</mark> engage in activities that would <strong><mark>undercut</strong> <strong>perceptions</strong> of <strong>American reliability</u></strong></mark>. Such moves, it should be noted, are not limited to those in the security realm. For example, the Nixon administration undertook several initiatives in the late 1960s and early 1970s that rocked Tokyo-Washington relations, and are still remembered as the “Nixon shocks.” While some of these were in the realm of security (including Nixon’s opening to China and the promulgation of the Nixon Doctrine), the others were in the trade area. These included a ten percent surcharge on all imports entering the US and suspended the convertibility of the dollar (i.e., removed the US from the gold standard).36</p><p>Part of the “shock” was the fundamental nature of these shifts. Even more damaging, however, was the failure of the Nixon Administration to consult their Japanese counterparts, catching them wholly off-guard. It took several years for the effects of these shocks to wear off. If the United States is intent upon expanding space relations with the PRC, then it would behoove it to consult Japan, in order to minimize the prospect of a “space shock.”</p><p><u><mark>Failing</mark> to do so <mark>may</mark> well <mark>incur</mark> a <strong><mark>Japanese reaction</u></strong></mark>. The decision on the part of Japan to build an explicitly intelligence-focused satellite was in response to the North Korean missile test of 1999, suggesting that <u><strong><mark>Tokyo</strong> is</mark> <strong>fully <mark>capable</strong> of </mark>undertaking <strong><mark>space-oriented responses</strong></mark> when it is concerned</u>.37 <u><mark>That</u></mark>, in turn, <u><mark>would</u></mark> potentially <u><strong><mark>arouse</strong></mark> the <strong><mark>ire of China</u></strong></mark>. <u>The tragic history of Sino-Japanese relations continues to cast a baleful influence upon current interactions between the two states</u>. <u>If <mark>there is not</mark> a <strong><mark>“space race”</strong> </mark>currently underway <mark>between <strong>Beijing and Tokyo</strong>, it would be</mark> most <mark>unfortunate if <strong>America</strong></mark>n actions were to <mark>precipitate one</u></mark>.</p> | 1NC | OFF | 1NC – Japan DA | 165,110 | 475 | 79,623 | ./documents/ndtceda19/CalBerkeley/FlGr/Cal%20Berkeley-Fleming-Gray-Neg-Texas-Semis.docx | 610,006 | N | Texas | Semis | Harvard BH | Turner Harper Stupek | 1AC - Test Ban
2NR - Appeasement DA | ndtceda19/CalBerkeley/FlGr/Cal%20Berkeley-Fleming-Gray-Neg-Texas-Semis.docx | null | 51,720 | FlGr | Cal Berkeley FlGr | null | Na..... | Fl..... | Mi..... | Gr..... | 19,242 | CalBerkeley | Cal Berkeley | null | null | 1,009 | ndtceda19 | NDT/CEDA 2019-20 | 2,019 | cx | college | 2 |
1,576,153 | Independently, debris hits on satellites causes Russia War. | Lewis 4 | Lewis 4 Jeffrey Lewis, in the Advanced Methods of Cooperative Study Program- Worked In the Office of the Undersecretary of Defense for Policy, Center for Defense Information, ‘4, "What if Space Were Weaponized," July 2004 pg online @ www.cdi.org/PDFs/scenarios.pdf) | e United States canceled its own ASAT program in the 1980s over concerns that the deployment of these weapons might be deeply destabilizi the forces remain on alert to conduct a number of possible contingencies, including a nuclear strike against Russia. This fact, of course, is not lost on the Russian leadership, which has been increasing its reliance on nuclear weapons to compensate for the country’s declining military might Russia dropped its pledge to refrain from first use Russian Defense Minister Sergei Ivanov reiterated that Moscow might use nuclear weapons “preemptively” in any number of contingencies, Russian observers were confident that what appeared to be a “small” attack was not a fragmentary picture of a much larger one. space-based sensors played a crucial role in assuring the Russian leadership that it was not under attack. The Russian command system, however, is no longer able to provide such reliable, early warning. The dissolution of the Soviet Union cost Moscow several radar stations in newly independent states, creating “attack corridors” through which Moscow could not see an attack launched by U.S. nuclear submarines Russia’s constellation of early-warning satellites has been allowed to decline only one or two of the six satellites remain operational leaving Russia with early warning for only six hours a day Russia will still have limited warning and will depend heavily on its space-based systems to provide warning of an American attack. Moscow would certainly have to worry that these ASATs could be used in conjunction with other space-enabled systems to disable Russia’s nuclear deterrent before the Russian leadership understood what was going on. What would happen if a piece of space debris were to [hit] a Russian early-warning satellite under these conditions Could the Russian military distinguish between an accident in space and the first phase of a U.S. attack? given the sorry state of Russia’s warning, optical imaging and signals intelligence satellites there is reason to ask the question advent of U.S. on-orbit ASATs make both the more difficult orbital plane and any warning systems moot Russians likely would have to make a judgment call state has the ability to definitively determine the cause of the satellite’s failure. United States does not maintain a sophisticated space surveillance system that would allow it to distinguish between a satellite malfunction, a debris strike or a deliberate attack and Russian space surveillance capabilities are much more limited by comparison. how confident could U.S. planners be that the Russians would be so calm if the accident in space occurred in tandem with a second false alarm, or occurred during the middle of a crisis? What might happen if the debris strike occurred shortly after a false alarm showing a missile launch? False alarms are appallingly common NORAD experienced 1,172 “moderately serious” false alarms between 1977 and 1983 The loss of an early-warning satellite could look rather ominous if it occurred during a period of major tension in the relationship. If the Lithuanian government were to close access to Kaliningrad in a fit of pique, this would trigger a major crisis between NATO and Russia. Under these circumstances, the loss of an early-warning satellite would be suspicious. It is any military’s nature during a crisis to interpret events in their worst-case light confidence is often the difference between war and peace. In times of crisis, false alarms can have a momentum of their own When information flow is disrupted whether by a deliberate attack or an accident confidence collapses and the result is panic and escalation | Russia dropped its pledge to refrain from first use Ivanov reiterated that Moscow might use nuc s preemptively What would happen if debris were to [hit] a Russian early-warning satellite Russians would make a judgment call U S does not maintain a system that would allow it to distinguish between a debris strike or attack It is any military’s nature during a crisis to interpret events in their worst-case When information flow is disrupted by attack or accident the result is escalation | Accidental Nuclear War Scenario Crisis Over Kalningrad (2010) This is the second of two scenarios that consider how U.S. space weapons might create incentives for America’s opponents to behave in dangerous ways. The previous scenario looked at the systemic risk of accidents that could arise from keeping nuclear weapons on high alert to guard against a space weapons attack. This section focuses on the risk that a single accident in space, such as a piece of space debris striking a Russian early-warning satellite, might be the catalyst for an accidental nuclear war. As we have noted in an earlier section, the United States canceled its own ASAT program in the 1980s over concerns that the deployment of these weapons might be deeply destabilizing. For all the talk about a “new relationship” between the United States and Russia, both sides retain thousands of nuclear forces on alert and configured to fight a nuclear war. When briefed about the size and status of U.S. nuclear forces, President George W. Bush reportedly asked “What do we need all these weapons for?” 43 The answer, as it was during the Cold War, is that the forces remain on alert to conduct a number of possible contingencies, including a nuclear strike against Russia. This fact, of course, is not lost on the Russian leadership, which has been increasing its reliance on nuclear weapons to compensate for the country’s declining military might. In the mid-1990s, Russia dropped its pledge to refrain from the “first use” of nuclear weapons and conducted a series of exercises in which Russian nuclear forces prepared to use nuclear weapons to repel a NATO invasion. In October 2003, Russian Defense Minister Sergei Ivanov reiterated that Moscow might use nuclear weapons “preemptively” in any number of contingencies, including a NATO attack. 44 So, it remains business as usual with U.S. and Russian nuclear forces. And business as usual includes the occasional false alarm of a nuclear attack. There have been several of these incidents over the years. In September 1983, as a relatively new Soviet early-warning satellite moved into position to monitor U.S. missile fields in North Dakota, the sun lined up in just such a way as to fool the Russian satellite into reporting that half a dozen U.S. missiles had been launched at the Soviet Union. Perhaps mindful that a brand new satellite might malfunction, the officer in charge of the command center that monitored data from the early-warning satellites refused to pass the alert to his superiors. He reportedly explained his caution by saying: “When people start a war, they don’t start it with only five missiles. You can do little damage with just five missiles.” 45 In January 1995, Norwegian scientists launched a sounding rocket on a trajectory similar to one that a U.S. Trident missile might take if it were launched to blind Russian radars with a high 26 What if Space Were Weaponized? altitude nuclear detonation. The incident was apparently serious enough that, the next day, Russian President Boris Yeltsin stated that he had activated his “nuclear football” – a device that allows the Russian president to communicate with his military advisors and review his options for launching his arsenal. In this case, the Russian early-warning satellites could clearly see that no attack was under way and the crisis passed without incident. 46 In both cases, Russian observers were confident that what appeared to be a “small” attack was not a fragmentary picture of a much larger one. In the case of the Norwegian sounding rocket, space-based sensors played a crucial role in assuring the Russian leadership that it was not under attack. The Russian command system, however, is no longer able to provide such reliable, early warning. The dissolution of the Soviet Union cost Moscow several radar stations in newly independent states, creating “attack corridors” through which Moscow could not see an attack launched by U.S. nuclear submarines. 47 Further, Russia’s constellation of early-warning satellites has been allowed to decline – only one or two of the six satellites remain operational, leaving Russia with early warning for only six hours a day. Russia is attempting to reconstitute its constellation of early-warning satellites, with several launches planned in the next few years. But Russia will still have limited warning and will depend heavily on its space-based systems to provide warning of an American attack. 48 As the previous section explained, the Pentagon is contemplating military missions in space that will improve U.S. ability to cripple Russian nuclear forces in a crisis before they can execute an attack on the United States. Anti-satellite weapons, in this scenario, would blind Russian reconnaissance and warning satellites and knock out communications satellites. Such strikes might be the prelude to a full-scale attack, or a limited effort, as attempted in a war game at Schriever Air Force Base, to conduct “early deterrence strikes” to signal U.S. resolve and control escalation. 49 By 2010, the United States may, in fact, have an arsenal of ASATs (perhaps even on orbit 24/7) ready to conduct these kinds of missions – to coerce opponents and, if necessary, support preemptive attacks. Moscow would certainly have to worry that these ASATs could be used in conjunction with other space-enabled systems – for example, long-range strike systems that could attack targets in less than 90 minutes – to disable Russia’s nuclear deterrent before the Russian leadership understood what was going on. What would happen if a piece of space debris were to disable [hit] a Russian early-warning satellite under these conditions? Could the Russian military distinguish between an accident in space and the first phase of a U.S. attack? Most Russian early-warning satellites are in elliptical Molniya orbits (a few are in GEO) and thus difficult to attack from the ground or air. At a minimum, Moscow would probably have some tactical warning of such a suspicious launch, but given the sorry state of Russia’s warning, optical imaging and signals intelligence satellites there is reason to ask the question. Further, the advent of U.S. on-orbit ASATs, as now envisioned 50 could make both the more difficult orbital plane and any warning systems moot. The unpleasant truth is that the Russians likely would have to make a judgment call. No state has the ability to definitively determine the cause of the satellite’s failure. Even the Accidental Nuclear War Scenarios 27 United States does not maintain (nor is it likely to have in place by 2010) a sophisticated space surveillance system that would allow it to distinguish between a satellite malfunction, a debris strike or a deliberate attack – and Russian space surveillance capabilities are much more limited by comparison. Even the risk assessments for collision with debris are speculative, particularly for the unique orbits in which Russian early-warning satellites operate. During peacetime, it is easy to imagine that the Russians would conclude that the loss of a satellite was either a malfunction or a debris strike. But how confident could U.S. planners be that the Russians would be so calm if the accident in space occurred in tandem with a second false alarm, or occurred during the middle of a crisis? What might happen if the debris strike occurred shortly after a false alarm showing a missile launch? False alarms are appallingly common – according to information obtained under the Freedom of Information Act, the U.S.-Canadian North American Aerospace Defense Command (NORAD) experienced 1,172 “moderately serious” false alarms between 1977 and 1983 – an average of almost three false alarms per week. Comparable information is not available about the Russian system, but there is no reason to believe that it is any more reliable. 51 Assessing the likelihood of these sorts of coincidences is difficult because Russia has never provided data about the frequency or duration of false alarms; nor indicated how seriously earlywarning data is taken by Russian leaders. Moreover, there is no reliable estimate of the debris risk for Russian satellites in highly elliptical orbits. 52 The important point, however, is that such a coincidence would only appear suspicious if the United States were in the business of disabling satellites – in other words, there is much less risk if Washington does not develop ASATs. The loss of an early-warning satellite could look rather ominous if it occurred during a period of major tension in the relationship. While NATO no longer sees Russia as much of a threat, the same cannot be said of the converse. Despite the warm talk, Russian leaders remain wary of NATO expansion, particularly the effect expansion may have on the Baltic port of Kaliningrad. Although part of Russia, Kaliningrad is separated from the rest of Russia by Lithuania and Poland. Russia has already complained about its decreasing lack of access to the port, particularly the uncooperative attitude of the Lithuanian government. 53 News reports suggest that an edgy Russia may have moved tactical nuclear weapons into the enclave. 54 If the Lithuanian government were to close access to Kaliningrad in a fit of pique, this would trigger a major crisis between NATO and Russia. Under these circumstances, the loss of an early-warning satellite would be suspicious. It is any military’s nature during a crisis to interpret events in their worst-case light. For example, consider the coincidences that occurred in early September 1956, during the extraordinarily tense period in international relations marked by the Suez Crisis and Hungarian uprising. 55 On one evening the White House received messages indicating: 1. the Turkish Air Force had gone on alert in response to unidentified aircraft penetrating its airspace; 2. one hundred Soviet MiG-15s were flying over Syria; 3. a British Canberra bomber had been shot down over Syria, most likely by a MiG; and 4. The Russian fleet was moving through the Dardanelles. Gen. Andrew 28 What if Space Were Weaponized? Goodpaster was reported to have worried that the confluence of events “might trigger off … the NATO operations plan” that called for a nuclear strike on the Soviet Union. Yet, all of these reports were false. The “jets” over Turkey were a flock of swans; the Soviet MiGs over Syria were a smaller, routine escort returning the president from a state visit to Moscow; the bomber crashed due to mechanical difficulties; and the Soviet fleet was beginning long-scheduled exercises. In an important sense, these were not “coincidences” but rather different manifestations of a common failure – human error resulting from extreme tension of an international crisis. As one author noted, “The detection and misinterpretation of these events, against the context of world tensions from Hungary and Suez, was the first major example of how the size and complexity of worldwide electronic warning systems could, at certain critical times, create momentum of its own.” Perhaps most worrisome, the United States might be blithely unaware of the degree to which the Russians were concerned about its actions and inadvertently escalate a crisis. During the early 1980s, the Soviet Union suffered a major “war scare” during which time its leadership concluded that bilateral relations were rapidly declining. This war scare was driven in part by the rhetoric of the Reagan administration, fortified by the selective reading of intelligence. During this period, NATO conducted a major command post exercise, Able Archer, that caused some elements of the Soviet military to raise their alert status. American officials were stunned to learn, after the fact, that the Kremlin had been acutely nervous about an American first strike during this period. 56 All of these incidents have a common theme – that confidence is often the difference between war and peace. In times of crisis, false alarms can have a momentum of their own. As in the second scenario in this monograph, the lesson is that commanders rely on the steady flow of reliable information. When that information flow is disrupted – whether by a deliberate attack or an accident – confidence collapses and the result is panic and escalation. Introducing ASAT weapons into this mix is all the more dangerous, because such weapons target the elements of the command system that keep leaders aware, informed and in control. As a result, the mere presence of such weapons is corrosive to the confidence that allows national nuclear forces to operate safely. | 12,579 | <h4>Independently, debris hits on satellites causes Russia War. </h4><p><u><strong>Lewis 4 </u></strong>Jeffrey Lewis, in the Advanced Methods of Cooperative Study Program- Worked In the Office of the Undersecretary of Defense for Policy, Center for Defense Information, ‘4, "What if Space Were Weaponized," July 2004 pg online @ www.cdi.org/PDFs/scenarios.pdf)</p><p>Accidental Nuclear War Scenario Crisis Over Kalningrad (2010) This is the second of two scenarios that consider how U.S. space weapons might create incentives for America’s opponents to behave in dangerous ways. The previous scenario looked at the systemic risk of accidents that could arise from keeping nuclear weapons on high alert to guard against a space weapons attack. This section focuses on the risk that a single accident in space, such as a piece of space debris striking a Russian early-warning satellite, might be the catalyst for an accidental nuclear war. As we have noted in an earlier section, th<u><strong>e United States canceled its own ASAT program in the 1980s over concerns that the deployment of these weapons might be deeply destabilizi</u></strong>ng. For all the talk about a “new relationship” between the United States and Russia, both sides retain thousands of nuclear forces on alert and configured to fight a nuclear war. When briefed about the size and status of U.S. nuclear forces, President George W. Bush reportedly asked “What do we need all these weapons for?” 43 The answer, as it was during the Cold War, is that <u><strong>the forces remain on alert to conduct a number of possible contingencies, including a nuclear strike against Russia. This fact, of course, is not lost on the Russian leadership, which has been increasing its reliance on nuclear weapons to compensate for the country’s declining military might</u></strong>. In the mid-1990s, <u><strong><mark>Russia dropped its pledge to refrain from</u></strong></mark> the “<u><strong><mark>first use</u></strong></mark>” of nuclear weapons and conducted a series of exercises in which Russian nuclear forces prepared to use nuclear weapons to repel a NATO invasion. In October 2003, <u><strong>Russian Defense Minister</u></strong> <u><strong>Sergei <mark>Ivanov reiterated that Moscow might use nuc</mark>lear weapon<mark>s</mark> “<mark>preemptively</mark>” in any number of contingencies, </u></strong>including a NATO attack. 44 So, it remains business as usual with U.S. and Russian nuclear forces. And business as usual includes the occasional false alarm of a nuclear attack. There have been several of these incidents over the years. In September 1983, as a relatively new Soviet early-warning satellite moved into position to monitor U.S. missile fields in North Dakota, the sun lined up in just such a way as to fool the Russian satellite into reporting that half a dozen U.S. missiles had been launched at the Soviet Union. Perhaps mindful that a brand new satellite might malfunction, the officer in charge of the command center that monitored data from the early-warning satellites refused to pass the alert to his superiors. He reportedly explained his caution by saying: “When people start a war, they don’t start it with only five missiles. You can do little damage with just five missiles.” 45 In January 1995, Norwegian scientists launched a sounding rocket on a trajectory similar to one that a U.S. Trident missile might take if it were launched to blind Russian radars with a high 26 What if Space Were Weaponized? altitude nuclear detonation. The incident was apparently serious enough that, the next day, Russian President Boris Yeltsin stated that he had activated his “nuclear football” – a device that allows the Russian president to communicate with his military advisors and review his options for launching his arsenal. In this case, the Russian early-warning satellites could clearly see that no attack was under way and the crisis passed without incident. 46 In both cases, <u><strong>Russian observers were confident that what appeared to be a “small” attack was not a fragmentary picture of a much larger one.</u></strong> In the case of the Norwegian sounding rocket, <u><strong>space-based sensors played a crucial role in assuring the Russian leadership that it was not under attack. The Russian command system, however, is no longer able to provide such reliable, early warning. The dissolution of the Soviet Union cost Moscow several radar stations in newly independent states, creating “attack corridors” through which Moscow could not see an attack launched by U.S. nuclear submarines</u></strong>. 47 Further, <u><strong>Russia’s constellation of early-warning satellites has been allowed to decline</u></strong> – <u><strong>only one or two of the six satellites remain operational</u></strong>, <u><strong>leaving Russia with early warning for only six hours a day</u></strong>. Russia is attempting to reconstitute its constellation of early-warning satellites, with several launches planned in the next few years. But <u><strong>Russia will still have limited warning and will depend heavily on its space-based systems to provide warning of an American attack.</u></strong> 48 As the previous section explained, the Pentagon is contemplating military missions in space that will improve U.S. ability to cripple Russian nuclear forces in a crisis before they can execute an attack on the United States. Anti-satellite weapons, in this scenario, would blind Russian reconnaissance and warning satellites and knock out communications satellites. Such strikes might be the prelude to a full-scale attack, or a limited effort, as attempted in a war game at Schriever Air Force Base, to conduct “early deterrence strikes” to signal U.S. resolve and control escalation. 49 By 2010, the United States may, in fact, have an arsenal of ASATs (perhaps even on orbit 24/7) ready to conduct these kinds of missions – to coerce opponents and, if necessary, support preemptive attacks. <u><strong>Moscow would certainly have to worry that these ASATs could be used in conjunction with other space-enabled systems</u></strong> – for example, long-range strike systems that could attack targets in less than 90 minutes – <u><strong>to disable Russia’s nuclear deterrent before the Russian leadership understood what was going on. <mark>What would happen if</mark> a piece of space <mark>debris were to</mark> </u></strong>disable <u><strong><mark>[hit] a Russian early-warning satellite</mark> under these conditions</u></strong>? <u><strong>Could the Russian military distinguish between an accident in space and the first phase of a U.S. attack?</u></strong> Most Russian early-warning satellites are in elliptical Molniya orbits (a few are in GEO) and thus difficult to attack from the ground or air. At a minimum, Moscow would probably have some tactical warning of such a suspicious launch, but <u><strong>given the sorry state of Russia’s warning, optical imaging and signals intelligence satellites there is reason to ask the question</u></strong>. Further, the <u><strong>advent of U.S. on-orbit ASATs</u></strong>, as now envisioned 50 could <u><strong>make both the more difficult orbital plane and any warning systems moot</u></strong>. The unpleasant truth is that the <u><strong><mark>Russians</mark> likely <mark>would</mark> have to <mark>make a judgment call</u></strong></mark>. No <u><strong>state has the ability to definitively determine the cause of the satellite’s failure. </u></strong>Even the Accidental Nuclear War Scenarios 27 <u><strong><mark>U</mark>nited <mark>S</mark>tates <mark>does not maintain</u></strong></mark> (nor is it likely to have in place by 2010) <u><strong><mark>a</mark> sophisticated space surveillance <mark>system that would allow it to distinguish between</mark> a satellite malfunction, <mark>a debris strike or</mark> a deliberate <mark>attack</u></strong></mark> – <u><strong>and Russian space surveillance capabilities are much more limited by comparison. </u></strong>Even the risk assessments for collision with debris are speculative, particularly for the unique orbits in which Russian early-warning satellites operate. During peacetime, it is easy to imagine that the Russians would conclude that the loss of a satellite was either a malfunction or a debris strike. But <u><strong>how confident could U.S. planners be that the Russians would be so calm if the accident in space occurred in tandem with a second false alarm, or occurred during the middle of a crisis? What might happen if the debris strike occurred shortly after a false alarm showing a missile launch? False alarms are appallingly common</u></strong> – according to information obtained under the Freedom of Information Act, the U.S.-Canadian North American Aerospace Defense Command (<u><strong>NORAD</u></strong>) <u><strong>experienced 1,172 “moderately serious” false alarms between 1977 and 1983</u></strong> – an average of almost three false alarms per week. Comparable information is not available about the Russian system, but there is no reason to believe that it is any more reliable. 51 Assessing the likelihood of these sorts of coincidences is difficult because Russia has never provided data about the frequency or duration of false alarms; nor indicated how seriously earlywarning data is taken by Russian leaders. Moreover, there is no reliable estimate of the debris risk for Russian satellites in highly elliptical orbits. 52 The important point, however, is that such a coincidence would only appear suspicious if the United States were in the business of disabling satellites – in other words, there is much less risk if Washington does not develop ASATs. <u><strong>The loss of an early-warning satellite could look rather ominous if it occurred during a period of major tension in the relationship.</u></strong> While NATO no longer sees Russia as much of a threat, the same cannot be said of the converse. Despite the warm talk, Russian leaders remain wary of NATO expansion, particularly the effect expansion may have on the Baltic port of Kaliningrad. Although part of Russia, Kaliningrad is separated from the rest of Russia by Lithuania and Poland. Russia has already complained about its decreasing lack of access to the port, particularly the uncooperative attitude of the Lithuanian government. 53 News reports suggest that an edgy Russia may have moved tactical nuclear weapons into the enclave. 54 <u><strong>If the Lithuanian government were to close access to Kaliningrad in a fit of pique, this would trigger a major crisis between NATO and Russia. Under these circumstances, the loss of an early-warning satellite would be suspicious. <mark>It is any military’s nature during a crisis to interpret events in their worst-case</mark> light</u></strong>. For example, consider the coincidences that occurred in early September 1956, during the extraordinarily tense period in international relations marked by the Suez Crisis and Hungarian uprising. 55 On one evening the White House received messages indicating: 1. the Turkish Air Force had gone on alert in response to unidentified aircraft penetrating its airspace; 2. one hundred Soviet MiG-15s were flying over Syria; 3. a British Canberra bomber had been shot down over Syria, most likely by a MiG; and 4. The Russian fleet was moving through the Dardanelles. Gen. Andrew 28 What if Space Were Weaponized? Goodpaster was reported to have worried that the confluence of events “might trigger off … the NATO operations plan” that called for a nuclear strike on the Soviet Union. Yet, all of these reports were false. The “jets” over Turkey were a flock of swans; the Soviet MiGs over Syria were a smaller, routine escort returning the president from a state visit to Moscow; the bomber crashed due to mechanical difficulties; and the Soviet fleet was beginning long-scheduled exercises. In an important sense, these were not “coincidences” but rather different manifestations of a common failure – human error resulting from extreme tension of an international crisis. As one author noted, “The detection and misinterpretation of these events, against the context of world tensions from Hungary and Suez, was the first major example of how the size and complexity of worldwide electronic warning systems could, at certain critical times, create momentum of its own.” Perhaps most worrisome, the United States might be blithely unaware of the degree to which the Russians were concerned about its actions and inadvertently escalate a crisis. During the early 1980s, the Soviet Union suffered a major “war scare” during which time its leadership concluded that bilateral relations were rapidly declining. This war scare was driven in part by the rhetoric of the Reagan administration, fortified by the selective reading of intelligence. During this period, NATO conducted a major command post exercise, Able Archer, that caused some elements of the Soviet military to raise their alert status. American officials were stunned to learn, after the fact, that the Kremlin had been acutely nervous about an American first strike during this period. 56 All of these incidents have a common theme – that <u><strong>confidence is often the difference between war and peace. In times of crisis, false alarms can have a momentum of their own</u></strong>. As in the second scenario in this monograph, the lesson is that commanders rely on the steady flow of reliable information. <u><strong><mark>When</u></strong></mark> that <u><strong><mark>information flow is disrupted</u></strong></mark> – <u><strong>whether <mark>by</mark> a deliberate <mark>attack or</mark> an <mark>accident</u></strong></mark> – <u><strong>confidence collapses and <mark>the result is</mark> panic and <mark>escalation</u></strong></mark>. Introducing ASAT weapons into this mix is all the more dangerous, because such weapons target the elements of the command system that keep leaders aware, informed and in control. As a result, the mere presence of such weapons is corrosive to the confidence that allows national nuclear forces to operate safely. </p> | 1AC | null | 1AC: Sustainable Space Advantage | 172,565 | 192 | 45,534 | ./documents/hsld21/SouthlakeCarroll/ka/Southlake%20Carroll-kaginele-Aff-11%20-%20arizona%20state-Round2.docx | 899,028 | A | 11 - arizona state | 2 | hamilton al | scott wheeler | 1ac - ptd
1nc - technoorientalism k
2nr - k | hsld21/SouthlakeCarroll/ka/Southlake%20Carroll-kaginele-Aff-11%20-%20arizona%20state-Round2.docx | null | 75,337 | prka | Southlake Carroll prka | null | pr..... | ka..... | null | null | 25,168 | SouthlakeCarroll | Southlake Carroll | TX | null | 1,029 | hsld21 | HS LD 2021-22 | 2,021 | ld | hs | 1 |
1,939,345 | Climate change causes extinction – | Sprat 19 | Sprat and Dunlop 19 (David Spratt and Ian Dunlop, *Research Director for Breakthrough National Centre for Climate Restoration and co-author of Climate Code Red: The case for emergency action; **member of the Club of Rome AND formerly an international oil, gas and coal industry executive, chairman of the Australian Coal Association, chief executive of the Australian Institute of Company Directors, and chair of the Australian Greenhouse Office Experts Group on Emissions Trading, "Existential climate-related security risk: A scenario approach," Breakthrough National Centre for Climate Restoration, 5-30-2019, https://docs.wixstatic.com/ugd/148cb0_90dc2a2637f348edae45943a88da04d4.pdf, Date Accessed: 7-5-2019, SB) | there is broad scientific acceptance that system tipping-points for the West Antarctic Ice Sheet and a sea-ice-free Arctic summer were passed well before 1.5°C of warming, for the Greenland Ice Sheet well before 2°C, and for widespread permafrost loss and large-scale Amazon drought and dieback by 2.5°C. The “hothouse Earth” scenario has been realised, and Earth is headed for another degree or more of warming, since human greenhouse emissions are significant. seas may eventually rise by more than 25 metres. Thirty-five percent of the global land area, and 55 percent of the global population, are subject to more than 20 days a year of lethal heat conditions, beyond the threshold of human survivability. The destabilisation of the Jet Stream has significantly affected the intensity and geographical distribution of the Asian and West African monsoons and, with the further slowing of the Gulf Stream, is impinging on life support systems in Europe. North America suffers from devastating weather extremes including wildfires, heatwaves, drought and inundation. The summer monsoons in China have failed, and water flows into the great rivers of Asia are severely reduced by more than one-third of the Himalayan ice sheet. Glacial loss reaches 70 percent in the Andes, and rainfall in Mexico and central America falls by half. permanent El Nino conditions prevail. Aridification emerges over more than 30 percent of the world’s land surface. Desertification is severe in southern Africa, the southern Mediterranean, west Asia, the Middle East, inland Australia and across the U S ecosystems collapse, including coral reef systems, the Amazon rainforest and in the Arctic. nations and regions become unviable. Deadly heat conditions persist for more than 100 days per year in West Africa, tropical South America, the Middle East and South-East Asia, which with land degradation and rising sea levels contributes to a billion people being displaced. Water availability decreases sharply ), affecting two billion people worldwide. Ag becomes nonviable in the dry subtropics. the world see a significant drop in food production and increasing extreme weather events, including heat waves, floods and storms. Food production is inadequate to feed the global population and food prices skyrocket, as a consequence of a one-fifth decline in crop yields, a decline in the nutrition content of crops, a catastrophic decline in insect populations, desertification, monsoon failure and chronic water shortages, and conditions too hot for human habitation agriculturally-important river deltas and the world’s most populous cities are abandoned. small islands become uninhabitable. Ten percent of Bangladesh is inundated, displacing 15 million people. even for 2°C of warming, more than a billion people may need to be relocated due to sea-level rise, and the scale of destruction is beyond our capacity to model, | 55 percent of the population subject to 20 days of lethal heat impinging on life support in Europe wate reduced by one-third Glacial loss permanent El Nino conditions Aridification over 30 percent ecosystems collapse coral reef Amazon Arctic Deadly heat conditions 100 days per year billion people displaced Water availability decreases Ag nonviable Food inadequate catastrophic decline in insect populations most populous cities abandoned destruction beyond our capacity to model | 2050: By 2050, there is broad scientific acceptance that system tipping-points for the West Antarctic Ice Sheet and a sea-ice-free Arctic summer were passed well before 1.5°C of warming, for the Greenland Ice Sheet well before 2°C, and for widespread permafrost loss and large-scale Amazon drought and dieback by 2.5°C. The “hothouse Earth” scenario has been realised, and Earth is headed for another degree or more of warming, especially since human greenhouse emissions are still significant. While sea levels have risen 0.5 metres by 2050, the increase may be 2–3 metres by 2100, and it is understood from historical analogues that seas may eventually rise by more than 25 metres. Thirty-five percent of the global land area, and 55 percent of the global population, are subject to more than 20 days a year of lethal heat conditions, beyond the threshold of human survivability. The destabilisation of the Jet Stream has very significantly affected the intensity and geographical distribution of the Asian and West African monsoons and, together with the further slowing of the Gulf Stream, is impinging on life support systems in Europe. North America suffers from devastating weather extremes including wildfires, heatwaves, drought and inundation. The summer monsoons in China have failed, and water flows into the great rivers of Asia are severely reduced by the loss of more than one-third of the Himalayan ice sheet. Glacial loss reaches 70 percent in the Andes, and rainfall in Mexico and central America falls by half. Semi-permanent El Nino conditions prevail. Aridification emerges over more than 30 percent of the world’s land surface. Desertification is severe in southern Africa, the southern Mediterranean, west Asia, the Middle East, inland Australia and across the south-western United States. Impacts: A number of ecosystems collapse, including coral reef systems, the Amazon rainforest and in the Arctic. Some poorer nations and regions, which lack capacity to provide artificially-cooled environments for their populations, become unviable. Deadly heat conditions persist for more than 100 days per year in West Africa, tropical South America, the Middle East and South-East Asia, which together with land degradation and rising sea levels contributes to 21 perhaps a billion people being displaced. Water availability decreases sharply in the most affected regions at lower latitudes (dry tropics and subtropics), affecting about two billion people worldwide. Agriculture becomes nonviable in the dry subtropics. Most regions in the world see a significant drop in food production and increasing numbers of extreme weather events, including heat waves, floods and storms. Food production is inadequate to feed the global population and food prices skyrocket, as a consequence of a one-fifth decline in crop yields, a decline in the nutrition content of food crops, a catastrophic decline in insect populations, desertification, monsoon failure and chronic water shortages, and conditions too hot for human habitation in significant food-growing regions. The lower reaches of the agriculturally-important river deltas such as the Mekong, Ganges and Nile are inundated, and significant sectors of some of the world’s most populous cities — including Chennai, Mumbai, Jakarta, Guangzhou, Tianjin, Hong Kong, Ho Chi Minh City, Shanghai, Lagos, Bangkok and Manila — are abandoned. Some small islands become uninhabitable. Ten percent of Bangladesh is inundated, displacing 15 million people. According to the Global Challenges Foundation’s Global Catastrophic Risks 2018 report, even for 2°C of warming, more than a billion people may need to be relocated due to sea-level rise, and In high-end scenarios “the scale of destruction is beyond our capacity to model, with a high likelihood of human civilization coming to an end”. 22 | 3,848 | <h4>Climate change causes extinction – </h4><p><strong>Sprat</strong> and Dunlop <strong>19</strong> (David Spratt and Ian Dunlop, *Research Director for Breakthrough National Centre for Climate Restoration and co-author of Climate Code Red: The case for emergency action; **member of the Club of Rome AND formerly an international oil, gas and coal industry executive, chairman of the Australian Coal Association, chief executive of the Australian Institute of Company Directors, and chair of the Australian Greenhouse Office Experts Group on Emissions Trading, "Existential climate-related security risk: A scenario approach," Breakthrough National Centre for Climate Restoration, 5-30-2019, https://docs.wixstatic.com/ugd/148cb0_90dc2a2637f348edae45943a88da04d4.pdf, Date Accessed: 7-5-2019, SB)</p><p>2050: By 2050, <u>there is <strong>broad scientific acceptance</strong> that system tipping-points for the West Antarctic Ice Sheet and a sea-ice-free Arctic summer were passed well before 1.5°C of warming, for the Greenland Ice Sheet well before 2°C, and for widespread permafrost loss and large-scale Amazon drought and dieback by 2.5°C. <strong>The “hothouse Earth” scenario has been realised</strong>, and Earth is headed for another degree or more of warming,</u> especially <u>since human greenhouse emissions are</u> still <u>significant.</u> While sea levels have risen 0.5 metres by 2050, the increase may be 2–3 metres by 2100, and it is understood from historical analogues that <u>seas may eventually rise by more than 25 metres. Thirty-five percent of the global land area, and <mark>55 percent of the</mark> global <mark>population</mark>, are <mark>subject to </mark>more than <mark>20 days </mark>a year <mark>of lethal heat</mark> conditions, <strong>beyond the threshold of human survivability. </strong>The destabilisation of the Jet Stream has</u> very <u>significantly affected the intensity and geographical distribution of the Asian and West African monsoons and, </u>together <u>with the further slowing of the Gulf Stream, is <mark>impinging on life support</mark> systems <mark>in Europe</mark>. North America suffers from <strong>devastating weather extremes including wildfires, heatwaves, drought and inundation.</strong> The summer monsoons in China have failed, and <mark>wate</mark>r flows into the great rivers of Asia are severely <mark>reduced by</u></mark> the loss of <u>more than <mark>one-third</mark> of the Himalayan ice sheet. <mark>Glacial loss</mark> reaches 70 percent in the Andes, and rainfall in Mexico and central America falls by half.</u> Semi-<u><mark>permanent El Nino conditions</mark> prevail. <mark>Aridification</mark> emerges <mark>over</mark> more than <mark>30 percent</mark> of the world’s land surface. Desertification is severe in southern Africa, the southern Mediterranean, west Asia, the Middle East, inland Australia and across the </u>south-western <u>U</u>nited <u>S</u>tates. Impacts: A number of <u><strong><mark>ecosystems collapse</strong></mark>, including <strong><mark>coral reef</mark> systems, the <mark>Amazon</mark> rainforest and in the <mark>Arctic</mark>. </u></strong>Some poorer <u>nations and regions</u>, which lack capacity to provide artificially-cooled environments for their populations, <u>become unviable. <mark>Deadly heat conditions</mark> persist for more than <mark>100 days per year</mark> in West Africa, tropical South America, the Middle East and South-East Asia, which</u> together <u>with land degradation and rising sea levels contributes to</u> 21 perhaps <u>a <mark>billion people</mark> being <mark>displaced</mark>. <strong><mark>Water availability decreases</mark> </strong>sharply</u> in the most affected regions at lower latitudes (dry tropics and subtropics<u>), affecting</u> about <u>two billion people worldwide. <strong><mark>Ag</u></strong></mark>riculture <u><strong>becomes <mark>nonviable</strong></mark> in the dry subtropics. </u>Most regions in <u>the world see a significant drop in food production and increasing</u> numbers of <u><strong>extreme weather events</strong>, including heat waves, floods and storms. <strong><mark>Food</mark> production is <mark>inadequate</strong></mark> to feed the global population and food prices skyrocket, as a consequence of a one-fifth decline in crop yields, a decline in the nutrition content of</u> food <u>crops, a <mark>catastrophic decline in insect</mark> <mark>populations</mark>, desertification, monsoon failure and <strong>chronic water shortages</strong>, and conditions <strong>too hot for human habitation</strong> </u>in significant food-growing regions. The lower reaches of the <u>agriculturally-important river deltas</u> such as the Mekong, Ganges and Nile are inundated, <u>and</u> significant sectors of some of <u>the world’s <mark>most populous cities</u></mark> — including Chennai, Mumbai, Jakarta, Guangzhou, Tianjin, Hong Kong, Ho Chi Minh City, Shanghai, Lagos, Bangkok and Manila — <u>are <strong><mark>abandoned</strong></mark>.</u> Some <u>small islands become <strong>uninhabitable</strong>. Ten percent of Bangladesh is inundated, displacing 15 million people. </u>According to the Global Challenges Foundation’s Global Catastrophic Risks 2018 report, <u>even for 2°C of warming, more than a billion people may need to be relocated due to sea-level rise, and</u> In high-end scenarios “<u>the scale of <mark>destruction</mark> is <mark>beyond our capacity to model</mark>, </u>with a high likelihood of human civilization coming to an end”. 22</p> | 1ac | 1ac--innovation | null | 5,227 | 2,313 | 57,222 | ./documents/hspolicy20/Mamaroneck/GuPe/Mamaroneck-Gupta-Peters-Aff-1st%20and%202nd%20Year%20National%20Championships%20at%20Woodward%20Academy-Round3.docx | 734,401 | A | 1st and 2nd Year National Championships at Woodward Academy | 3 | Peninsula DG | Mokhemar, Miriam | 1ac -- antitrust
2nr -- disease good adv cp | hspolicy20/Mamaroneck/GuPe/Mamaroneck-Gupta-Peters-Aff-1st%20and%202nd%20Year%20National%20Championships%20at%20Woodward%20Academy-Round3.docx | null | 62,635 | GuPe | Mamaroneck GuPe | null | Ro..... | Gu..... | Lu..... | Pe..... | 21,706 | Mamaroneck | Mamaroneck | NY | null | 1,019 | hspolicy20 | HS Policy 2020-21 | 2,020 | cx | hs | 2 |
1,899,366 | The net benefit is delgado—rejecting piecemeal reform is violent paternalistic and wrong | Delgado 13 | Richard Delgado 13, J.D., John J. Sparkman Chair of Law, Alabama School of Law, “Does Critical Legal Studies Have What Minorities Want?” in Arguing About Law, ed. Aileen Kavanagh, John Oberdiek, Routledge, pg. 589-590 | For minorities, however, that rights minimize many forms of coercion is of enormous importance 42 The CLS critique of piecemeal reform is familiar, imperialistic and wrong. Minorities know from bitter experience that occasional court victories do not mean the Promised Land is at hand.13 The critique is imperialistic in that it tells minorities and other oppressed peoples how they should interpret events affecting them." A court order directing a housing authority to disburse funds for heating in subsidized housing may postpone the revolution, or it may not. In the meantime, the order keeps a number of poor families warm. This may mean more to them than it does to a comfortable academic working in a warm office. It smacks of paternalism to assert that the possibility of revolution later outweighs the certainty of heat now, unless there is evidence for that possibility. The Crits do not offer such evidence. Indeed, some incremental changes may bring revolutionary changes closer, not push them further away. Not all small reforms induce complacency; some may whet the appetite for further combat. The welfare family may hold a tenants' union meeting in their heated living room. CLS scholars' critique of piecemeal reform often misses these possibilities, and neglects die question of whether total change, when it comes, will be what we want. | The critique of piecemeal reform is imperialistic and wrong. Minorities know that victories do not mean the Promised Land A court order directing a housing authority to disburse funds for heating may postpone the revolution the order keeps a number of poor families warm. This may mean more to them than a comfortable academic . It smacks of paternalism to assert that the possibility of revolution later outweighs the certainty of heat now some incremental changes may bring revolutionary changes closer, Not all small reforms induce complacency some may whet the appetite for further combat critique of piecemeal reform often misses these possibilities | For minorities, however, that rights minimize many forms of coercion is of enormous importance. At the same time, the psychic rewards that Crits believe will result from a rightless interracial "community" are far from our experience. Even if such rewards were achievable, they would necessarily rank lower than simple security on our stale of need. Of course, a Utopian community of the sort Crits advocate might provide minorities with both security and psychic satisfaction. As will be shown later, however, that hope is probably vain.56 In short, the two groups sec rights differently. White CLS members see rights as oppressive, alienating and mystifying. For minorities, they are invigorating cloaks of safety that unite us in a common bond. Instead of coming to grips with the different function of rights for the two groups, Crits insist that minorities adopt their viewpoint, labeling disagreement on our part false consciousness" or a lack of political sophistication. 2. The CLS critique of piecemeal reform Critical scholars reject the idea of piecemeal reform. Incremental change, they argue, merely postpones the wholesale reformation that must occur to create a decent society.'8 Even worse, an unfair social system survives by using piecemeal reform to disguise and legitimize oppression.19 Those who control the system weaken resistance by pointing to the occasional concession to, or periodic court victory of, a black plaintiff or worker as evidence that the system is fair and just.'10 In fact, Crits believe that teaching the common law or using the case method in law school is a disguised means of preaching incre-mentalism and thereby maintaining the current power structure.41 To avoid this, CLS scholars urge in an unabashedly political fashion.42 The CLS critique of piecemeal reform is familiar, imperialistic and wrong. Minorities know from bitter experience that occasional court victories do not mean the Promised Land is at hand.13 The critique is imperialistic in that it tells minorities and other oppressed peoples how they should interpret events affecting them." A court order directing a housing authority to disburse funds for heating in subsidized housing may postpone the revolution, or it may not. In the meantime, the order keeps a number of poor families warm. This may mean more to them than it does to a comfortable academic working in a warm office. It smacks of paternalism to assert that the possibility of revolution later outweighs the certainty of heat now, unless there is evidence for that possibility. The Crits do not offer such evidence. Indeed, some incremental changes may bring revolutionary changes closer, not push them further away. Not all small reforms induce complacency; some may whet the appetite for further combat. The welfare family may hold a tenants' union meeting in their heated living room. CLS scholars' critique of piecemeal reform often misses these possibilities, and neglects die question of whether total change, when it comes, will be what we want. | 3,031 | <h4>The net benefit is delgado—rejecting piecemeal reform is violent paternalistic and wrong</h4><p>Richard<strong> Delgado 13</strong>, J.D., John J. Sparkman Chair of Law, Alabama School of Law,<u> “Does Critical Legal Studies Have What Minorities Want?” in Arguing About Law, ed. Aileen Kavanagh, John Oberdiek, Routledge, pg. 589-590</p><p>For minorities, however, that rights minimize many forms of coercion is of <strong>enormous importance</u></strong>. At the same time, the psychic rewards that Crits believe will result from a rightless interracial "community" are far from our experience. Even if such rewards were achievable, they would necessarily rank lower than simple security on our stale of need. Of course, a Utopian community of the sort Crits advocate might provide minorities with both security and psychic satisfaction. As will be shown later, however, that hope is probably vain.56 In short, the two groups sec rights differently. White CLS members see rights as oppressive, alienating and mystifying. For minorities, they are invigorating cloaks of safety that unite us in a common bond. Instead of coming to grips with the different function of rights for the two groups, Crits insist that minorities adopt their viewpoint, labeling disagreement on our part false consciousness" or a lack of political sophistication. 2. The CLS critique of piecemeal reform Critical scholars reject the idea of piecemeal reform. Incremental change, they argue, merely postpones the wholesale reformation that must occur to create a decent society.'8 Even worse, an unfair social system survives by using piecemeal reform to disguise and legitimize oppression.19 Those who control the system weaken resistance by pointing to the occasional concession to, or periodic court victory of, a black plaintiff or worker as evidence that the system is fair and just.'10 In fact, Crits believe that teaching the common law or using the case method in law school is a disguised means of preaching incre-mentalism and thereby maintaining the current power structure.41 To avoid this, CLS scholars urge in an unabashedly political fashion.<u>42 <mark>The</mark> CLS <mark>critique of piecemeal</mark> <mark>reform</mark> <mark>is</mark> familiar, <strong><mark>imperialistic and wrong.</mark> </strong><mark>Minorities</mark> <mark>know</mark> from bitter experience <mark>that</mark> occasional court <mark>victories do not mean the Promised</mark> <mark>Land</mark> is at hand.13 The critique is imperialistic in that it tells minorities and other oppressed peoples how they should interpret events affecting them." <mark>A court order directing a housing authority to disburse funds for heating</mark> in subsidized housing <mark>may postpone the</mark> <mark>revolution</mark>, or it may not. In the meantime, <mark>the order keeps a number of poor families warm. This may mean more to them than</mark> it does to <mark>a comfortable academic</mark> working in a warm office<mark>. It <strong>smacks of paternalism</strong> to assert that the possibility of revolution later outweighs the certainty of heat now</mark>, unless there is evidence for that possibility. The Crits do not offer such evidence. Indeed, <mark>some <strong>incremental changes may bring revolutionary changes closer</strong>,</mark> not push them further away. <strong><mark>Not all small reforms induce complacency</strong></mark>; <mark>some may whet the appetite for further combat</mark>. The welfare family may hold a tenants' union meeting in their heated living room. CLS scholars' <mark>critique of piecemeal reform often</mark> <strong><mark>misses these possibilities</strong></mark>, and neglects die question of whether total change, when it comes, will be what we want. </p></u> | Off | Afropessimism | 2AC AT: Lexington BY AfroPess | 334,531 | 153 | 56,016 | ./documents/hspolicy20/KentDenver/AbHu/Kent%20Denver-Abarca-Hughes-Aff-9-Berkeley-Round3.docx | 731,547 | A | 9-Berkeley | 3 | Lexington BY | Victoria Yonter | 1AC
Marihuana v5B
1NC
Black Framework Procedural
Metaphors Procedural
T Hold The Police Accountable
4th branch of gov't for ediscourse CP
Afropessimism K
2NR
Afropessimism
CP | hspolicy20/KentDenver/AbHu/Kent%20Denver-Abarca-Hughes-Aff-9-Berkeley-Round3.docx | null | 62,468 | AbHu | Kent Denver AbHu | null | El..... | Ab..... | Ja..... | Hu..... | 21,670 | KentDenver | Kent Denver | CO | null | 1,019 | hspolicy20 | HS Policy 2020-21 | 2,020 | cx | hs | 2 |
2,360,938 | US hegemony is sustainable and secure -- BUT America’s role requires a continued commitment to upholding democracy that give it a structural edge over revisionist powers | Kroenig 20 | Kroenig 20 -- Matthew Kroenig (American political scientist, best-selling author, and an award-winning national security strategist. Professor in the Department of Government and the Edmund A. Walsh School of Foreign Service at Georgetown University), 2020, The Return of Great Power Rivalry: Democracy versus Autocracy from the Ancient World to the U.S. and China, ISBN 9780190080242 WJ | Great power rivalry has returned to international politics the United States faces serious geopolitical challenges from autocratic competitors, Russia and China
democracies have built-in advantages in long-run geopolitical competitions the United States will likely remain the world’s leading state for the foreseeable future to succeed in international political competition, a state must possess economic, diplomatic, and military strength democracies perform better in key economic, diplomatic, and military functions democracies tend to amass more wealth and power than their autocratic competitors and to excel in great power rivalries
This argument was then demonstrated through some simple statistics and a series of seven historical studies Athens against Persia and Sparta, the Roman Republic versus Carthage and Macedon, the Venetian Republic against the Byzantine Empire and the Duchy of Milan, the Dutch Republic and the Spanish Empire, Great Britain and France, the United Kingdom and Germany, and the United States and the Soviet Union These studies did not show that democracies maintain permanent global hegemony, but they did reveal that open states have consistent, structural advantages in great power competitions that democracies have a knack for landing at or near the top of the global pecking order Autocrats, such as Xerxes, Phillip II, Louis XIV, Napoleon, Hitler, and Stalin, have repeatedly made bids for global mastery, but they failed in the end
The same fate likely awaits Messrs. Xi and Putin Washington possesses significant power advantages over Moscow and Beijing America’s fundamentals still look much better than Russia’s and China’s
The United States will likely remain the world’s leading power and Russia and China may be in trouble
autocracies can perform certain tasks, like taking bold action, more easily than democracies this advantage often leads to big mistakes other supposed advantages of autocracies are not really inherent democracies tend to maintain a more stable long-term strategic direction the alleged weaknesses of democracies put forward by autocratic advantage advocates, such as checks and balances resulting in stalemate and discord, are actually among their greatest strengths There is just not that much evidence for the idea that autocratic systems are better suited for great power rivalry The increasingly autocratic systems in Russia and China are a major problem for Russia and China As Xi and Putin systematically eliminate any domestic political obstacles to their unchecked power, they also exacerbate the weaknesses inherent in their autocratic political models.
Democracy is the best machine ever invented for generating enormous state wealth, influence, power, and prestige on the international stage it is difficult if not impossible to achieve lasting global mastery without it.
Autocrats have some explaining to do, not just because their political systems are immoral, but also because they are corrupt, inefficient, and ultimately make their countries
IR scholars take power as a given, or “exogenous” variable, and do not examine what generates power in the first place
fundamental causes of power
The argument of this book is that democracies dominate
balancing behavior often depends on the regime type of the potential hegemon
this book gives us good reason to believe that the United States will continue to be the world’s leading country indefinitely the United States is and likely will continue to be the leading state among multiple, competing great powers
The laws of social science, however, are probabilistic and not deterministic what should the United States do at this moment to maximize its chances of success
To design a sound strategy, one must first accurately survey the strategic environment Russia and China are unlikely to replace the United States as global leader, but they do pose a serious threat to U.S. and allied security and economic well-being
They cannot outcompete market economies and they are frustrated that the democratic core is pushing back on their attempts to prey on the international economic system they are threatened by the U.S.-led, rules-based order and they are doing their best to either revise it or tear it down
These are not objectives that the United States and its allies should accommodate Giving in to Russia and Chinese demands would mean a return to international conflict, decreased worldwide living standards, and the retreat of global democracy and good governance
How then can the United States best maintain its international leadership position it can begin by learning from the fates of the liberal hegemons that have preceded it.
Domestically, therefore, Washington must continue to nurture its greatest source of strength: its institutions America’s greatest advantage is its underlying domestic political system. Democracy is the master variable that explains U.S. success | the U S faces serious geopolitical challenges
democracies have built-in advantages the U S will likely remain the leading state for the foreseeable future democracies perform better in economic, diplomatic, and military functions democracies excel in great power rivalries.
democracies have consistent, structural advantages that have a knack for landing at the top
America’s fundamentals still look much better
autocracies advantage often leads to big mistakes democracies maintain stable long-term strategic direction weaknesses of democracies such as checks and balances are their greatest strengths As Xi and Putin eliminate domestic obstacles they exacerbate weaknesses
Democracy is the best machine for enormous wealth, influence, power, and prestige it is difficult to achieve lasting global mastery without it.
IR scholars do not examine what generates power in the first place
The laws of social science, are probabilistic
Russia and China
cannot outcompete market economies they are doing their best to revise it or tear it down
the United States can begin by learning from the fates of liberal hegemons
therefore, Washington must continue to nurture its greatest strength institutions Democracy is the master variable | Great power rivalry has returned to international politics. After a quarter century of virtually uncontested American leadership, the United States faces serious geopolitical challenges from autocratic competitors, Russia and China. Will the United States retain its position as the world’s leading state, or will the U.S.-led global order be disrupted or displaced by Russia and China?
This book argued that democracies have built-in advantages in long-run geopolitical competitions and that the United States will likely remain the world’s leading state for the foreseeable future. It came to this conclusion by building on the political philosophy canon and contemporary social science research to develop a new way of thinking about power in international politics, tracing the origins of global power to domestic political institutions. It argued that to succeed in international political competition, a state must possess economic, diplomatic, and military strength. It further maintained that democracies perform better in key economic, diplomatic, and military functions. For this reason, democracies tend to amass more wealth and power than their autocratic competitors and to excel in great power rivalries.
This argument was then demonstrated through some simple statistics and a series of seven historical studies, comparing democratic and autocratic rivals from the ancient world to the present, including Athens against Persia and Sparta, the Roman Republic versus Carthage and Macedon, the Venetian Republic against the Byzantine Empire and the Duchy of Milan, the Dutch Republic and the Spanish Empire, Great Britain and France, the United Kingdom and Germany, and the United States and the Soviet Union. These studies did not show that democracies maintain permanent global hegemony, but they did reveal that open states have consistent, structural advantages in great power competitions. It also demonstrated that democracies have a knack for landing at or near the top of the global pecking order and that they have, on balance, fared better in enduring rivalries than their autocratic rivals. More open polities have played an outsized role in great power competition for over two thousand years and have ruled the international system for the past half a millennium. Autocrats, such as Xerxes, Phillip II, Louis XIV, Napoleon, Hitler, and Stalin, have repeatedly made bids for global mastery, but they failed in the end, with their democratic competitors standing triumphantly over them.
The same fate likely awaits Messrs. Xi and Putin. Indeed, this book examined the current competition between the democratic United States and its autocratic rivals, Russia and China. The exercise demonstrated that Washington possesses significant power advantages over Moscow and Beijing. In many important areas, the gap in America’s favor even seems to be growing. A careful examination into the domestic political institutions of all three states showed that, for all of its problems, America’s fundamentals still look much better than Russia’s and China’s.
Taken together, therefore, the book found significant support for the idea that democracies enjoy a systematic advantage in great power politics. The United States will likely remain the world’s leading power and Russia and China may be in trouble.
The competing autocratic advantage argument was considered, but it did not hold up under investigation. To be sure, autocracies can perform certain tasks, like taking bold action, more easily than democracies, but this so-called advantage often leads to big mistakes. Moreover, other supposed advantages of autocracies are not really inherent to autocracies. Some argue that autocracies are better at steady, long-run planning or at acting without scruples, but throughout history we have seen many fragile and fickle autocrats and stable and stony democrats. Indeed, contrary to conventional wisdom, we saw that democracies tend to maintain a more stable long-term strategic direction. Further, the alleged weaknesses of democracies put forward by autocratic advantage advocates, such as checks and balances resulting in stalemate and discord, are actually among their greatest strengths. There is just not that much evidence for the idea that autocratic systems are better suited for great power rivalry. Currently, many in the West are concerned that President Xi in China and Russia’s President Putin are tightening their grips on power. They see these steps as indications of firm leadership, just as Western democracies appear to be more fractious and harder to govern than ever. But this is the wrong lesson to draw. The increasingly autocratic systems in Russia and China are a major problem, not for the United States, but for Russia and China. As Xi and Putin systematically eliminate any domestic political obstacles to their unchecked power, they also exacerbate the weaknesses inherent in their autocratic political models.
This book, therefore, made the “hard-power” case for democracy. Generally, democracy is admired because it is the best political system for advancing freedom, human rights, the rule of law, and human dignity. Those are important attributes, and democracy is rightly celebrated for these normative reasons. But by focusing too much on these softer assets, we overlook other important and practical benefits of democracy: Democracy is the best machine ever invented for generating enormous state wealth, influence, power, and prestige on the international stage. Indeed, it is difficult if not impossible to achieve lasting global mastery without it.
The United States and its democratic allies and partners should be proud of their domestic political systems not just because they are morally superior but also because they are more effective. Autocrats have some explaining to do, not just because their political systems are immoral, but also because they are corrupt, inefficient, and ultimately make their countries weaker.
International relations (IR) scholars have thoroughly studied the role of power in international politics, but they have largely overlooked some of the most interesting and important issues. They have asked: What kind of international distribution of power is more stable? Are bipolar worlds with two major powers more or less peaceful than multipolar worlds with three or more great powers? What are the conditions under which power transitions lead to war? Do international systems with one dominant power tend to have greater levels of economic openness? And the list goes on.
In all of these studies, however, IR scholars have been obsessed with the effects of power, not its causes. Rather, they take power as a given, or “exogenous” variable, and do not examine what generates power in the first place.
But questions about the fundamental causes of power may be the most critical to understanding international politics. Why are some countries more powerful than others? Why do some countries rise to enter the circle of the great powers while others do not? Why do some great powers achieve global ascendancy while others burn out? Why do power transitions occur? After millennia of the world’s leading thinkers pondering the role of power in world statecraft, we have barely begun to scratch the surface on this set of important questions.
This book advances IR theory, therefore, by providing a clear and novel theoretical explanation that traces the origins of power in world politics to domestic political institutions. The argument of this book is that democracies dominate.
There are other implications for international relations theory as well. IR scholars argue that states form coalitions to balance against dominant states, but this study showed that balancing behavior often depends on the regime type of the potential hegemon. States balance against autocracies, consistent with past theory, but they often bandwagon with powerful democracies. In addition, foreign-imposed regime change is often seen as an aberration, especially following the U.S. invasion of Iraq, but the historical review in this book revealed that it is actually a recurring feature of international politics. Democratic and autocratic states alike regularly attempt to overthrow the enemy’s form of government and install a new one in their own image. Moreover, democratic peace theory may hold in more modern times, but open states often engaged in direct warfare in the past, from the ancient world to the Italian Renaissance.
Turning to real-world implications, while many predict an end to the American era, this book gives us good reason to believe that the United States will continue to be the world’s leading country indefinitely. We are no longer living in the “unipolar moment” of overwhelming American primacy that we witnessed for the twenty-five years from 1989 to 2014.1 But the United States is and likely will continue to be the leading state among multiple, competing great powers.
By my calculation, the average reign for a dominant democracy atop the international system is 130 years, with a range of 95 years for Athens at the low end and 221 years for Great Britain at the high end. The United States clocks in at 75 years and counting. If history is any guide, therefore, it still has a couple of good decades and maybe another century to go.
The laws of social science, however, are probabilistic and not deterministic. In other words, unlike the laws of gravity in physics, none of our theories are certain in international relations. As Machiavelli cautions, success in international politics is the result of both virtu and fortuna. The literal translations of these words are virtue and fortune, but his intended meaning was somewhat closer to what we would today call skill and circumstances. Machiavelli argued that even the most skilled leaders sometimes fail due to other overriding forces and that when circumstances are propitious, skilled leaders must still be prepared to seize the moment. In other words, the U.S. system is competitive, but Washington still must compete. So, what should the United States do at this moment to maximize its chances of success?
To design a sound strategy, one must first accurately survey the strategic environment. Russia and China are unlikely to replace the United States as global leader, but they do pose a serious threat to U.S. and allied security and economic well-being.
Moscow and Beijing rightly believe that the U.S.-led, liberal international order poses an existential threat. They do not like to see the United States projecting military power across the globe. They are bothered by the spread of America’s alliance network right up to their sovereign borders. They do not have to play by the rules at home, so they chafe under an expectation that they follow a rules-based order abroad. They cannot outcompete market economies and they are frustrated that the democratic core is pushing back on their attempts to prey on the international economic system. They rightly fear that the spread of democracy could led to the very collapse of their regimes. In sum, they are threatened by the U.S.-led, rules-based order and they are doing their best to either revise it or tear it down; as President Putin has said, “new rules or no rules.”
Make no mistake, the threat these states pose to the U.S. led order is ideological in nature. The renewed great power competition with Russia and China is not purely a realist game of great powers pragmatically jockeying for power and influence. Rather, like many of the autocracy versus democracy battles we have seen throughout history, it is a clash of political models. It is a fundamental dispute about the best way to govern societies both at home and abroad. For some, the autocratic system of domestic repression, state-led economies, and an illiberal foreign policy will be appealing. But nearly all of America’s traditional friends and allies will be much more attracted to the U.S. model of open markets and free politics. We must make it clear to these partners that their day-to-day engagements with Russia and China are not, therefore, isolated decisions about whether to, for example, buy cheap Russian gas or allow Chinese infrastructure investment, but rather a more fundamental choice between democracy and autocracy. They must decide what type of political system they want for themselves and others and what kind of world system they want to inhabit.
Some have argued that Russia and China do not pose an ideological challenge because, unlike the Soviet Union, they are not intentionally looking to export their model. China is, however, helping autocrats around the world deploy technology that will help governments repress their citizens. Moreover, Moscow and Beijing are contributing to an international environment characterized by democratic backsliding globally as other strongmen eagerly emulate their models. Furthermore, and perhaps most importantly, this is an ideological competition because Moscow and Beijing are threatened by democratic ideology. They want to create an international system in which their regimes can continue to survive and thrive; they want to make the world safe for autocracy.
These are not objectives that the United States and its allies should accommodate. While the U.S.-led order may not serve the interests of autocrats in Russia and China, it has made the world a more peaceful, prosperous and well-governed place over the past seventy-five years. Giving in to Russia and Chinese demands would mean a return to international conflict, decreased worldwide living standards, and the retreat of global democracy and good governance.
How then can the United States best maintain its international leadership position? To stave off decline, it can begin by learning from the fates of the liberal hegemons that have preceded it. We have seen in this book that democratic great powers have done quite well historically, but they have fallen for three reasons. Athens was defeated primarily due to a rash decision permitted by its system of direct democracy. Rome and Venice lost their vitality when they closed the open political systems that had sustained their rise. Finally, the Dutch Republic and Great Britain were surpassed by other, even more competitive, democratic rivals; England overtook the Dutch Republic and Great Britain passed the baton of democratic global leadership to the United States.
Domestically, therefore, Washington must continue to nurture its greatest source of strength: its institutions. Some argue that America’s greatest advantage is its innovative economy, its global network of alliances, or its military dominance, but this book explained how all of these positive attributes are, in fact, byproducts of America’s underlying domestic political system. Democracy is the master variable that explains U.S. success | 14,901 | <h4>US hegemony is sustainable and secure -- BUT America’s role requires a continued commitment to upholding <u>democracy</u> that give it a <u>structural edge</u> over revisionist powers</h4><p><u><strong>Kroenig 20</u></strong> -- Matthew Kroenig (American political scientist, best-selling author, and an award-winning national security strategist. Professor in the Department of Government and the Edmund A. Walsh School of Foreign Service at Georgetown University), 2020, The Return of Great Power Rivalry: Democracy versus Autocracy from the Ancient World to the U.S. and China, ISBN 9780190080242 WJ</p><p><u><strong>Great power rivalry has returned to international politics</u></strong>. After a quarter century of virtually uncontested American leadership, <u><strong><mark>the U</mark>nited <mark>S</mark>tates <mark>faces serious geopolitical challenges</mark> from autocratic competitors, Russia and China</u></strong>. Will the United States retain its position as the world’s leading state, or will the U.S.-led global order be disrupted or displaced by Russia and China?</p><p>This book argued that <u><strong><mark>democracies have built-in advantages</mark> in long-run geopolitical competitions</u></strong> and that <u><strong><mark>the</mark> <mark>U</mark>nited <mark>S</mark>tates <mark>will likely remain the</mark> world’s <mark>leading state for the foreseeable future</u></strong></mark>. It came to this conclusion by building on the political philosophy canon and contemporary social science research to develop a new way of thinking about power in international politics, tracing the origins of global power to domestic political institutions. It argued that <u><strong>to succeed in international political competition, a state must possess economic, diplomatic, and military strength</u></strong>. It further maintained that <u><strong><mark>democracies perform better in</mark> key <mark>economic, diplomatic, and military functions</u></strong></mark>. For this reason, <u><strong><mark>democracies</mark> tend to amass more wealth and power than their autocratic competitors and to <mark>excel in great power rivalries</u></strong>.</p><p><u><strong></mark>This argument was then demonstrated through some simple statistics and a series of seven historical studies</u></strong>, comparing democratic and autocratic rivals from the ancient world to the present, including <u><strong>Athens against Persia and Sparta, the Roman Republic versus Carthage and Macedon, the Venetian Republic against the Byzantine Empire and the Duchy of Milan, the Dutch Republic and the Spanish Empire, Great Britain and France, the United Kingdom and Germany, and the United States and the Soviet Union</u></strong>. <u><strong>These studies did not show that <mark>democracies</mark> maintain permanent global hegemony, but they did reveal that open states <mark>have consistent, structural advantages</mark> in great power competitions</u></strong>. It also demonstrated <u><strong><mark>that</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>democracies <mark>have a knack for landing at</mark> or near <mark>the top</mark> of the global pecking order</u></strong> and that they have, on balance, fared better in enduring rivalries than their autocratic rivals. More open polities have played an outsized role in great power competition for over two thousand years and have ruled the international system for the past half a millennium. <u><strong>Autocrats, such as Xerxes, Phillip II, Louis XIV, Napoleon, Hitler, and Stalin, have repeatedly made bids for global mastery, but they failed in the end</u></strong>, with their democratic competitors standing triumphantly over them.</p><p><u><strong>The same fate likely awaits Messrs. Xi and Putin</u></strong>. Indeed, this book examined the current competition between the democratic United States and its autocratic rivals, Russia and China. The exercise demonstrated that <u><strong>Washington possesses significant power advantages over Moscow and Beijing</u></strong>. In many important areas, the gap in America’s favor even seems to be growing. A careful examination into the domestic political institutions of all three states showed that, for all of its problems, <u><strong><mark>America’s fundamentals still look much better</mark> than Russia’s and China’s</u></strong>.</p><p>Taken together, therefore, the book found significant support for the idea that democracies enjoy a systematic advantage in great power politics. <u><strong>The United States will likely remain the world’s leading power and Russia and China may be in trouble</u></strong>.</p><p>The competing autocratic advantage argument was considered, but it did not hold up under investigation. To be sure, <u><strong><mark>autocracies</mark> can perform certain tasks, like taking bold action, more easily than democracies</u></strong>, but <u><strong>this</u></strong> so-called <u><strong><mark>advantage often leads to big mistakes</u></strong></mark>. Moreover, <u><strong>other supposed advantages of autocracies are not really inherent</u></strong> to autocracies. Some argue that autocracies are better at steady, long-run planning or at acting without scruples, but throughout history we have seen many fragile and fickle autocrats and stable and stony democrats. Indeed, contrary to conventional wisdom, we saw that <u><strong><mark>democracies</mark> tend to <mark>maintain</mark> a more <mark>stable long-term strategic direction</u></strong></mark>. Further, <u><strong>the alleged <mark>weaknesses of democracies</mark> put forward by autocratic advantage advocates, <mark>such as checks and balances</mark> resulting in stalemate and discord, <mark>are</mark> actually among <mark>their greatest strengths</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong>There is just not that much evidence for the idea that autocratic systems are better suited for great power rivalry</u></strong>. Currently, many in the West are concerned that President Xi in China and Russia’s President Putin are tightening their grips on power. They see these steps as indications of firm leadership, just as Western democracies appear to be more fractious and harder to govern than ever. But this is the wrong lesson to draw. <u><strong>The increasingly autocratic systems in Russia and China are a major problem</u></strong>, not for the United States, but <u><strong>for Russia and China</u></strong>. <u><strong><mark>As Xi and Putin</mark> systematically <mark>eliminate</mark> any <mark>domestic</mark> political <mark>obstacles</mark> to their unchecked power, <mark>they</mark> also <mark>exacerbate</mark> the <mark>weaknesses</mark> inherent in their autocratic political models.</p><p></u></strong>This book, therefore, made the “hard-power” case for democracy. Generally, democracy is admired because it is the best political system for advancing freedom, human rights, the rule of law, and human dignity. Those are important attributes, and democracy is rightly celebrated for these normative reasons. But by focusing too much on these softer assets, we overlook other important and practical benefits of democracy: <u><strong><mark>Democracy is the best machine</mark> ever invented <mark>for</mark> generating <mark>enormous</mark> state <mark>wealth, influence, power, and prestige</mark> on the international stage</u></strong>. Indeed, <u><strong><mark>it is difficult</mark> if not impossible <mark>to</mark> <mark>achieve lasting global mastery without it.</p><p></u></strong></mark>The United States and its democratic allies and partners should be proud of their domestic political systems not just because they are morally superior but also because they are more effective. <u><strong>Autocrats have some explaining to do, not just because their political systems are immoral, but also because they are corrupt, inefficient, and ultimately make their countries</u></strong> weaker.</p><p>International relations (IR) scholars have thoroughly studied the role of power in international politics, but they have largely overlooked some of the most interesting and important issues. They have asked: What kind of international distribution of power is more stable? Are bipolar worlds with two major powers more or less peaceful than multipolar worlds with three or more great powers? What are the conditions under which power transitions lead to war? Do international systems with one dominant power tend to have greater levels of economic openness? And the list goes on.</p><p>In all of these studies, however, <u><strong><mark>IR scholars</u></strong></mark> have been obsessed with the effects of power, not its causes. Rather, they <u><strong>take power as a given, or “exogenous” variable, and <mark>do not examine what generates power in the first place</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>But questions about the <u><strong>fundamental causes of power</u></strong> may be the most critical to understanding international politics. Why are some countries more powerful than others? Why do some countries rise to enter the circle of the great powers while others do not? Why do some great powers achieve global ascendancy while others burn out? Why do power transitions occur? After millennia of the world’s leading thinkers pondering the role of power in world statecraft, we have barely begun to scratch the surface on this set of important questions.</p><p>This book advances IR theory, therefore, by providing a clear and novel theoretical explanation that traces the origins of power in world politics to domestic political institutions. <u><strong>The argument of this book is that democracies dominate</u></strong>.</p><p>There are other implications for international relations theory as well. IR scholars argue that states form coalitions to balance against dominant states, but this study showed that <u><strong>balancing behavior often depends on the regime type of the potential hegemon</u></strong>. States balance against autocracies, consistent with past theory, but they often bandwagon with powerful democracies. In addition, foreign-imposed regime change is often seen as an aberration, especially following the U.S. invasion of Iraq, but the historical review in this book revealed that it is actually a recurring feature of international politics. Democratic and autocratic states alike regularly attempt to overthrow the enemy’s form of government and install a new one in their own image. Moreover, democratic peace theory may hold in more modern times, but open states often engaged in direct warfare in the past, from the ancient world to the Italian Renaissance.</p><p>Turning to real-world implications, while many predict an end to the American era, <u><strong>this book gives us good reason to believe that the United States will continue to be the world’s leading country indefinitely</u></strong>. We are no longer living in the “unipolar moment” of overwhelming American primacy that we witnessed for the twenty-five years from 1989 to 2014.1 But <u><strong>the United States is and likely will continue to be the leading state among multiple, competing great powers</u></strong>.</p><p>By my calculation, the average reign for a dominant democracy atop the international system is 130 years, with a range of 95 years for Athens at the low end and 221 years for Great Britain at the high end. The United States clocks in at 75 years and counting. If history is any guide, therefore, it still has a couple of good decades and maybe another century to go.</p><p><u><strong><mark>The laws of social science, </mark>however, <mark>are probabilistic</mark> and not deterministic</u></strong>. In other words, unlike the laws of gravity in physics, none of our theories are certain in international relations. As Machiavelli cautions, success in international politics is the result of both virtu and fortuna. The literal translations of these words are virtue and fortune, but his intended meaning was somewhat closer to what we would today call skill and circumstances. Machiavelli argued that even the most skilled leaders sometimes fail due to other overriding forces and that when circumstances are propitious, skilled leaders must still be prepared to seize the moment. In other words, the U.S. system is competitive, but Washington still must compete. So, <u><strong>what should the United States do at this moment to maximize its chances of success</u></strong>?</p><p><u><strong>To design a sound strategy, one must first accurately survey the strategic environment</u></strong>. <u><strong><mark>Russia and China</mark> are unlikely to replace the United States as global leader, but they do pose a serious threat to U.S. and allied security and economic well-being</u></strong>.</p><p>Moscow and Beijing rightly believe that the U.S.-led, liberal international order poses an existential threat. They do not like to see the United States projecting military power across the globe. They are bothered by the spread of America’s alliance network right up to their sovereign borders. They do not have to play by the rules at home, so they chafe under an expectation that they follow a rules-based order abroad. <u><strong>They <mark>cannot outcompete market economies</mark> and they are frustrated that the democratic core is pushing back on their attempts to prey on the international economic system</u></strong>. They rightly fear that the spread of democracy could led to the very collapse of their regimes. In sum, <u><strong>they are threatened by the U.S.-led, rules-based order and <mark>they are doing their best to</mark> either <mark>revise it or tear it down</u></strong></mark>; as President Putin has said, “new rules or no rules.”</p><p>Make no mistake, the threat these states pose to the U.S. led order is ideological in nature. The renewed great power competition with Russia and China is not purely a realist game of great powers pragmatically jockeying for power and influence. Rather, like many of the autocracy versus democracy battles we have seen throughout history, it is a clash of political models. It is a fundamental dispute about the best way to govern societies both at home and abroad. For some, the autocratic system of domestic repression, state-led economies, and an illiberal foreign policy will be appealing. But nearly all of America’s traditional friends and allies will be much more attracted to the U.S. model of open markets and free politics. We must make it clear to these partners that their day-to-day engagements with Russia and China are not, therefore, isolated decisions about whether to, for example, buy cheap Russian gas or allow Chinese infrastructure investment, but rather a more fundamental choice between democracy and autocracy. They must decide what type of political system they want for themselves and others and what kind of world system they want to inhabit.</p><p>Some have argued that Russia and China do not pose an ideological challenge because, unlike the Soviet Union, they are not intentionally looking to export their model. China is, however, helping autocrats around the world deploy technology that will help governments repress their citizens. Moreover, Moscow and Beijing are contributing to an international environment characterized by democratic backsliding globally as other strongmen eagerly emulate their models. Furthermore, and perhaps most importantly, this is an ideological competition because Moscow and Beijing are threatened by democratic ideology. They want to create an international system in which their regimes can continue to survive and thrive; they want to make the world safe for autocracy.</p><p><u><strong>These are not objectives that the United States and its allies should accommodate</u></strong>. While the U.S.-led order may not serve the interests of autocrats in Russia and China, it has made the world a more peaceful, prosperous and well-governed place over the past seventy-five years. <u><strong>Giving in to Russia and Chinese demands would mean a return to international conflict, decreased worldwide living standards, and the retreat of global democracy and good governance</u></strong>.</p><p><u><strong>How then can <mark>the United States</mark> best maintain its international leadership position</u></strong>? To stave off decline, <u><strong>it <mark>can begin by learning from the fates of</mark> the <mark>liberal hegemons</mark> that have preceded it.</u></strong> We have seen in this book that democratic great powers have done quite well historically, but they have fallen for three reasons. Athens was defeated primarily due to a rash decision permitted by its system of direct democracy. Rome and Venice lost their vitality when they closed the open political systems that had sustained their rise. Finally, the Dutch Republic and Great Britain were surpassed by other, even more competitive, democratic rivals; England overtook the Dutch Republic and Great Britain passed the baton of democratic global leadership to the United States.</p><p><u><strong>Domestically, <mark>therefore, Washington must continue to nurture its greatest</mark> source of <mark>strength</mark>: its <mark>institutions</u></strong></mark>. Some argue that <u><strong>America’s greatest advantage is its</u></strong> innovative economy, its global network of alliances, or its military dominance, but this book explained how all of these positive attributes are, in fact, byproducts of America’s <u><strong>underlying domestic political system. <mark>Democracy is the master variable</mark> that explains U.S. success</p></u></strong> | 1ac | null | null | 904,174 | 136 | 75,162 | ./documents/hsld20/SouthlakeCarroll/Ka/Southlake%20Carroll-Kaginele-Aff-glenbrooks-Round2.docx | 874,019 | A | glenbrooks | 2 | harker ds | parth misra | 1ac - niec
1nc - cap k
2nr - same | hsld20/SouthlakeCarroll/Ka/Southlake%20Carroll-Kaginele-Aff-glenbrooks-Round2.docx | null | 73,782 | PrKa | Southlake Carroll PrKa | null | Pr..... | Ka..... | null | null | 24,728 | SouthlakeCarroll | Southlake Carroll | TX | null | 1,028 | hsld20 | HS LD 2020-21 | 2,020 | ld | hs | 1 |
2,102,129 | Economic competitiveness is key to global stability and suppress global conflicts | Hubbard 10 | Hubbard 10 Jesse Hubbard 5-28-2010 “Hegemonic Stability Theory: An Empirical Analysis” https://isrj.wordpress.com/2010/05/28/hegemonic-stability-theory/ (Open Society Foundations program assistant)//Elmer | Regression analysis of this data shows that Pearson’s r-value is -.836. In the case of American hegemony, economic strength is a better predictor of violent conflict than even overall national power, which had an r-value of -.819. The data is also well within the realm of statistical significance, with a p-value of .0014. While the data for British hegemony was not as striking, the same overall pattern holds true in both cases. During both periods of hegemony, hegemonic strength was negatively related with violent conflict, and yet use of force by the hegemon was positively correlated with violent conflict in both cases. Finally, in both cases, economic power was more closely associated with conflict levels than military power. Statistical analysis created a more complicated picture of the hegemon’s role in fostering stability than initially anticipated. VI. Conclusions and Implications for Theory and Policy economic instability between the First and Second World Wars could be attributed to the lack of an economic hegemon after World War II, the United States played a leading role in creating institutions like the GATT that had an essential role in facilitating global trade Another theory that could provide insight into the patterns observed in this research is that of preponderance of power. Gilpin theorized that when a state has the preponderance of power in the international system, rivals are more likely to resolve their disagreements without resorting to armed conflict (Gilpi n 1983). The logic behind this claim is simple – it makes more sense to challenge a weaker hegemon than a stronger one. This simple yet powerful theory can help explain the puzzlingly strong positive correlation between military conflicts engaged in by the hegemon and conflict overall. It is not necessarily that military involvement by the hegemon instigates further conflict in the international system. Rather, this military involvement could be a function of the hegemon’s weaker position, which is the true cause of the higher levels of conflict in the international system. Additionally, it is important to note that military power is, in the long run, dependent on economic strength. Thus, it is possible that as hegemons lose relative economic power, other nations are tempted to challenge them even if their short-term military capabilities are still strong. This would help explain some of the variation found between the economic and military data. The results of this analysis are of clear importance beyond the realm of theory. As the debate rages over the role of the United States in the world, hegemonic stability theory has some useful insights to bring to the table. What this research makes clear is that a strong hegemon can exert a positive influence on stability in the international system. However, this should not give policymakers a justification to engage in conflict or escalate military budgets purely for the sake of international stability. If anything, this research points to the central importance of economic influence in fostering international stability. To misconstrue these findings to justify anything else would be a grave error indeed. Hegemons may play a stabilizing role in the international system, but this role is complicated. It is economic strength, not military dominance that is the true test of hegemony. A weak state with a strong military is a paper tiger – it may appear fearsome, but it is vulnerable to even a short blast of wind. | Regression analysis shows In the case of American hegemony, economic strength is a better predictor of conflict than even overall power instability could be attributed to the lack of an economic hegemon when a state has power rivals are more likely to resolve disagreements without resorting to armed conflict military power is, dependent on economic strength as hegemons lose economic power, other nations challenge them even if their short-term military capabilities are still strong this research points to the central importance of economic influence in fostering international stability It is economic strength that is the true test of hegemony | Regression analysis of this data shows that Pearson’s r-value is -.836. In the case of American hegemony, economic strength is a better predictor of violent conflict than even overall national power, which had an r-value of -.819. The data is also well within the realm of statistical significance, with a p-value of .0014. While the data for British hegemony was not as striking, the same overall pattern holds true in both cases. During both periods of hegemony, hegemonic strength was negatively related with violent conflict, and yet use of force by the hegemon was positively correlated with violent conflict in both cases. Finally, in both cases, economic power was more closely associated with conflict levels than military power. Statistical analysis created a more complicated picture of the hegemon’s role in fostering stability than initially anticipated. VI. Conclusions and Implications for Theory and Policy To elucidate some answers regarding the complexities my analysis unearthed, I turned first to the existing theoretical literature on hegemonic stability theory. The existing literature provides some potential frameworks for understanding these results. Since economic strength proved to be of such crucial importance, reexamining the literature that focuses on hegemonic stability theory’s economic implications was the logical first step. As explained above, the literature on hegemonic stability theory can be broadly divided into two camps – that which focuses on the international economic system, and that which focuses on armed conflict and instability. This research falls squarely into the second camp, but insights from the first camp are still of relevance. Even Kindleberger’s early work on this question is of relevance. Kindleberger posited that the economic instability between the First and Second World Wars could be attributed to the lack of an economic hegemon (Kindleberger 1973). But economic instability obviously has spillover effects into the international political arena. Keynes, writing after WWI, warned in his seminal tract The Economic Consequences of the Peace that Germany’s economic humiliation could have a radicalizing effect on the nation’s political culture (Keynes 1919). Given later events, his warning seems prescient. In the years since the Second World War, however, the European continent has not relapsed into armed conflict. What was different after the second global conflagration? Crucially, the United States was in a far more powerful position than Britain was after WWI. As the tables above show, Britain’s economic strength after the First World War was about 13% of the total in strength in the international system. In contrast, the United States possessed about 53% of relative economic power in the international system in the years immediately following WWII. The U.S. helped rebuild Europe’s economic strength with billions of dollars in investment through the Marshall Plan, assistance that was never available to the defeated powers after the First World War (Kindleberger 1973). The interwar years were also marked by a series of debilitating trade wars that likely worsened the Great Depression (Ibid.). In contrast, when Britain was more powerful, it was able to facilitate greater free trade, and after World War II, the United States played a leading role in creating institutions like the GATT that had an essential role in facilitating global trade (Organski 1958). The possibility that economic stability is an important factor in the overall security environment should not be discounted, especially given the results of my statistical analysis. Another theory that could provide insight into the patterns observed in this research is that of preponderance of power. Gilpin theorized that when a state has the preponderance of power in the international system, rivals are more likely to resolve their disagreements without resorting to armed conflict (Gilpi n 1983). The logic behind this claim is simple – it makes more sense to challenge a weaker hegemon than a stronger one. This simple yet powerful theory can help explain the puzzlingly strong positive correlation between military conflicts engaged in by the hegemon and conflict overall. It is not necessarily that military involvement by the hegemon instigates further conflict in the international system. Rather, this military involvement could be a function of the hegemon’s weaker position, which is the true cause of the higher levels of conflict in the international system. Additionally, it is important to note that military power is, in the long run, dependent on economic strength. Thus, it is possible that as hegemons lose relative economic power, other nations are tempted to challenge them even if their short-term military capabilities are still strong. This would help explain some of the variation found between the economic and military data. The results of this analysis are of clear importance beyond the realm of theory. As the debate rages over the role of the United States in the world, hegemonic stability theory has some useful insights to bring to the table. What this research makes clear is that a strong hegemon can exert a positive influence on stability in the international system. However, this should not give policymakers a justification to engage in conflict or escalate military budgets purely for the sake of international stability. If anything, this research points to the central importance of economic influence in fostering international stability. To misconstrue these findings to justify anything else would be a grave error indeed. Hegemons may play a stabilizing role in the international system, but this role is complicated. It is economic strength, not military dominance that is the true test of hegemony. A weak state with a strong military is a paper tiger – it may appear fearsome, but it is vulnerable to even a short blast of wind. | 5,936 | <h4>Economic competitiveness is key to global stability and suppress global conflicts</h4><p><strong>Hubbard 10</strong> Jesse Hubbard 5-28-2010 “Hegemonic Stability Theory: An Empirical Analysis” https://isrj.wordpress.com/2010/05/28/hegemonic-stability-theory/<u> (Open Society Foundations program assistant)//Elmer</p><p><strong><mark>Regression analysis </mark>of this data <mark>shows</strong></mark> that Pearson’s r-value is -.836. <strong><mark>In the case of American</mark> <mark>hegemony, economic strength is a better predictor of </mark>violent <mark>conflict than even overall</mark> national <mark>power</strong></mark>, which had an r-value of -.819. The data is also well within the realm of statistical significance, with a p-value of .0014. While the data for British hegemony was not as striking, the same overall pattern holds true in both cases. During both periods of hegemony, hegemonic strength was negatively related with violent conflict, and yet use of force by the hegemon was positively correlated with violent conflict in both cases. Finally, in both cases, economic power was more closely associated with conflict levels than military power. Statistical analysis created a more complicated picture of the hegemon’s role in fostering stability than initially anticipated. VI. Conclusions and Implications for Theory and Policy </u>To elucidate some answers regarding the complexities my analysis unearthed, I turned first to the existing theoretical literature on hegemonic stability theory. The existing literature provides some potential frameworks for understanding these results. Since economic strength proved to be of such crucial importance, reexamining the literature that focuses on hegemonic stability theory’s economic implications was the logical first step. As explained above, the literature on hegemonic stability theory can be broadly divided into two camps – that which focuses on the international economic system, and that which focuses on armed conflict and instability. This research falls squarely into the second camp, but insights from the first camp are still of relevance. Even Kindleberger’s early work on this question is of relevance. Kindleberger posited that the <u>economic<strong> <mark>instability </strong></mark>between the First and Second World Wars<strong> <mark>could be attributed to the lack of an economic hegemon</u></strong></mark> (Kindleberger 1973). But economic instability obviously has spillover effects into the international political arena. Keynes, writing after WWI, warned in his seminal tract The Economic Consequences of the Peace that Germany’s economic humiliation could have a radicalizing effect on the nation’s political culture (Keynes 1919). Given later events, his warning seems prescient. In the years since the Second World War, however, the European continent has not relapsed into armed conflict. What was different after the second global conflagration? Crucially, the United States was in a far more powerful position than Britain was after WWI. As the tables above show, Britain’s economic strength after the First World War was about 13% of the total in strength in the international system. In contrast, the United States possessed about 53% of relative economic power in the international system in the years immediately following WWII. The U.S. helped rebuild Europe’s economic strength with billions of dollars in investment through the Marshall Plan, assistance that was never available to the defeated powers after the First World War (Kindleberger 1973). The interwar years were also marked by a series of debilitating trade wars that likely worsened the Great Depression (Ibid.). In contrast, when Britain was more powerful, it was able to facilitate greater free trade, and <u>after World War II,<strong> the United States played a leading role in creating institutions like the GATT that had an essential role in facilitating global trade</u></strong> (Organski 1958). The possibility that economic stability is an important factor in the overall security environment should not be discounted, especially given the results of my statistical analysis. <u>Another theory that could provide insight into the patterns observed in this research is that of preponderance of power. Gilpin theorized that <strong><mark>when a state has </mark>the preponderance of <mark>power </mark>in the international system, <mark>rivals are more likely to resolve</mark> their <mark>disagreements without resorting to armed conflict</strong> </mark>(Gilpi n 1983). The logic behind this claim is simple – it makes more sense to challenge a weaker hegemon than a stronger one. This simple yet powerful theory can help explain the puzzlingly strong positive correlation between military conflicts engaged in by the hegemon and conflict overall. It is not necessarily that military involvement by the hegemon instigates further conflict in the international system. Rather, this military involvement could be a function of the hegemon’s weaker position, which is the true cause of the higher levels of conflict in the international system. Additionally, it is important to note that <strong><mark>military power is,</strong></mark> in the long run, <strong><mark>dependent on economic strength</strong></mark>. Thus, it is possible that <strong><mark>as hegemons lose </mark>relative <mark>economic power, other nations </mark>are tempted to <mark>challenge them even if their short-term military capabilities are still strong</strong></mark>. This would help explain some of the variation found between the economic and military data. The results of this analysis are of clear importance beyond the realm of theory. As the debate rages over the role of the United States in the world, hegemonic stability theory has some useful insights to bring to the table. What this research makes clear is that a strong hegemon can exert a positive influence on stability in the international system. However, this should not give policymakers a justification to engage in conflict or escalate military budgets purely for the sake of international stability. If anything, <strong><mark>this research points to the central importance of economic influence in fostering international stability</strong></mark>. To misconstrue these findings to justify anything else would be a grave error indeed. Hegemons may play a stabilizing role in the international system, but this role is complicated. <strong><mark>It is economic strength</mark>, not military dominance <mark>that is the true test of hegemony</strong></mark>. <strong>A weak state with a strong military is a paper tiger</strong> – it may appear fearsome, but it is vulnerable to even a short blast of wind.</p></u> | 1NC Alta Round 2 | Offs | 3 | 129,547 | 219 | 62,923 | ./documents/hsld20/Brophy/Ag/Brophy-Agha-Neg-Alta-Round4.docx | 854,910 | N | Alta | 4 | Brentwood MM | Cameron Lange | pics good and pic | hsld20/Brophy/Ag/Brophy-Agha-Neg-Alta-Round4.docx | null | 72,787 | SaAg | Brophy SaAg | null | Sa..... | Ag..... | null | null | 24,442 | Brophy | Brophy | AZ | null | 1,028 | hsld20 | HS LD 2020-21 | 2,020 | ld | hs | 1 |
1,210,234 | We meet their card ??? We’re green. | Solanes ‘9 | Solanes ‘9 [Miguel; December 2009; Consultant for the International Institute for Sustainable Development, Head of the Department of Economic and Institutional Analysis of IMDEA Water, water and law advisor for the United Nations system since 1984, M.A. in Water Resource Management at Colorado State University; IISD, “Water Resources Legislation: A Search for Common Principles,” https://www.iisd.org/system/files/publications/water_resources_legislation.pdf] | Water resources have historically been subjected to government control its potential for good or damage justified government regulation and ownership the water resources legislation include permanent oversight and protection and conditionalities to water uses and water rights
government activities conflict with investors by enacting new regulations, requiring efficiency in water uses, reforming water permits, and the like | Water resources have historically been subject to government control it justified regulation and ownership water resource legislation include oversight and conditionalities to water uses and water rights
new regulations reforming water permits | Introduction
Water resources have historically been subjected to government control. Its multiple economic, social and environmental roles, and its potential for either good or damage have justified government regulation and ownership since ancient times. At present, the water resources legislation of varying countries shares many features, including statements of water policies, public ownership and quality protection. They also include permanent oversight and protection and conditionalities to water uses and water rights.
The identification of common principles of water law is particularly important at a time when international investment is protected by international investment treaties whose main objective is protecting international investments without any duty of consideration for the general concerns of public interest.
The search for general principles of law, shared by domestic national systems, will contribute elements that highlight the gaps and differences between the decisions of arbitration courts and the principles informing national legislation and the decisions of national courts. Identifying gaps will also contribute to a body of constructive criticism of investment arbitration practices, hopefully leading to the overhaul of the criteria and principles applied by investment arbitration courts.
Water is an obvious asset in many international investments, including, but not limited to, agriculture, mining, oil, energy, tourism, land development, forestry and provision of water and sanitation services. At the same time, water can be affected by the practices of international investors: it can be polluted, water sources can be affected by economic activities and water-associated risks can be aggravated by defective land practices. Thus, different government activities could potentially conflict with foreign investors by enacting new regulations, requiring efficiency in water uses, reforming the conditions of water permits, and the like. | 1,984 | <h4>We meet their card ??? We’re <mark>green<strong></mark>.</h4><p>Solanes ‘9 </strong>[Miguel; December 2009; Consultant for the International Institute for Sustainable Development, Head of the Department of Economic and Institutional Analysis of IMDEA Water, water and law advisor for the United Nations system since 1984, M.A. in Water Resource Management at Colorado State University; IISD, “Water Resources Legislation: A Search for Common Principles,” https://www.iisd.org/system/files/publications/water_resources_legislation.pdf]</p><p>Introduction</p><p><u><strong><mark>Water resources have historically been subject</mark>ed <mark>to government control</u></strong></mark>. Its multiple economic, social and environmental roles, and <u><strong><mark>it</mark>s potential for</u></strong> either <u><strong>good or damage</u></strong> have <u><strong><mark>justified</mark> government <mark>regulation and ownership</u></strong></mark> since ancient times. At present, <u><strong>the <mark>water resource</mark>s <mark>legislation</u></strong></mark> of varying countries shares many features, including statements of water policies, public ownership and quality protection. They also <u><strong><mark>include</mark> permanent <mark>oversight and</mark> protection and <mark>conditionalities to water uses and water rights</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>The identification of common principles of water law is particularly important at a time when international investment is protected by international investment treaties whose main objective is protecting international investments without any duty of consideration for the general concerns of public interest.</p><p>The search for general principles of law, shared by domestic national systems, will contribute elements that highlight the gaps and differences between the decisions of arbitration courts and the principles informing national legislation and the decisions of national courts. Identifying gaps will also contribute to a body of constructive criticism of investment arbitration practices, hopefully leading to the overhaul of the criteria and principles applied by investment arbitration courts.</p><p>Water is an obvious asset in many international investments, including, but not limited to, agriculture, mining, oil, energy, tourism, land development, forestry and provision of water and sanitation services. At the same time, water can be affected by the practices of international investors: it can be polluted, water sources can be affected by economic activities and water-associated risks can be aggravated by defective land practices. Thus, different <u><strong>government activities</u></strong> could potentially <u><strong>conflict with</u></strong> foreign <u><strong>investors by enacting <mark>new regulations</mark>, requiring efficiency in water uses, <mark>reforming</u></strong></mark> the conditions of <u><strong><mark>water permits</mark>, and the like</u></strong>.</p> | 2AC | T — Regulation | 2AC — T-Protection | 36,007 | 167 | 29,674 | ./documents/hspolicy21/Peninsula/LaLa/Peninsula-Lai-Lai-Aff-04%20-%20Meadows-Round4.docx | 753,576 | A | 04 - Meadows | 4 | MBA GH | Conor Cameron | 1AC - Water Marktes
1NC - T-Regulation - T-Oceans - Guidance CP - States CP - Capitalism K - Infrastructure DA
2NR - T-Regulation | hspolicy21/Peninsula/LaLa/Peninsula-Lai-Lai-Aff-04%20-%20Meadows-Round4.docx | null | 64,299 | LaLa | Peninsula LaLa | null | Ke..... | La..... | De..... | La..... | 22,099 | Peninsula | Peninsula | CA | null | 1,020 | hspolicy21 | HS Policy 2021-22 | 2,021 | cx | hs | 2 |
4,089,015 | Those spikes go global. | Klare 12 | Klare 12 Michael Klare 8-7-2012 “The Hunger Wars in Our Future” http://www.huffingtonpost.com/michael-t-klare/the-hunger-wars-in-our-fu_b_1751968.html (professor of peace and world security studies at Hampshire College)//Elmer | so many nations depend on grain imports from the U.S. to supplement their own harvests, and because intense drought and floods are damaging crops elsewhere as well, food supplies are expected to shrink and prices to rise across the planet What happens to the U.S. supply has immense impact around the world As the crops most affected by the drought, corn and soybeans disappear the price of all grains, including wheat, is likely to soar The Hunger Games, 2007-2011 What happens next is, of course, impossible to predict, but if the recent past is any guide, it could turn ugly. In 2007-2008, when rice, corn, and wheat experienced prices hikes of 100 percent or more, sharply higher prices -- especially for bread -- sparked “food riots” in more than two dozen countries, including Bangladesh, Cameroon, Egypt, Haiti, Indonesia, Senegal, and Yemen a surge in food prices resulted in widespread social unrest this time concentrated in North Africa and the Middle East | so many nations depend on grain imports from the U.S. to supplement their own harvests, food supplies are expected to shrink What happens to the U.S. supply has immense impact around the world As corn and soybeans disappear the price of all grains soar higher prices sparked “food riots” in two dozen countries a surge resulted in widespread social unrest | It is in the international arena, however, that the Great Drought is likely to have its most devastating effects. Because so many nations depend on grain imports from the U.S. to supplement their own harvests, and because intense drought and floods are damaging crops elsewhere as well, food supplies are expected to shrink and prices to rise across the planet. “What happens to the U.S. supply has immense impact around the world,” says Robert Thompson, a food expert at the Chicago Council on Global Affairs. As the crops most affected by the drought, corn and soybeans, disappear from world markets, he noted, the price of all grains, including wheat, is likely to soar, causing immense hardship to those who already have trouble affording enough food to feed their families. The Hunger Games, 2007-2011 What happens next is, of course, impossible to predict, but if the recent past is any guide, it could turn ugly. In 2007-2008, when rice, corn, and wheat experienced prices hikes of 100 percent or more, sharply higher prices -- especially for bread -- sparked “food riots” in more than two dozen countries, including Bangladesh, Cameroon, Egypt, Haiti, Indonesia, Senegal, and Yemen. In Haiti, the rioting became so violent and public confidence in the government’s ability to address the problem dropped so precipitously that the Haitian Senate voted to oust the country’s prime minister, Jacques-Édouard Alexis. In other countries, angry protestors clashed with army and police forces, leaving scores dead. Those price increases of 2007-2008 were largely attributed to the soaring cost of oil, which made food production more expensive. (Oil’s use is widespread in farming operations, irrigation, food delivery, and pesticide manufacture.) At the same time, increasing amounts of cropland worldwide were being diverted from food crops to the cultivation of plants used in making biofuels. The next price spike in 2010-11 was, however, closely associated with climate change. An intense drought gripped much of eastern Russia during the summer of 2010, reducing the wheat harvest in that breadbasket region by one-fifth and prompting Moscow to ban all wheat exports. Drought also hurt China’s grain harvest, while intense flooding destroyed much of Australia’s wheat crop. Together with other extreme-weather-related effects, these disasters sent wheat prices soaring by more than 50 percent and the price of most food staples by 32 percent. Once again, a surge in food prices resulted in widespread social unrest, this time concentrated in North Africa and the Middle East. The earliest protests arose over the cost of staples in Algeria and then Tunisia, where -- no coincidence -- the precipitating event was a young food vendor, Mohamed Bouazizi, setting himself on fire to protest government harassment. Anger over rising food and fuel prices combined with long-simmering resentments about government repression and corruption sparked what became known as the Arab Spring. The rising cost of basic staples, especially a loaf of bread, was also a cause of unrest in Egypt, Jordan, and Sudan. Other factors, notably anger at entrenched autocratic regimes, may have proved more powerful in those places, but as the author of Tropic of Chaos, Christian Parenti, wrote, “The initial trouble was traceable, at least in part, to the price of that loaf of bread.” | 3,368 | <h4>Those spikes go <u>global</u>. </h4><p><strong>Klare 12</strong> Michael Klare 8-7-2012 “The Hunger Wars in Our Future” http://www.huffingtonpost.com/michael-t-klare/the-hunger-wars-in-our-fu_b_1751968.html (professor of peace and world security studies at Hampshire College)//Elmer </p><p>It is in the international arena, however, that the Great Drought is likely to have its most devastating effects. Because <u><strong><mark>so many nations</u></strong> <u><strong>depend on grain imports from the U.S. to supplement their own harvests,</u></strong> <u></mark>and because intense drought and floods are damaging crops elsewhere as well, <strong><mark>food supplies are expected to shrink</strong></mark> and prices to rise across the planet</u>. “<u><strong><mark>What happens to the U.S. supply has immense impact around the world</u></strong></mark>,” says Robert Thompson, a food expert at the Chicago Council on Global Affairs. <u><strong><mark>As</u></strong> <u></mark>the crops most affected by the drought,</u> <u><strong><mark>corn and soybeans</u></strong></mark>, <u><strong><mark>disappear</u></strong> </mark>from world markets, he noted, <u><strong><mark>the price of all grains</strong></mark>, including wheat, is likely to</u> <u><strong><mark>soar</u></strong></mark>, causing immense hardship to those who already have trouble affording enough food to feed their families. <u>The Hunger Games, 2007-2011 What happens next is, of course, impossible to predict, but if the recent past is any guide, it could turn ugly. In 2007-2008, when rice, corn, and wheat experienced prices hikes of 100 percent or more, sharply <strong><mark>higher prices</strong> </mark>-- especially for bread -- <strong><mark>sparked “food riots”</strong> <strong>in</strong> </mark>more than <strong><mark>two dozen countries</strong></mark>, including Bangladesh, Cameroon, Egypt, Haiti, Indonesia, Senegal, and Yemen</u>. In Haiti, the rioting became so violent and public confidence in the government’s ability to address the problem dropped so precipitously that the Haitian Senate voted to oust the country’s prime minister, Jacques-Édouard Alexis. In other countries, angry protestors clashed with army and police forces, leaving scores dead. Those price increases of 2007-2008 were largely attributed to the soaring cost of oil, which made food production more expensive. (Oil’s use is widespread in farming operations, irrigation, food delivery, and pesticide manufacture.) At the same time, increasing amounts of cropland worldwide were being diverted from food crops to the cultivation of plants used in making biofuels. The next price spike in 2010-11 was, however, closely associated with climate change. An intense drought gripped much of eastern Russia during the summer of 2010, reducing the wheat harvest in that breadbasket region by one-fifth and prompting Moscow to ban all wheat exports. Drought also hurt China’s grain harvest, while intense flooding destroyed much of Australia’s wheat crop. Together with other extreme-weather-related effects, these disasters sent wheat prices soaring by more than 50 percent and the price of most food staples by 32 percent. Once again, <u><strong><mark>a surge</u></strong> <u></mark>in food prices</u> <u><strong><mark>resulted in widespread social unrest</u></strong></mark>, <u>this time concentrated in North Africa and the Middle East</u>. The earliest protests arose over the cost of staples in Algeria and then Tunisia, where -- no coincidence -- the precipitating event was a young food vendor, Mohamed Bouazizi, setting himself on fire to protest government harassment. Anger over rising food and fuel prices combined with long-simmering resentments about government repression and corruption sparked what became known as the Arab Spring. The rising cost of basic staples, especially a loaf of bread, was also a cause of unrest in Egypt, Jordan, and Sudan. Other factors, notably anger at entrenched autocratic regimes, may have proved more powerful in those places, but as the author of Tropic of Chaos, Christian Parenti, wrote, “The initial trouble was traceable, at least in part, to the price of that loaf of bread.” </p> | 1AC vs K (send) | ***1AC*** | 1AC: Rural Economies | 89,860 | 328 | 140,168 | ./documents/hsld22/StrathHaven/AvMa/StrathHaven-AvMa-Aff-Loyola-Invitational-Round-3.docx | 921,159 | A | Loyola Invitational | 3 | Troy Independent AP | Nethmin Liyanage | 1AC - Stock
1NC - ESPEC, States CP, Midterms DA, Cap K, case
1AR - all, RVIs, condo bad, 50 state fiat bad, private multi-actor fiat bad
2NR - theory, K
2AR - private multi-actor fiat bad, case, K | hsld22/StrathHaven/AvMa/StrathHaven-AvMa-Aff-Loyola-Invitational-Round-3.docx | 2022-09-03 17:09:20 | 79,344 | AvMa | Strath Haven AvMa | big furry
? sophia tian
meow
- also sophia tian
Hey, I'm Ava! She/her pronouns, let me know if you'd like any accommodations for the round. See bottom for a trigger warning!!!
Email is your best bet ([email protected]).
I os everything, cites don't work for some reason.
Let me know if there's any disclosure/theory interps you want me to meet.
Check out Circuit Debater! https://ld.circuitdebater.org/w/index.php/Library
Hmu if you want to start a petition to go back to the old wiki!
***TW: Big Data AC for SO says the word s**cide in it --- it's non-graphic (literally just the word is in a card), I can absolutely take it out, so please let me know before round if that's triggering/makes you uncomfortable in the slightest!*** | Av..... | Ma..... | null | null | 26,586 | StrathHaven | Strath Haven | PA | 4,417 | 2,003 | hsld22 | HS LD 2022-23 | 2,022 | ld | hs | 1 |
4,693,019 | Open-borders leads to the rise of right-wing populists – that decks global growth. | Kaufmann, 2021 | Kaufmann, 7-21-2021 (Eric Kaufmann, Eric Kaufmann is Professor of Politics at Birkbeck College, University of London. He is the author of Whiteshift: Populism, Immigration and the Future of White Majorities (Penguin 2018; Abrams 2019); Shall the Religious Inherit the Earth (Profile 2010), The Rise and Fall of Anglo-America (Harvard 2004), The Orange Order (Oxford 2007) and Unionism and Orangeism in Northern Ireland since 1945 with H. Patterson (Manchester 2007). He is co-editor, among others, of Political Demography (Oxford 2012) and Whither the Child: Causes and Consequences of Low Fertility (Paradigm 2012), and editor of Rethinking Ethnicity: Majority Groups and Dominant Minorities (Routledge 2004). An editor of the journal Nations & Nationalism, he has written for New York Times, Times of London, Financial Times, Newsweek International, Foreign Policy and Prospect magazines., "Divided: Open Borders And The Political Fracturing Of Societies," Cato Unbound, https://www.cato-unbound.org/2021/07/21/eric-kaufmann/divided-open-borders-political-fracturing-societies/, accessed on 12-15-2022) AB | In the West, the rise of populist right parties is linked to higher levels of immigration. In Europe, study of 10 countries found a significant correlation between changes in immigration levels and populist right voting. immigration broke through as a central issue in American politics.
The counter-claim that diverse areas like major cities do not vote for populism, and that therefore diversity has nothing to do with the rise of populism, is misleading. there is very little difference in support for national populism between diverse regions and homogeneous ones. white working-class Londoners are as likely as rural white working-class voters to have voted Leave. In Eastern Europe, it is countries located inside the EU and thus exposed to potential immigration, like Hungary, rather than outside it, like Serbia, that have seen an upsurge of national populism.
The rise of populism is a prelude to a more intractable political polarization as the basis of politics shifts from class and economics to culture . In Britain, the Conservative Party now has a more working-class composition than the Labour Party, something absolutely unthinkable from the 19th century until 1997. In the United States, the Republicans are also becoming much more working-class, while the Democrats control the wealthiest ZIP codes in the country. The reason for this change is that attitudes to immigration have become more important than views on economic redistribution for voting.
Meta analyses of immigration attitudes find that people’s views on immigration have virtually nothing to do with their income or employment situation. Instead, they are shaped by deep-seated psychological preferences. The populist response to immigration triggers a moralistic politics among “identity liberals,” This demonization of the white working class and populist conservatives in turn produces blowback against the elite, setting in motion a toxic ratchet of accusation and counter-accusation, a zero-sum conflict with no room for compromise.
A secondary reflex arising out of anti-immigration populism is for populists to sour on globalization, withdraw from international institutions, and move toward isolationism in foreign policy. hostility to immigration and increased diversity tends to shape economic attitudes such as support for free trade. the rise of populism seems linked to more protectionism and mistrust of multilateral institutions, which can hardly be conducive to global growth.
Electorally, the rise of populism and shift of the basis of politics from economics to culture benefits the right left-wing anti-immigration voters change the character of the conservative parties they join. Since 2017, Britain’s Conservative Party has embraced high public spending and the “leveling up” of poorer regions because they get more of their seats from these areas than used to be the case under Thatcher. In the United States, fiscal conservatives with their tax cuts still dominate in Congress, but Trump did particularly well among left-leaning anti-immigration Republicans who support Social Security, Medicare, and infrastructure spending. Do not discount the possibility of a more Michael Lind/Theodore Roosevelt-style populist Republicanism emerging in the future and tacking left on economics but right on culture.
even if my objective function was merely to maximize global wealth and economic freedom, I think open borders is the wrong move. It will result in increasingly fractious host societies, stimulating populism, polarization, protectionism, and even civil violence. | the rise of populist right parties is linked to higher levels of immigration.
The rise of populism is a prelude to polarization immigration become more important than economic redistribution for voting
Meta analyses find people’s views on immigration are shaped by deep-seated preferences The populist response produces blowback , a zero-sum conflict
arising out of anti-immigration populism is for populists to sour on globalization, withdraw from international institutions, and move toward isolationism hostility to immigration shape economic attitudes for free trade protectionism and mistrust of institutions
the rise of populism benefits the right
to maximize global economic freedom, open borders is the wrong move. It will result in fractious societies, stimulating populism, polarization, protectionism, and civil violence. | In the West, the rise of populist right parties is linked to higher levels of immigration. In Europe, James Dennison and Andrew Geddes’s (2019) study of 10 countries between 2005 and 2016 found a significant correlation between changes in immigration levels, the salience of immigration for voters, and populist right voting. The United States is a partial exception to this rule insofar as universalist conservatism—a fusion of the religious right, neoconservatism and fiscal conservatism—among conservative media and political elites kept the immigration issue away from the center of federal politics. But, beginning with Pat Buchanan and Pete Wilson in the early 1990s, moving through to local anti-immigration ordinances in the 2000s, and then, via the grassroots Tea Party and congressional Republicans to Trump in 2015, immigration broke through as a central issue in American politics.
The counter-claim that diverse areas like major cities do not vote for populism, and that therefore diversity has nothing to do with the rise of populism, is misleading. Once one accounts for age, education and nonwhite share, there is very little difference in support for national populism between diverse regions and homogeneous ones. London, for instance, voted to remain in the European Union, but it is only 45 percent white British and is younger and has more residents with college degrees than the rest of England. 38 percent of the capital still voted Leave, and white working-class Londoners are as likely as rural white working-class voters to have voted Leave. In Eastern Europe, it is countries located inside the EU and thus exposed to potential immigration, like Hungary, rather than outside it, like Serbia, that have seen an upsurge of national populism.
The rise of populism is a prelude to a more intractable political polarization as the basis of politics shifts from class and economics (left vs right) to culture (nationalist vs cosmopolitan). In Britain, the Conservative Party now has a more working-class composition than the Labour Party, something absolutely unthinkable from the 19th century until 1997. In the United States, the Republicans are also becoming much more working-class, while the Democrats control the wealthiest ZIP codes in the country. The reason for this change is that attitudes to immigration have become more important than views on economic redistribution for voting.
Meta analyses of immigration attitudes, notably Hainmueller and Hopkins (2014), find that people’s views on immigration have virtually nothing to do with their income or employment situation. Instead, they are shaped by deep-seated psychological preferences. Whether one views difference as disorder or as interesting, whether one views change as loss or as stimulating, is half heritable. Trying to teach or shame these inclinations out of people only leads to resentment (Stenner 2005). We thus see radically different responses to immigration within the white population of western countries. The populist response to immigration triggers a moralistic politics among what Sobolewska and Ford (2020) term “identity liberals,” many of whom are younger, urban, and highly educated. This demonization of the white working class and populist conservatives, such as Brexiteers or Trump voters, in turn produces blowback against the elite, setting in motion a toxic ratchet of accusation and counter-accusation, a zero-sum conflict with no room for compromise.
How does this affect economic freedom and growth? A secondary reflex arising out of anti-immigration populism is for populists to sour on globalization, withdraw from international institutions, and move toward isolationism in foreign policy. This is because, as Yotam Margalit (2019) has shown, hostility to immigration and increased diversity tends to shape economic attitudes such as support for free trade. This is not a straightforward relationship: Brexit reduced Britain’s ties to Europe but opened it up, potentially, to ties to non-EU markets. Yet the rise of populism seems linked to more protectionism and mistrust of multilateral institutions, which can hardly be conducive to global growth.
There are some counter trends. Electorally, the rise of populism and shift of the basis of politics from economics to culture benefits the right, with the European left recording their worst results since 1945 in country after country as the white working class shifts right. This probably weakens the left and protects economic freedom in an age of surging inequality, but we also must bear in mind that left-wing anti-immigration voters change the character of the conservative parties they join. Since 2017, Britain’s Conservative Party has embraced high public spending and the “leveling up” of poorer regions because they get more of their seats from these areas than used to be the case under Thatcher. In the United States, fiscal conservatives with their tax cuts still dominate in Congress, but Trump did particularly well among left-leaning anti-immigration Republicans who support Social Security, Medicare, and infrastructure spending. Do not discount the possibility of a more Michael Lind/Theodore Roosevelt-style populist Republicanism emerging in the future and tacking left on economics but right on culture.
I am more of a believer in the virtues of a welfare state than Powell and Nowrasteh. I also think a world in which we must be as attached to strangers as to those we have special ties to is a worse one than the one we currently inhabit. But even if my objective function was merely to maximize global wealth and economic freedom, I think open borders is the wrong move. It will result in increasingly fractious host societies, stimulating populism, polarization, protectionism, and even civil violence. | 5,803 | <h4>Open-borders leads to the rise of right-wing populists – that decks global growth.</h4><p><strong>Kaufmann,</strong> 7-21-<strong>2021<u></strong> (Eric Kaufmann, Eric Kaufmann is Professor of Politics at Birkbeck College, University of London. He is the author of Whiteshift: Populism, Immigration and the Future of White Majorities (Penguin 2018; Abrams 2019); Shall the Religious Inherit the Earth (Profile 2010), The Rise and Fall of Anglo-America (Harvard 2004), The Orange Order (Oxford 2007) and Unionism and Orangeism in Northern Ireland since 1945 with H. Patterson (Manchester 2007). He is co-editor, among others, of Political Demography (Oxford 2012) and Whither the Child: Causes and Consequences of Low Fertility (Paradigm 2012), and editor of Rethinking Ethnicity: Majority Groups and Dominant Minorities (Routledge 2004). An editor of the journal Nations & Nationalism, he has written for New York Times, Times of London, Financial Times, Newsweek International, Foreign Policy and Prospect magazines., "Divided: Open Borders And The Political Fracturing Of Societies," Cato Unbound, https://www.cato-unbound.org/2021/07/21/eric-kaufmann/divided-open-borders-political-fracturing-societies/, accessed on 12-15-2022) AB</p><p>In the West,<strong> <mark>the rise of populist right parties is linked to higher levels of immigration</strong>.</mark> In Europe,</u> James Dennison and Andrew Geddes’s (2019) <u>study of 10 countries </u>between 2005 and 2016 <u>found a significant correlation between changes in immigration levels</u>, the salience of immigration for voters,<u> and populist right voting. </u>The United States is a partial exception to this rule insofar as universalist conservatism—a fusion of the religious right, neoconservatism and fiscal conservatism—among conservative media and political elites kept the immigration issue away from the center of federal politics. But, beginning with Pat Buchanan and Pete Wilson in the early 1990s, moving through to local anti-immigration ordinances in the 2000s, and then, via the grassroots Tea Party and congressional Republicans to Trump in 2015, <u>immigration broke through as <strong>a central issue in American politics</strong>.</p><p>The counter-claim that diverse areas like major cities do not vote for populism, and that therefore diversity has nothing to do with the rise of populism, is <strong>misleading</strong>.</u> Once one accounts for age, education and nonwhite share,<u> there is very little difference in support for national populism between diverse regions and homogeneous ones.</u> London, for instance, voted to remain in the European Union, but it is only 45 percent white British and is younger and has more residents with college degrees than the rest of England. 38 percent of the capital still voted Leave, and <u>white working-class Londoners are as likely as rural white working-class voters to have voted Leave. In Eastern Europe, it is countries located inside the EU and thus exposed to potential immigration, like Hungary, rather than outside it, like Serbia, that have seen an <strong>upsurge of national populism</strong>.</p><p><mark>The rise of populism is a prelude to</mark> a more intractable political <mark>polarization</mark> as the basis of politics shifts from class and economics</u> (left vs right) <u>to culture</u> (nationalist vs cosmopolitan)<u>. In Britain, the Conservative Party now has a more working-class composition than the Labour Party, something absolutely unthinkable from the 19th century until 1997. In the United States, the Republicans are also becoming much more working-class, while the Democrats control the wealthiest ZIP codes in the country. The reason for this change is that<strong> attitudes to <mark>immigration</mark> have <mark>become more important than</mark> views on <mark>economic redistribution for voting</strong></mark>.</p><p><mark>Meta analyses</mark> of immigration attitudes</u>, notably Hainmueller and Hopkins (2014),<u> <mark>find</mark> that <mark>people’s views on immigration</mark> have virtually nothing to do with their income or employment situation. Instead, they <mark>are shaped by deep-seated</mark> psychological <mark>preferences</mark>.</u> Whether one views difference as disorder or as interesting, whether one views change as loss or as stimulating, is half heritable. Trying to teach or shame these inclinations out of people only leads to resentment (Stenner 2005). We thus see radically different responses to immigration within the white population of western countries.<u> <mark>The populist response</mark> to immigration triggers a moralistic politics among </u>what Sobolewska and Ford (2020) term<u> “identity liberals,”</u> many of whom are younger, urban, and highly educated. <u>This demonization of the white working class and populist conservatives</u>, such as Brexiteers or Trump voters, <u>in turn <mark>produces <strong>blowback</strong></mark> against the elite, setting in motion a toxic ratchet of accusation and counter-accusation<mark>, a zero-sum conflict<strong></mark> with no room for compromise.</p><p></u></strong>How does this affect economic freedom and growth? <u>A secondary reflex <mark>arising out of anti-immigration populism is for populists to <strong>sour on globalization</strong>,<strong> withdraw from international institutions</strong>, and move toward <strong>isolationism</strong></mark> in foreign policy. </u>This is because, as Yotam Margalit (2019) has shown, <u><mark>hostility to immigration</mark> and increased diversity tends to <strong><mark>shape</strong> economic attitudes </mark>such as support <mark>for free trade</mark>. </u>This is not a straightforward relationship: Brexit reduced Britain’s ties to Europe but opened it up, potentially, to ties to non-EU markets. Yet <u>the rise of populism seems linked to more <mark>protectionism and mistrust of </mark>multilateral <mark>institutions</mark>, which can hardly be conducive to global growth.</p><p></u>There are some counter trends. <u>Electorally, <mark>the rise of populism</mark> and shift of the basis of politics from economics to culture <mark>benefits the right</u></mark>, with the European left recording their worst results since 1945 in country after country as the white working class shifts right. This probably weakens the left and protects economic freedom in an age of surging inequality, but we also must bear in mind that <u>left-wing anti-immigration voters change the character of the conservative parties they join. <strong>Since 2017, Britain’s Conservative Party has embraced high public spending and the “leveling up” of poorer regions because they get more of their seats from these areas than used to be the case under Thatcher. In the United States, fiscal conservatives with their tax cuts still dominate in Congress, but Trump did particularly well among left-leaning anti-immigration Republicans who support Social Security, Medicare, and infrastructure spending. Do not discount the possibility of a more Michael Lind/Theodore Roosevelt-style populist Republicanism emerging in the future and tacking left on economics but right on culture.</p><p></u></strong>I am more of a believer in the virtues of a welfare state than Powell and Nowrasteh. I also think a world in which we must be as attached to strangers as to those we have special ties to is a worse one than the one we currently inhabit. But <u>even if my objective function was merely <mark>to maximize global </mark>wealth and <mark>economic freedom,</mark> I think <strong><mark>open borders is the wrong move</strong>. <strong>It will result in</mark> increasingly <mark>fractious</mark> host <mark>societies, stimulating populism, polarization, protectionism, and</mark> even <mark>civil violence.</p></u></strong></mark> | null | 1 | null | 1,699,114 | 212 | 163,517 | ./documents/hsld22/Harker/SoSh/Harker-SoSh-Neg-37th-Annual-Stanford-Invitational-Round-2.docx | 975,148 | N | 37th Annual Stanford Invitational | 2 | Cary RR | Vu | 1ac - schengen
1nc - taxes, populism da, case
1ar- all
2nr - pop da. case
2ar - all | hsld22/Harker/SoSh/Harker-SoSh-Neg-37th-Annual-Stanford-Invitational-Round-2.docx | 2023-02-12 08:09:56 | 80,962 | SoSh | Harker SoSh | null | So..... | Sh..... | null | null | 26,565 | Harker | Harker | CA | null | 2,003 | hsld22 | HS LD 2022-23 | 2,022 | ld | hs | 1 |
2,690,913 | A victorious Russia will install a global white supremacist regime that co-opts racial radicalism in the service of neo-fascist geopolitical goals | Coursey 18 | Lee Edwin Coursey 18. International affairs and history analyst and software engineer in the field of artificial intelligence. 01-07-18. “Russia’s Plan for World Domination – and America’s Unwitting Cooperation With It.” LeeCoWeb. https://www.leecoweb.com/russian_plan/ | after the Cold War, Russia experienced a crushing recession that left millions unemployed. The subsequent vacuum saw rapid expansion of the European Union NATO expanded adding over a dozen European countries This expansion has put NATO allies, and NATO weapons, into countries immediately bordering Russia. The spread of western ideals such as free speech, free and open elections, and multiculturalism into eastern Europe are perceived as a threat to Russian culture From the Russian point of view, the collapse of the Soviet Union and the end of the Cold War was both a humiliating defeat and a harsh rebuke A new post-Soviet, neo-fascist political philosophy rose from the ashes of Communism, and Russia is actively engaged in pursuing this philosophy. Their goal is nothing less than the creation of a new Eurasian Empire controlled by Russia Aleksandr Dugin defined new Russian strategy in a 600-page treatise entitled Foundations of Geopolitics. There has not been another book published in Russia during the post-communist period which has exerted an influence on Russian military, police, and statist foreign policy elites comparable to Dugin’s neo-fascist treatise Russia’s ultimate goal should be nothing less than rule of the world by ethnic Russians The philosophical basis for this empire will include the rejection of “Atlanticism,” identification of America as a common enemy, and refusal to allow traditional liberal political ideals to affect Russia’s society or political system the Russian political elites, headed by Putin, view Dugin’s new Eurasian Empire not as a restoration of an idealized Russian Empire, but as a replacement for the Soviet Union Eurasianism provides an ideological basis for a new form of Russian imperialism In terms of tactics, Foundations of Geopolitics recommends subversion of America and its alliances by encouraging and supporting separatism, isolationism, nationalism, and the creation of factions. It also calls for supporting radical separatist movements in western countries including support for organizations that espouse extremist racist and sectarian ideals. Here is a passage : “It is especially important to introduce geopolitical disorder into internal American activity, encouraging all kinds of separatism and ethnic, social and racial conflicts, actively supporting all dissident movements — extremist, racist, and sectarian groups, thus destabilizing internal political processes in the U.S. It would also make sense simultaneously to support isolationist tendencies in American politics.” Russia’s actions, both overt and covert, offer strong indications that her political and military leaders are actively pursuing the strategy described in Foundations “A social media campaign calling itself “Blacktivist” and linked to the Russian government used Facebook and Twitter in an apparent attempt to amplify racial tensions during the U.S. presidential election. Both Blacktivist accounts regularly shared content intended to stoke outrage. “Black people should wake up as soon as possible,” fake accounts provide evidence that Russian-linked social media accounts saw racial tensions as something to be exploited in order to achieve the broader Russian goal of dividing Americans and creating chaos Russian propaganda and incitements to separatism are spread through social media the ads and accounts appeared to focus on amplifying divisive social and political messages across the ideological spectrum — touching on topics from LGBT matters to race issues to immigration to gun rights. | western ideals are perceived as a threat to Russian culture From the Russian point of view, the collapse of the Soviet Union was a humiliating defeat A new post-Soviet, neo-fascist political philosophy rose from the ashes Their goal is a new Eurasian Empire controlled by Russia Dugin exerted an influence on Russian military, police, and statist elites comparable to Dugin’s neo-fascist treatise Russia’s goal nothing less than rule of the world by ethnic Russians In terms of tactics calls for supporting radical separatist movements that espouse racist ideals encouraging racial conflicts destabilizing internal political processes A social media campaign linked to the Russian used Facebook and Twitter to amplify racial tensions dividing Americans and creating chaos | In the aftermath of the Cold War, Russia experienced a crushing recession that left millions unemployed. The subsequent vacuum in the decades that followed saw the rapid expansion of the European Union and its single free market eastward. The EU now includes several former Soviet states, including some immediately bordering Russia (e.g., Estonia and Latvia.) More importantly, from a Russian security perspective, the NATO military alliance also expanded aggressively eastward after the Cold War, adding over a dozen European countries as members between 1999 and 2017. This expansion has put NATO allies, and NATO weapons, into countries immediately bordering Russia. The spread of western ideals such as free speech, free and open elections, and multiculturalism into eastern Europe are perceived as a threat to Russian culture and Russian influence. From the Russian point of view, the collapse of the Soviet Union and the end of the Cold War was both a humiliating defeat and a harsh rebuke of Soviet-style Communism. A new post-Soviet, neo-fascist political philosophy rose from the ashes of Communism, and Russia is actively engaged in pursuing this philosophy. Their goal is nothing less than the creation of a new Eurasian Empire controlled by, and answering to, Russia. A New Blueprint (or “Putin’s To-Do List”) The Russian political elite could not tolerate the growing threat on their western border, but they needed a new geopolitical strategy – one that would establish goals and methods different from those that had failed the Soviet Union. In 1997, Aleksandr Dugin articulated and defined that new Russian strategy in a 600-page treatise entitled Foundations of Geopolitics. According to historian and Hoover Institution specialist John B. Dunlop, “There has probably not been another book published in Russia during the post-communist period which has exerted an influence on Russian military, police, and statist foreign policy elites comparable to that of Aleksandr Dugin’s 1997 neo-fascist treatise.” The Foundations of Geopolitics sold out in four editions, and continues to be assigned as a textbook at the General Staff Academy and other military universities in Russia. [source] Eurasian-ism As espoused by Dugin, Russia’s ultimate goal should be nothing less than rule of the world by ethnic Russians, based on a Eurasian empire extending from “Dublin to Vladivostok.” The philosophical basis for this empire will include the rejection of “Atlanticism,” identification of America as a common enemy, and refusal to allow traditional liberal political ideals (e.g., freedom of the press, freedom of speech, free markets, civil rights, etc.,) to affect Russia’s society or political system. According to political scientist Andreas Umland, the Russian political elites, headed by Vladimir Putin, view Dugin’s new Eurasian Empire not as a restoration of an idealized Russian Empire, but as a replacement for the Soviet Union. Eurasianism provides an ideological basis for a new form of Russian imperialism. As for strategic stepping stones toward a new Russian empire, Dugin offers a long list objectives. I have listed just a few of these below: Separate the United Kingdom from Europe. Russian annexation of Ukraine. A strategic alliance between Russia and Iran. Create “geopolitical shocks” within Turkey. Russian annexation of Tibet, Mongolia, and Manchuria. Finland should be absorbed into Russia. Encourage Germany and France to cooperate with each other and isolate themselves from Europe. Dismember the nation of Georgia. Geopolitical defeat of the United States Sound familiar? In terms of tactics, Foundations of Geopolitics recommends subversion of America and its alliances by encouraging and supporting separatism, isolationism, nationalism, and the creation of factions. It also calls for supporting radical separatist movements in western countries, including support for organizations that espouse extremist, racist, and sectarian ideals. Here is a passage taken directly from Dugin’s Foundations of Geopolitics (via Dunlop): “It is especially important to introduce geopolitical disorder into internal American activity, encouraging all kinds of separatism and ethnic, social and racial conflicts, actively supporting all dissident movements — extremist, racist, and sectarian groups, thus destabilizing internal political processes in the U.S. It would also make sense simultaneously to support isolationist tendencies in American politics.” Evidence Russia Is Actively Pursuing Dugin’s Strategy Russia’s actions, both overt and covert, offer strong indications that her political and military leaders are actively pursuing the strategy described in Foundations. The overt actions include: Russian invasion of the nation of Georgia (2008.) Russian annexation of the Crimea region of Ukraine (2014.) Economic and military support for anti-western regimes in Syria and Iran. As for covert (or disguised) actions by the Russian government in support of the Foundations strategy, consider these recent findings from western intelligence and news agencies: BREXIT: “More than 150,000 Russian-language Twitter accounts posted tens of thousands of messages in English urging Britain to leave the European Union in the days before last year’s referendum on the issue. … Most of the messages sought to inflame fears about Muslims and immigrants to help drive the vote.” – New York Times, 15-NOV-2017 US ELECTIONS: “Posts that circulated to a targeted, swing-state audience on Facebook railed against illegal immigrants and claimed “the only viable option is to elect Trump.” They were shared by what looked like a grassroots American, anti-immigrant group called Secured Borders, but Congressional investigators say the group is actually a Russian fabrication designed to influence American voters during and after the presidential election.” – ABC News, 27-SEP-2017 US ELECTIONS: “Russian agents intending to sow discord among American citizens disseminated inflammatory posts that reached 126 million users on Facebook, published more than 131,000 messages on Twitter and uploaded over 1,000 videos to Google’s YouTube service.” – New York Times, 30-OCT-2017 US ELECTIONS: “In July 2015, Russian intelligence gained access to Democratic National Committee (DNC) networks and maintained that access until at least June 2016.” – Findings from the Office of the Director of National Intelligence, 6-JAN-2017 US SOCIAL UNREST: “Two Russian Facebook pages organized dueling rallies in front of the Islamic Da’wah Center of Houston. Heart of Texas, a Russian-controlled Facebook group that promoted Texas secession, leaned into an image of the state as a land of guns and barbecue and amassed hundreds of thousands of followers. One of their ads on Facebook announced a noon rally on May 21, 2016 to “Stop Islamification of Texas.” A separate Russian-sponsored group, United Muslims of America, advertised a “Save Islamic Knowledge” rally for the same place and time. – The Texas Tribune, 1-NOV-2017 US SOCIAL UNREST: “A social media campaign calling itself “Blacktivist” and linked to the Russian government used both Facebook and Twitter in an apparent attempt to amplify racial tensions during the U.S. presidential election. Both Blacktivist accounts regularly shared content intended to stoke outrage. “Black people should wake up as soon as possible,” one post on the Twitter account read. “Black families are divided and destroyed by mass incarceration and death of black men,” another read. The accounts also posted videos of police violence against African Americans. These fake accounts provide further evidence that Russian-linked social media accounts saw racial tensions as something to be exploited in order to achieve the broader Russian goal of dividing Americans and creating chaos.” CNN, 28-SEP-2017 NOTE TO READERS: Even in light of the information above, I DO NOT necessarily believe that Hillary Clinton would have won the 2016 US Presidential election in the absence of Russian interference – I simply do not have enough data from which to draw that conclusion. I am however certain that Russia wanted Trump to win and spent millions of dollars on propaganda directed at Americans toward that end. How We (Americans) Are Helping Russia Achieve Its Imperialistic Goals Russian propaganda and incitements to separatism are spread through social media, and their success depends on our willingness to reflexively share stories that outrage us. As unwitting agents for Russia, each of us is helping spread the seeds of our own political and economic demise. Hundreds of fake Facebook accounts operating from within Russia purchased $100,000 worth of Facebook ads between mid-2015 and early 2017. These fake Facebook accounts managed to reach 126 million Facebook users during this time frame. Besides their sheer volume, one of the most striking aspects of the ads purchased by these fake accounts is their alignment with the strategy described in Foundations of Geopolitics, namely the creation of division and mistrust among Americans. Alex Stamos, the Chief Information Security Officer for Facebook, issued a statement about the ad placements on September 6, 2017. In it, he made these observations: The vast majority of ads run by these accounts didn’t specifically reference the US presidential election, voting or a particular candidate. Rather, the ads and accounts appeared to focus on amplifying divisive social and political messages across the ideological spectrum — touching on topics from LGBT matters to race issues to immigration to gun rights. | 9,606 | <h4>A victorious Russia will install a <u>global white supremacist regime</u> that co-opts racial radicalism in the service of neo-fascist geopolitical goals</h4><p>Lee Edwin <strong>Coursey 18<u></strong>. International affairs and history analyst and software engineer in the field of artificial intelligence. 01-07-18. “Russia’s Plan for World Domination – and America’s Unwitting Cooperation With It.” LeeCoWeb. https://www.leecoweb.com/russian_plan/</p><p></u>In the <u>after</u>math of <u>the Cold War, Russia experienced a crushing recession that left millions unemployed. The subsequent vacuum</u> in the decades that followed <u>saw</u> the <u>rapid expansion of the European Union </u>and its single free market eastward. The EU now includes several former Soviet states, including some immediately bordering Russia (e.g., Estonia and Latvia.) More importantly, from a Russian security perspective, the <u>NATO</u> military alliance also <u>expanded</u> aggressively eastward after the Cold War, <u>adding over a dozen European countries</u> as members between 1999 and 2017. <u>This expansion has put NATO allies, and NATO weapons, into countries immediately bordering Russia. The spread of <mark>western ideals</mark> such as free speech, free and open elections, and multiculturalism into eastern Europe <mark>are perceived as a <strong>threat to Russian culture</u></strong></mark> and Russian influence. <u><mark>From the Russian point of view, the collapse of the Soviet Union</mark> and the end of the Cold War <mark>was</mark> both <mark>a <strong>humiliating defeat</u></strong></mark> <u>and a <strong>harsh rebuke</u></strong> of Soviet-style Communism. <u><mark>A new <strong>post-Soviet, neo-fascist political philosophy</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>rose from the ashes</mark> of Communism, and Russia is actively engaged in pursuing this philosophy. <mark>Their goal is</mark> nothing less than the creation of <mark>a <strong>new Eurasian Empire controlled by</u></strong></mark>, and answering to, <u><strong><mark>Russia</u></strong></mark>. A New Blueprint (or “Putin’s To-Do List”) The Russian political elite could not tolerate the growing threat on their western border, but they needed a new geopolitical strategy – one that would establish goals and methods different from those that had failed the Soviet Union. In 1997, <u><strong>Aleksandr <mark>Dugin</u></strong></mark> articulated and <u><strong>defined</u></strong> that <u>new Russian strategy in a 600-page treatise entitled Foundations of Geopolitics.</u> According to historian and Hoover Institution specialist John B. Dunlop, “<u>There has</u> probably <u>not been another book published in Russia during the post-communist period which has <mark>exerted an influence on Russian <strong>military, police, and statist</mark> foreign policy <mark>elites comparable</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>to</u></mark> that of Aleksandr <u><mark>Dugin’s</u></mark> 1997 <u><strong><mark>neo-fascist</u></strong></mark> <u><strong><mark>treatise</u></strong></mark>.” The Foundations of Geopolitics sold out in four editions, and continues to be assigned as a textbook at the General Staff Academy and other military universities in Russia. [source] Eurasian-ism As espoused by Dugin, <u><mark>Russia’s</mark> ultimate <mark>goal</mark> should be <mark>nothing less than <strong>rule of the world by ethnic Russians</u></strong></mark>, based on a Eurasian empire extending from “Dublin to Vladivostok.” <u>The philosophical basis for this empire will include the rejection of “Atlanticism,” identification of America as a common enemy, and refusal to allow traditional liberal political ideals</u> (e.g., freedom of the press, freedom of speech, free markets, civil rights, etc.,) <u>to affect Russia’s society or political system</u>. According to political scientist Andreas Umland, <u>the Russian political elites, headed by</u> Vladimir <u>Putin, view Dugin’s new Eurasian Empire not as a restoration of an idealized <strong>Russian</strong> Empire, but as a <strong>replacement for the Soviet Union</u></strong>. <u>Eurasianism provides an ideological basis for a new form of Russian imperialism</u>. As for strategic stepping stones toward a new Russian empire, Dugin offers a long list objectives. I have listed just a few of these below: Separate the United Kingdom from Europe. Russian annexation of Ukraine. A strategic alliance between Russia and Iran. Create “geopolitical shocks” within Turkey. Russian annexation of Tibet, Mongolia, and Manchuria. Finland should be absorbed into Russia. Encourage Germany and France to cooperate with each other and isolate themselves from Europe. Dismember the nation of Georgia. Geopolitical defeat of the United States Sound familiar? <u><mark>In terms of <strong>tactics</strong></mark>,</u> <u>Foundations of Geopolitics</u> <u>recommends <strong>subversion of America and its alliances</u></strong> <u>by encouraging and supporting <strong>separatism</strong>, isolationism, nationalism, and the creation of <strong>factions</strong>. It also <mark>calls for <strong>supporting radical separatist movements</mark> in western countries</u></strong>, <u>including support for organizations <mark>that espouse</u></mark> <u><strong>extremist</u></strong>, <u><strong><mark>racist</u></strong></mark>, <u>and</u> <u><strong>sectarian <mark>ideals</strong></mark>. Here is a passage</u> taken directly from Dugin’s Foundations of Geopolitics (via Dunlop)<u><strong>:</u></strong> <u><strong>“</strong>It is especially important to introduce geopolitical disorder into internal American activity, <mark>encouraging</mark> all kinds of separatism and <strong>ethnic</strong>, <strong>social</strong> and <strong><mark>racial conflicts</strong></mark>, actively supporting all <strong>dissident movements</u></strong> <u>— extremist, racist, and sectarian groups, thus <strong><mark>destabilizing internal political processes</strong></mark> in the U.S. It would also make sense simultaneously to support isolationist tendencies in American politics.” </u>Evidence Russia Is Actively Pursuing Dugin’s Strategy <u>Russia’s actions, both <strong>overt</strong> and <strong>covert</strong>, offer <strong>strong indications that her political and military leaders are actively pursuing the strategy described in Foundations</u></strong>. The overt actions include: Russian invasion of the nation of Georgia (2008.) Russian annexation of the Crimea region of Ukraine (2014.) Economic and military support for anti-western regimes in Syria and Iran. As for covert (or disguised) actions by the Russian government in support of the Foundations strategy, consider these recent findings from western intelligence and news agencies: BREXIT: “More than 150,000 Russian-language Twitter accounts posted tens of thousands of messages in English urging Britain to leave the European Union in the days before last year’s referendum on the issue. … Most of the messages sought to inflame fears about Muslims and immigrants to help drive the vote.” – New York Times, 15-NOV-2017 US ELECTIONS: “Posts that circulated to a targeted, swing-state audience on Facebook railed against illegal immigrants and claimed “the only viable option is to elect Trump.” They were shared by what looked like a grassroots American, anti-immigrant group called Secured Borders, but Congressional investigators say the group is actually a Russian fabrication designed to influence American voters during and after the presidential election.” – ABC News, 27-SEP-2017 US ELECTIONS: “Russian agents intending to sow discord among American citizens disseminated inflammatory posts that reached 126 million users on Facebook, published more than 131,000 messages on Twitter and uploaded over 1,000 videos to Google’s YouTube service.” – New York Times, 30-OCT-2017 US ELECTIONS: “In July 2015, Russian intelligence gained access to Democratic National Committee (DNC) networks and maintained that access until at least June 2016.” – Findings from the Office of the Director of National Intelligence, 6-JAN-2017 US SOCIAL UNREST: “Two Russian Facebook pages organized dueling rallies in front of the Islamic Da’wah Center of Houston. Heart of Texas, a Russian-controlled Facebook group that promoted Texas secession, leaned into an image of the state as a land of guns and barbecue and amassed hundreds of thousands of followers. One of their ads on Facebook announced a noon rally on May 21, 2016 to “Stop Islamification of Texas.” A separate Russian-sponsored group, United Muslims of America, advertised a “Save Islamic Knowledge” rally for the same place and time. – The Texas Tribune, 1-NOV-2017 US SOCIAL UNREST: <u>“<mark>A social media campaign</mark> calling itself <strong>“Blacktivist”</u></strong> <u>and</u> <u><strong><mark>linked to the Russian</mark> government</u></strong> <u><mark>used</u></mark> both <u><strong><mark>Facebook and Twitter</u></strong></mark> <u>in an apparent attempt <mark>to <strong>amplify racial tensions</u></strong></mark> <u>during the U.S. presidential election. Both Blacktivist accounts regularly shared content intended to stoke outrage. “Black people should wake up as soon as possible,”</u> one post on the Twitter account read. “Black families are divided and destroyed by mass incarceration and death of black men,” another read. The accounts also posted videos of police violence against African Americans. These <u>fake accounts provide</u> further <u>evidence that Russian-linked social media accounts saw</u> <u><strong>racial tensions</u></strong> <u>as</u> <u><strong>something to be exploited</u></strong> <u>in order to achieve the broader Russian goal of</u> <u><strong><mark>dividing Americans</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>and creating</u></mark> <u><strong><mark>chaos</u></strong></mark>.” CNN, 28-SEP-2017 NOTE TO READERS: Even in light of the information above, I DO NOT necessarily believe that Hillary Clinton would have won the 2016 US Presidential election in the absence of Russian interference – I simply do not have enough data from which to draw that conclusion. I am however certain that Russia wanted Trump to win and spent millions of dollars on propaganda directed at Americans toward that end. How We (Americans) Are Helping Russia Achieve Its Imperialistic Goals <u>Russian propaganda and incitements to separatism are spread through</u> <u><strong>social media</u></strong>, and their success depends on our willingness to reflexively share stories that outrage us. As unwitting agents for Russia, each of us is helping spread the seeds of our own political and economic demise. Hundreds of fake Facebook accounts operating from within Russia purchased $100,000 worth of Facebook ads between mid-2015 and early 2017. These fake Facebook accounts managed to reach 126 million Facebook users during this time frame. Besides their sheer volume, one of the most striking aspects of the ads purchased by these fake accounts is their alignment with the strategy described in Foundations of Geopolitics, namely the creation of division and mistrust among Americans. Alex Stamos, the Chief Information Security Officer for Facebook, issued a statement about the ad placements on September 6, 2017. In it, he made these observations: The vast majority of ads run by these accounts didn’t specifically reference the US presidential election, voting or a particular candidate. Rather, <u>the ads and accounts appeared to focus on amplifying divisive social and political messages across the ideological spectrum — touching on topics from LGBT matters to race issues to immigration to gun rights.</p></u> | null | 1NC | DA | 94,069 | 200 | 85,466 | ./documents/hspolicy19/GeorgetownDay/PaRi/Georgetown%20Day-Partman-Ritter-Neg-Pace%20RR-Round1.docx | 710,407 | N | Pace RR | 1 | LRC GL | Klarman, Shaikh | 1AC - Failed IR
1NC - FW Russian Expansionism Da ICJ CP Folk Politics K Case | hspolicy19/GeorgetownDay/PaRi/Georgetown%20Day-Partman-Ritter-Neg-Pace%20RR-Round1.docx | null | 60,537 | PaRi | Georgetown Day PaRi | null | Ia..... | Pa..... | Ga..... | Ri..... | 21,196 | GeorgetownDay | Georgetown Day | DC | null | 1,018 | hspolicy19 | HS Policy 2019-20 | 2,019 | cx | hs | 2 |
2,775,521 | China is the key player on preventing prolif – a US concession on Taiwan is key to unlock further cooperation | Hiim 18, | H.S. Hiim 18, Oslo PhD, “Counterproliferation Bargaining with the United States: China and the Spread of Nuclear Weapons,” Asian Security, 14.3, Taylor and Francis | nonproliferation translate into a source of leverage for China over the U S China has engaged in issue-linkage as a bargaining tactic By linking its policy on nonproliferation to other, initially unrelated issues – such as US policy toward Taiwan – China has sought to enhance its bargaining leverage introducing items that are not connected by any intellectual coherence at all issue-linkage strategies can also be used for blackmail and threats China has also made use of linkage strategies in other areas besides nonproliferation China has used the Senkaku conflict to compel Japan to change its policy in other, unrelated areas Linkage strategies may have a deterrent effect China occupies a pivotal position in international efforts to prevent nuclear proliferation China is a major source of nuclear technology and materials. It is also a crucial supplier of ballistic missiles and missile technology, which are most states’ preferred means of delivery Beijing has provided several states with nuclear assistance easing their path to the bomb China has a strong influence on how nonproliferation challenges are managed in arenas like the UNSC and IAEA as well as in multilateral negotiations China has provided economic, diplomatic, and military support to confirmed or suspected proliferators such as Pakistan, North Korea, and Iran China has a determining impact on whether international efforts to curb proliferation fail or succeed. This linkage has been more credible in cases where China has had an interest in supporting a proliferating state such as the Iran case China has at several junctures followed through and impeded cooperation with the US on nonproliferation, at least partly to demonstrate that the linkage is credible issue-linkage is most likely to occur if your counterpart has influence over an issue where you have major interests in Sino–US relations, the US wields influence over the Taiwan issue, and particularly US weapons sales to Taipei. To China, preventing Taiwanese independence is a core interest, and US arms transfers are perceived in Beijing as particularly unwelcome interferences. | China engaged in issue-linkage as a bargaining tactic By linking nonprolif to US policy toward Taiwan China occupies a pivotal position to prevent prolif a major source of nuclear tech supplier of missiles China has a strong influence on UNSC IAEA China has provided support to proliferators such as Pakistan, No Ko , and Iran China has a determining impact on whether efforts to curb prolif r succeed linkage is most likely if your counterpart has influence over major interests the US wields influence over Taiwan particularly sales to Taipei. To China, preventing Taiwanese independence is a core interest, and arms are unwelcome interferences | Issue-Linkage and nonproliferation How can nonproliferation policy translate into a source of leverage for China over the United States? In essence, China has engaged in issue-linkage as a bargaining tactic. By linking its policy on nonproliferation to other, initially unrelated issues – such as US policy toward Taiwan – China has sought to enhance its bargaining leverage. This bargaining approach conforms to what Ernst Haas has defined as tactical issue-linkage, namely “introducing into the agenda of multilateral negotiations items that are not connected by any intellectual coherence at all” in order to obtain greater bargaining leverage.7 The question of issue-linkage has received increasing attention during the last decades, partly because of what some have termed the issue-proliferation in international politics.8 The politics of linkage has often been associated with neoliberal theories, as issue-proliferation is a key tenet of interdependence.9 It has also often been seen as a primarily positive mechanism that facilitates cooperation. In Haas’ view, for example, positive inducements such as promises of side-payments can lead to cooperation in an initially unrelated area. Such bargaining can take place within international regimes.10 However, issue-linkage is no recent invention, and it is just as much – or perhaps even more – a phenomenon of realist international politics.11 That states have multiple goals, which facilitates issue-linkage, is not at odds with realist theories.12 Moreover, issue-linkage strategies do not necessarily take the form of positive inducements but can also be used for blackmail and threats.13 There are numerous examples of what may be termed realist applications of issue-linkage. Henry Kissinger and Richard Nixon made extensive use of linkage in their diplomacy towards the Soviet Union, for example, by making cooperation on arms control contingent on Soviet behavior towards the settlement of the Vietnam War.14 China, which arguably is a quintessentially realist actor, has also made use of linkage strategies in its foreign policy in other areas besides nonproliferation policy.15 For example, Krista Wiegand has demonstrated how China has used the Senkaku/Diaoyu islands territorial conflict to compel Japan to change its policy in other, unrelated areas.16 Several scholars make an analytical separation between issue-linkage as a condition and a bargaining strategy. For example, Robert Art refers to “functional” and “artificial” linkages. In case of the former, there is a causal connection between two issues. For example, the price of the dollar and the price of oil are functionally linked. In the latter case, “a statesman has made a connection where none before existed.” 17 Although this separation is analytically useful, it is important to highlight that once an initially “artificial” linkage between two issues have been made by a statesman, that linkage may stick. Upon their next encounter, even if a linkage is not communicated, a state’s counterpart may assume that it is still in place. Linkage strategies may therefore have a deterrent effect: the assumption that a linkage is in place may stay the hand of the other party. Linkage strategies may thus be used not only to compel policy shifts or extract concessions but also to deter other states from initiating unwanted policies at a later stage. A purpose of linkage politics is to transfer strength from one issue to an area where you are relatively weak.18 Bargaining strength can be defined in this context as: (a) having the ability to affect or even control an outcome (b) over which another party has significant interests. Put differently, a party can enhance its bargaining strength by having the ability to impose costs on its counterpart.19 Both of the conditions outlined are present in the case of China and nonproliferation. First, China occupies a pivotal position in international efforts to prevent nuclear proliferation. Its importance springs from two major dimensions. China is a major source of nuclear technology and materials. It is also a crucial supplier of ballistic missiles and missile technology, which are most states’ preferred means of delivery for nuclear weapons. Beijing has provided several states with nuclear and missile assistance, potentially easing their path to the bomb. More broadly, as a major player in the international system, China has a strong influence on how nonproliferation challenges are managed in arenas like the United Nations Security Council (UNSC) and the International Atomic Energy Agency (IAEA), as well as in multilateral negotiations. Beyond its institutional role, China has provided economic, diplomatic, and military support to confirmed or suspected proliferators such as Pakistan, North Korea, and Iran. Through these ties, China has a determining impact on whether international efforts to curb proliferation fail or succeed. Second, preventing the proliferation of nuclear weapons is a key US foreign policy objective. Although the strength of the preferences has varied across administrations and between different instances of proliferators, halting proliferation has been a key leg of US grand strategy since the dawn of the nuclear age, according to a recent study.20 If anything, preventing proliferation has only become more central to US policymakers in the post-Cold War era. With the decline of the Soviet threat, US policymakers have identified nuclear proliferation as the most significant threat facing America. After 9/11, worries about terrorists gaining access to nuclear weapons exacerbated these concerns.21 The credibility and likely effectiveness of linkage strategies is dependent on the linking state’s interest in the outcome. If a state threatens to take actions that are not in its interests if the other party fails to comply on another issue, the other party may regard the threat as lacking credibility. If the action, on the other hand, is in the interest of the linking state, the linkage is likely to appear as more credible.22 As I will detail in the following, this difference is important in the case of China and its policy of linking proliferation cooperation to other policy outcomes. This linkage has been more credible in cases where China has had an interest in supporting a proliferating state (or at least been indifferent to the outcome), such as the Iran case. It has been less credible in cases where it is not in China’s interest to support the proliferating state, such as in the North Korean case. A further, related point is that credibility is enhanced if the linker follows through on its threats. Conversely, credibility is reduced if the threats are exposed as bluffs. This has arguably affected China’s linkage approach. To demonstrate that it is not bluffing, China has at several junctures followed through and impeded cooperation with the US on nonproliferation, at least partly to demonstrate that the linkage is credible. A final point worth noting is that issue-linkage is most likely to occur – or worthwhile to pursue – if your counterpart has influence over an issue where you have major interests. Put differently, if the counterpart does not have anything you want, there is no point in bargaining. However, in Sino–US relations, the US wields influence over a range of issues that are of major importance to Beijing. A crucial one is the Taiwan issue, and particularly US weapons sales to Taipei. To China, preventing Taiwanese independence is a core interest, and US arms transfers are perceived in Beijing as particularly unwelcome interferences. However, there are also several other issues that China can and has linked to nonproliferation policy. Washington’s missile defense efforts have been unwelcome in Beijing, and China has on several occasions tried to signal to the US that these efforts may lead to Chinese non-cooperation in other areas. Another example is receiving the Dalai Lama and other actions that China perceives as support of the Tibetan exile government, which Beijing sees as violating crucial national interests. | 8,116 | <h4>China is the <u>key player</u> on preventing prolif – a <u>US concession on Taiwan</u> is key to <u>unlock</u> further cooperation </h4><p>H.S. <strong>Hiim 18,</strong> Oslo PhD, “Counterproliferation Bargaining with the United States: China and the Spread of Nuclear Weapons,” Asian Security, 14.3, Taylor and Francis</p><p>Issue-Linkage and nonproliferation How can <u>nonproliferation</u> policy <u>translate into a source of leverage for China over the U</u>nited <u>S</u>tates? In essence, <u><mark>China</mark> has <mark>engaged in issue-linkage as a <strong>bargaining tactic</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong><mark>By linking</mark> its policy on <mark>nonprolif</mark>eration <mark>to</strong></mark> other, initially unrelated issues – such as <strong><mark>US policy toward Taiwan</strong></mark> – China has sought to enhance its bargaining leverage</u>. This bargaining approach conforms to what Ernst Haas has defined as tactical issue-linkage, namely “<u>introducing</u> into the agenda of multilateral negotiations <u>items that are not connected by any intellectual coherence at all</u>” in order to obtain greater bargaining leverage.7 The question of issue-linkage has received increasing attention during the last decades, partly because of what some have termed the issue-proliferation in international politics.8 The politics of linkage has often been associated with neoliberal theories, as issue-proliferation is a key tenet of interdependence.9 It has also often been seen as a primarily positive mechanism that facilitates cooperation. In Haas’ view, for example, positive inducements such as promises of side-payments can lead to cooperation in an initially unrelated area. Such bargaining can take place within international regimes.10 However, issue-linkage is no recent invention, and it is just as much – or perhaps even more – a phenomenon of realist international politics.11 That states have multiple goals, which facilitates issue-linkage, is not at odds with realist theories.12 Moreover, <u>issue-linkage strategies</u> do not necessarily take the form of positive inducements but <u>can also be used for <strong>blackmail</strong><mark> </mark>and <strong>threats</u></strong>.13 There are numerous examples of what may be termed realist applications of issue-linkage. Henry Kissinger and Richard Nixon made extensive use of linkage in their diplomacy towards the Soviet Union, for example, by making cooperation on arms control contingent on Soviet behavior towards the settlement of the Vietnam War.14 <u>China</u>, which arguably is a quintessentially realist actor, <u>has also made use of linkage strategies in</u> its foreign policy in <u>other areas besides nonproliferation</u> policy.15 For example, Krista Wiegand has demonstrated how <u>China has used the Senkaku</u>/Diaoyu islands territorial <u>conflict to compel Japan to change its policy in other, unrelated areas</u>.16 Several scholars make an analytical separation between issue-linkage as a condition and a bargaining strategy. For example, Robert Art refers to “functional” and “artificial” linkages. In case of the former, there is a causal connection between two issues. For example, the price of the dollar and the price of oil are functionally linked. In the latter case, “a statesman has made a connection where none before existed.” 17 Although this separation is analytically useful, it is important to highlight that once an initially “artificial” linkage between two issues have been made by a statesman, that linkage may stick. Upon their next encounter, even if a linkage is not communicated, a state’s counterpart may assume that it is still in place. <u>Linkage strategies may</u> therefore <u>have a deterrent effect</u>: the assumption that a linkage is in place may stay the hand of the other party. Linkage strategies may thus be used not only to compel policy shifts or extract concessions but also to deter other states from initiating unwanted policies at a later stage. A purpose of linkage politics is to transfer strength from one issue to an area where you are relatively weak.18 Bargaining strength can be defined in this context as: (a) having the ability to affect or even control an outcome (b) over which another party has significant interests. Put differently, a party can enhance its bargaining strength by having the ability to impose costs on its counterpart.19 Both of the conditions outlined are present in the case of China and nonproliferation. First, <u><mark>China occupies a <strong>pivotal position</strong></mark> in international efforts <strong><mark>to prevent</mark> nuclear <mark>prolif</mark>eration</u></strong>. Its importance springs from two major dimensions. <u>China is <mark>a <strong>major source of nuclear tech</mark>nology and materials</strong>. It is also a crucial <mark>supplier of</mark> ballistic <mark>missiles</mark> and missile technology, which are most states’ preferred means of delivery</u> for nuclear weapons. <u>Beijing has provided several states with nuclear</u> and missile <u>assistance</u>, potentially <u>easing their path to the bomb</u>. More broadly, as a major player in the international system, <u><mark>China has a <strong>strong influence</strong> on</mark> how nonproliferation challenges are managed in arenas like the</u> United Nations Security Council (<u><mark>UNSC</u></mark>) <u>and</u> the International Atomic Energy Agency (<u><mark>IAEA</u></mark>), <u>as well as in multilateral negotiations</u>. Beyond its institutional role, <u><mark>China has provided</mark> economic, diplomatic, and military <mark>support to</mark> confirmed or suspected <mark>proliferators such as <strong>Pakistan, No</mark>rth<mark> Ko</mark>rea<mark>, and Iran</u></strong></mark>. Through these ties, <u><mark>China has a <strong>determining impact</strong> on whether</mark> international <mark>efforts to curb prolif</mark>eration <strong>fail o<mark>r succeed</strong></mark>.</u> Second, preventing the proliferation of nuclear weapons is a key US foreign policy objective. Although the strength of the preferences has varied across administrations and between different instances of proliferators, halting proliferation has been a key leg of US grand strategy since the dawn of the nuclear age, according to a recent study.20 If anything, preventing proliferation has only become more central to US policymakers in the post-Cold War era. With the decline of the Soviet threat, US policymakers have identified nuclear proliferation as the most significant threat facing America. After 9/11, worries about terrorists gaining access to nuclear weapons exacerbated these concerns.21 The credibility and likely effectiveness of linkage strategies is dependent on the linking state’s interest in the outcome. If a state threatens to take actions that are not in its interests if the other party fails to comply on another issue, the other party may regard the threat as lacking credibility. If the action, on the other hand, is in the interest of the linking state, the linkage is likely to appear as more credible.22 As I will detail in the following, this difference is important in the case of China and its policy of linking proliferation cooperation to other policy outcomes. <u>This linkage has been <strong>more credible</strong> in cases where China has had an interest in supporting a proliferating state</u> (or at least been indifferent to the outcome), <u>such as the Iran case</u>. It has been less credible in cases where it is not in China’s interest to support the proliferating state, such as in the North Korean case. A further, related point is that credibility is enhanced if the linker follows through on its threats. Conversely, credibility is reduced if the threats are exposed as bluffs. This has arguably affected China’s linkage approach. To demonstrate that it is not bluffing, <u>China has at several junctures followed through and impeded cooperation with the US on nonproliferation, at least partly to demonstrate that the linkage is credible</u>. A final point worth noting is that <u>issue-<mark>linkage is most likely</mark> to occur</u> – or worthwhile to pursue – <u><mark>if your counterpart has <strong>influence over</mark> an issue where you have <mark>major interests</u></strong></mark>. Put differently, if the counterpart does not have anything you want, there is no point in bargaining. However, <u>in Sino–US relations, <mark>the US wields influence over</u></mark> a range of issues that are of major importance to Beijing. A crucial one is <u><strong>the <mark>Taiwan</mark> issue</strong>, and <strong><mark>particularly </mark>US weapons <mark>sales to Taipei</strong>. To China,</mark> <strong><mark>preventing Taiwanese independence is a core interest, and </mark>US <mark>arms </mark>transfers <mark>are</strong></mark> perceived in Beijing as particularly <strong><mark>unwelcome interferences</strong></mark>.</u> However, there are also several other issues that China can and has linked to nonproliferation policy. Washington’s missile defense efforts have been unwelcome in Beijing, and China has on several occasions tried to signal to the US that these efforts may lead to Chinese non-cooperation in other areas. Another example is receiving the Dalai Lama and other actions that China perceives as support of the Tibetan exile government, which Beijing sees as violating crucial national interests.</p> | 1AC – MBA KP | Relations | null | 71,851 | 219 | 87,756 | ./documents/hspolicy19/MontgomeryBell/PaKa/Montgomery%20Bell-Pacconi-Kalams-Aff-Westminster-Round2.docx | 717,338 | A | Westminster | 2 | Galloway SV | Alexandra Dresdner | 1AC - Taiwan
1NC - T Substantial Soft Balancing CP USMCA DA
2NR - USMCA DA | hspolicy19/MontgomeryBell/PaKa/Montgomery%20Bell-Pacconi-Kalams-Aff-Westminster-Round2.docx | null | 61,136 | PaKa | Montgomery Bell PaKa | null | Ja..... | Pa..... | Al..... | Ka..... | 21,322 | MontgomeryBell | Montgomery Bell | TN | null | 1,018 | hspolicy19 | HS Policy 2019-20 | 2,019 | cx | hs | 2 |
2,967,571 | The affirmative’s politics are tied to a rehabilitative futurism where the signifier of the fantasmatic child is placed forward to eradicate and cure disability – this deems the disabled child a threat and excludes disability from the political. | Mollow 2 | Mollow 2 Anna (2015): The Disability Drive, A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in English in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Professor Kent Puckett, Chair Professor Celeste G. Langan Professor Melinda Y. Chen Spring 2015 https://digitalassets.lib.berkeley.edu/etd/ucb/text/Mollow_berkeley_0028E_15181.pdf SJCP//JG | Indeed, the figure that Edelman calls “the disciplinary image of the “innocent” Child” is inextricable not only from queerness but also from disability For example, the Child is the centerpiece of the telethon, a ritual display of pity that demeans disabled people. When Jerry Lewis counters disability activists’ objections to his assertion that a disabled person is “half a person,” he insists that he is only fighting for the Children: “Please, I’m begging for survival. I want my kids alive,” he implores The logic of the telethon, in other words, relies on an ideology that might be defined as “rehabilitative futurism,” a term that I coin to overlap and intersect with Edelman’s notion of “reproductive futurism.” If, as Edelman maintains, the future is envisaged in terms of a fantasmatic “Child,” then the survival of this future-figured-as-Child is threatened by both queerness and disability. Futurity is habitually imagined in terms that fantasize the eradication of disability: a recovery of a “crippled” or “hobbled” economy, a cure for society’s ills, an end to suffering and disease | the image of the Child is inextricable from from disability Lewis assert disabled person is “half a person he is only fighting for the Children begging for survival I want my kids alive rehabilitative futurism future envisaged in a fantasmatic “Child threatened by disability Futurity is habitually imagined fantasize eradication of disability recovery of a “crippled” economy cure for society’s ills | Elsewhere, I have argued that No Future’s impassioned polemic is one that disability studies might take to heart.109 Indeed, the figure that Edelman calls “the disciplinary image of the “innocent” Child” is inextricable not only from queerness but also from disability (19). For example, the Child is the centerpiece of the telethon, a ritual display of pity that demeans disabled people. When Jerry Lewis counters disability activists’ objections to his assertion that a disabled person is “half a person,” he insists that he is only fighting for the Children: “Please, I’m begging for survival. I want my kids alive,” he implores (in Johnson, Too Late 53, 58). If the Child makes an excellent alibi for ableism, perhaps this is because, as Edelman points out, the idea of not fighting for this figure is unthinkable. Thus, when Harriet McBryde Johnson hands out leaflets protesting the Muscular Dystrophy Association, a confused passerby cannot make sense of what her protest is about. “You’re against Jerry Lewis!” he exclaims (61). The passerby’s surprise is likely informed by a logic similar to that which, in Edelman’s analysis, undergirds the use of the word “choice” by advocates of legal abortion: “Who would, after all, come out for abortion or stand against reproduction, against futurity, and so against life?” (16). Similarly, why would anyone come out for disability, and so against the Child who, without a cure, might never walk, might never lead a normal life, might not even have a future at all? The logic of the telethon, in other words, relies on an ideology that might be defined as “rehabilitative futurism,” a term that I coin to overlap and intersect with Edelman’s notion of “reproductive futurism.” If, as Edelman maintains, the future is envisaged in terms of a fantasmatic “Child,” then the survival of this future-figured-as-Child is threatened by both queerness and disability. Futurity is habitually imagined in terms that fantasize the eradication of disability: a recovery of a “crippled” or “hobbled” economy, a cure for society’s ills, an end to suffering and disease. Eugenic ideologies are also grounded in both reproductive and rehabilitative futurism: procreation by the fit and elimination of the disabled, eugenicists promised, would bring forth a better future.110 | 2,308 | <h4>The affirmative’s politics are tied to a rehabilitative futurism where the signifier of the fantasmatic child is placed forward to eradicate and cure disability – this deems the disabled child a threat and excludes disability from the political.</h4><p><strong>Mollow 2</strong> Anna (2015): The Disability Drive, A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in English in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Professor Kent Puckett, Chair Professor Celeste G. Langan Professor Melinda Y. Chen Spring 2015 https://digitalassets.lib.berkeley.edu/etd/ucb/text/Mollow_berkeley_0028E_15181.pdf SJCP//JG</p><p>Elsewhere, I have argued that No Future’s impassioned polemic is one that disability studies might take to heart.109 <u><strong>Indeed, the figure that Edelman calls “<mark>the</mark> disciplinary <mark>image of the</mark> “innocent” <mark>Child</mark>” <mark>is</mark> <mark>inextricable</mark> not only <mark>from</mark> queerness but also <mark>from disability</u></strong></mark> (19). <u><strong>For example, the Child is the centerpiece of the telethon, a ritual display of pity that demeans disabled people. When Jerry <mark>Lewis</mark> counters disability activists’ objections to his <mark>assert</mark>ion that a <mark>disabled person is “half a person</mark>,” he insists that <mark>he is only fighting for the Children</mark>: “Please, I’m <mark>begging for survival</mark>. <mark>I want my kids alive</mark>,” he implores</u></strong> (in Johnson, Too Late 53, 58). If the Child makes an excellent alibi for ableism, perhaps this is because, as Edelman points out, the idea of not fighting for this figure is unthinkable. Thus, when Harriet McBryde Johnson hands out leaflets protesting the Muscular Dystrophy Association, a confused passerby cannot make sense of what her protest is about. “You’re against Jerry Lewis!” he exclaims (61). The passerby’s surprise is likely informed by a logic similar to that which, in Edelman’s analysis, undergirds the use of the word “choice” by advocates of legal abortion: “Who would, after all, come out for abortion or stand against reproduction, against futurity, and so against life?” (16). Similarly, why would anyone come out for disability, and so against the Child who, without a cure, might never walk, might never lead a normal life, might not even have a future at all? <u><strong>The logic of the telethon, in other words, relies on an ideology that might be defined as “<mark>rehabilitative futurism</mark>,” a term that I coin to overlap and intersect with Edelman’s notion of “reproductive futurism.” If, as Edelman maintains, the <mark>future</mark> is <mark>envisaged</mark> <mark>in</mark> terms of <mark>a fantasmatic “Child</mark>,” then the survival of this future-figured-as-Child is <mark>threatened by </mark>both queerness and <mark>disability</mark>.</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>Futurity is habitually imagined</mark> in terms that <mark>fantasize</mark> the <mark>eradication of disability</mark>: a <mark>recovery of a “crippled”</mark> or “hobbled” <mark>economy</mark>, a <mark>cure for</mark> <mark>society’s ills</mark>, an end to suffering and disease</u></strong>. Eugenic ideologies are also grounded in both reproductive and rehabilitative futurism: procreation by the fit and elimination of the disabled, eugenicists promised, would bring forth a better future.110 </p> | 1NC | 1 | null | 361,406 | 399 | 96,474 | ./documents/hsld19/StrakeJesuit/Ge/Strake%20Jesuit-Georges-Neg-TOC-Octas.docx | 849,163 | N | TOC | Octas | Valley AJ | Curtis, Melin, Zhou | 1AC - Semiocapitalism
1NC - Disability K AC
1AR - AC K
2NR - K AC
2AR - AC K | hsld19/StrakeJesuit/Ge/Strake%20Jesuit-Georges-Neg-TOC-Octas.docx | null | 72,421 | JoGe | Strake Jesuit JoGe | null | Jo..... | Ge..... | null | null | 24,333 | StrakeJesuit | Strake Jesuit | TX | null | 1,027 | hsld19 | HS LD 2019-20 | 2,019 | ld | hs | 1 |
1,831,942 | No nuke terror or escalation | Weiss 15 | Weiss 15 (Leonard, visiting scholar at the Center for International Security and Cooperation at Stanford University, and a member of the National Advisory Board of the Center for Arms Control and Non-Proliferation in Washington, DC, former professor of applied mathematics and engineering at Brown University and the University of Maryland, “On fear and nuclear terrorism,” Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists, March/April 2015, Vol. 71, No. 2, p. 75-87] | Although there has been much commentary on the interest that Osama bin Laden, when he was alive, reportedly expressed and some terrorists desire to obtain such weapons, evidence of any terrorist group working seriously toward the theft of nuclear weapons or the acquisition of such weapons by other means is virtually nonexistent. This Terrorists understand that it is not hard to terrorize a population without committing mass murder .” If public sympathy is important to their cause, an apparent plan or commission of mass murder is not going to help them, and indeed will make their enemies even more implacable The acquisition of nuclear weapons by terrorists is not like the acquisition of conventional weapons; it requires significant time, planning, resources, and expertise, with no guarantees that an acquired device would work. It requires putting aside at least some aspects of a group’s more immediate activities and goals for an attempted operation that no terrorist group has previously accomplished consider the three possibilities for terrorists to obtain a nuclear weapon: steal one; be given one created by a nuclear weapon state; manufacture one. None of these possibilities has a high probability of occurring Nothing is better protected in a nuclear weapon state than the weapons themselves, which have multiple layers of safeguards that include intelligence and surveillance, electronic locks gated and locked storage facilities, armed guards, and teams of elite responders if an attempt at theft were to occur most weapon states have such protections, and there is no reason to believe that such protections are missing in the remaining states, since no weapon state would want to put itself at risk of an unintended nuclear detonation of its own weapons by a malevolent agent. Thus, the likelihood of an unauthorized agent secretly planning a theft, without being discovered, and getting access to weapons is extremely low Pakistan is frequently suggested as a possible candidate Pakistan is not about to collapse, and the Pakistanis are known to have received major international assistance in technologies for protecting their weapons from unauthorized use, store them in somewhat disassembled fashion at multiple locations, and have a sophisticated nuclear security structure in place the weapons are assembled at times of high tension in the region, and, to keep a degree of uncertainty in their location, they are moved from place to place, making them more vulnerable to seizure at such times Acquiring nukes There are at least two reasons why this scenario is unlikely once a weapon state loses control of a weapon, it cannot be sure the weapon will be used by the terrorist group as intended the state cannot be sure that the transfer of the weapon has been undetected either before or after the fact of its detonation This is a powerful deterrent to such a transfer, making the transfer a low-probability event. Manufacturing a nuclear weapon. To accomplish this, a terrorist group would have to obtain an appropriate amount of materials plutonium is very highly protected Reactor-grade plutonium is a more attractive target terrorist use of plutonium for a nuclear explosive device would require the construction of an implosion weapon, a notoriously difficult technical problem the use of reactor-grade plutonium would require a still more sophisticated design technical complications present themselves even if one discounts the high probability that the plan would be discovered at some stage translating this into a real-world situation suggests an extremely low probability of technical success. More likely would be the death of persons in the attempt to build the device an insider threat would require intimate knowledge of the materials accounting system on which safeguards in that state are based and adds another layer of complexity to an operation with low probability of success. The situation is different in the case of using highly enriched uranium stealing that much highly enriched material is a major problem for any thief and one significantly greater than the stealing of small amounts of HEU and lower-enriched material that has been reported from time to time over the past two decades fashioning the material into a form more useful for explosive purposes could mean a need for still more material than suggested above, plus a means for machining it, as would be the case for HEU fuel assemblies from a research reactor there is only one known case of a major theft of HEU The circumstances under which this theft occurred were unique, and there was significant information about the contractor’s relationship to Israel that should have rung alarm bells and would do so today there has been a significant effort to increase protection
of such materials particularly through the efforts of advocates like Bunn there is little to no evidence that terrorist groups in or outside the region are seriously trying to obtain a nuclear capability here is one stark example of a terrorist organization that actually started a nuclear effort: the Aum Shinrikyo group. the nuclear weapon effort stalled and was abandoned Aum Shinrikyo is now a small organization under continuing close surveillance. What about highly organized groups like the Islamic State (IS)? how would nuclear terrorism fit in with a program for building and sustaining a new caliphate that would restore past glories of Islamic society, especially since, like any organized government, the Islamic State would itself be vulnerable to nuclear attack Building a new Islamic state out of radioactive ashes is an unlikely ambition for such groups. Even if a terror group were to achieve technical nuclear proficiency, the time, money, and infrastructure needed to build nuclear weapons creates significant risks of discovery that would put the group at risk of attack. Given the ease of obtaining conventional explosives and the ability to deploy them, a terrorist group is unlikely to exchange a big part of its operational program to engage in a risky nuclear development effort with such doubtful prospects 9/11 has heightened sensitivity to the need for protection, lowering further the probability of a successful effort. | Although some desire weapons, evidence of any group working seriously toward theft or other means is nonexistent. This is not going to help them, weapons; it requires significant time, resources, and expertise, with no guarantees It requires putting aside goals Nothing is better protected than weapons themselves, which have multiple layers there is no reason to believe protections are missing in the remaining states Pakistan is not about to collapse, and received major international assistance and sophisticated security a state cannot be sure the weapon will be used as intended This is a powerful deterrent plutonium is highly protected Reactor plutonium would require a notoriously difficult technical problem even if one discounts the high probability that the plan would be discovered this suggests extremely low technical success explosive purposes mean still more material there has been a significant effort
What about highly organized how would nuclear terrorism fit in Even if a group were to achieve proficiency, the time, money, and infrastructure creates discovery | If the fear of nuclear war has thus had some positive effects, the fear of nuclear terrorism has had mainly negative effects on the lives of millions of people around the world, including in the United States, and even affects negatively the prospects for a more peaceful world. Although there has been much commentary on the interest that Osama bin Laden, when he was alive, reportedly expressed in obtaining nuclear weapons (see Mowatt-Larssen, 2010), and some terrorists no doubt desire to obtain such weapons, evidence of any terrorist group working seriously toward the theft of nuclear weapons or the acquisition of such weapons by other means is virtually nonexistent. This may be due to a combination of reasons. Terrorists understand that it is not hard to terrorize a population without committing mass murder: In 2002, a single sniper in the Washington, DC area, operating within his own automobile and with one accomplice, killed 10 people and changed the behavior of virtually the entire populace of the city over a period of three weeks by instilling fear of being a randomly chosen shooting victim when out shopping. Terrorists who believe the commission of violence helps their cause have access to many explosive materials and conventional weapons to ply their “trade.” If public sympathy is important to their cause, an apparent plan or commission of mass murder is not going to help them, and indeed will make their enemies even more implacable, reducing the prospects of achieving their goals. The acquisition of nuclear weapons by terrorists is not like the acquisition of conventional weapons; it requires significant time, planning, resources, and expertise, with no guarantees that an acquired device would work. It requires putting aside at least some aspects of a group’s more immediate activities and goals for an attempted operation that no terrorist group has previously accomplished. While absence of evidence does not mean evidence of absence (as then-Secretary of Defense Donald Rumsfeld kept reminding us during the search for Saddam’s nonexistent nuclear weapons), it is reasonable to conclude that the fear of nuclear terrorism has swamped realistic consideration of the threat. As Brian Jenkins, a longtime observer of terrorist groups, wrote in 2008: Nuclear terrorism … turns out to be a world of truly worrisome particles of truth. Yet it is also a world of fantasies, nightmares, urban legends, fakes, hoaxes, scams, stings, mysterious substances, terrorist boasts, sensational claims, description of vast conspiracies, allegations of coverups, lurid headlines, layers of misinformation and disinformation. Much is inconclusive or contradictory. Only the terror is real. (Jenkins, 2008: 26) The three ways terrorists might get a nuke To illustrate in more detail how fear has distorted the threat of nuclear terrorism, consider the three possibilities for terrorists to obtain a nuclear weapon: steal one; be given one created by a nuclear weapon state; manufacture one. None of these possibilities has a high probability of occurring. Stealing nukes. Nothing is better protected in a nuclear weapon state than the weapons themselves, which have multiple layers of safeguards that, in the United States, include intelligence and surveillance, electronic locks (including so-called “permissive action links” that prevent detonation unless a code is entered into the lock), gated and locked storage facilities, armed guards, and teams of elite responders if an attempt at theft were to occur. We know that most weapon states have such protections, and there is no reason to believe that such protections are missing in the remaining states, since no weapon state would want to put itself at risk of an unintended nuclear detonation of its own weapons by a malevolent agent. Thus, the likelihood of an unauthorized agent secretly planning a theft, without being discovered, and getting access to weapons with the intent and physical ability to carry them off in the face of such layers of protection is extremely low—but it isn’t impossible, especially in the case where the thief is an insider. The insider threat helped give credibility to the stories, circulating about 20 years ago, that there were “loose nukes” in the USSR, based on some statements by a Soviet general who claimed the regime could not account for more than 40 “suitcase nukes” that had been built. The Russian government denied the claim, and at this point there is no evidence that any nukes were ever loose. Now, it is unclear if any such weapon would even work after 20 years of corrosion of both the nuclear and non-nuclear materials in the device and the radioactive decay of certain isotopes. Because of the large number of terrorist groups operating in its geographic vicinity, Pakistan is frequently suggested as a possible candidate for scenarios in which a terrorist group either seizes a weapon via collaboration with insiders sympathetic to its cause, or in which terrorists “inherit” nuclear weapons by taking over the arsenal of a failed nuclear state that has devolved into chaos. Attacks by a terrorist group on a Pakistani military base, at Kamra, which is believed to house nuclear weapons in some form, have been referenced in connection with such security concerns (Nelson and Hussain, 2012). However, the Kamra base contained US fighter planes, including F-16s, used to bomb Taliban bases in tribal areas bordering Afghanistan, so the planes, not nuclear weapons, were the likely target of the terrorists, and in any case the mission was a failure. Moreover, Pakistan is not about to collapse, and the Pakistanis are known to have received major international assistance in technologies for protecting their weapons from unauthorized use, store them in somewhat disassembled fashion at multiple locations, and have a sophisticated nuclear security structure in place (see Gregory, 2013; Khan, 2012). However, the weapons are assembled at times of high tension in the region, and, to keep a degree of uncertainty in their location, they are moved from place to place, making them more vulnerable to seizure at such times (Goldberg and Ambinder, 2011). (It should be noted that US nuclear weapons were subject to such risks during various times when the weapons traveled US highways in disguised trucks and accompanying vehicles, but such travel and the possibility of terrorist seizure was never mentioned publicly.) Such scenarios of seizure in Pakistan would require a major security breakdown within the army leading to a takeover of weapons by a nihilistic terrorist group with little warning, while army loyalists along with India and other interested parties (like the United States) stand by and do not intervene. This is not a particularly realistic scenario, but it’s also not a reason to conclude that Pakistan’s nuclear arsenal is of no concern. It is, not only because of an internal threat, but especially because it raises the possibility of nuclear war with India. For this and other reasons, intelligence agencies in multiple countries spend considerable resources tracking the Pakistani nuclear situation to reduce the likelihood of surprises. But any consideration of Pakistan’s nuclear arsenal does bring home (once again) the folly of US policy in the 1980s, when stopping the Pakistani nuclear program was put on a back burner in order to prosecute the Cold War against the Soviets in Afghanistan (which ultimately led to the establishment of Al Qaeda). Some of the loudest voices expressing concern about nuclear terrorism belong to former senior government officials who supported US assistance to the mujahideen and the accompanying diminution of US opposition to Pakistan’s nuclear activities. Acquiring nukes as a gift. Following the shock of 9/11, government officials and the media imagined many scenarios in which terrorists obtain nuclear weapons; one of those scenarios involves a weapon state using a terrorist group for delivery of a nuclear weapon. There are at least two reasons why this scenario is unlikely: First, once a weapon state loses control of a weapon, it cannot be sure the weapon will be used by the terrorist group as intended. Second, the state cannot be sure that the transfer of the weapon has been undetected either before or after the fact of its detonation (see Lieber and Press, 2013). The use of the weapon by a terrorist group will ultimately result in the transferring nation becoming a nuclear target just as if it had itself detonated the device. This is a powerful deterrent to such a transfer, making the transfer a low-probability event. Although these first two ways in which terrorists might obtain a nuclear weapon have very small probabilities of occurring (there is no available data suggesting that terrorist groups have produced plans for stealing a weapon, nor has there been any public information suggesting that any nuclear weapon state has seriously considered providing a nuclear weapon to a sub-national group), the probabilities cannot be said to be zero as long as nuclear weapons exist. Manufacturing a nuclear weapon. To accomplish this, a terrorist group would have to obtain an appropriate amount of one of the two most popular materials for nuclear weapons, highly enriched uranium (HEU) or plutonium separated from fuel used in a production reactor or a power reactor. Weapon-grade plutonium is found in weapon manufacturing facilities in nuclear weapon states and is very highly protected until it is inserted in a weapon. Reactor-grade plutonium, although still capable of being weaponized, is less protected, and in that sense is a more attractive target for a terrorist, especially since it has been produced and stored in prodigious quantities in a number of nuclear weapon states and non-weapon states, particularly Japan. But terrorist use of plutonium for a nuclear explosive device would require the construction of an implosion weapon, requiring the fashioning of an appropriate explosive lens of TNT, a notoriously difficult technical problem. And if a high nuclear yield (much greater than 1 kiloton) is desired, the use of reactor-grade plutonium would require a still more sophisticated design. Moreover, if the plutonium is only available through chemical separation from some (presumably stolen) spent fuel rods, additional technical complications present themselves. There is at least one study showing that a small team of people with the appropriate technical skills and equipment could, in principle, build a plutonium-based nuclear explosive device (Mark et al., 1986). But even if one discounts the high probability that the plan would be discovered at some stage (missing plutonium or spent fuel rods would put the authorities and intelligence operations under high alert), translating this into a real-world situation suggests an extremely low probability of technical success. More likely, according to one well-known weapon designer,4 would be the death of the person or persons in the attempt to build the device. There is the possibility of an insider threat; in one example, a team of people working at a reactor or reprocessing site could conspire to steal some material and try to hide the diversion as MUF (materials unaccounted for) within the nuclear safeguards system. But this scenario would require intimate knowledge of the materials accounting system on which safeguards in that state are based and adds another layer of complexity to an operation with low probability of success. The situation is different in the case of using highly enriched uranium, which presents fewer technical challenges. Here an implosion design is not necessary, and a “gun type” design is the more likely approach. Fear of this scenario has sometimes been promoted in the literature via the quotation of a famous statement by nuclear physicist Luis Alvarez that dropping a subcritical amount of HEU onto another subcritical amount from a distance of five feet could result in a nuclear yield. The probability of such a yield (and its size) would depend on the geometry of the HEU components and the amount of material. More likely than a substantial nuclear explosion from such a scenario would be a criticality accident that would release an intense burst of radiation, killing persons in the immediate vicinity, or (even less likely) a low-yield nuclear “fizzle” that could be quite damaging locally (like a large TNT explosion) but also carry a psychological effect because of its nuclear dimension. In any case, since the critical mass of a bare metal perfect sphere of pure U-235 is approximately 56 kilograms, stealing that much highly enriched material (and getting away without detection, an armed fight, or a criticality accident) is a major problem for any thief and one significantly greater than the stealing of small amounts of HEU and lower-enriched material that has been reported from time to time over the past two decades, mostly from former Soviet sites that have since had their security greatly strengthened. Moreover, fashioning the material into a form more useful or convenient for explosive purposes could likely mean a need for still more material than suggested above, plus a means for machining it, as would be the case for HEU fuel assemblies from a research reactor. In a recent paper, physics professor B. C. Reed discusses the feasibility of terrorists building a low-yield, gun-type fission weapon, but admittedly avoids the issue of whether the terrorists would likely have the technical ability to carry feasibility to realization and whether the terrorists are likely to be successful in stealing the needed material and hiding their project as it proceeds (Reed, 2014). But this is the crux of the nuclear terrorism issue. There is no argument about feasibility, which has been accepted for decades, even for plutonium-based weapons, ever since Ted Taylor first raised it in the early 1970s5 and a Senate subcommittee held hearings in the late 1970s on a weapon design created by a Harvard dropout from information he obtained from the public section of the Los Alamos National Laboratory library (Fialka, 1978). Likewise, no one can deny the terrible consequences of a nuclear explosion. The question is the level of risk, and what steps are acceptable in a democracy for reducing it. Although the attention in the literature given to nuclear terrorism scenarios involving HEU would suggest major attempts to obtain such material by terrorist groups, there is only one known case of a major theft of HEU. It involves a US government contractor processing HEU for the US Navy in Apollo, Pennsylvania in the 1970s at a time when security and materials accounting were extremely lax. The theft was almost surely carried out by agents of the Israeli government with the probable involvement of a person or persons working for the contractor, not a sub-national terrorist group intent on making its own weapons (Gilinsky and Mattson, 2010). The circumstances under which this theft occurred were unique, and there was significant information about the contractor’s relationship to Israel that should have rung alarm bells and would do so today. Although it involved a government and not a sub-national group, the theft underscores the importance of security and accounting of nuclear materials, especially because the technical requirements for making an HEU weapon are less daunting than for a plutonium weapon, and the probability of success by a terrorist group, though low, is certainly greater than zero. Over the past two decades, there has been a significant effort to increase protection
of such materials, particularly in recent years through the efforts of nongovernmental organizations like the International Panel on Fissile Materials6 and advocates like Matthew Bunn working within the Obama administration (Bunn and Newman, 2008), though the administration has apparently not seen the need to make the materials as secure as the weapons themselves. Are terrorists even interested in making their own nuclear weapons? A recent paper (Friedman and Lewis, 2014) postulates a scenario by which terrorists might seize nuclear materials in Pakistan for fashioning a weapon. While jihadist sympathizers are known to have worked within the Pakistani nuclear establishment, there is little to no evidence that terrorist groups in or outside the region are seriously trying to obtain a nuclear capability. And Pakistan has been operating a uranium enrichment plant for its weapons program for nearly 30 years with no credible reports of diversion of HEU from the plant. There is one stark example of a terrorist organization that actually started a nuclear effort: the Aum Shinrikyo group. At its peak, this religious cult had a membership estimated in the tens of thousands spread over a variety of countries, including Japan; its members had scientific expertise in many areas; and the group was well funded. Aum Shinrikyo obtained access to natural uranium supplies, but the nuclear weapon effort stalled and was abandoned. The group was also interested in chemical weapons and did produce sarin nerve gas with which they attacked the Tokyo subway system, killing 13 persons. Aum Shinrikyo is now a small organization under continuing close surveillance. What about highly organized groups, designated appropriately as terrorist, that have acquired enough territory to enable them to operate in a quasi-governmental fashion, like the Islamic State (IS)? Such organizations are certainly dangerous, but how would nuclear terrorism fit in with a program for building and sustaining a new caliphate that would restore past glories of Islamic society, especially since, like any organized government, the Islamic State would itself be vulnerable to nuclear attack? Building a new Islamic state out of radioactive ashes is an unlikely ambition for such groups. However, now that it has become notorious, apocalyptic pronouncements in Western media may begin at any time, warning of the possible acquisition and use of nuclear weapons by IS. Even if a terror group were to achieve technical nuclear proficiency, the time, money, and infrastructure needed to build nuclear weapons creates significant risks of discovery that would put the group at risk of attack. Given the ease of obtaining conventional explosives and the ability to deploy them, a terrorist group is unlikely to exchange a big part of its operational program to engage in a risky nuclear development effort with such doubtful prospects. And, of course, 9/11 has heightened sensitivity to the need for protection, lowering further the probability of a successful effort. | 18,704 | <h4>No nuke terror or escalation</h4><p><strong>Weiss 15</strong> (Leonard, visiting scholar at the Center for International Security and Cooperation at Stanford University, and a member of the National Advisory Board of the Center for Arms Control and Non-Proliferation in Washington, DC, former professor of applied mathematics and engineering at Brown University and the University of Maryland, “On fear and nuclear terrorism,” Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists, March/April 2015, Vol. 71, No. 2, p. 75-87<u>]</p><p></u>If the fear of nuclear war has thus had some positive effects, the fear of nuclear terrorism has had mainly negative effects on the lives of millions of people around the world, including in the United States, and even affects negatively the prospects for a more peaceful world. <u><mark>Although</mark> there has been much commentary on</u> <u>the interest that Osama bin Laden, when he was alive, reportedly expressed</u> in obtaining nuclear weapons (see Mowatt-Larssen, 2010), <u>and <mark>some</mark> terrorists</u> no doubt <u><mark>desire</mark> to obtain such <mark>weapons, <strong>evidence</strong> of any</mark> terrorist <mark>group <strong>working seriously</strong> toward</mark> the <mark>theft </mark>of nuclear weapons <mark>or</mark> the acquisition of such weapons by <mark>other means is</mark> <strong>virtually <mark>nonexistent</strong>. This</mark> </u>may be due to a combination of reasons. <u>Terrorists understand that it is not hard to terrorize a population without committing mass murder</u>: In 2002, a single sniper in the Washington, DC area, operating within his own automobile and with one accomplice, killed 10 people and changed the behavior of virtually the entire populace of the city over a period of three weeks by instilling fear of being a randomly chosen shooting victim when out shopping. Terrorists who believe the commission of violence helps their cause have access to many explosive materials and conventional weapons to ply their “trade<u>.” If public sympathy is important to their cause, an apparent plan or commission of mass murder <mark>is not going to help them, </mark>and indeed will make their enemies even more implacable</u>, reducing the prospects of achieving their goals. <u>The acquisition of nuclear weapons by terrorists is not like the acquisition of conventional <mark>weapons; it requires significant <strong>time</strong>, <strong></mark>planning</strong>, <strong><mark>resources</strong>, and <strong>expertise</strong>, with no guarantees</mark> that an acquired device would work. <mark>It requires putting aside</mark> at least some aspects of a group’s more immediate activities and <mark>goals</mark> for an attempted operation that no terrorist group has previously accomplished</u>. While absence of evidence does not mean evidence of absence (as then-Secretary of Defense Donald Rumsfeld kept reminding us during the search for Saddam’s nonexistent nuclear weapons), it is reasonable to conclude that the fear of nuclear terrorism has swamped realistic consideration of the threat. As Brian Jenkins, a longtime observer of terrorist groups, wrote in 2008: Nuclear terrorism … turns out to be a world of truly worrisome particles of truth. Yet it is also a world of fantasies, nightmares, urban legends, fakes, hoaxes, scams, stings, mysterious substances, terrorist boasts, sensational claims, description of vast conspiracies, allegations of coverups, lurid headlines, layers of misinformation and disinformation. Much is inconclusive or contradictory. Only the terror is real. (Jenkins, 2008: 26) The three ways terrorists might get a nuke To illustrate in more detail how fear has distorted the threat of nuclear terrorism, <u>consider the three possibilities for terrorists to obtain a nuclear weapon: steal one; be given one created by a nuclear weapon state; manufacture one. <strong>None of these possibilities has a high probability of occurring</u></strong>. Stealing nukes. <u><mark>Nothing is better protected</mark> in a nuclear weapon state <mark>than</mark> the <mark>weapons themselves, which have multiple layers</mark> of safeguards that</u>, in the United States, <u>include intelligence and surveillance, electronic locks</u> (including so-called “permissive action links” that prevent detonation unless a code is entered into the lock), <u>gated and locked storage facilities, armed guards, and teams of elite responders if an attempt at theft were to occur</u>. We know that <u>most weapon states have such protections, and <mark>there is <strong>no reason</strong> to believe </mark>that such <mark>protections are missing in the remaining states</mark>, since no weapon state would want to put itself at risk of an unintended nuclear detonation of its own weapons by a malevolent agent. Thus, the likelihood of an unauthorized agent secretly planning a theft, without being discovered, and getting access to weapons</u> with the intent and physical ability to carry them off in the face of such layers of protection <u>is <strong>extremely low</u></strong>—but it isn’t impossible, especially in the case where the thief is an insider. The insider threat helped give credibility to the stories, circulating about 20 years ago, that there were “loose nukes” in the USSR, based on some statements by a Soviet general who claimed the regime could not account for more than 40 “suitcase nukes” that had been built. The Russian government denied the claim, and at this point there is no evidence that any nukes were ever loose. Now, it is unclear if any such weapon would even work after 20 years of corrosion of both the nuclear and non-nuclear materials in the device and the radioactive decay of certain isotopes. Because of the large number of terrorist groups operating in its geographic vicinity, <u>Pakistan is frequently suggested as a possible candidate</u> for scenarios in which a terrorist group either seizes a weapon via collaboration with insiders sympathetic to its cause, or in which terrorists “inherit” nuclear weapons by taking over the arsenal of a failed nuclear state that has devolved into chaos. Attacks by a terrorist group on a Pakistani military base, at Kamra, which is believed to house nuclear weapons in some form, have been referenced in connection with such security concerns (Nelson and Hussain, 2012). However, the Kamra base contained US fighter planes, including F-16s, used to bomb Taliban bases in tribal areas bordering Afghanistan, so the planes, not nuclear weapons, were the likely target of the terrorists, and in any case the mission was a failure. Moreover, <u><mark>Pakistan is not about to collapse, and</mark> the Pakistanis are known to have <mark>received <strong>major international assistance</strong></mark> in technologies for protecting their weapons from unauthorized use, store them in somewhat disassembled fashion at multiple locations, <mark>and</mark> have a <strong><mark>sophisticated</mark> nuclear <mark>security</mark> structure</strong> in place</u> (see Gregory, 2013; Khan, 2012). However, <u>the weapons are assembled at times of high tension in the region, and, to keep a degree of uncertainty in their location, they are moved from place to place, making them more vulnerable to seizure at such times</u> (Goldberg and Ambinder, 2011). (It should be noted that US nuclear weapons were subject to such risks during various times when the weapons traveled US highways in disguised trucks and accompanying vehicles, but such travel and the possibility of terrorist seizure was never mentioned publicly.) Such scenarios of seizure in Pakistan would require a major security breakdown within the army leading to a takeover of weapons by a nihilistic terrorist group with little warning, while army loyalists along with India and other interested parties (like the United States) stand by and do not intervene. This is not a particularly realistic scenario, but it’s also not a reason to conclude that Pakistan’s nuclear arsenal is of no concern. It is, not only because of an internal threat, but especially because it raises the possibility of nuclear war with India. For this and other reasons, intelligence agencies in multiple countries spend considerable resources tracking the Pakistani nuclear situation to reduce the likelihood of surprises. But any consideration of Pakistan’s nuclear arsenal does bring home (once again) the folly of US policy in the 1980s, when stopping the Pakistani nuclear program was put on a back burner in order to prosecute the Cold War against the Soviets in Afghanistan (which ultimately led to the establishment of Al Qaeda). Some of the loudest voices expressing concern about nuclear terrorism belong to former senior government officials who supported US assistance to the mujahideen and the accompanying diminution of US opposition to Pakistan’s nuclear activities. <u>Acquiring nukes</u> as a gift. Following the shock of 9/11, government officials and the media imagined many scenarios in which terrorists obtain nuclear weapons; one of those scenarios involves a weapon state using a terrorist group for delivery of a nuclear weapon. <u>There are at least two reasons why this scenario is unlikely</u>: First, <u>once <mark>a</mark> weapon <mark>state</mark> loses control of a weapon, it <mark>cannot be sure the weapon will be used</mark> by the terrorist group <mark>as intended</u></mark>. Second, <u>the state cannot be sure that the transfer of the weapon has been undetected either before or after the fact of its detonation</u> (see Lieber and Press, 2013). The use of the weapon by a terrorist group will ultimately result in the transferring nation becoming a nuclear target just as if it had itself detonated the device. <u><mark>This is <strong>a powerful deterrent</strong></mark> to such a transfer, making the transfer a low-probability event.<strong> </u></strong>Although these first two ways in which terrorists might obtain a nuclear weapon have very small probabilities of occurring (there is no available data suggesting that terrorist groups have produced plans for stealing a weapon, nor has there been any public information suggesting that any nuclear weapon state has seriously considered providing a nuclear weapon to a sub-national group), the probabilities cannot be said to be zero as long as nuclear weapons exist. <u>Manufacturing a nuclear weapon. To accomplish this, a terrorist group would have to obtain an appropriate amount of</u> one of the two most popular <u>materials</u> for nuclear weapons, highly enriched uranium (HEU) or plutonium separated from fuel used in a production reactor or a power reactor. Weapon-grade <u><mark>plutonium</u></mark> is found in weapon manufacturing facilities in nuclear weapon states and <u><mark>is</mark> very <mark>highly protected</u></mark> until it is inserted in a weapon. <u><mark>Reactor</mark>-grade <mark>plutonium</u></mark>, although still capable of being weaponized, is less protected, and in that sense <u>is a more attractive target</u> for a terrorist, especially since it has been produced and stored in prodigious quantities in a number of nuclear weapon states and non-weapon states, particularly Japan. But <u>terrorist use of plutonium for a nuclear explosive device <mark>would require</mark> the construction of an implosion weapon,</u> requiring the fashioning of an appropriate explosive lens of TNT, <u><mark>a <strong>notoriously difficult</strong> technical problem</u></mark>. And if a high nuclear yield (much greater than 1 kiloton) is desired, <u>the use of reactor-grade plutonium would require a still more sophisticated design</u>. Moreover, if the plutonium is only available through chemical separation from some (presumably stolen) spent fuel rods, additional <u>technical complications present themselves</u>. There is at least one study showing that a small team of people with the appropriate technical skills and equipment could, in principle, build a plutonium-based nuclear explosive device (Mark et al., 1986). But <u><mark>even if one discounts the high probability that the plan <strong>would be discovered</strong></mark> at some stage</u> (missing plutonium or spent fuel rods would put the authorities and intelligence operations under high alert), <u>translating <mark>this</mark> into a real-world situation <mark>suggests</mark> an <strong><mark>extremely low </mark>probability of <mark>technical success</strong></mark>. More likely</u>, according to one well-known weapon designer,4 <u>would be the death of</u> the person or <u>persons in the attempt to build the device</u>. There is the possibility of <u>an insider threat</u>; in one example, a team of people working at a reactor or reprocessing site could conspire to steal some material and try to hide the diversion as MUF (materials unaccounted for) within the nuclear safeguards system. But this scenario <u>would require intimate knowledge of the materials accounting system on which safeguards in that state are based and adds another layer of complexity to an operation with low probability of success. The situation is different in the case of using highly enriched uranium</u>, which presents fewer technical challenges. Here an implosion design is not necessary, and a “gun type” design is the more likely approach. Fear of this scenario has sometimes been promoted in the literature via the quotation of a famous statement by nuclear physicist Luis Alvarez that dropping a subcritical amount of HEU onto another subcritical amount from a distance of five feet could result in a nuclear yield. The probability of such a yield (and its size) would depend on the geometry of the HEU components and the amount of material. More likely than a substantial nuclear explosion from such a scenario would be a criticality accident that would release an intense burst of radiation, killing persons in the immediate vicinity, or (even less likely) a low-yield nuclear “fizzle” that could be quite damaging locally (like a large TNT explosion) but also carry a psychological effect because of its nuclear dimension. In any case, since the critical mass of a bare metal perfect sphere of pure U-235 is approximately 56 kilograms, <u>stealing that much highly enriched material</u> (and getting away without detection, an armed fight, or a criticality accident) <u>is <strong>a major problem</strong> for any thief and one significantly greater than the stealing of small amounts of HEU and lower-enriched material that has been reported from time to time over the past two decades</u>, mostly from former Soviet sites that have since had their security greatly strengthened. Moreover, <u>fashioning the material into a form more useful</u> or convenient <u>for <mark>explosive purposes </mark>could</u> likely <u><mark>mean </mark>a need for <mark>still more material</mark> than suggested above, plus a means for machining it, as would be the case for HEU fuel assemblies from a research reactor</u>. In a recent paper, physics professor B. C. Reed discusses the feasibility of terrorists building a low-yield, gun-type fission weapon, but admittedly avoids the issue of whether the terrorists would likely have the technical ability to carry feasibility to realization and whether the terrorists are likely to be successful in stealing the needed material and hiding their project as it proceeds (Reed, 2014). But this is the crux of the nuclear terrorism issue. There is no argument about feasibility, which has been accepted for decades, even for plutonium-based weapons, ever since Ted Taylor first raised it in the early 1970s5 and a Senate subcommittee held hearings in the late 1970s on a weapon design created by a Harvard dropout from information he obtained from the public section of the Los Alamos National Laboratory library (Fialka, 1978). Likewise, no one can deny the terrible consequences of a nuclear explosion. The question is the level of risk, and what steps are acceptable in a democracy for reducing it. Although the attention in the literature given to nuclear terrorism scenarios involving HEU would suggest major attempts to obtain such material by terrorist groups, <u>there is only one known case of a major theft of HEU</u>. It involves a US government contractor processing HEU for the US Navy in Apollo, Pennsylvania in the 1970s at a time when security and materials accounting were extremely lax. The theft was almost surely carried out by agents of the Israeli government with the probable involvement of a person or persons working for the contractor, not a sub-national terrorist group intent on making its own weapons (Gilinsky and Mattson, 2010). <u>The circumstances under which this theft occurred were unique, and there was significant information about the contractor’s relationship to Israel that should have rung alarm bells and would do so today</u>. Although it involved a government and not a sub-national group, the theft underscores the importance of security and accounting of nuclear materials, especially because the technical requirements for making an HEU weapon are less daunting than for a plutonium weapon, and the probability of success by a terrorist group, though low, is certainly greater than zero. Over the past two decades, <u><mark>there has been <strong>a significant effort</strong></mark> to increase protection</p><p> of such materials</u>, <u>particularly</u> in recent years <u>through the efforts of</u> nongovernmental organizations like the International Panel on Fissile Materials6 and <u>advocates like</u> Matthew <u><strong>Bunn</u></strong> working within the Obama administration (Bunn and Newman, 2008), though the administration has apparently not seen the need to make the materials as secure as the weapons themselves. Are terrorists even interested in making their own nuclear weapons? A recent paper (Friedman and Lewis, 2014) postulates a scenario by which terrorists might seize nuclear materials in Pakistan for fashioning a weapon. While jihadist sympathizers are known to have worked within the Pakistani nuclear establishment, <u>there is <strong>little to no evidence</strong> that terrorist groups in or outside the region are seriously trying to obtain a nuclear capability</u>. And Pakistan has been operating a uranium enrichment plant for its weapons program for nearly 30 years with no credible reports of diversion of HEU from the plant. T<u>here is one stark example of a terrorist organization that actually started a nuclear effort: the Aum Shinrikyo group.</u> At its peak, this religious cult had a membership estimated in the tens of thousands spread over a variety of countries, including Japan; its members had scientific expertise in many areas; and the group was well funded. Aum Shinrikyo obtained access to natural uranium supplies, but <u>the nuclear weapon effort stalled and was abandoned</u>. The group was also interested in chemical weapons and did produce sarin nerve gas with which they attacked the Tokyo subway system, killing 13 persons. <u>Aum Shinrikyo is now a small organization under continuing close surveillance. <mark>What about highly organized</mark> groups</u>, designated appropriately as terrorist, that have acquired enough territory to enable them to operate in a quasi-governmental fashion, <u>like the Islamic State (IS)?</u> Such organizations are certainly dangerous, but <u><mark>how would nuclear terrorism fit in</mark> with a program for building and sustaining a new caliphate that would restore past glories of Islamic society, especially since, like any organized government, the Islamic State would itself be vulnerable to nuclear attack</u>? <u>Building a new Islamic state out of radioactive ashes is an unlikely ambition for such groups.</u> However, now that it has become notorious, apocalyptic pronouncements in Western media may begin at any time, warning of the possible acquisition and use of nuclear weapons by IS. <u><mark>Even if a</mark> terror <mark>group were to achieve</mark> technical nuclear <mark>proficiency, the <strong>time, money, and infrastructure</strong></mark> needed to build nuclear weapons <mark>creates</mark> <strong>significant risks of <mark>discovery</strong></mark> that would put the group at risk of attack. Given the ease of obtaining conventional explosives and the ability to deploy them, a terrorist group is unlikely to <strong>exchange a big part of its operational program</strong> to engage in a risky nuclear development effort with such doubtful prospects</u>. And, of course, <u>9/11 has heightened sensitivity to the need for protection, lowering further the probability of a successful effort. </p></u> | 1NC | Russia | 1nc - Russia Coop - No Terror | 47,827 | 578 | 53,685 | ./documents/ndtceda20/WichitaState/BeMi/Wichita%20State-Benson-Mitchell-Neg-NU-Round4.docx | 622,597 | N | NU | 4 | UC Berkeley EE | Nate Graziano | 1ac - Baltic States
1nc - deterrence assurance dos flexible response secret diplomacy t-nato revoke article 5
2nr - assurance | ndtceda20/WichitaState/BeMi/Wichita%20State-Benson-Mitchell-Neg-NU-Round4.docx | null | 52,561 | BeMi | Wichita State BeMi | null | Ka..... | Be..... | Co..... | Mi..... | 19,363 | WichitaState | Wichita State | null | null | 1,010 | ndtceda20 | NDT/CEDA 2020-21 | 2,020 | cx | college | 2 |
1,973,460 | 2. Asset Forfeiture---it’s legal and strengthens evidence gathering. | Zoppei 12. | Zoppei 12. Verena Zoppei – Master of Laws Program, The University of The Western Cape. “Tax evasion as a predicate offence for money laundering,” 29 October 2012. https://pdfs.semanticscholar.org/3822/c0633200eeb1ca7c937140f6649c5726a277.pdf | this section aims at analysing whether criminalising tax evasion under the umbrella of the ML would be an effective and appropriate way of dealing with the issue. AML consists of two elements, one of criminal law, that is the criminalisation of the conduct, and one regulatory, which aims at preventing the abuse of the financial system for ML purposes. The primary reason for fighting ML is to enable law enforcement authorities to confiscate the proceeds of predicate criminal activities in those situations where confiscation might otherwise not be possible The crime of ML was, in fact, invented, to “follow the money” of criminal groups, since the imprisonment of even top ranking criminals did not result in a reduction of organised crime rates. The underlying idea was to attack the criminals' economic wealth, through assets recovery mechanisms. Assets recovery has been recognised as a key element also in the fight against corruption Additionally, since most high level criminals usually stay aloof from the commission of crimes, while enjoying the financial profits, ML can serve the purpose of gathering evidence against top criminals by tracking the movement of money. The crime of ML punishes conduct aimed at disguising and concealing the origin or the ownership of the proceeds of crime. In particular, when AML law allows the confiscation of the equivalent, this can result in an advantage for law enforcement, when proceeds of crimes have been intermingled with lawful assets, or are held by bona fide third parties. Financial gain is also what moves tax evaders. If the earnings resulting from tax evasion might be confiscated as proceeds of ML, this may become a deterrent for legal persons involved in fiscal crimes. | criminalising tax evasion under ML would be effective AML prevent the abuse for ML purposes to enable authorities to confiscate the proceeds of predicate activities where confiscation might otherwise not be possible through assets recovery mechanisms ML can gather evidence against criminals by tracking money crime punishes concealing the proceeds of crime If the earnings might be confiscated this may become a deterrent for fiscal crimes | 3 Criminalisation of tax evasion under ML Following the discussion of the harmful consequences of fiscal competition, and the most common methods of tax evasion, this section aims at analysing whether criminalising tax evasion under the umbrella of the ML would be an effective and appropriate way of dealing with the issue. AML consists of two elements, one of criminal law, that is the criminalisation of the conduct, and one regulatory, which aims at preventing the abuse of the financial system for ML purposes. 3.1 The rationale of AML “The primary reason for fighting ML is to enable law enforcement authorities to confiscate the proceeds of predicate criminal activities in those situations where confiscation might otherwise not be possible”.92 The crime of ML was, in fact, invented, to “follow the money” of criminal groups, since the imprisonment of even top ranking criminals did not result in a reduction of organised crime rates.93 The underlying idea was to attack the criminals' economic wealth, through assets recovery mechanisms. This, it was believed, would improve the effectiveness of the fight against ML and criminal activities, such as drug trafficking.94 Assets recovery has been recognised as a key element also in the fight against corruption, under UNCAC.95 Additionally, since most high level criminals usually stay aloof from the commission of crimes, while enjoying the financial profits, ML can serve the purpose of gathering evidence against top criminals by tracking the movement of money.96 The crime of ML punishes conduct aimed at disguising and concealing the origin or the ownership of the proceeds of crime. In particular, when AML law allows the confiscation of the equivalent, this can result in an advantage for law enforcement, when proceeds of crimes have been intermingled with lawful assets, or are held by bona fide third parties. In the first case it should be still possible to confiscate the equivalent value of assets from the money launderer, and, in the second case, the object of confiscation will be any property deriving from the ML, even the profit made by the selling of the criminal assets to bona fide third parties. Financial gain is also what moves tax evaders. If the earnings resulting from tax evasion might be confiscated as proceeds of ML, this may become a deterrent for legal persons involved in fiscal crimes. The question, with regard to legitimacy under criminal laws, is this: Can tax evasion be the predicate offence which justifies the court in issuing a confiscation order? | 2,550 | <h4>2. Asset Forfeiture---it’s <u>legal</u> and strengthens <u>evidence gathering</u>. </h4><p><strong>Zoppei 12.</strong> Verena Zoppei – Master of Laws Program, The University of The Western Cape. “Tax evasion as a predicate offence for money laundering,” 29 October 2012. https://pdfs.semanticscholar.org/3822/c0633200eeb1ca7c937140f6649c5726a277.pdf</p><p>3 Criminalisation of tax evasion under ML Following the discussion of the harmful consequences of fiscal competition, and the most common methods of tax evasion, <u>this section aims at analysing whether <mark>criminalising tax evasion under</mark> the umbrella of the <mark>ML would be</mark> an <mark>effective</mark> and appropriate way of dealing with the issue. <mark>AML</mark> consists of two elements, one of criminal law, that is the criminalisation of the conduct, and one regulatory, which <strong>aims at <mark>prevent</mark>ing <mark>the abuse </mark>of the financial system <mark>for ML purposes</strong></mark>.</u> 3.1 The rationale of AML “<u>The primary reason for fighting ML is <mark>to <strong>enable</mark> law enforcement <mark>authorities to confiscate the proceeds of predicate</mark> criminal <mark>activities</mark> in those situations <mark>where confiscation might otherwise not be possible</u></strong></mark>”.92 <u>The crime of ML was, in fact, invented, to “follow the money” of criminal groups, since the imprisonment of even top ranking criminals did not result in a reduction of organised crime rates.</u>93 <u>The underlying idea was to attack the criminals' economic wealth, <mark>through <strong>assets recovery mechanisms</strong></mark>.</u> This, it was believed, would improve the effectiveness of the fight against ML and criminal activities, such as drug trafficking.94 <u>Assets recovery has been recognised as a key element also in the <strong>fight against corruption</u></strong>, under UNCAC.95 <u>Additionally, since most high level criminals usually stay aloof from the commission of crimes, while enjoying the financial profits, <mark>ML can</mark> serve the purpose of <strong><mark>gather</mark>ing <mark>evidence against </mark>top <mark>criminals by tracking </mark>the movement of <mark>money</strong></mark>.</u>96 <u>The <mark>crime</mark> of ML <mark>punishes</mark> conduct aimed at disguising and <mark>concealing </mark>the origin or the ownership of <mark>the proceeds of crime</mark>. In particular, when AML law allows the confiscation of the equivalent, this can result in an advantage for law enforcement, when proceeds of crimes have been intermingled with lawful assets, or are held by bona fide third parties.</u> In the first case it should be still possible to confiscate the equivalent value of assets from the money launderer, and, in the second case, the object of confiscation will be any property deriving from the ML, even the profit made by the selling of the criminal assets to bona fide third parties. <u>Financial gain is also what moves tax evaders. <mark>If the earnings</mark> resulting from tax evasion <mark>might be confiscated</mark> as proceeds of ML, <mark>this may become a deterrent for</mark> legal persons involved in <mark>fiscal crimes</mark>.</u> The question, with regard to legitimacy under criminal laws, is this: Can tax evasion be the predicate offence which justifies the court in issuing a confiscation order? </p> | 1AC | null | 1AC---Taxes | 829,682 | 151 | 58,174 | ./documents/hspolicy20/MontgomeryBell/HeMa/Montgomery%20Bell-Herrmann-Maxwell-Aff-Notre%20Dame-Round5.docx | 735,039 | A | Notre Dame | 5 | Interlake OZ | Luke Hartman | 1AC - Taxes
2NR - DDEV | hspolicy20/MontgomeryBell/HeMa/Montgomery%20Bell-Herrmann-Maxwell-Aff-Notre%20Dame-Round5.docx | null | 62,694 | HeMa | Montgomery Bell HeMa | null | Ge..... | He..... | As..... | Ma..... | 21,723 | MontgomeryBell | Montgomery Bell | TN | null | 1,019 | hspolicy20 | HS Policy 2020-21 | 2,020 | cx | hs | 2 |
615,892 | Nuclear Proliferation causes Nuclear War. | Kroenig 15 //Re-cut by Elmer | Kroenig 15 (Matthew Kroenig; Associate Professor and International Relations Field Chair in the Department of Government and School of Foreign Service at Georgetown University; 2015, “The History of Proliferation Optimism: Does It Have a Future?”; Journal of Strategic Studies, Volume 38, Issue 1-2)//Re-cut by Elmer | The spread of nuclear weapons poses at least six severe threats to international peace and security including: nuclear war, nuclear terrorism, global and regional instability, constrained US freedom of action, weakened alliances, and further nuclear proliferation. we should be pessimistic about the likely consequences of nuclear proliferation The greatest threat is nuclear war. The more states in possession of nuclear weapons the greater the probability that somewhere, someday, there will be a catastrophic nuclear war. Before reaching a state of MAD new nuclear states go through a transition period in which they lack a secure-second strike capability one or both states might believe that it has an incentive to use nuclear weapons first given its small size and lack of strategic depth, Israel might not be confident that it could absorb a nuclear strike and respond with a devastating counterstrike Iran might eventually be able to build a large and survivable nuclear arsenal, but, when it first crosses the nuclear threshold, Tehran will have a small and vulnerable nuclear force the state with the nuclear advantage might believe it has a splendid first strike capability. In a crisis, Israel might decide to launch a preventive nuclear strike to disarm Iran’s nuclear capabilities. this incentive might be further increased by Israel’s aggressive strategic culture that emphasizes preemptive action. the state with a small and vulnerable might feel use them or lose them pressures leaders can make a ‘threat that leaves something to chance’. They can initiate a nuclear crisis By playing these risky games of nuclear brinkmanship, states can increase the risk of nuclear war in an attempt to force a less resolved adversary to back down. crises have not resulted in nuclear war, but many of them have come close When we think about future nuclear crisis dyads with fewer sources of stability than existed during the Cold War, we can see that there is a real risk that a future crisis could result in a devastating nuclear exchange The spread of nuclear weapons also increases the risk of nuclear terrorism Laden declared it a ‘religious duty’ for Al- Qa’eda to acquire nuclear weapons and radical clerics have issued fatwas declaring it permissible to use nuclear weapons in Jihad against the West Unlike states, which can be more easily deterred, there is little doubt that if terrorists acquired nuclear weapons, they would use them.56 Analysts have pointed out hurdles that terrorists would have to overcome in order to acquire nuclear weapons.58 Nevertheless as nuclear weapons spread, the possibility that they will eventually fall into terrorist hands increases States could intentionally transfer nuclear weapons or to terrorist groups as weapons spread the probability that a leader might someday purposely arm a terrorist group increases a new nuclear state, with underdeveloped security procedures, might be vulnerable to theft, allowing terrorist groups or corrupt or ideologically-motivated insiders to transfer dangerous material to terrorists. a nuclear-armed state could collapse resulting in a breakdown of law and order and a loose nukes problem Historically the spread of nuclear weapons has emboldened their possessors and contributed to regional instability Recent scholarly analyses have demonstrated that, after controlling for other relevant factors, nuclear-weapon states are more likely to engage in conflict than nonnuclear weapon states this aggressiveness is more pronounced in new nuclear states that have less experience with nuclear diplomacy. nuclear-armed Iran would likely step up support to terrorist and proxy groups and engage in more aggressive coercive diplomacy we could witness an even more crisis prone Middle East. And in a poly-nuclear Middle East any one of those crises could result in a catastrophic nuclear exchange. | The spread of nuc s poses severe threats to international security including nuc war global instability Before MAD new states lack secure-second strike capability it has an incentive to use first a preventive strike emphasizes use em or lose em pressures leaders can initiate a nuclear crisis By playing brinkmanship states can increase the risk to force a less resolved adversary to back down a future crisis could result in a nuclear exchange as nuclear weapons spread possibility they fall into terrorist hands increases intentionally transfer loose nukes Historically spread of nuclear weapons contributed to regional instability aggressiveness is more pronounced in new nuclear states crises could result in a catastrophic nuclear exchange | The spread of nuclear weapons poses at least six severe threats to international peace and security including: nuclear war, nuclear terrorism, global and regional instability, constrained US freedom of action, weakened alliances, and further nuclear proliferation. Each of these threats has received extensive treatment elsewhere and this review is not intended to replicate or even necessarily to improve upon these previous efforts. Rather the goals of this section are more modest: to usefully bring together and recap the many reasons why we should be pessimistic about the likely consequences of nuclear proliferation. Many of these threats will be illuminated with a discussion of a case of much contemporary concern: Iran’s advanced nuclear program. Nuclear War The greatest threat posed by the spread of nuclear weapons is nuclear war. The more states in possession of nuclear weapons, the greater the probability that somewhere, someday, there will be a catastrophic nuclear war. To date, nuclear weapons have only been used in warfare once. In 1945, the United States used nuclear weapons on Hiroshima and Nagasaki, bringing World War II to a close. Many analysts point to the 65-plus-year tradition of nuclear non-use as evidence that nuclear weapons are unusable, but it would be naïve to think that nuclear weapons will never be used again simply because they have not been used for some time. After all, analysts in the 1990s argued that worldwide economic downturns like the Great Depression were a thing of the past, only to be surprised by the dot-com bubble bursting later in the decade and the Great Recession of the late 2000s.48 This author, for one, would be surprised if nuclear weapons are not used again sometime in his lifetime. Before reaching a state of MAD, new nuclear states go through a transition period in which they lack a secure-second strike capability. In this context, one or both states might believe that it has an incentive to use nuclear weapons first. For example, if Iran acquires nuclear weapons, neither Iran, nor its nuclear-armed rival, Israel, will have a secure, second-strike capability. Even though it is believed to have a large arsenal, given its small size and lack of strategic depth, Israel might not be confident that it could absorb a nuclear strike and respond with a devastating counterstrike. Similarly, Iran might eventually be able to build a large and survivable nuclear arsenal, but, when it first crosses the nuclear threshold, Tehran will have a small and vulnerable nuclear force. In these pre-MAD situations, there are at least three ways that nuclear war could occur. First, the state with the nuclear advantage might believe it has a splendid first strike capability. In a crisis, Israel might, therefore, decide to launch a preventive nuclear strike to disarm Iran’s nuclear capabilities. Indeed, this incentive might be further increased by Israel’s aggressive strategic culture that emphasizes preemptive action. Second, the state with a small and vulnerable nuclear arsenal, in this case Iran, might feel use them or lose them pressures. That is, in a crisis, Iran might decide to strike first rather than risk having its entire nuclear arsenal destroyed. Third, as Thomas Schelling has argued, nuclear war could result due to the reciprocal fear of surprise attack.49 If there are advantages to striking first, one state might start a nuclear war in the belief that war is inevitable and that it would be better to go first than to go second. Fortunately, there is no historic evidence of this dynamic occurring in a nuclear context, but it is still possible. In an Israeli–Iranian crisis, for example, Israel and Iran might both prefer to avoid a nuclear war, but decide to strike first rather than suffer a devastating first attack from an opponent. Even in a world of MAD, however, when both sides have secure, second-strike capabilities, there is still a risk of nuclear war. Rational deterrence theory assumes nuclear-armed states are governed by rational leaders who would not intentionally launch a suicidal nuclear war. This assumption appears to have applied to past and current nuclear powers, but there is no guarantee that it will continue to hold in the future. Iran’s theocratic government, despite its inflammatory rhetoric, has followed a fairly pragmatic foreign policy since 1979, but it contains leaders who hold millenarian religious worldviews and could one day ascend to power. We cannot rule out the possibility that, as nuclear weapons continue to spread, some leader somewhere will choose to launch a nuclear war, knowing full well that it could result in self-destruction. One does not need to resort to irrationality, however, to imagine nuclear war under MAD. Nuclear weapons may deter leaders from intentionally launching full-scale wars, but they do not mean the end of international politics. As was discussed above, nuclear-armed states still have conflicts of interest and leaders still seek to coerce nuclear-armed adversaries. Leaders might, therefore, choose to launch a limited nuclear war.50 This strategy might be especially attractive to states in a position of conventional inferiority that might have an incentive to escalate a crisis quickly to the nuclear level. During the Cold War, the United States planned to use nuclear weapons first to stop a Soviet invasion of Western Europe given NATO’s conventional inferiority.51 As Russia’s conventional power has deteriorated since the end of the Cold War, Moscow has come to rely more heavily on nuclear weapons in its military doctrine. Indeed, Russian strategy calls for the use of nuclear weapons early in a conflict (something that most Western strategists would consider to be escalatory) as a way to de-escalate a crisis. Similarly, Pakistan’s military plans for nuclear use in the event of an invasion from conventionally stronger India. And finally, Chinese generals openly talk about the possibility of nuclear use against a US superpower in a possible East Asia contingency. Second, as was also discussed above, leaders can make a ‘threat that leaves something to chance’.52 They can initiate a nuclear crisis. By playing these risky games of nuclear brinkmanship, states can increase the risk of nuclear war in an attempt to force a less resolved adversary to back down. Historical crises have not resulted in nuclear war, but many of them, including the 1962 Cuban Missile Crisis, have come close. And scholars have documented historical incidents when accidents nearly led to war.53 When we think about future nuclear crisis dyads, such as Iran and Israel, with fewer sources of stability than existed during the Cold War, we can see that there is a real risk that a future crisis could result in a devastating nuclear exchange. Nuclear Terrorism The spread of nuclear weapons also increases the risk of nuclear terrorism.54 While September 11th was one of the greatest tragedies in American history, it would have been much worse had Osama Bin Laden possessed nuclear weapons. Bin Laden declared it a ‘religious duty’ for Al- Qa’eda to acquire nuclear weapons and radical clerics have issued fatwas declaring it permissible to use nuclear weapons in Jihad against the West.55 Unlike states, which can be more easily deterred, there is little doubt that if terrorists acquired nuclear weapons, they would use them.56 Indeed, in recent years, many US politicians and security analysts have argued that nuclear terrorism poses the greatest threat to US national security.57 Analysts have pointed out the tremendous hurdles that terrorists would have to overcome in order to acquire nuclear weapons.58 Nevertheless, as nuclear weapons spread, the possibility that they will eventually fall into terrorist hands increases. States could intentionally transfer nuclear weapons, or the fissile material required to build them, to terrorist groups. There are good reasons why a state might be reluctant to transfer nuclear weapons to terrorists, but, as nuclear weapons spread, the probability that a leader might someday purposely arm a terrorist group increases. Some fear, for example, that Iran, with its close ties to Hamas and Hizballah, might be at a heightened risk of transferring nuclear weapons to terrorists. Moreover, even if no state would ever intentionally transfer nuclear capabilities to terrorists, a new nuclear state, with underdeveloped security procedures, might be vulnerable to theft, allowing terrorist groups or corrupt or ideologically-motivated insiders to transfer dangerous material to terrorists. There is evidence, for example, that representatives from Pakistan’s atomic energy establishment met with Al-Qa’eda members to discuss a possible nuclear deal.59 Finally, a nuclear-armed state could collapse, resulting in a breakdown of law and order and a loose nukes problem. US officials are currently very concerned about what would happen to Pakistan’s nuclear weapons if the government were to fall. As nuclear weapons spread, this problem is only further amplified. Iran is a country with a history of revolutions and a government with a tenuous hold on power. The regime change that Washington has long dreamed about in Tehran could actually become a nightmare if a nuclear-armed Iran suffered a breakdown in authority, forcing us to worry about the fate of Iran’s nuclear arsenal. Regional Instability The spread of nuclear weapons also emboldens nuclear powers, contributing to regional instability. States that lack nuclear weapons need to fear direct military attack from other states, but states with nuclear weapons can be confident that they can deter an intentional military attack, giving them an incentive to be more aggressive in the conduct of their foreign policy. In this way, nuclear weapons provide a shield under which states can feel free to engage in lower-level aggression. Indeed, international relations theories about the ‘stability-instability paradox’ maintain that stability at the nuclear level contributes to conventional instability.60 Historically, we have seen that the spread of nuclear weapons has emboldened their possessors and contributed to regional instability. Recent scholarly analyses have demonstrated that, after controlling for other relevant factors, nuclear-weapon states are more likely to engage in conflict than nonnuclear-weapon states and that this aggressiveness is more pronounced in new nuclear states that have less experience with nuclear diplomacy.61 Similarly, research on internal decision-making in Pakistan reveals that Pakistani foreign policymakers may have been emboldened by the acquisition of nuclear weapons, which encouraged them to initiate militarized disputes against India.62 Currently, Iran restrains its foreign policy because it fears major military retaliation from the United States or Israel, but with nuclear weapons it could feel free to push harder. A nuclear-armed Iran would likely step up support to terrorist and proxy groups and engage in more aggressive coercive diplomacy. With a nuclear-armed Iran increasingly throwing its weight around in the region, we could witness an even more crisis prone Middle East. And in a poly-nuclear Middle East with Israel, Iran, and, in the future, possibly other states, armed with nuclear weapons, any one of those crises could result in a catastrophic nuclear exchange. | 11,405 | <h4>Nuclear Proliferation causes <u>Nuclear War</u>.</h4><p><strong>Kroenig 15 </strong>(Matthew Kroenig; Associate Professor and International Relations Field Chair in the Department of Government and School of Foreign Service at Georgetown University; 2015, “The History of Proliferation Optimism: Does It Have a Future?”; Journal of Strategic Studies, Volume 38, Issue 1-2)<u><strong>//Re-cut by Elmer</p><p><mark>The spread of nuc</mark>lear weapon<mark>s poses</mark> at least six <mark>severe threats to international</mark> peace and <mark>security including</mark>: <mark>nuc</mark>lear <mark>war</mark>, nuclear terrorism, <mark>global</mark> and</u></strong> <u><strong>regional <mark>instability</mark>, constrained US freedom of action, weakened alliances, and further nuclear proliferation.</u></strong> Each of these threats has received extensive treatment elsewhere and this review is not intended to replicate or even necessarily to improve upon these previous efforts. Rather the goals of this section are more modest: to usefully bring together and recap the many reasons why <u><strong>we should be pessimistic about the likely consequences of nuclear proliferation</u></strong>. Many of these threats will be illuminated with a discussion of a case of much contemporary concern: Iran’s advanced nuclear program. Nuclear War <u><strong>The greatest threat</u></strong> posed by the spread of nuclear weapons <u><strong>is nuclear war. The more states in possession of nuclear weapons</u></strong>, <u><strong>the greater the probability that somewhere, someday, there will be a catastrophic nuclear war.</u></strong> To date, nuclear weapons have only been used in warfare once. In 1945, the United States used nuclear weapons on Hiroshima and Nagasaki, bringing World War II to a close. Many analysts point to the 65-plus-year tradition of nuclear non-use as evidence that nuclear weapons are unusable, but it would be naïve to think that nuclear weapons will never be used again simply because they have not been used for some time. After all, analysts in the 1990s argued that worldwide economic downturns like the Great Depression were a thing of the past, only to be surprised by the dot-com bubble bursting later in the decade and the Great Recession of the late 2000s.48 This author, for one, would be surprised if nuclear weapons are not used again sometime in his lifetime. <u><strong><mark>Before</mark> reaching a state of <mark>MAD</u></strong></mark>, <u><strong><mark>new</mark> nuclear <mark>states </mark>go through a transition period in which they<mark> lack</mark> a <mark>secure-second strike capability</u></strong></mark>. In this context, <u><strong>one or both states might believe that <mark>it has an incentive to use</mark> nuclear weapons <mark>first</u></strong></mark>. For example, if Iran acquires nuclear weapons, neither Iran, nor its nuclear-armed rival, Israel, will have a secure, second-strike capability. Even though it is believed to have a large arsenal, <u><strong>given its small size and lack of strategic depth, Israel might not be confident that it could absorb a nuclear strike and respond with a devastating counterstrike</u></strong>. Similarly, <u><strong>Iran might eventually be able to build a large and survivable nuclear arsenal, but, when it first crosses the nuclear threshold, Tehran will have a small and vulnerable nuclear force</u></strong>. In these pre-MAD situations, there are at least three ways that nuclear war could occur. First, <u><strong>the state with the nuclear advantage might believe it has a</u></strong> <u><strong>splendid first strike capability. In a crisis, Israel might</u></strong>, therefore, <u><strong>decide to launch <mark>a preventive</mark> nuclear <mark>strike</mark> to disarm Iran’s nuclear capabilities. </u></strong>Indeed, <u><strong>this</u></strong> <u><strong>incentive</u></strong> <u><strong>might be further increased by Israel’s aggressive strategic culture that <mark>emphasizes</mark> preemptive action.</u></strong> Second, <u><strong>the state with a small and vulnerable</u></strong> nuclear arsenal, in this case Iran, <u><strong>might feel <mark>use </mark>th<mark>em or lose </mark>th<mark>em pressures</u></strong></mark>. That is, in a crisis, Iran might decide to strike first rather than risk having its entire nuclear arsenal destroyed. Third, as Thomas Schelling has argued, nuclear war could result due to the reciprocal fear of surprise attack.49 If there are advantages to striking first, one state might start a nuclear war in the belief that war is inevitable and that it would be better to go first than to go second. Fortunately, there is no historic evidence of this dynamic occurring in a nuclear context, but it is still possible. In an Israeli–Iranian crisis, for example, Israel and Iran might both prefer to avoid a nuclear war, but decide to strike first rather than suffer a devastating first attack from an opponent. Even in a world of MAD, however, when both sides have secure, second-strike capabilities, there is still a risk of nuclear war. Rational deterrence theory assumes nuclear-armed states are governed by rational leaders who would not intentionally launch a suicidal nuclear war. This assumption appears to have applied to past and current nuclear powers, but there is no guarantee that it will continue to hold in the future. Iran’s theocratic government, despite its inflammatory rhetoric, has followed a fairly pragmatic foreign policy since 1979, but it contains leaders who hold millenarian religious worldviews and could one day ascend to power. We cannot rule out the possibility that, as nuclear weapons continue to spread, some leader somewhere will choose to launch a nuclear war, knowing full well that it could result in self-destruction. One does not need to resort to irrationality, however, to imagine nuclear war under MAD. Nuclear weapons may deter leaders from intentionally launching full-scale wars, but they do not mean the end of international politics. As was discussed above, nuclear-armed states still have conflicts of interest and leaders still seek to coerce nuclear-armed adversaries. Leaders might, therefore, choose to launch a limited nuclear war.50 This strategy might be especially attractive to states in a position of conventional inferiority that might have an incentive to escalate a crisis quickly to the nuclear level. During the Cold War, the United States planned to use nuclear weapons first to stop a Soviet invasion of Western Europe given NATO’s conventional inferiority.51 As Russia’s conventional power has deteriorated since the end of the Cold War, Moscow has come to rely more heavily on nuclear weapons in its military doctrine. Indeed, Russian strategy calls for the use of nuclear weapons early in a conflict (something that most Western strategists would consider to be escalatory) as a way to de-escalate a crisis. Similarly, Pakistan’s military plans for nuclear use in the event of an invasion from conventionally stronger India. And finally, Chinese generals openly talk about the possibility of nuclear use against a US superpower in a possible East Asia contingency. Second, as was also discussed above, <u><strong><mark>leaders</mark> can make a ‘threat that leaves something to chance’.</u></strong>52 <u><strong>They <mark>can initiate a nuclear crisis</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong><mark>By playing </mark>these risky games of nuclear <mark>brinkmanship</mark>, <mark>states can increase the risk</mark> of nuclear war in an attempt <mark>to force a less resolved adversary to back</mark> <mark>down</mark>.</u></strong> Historical <u><strong>crises have not resulted in nuclear war, but many of them</u></strong>, including the 1962 Cuban Missile Crisis, <u><strong>have come close</u></strong>. And scholars have documented historical incidents when accidents nearly led to war.53 <u><strong>When we think about future nuclear crisis dyads</u></strong>, such as Iran and Israel, <u><strong>with fewer sources of stability than existed during the Cold War, we can see that there is a real risk that <mark>a future crisis could result in a </mark>devastating <mark>nuclear exchange</u></strong></mark>. Nuclear Terrorism <u><strong>The spread of nuclear weapons also increases the risk of nuclear terrorism</u></strong>.54 While September 11th was one of the greatest tragedies in American history, it would have been much worse had Osama Bin Laden possessed nuclear weapons. Bin <u><strong>Laden declared it a ‘religious duty’ for Al- Qa’eda to acquire</u></strong> <u><strong>nuclear weapons and radical clerics have issued fatwas declaring it permissible to use nuclear weapons in Jihad against the West</u></strong>.55 <u><strong>Unlike states, which can be more easily deterred, there is little doubt that if terrorists acquired nuclear weapons, they would use them.56</u></strong> Indeed, in recent years, many US politicians and security analysts have argued that nuclear terrorism poses the greatest threat to US national security.57 <u><strong>Analysts</u></strong> <u><strong>have pointed out</u></strong> the tremendous<u><strong> hurdles</u></strong> <u><strong>that terrorists would have to overcome</u></strong> <u><strong>in order to acquire nuclear weapons.58</u></strong> <u><strong>Nevertheless</u></strong>, <u><strong><mark>as nuclear weapons spread</mark>, the <mark>possibility </mark>that <mark>they </mark>will eventually <mark>fall into terrorist hands increases</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong>States could <mark>intentionally transfer </mark>nuclear weapons</u></strong>, <u><strong>or</u></strong> the fissile material required to build them, <u><strong>to terrorist groups</u></strong>. There are good reasons why a state might be reluctant to transfer nuclear weapons to terrorists, but, <u><strong>as</u></strong> nuclear <u><strong>weapons spread</u></strong>, <u><strong>the probability that a leader might someday purposely arm a terrorist group increases</u></strong>. Some fear, for example, that Iran, with its close ties to Hamas and Hizballah, might be at a heightened risk of transferring nuclear weapons to terrorists. Moreover, even if no state would ever intentionally transfer nuclear capabilities to terrorists, <u><strong>a new nuclear state, with underdeveloped security procedures, might be vulnerable to theft, allowing terrorist groups or corrupt or ideologically-motivated insiders to transfer dangerous material to terrorists.</u></strong> There is evidence, for example, that representatives from Pakistan’s atomic energy establishment met with Al-Qa’eda members to discuss a possible nuclear deal.59 Finally, <u><strong>a nuclear-armed state could collapse</u></strong>, <u><strong>resulting in a breakdown of law and order and a <mark>loose nukes </mark>problem</u></strong>. US officials are currently very concerned about what would happen to Pakistan’s nuclear weapons if the government were to fall. As nuclear weapons spread, this problem is only further amplified. Iran is a country with a history of revolutions and a government with a tenuous hold on power. The regime change that Washington has long dreamed about in Tehran could actually become a nightmare if a nuclear-armed Iran suffered a breakdown in authority, forcing us to worry about the fate of Iran’s nuclear arsenal. Regional Instability The spread of nuclear weapons also emboldens nuclear powers, contributing to regional instability. States that lack nuclear weapons need to fear direct military attack from other states, but states with nuclear weapons can be confident that they can deter an intentional military attack, giving them an incentive to be more aggressive in the conduct of their foreign policy. In this way, nuclear weapons provide a shield under which states can feel free to engage in lower-level aggression. Indeed, international relations theories about the ‘stability-instability paradox’ maintain that stability at the nuclear level contributes to conventional instability.60 <u><strong><mark>Historically</u></strong></mark>, we have seen that <u><strong>the <mark>spread</mark> <mark>of nuclear weapons </mark>has emboldened their possessors and <mark>contributed to regional instability</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong>Recent scholarly analyses have demonstrated that, after controlling for other relevant factors, nuclear-weapon states are more likely to engage in conflict than nonnuclear</u></strong>-<u><strong>weapon states</u></strong> and that <u><strong>this <mark>aggressiveness is more pronounced in new nuclear states</mark> that have less experience with nuclear diplomacy.</u></strong>61 Similarly, research on internal decision-making in Pakistan reveals that Pakistani foreign policymakers may have been emboldened by the acquisition of nuclear weapons, which encouraged them to initiate militarized disputes against India.62 Currently, Iran restrains its foreign policy because it fears major military retaliation from the United States or Israel, but with nuclear weapons it could feel free to push harder. A <u><strong>nuclear-armed Iran would likely step up support to terrorist and proxy groups and engage in more aggressive coercive diplomacy</u></strong>. With a nuclear-armed Iran increasingly throwing its weight around in the region, <u><strong>we could witness an even more crisis prone Middle East.</u></strong> <u><strong>And in a poly-nuclear Middle East</u></strong> with Israel, Iran, and, in the future, possibly other states, armed with nuclear weapons, <u><strong>any one of those <mark>crises could result in a catastrophic nuclear exchange</mark>.</p></u></strong> | null | 1AC | 1AC: Lunar Heritage | 6,955 | 2,098 | 11,054 | ./documents/hsld21/DiamondBar/Ch/Diamond%20Bar-Chu-Aff-Palm%20Classic-Round3.docx | 885,468 | A | Palm Classic | 3 | Westridge TW | Jared Burke | 1AC - Lunar heritage
1NC - Set col - Case
1AR - All
2NR - Set Col
2AR - Case - Set col | hsld21/DiamondBar/Ch/Diamond%20Bar-Chu-Aff-Palm%20Classic-Round3.docx | null | 74,559 | NaCh | Diamond Bar NaCh | null | Na..... | Ch..... | null | null | 24,972 | DiamondBar | Diamond Bar | CA | null | 1,029 | hsld21 | HS LD 2021-22 | 2,021 | ld | hs | 1 |
1,589,933 | Yes scale-up for covid. | Erfani et al 21 | Erfani et al 21 [Parsa; Lawrence Gostin; Vanessa Kerry; Parsa Erfani is a Fogarty Global Health Scholar at Harvard Medical School and the University of Global Health Equity. Lawrence Gostin is a professor at Georgetown University Law Center, director of the school’s O’Neill Institute for National and Global Health Law, and director of the World Health Organization Center on National and Global Health Law. Vanessa Kerry is a critical care physician at Massachusetts General Hospital, director of the Program for Global Public Policy at Harvard Medical School, and CEO of Seed Global Health, a nonprofit that trains health workers in countries with critical shortages; “Beyond a symbolic gesture: What’s needed to turn the IP waiver into Covid-19 vaccines,” STAT; 5/19/21; https://www.statnews.com/2021/05/19/beyond-a-symbolic-gesture-whats-needed-to-turn-the-ip-waiver-into-covid-19-vaccines/] Justin | Currently many idle suppliers can’t begin vaccine production until they upgrade and repurpose existing manufacturing capacity for new technology. Opponents often argue that this step is the true barrier to rapid scale-up
This argument ignores two core truths: In many cases, manufacturing capacity needs only repurposing which can take mere months. And Covid-19, at the current global response and vaccination rates, will be a threat for years.
Both truths suggest that we pass the blueprint and build the kitchen.
Facilitating structures to transfer technology and capacity are already in place. The WHO launched the mRNA technology transfer hub model with the financial, training, and logistical support needed to scale up vaccine manufacturing capacity. Scores of manufacturers in these countries have already expressed interest. This initiative, however, requires recipient manufacturers to acquire the IP necessary for mRNA technologies— which is currently missing. | Opponents argue barrier scale-up
argument ignores manufacturing repurposing take months
structures in place. WHO launched mRNA transfer hub with financial, training logistical support to scale up manufacturers expressed interest. This requires IP which is missing | Currently many idle suppliers can’t begin vaccine production until they upgrade and repurpose existing manufacturing capacity for new technology. Opponents often argue that this step is the true barrier to rapid scale-up. One high-profile detractor, BIO President and CEO Michelle McMurry-Heath, argues that “handing [needy countries] the blueprint to construct a kitchen that — in optimal conditions — can take a year to build will not help us stop the emergence of dangerous new Covid variants.”
This argument ignores two core truths: In many cases, manufacturing capacity needs only repurposing which can take mere months. And Covid-19, at the current global response and vaccination rates, will be a threat for years.
Both truths suggest that we pass the blueprint and build the kitchen.
Facilitating structures to transfer technology and capacity are already in place. The WHO launched the mRNA technology transfer hub model last month to provide manufacturers in low- and middle-income countries with the financial, training, and logistical support needed to scale up vaccine manufacturing capacity. Scores of manufacturers in these countries have already expressed interest. This initiative, however, requires recipient manufacturers to acquire the IP necessary for mRNA technologies— which is currently missing. | 1,319 | <h4>Yes <u>scale-up</u> for covid.</h4><p><strong>Erfani et al 21</strong> [Parsa; Lawrence Gostin; Vanessa Kerry; Parsa Erfani is a Fogarty Global Health Scholar at Harvard Medical School and the University of Global Health Equity. Lawrence Gostin is a professor at Georgetown University Law Center, director of the school’s O’Neill Institute for National and Global Health Law, and director of the World Health Organization Center on National and Global Health Law. Vanessa Kerry is a critical care physician at Massachusetts General Hospital, director of the Program for Global Public Policy at Harvard Medical School, and CEO of Seed Global Health, a nonprofit that trains health workers in countries with critical shortages; “Beyond a symbolic gesture: What’s needed to turn the IP waiver into Covid-19 vaccines,” STAT; 5/19/21; https://www.statnews.com/2021/05/19/beyond-a-symbolic-gesture-whats-needed-to-turn-the-ip-waiver-into-covid-19-vaccines/] Justin</p><p><u>Currently many idle suppliers <strong>can’t begin vaccine production</strong> until they upgrade and <strong>repurpose existing manufacturing capacity</strong> for new technology. <mark>Opponents</mark> often <mark>argue</mark> that <strong>this step is the true <mark>barrier </mark>to rapid <mark>scale-up</u></strong></mark>. One high-profile detractor, BIO President and CEO Michelle McMurry-Heath, argues that “handing [needy countries] the blueprint to construct a kitchen that — in optimal conditions — can take a year to build will not help us stop the emergence of dangerous new Covid variants.”</p><p><u>This <mark>argument <strong>ignores</mark> two core truths</strong>: In many cases, <strong><mark>manufacturing</mark> capacity needs only <mark>repurposing</mark> which can <mark>take </mark>mere <mark>months</mark>. And Covid-19, at the current global response and vaccination rates, will be a threat for years.</p><p></strong>Both truths suggest that we <strong>pass the blueprint and build the kitchen.</p><p></strong>Facilitating <mark>structures </mark>to transfer technology and capacity are <strong>already <mark>in place</strong>.</mark> The <mark>WHO launched</mark> the <strong><mark>mRNA</mark> technology <mark>transfer hub</mark> model</u></strong> last month to provide manufacturers in low- and middle-income countries <u><mark>with</mark> the <strong><mark>financial, training</mark>, and <mark>logistical support</mark> needed</strong> <mark>to scale up</mark> vaccine manufacturing capacity. Scores of <mark>manufacturers </mark>in these countries have already <strong><mark>expressed interest</strong>. This</mark> initiative, however, <mark>requires</mark> recipient manufacturers to acquire <strong>the <mark>IP </mark>necessary for mRNA technologies— <mark>which is</mark> currently <mark>missing</mark>.</p></u></strong> | null | null | 1AC – Adv – Pandemics | 361,534 | 133 | 46,013 | ./documents/hsld21/StrakeJesuit/St/Strake%20Jesuit-Stuckert-Aff-Grapevine%20Classic-Round3.docx | 900,588 | A | Grapevine Classic | 3 | Harrison JP | Allison Aldridge | 1AC - Pandemics v2
1N - Black marxism K Case
1AR - All
2NR - K
2AR - Case Perm on K | hsld21/StrakeJesuit/St/Strake%20Jesuit-Stuckert-Aff-Grapevine%20Classic-Round3.docx | null | 75,375 | MiSt | Strake Jesuit MiSt | null | Mi..... | St..... | null | null | 25,176 | StrakeJesuit | Strake Jesuit | TX | null | 1,029 | hsld21 | HS LD 2021-22 | 2,021 | ld | hs | 1 |
1,024,842 | Violation – the aff changes a standard, topical affs must institute a per se violation. | Stevens 90 | John Paul Stevens 90, Justice, Supreme Court of the United States, “FTC v. Superior Court Trial Lawyers Ass'n,” 493 U.S. 411, Lexis | Appeals assumed that the per se rule prohibiting activity "is only a rule of 'administrative convenience and efficiency,' not a statutory command The per se rules are, of course, the product of judicial interpretations but nevertheless have the same force and effect as any other statutory commands while the per se rule is indeed justified in part by "administrative convenience," the Court of Appeals erred in describing the prohibition as justified only by such concerns. The per se rules reflect a long-standing judgment that prohibited practices by their nature have "a substantial potential for impact on competition."
the rule of reason in antitrust law generates
two complementary categories of antitrust analysis. In the first category are agreements whose nature and necessary effect are so plainly anticompetitive that no study is needed to establish their illegality -- they are 'illegal per se.' In the second category are agreements whose competitive effect can only be evaluated by analyzing the facts peculiar to the business, the history of the restraint, and the reasons why it was imposed
The per se rules in antitrust serve purposes analogous to per se restrictions upon stunt flying or speeding Perhaps most violations of such rules actually cause no harm many experienced drivers and pilots can operate much more safely, even at prohibited speeds, than the average citizen.
Yet the laws may nonetheless be enforced against these skilled persons without proof that their conduct was actually harmful or dangerous.
these per se rules are supported by the observation that every speeder and every stunt pilot poses some threat to the community | per se rules reflect a long-standing judgment that prohibited practices by their nature have potential impact on competition
agreements are so plainly anticompetitive that no study is needed to establish illegality 'illegal per se.'
Yet laws may be enforced without proof that conduct was harmful | LEdHN[3C] [3C]LEdHN[14] [14]Equally important is the second error implicit in respondents' claim to immunity from the per se rules. In its opinion, the Court of Appeals assumed that the antitrust laws permit, but do not require, the condemnation of price fixing and boycotts without proof of market power. 15 The opinion further assumed that the per se rule prohibiting such activity "is only a rule of 'administrative convenience and efficiency,' not a statutory command." 272 U.S. App. D. C., at 295, 856 F. 2d, at 249.This statement contains two errors. HN10 [****42] The per se [*433] rules are, of course, the product of judicial interpretations of the Sherman Act, but the rules nevertheless have the same force and effect as any other statutory commands. Moreover, while the per se rule against price fixing and boycotts is indeed justified in part by "administrative convenience," the Court of Appeals erred in describing the prohibition as justified only by such concerns. The per se rules also reflect a long-standing judgment that the prohibited practices by their nature have "a substantial potential for impact on competition." Jefferson Parish Hospital District No. 2 v. Hyde, 466 U.S. 2, 16 (1984).
[****43] LEdHN[15] [15]As we explained in Professional Engineers, HN11 the rule of reason in antitrust law generates
"two complementary categories of antitrust analysis. In the first category are agreements whose nature and necessary effect are so plainly anticompetitive that no elaborate study of the industry is needed to establish their illegality -- they are 'illegal per se.' In the second category are agreements whose competitive effect can only be evaluated by analyzing the facts peculiar to the business, the history of the restraint, and the reasons why it was imposed." 435 U.S., at 692.
[***873] "Once experience with a particular kind of restraint enables the Court to predict with confidence that the rule of reason will condemn it, it has applied a conclusive presumption that the restraint is unreasonable." Arizona v. Maricopa County Medical Society, 457 U.S. 332, 344 (1982).
[**781] LEdHN[16] [16] [****44] The per se rules in antitrust law serve purposes analogous to per se restrictions upon, for example, stunt flying in congested areas or speeding. Laws prohibiting stunt flying or setting speed limits are justified by the State's interest in protecting human life and property. Perhaps most violations of such rules actually cause no harm. No doubt many experienced drivers and pilots can operate much more safely, even at prohibited speeds, than the average citizen.
[*434] If the especially skilled drivers and pilots were to paint messages on their cars, or attach streamers to their planes, their conduct would have an expressive component. High speeds and unusual maneuvers would help to draw attention to their messages. Yet the laws may nonetheless be enforced against these skilled persons without proof that their conduct was actually harmful or dangerous.
In part, the justification for these per se rules is rooted in administrative convenience. They are also supported, however, by the observation that every speeder and every stunt pilot poses some threat to the community. An unpredictable event may overwhelm the skills of the best driver or pilot, even if the [****45] proposed course of action was entirely prudent when initiated. A bad driver going slowly may be more dangerous that a good driver going quickly, but a good driver who obeys the law is safer still. | 3,533 | <h4>Violation – the aff changes a standard, topical affs must institute a per se violation.</h4><p>John Paul <strong>Stevens 90</strong>, Justice, Supreme Court of the United States, “FTC v. Superior Court Trial Lawyers Ass'n,” 493 U.S. 411, Lexis</p><p>LEdHN[3C] [3C]LEdHN[14] [14]Equally important is the second error implicit in respondents' claim to immunity from the per se rules. In its opinion, the Court of <u>Appeals</u> <u><strong>assumed</u></strong> that the antitrust laws permit, but do not require, the condemnation of price fixing and boycotts without proof of market power. 15 The opinion further assumed <u>that the <strong>per se rule</strong> <strong>prohibiting</u></strong> such <u>activity "is only a rule of 'administrative convenience and efficiency,' <strong>not</strong> a <strong>statutory command</u></strong>." 272 U.S. App. D. C., at 295, 856 F. 2d, at 249.This statement contains two errors. HN10 [****42] <u>The per se</u> [*433] <u>rules are, of course, the product of <strong>judicial</strong> interpretations</u> of the Sherman Act, <u>but</u> the rules <u>nevertheless have the same force and effect as <strong>any other</strong> <strong>statutory</strong> commands</u>. Moreover, <u>while the per se rule</u> against price fixing and boycotts <u>is indeed <strong>justified</strong> in part by "administrative convenience," the Court of Appeals erred in describing the prohibition as justified</u> <u><strong>only</u></strong> <u>by such concerns. The <strong><mark>per se rules</u></strong></mark> also <u><mark>reflect a <strong>long-standing judgment</u></strong> <u>that</u></mark> the <u><strong><mark>prohibited practices</u></strong> <u>by their <strong>nature</u></strong> <u>have</mark> "a substantial <mark>potential</mark> for <mark>impact on competition</mark>."</u> Jefferson Parish Hospital District No. 2 v. Hyde, 466 U.S. 2, 16 (1984).</p><p> [****43] LEdHN[15] [15]As we explained in Professional Engineers, HN11 <u>the rule of reason in antitrust law generates</p><p></u>"<u>two complementary categories of antitrust analysis. In the first category are <strong><mark>agreements</strong></mark> whose nature and necessary effect <mark>are <strong>so plainly anticompetitive</u></strong> <u>that</u> <u><strong>no</u></strong></mark> elaborate <u><strong><mark>study</u></strong></mark> of the industry <u><mark>is needed to establish</mark> their <mark>illegality</mark> -- they are <mark>'illegal <strong>per se.'</u></strong></mark> <u>In the second category are agreements whose competitive effect can only be evaluated by analyzing the facts peculiar to the business, the history of the restraint, and the reasons why it was imposed</u>." 435 U.S., at 692.</p><p>[***873] "Once experience with a particular kind of restraint enables the Court to predict with confidence that the rule of reason will condemn it, it has applied a conclusive presumption that the restraint is unreasonable." Arizona v. Maricopa County Medical Society, 457 U.S. 332, 344 (1982).</p><p>[**781] LEdHN[16] [16] [****44] <u>The per se rules in <strong>antitrust</u></strong> law <u>serve purposes analogous to per se restrictions upon</u>, for example, <u><strong>stunt flying</u></strong> in congested areas <u>or</u> <u><strong>speeding</u></strong>. Laws prohibiting stunt flying or setting speed limits are justified by the State's interest in protecting human life and property. <u>Perhaps</u> <u><strong>most</u></strong> <u>violations of such rules <strong>actually</strong> cause <strong>no harm</u></strong>. No doubt <u>many</u> <u><strong>experienced</u></strong> <u>drivers and pilots can operate much more safely, even <strong>at prohibited speeds</strong>, than the average citizen.</p><p></u> [*434] If the especially skilled drivers and pilots were to paint messages on their cars, or attach streamers to their planes, their conduct would have an expressive component. High speeds and unusual maneuvers would help to draw attention to their messages. <u><mark>Yet</mark> the <mark>laws may</mark> nonetheless <mark>be <strong>enforced</strong></mark> against these skilled persons <strong><mark>without proof</strong> that</mark> their <mark>conduct was <strong></mark>actually <mark>harmful</mark> or dangerous</strong>.</p><p></u>In part, the justification for <u>these per se rules</u> is rooted in administrative convenience. They <u>are</u> also <u><strong>supported</u></strong>, however, <u>by the observation that every speeder and every stunt pilot poses <strong>some threat to the community</u></strong>. An unpredictable event may overwhelm the skills of the best driver or pilot, even if the [****45] proposed course of action was entirely prudent when initiated. A bad driver going slowly may be more dangerous that a good driver going quickly, but a good driver who obeys the law is safer still.</p> | 1NC R1 vs Wyoming-Columbia | Off | 1NC – T Prohibit | 330,179 | 146 | 24,730 | ./documents/ndtceda21/Trinity/NeMo/Trinity-Nelson-Moore-Neg-Wake-Round1.docx | 627,370 | N | Wake | 1 | WyomingColumbia LD | Case Harrigan | 1AC - Protection of Competition
1NC - adv cp ftc cp t prohibit doj da gangster antitrust da nationalization cp interest rates da case turns
2NR - adv cp and doj da | ndtceda21/Trinity/NeMo/Trinity-Nelson-Moore-Neg-Wake-Round1.docx | null | 52,906 | NeMo | Trinity NeMo | null | Ke..... | Ne..... | Ja..... | Mo..... | 19,421 | Trinity | Trinity | null | null | 1,011 | ndtceda21 | NDT/CEDA 2021-22 | 2,021 | cx | college | 2 |
1,154,448 | The affirmative is riddled with leftist melancholia – debate is a massive network of scholars, activists, policymakers, all of whom can and should orient their energy toward the production of a better world – the presumption that we should not challenge structures on the level of scope and scale with the resources that debate offers us is an explicit concession to fascism. Vote neg on presumption -- regardless of the benefits of their method for them, fragmented politics are fundamentally non-unique and non-inherent. | Hester 17 | Hester 17(Helen Hester is Associate Professor of Media and Communication at the University of West London. Her research interests include technofeminism, sexuality studies, and theories of social reproduction. She is a member of the international feminist collective Laboria Cuboniks. “Promethean Labors and Domestic Realism” 25 September 2017 http://www.e-flux.com/architecture/artificial-labor/140680/promethean-labors-and-domestic-realism/ rvs) | Stabile is amongst those who have been critical of an absence of systemic thinking within postmodern feminisms, remarking upon a “growing emphasis on fragmentations and single-issue politics.” Stabile dismisses this kind of thinking which, in “so resolutely avoiding ‘totalizing’ ignores or jettisons a structural analysis of capitalism.” The difference in scope and scale between that which is being opposed and the strategies being used to oppose it is generative of a sense of disempowerment. postmodern social theorists “accept the systemic nature of capitalism, as made visible in its consolidation of power and its global expansion Capitalism’s power as a system is therefore identified and named as a totality”; on the other hand, these theorists “celebrate local, fragmented, or partial forms of knowledge as the only forms of knowledge available” and criticize big-picture speculative thinking for its potentially oppressive tendencies or applications. The legacies of this kind of political theorizing are still being felt today, and continue to shape the perceived horizons of possibility for progressive projects. these projects are not sufficient as ends in themselves. operating via a diversity of means and across a variety of scales, they cannot serve as a suitable basis for any politics seeking to contest the imaginaries of the right or to contend with the expansive hegemonic project of neoliberal capitalism. politics based around the ideas that “the local is ethical, simpler is better, the organic is healthy, permanence is oppressive, and progress is over” is not always the best weapon in an attempt to contend with the complex technomaterial conditions of the world as it stands. There is a persistent kind of abstraction anxiety hanging over progressive politics; an anxiety that haunts a contemporary leftist feminism still unwilling or unable to critically reappraise the tendencies a renewed appetite for ambitious and future-oriented emancipatory politics has begun to make itself felt at the fringes of the left—and indeed, to gather momentum and popular support more broadly the most remarkable example of this tendency within philosophically-inflected political theory circles has been accelerationism, with its calls to build an “intellectual infrastructure” capable of “creating a new ideology, economic and social models, and a vision of the good to replace and surpass the emaciated ideals that rule our world today.” Wolfendale, meanwhile, sees it as a “politics of intervention”—one that starts from the insistence that nothing be exempted in advance from the enactment of re/visionary processes. | a “growing emphasis on fragmentations and single-issue politics. in avoiding ‘totalizing’ jettisons a structural analysis of capitalism The difference in scope between that which is being opposed and the strategies being used to oppose it is generative of disempowerment. Capitalism’s power is a totality on the other hand, these theorists “celebrate local, fragmented, or partial forms of knowledge as the only forms available” and criticize big-picture thinking for its potentially oppressive applications. they cannot serve as a suitable basis for any politics seeking to contest t the expansive hegemonic project of neoliberal capitalism. There is a persistent kind of abstraction anxiety hanging over progressive politics a renewed appetite for ambitious and future-oriented emancipatory politics has begun to make itself felt accelerationism, calls to build an “intellectual infrastructure” capable of “creating a new ideology, economic and social models, nothing be exempted in advance from the enactment of re/visionary processes | There has been an excess of modesty in the feminist agendas of recent decades. Carol A. Stabile is amongst those who have been critical of an absence of systemic thinking within postmodern feminisms, remarking upon a “growing emphasis on fragmentations and single-issue politics.”1 Stabile dismisses this kind of thinking which, in “so resolutely avoiding ‘totalizing’—the bête noire of contemporary critical theory—[…] ignores or jettisons a structural analysis of capitalism.”2 The difference in scope and scale between that which is being opposed and the strategies being used to oppose it is generative of a sense of disempowerment. On the one hand, Stabile argues, postmodern social theorists “accept the systemic nature of capitalism, as made visible in its consolidation of power and its global expansion […] Capitalism’s power as a system is therefore identified and named as a totality”; on the other hand, these theorists “celebrate local, fragmented, or partial forms of knowledge as the only forms of knowledge available” and criticize big-picture speculative thinking for its potentially oppressive tendencies or applications.3 Nancy Fraser, too, has addressed this apparent “shrinking of emancipatory vision at the fin de siècle,” linking this with “a major shift in the feminist imaginary” during the 1980s and 1990s—that is, with a move away from attempting to remake political economy (redistribution) and towards an effort at transforming culture (recognition).4 The legacies of this kind of political theorizing—legacies some might describe as “folk political”—are still being felt today, and continue to shape the perceived horizons of possibility for progressive projects.5 Yet these projects, which are frequently valuable, necessary, and effective on their own terms, are not sufficient as ends in themselves. To the extent that they are conceptualized in detachment from an ecology of other interventions, operating via a diversity of means and across a variety of scales, they cannot serve as a suitable basis for any politics seeking to contest the imaginaries of the right or to contend with the expansive hegemonic project of neoliberal capitalism. It is for this reason that Nick Srnicek and Alex Williams’s work positions itself as somewhat skeptical about fragmentations and single-issue politics, pointing out that problems such as “global exploitation, planetary climate change, rising surplus populations, [and] the repeated crises of capitalism are abstract in appearance, complex in structure, and non-localized.”6 As such, a politics based around the ideas that “the local is ethical, simpler is better, the organic is healthy, permanence is oppressive, and progress is over” is not always the best weapon in an attempt to contend with the complex technomaterial conditions of the world as it stands.7 There is a persistent kind of abstraction anxiety hanging over progressive politics; an anxiety that haunts a contemporary leftist feminism still unwilling or unable to critically reappraise the tendencies that Stabile identified in the 90s. Recently, however, a renewed appetite for ambitious and future-oriented emancipatory politics has begun to make itself felt at the fringes of the left—and indeed, to gather momentum and popular support more broadly.8 Perhaps the most remarkable example of this tendency within philosophically-inflected political theory circles has been accelerationism, with its calls to build an “intellectual infrastructure” capable of “creating a new ideology, economic and social models, and a vision of the good to replace and surpass the emaciated ideals that rule our world today.”9 These so-called “Promethean” ideas have generated widespread interest, arguably both reflecting and contributing to the changing tenor of activist discourse. Interestingly, this term has to some extent emerged in opposition to the pejorative “folk political,” acting as a shorthand for a very different set of values and perspectives. In a recent critical piece, Alexander Galloway suggests that “Prometheanism” could be defined as “technology for humans to overcome natural limit.”10 Peter Wolfendale, meanwhile, sees it as a “politics of intervention”—one that starts from the insistence that nothing be exempted in advance from the enactment of re/visionary processes.11 | 4,328 | <h4>The affirmative is riddled with leftist melancholia – debate is a massive network of scholars, activists, policymakers, all of whom can and should orient their energy toward the production of a better world – the presumption that we should not challenge structures on the level of scope and scale with the resources that debate offers us is an explicit concession to fascism. Vote neg on presumption -- regardless of the benefits of their method for them, fragmented politics are fundamentally non-unique and non-inherent. </h4><p><strong>Hester 17</strong>(Helen Hester is Associate Professor of Media and Communication at the University of West London. Her research interests include technofeminism, sexuality studies, and theories of social reproduction. She is a member of the international feminist collective Laboria Cuboniks. “Promethean Labors and Domestic Realism” 25 September 2017 http://www.e-flux.com/architecture/artificial-labor/140680/promethean-labors-and-domestic-realism/ rvs)</p><p>There has been an excess of modesty in the feminist agendas of recent decades. Carol A. <u>Stabile is amongst those who have been critical of an absence of systemic thinking within postmodern feminisms, remarking upon <mark>a “growing emphasis on fragmentations and single-issue politics.</mark>”</u>1 <u>Stabile dismisses this kind of thinking which, <mark>in</mark> “so resolutely <mark>avoiding ‘totalizing’</u></mark>—the bête noire of contemporary critical theory—[…] <u>ignores or <mark>jettisons a structural analysis of capitalism</mark>.”</u>2 <u><mark>The difference in scope</mark> and scale <mark>between that which is being opposed and the strategies being used to oppose it is generative of</mark> a sense of <mark>disempowerment. </u></mark>On the one hand, Stabile argues, <u>postmodern social theorists “accept the systemic nature of capitalism, as made visible in its consolidation of power and its global expansion</u> […] <u><mark>Capitalism’s power</mark> as a system <mark>is </mark>therefore identified and named as <mark>a totality</mark>”; <mark>on the other hand, these theorists “celebrate local, fragmented, or partial forms of knowledge as the only forms</mark> of knowledge <mark>available” and criticize big-picture</mark> speculative <mark>thinking for its potentially oppressive </mark>tendencies or <mark>applications.</u></mark>3 Nancy Fraser, too, has addressed this apparent “shrinking of emancipatory vision at the fin de siècle,” linking this with “a major shift in the feminist imaginary” during the 1980s and 1990s—that is, with a move away from attempting to remake political economy (redistribution) and towards an effort at transforming culture (recognition).4 <u>The legacies of this kind of political theorizing</u>—legacies some might describe as “folk political”—<u>are still being felt today, and continue to shape the perceived horizons of possibility for progressive projects.</u>5 Yet <u>these projects</u>, which are frequently valuable, necessary, and effective on their own terms, <u>are not sufficient as ends in themselves. </u>To the extent that they are conceptualized in detachment from an ecology of other interventions, <u>operating via a diversity of means and across a variety of scales, <mark>they cannot serve as a suitable basis for any politics seeking to contest t</mark>he imaginaries of the right or to contend with <mark>the expansive hegemonic project of neoliberal capitalism.</mark> </u>It is for this reason that Nick Srnicek and Alex Williams’s work positions itself as somewhat skeptical about fragmentations and single-issue politics, pointing out that problems such as “global exploitation, planetary climate change, rising surplus populations, [and] the repeated crises of capitalism are abstract in appearance, complex in structure, and non-localized.”6 As such, a<u> politics based around the ideas that “the local is ethical, simpler is better, the organic is healthy, permanence is oppressive, and progress is over” is not always the best weapon in an attempt to contend with the complex technomaterial conditions of the world as it stands.</u>7 <u><mark>There is a persistent kind of abstraction anxiety hanging over progressive politics</mark>; an anxiety that haunts a contemporary leftist feminism still unwilling or unable to critically reappraise the tendencies</u> that Stabile identified in the 90s. Recently, however, <u><mark>a renewed appetite for ambitious and future-oriented emancipatory politics has begun to make itself felt</mark> at the fringes of the left—and indeed, to gather momentum and popular support more broadly</u>.8 Perhaps <u>the most remarkable example of this tendency within philosophically-inflected political theory circles has been <mark>accelerationism,</mark> with its <mark>calls to build an “intellectual infrastructure” capable of “creating a new ideology, economic and social models,</mark> and a vision of the good to replace and surpass the emaciated ideals that rule our world today.”</u>9 These so-called “Promethean” ideas have generated widespread interest, arguably both reflecting and contributing to the changing tenor of activist discourse. Interestingly, this term has to some extent emerged in opposition to the pejorative “folk political,” acting as a shorthand for a very different set of values and perspectives. In a recent critical piece, Alexander Galloway suggests that “Prometheanism” could be defined as “technology for humans to overcome natural limit.”10 Peter <u>Wolfendale, meanwhile, sees it as a “politics of intervention”—one that starts from the insistence that <mark>nothing be exempted in advance from the enactment of re/visionary processes</mark>.</u>11</p> | 1NC | Off | 1NC – K | 51,696 | 243 | 28,416 | ./documents/hspolicy21/MinneapolisSouth/CoNi/Minneapolis%20South-Conry-Niblett-Neg-Berkeley-Round5.docx | 751,149 | N | Berkeley | 5 | Bell SJ | Dhruv Sudesh | 1AC - hydraulics
1NC - FW cap k
2NR - FW | hspolicy21/MinneapolisSouth/CoNi/Minneapolis%20South-Conry-Niblett-Neg-Berkeley-Round5.docx | null | 64,090 | CoNi | Minneapolis South CoNi | null | Cl..... | Co..... | An..... | Ni..... | 22,055 | MinneapolisSouth | Minneapolis South | MN | null | 1,020 | hspolicy21 | HS Policy 2021-22 | 2,021 | cx | hs | 2 |
1,168,558 | War with China causes extinction. | Starr 17 | Steven Starr 17, director of the University of Missouri's Clinical Laboratory Science Program and senior scientist at the Physicians for Social Responsibility, 1/9/2017, “Turning a Blind Eye Towards Armageddon—U.S. Leaders Reject Nuclear Winter Studies,” https://fas.org/2017/01/turning-a-blind-eye-towards-armageddon-u-s-leaders-reject-nuclear-winter-studies/, pacc | blast fire and radiation from 100 atomic bombs produce direct fatalities comparable to World War II the long-term environmental effects significantly disrupt global weather which would result in global famine
nuclear firestorms would cause black carbon smoke could not be rained out remain for more than a decade smoke absorb sunlight produc ozone losses would create UV-B indices unprecedented
smoke produce coldest temp s in 1,000 years global food production would decrease by 20 to 40 percent shortening of growing seasons and decreases in agricultural production cause two billion to perish from famine
war with U.S. and Russian nuclear weapons
colder than e height of the Ice Age rainfall decrease 90% Growing seasons would be completely eliminated for a decade it would be too cold and dark to grow food doom the human population
militarized confrontation with China
sleepwalking towards nuclear war | 100 bombs result in
firestorms cause black carbon could not be rained out for a decade absorb sunlight produc ozone losses
cold temp s shorten growing seasons two billion perish from famine
Growing seasons would be eliminated doom the population
confrontation with China
walking towards nuc war | The detonation of an atomic bomb with this explosive power will instantly ignite fires over a surface area of three to five square miles. In the recent studies, the scientists calculated that the blast, fire, and radiation from a war fought with 100 atomic bombs could produce direct fatalities comparable to all of those worldwide in World War II, or to those once estimated for a “counterforce” nuclear war between the superpowers. However, the long-term environmental effects of the war could significantly disrupt the global weather for at least a decade, which would likely result in a vast global famine.
The scientists predicted that nuclear firestorms in the burning cities would cause at least five million tons of black carbon smoke to quickly rise above cloud level into the stratosphere, where it could not be rained out. The smoke would circle the Earth in less than two weeks and would form a global stratospheric smoke layer that would remain for more than a decade. The smoke would absorb warming sunlight, which would heat the smoke to temperatures near the boiling point of water, producing ozone losses of 20 to 50 percent over populated areas. This would almost double the amount of UV-B reaching the most populated regions of the mid-latitudes, and it would create UV-B indices unprecedented in human history. In North America and Central Europe, the time required to get a painful sunburn at mid-day in June could decrease to as little as six minutes for fair-skinned individuals.
As the smoke layer blocked warming sunlight from reaching the Earth’s surface, it would produce the coldest average surface temperatures in the last 1,000 years. The scientists calculated that global food production would decrease by 20 to 40 percent during a five-year period following such a war. Medical experts have predicted that the shortening of growing seasons and corresponding decreases in agricultural production could cause up to two billion people to perish from famine.
The climatologists also investigated the effects of a nuclear war fought with the vastly more powerful modern thermonuclear weapons possessed by the United States, Russia, China, France, and England. Some of the thermonuclear weapons constructed during the 1950s and 1960s were 1,000 times more powerful than an atomic bomb.
nuclear-firestrom
During the last 30 years, the average size of thermonuclear or “strategic” nuclear weapons has decreased. Yet today, each of the approximately 3,540 strategic weapons deployed by the United States and Russia is seven to 80 times more powerful than the atomic bombs modeled in the India-Pakistan study. The smallest strategic nuclear weapon has an explosive power of 100,000 tons of TNT, compared to an atomic bomb with an average explosive power of 15,000 tons of TNT.
Strategic nuclear weapons produce much larger nuclear firestorms than do atomic bombs. For example, a standard Russian 800-kiloton warhead, on an average day, will ignite fires covering a surface area of 90 to 152 square miles.
A war fought with hundreds or thousands of U.S. and Russian strategic nuclear weapons would ignite immense nuclear firestorms covering land surface areas of many thousands or tens of thousands of square miles. The scientists calculated that these fires would produce up to 180 million tons of black carbon soot and smoke, which would form a dense, global stratospheric smoke layer. The smoke would remain in the stratosphere for 10 to 20 years, and it would block as much as 70 percent of sunlight from reaching the surface of the Northern Hemisphere and 35 percent from the Southern Hemisphere. So much sunlight would be blocked by the smoke that the noonday sun would resemble a full moon at midnight.
Under such conditions, it would only require a matter of days or weeks for daily minimum temperatures to fall below freezing in the largest agricultural areas of the Northern Hemisphere, where freezing temperatures would occur every day for a period of between one to more than two years. Average surface temperatures would become colder than those experienced 18,000 years ago at the height of the last Ice Age, and the prolonged cold would cause average rainfall to decrease by up to 90%. Growing seasons would be completely eliminated for more than a decade; it would be too cold and dark to grow food crops, which would doom the majority of the human population.
NUCLEAR WINTER IN BRIEF
The profound cold and darkness following nuclear war became known as nuclear winter and was first predicted in 1983 by a group of NASA scientists led by Carl Sagan. During the mid-1980s, a large body of research was done by such groups as the Scientific Committee on Problems of the Environment (SCOPE), the World Meteorological Organization, and the U.S. National Research Council of the U.S. National Academy of Sciences; their work essentially supported the initial findings of the 1983 studies.
The idea of nuclear winter, published and supported by prominent scientists, generated extensive public alarm and put political pressure on the United States and Soviet Union to reverse a runaway nuclear arms race, which, by 1986, had created a global nuclear arsenal of more than 65,000 nuclear weapons. Unfortunately, this created a backlash among many powerful military and industrial interests, who undertook an extensive media campaign to brand nuclear winter as “bad science” and the scientists who discovered it as “irresponsible.”
Critics used various uncertainties in the studies and the first climate models (which are primitive by today’s standards) as a basis to criticize and reject the concept of nuclear winter. In 1986, the Council on Foreign Relations published an article by scientists from the National Center for Atmospheric Research, who predicted drops in global cooling about half as large as those first predicted by the 1983 studies and described this as a “nuclear autumn.” The nuclear autumn studies were later shown to be deeply flawed, but the proof came too late to stop a massive smear campaign that effectively discredited the initial studies.
Nuclear winter was subject to criticism and damning articles in the Wall Street Journal and Time magazine. In 1987, the National Review called nuclear winter a “fraud.” In 2000, Discover Magazine published an article that described nuclear winter as one of “The Twenty Greatest Scientific Blunders in History.” The endless smear campaign was successful; the general public, and even most anti-nuclear activists, were left with the idea that nuclear winter had been scientifically disproved.
REJECTION BY LEADERS
Yet the scientists did not give up. In 2006, they returned to their labs to perform the research I have previously described. Their new research not only upheld the previous findings but also found that the earlier studies actually underestimated the environmental effects of nuclear war.
Dr. Robock of Rutgers and Dr. Toon of the University of Colorado have spent years attempting to bring official attention to their work and get follow-up research studies done by appropriate agencies in the federal government. In a recent (2016) interview, Dr. Toon stated:
The Department of Energy and the Department of Defense, which should be investigating this problem, have done absolutely nothing. They have not published a single paper, in the open literature, analyzing this problem … We have made a list of where we think the important issues are, and we have gone to every [federal] agency we can think of with these lists, and said “Don’t you think someone should study this?” Basically, everyone we have tried so far has said, “Well that’s not my job.”
In the same interview, Dr. Robock also noted:
The Department of Homeland Security really should fund this. They will fund you to study one terrorist bomb in New York City. When you explain to them that a war between India and Pakistan is a much greater threat to the U.S. homeland than one terrorist bomb, as horrible as that is, they respond with “Oh, well that’s not my job, go talk to some other program manager” — who, of course, doesn’t exist.
After the more recent series of studies were published in 2007 and 2008, Drs. Robock and Toon also made a number of requests to meet with members of the Obama administration. The scientists offered to brief Cabinet members and the White House staff about their findings, which they assumed would have a great impact upon nuclear weapons policy. Their offers were met with indifference.
Finally, after several years of trying, Drs. Robock and Toon were allowed an audience with John Holdren, Senior Advisor to President Barack Obama on Science and Technology. Dr. Robock also eventually met with Rose Gottemoeller, then Under Secretary of State for Arms Control and International Security. Dr. Robock has written to me that, after these meetings, he and Dr. Toon were left with the impression that neither Holdren nor Gottemoeller think the nuclear winter research “is correct.”
But it is not only Holdren and Gottemoeller who reject the nuclear winter research. Greg Mello, of the Los Alamos Study Group, cites a source who confirms that the group that determines the “full range of activities related to the development, production, maintenance (upkeep) and elimination (retirement, disassembly and disposal) of all United States nuclear weapons — the members of the U.S. Nuclear Weapons Council — have stated that “the predictions of nuclear winter were disproved years ago.”
The members of the U.S. Nuclear Weapons Council include:
Under Secretary of Defense for Acquisition, Technology, and Logistics
Vice Chairman of the Joint Chiefs of Staff
Under Secretary for Nuclear Security of the Department of Energy
Under Secretary of Defense for Policy
Commander of the United States Strategic Command
It is important to understand that some members of this group — especially the Commander of the U.S. Strategic Command (USSTRATCOM) — also develop the policies that guide the use of nuclear weapons.
Perhaps General John Hyten, Head of USSTRATCOM, who is in charge of the U.S. nuclear triad, and General Paul Selva, Vice Chairman of the Joint Chiefs of Staff, the second highest ranking officer in the United States, have never seen or heard of the 21st century nuclear winter studies. Perhaps when they hear a question about “nuclear winter,” they only remember the smear campaigns done against the early studies. Or, maybe, they just choose not to accept the new scientific research on nuclear winter, despite the fact that it has withstood the criticism of the global scientific community.
Regardless, the rejection of nuclear winter research by the top leaders of the United States raises some profoundly important questions: Do U.S. military and political leaders fully understand the consequences of nuclear war? Do they realize that even a “successful” nuclear first-strike against Russia could cause most Americans to die from nuclear famine?
In 2010, Drs. Toon and Robock wrote in Physics Today:
We estimate that the direct effects of using the 2012 arsenals would lead to hundreds of millions of fatalities. The indirect effects would likely eliminate the majority of the human population.
In 2013, Drs. Toon and Robock wrote in the Bulletin of Atomic Scientists that:
A nuclear war between Russia and the United States, even after the arsenal reductions planned under New START, could produce a nuclear winter. Hence, an attack by either side could be suicidal, resulting in Self-Assured Destruction.
RENEWED COLD WAR
Although president-elect Trump appears to favor a return to the policy of détente with Russia, many if not most U.S. political leaders appear to support the Obama administration’s policies of direct confrontation with Putin’s Russia. Mainstream corporate media, including the editorial boards of The New York Times and The Washington Post, routinely engage in anti-Russian and anti-Putin rhetoric that surpasses the hate speech of the McCarthy era. Under President Obama, the United States has renewed the Cold War with Russia, with little or no debate or protest, and has subsequently engaged in proxy wars with Russia in Ukraine and Syria, as well as threatening military action against China in the South China Sea.
In response to what NATO leaders describe as Russia’s “dangerous and aggressive actions,” NATO has built up a “rapid-response force” of 40,000 troops on the Russian border in the Baltic States and Poland. This force includes hundreds of tanks, armored vehicles, and heavy artillery. NATO troops stationed in Estonia are within artillery range of St. Petersburg, the second largest city of Russia.
The United States has deployed its Aegis Ashore Ballistic Missile Defense (BMD) system in Romania and is constructing another such BMD system in Poland. The Mark 41 launch system used in the Aegis Ashore systems can be used to launch a variety of missiles, including long-range nuclear-armed cruise missiles.
In other words, the United States has built and is building launch sites for nuclear missiles on the Russian border. This fact has been widely reported on Russian TV and has infuriated the Russian public. In June, Russian President Putin specifically warned that Russia would be forced to retaliate against this threat.
While Russian officials maintain that its actions are normal and routine, Russia now appears to be preparing for war. On October 5, 2016, Russia conducted a nation-wide civil defense drill that included 40 million of its people being directed to fallout shelters. Reuters reported two days later that Russia had moved its Iskander nuclear-capable missiles to Kaliningrad, which borders Poland.
While the United States ignores the danger of nuclear war, Russian scholar Stephen Cohen reports that the danger of war with the United States is the leading news story in Russia. Cohen states:
Just as there is no discussion of the most existential question of our time, in the American political class — the possibility of war with Russia — it is the only thing being discussed in the Russian political class . . . These are two different political universes. In Russia, all the discussion in the newspapers, and there is plenty of free discussion on talk show TV, which echoes what the Kremlin is thinking, online, in the elite newspapers, and in the popular broadcasts, the number 1, 2, 3, and 4 topics of the day are the possibility of war with the United States.
Cohen goes on to say:
I conclude from this that the leadership of Russia actually believes now, in reaction to what the United States and NATO have said and done over the last two years, and particularly in reaction to the breakdown of the proposed cooperation in Syria, and the rhetoric coming out of Washington, that war is a real possibility. I can’t remember when, since the Cuban Missile Crisis, that the Moscow leadership came to this conclusion in its collective head.
Perhaps this narrative will change under president-elect Trump. However, he is inheriting a situation fraught with danger, which retains the possibility of direct military conflict with Russia in Ukraine and Syria, as well as increasingly militarized confrontation with China in the South China Sea.
My own personal assessment of the state of the nuclear danger today is that it is profound. The United States is sleepwalking towards nuclear war. Our leaders have turned a blind eye to the scientifically predicted consequences of nuclear war, and our military appears to be intent on making “Russia back down.” This is a recipe for unlimited human disaster. | 15,580 | <h4>War with China causes <u>extinction</u>.</h4><p>Steven <strong>Starr 17</strong>, director of the University of Missouri's Clinical Laboratory Science Program and senior scientist at the Physicians for Social Responsibility, 1/9/2017, “Turning a Blind Eye Towards Armageddon—U.S. Leaders Reject Nuclear Winter Studies,” https://fas.org/2017/01/turning-a-blind-eye-towards-armageddon-u-s-leaders-reject-nuclear-winter-studies/, pacc </p><p>The detonation of an atomic bomb with this explosive power will instantly ignite fires over a surface area of three to five square miles. In the recent studies, the scientists calculated that the <u><strong>blast</u></strong>, <u><strong>fire</u></strong>, <u>and <strong>radiation</strong> from</u> a war fought with <u><strong><mark>100</mark> atomic <mark>bombs</u></strong></mark> could <u>produce direct fatalities comparable to</u> all of those worldwide in <u><strong>World War II</u></strong>, or to those once estimated for a “counterforce” nuclear war between the superpowers. However, <u>the <strong>long-term environmental effects</u></strong> of the war could <u>significantly disrupt</u> the <u><strong>global weather</u></strong> for at least a decade, <u>which would</u> likely <u><mark>result in</u></mark> a vast <u><strong>global famine</u></strong>.</p><p>The scientists predicted that <u><strong>nuclear <mark>firestorms</u></strong></mark> in the burning cities <u>would <mark>cause</u></mark> at least five million tons of <u><strong><mark>black carbon</mark> smoke</u></strong> to quickly rise above cloud level into the stratosphere, where it <u><mark>could <strong>not</strong> be <strong>rained out</u></strong></mark>. The smoke would circle the Earth in less than two weeks and would form a global stratospheric smoke layer that would <u>remain <mark>for</mark> <strong>more than <mark>a decade</u></strong></mark>. The <u>smoke</u> would <u><mark>absorb</u></mark> warming <u><strong><mark>sunlight</u></strong></mark>, which would heat the smoke to temperatures near the boiling point of water, <u><mark>produc</u></mark>ing <u><strong><mark>ozone losses</u></strong></mark> of 20 to 50 percent over populated areas. This would almost double the amount of UV-B reaching the most populated regions of the mid-latitudes, and it <u>would create <strong>UV</strong>-B indices <strong>unprecedented</u></strong> in human history. In North America and Central Europe, the time required to get a painful sunburn at mid-day in June could decrease to as little as six minutes for fair-skinned individuals.</p><p>As the <u>smoke</u> layer blocked warming sunlight from reaching the Earth’s surface, it would <u>produce</u> the <u><strong><mark>cold</mark>est</u></strong> average surface <u><strong><mark>temp</u></strong></mark>erature<u><strong><mark>s</strong></mark> in</u> the last <u>1,000 years</u>. The scientists calculated that <u><strong>global food production</strong> would decrease by 20 to 40 percent</u> during a five-year period following such a war. Medical experts have predicted that the <u><strong><mark>shorten</mark>ing of <mark>growing seasons</strong></mark> and</u> corresponding <u>decreases in <strong>agricultural production</u></strong> could <u>cause</u> up to <u><strong><mark>two billion</u></strong></mark> people <u>to <mark>perish from <strong>famine</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>The climatologists also investigated the effects of a nuclear war fought with the vastly more powerful modern thermonuclear weapons possessed by the United States, Russia, China, France, and England. Some of the thermonuclear weapons constructed during the 1950s and 1960s were 1,000 times more powerful than an atomic bomb.</p><p>nuclear-firestrom</p><p>During the last 30 years, the average size of thermonuclear or “strategic” nuclear weapons has decreased. Yet today, each of the approximately 3,540 strategic weapons deployed by the United States and Russia is seven to 80 times more powerful than the atomic bombs modeled in the India-Pakistan study. The smallest strategic nuclear weapon has an explosive power of 100,000 tons of TNT, compared to an atomic bomb with an average explosive power of 15,000 tons of TNT.</p><p>Strategic nuclear weapons produce much larger nuclear firestorms than do atomic bombs. For example, a standard Russian 800-kiloton warhead, on an average day, will ignite fires covering a surface area of 90 to 152 square miles.</p><p>A <u>war</u> fought <u>with</u> hundreds or thousands of <u><strong>U.S. and Russian</u></strong> strategic <u><strong>nuclear weapons</u></strong> would ignite immense nuclear firestorms covering land surface areas of many thousands or tens of thousands of square miles. The scientists calculated that these fires would produce up to 180 million tons of black carbon soot and smoke, which would form a dense, global stratospheric smoke layer. The smoke would remain in the stratosphere for 10 to 20 years, and it would block as much as 70 percent of sunlight from reaching the surface of the Northern Hemisphere and 35 percent from the Southern Hemisphere. So much sunlight would be blocked by the smoke that the noonday sun would resemble a full moon at midnight.</p><p>Under such conditions, it would only require a matter of days or weeks for daily minimum temperatures to fall below freezing in the largest agricultural areas of the Northern Hemisphere, where freezing temperatures would occur every day for a period of between one to more than two years. Average surface temperatures would become <u><strong>colder</strong> than</u> those experienced 18,000 years ago at th<u>e height of the</u> last <u><strong>Ice Age</u></strong>, and the prolonged cold would cause average <u><strong>rainfall</u></strong> to <u>decrease</u> by up to <u>90%</u>. <u><strong><mark>Growing seasons</strong> would be</mark> <strong>completely <mark>eliminated</strong></mark> for</u> more than <u>a decade</u>; <u>it would be <strong>too cold</strong> and <strong>dark</strong> to grow food</u> crops, which would <u><mark>doom</u></mark> the majority of <u><strong><mark>the</mark> human <mark>population</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>NUCLEAR WINTER IN BRIEF</p><p>The profound cold and darkness following nuclear war became known as nuclear winter and was first predicted in 1983 by a group of NASA scientists led by Carl Sagan. During the mid-1980s, a large body of research was done by such groups as the Scientific Committee on Problems of the Environment (SCOPE), the World Meteorological Organization, and the U.S. National Research Council of the U.S. National Academy of Sciences; their work essentially supported the initial findings of the 1983 studies.</p><p>The idea of nuclear winter, published and supported by prominent scientists, generated extensive public alarm and put political pressure on the United States and Soviet Union to reverse a runaway nuclear arms race, which, by 1986, had created a global nuclear arsenal of more than 65,000 nuclear weapons. Unfortunately, this created a backlash among many powerful military and industrial interests, who undertook an extensive media campaign to brand nuclear winter as “bad science” and the scientists who discovered it as “irresponsible.”</p><p>Critics used various uncertainties in the studies and the first climate models (which are primitive by today’s standards) as a basis to criticize and reject the concept of nuclear winter. In 1986, the Council on Foreign Relations published an article by scientists from the National Center for Atmospheric Research, who predicted drops in global cooling about half as large as those first predicted by the 1983 studies and described this as a “nuclear autumn.” The nuclear autumn studies were later shown to be deeply flawed, but the proof came too late to stop a massive smear campaign that effectively discredited the initial studies.</p><p>Nuclear winter was subject to criticism and damning articles in the Wall Street Journal and Time magazine. In 1987, the National Review called nuclear winter a “fraud.” In 2000, Discover Magazine published an article that described nuclear winter as one of “The Twenty Greatest Scientific Blunders in History.” The endless smear campaign was successful; the general public, and even most anti-nuclear activists, were left with the idea that nuclear winter had been scientifically disproved.</p><p>REJECTION BY LEADERS</p><p>Yet the scientists did not give up. In 2006, they returned to their labs to perform the research I have previously described. Their new research not only upheld the previous findings but also found that the earlier studies actually underestimated the environmental effects of nuclear war.</p><p>Dr. Robock of Rutgers and Dr. Toon of the University of Colorado have spent years attempting to bring official attention to their work and get follow-up research studies done by appropriate agencies in the federal government. In a recent (2016) interview, Dr. Toon stated:</p><p>The Department of Energy and the Department of Defense, which should be investigating this problem, have done absolutely nothing. They have not published a single paper, in the open literature, analyzing this problem … We have made a list of where we think the important issues are, and we have gone to every [federal] agency we can think of with these lists, and said “Don’t you think someone should study this?” Basically, everyone we have tried so far has said, “Well that’s not my job.”</p><p>In the same interview, Dr. Robock also noted:</p><p>The Department of Homeland Security really should fund this. They will fund you to study one terrorist bomb in New York City. When you explain to them that a war between India and Pakistan is a much greater threat to the U.S. homeland than one terrorist bomb, as horrible as that is, they respond with “Oh, well that’s not my job, go talk to some other program manager” — who, of course, doesn’t exist.</p><p>After the more recent series of studies were published in 2007 and 2008, Drs. Robock and Toon also made a number of requests to meet with members of the Obama administration. The scientists offered to brief Cabinet members and the White House staff about their findings, which they assumed would have a great impact upon nuclear weapons policy. Their offers were met with indifference.</p><p>Finally, after several years of trying, Drs. Robock and Toon were allowed an audience with John Holdren, Senior Advisor to President Barack Obama on Science and Technology. Dr. Robock also eventually met with Rose Gottemoeller, then Under Secretary of State for Arms Control and International Security. Dr. Robock has written to me that, after these meetings, he and Dr. Toon were left with the impression that neither Holdren nor Gottemoeller think the nuclear winter research “is correct.”</p><p>But it is not only Holdren and Gottemoeller who reject the nuclear winter research. Greg Mello, of the Los Alamos Study Group, cites a source who confirms that the group that determines the “full range of activities related to the development, production, maintenance (upkeep) and elimination (retirement, disassembly and disposal) of all United States nuclear weapons — the members of the U.S. Nuclear Weapons Council — have stated that “the predictions of nuclear winter were disproved years ago.”</p><p>The members of the U.S. Nuclear Weapons Council include:</p><p>Under Secretary of Defense for Acquisition, Technology, and Logistics</p><p>Vice Chairman of the Joint Chiefs of Staff</p><p>Under Secretary for Nuclear Security of the Department of Energy</p><p>Under Secretary of Defense for Policy</p><p>Commander of the United States Strategic Command</p><p>It is important to understand that some members of this group — especially the Commander of the U.S. Strategic Command (USSTRATCOM) — also develop the policies that guide the use of nuclear weapons.</p><p>Perhaps General John Hyten, Head of USSTRATCOM, who is in charge of the U.S. nuclear triad, and General Paul Selva, Vice Chairman of the Joint Chiefs of Staff, the second highest ranking officer in the United States, have never seen or heard of the 21st century nuclear winter studies. Perhaps when they hear a question about “nuclear winter,” they only remember the smear campaigns done against the early studies. Or, maybe, they just choose not to accept the new scientific research on nuclear winter, despite the fact that it has withstood the criticism of the global scientific community.</p><p>Regardless, the rejection of nuclear winter research by the top leaders of the United States raises some profoundly important questions: Do U.S. military and political leaders fully understand the consequences of nuclear war? Do they realize that even a “successful” nuclear first-strike against Russia could cause most Americans to die from nuclear famine?</p><p>In 2010, Drs. Toon and Robock wrote in Physics Today:</p><p>We estimate that the direct effects of using the 2012 arsenals would lead to hundreds of millions of fatalities. The indirect effects would likely eliminate the majority of the human population.</p><p>In 2013, Drs. Toon and Robock wrote in the Bulletin of Atomic Scientists that:</p><p>A nuclear war between Russia and the United States, even after the arsenal reductions planned under New START, could produce a nuclear winter. Hence, an attack by either side could be suicidal, resulting in Self-Assured Destruction.</p><p>RENEWED COLD WAR</p><p>Although president-elect Trump appears to favor a return to the policy of détente with Russia, many if not most U.S. political leaders appear to support the Obama administration’s policies of direct confrontation with Putin’s Russia. Mainstream corporate media, including the editorial boards of The New York Times and The Washington Post, routinely engage in anti-Russian and anti-Putin rhetoric that surpasses the hate speech of the McCarthy era. Under President Obama, the United States has renewed the Cold War with Russia, with little or no debate or protest, and has subsequently engaged in proxy wars with Russia in Ukraine and Syria, as well as threatening military action against China in the South China Sea.</p><p>In response to what NATO leaders describe as Russia’s “dangerous and aggressive actions,” NATO has built up a “rapid-response force” of 40,000 troops on the Russian border in the Baltic States and Poland. This force includes hundreds of tanks, armored vehicles, and heavy artillery. NATO troops stationed in Estonia are within artillery range of St. Petersburg, the second largest city of Russia.</p><p>The United States has deployed its Aegis Ashore Ballistic Missile Defense (BMD) system in Romania and is constructing another such BMD system in Poland. The Mark 41 launch system used in the Aegis Ashore systems can be used to launch a variety of missiles, including long-range nuclear-armed cruise missiles.</p><p>In other words, the United States has built and is building launch sites for nuclear missiles on the Russian border. This fact has been widely reported on Russian TV and has infuriated the Russian public. In June, Russian President Putin specifically warned that Russia would be forced to retaliate against this threat.</p><p>While Russian officials maintain that its actions are normal and routine, Russia now appears to be preparing for war. On October 5, 2016, Russia conducted a nation-wide civil defense drill that included 40 million of its people being directed to fallout shelters. Reuters reported two days later that Russia had moved its Iskander nuclear-capable missiles to Kaliningrad, which borders Poland.</p><p>While the United States ignores the danger of nuclear war, Russian scholar Stephen Cohen reports that the danger of war with the United States is the leading news story in Russia. Cohen states:</p><p>Just as there is no discussion of the most existential question of our time, in the American political class — the possibility of war with Russia — it is the only thing being discussed in the Russian political class . . . These are two different political universes. In Russia, all the discussion in the newspapers, and there is plenty of free discussion on talk show TV, which echoes what the Kremlin is thinking, online, in the elite newspapers, and in the popular broadcasts, the number 1, 2, 3, and 4 topics of the day are the possibility of war with the United States.</p><p>Cohen goes on to say:</p><p>I conclude from this that the leadership of Russia actually believes now, in reaction to what the United States and NATO have said and done over the last two years, and particularly in reaction to the breakdown of the proposed cooperation in Syria, and the rhetoric coming out of Washington, that war is a real possibility. I can’t remember when, since the Cuban Missile Crisis, that the Moscow leadership came to this conclusion in its collective head.</p><p>Perhaps this narrative will change under president-elect Trump. However, he is inheriting a situation fraught with danger, which retains the possibility of direct military conflict with Russia in Ukraine and Syria, as well as increasingly <u><strong>militarized <mark>confrontation with China</u></strong></mark> in the South China Sea.</p><p>My own personal assessment of the state of the nuclear danger today is that it is profound. The United States is <u>sleep<mark>walking towards <strong>nuc</mark>lear <mark>war</u></strong></mark>. Our leaders have turned a blind eye to the scientifically predicted consequences of nuclear war, and our military appears to be intent on making “Russia back down.” This is a recipe for unlimited human disaster.</p> | 1AC | 1AC---SDGs | 1AC---China | 11,696 | 1,360 | 28,671 | ./documents/hspolicy21/MontgomeryBell/HeMa/Montgomery%20Bell-Herrmann-Maxwell-Aff-Glenbrooks-Round7.docx | 751,265 | A | Glenbrooks | 7 | Barstow AP | Stephen Lowe | 1AC - SDGs
2NR - Setcol | hspolicy21/MontgomeryBell/HeMa/Montgomery%20Bell-Herrmann-Maxwell-Aff-Glenbrooks-Round7.docx | null | 64,100 | HeMa | Montgomery Bell HeMa | null | Ge..... | He..... | As..... | Ma..... | 22,058 | MontgomeryBell | Montgomery Bell | TN | null | 1,020 | hspolicy21 | HS Policy 2021-22 | 2,021 | cx | hs | 2 |
4,074,872 | Job Lock specifically true for Tech Entrepreneurs. | Aggarwal et Al 13 | Aggarwal et Al 13, Raj, Krisztina'Z. Holly, and Vivek Wadhwa. "Health insurance availability and entrepreneurship." Journal of Developmental Entrepreneurship 18.04 (2013): 1350025. (Sullivan Professor of Finance and International Business & Dean at the College of Business Administration at the University of Akron)//Elmer | among “Valleys of Death” an entrepreneur must cross before commercial success the lack of health insurance may be the first and one of the most daunting. Like other such studies based on secondary data, they do not address the motivations of actual entrepreneurs or what types of potential entrepreneurs may be deterred from entrepreneurship–they only indirectly estimate the aggregate outcomes regarding the impact of health care availability on entrepreneurs, and of course, these reported outcomes may result from many causes. The company founders came from a variety of industries including aerospace and defense, computer and electronics, healthcare and services but were highly concentrated in technology sectors with 77 percent indicating their current company made computer hardware/software or other forms of technology products and services. Other sectors included biotech, medical, military and other (non-technology). Our results are very strong and significant and provide fresh insights into the role of health insurance on entrepreneurs. We document that the lack of health insurance has a strong and significant inhibiting impact on U.S. entrepreneurs. This paper also documents that the importance of health insurance availability increases for entrepreneurs that are self-funded, married, have children, are from less privileged backgrounds and are in advanced stages of their lives as indicated by having advanced degrees or long work experience when they become entrepreneurs. based on primary data from a representative sample of high technology companies founders are older experienced and married with children who often have more than one college degree The most frequent source of funding used in these business start-ups was personal savings supplemented by investments from friends and family | among “Valleys of Death” an entrepreneur must cross before commercial success the lack of health insurance may be the most daunting. The founders highly concentrated in technology sectors 77 percent indicating computer hardware Other sectors included biotech, medical Our results are very strong and significant lack of health insurance has significant inhibiting impact on U.S. entrepreneurs. This paper also documents that the importance of health insurance availability increases based on primary data from a representative sample of high technology companies founders are older experienced | Introduction It has been contended in the popular press that the difficulty in obtaining affordable health insurance inhibits or prevents entrepreneurship in the United States.a Given the importance of health insurance in modern times, among the many “Valleys of Death” an entrepreneur must cross before commercial success, the lack of health insurance may be the first and one of the most daunting. Entrepreneurship is important for economic growth, innovation and employment; therefore, it seems important to investigate any possible negative effects the lack of availability of health insurance has on entrepreneurs. Unfortunately, there are only a few research studies on the subject and they do not seem to agree on the impact of the lack of health insurance on U.S. entrepreneurship. Holtz-Eakin et al. (1996) contend that a lack of health insurance does not impact entrepreneurship. In contrast, the two other published studies on this topic, Wellington (2001) and Fairlie et al. (2011), document significant negative impacts of the lack of health insurance on entrepreneurship, as does the unpublished report (DeCicca, 2010). Thus, it seems existing studies do not agree and it appears we do not know enough about the impact of the lack of health insurance on entrepreneurship. The data used in these prior studies are all generally from the early- to mid-1990s. In addition, a recent (2013) study by the Urban Institute, again using secondary macro-economic data (more details in footnote 4), also contends that the lack of health care insurance has an inhibiting impact on entrepreneurship (Blumberg et al., 2013). All of these studies rely on secondary data that may only indirectly represent the actual conditions on the ground among entrepreneurs. Like other such studies based on secondary data, they do not address the motivations of actual entrepreneurs or what types of potential entrepreneurs may be deterred from entrepreneurship–they only indirectly estimate the aggregate outcomes regarding the impact of health care availability on entrepreneurs, and of course, these reported outcomes may result from many causes. Given the lack of agreement among prior studies and the secondary nature of data used by them, a new study that takes a different approach may be illuminating and contribute to a better understanding of the impact of health insurance on U.S. entrepreneurship. We contend there is much need to assess the impact more directly by collecting and analyzing primary data from entrepreneurs about the importance and impact of health insurance. This paper does exactly that and fills this gap in the literature by examining the impact based on primary data from a recent, large and representative survey of such entrepreneurs. This paper documents that the difficulty of obtaining affordable health insurance has a significant inhibiting impact on U.S. entrepreneurs.b It also documents that the impact of the lack of health insurance on inhibiting entrepreneurs is stronger for older and married entrepreneurs. This inhibiting effect is also stronger for entrepreneurs with children and from poorer socio-economic backgrounds. We place these results in a broader context by summarizing the self-reported socio-economic background of entrepreneurs; thus, providing a fresh portrait of entrepreneurs different from popular and media stereotypes. As an example, unlike popular mythology, we find most entrepreneurs start their businesses later in life (on average in their forties) after they have gained some work experience. These results should be of much interest to scholars and policymakers. The rest of the paper is organized as follows. The next section provides a brief overview of the literature on entrepreneurship and its relationship to health insurance culminating in a set of hypotheses followed by the section on data and the research methodology. This is followed by a discussion regarding the results, and finally a concluding section 2. Health Insurance and Entrepreneurship 2.1. Role and scope of entrepreneurship Generally, although entrepreneurship is considered important for economic growth, it is not clearly defined and well-integrated with economic or managerial theory. Endres and Woods (2006) identify at least three major theoretical perspectives on entrepreneurship; the neoclassical entrepreneur who is a risk bearing utility maximizer who contributes to a general equilibrium in the supply and demand for firms, the ‘Austrian School’ entrepreneur who is specially alert to opportunities, and the behavioral school entrepreneur who is a decision maker with explicit cognitive limits. Somewhat as a result of these different definitions, the study of entrepreneurship and the study of economic organization lack interaction. In fact, the modern theory of the firm virtually ignores entrepreneurship, while the literature on entrepreneurship often sees little value in the economic theory of the firm (Foss et al., 2011). Analysis of entrepreneurship and business formation has also been hindered by the lack of an agreed upon acceptable theoretical framework. One challenge is that entrepreneurship bridges a number of fields of study. For example, entrepreneurship connects the macro and micro perspectives in economics. In the macroeconomic perspective, entrepreneurship is considered an important process facilitating rejuvenation in Schumpeterian creative destruction where inefficient businesses go bankrupt while others rise up in their place (Schumpeter, 1934). In the microeconomic perspective, the growth of new businesses includes the entrepreneurial process (Kirzner, 1979) as well as the growth of a firm (Penrose, 1959). The personal-psychological aspects of entrepreneurship and entrepreneurs as risk takers have long been recognized as important (McClelland, 1961). Entrepreneurship is particularly risky because it involves creating a new enterprise and taking on the liability of newness (Stinchcombe, 1965). Consequently, entrepreneurship connects well to management theory and it is noted that it requires superior human capital. Many theoretical and empirical studies have demonstrated the importance of knowledge and experience in enabling firms to successfully implement and adapt to changes in technology (Bartel and Lichtenberg, 1987; Davidsson and Honig, 2003; Koellinger, 2008). These studies share in common an underlying assumption, based on human capital theory (Becker, 1964), that employees with more human capital (in the form of education and experience) are more productive than comparable employees in high technology, entrepreneurial firms and industries. As this very brief review above illustrates, entrepreneurship spans many large and important areas of study. Perhaps, because of this, despite the vast existing literature on entrepreneurship, much remains to be learned (DeNardi and Villamil, 2009). For example, Carsrud and Brännback (2011) note that we know relatively little about the motivations of entrepreneurs. We do know that entrepreneurship results from a risky occupational choice. The view of entrepreneurs as primary risk-takers is deeply rooted in the “Knightian” tradition, which views entrepreneurs as ultimately bearing the economic risk of failure (Ilmakunnas and Kanniainen, 2001).c This ability and/or need of entrepreneurs to bear risk make them a central part of the Shumpeterian process of creative destruction, a process essential for economic progress. Thus, there is much interest in entrepreneurship and its role in the economy. Entrepreneurs and innovators are considered very important for economic growth and job creation, especially because newly formed and small businesses are the engines that create most new jobs. This is especially true in this century because large companies are not new job creators. In an analysis of global entrepreneurship patterns Lerner (2010) emphasizes the importance of entrepreneurship in economic growth and notes that public policy can be very important in promoting and facilitating entrepreneurship. As Lerner (2010) implies, there can be many obstacles to entrepreneurship. For example, Klappera et al. (2006) show that regulatory requirements can act as entry barriers, thereby limiting entrepreneurship. Similarly, Beck and Demirguc-Kunt (2006) show that the small and medium enterprise (SME) contribution to economic growth is likely limited by obstacles in access to finance and that appropriate public policy can mitigate these negative effects. Blanchflower and Oswald (1998) and Kerr and Nanda (2011) also make the same points about entrepreneurship being limited by financing constraints. Consequently, there is also much interest in the nature of public policy, which is best suited to encourage job creation and new business formation by reducing or removing obstacles that may deter entrepreneurship. Thus, entrepreneurship is a topic that has important policy implications, especially because policy can remove or reduce the effects of obstacles to entrepreneurship. This paper contributes to the literature on entrepreneurship and explores the deterrent role of one such set of obstacles, health care insurance. 2.2. Health care insurance and entrepreneurship In the United States, health care is provided by private providers who are paid either by private health insurance companies or by the government. Most large employers provide private health insurance to their employees with the employees contributing significant portions of the costs. Indeed, in modern times health insurance has come to be considered a basic requirement almost like food and shelter. Changing employers usually means changing health insurance providers and this change has been shown to deter job mobility in the United States (Gruber and Madrian, 1994). Further, this heavy reliance on employerprovided health insurance also likely acts as a deterrent to entrepreneurship. Concerns that health insurance costs and availability are “killing new-business dreams” (Keen, 2005) and that they bias and distort employment choices against start-ups (Leonhardt, 2009; Baumol et al., 2007) have been voiced for several years. Indeed, the availability of health insurance is likely to be an important determinant of entrepreneurship. As is well known, private health insurance is expensive and sometimes unavailable (especially for the self-employed) and a majority of working-aged Americans obtain health insurance coverage as a benefit offered by their employers (Fronstin, 2004). Conditional on working for an employer that offers health insurance, it is generally agreed that individual coverage is more difficult to obtain and more expensive than equivalent group coverage, due in large part to possible adverse selection (common in the insurance markets). For example, potential adverse selection leads insurers in the individual market to engage in medical underwriting, a process by which they attempt to gather information on the “riskiness” of applicants. Based on such information, insurers may attach riders or other exclusions on existing health conditions; rate an applicant as “substandard,” resulting in higher premiums or in outright denial of coverage. Because individuals who leave jobs with employer-sponsored coverage must eventually forfeit their coverage, the higher costs associated with individual policies, coupled with potential difficulty (or impossibility) in obtaining or maintaining coverage, may discourage job mobility (see, for example, Buchmueller and Valletta, 1996; Cooper and Monheit, 1993; Gruber and Madrian, 1994; Madrian, 1994b). Such health insurance related immobility may be especially binding for individuals who face relatively high experience-rated premiums in the non-group market (e.g., individuals healthy enough to work but considered “bad risks” by health insurers) and individuals who lack existing alternative sources of coverage (e.g., unmarried individuals, those ineligible for government-sponsored health insurance, etc.). Finally, it should be noted that certain individuals, like those with long-term chronic health problems or those who anticipate poor future health, may sort into employment that offers access to group health insurance relatively early in their working lives. Clearly, it is reasonable to expect that similar considerations influence the impact of health insurance availability on entrepreneurship with the consequence that the lack of affordable health insurance is likely to discourage entrepreneurship. Lack of health insurance is likely to deter entrepreneurship for a number of reasons. First, given the high potential costs of illness and medical treatment, most people are highly averse to foregoing health insurance. Further, the heavy reliance on employerprovided health insurance especially acts as a deterrent to entrepreneurship because it is harder to self-insure against more persistent shocks and the welfare cost of missing consumption insurance increases with shock persistence (Buera and Shin, 2011). Second, entrepreneurship is generally considered riskier than working for an employer. The lack of health insurance for self employed and entrepreneurs just adds another layer of extra financial and business risk–with this extra risk pushing many over the edge into foregoing entrepreneurship. These health insurance issues have taken on a new salience with the passage of the Patient Protection and Affordable Care Act of 2010 (PPACA). PPACA mandates that, starting in 2014, all U.S. citizens and residents, other than those under incarceration and those exempted for religious reasons, must ensure they have at least minimum health care coverage. Individuals without coverage for themselves and their dependents will be levied a penalty for each month they fail to have coverage. Under PPACA, states will create “exchanges” where individual consumers can purchase insurance, and insurers will not be able to apply pre-existing condition exclusions and price premiums based on health status. According to initial macro-economic estimates that confirm the importance of health insurance for entrepreneurship, these features of PPACA can potentially weaken the negative impact of health insurance on entrepreneurship.d However, PPACA exempts existing health plans from these regulations allowing the problem to persist for some time (Eibner et al., 2010). 2.3. Empirical evidence of health insurance impact on entrepreneurship Surprisingly, despite a strong and continuing interest in the nature and determinants of entrepreneurship, scholars have devoted relatively little attention to the role health insurance availability plays in the entrepreneurial decisions. This lack of attention is especially surprising in the context of several studies on the influence of health insurance availability on job mobility. Fortunately, there seem to be a few published studies on the topic of health insurance and entrepreneurship. Using secondary panel data from the early 1990s, Holtz-Eakin et al. (1996) examine the impact of health insurance on the transition from traditional employment to selfemployment. In particular, they compare the characteristics of individuals who transition from traditional to self-employment with their counterparts who remained wage earners. They find that health insurance portability had no systematic effect on this transition. However, again using secondary economic data from the early 1990s, Wellington (2001) estimates the impact of health insurance availability through a spouse on the probability of self-employment. She finds the availability of health insurance could increase self-employment by between 2 and 3.5 percent. Fairlie et al. (2011), hereafter known as FKG, provides an interesting approach to estimating the impact of health insurance on entrepreneurship. They compare business formation rates among those just under age 65 to those who are just over age 65 and find there is a significant jump in new business formation among those who are just above age 65. Their interpretation of this finding is that this jump is attributable to the availability of Medicare, and that a lack of other than employer provided health insurance is a deterrent to entrepreneurship. Finally, in an unpublished study, DeCicca (2010), using data on the 1993 implementation of a community health insurance program in New Jersey, estimated that self-employment went up significantly especially among the unmarried (by as much as 14–20 percent compared to reference groups) as a result of this guaranteed availability of health insurance. These prior studies on the impact of health insurance on entrepreneurship provide indirect, albeit sometimes very strong, evidence based on secondary economic data of the hypothesized negative effect of the lack of health insurance on entrepreneurship. This paper takes a somewhat different approach and provides more direct evidence supporting these prior conclusions, but based in this study on the analysis of data collected directly from entrepreneurs. Although such data also has some disadvantages, it nevertheless adds value because it provides a different perspective. Thus, this paper makes an important contribution to our understanding of the relationship between entrepreneurship and health insurance. 2.4. Hypotheses Clearly, the impact of the difficulty of obtaining affordable health insurance on entrepreneurs is more meaningful for individuals who do not work for others and lack alternatives to their own employer-sponsored health insurance coverage. One may also expect a greater negative impact on entrepreneurs who would otherwise have more difficulty obtaining health insurance. One example of such a group is unmarried entrepreneurs. Although married entrepreneurs typically are eligible for group health insurance offered by a spouse’s employer, unmarried individuals generally do not have this option. Similarly, the lack of health insurance is likely to be more important for older entrepreneurs with children and for those from less fortunate socio-economic backgrounds. To test these possibilities, we assess the impact of the health insurance on entrepreneurship as it varies by marital status, socio-economic background and other entrepreneur characteristics. Thus, we hypothesize that: H1: The difficulty of obtaining health insurance is an important deterring factor considered by entrepreneurs in becoming entrepreneurs. H2a: The importance of the difficulty of obtaining of health insurance as an entrepreneurship deterrent depends on the marital status of the entrepreneur. H2b: The difficulty of obtaining health insurance as an entrepreneurship deterrent is stronger for entrepreneurs with children. H3: The difficulty of obtaining health insurance as an entrepreneurship deterrent is stronger for entrepreneurs who have fewer other means and are of lower socio-economic status. 3. Data and Methodology Prior studies in this area have been based on the analysis of secondary economic and demographic data. In contrast, this paper is based on primary data collected by a team of researchers at Duke University in a 2009 survey of entrepreneurial company founders.e The surveyed sample consisted of company founders listed in the data base, One Source, randomized and stratified by industry and region of the United States. The researchers visited the websites of these companies to make sure the company was still in operation and to obtain names and contact information of founders. The guidelines that were provided for defining a “founder” was an early employee, typically joining the company in its first year, before the company developed its products and perfected its business model. The founders were asked detailed questions about their backgrounds, motivations and experiences in launching companies. The founders were also asked to categorize their companies by industry. The researchers then contacted company founders through email and requested they complete a brief online survey consisting of a series of questions about their own personal and family backgrounds as well as their views on and motivations toward starting a business. As follow ups, our team of researchers sent up to four unsolicited reminder emails to these founders. In some cases where necessary, the e-mails were followed up with phone calls. Of the founders who could be reached, it is estimated that approximately 40 percent completed the survey and five hundred and forty nine respondents took part in the survey. Five hundred and ten (or 92.9%) of these respondents answered all of the questions asked. Our sample is representative of U.S. entrepreneurs as a chi-square analysis of the regional and industry distributions of our sample and the complete OneSource list indicated no significant differences. The company founders came from a variety of industries including aerospace and defense, computer and electronics, healthcare and services but were highly concentrated in technology sectors with 77 percent indicating their current company made computer hardware/software or other forms of technology products and services. Other sectors included biotech, medical, military and other (non-technology). Although this survey can be generalized to the entire population of tech entrepreneurs in the United States, it is more reliable if it is considered to be illustrative of the backgrounds of entrepreneurs in high growth industries (because a significant proportion of the company founders focused on such industries). Unfortunately, like most research in this area, the results are affected by a survivorship bias, in that we are only able to reach entrepreneurs whose companies were still in existence. Nevertheless, this survey has yielded a unique and important primary data set that is particularly valuable because prior studies in this area have relied on secondary data. Analysis of this unusual primary data set done in this study can provide a fresh and unique perspective, new insights and an independent confirmation (or refutation) of prior findings. 4. Empirical Findings This nation-wide survey of company founders used an extensive questionnaire and yielded a rich trove of primary data about entrepreneurs. In this paper we focus on how entrepreneurship is influenced by the availability of health insurance. However, as a start we also provide a brief overview of the other findings of this survey to form the backdrop to our findings on the impact of health insurance on entrepreneurship (these findings are not published but are available in the working papers of Wadhwa et al. (2009a,b) 4.1. General background of entrepreneurs As a start, it is interesting to note here briefly, that the widely held stereotype of an entrepreneur (at least as portrayed in the media) is that of a recent college graduate or a college drop-out living a monastic life, sleeping in the office and going to a venture capitalist for start-up funds. Further this stereotype seems to include the fact that such an individual has rarely worked for other companies or other people. However, this stereotype is really a caricature and is not even true according the findings from this survey. The average entrepreneur or founder of a fast-growing technology or knowledge industry company is middle-aged, married, has children and worked for many years at a company or for someone else before branching out and starting his or her own business. Company founders tend to be middle-aged, well-educated and did better in high-school than in college. The average and median age of company founders when they started their current company was 40 years. 95.1 percent of the founders had earned Bachelor’s degrees and 47 percent had more advanced degrees.f Most had significant industry experience when starting their companies. The majority of respondents (75 percent) had worked as an employee at a company for more than six years before launching their own company and nearly half (48 percent) launched their first company with more than ten years of work experience. Significant percentages of respondents started their first company after working for someone else for 11–15 years (23%), 16–20 years (14 percent), or greater than 20 years (10 percent). Company founders tend to come from middle-class backgrounds, are better educated and more entrepreneurial than their parents. 72 percent of the founders came from middle class backgrounds and less than 1 percent came from extremely rich or extremely poor backgrounds. The fathers of 50 percent of the company founders held bachelors or advanced degrees as did 34 percent of the mothers. The average birth order of respondents in their family was 2.2 and the average number of siblings was 3.1. More than half (52%) of respondents were the first in their family to launch a business but 39 percent, 7 percent and 15 percent respectively had a father, mother or siblings who had previously started businesses. Most founders were married and had children and 70 percent of respondents indicated they were married when they launched their first business. Furthermore, 60 percent indicated they had at least one child when they launched their first business while 44 percent had two or more children. We asked company founders to rank the importance of a series of factors on the success of their most recent startups and to tell us what other factors were important. 96 percent ranked prior work experience as an important success factor with 58 percent ranking this as extremely important. 88 percent said that learning from previous successes and 78 percent said that learning from previous failures played an important role in their present successes. 40 percent said lessons from failures were extremely important. 82 percent said their management team was important to their success and 35 percent said this was extremely important. 73 percent said good fortune was an important factor in their success and 22 percent ranked this as extremely important. 70 percent said their university education was important. Ivy-league graduates valued this more, with 86 percent indicating this was important. Only 19 percent believed university or alumni networks were important but of the Ivy-league graduates, 29 percent ranked these as important. 73 percent said professional networks were important to the success of their current business and 62 percent of respondents felt the same way about personal networks. 68 percent of the overall sample considered availability of financing/capital as important. Of the entrepreneurs who received advice or assistance from their company’s investors, only 36 percent ranked it as important, 38 percent saying that it was not at all important. The vast majority (86%) of entrepreneurs ranked the assistance provided by the state or region as not at all or slightly important. Company founders were also asked to provide an opinion on the factors that may prevent others from starting their own business. We wanted to understand the barriers potential entrepreneurs may face from the perspective of those who had already faced these. The factor ranked as important most commonly—by 98 percent—was lack of willingness or of ability to take risks, 50 percent believing this to be an extremely important barrier to entrepreneurship. This clearly indicates these company founders considered entrepreneurship to be a risky endeavor. Regarding barriers, among company founders, 92 percent said the amount of time and effort required, 89 percent said business management skills, 84 percent said knowledge of how to start a business, 83 percent said knowledge about the industry and markets, and 73 percent believed family or financial pressures to keep a traditional, steady job. Further, 91 percent said difficulty in raising capital was an important inhibitor. The most significant source of funding for all businesses was their personal savings with 70 percent saying they had used personal savings as a main source of funding for their first business. Even in subsequent startups, more than half of the entrepreneurs relied on their personal savings. Venture capital and private/angel investments play a relatively small role in the startups of first-time entrepreneurs and only 11 percent received venture capital and 9 percent received angel financing for their first startups. But the percentage who took venture and angel funding increased with subsequent business launches, with 26 percent and 22 percent respectively of entrepreneurs’ most recent startups receiving such funding. Friends and family provided funding for 16 percent and banks provided funding for another 16 percent, while corporate investments played the major role in 7 percent of the startups. Thus, in summary, entrepreneurial company founders are generally in their 40s or 50s and are not bachelors (72.5% of entrepreneurs were married when they launched their first venture). Further, 61.1 percent of respondents indicated they had at least one child when they launched their first business. Many entrepreneurs are first-born (around 42%), but second- and later-borns are in the majority. Most entrepreneurs are not from wealthy backgrounds either with about 71 percent of our entrepreneurs coming from middle class backgrounds and a majority of them coming from lower-middle and mid-middle class backgrounds. A majority of company founders (53%) were found to be the first ones in their family to launch a business. Less than half of the parents of respondents had college or advanced degrees. More than three-quarters of the entrepreneurs we surveyed had worked for someone else for at least six years before launching their businesses. In contrast to the importance of venture capital in the media, reflecting the findings of other studies the most significant source of funding for the businesses started by respondents was their personal savings. In our surveys, 70 percent said they had used personal savings as a main source of funding for their first business, more than four times the number for any other category. Even in subsequent start ups, more than half of the entrepreneurs relied on their personal savings. Friends, family or bank loans were a source of funding for approximately 13 to 16 percent of our sample. Just 10.8 percent received venture capital, and 9.2 percent received angel financing.g The main obstacle entrepreneurs reported was lack of knowledge about starting a business, and fear of failure and its aftermath. As this brief review of the overall findings indicates, the findings of this survey paint a picture of an entrepreneur who is quite different from the widely held stereotypes. This survey also provides important new details of the backgrounds of company founders. Consequently, these findings have important policy implications for encouraging entrepreneurship, an important issue, given that the vast majority of new jobs in the United States are created by small new companies. 4.2. Health insurance and entrepreneurs 4.2.1. Importance of health insurance The surveyed entrepreneurs were asked two questions related to health insurance and its importance for the entrepreneurial decision. The first asked them about the importance of access to health insurance in their decision to become entrepreneurs. The second, a follow up, asked them about the importance of the challenges posed by the possible lack of health insurance. Figure 1 summarizes their responses. As the results presented in Panel A of Figure 1 indicate, a vast majority (88%) of the responding entrepreneurs indicated the availability of health insurance was an important factor in their decision to become entrepreneurs with only 12 percent indicating this was not a factor. This evidence is strong support for our first hypothesis. Further, as Panel B of Figure 1 indicates, the availability of health insurance was not only a factor in the entrepreneurial decision, it was a challenge (meaning a significant obstacle to be overcome) for about half the entrepreneurs. Overall, as expected, the availability of health insurance seems to be an important factor in the decision to become an entrepreneur. 4.2.2. Health insurance and entrepreneur marital status The marital status of an entrepreneur seems to make an important difference when it comes to the importance of health insurance. Responses to both the importance of access to health insurance in the decision to become an entrepreneur and the challenges posed by the possible lack of health insurance questions were cross tabulated with the entrepreneur’s marital status (almost all, 508 out of 540, or 94 percent, of the responders provided this information). Figure 2 summarizes the responses for single versus married respondents As these responses indicate in Panel A of Figure 2, the importance of losing health insurance was a somewhat more important factor in the entrepreneurial decision for married entrepreneurs. 89.2 percent of married entrepreneurs felt it was an important factor as compared to 86.2 percent of single entrepreneurs. However, this difference is not statistically significant (Z ¼ 0:98, p ¼ 33%). Yet, as the results shown in Panel B of Figure 2 indicate, the differences between single and married entrepreneurs were somewhat more important in terms of the challenges posed by the lack of health insurance. 50.4 percent of married entrepreneurs felt a lack of health insurance was a challenge versus only 45.4 percent of the single entrepreneurs; this difference is statistically significant at a better than two percent level (Z ¼ 1:47, p ¼ 1:4%). This evidence supports our hypothesis 2a. As the results in Figure 2 show, as can be expected, the availability of health insurance is a more significant challenge for married entrepreneurs. 4.2.3. Health insurance and entrepreneurs with children Analysis of the importance of the availability of health insurance for the entrepreneurial decision for those with children is presented in Figure 3. As the results presented in this exhibit for entrepreneurs with (296) and without (197) children indicate, a slightly higher proportion of those with children (88.85%) express concern about health insurance as compared to those without children (87.31%). However, these differences are not statistically significant (Z ¼ 1:54, p ¼ 60:4%). Similarly, analysis of the importance of the challenge of the lack of health insurance for the entrepreneur for those with (303) and without (202) children, indicates a higher proportion of those with children (54.13%) express concern about health insurance as compared to those without children (45.05%). However, these differences are again not statistically significant (Z ¼ 1:00, p ¼ 31%). The results regarding the impact of the number of children on entrepreneurship are presented in Figure 3 and we see that the differences discussed above become significant. For entrepreneurs with three or more children find the lack of health insurance is significant in the entrepreneurial decision. This evidence supports our hypothesis 2b. Panel B of Figure 4 shows the impact of health insurance on entrepreneurship by those with varying number of children. As this figure shows, the impact of health insurance on the entrepreneurial decision clearly increases in importance as the number of children increase. 4.2.4. Health insurance and entrepreneur socio-economic background Figure 4 presents results regarding the impact of the self-classified socio-economic background of the entrepreneur on the importance of health insurance. As these results show, entrepreneurs from less privileged backgrounds (below the upper middle class) were significantly more likely to consider health insurance in making their entrepreneurial decision (Z ¼ 1:84, p ¼ 6:7%).h Similarly, entrepreneurs from less privileged backgrounds were significantly more likely to consider health insurance to be a challenge (Z ¼ 2:73, p ¼ 0:7%). This evidence is strong support for our third hypothesis. A more detailed analysis of the impact of socio-economic background on the role of health insurance in the entrepreneurial decision is presented in Panel B of Figure 4. As this data show, the role of health insurance in the entrepreneurial decision increases in importance as the socio-economic background of an entrepreneur declines. 4.2.5. Health insurance and other entrepreneur characteristics The first entrepreneur characteristic we examined for impact on the importance of health care for the entrepreneurial decision was the nature of funding used for the first venture founded by the entrepreneur. As the data in Panel A of Figure 5 show, analysis of the importance of the availability of health insurance for the entrepreneurship decision between entrepreneurs with (277) and those without (219) outside institutional funding indicates a higher proportion of those with self funding (87.21%) express concern about health insurance as compared to those with outside funding (85.49%). However, these differences are not statistically significant (Z ¼ 0:67, p ¼ 50%). Similarly, analysis of the importance of the challenge of the lack of health insurance for the entrepreneur for those with (285) outside institutional funding and those with self funding (223), indicates a higher proportion of those with self funding (55.16%) express concern about health insurance as compared to those with outside funding (46.67%) with these differences being statistically significant (Z ¼1.90, p ¼ 5:8%). Next, we examine the role of education in moderating the impact of health insurance availability on entrepreneurship. The results are shown in Panel B of Figure 5. As these results indicate, all entrepreneurs thought the availability of health insurance is an important factor in the entrepreneurial decision, entrepreneurs with advanced (graduate) degrees were less likely to think so than those with a bachelor’s degree or less education. These differences were statistically significant (Z ¼ 2:93, p ¼ 0:4%). Similarly, all entrepreneurs thought the availability of health insurance is an important challenge for entrepreneurs, but entrepreneurs with just a bachelor’s degree or less education were significantly more likely to think so than those with advanced college degrees (Z ¼ 3:52, p ¼ 0:0%). Analysis of the self-reported performance in college on the importance of health insurance for entrepreneurs is presented in Panel C of Figure 5. As these results show, entrepreneurs with above average performance in college were slightly less likely to consider health insurance to be important but these differences were not statistically significant (Z ¼ 0:58, p ¼ 56:4%). However, entrepreneurs with lower self-reported performance in college were significantly more likely to consider health insurance to be a continuing challenge (Z ¼ 1:82, p ¼ 7:0%). The analysis of the role of prior work experience on the importance of health insurance is presented in Panel D of Figure 5. As these results show, entrepreneurs with ten or more years of work experience prior to starting their business were significantly more likely to consider health insurance in making their entrepreneurial decision (Z ¼ 1:98, p ¼ 4:9%). Similarly, entrepreneurs with long prior work experience were somewhat more likely to consider health insurance to be a challenge but the difference was not statistically significant (Z ¼ 1:07, p ¼ 28:5%). 4.2.6. Discussion Overall, the results presented here show that health insurance is an important factor in the entrepreneurial decision and has been a continuing challenge for entrepreneurs. The importance of health insurance availability increases for entrepreneurs who are self-funded, married, have children, are from less privileged backgrounds and are in advanced stages of their lives as indicated by having advanced degrees or long work experience when they become entrepreneurs. These results are important for not only understanding the nature of entrepreneurship but also for formulating public policy in this area, especially because entrepreneurship is perhaps the most important source of job creation and economic growth in the United States and other countries. Thus, public policy that improves the availability of health insurance for the self-employed is likely to pay large and significant dividends in the form of economic growth and job creation. To encourage and facilitate entrepreneurship in the United States and other countries, we recommend that, for example, health insurance reform should make it easier for the self-employed to obtain health insurance. Fortunately, steps are already being taken by the United States and many other governments to make progress in this regard. 5. Conclusions Concern has long been expressed that lack of appropriate health insurance alternatives has deterred entrepreneurship. In spite of the interest in this topic, there are few direct studies based on primary data of the impact of a lack of health insurance alternatives for the self employed. This concern has become more salient with recent changes such as the political and legal challenges to the new health care bill (PPACA) signed into law by President Obama. This paper examines the role of health insurance availability on U.S. entrepreneurs. Unlike prior studies that have analyzed secondary data, this paper uses a unique primary data set from a representative, recent survey of entrepreneurs to complement and supplement the results of prior studies. Given that prior studies in this area have mostly relied on macroeconomic and demographic secondary data, analysis of this unusual primary data set provides an opportunity for a fresh and unique perspective, new insights and an independent confirmation (or refutation) of prior findings based on secondary data. Our results are very strong and significant and provide fresh insights into the role of health insurance on entrepreneurs. We document that the lack of health insurance has a strong and significant inhibiting impact on U.S. entrepreneurs. This paper also documents that the importance of health insurance availability increases for entrepreneurs that are self-funded, married, have children, are from less privileged backgrounds and are in advanced stages of their lives as indicated by having advanced degrees or long work experience when they become entrepreneurs. Generally, entrepreneurs are deterred from company formation and job creation by the lack of access to health insurance. This paper also reports on the backgrounds of company founders based on primary data collected in a survey directly from a representative sample of founders of high technology companies. The results show that most company founders are not young college drop-outs but are generally older, experienced and married with children who often have more than one college degree. The most frequent source of funding used in these business start-ups was personal savings supplemented by investments from friends and family. This summary of the self-reported socio-economic background of entrepreneurs provides a fresh portrait that is different from popular and media stereotypes. The results presented here are important for not only understanding the nature of entrepreneurship but also for formulating public policy in this area. It has been widely noted that entrepreneurship is perhaps the most important source of jobs and economic growth in the United States and other economies. Thus, anything that can be done to improve the availability of health insurance for entrepreneurs is likely to pay large and significant dividends in the form of economic growth and job creation. To encourage and facilitate entrepreneurship in the United States and other countries, we recommend that, for example, health insurance reform should make it easier for the self-employed to get health insurance. Fortunately, steps are already being taken by the United States and other governments to make progress in this regard. | 44,071 | <h4>Job Lock specifically true for <u>Tech Entrepreneurs</u>.</h4><p><strong>Aggarwal et Al 13</strong>, Raj, Krisztina'Z. Holly, and Vivek Wadhwa. "Health insurance availability and entrepreneurship." Journal of Developmental Entrepreneurship 18.04 (2013): 1350025. (Sullivan Professor of Finance and International Business & Dean at the College of Business Administration at the University of Akron)//Elmer</p><p>Introduction It has been contended in the popular press that the difficulty in obtaining affordable health insurance inhibits or prevents entrepreneurship in the United States.a Given the importance of health insurance in modern times, <u><strong><mark>among</u></strong></mark> the many <u><strong><mark>“Valleys of Death” an entrepreneur must cross before commercial success</u></strong></mark>, <u><strong><mark>the lack of health insurance may be the</u></strong></mark> <u>first and one of the</u> <u><strong><mark>most daunting.</u></strong></mark> Entrepreneurship is important for economic growth, innovation and employment; therefore, it seems important to investigate any possible negative effects the lack of availability of health insurance has on entrepreneurs. Unfortunately, there are only a few research studies on the subject and they do not seem to agree on the impact of the lack of health insurance on U.S. entrepreneurship. Holtz-Eakin et al. (1996) contend that a lack of health insurance does not impact entrepreneurship. In contrast, the two other published studies on this topic, Wellington (2001) and Fairlie et al. (2011), document significant negative impacts of the lack of health insurance on entrepreneurship, as does the unpublished report (DeCicca, 2010). Thus, it seems existing studies do not agree and it appears we do not know enough about the impact of the lack of health insurance on entrepreneurship. The data used in these prior studies are all generally from the early- to mid-1990s. In addition, a recent (2013) study by the Urban Institute, again using secondary macro-economic data (more details in footnote 4), also contends that the lack of health care insurance has an inhibiting impact on entrepreneurship (Blumberg et al., 2013). All of these studies rely on secondary data that may only indirectly represent the actual conditions on the ground among entrepreneurs. <u>Like other such studies based on secondary data, they do not address the motivations of actual entrepreneurs or what types of potential entrepreneurs may be deterred from entrepreneurship–they only indirectly estimate the aggregate outcomes regarding the impact of health care availability on entrepreneurs, and of course, these reported outcomes may result from many causes.</u> Given the lack of agreement among prior studies and the secondary nature of data used by them, a new study that takes a different approach may be illuminating and contribute to a better understanding of the impact of health insurance on U.S. entrepreneurship. We contend there is much need to assess the impact more directly by collecting and analyzing primary data from entrepreneurs about the importance and impact of health insurance. This paper does exactly that and fills this gap in the literature by examining the impact based on primary data from a recent, large and representative survey of such entrepreneurs. This paper documents that the difficulty of obtaining affordable health insurance has a significant inhibiting impact on U.S. entrepreneurs.b It also documents that the impact of the lack of health insurance on inhibiting entrepreneurs is stronger for older and married entrepreneurs. This inhibiting effect is also stronger for entrepreneurs with children and from poorer socio-economic backgrounds. We place these results in a broader context by summarizing the self-reported socio-economic background of entrepreneurs; thus, providing a fresh portrait of entrepreneurs different from popular and media stereotypes. As an example, unlike popular mythology, we find most entrepreneurs start their businesses later in life (on average in their forties) after they have gained some work experience. These results should be of much interest to scholars and policymakers. The rest of the paper is organized as follows. The next section provides a brief overview of the literature on entrepreneurship and its relationship to health insurance culminating in a set of hypotheses followed by the section on data and the research methodology. This is followed by a discussion regarding the results, and finally a concluding section 2. Health Insurance and Entrepreneurship 2.1. Role and scope of entrepreneurship Generally, although entrepreneurship is considered important for economic growth, it is not clearly defined and well-integrated with economic or managerial theory. Endres and Woods (2006) identify at least three major theoretical perspectives on entrepreneurship; the neoclassical entrepreneur who is a risk bearing utility maximizer who contributes to a general equilibrium in the supply and demand for firms, the ‘Austrian School’ entrepreneur who is specially alert to opportunities, and the behavioral school entrepreneur who is a decision maker with explicit cognitive limits. Somewhat as a result of these different definitions, the study of entrepreneurship and the study of economic organization lack interaction. In fact, the modern theory of the firm virtually ignores entrepreneurship, while the literature on entrepreneurship often sees little value in the economic theory of the firm (Foss et al., 2011). Analysis of entrepreneurship and business formation has also been hindered by the lack of an agreed upon acceptable theoretical framework. One challenge is that entrepreneurship bridges a number of fields of study. For example, entrepreneurship connects the macro and micro perspectives in economics. In the macroeconomic perspective, entrepreneurship is considered an important process facilitating rejuvenation in Schumpeterian creative destruction where inefficient businesses go bankrupt while others rise up in their place (Schumpeter, 1934). In the microeconomic perspective, the growth of new businesses includes the entrepreneurial process (Kirzner, 1979) as well as the growth of a firm (Penrose, 1959). The personal-psychological aspects of entrepreneurship and entrepreneurs as risk takers have long been recognized as important (McClelland, 1961). Entrepreneurship is particularly risky because it involves creating a new enterprise and taking on the liability of newness (Stinchcombe, 1965). Consequently, entrepreneurship connects well to management theory and it is noted that it requires superior human capital. Many theoretical and empirical studies have demonstrated the importance of knowledge and experience in enabling firms to successfully implement and adapt to changes in technology (Bartel and Lichtenberg, 1987; Davidsson and Honig, 2003; Koellinger, 2008). These studies share in common an underlying assumption, based on human capital theory (Becker, 1964), that employees with more human capital (in the form of education and experience) are more productive than comparable employees in high technology, entrepreneurial firms and industries. As this very brief review above illustrates, entrepreneurship spans many large and important areas of study. Perhaps, because of this, despite the vast existing literature on entrepreneurship, much remains to be learned (DeNardi and Villamil, 2009). For example, Carsrud and Brännback (2011) note that we know relatively little about the motivations of entrepreneurs. We do know that entrepreneurship results from a risky occupational choice. The view of entrepreneurs as primary risk-takers is deeply rooted in the “Knightian” tradition, which views entrepreneurs as ultimately bearing the economic risk of failure (Ilmakunnas and Kanniainen, 2001).c This ability and/or need of entrepreneurs to bear risk make them a central part of the Shumpeterian process of creative destruction, a process essential for economic progress. Thus, there is much interest in entrepreneurship and its role in the economy. Entrepreneurs and innovators are considered very important for economic growth and job creation, especially because newly formed and small businesses are the engines that create most new jobs. This is especially true in this century because large companies are not new job creators. In an analysis of global entrepreneurship patterns Lerner (2010) emphasizes the importance of entrepreneurship in economic growth and notes that public policy can be very important in promoting and facilitating entrepreneurship. As Lerner (2010) implies, there can be many obstacles to entrepreneurship. For example, Klappera et al. (2006) show that regulatory requirements can act as entry barriers, thereby limiting entrepreneurship. Similarly, Beck and Demirguc-Kunt (2006) show that the small and medium enterprise (SME) contribution to economic growth is likely limited by obstacles in access to finance and that appropriate public policy can mitigate these negative effects. Blanchflower and Oswald (1998) and Kerr and Nanda (2011) also make the same points about entrepreneurship being limited by financing constraints. Consequently, there is also much interest in the nature of public policy, which is best suited to encourage job creation and new business formation by reducing or removing obstacles that may deter entrepreneurship. Thus, entrepreneurship is a topic that has important policy implications, especially because policy can remove or reduce the effects of obstacles to entrepreneurship. This paper contributes to the literature on entrepreneurship and explores the deterrent role of one such set of obstacles, health care insurance. 2.2. Health care insurance and entrepreneurship In the United States, health care is provided by private providers who are paid either by private health insurance companies or by the government. Most large employers provide private health insurance to their employees with the employees contributing significant portions of the costs. Indeed, in modern times health insurance has come to be considered a basic requirement almost like food and shelter. Changing employers usually means changing health insurance providers and this change has been shown to deter job mobility in the United States (Gruber and Madrian, 1994). Further, this heavy reliance on employerprovided health insurance also likely acts as a deterrent to entrepreneurship. Concerns that health insurance costs and availability are “killing new-business dreams” (Keen, 2005) and that they bias and distort employment choices against start-ups (Leonhardt, 2009; Baumol et al., 2007) have been voiced for several years. Indeed, the availability of health insurance is likely to be an important determinant of entrepreneurship. As is well known, private health insurance is expensive and sometimes unavailable (especially for the self-employed) and a majority of working-aged Americans obtain health insurance coverage as a benefit offered by their employers (Fronstin, 2004). Conditional on working for an employer that offers health insurance, it is generally agreed that individual coverage is more difficult to obtain and more expensive than equivalent group coverage, due in large part to possible adverse selection (common in the insurance markets). For example, potential adverse selection leads insurers in the individual market to engage in medical underwriting, a process by which they attempt to gather information on the “riskiness” of applicants. Based on such information, insurers may attach riders or other exclusions on existing health conditions; rate an applicant as “substandard,” resulting in higher premiums or in outright denial of coverage. Because individuals who leave jobs with employer-sponsored coverage must eventually forfeit their coverage, the higher costs associated with individual policies, coupled with potential difficulty (or impossibility) in obtaining or maintaining coverage, may discourage job mobility (see, for example, Buchmueller and Valletta, 1996; Cooper and Monheit, 1993; Gruber and Madrian, 1994; Madrian, 1994b). Such health insurance related immobility may be especially binding for individuals who face relatively high experience-rated premiums in the non-group market (e.g., individuals healthy enough to work but considered “bad risks” by health insurers) and individuals who lack existing alternative sources of coverage (e.g., unmarried individuals, those ineligible for government-sponsored health insurance, etc.). Finally, it should be noted that certain individuals, like those with long-term chronic health problems or those who anticipate poor future health, may sort into employment that offers access to group health insurance relatively early in their working lives. Clearly, it is reasonable to expect that similar considerations influence the impact of health insurance availability on entrepreneurship with the consequence that the lack of affordable health insurance is likely to discourage entrepreneurship. Lack of health insurance is likely to deter entrepreneurship for a number of reasons. First, given the high potential costs of illness and medical treatment, most people are highly averse to foregoing health insurance. Further, the heavy reliance on employerprovided health insurance especially acts as a deterrent to entrepreneurship because it is harder to self-insure against more persistent shocks and the welfare cost of missing consumption insurance increases with shock persistence (Buera and Shin, 2011). Second, entrepreneurship is generally considered riskier than working for an employer. The lack of health insurance for self employed and entrepreneurs just adds another layer of extra financial and business risk–with this extra risk pushing many over the edge into foregoing entrepreneurship. These health insurance issues have taken on a new salience with the passage of the Patient Protection and Affordable Care Act of 2010 (PPACA). PPACA mandates that, starting in 2014, all U.S. citizens and residents, other than those under incarceration and those exempted for religious reasons, must ensure they have at least minimum health care coverage. Individuals without coverage for themselves and their dependents will be levied a penalty for each month they fail to have coverage. Under PPACA, states will create “exchanges” where individual consumers can purchase insurance, and insurers will not be able to apply pre-existing condition exclusions and price premiums based on health status. According to initial macro-economic estimates that confirm the importance of health insurance for entrepreneurship, these features of PPACA can potentially weaken the negative impact of health insurance on entrepreneurship.d However, PPACA exempts existing health plans from these regulations allowing the problem to persist for some time (Eibner et al., 2010). 2.3. Empirical evidence of health insurance impact on entrepreneurship Surprisingly, despite a strong and continuing interest in the nature and determinants of entrepreneurship, scholars have devoted relatively little attention to the role health insurance availability plays in the entrepreneurial decisions. This lack of attention is especially surprising in the context of several studies on the influence of health insurance availability on job mobility. Fortunately, there seem to be a few published studies on the topic of health insurance and entrepreneurship. Using secondary panel data from the early 1990s, Holtz-Eakin et al. (1996) examine the impact of health insurance on the transition from traditional employment to selfemployment. In particular, they compare the characteristics of individuals who transition from traditional to self-employment with their counterparts who remained wage earners. They find that health insurance portability had no systematic effect on this transition. However, again using secondary economic data from the early 1990s, Wellington (2001) estimates the impact of health insurance availability through a spouse on the probability of self-employment. She finds the availability of health insurance could increase self-employment by between 2 and 3.5 percent. Fairlie et al. (2011), hereafter known as FKG, provides an interesting approach to estimating the impact of health insurance on entrepreneurship. They compare business formation rates among those just under age 65 to those who are just over age 65 and find there is a significant jump in new business formation among those who are just above age 65. Their interpretation of this finding is that this jump is attributable to the availability of Medicare, and that a lack of other than employer provided health insurance is a deterrent to entrepreneurship. Finally, in an unpublished study, DeCicca (2010), using data on the 1993 implementation of a community health insurance program in New Jersey, estimated that self-employment went up significantly especially among the unmarried (by as much as 14–20 percent compared to reference groups) as a result of this guaranteed availability of health insurance. These prior studies on the impact of health insurance on entrepreneurship provide indirect, albeit sometimes very strong, evidence based on secondary economic data of the hypothesized negative effect of the lack of health insurance on entrepreneurship. This paper takes a somewhat different approach and provides more direct evidence supporting these prior conclusions, but based in this study on the analysis of data collected directly from entrepreneurs. Although such data also has some disadvantages, it nevertheless adds value because it provides a different perspective. Thus, this paper makes an important contribution to our understanding of the relationship between entrepreneurship and health insurance. 2.4. Hypotheses Clearly, the impact of the difficulty of obtaining affordable health insurance on entrepreneurs is more meaningful for individuals who do not work for others and lack alternatives to their own employer-sponsored health insurance coverage. One may also expect a greater negative impact on entrepreneurs who would otherwise have more difficulty obtaining health insurance. One example of such a group is unmarried entrepreneurs. Although married entrepreneurs typically are eligible for group health insurance offered by a spouse’s employer, unmarried individuals generally do not have this option. Similarly, the lack of health insurance is likely to be more important for older entrepreneurs with children and for those from less fortunate socio-economic backgrounds. To test these possibilities, we assess the impact of the health insurance on entrepreneurship as it varies by marital status, socio-economic background and other entrepreneur characteristics. Thus, we hypothesize that: H1: The difficulty of obtaining health insurance is an important deterring factor considered by entrepreneurs in becoming entrepreneurs. H2a: The importance of the difficulty of obtaining of health insurance as an entrepreneurship deterrent depends on the marital status of the entrepreneur. H2b: The difficulty of obtaining health insurance as an entrepreneurship deterrent is stronger for entrepreneurs with children. H3: The difficulty of obtaining health insurance as an entrepreneurship deterrent is stronger for entrepreneurs who have fewer other means and are of lower socio-economic status. 3. Data and Methodology Prior studies in this area have been based on the analysis of secondary economic and demographic data. In contrast, this paper is based on primary data collected by a team of researchers at Duke University in a 2009 survey of entrepreneurial company founders.e The surveyed sample consisted of company founders listed in the data base, One Source, randomized and stratified by industry and region of the United States. The researchers visited the websites of these companies to make sure the company was still in operation and to obtain names and contact information of founders. The guidelines that were provided for defining a “founder” was an early employee, typically joining the company in its first year, before the company developed its products and perfected its business model. The founders were asked detailed questions about their backgrounds, motivations and experiences in launching companies. The founders were also asked to categorize their companies by industry. The researchers then contacted company founders through email and requested they complete a brief online survey consisting of a series of questions about their own personal and family backgrounds as well as their views on and motivations toward starting a business. As follow ups, our team of researchers sent up to four unsolicited reminder emails to these founders. In some cases where necessary, the e-mails were followed up with phone calls. Of the founders who could be reached, it is estimated that approximately 40 percent completed the survey and five hundred and forty nine respondents took part in the survey. Five hundred and ten (or 92.9%) of these respondents answered all of the questions asked. Our sample is representative of U.S. entrepreneurs as a chi-square analysis of the regional and industry distributions of our sample and the complete OneSource list indicated no significant differences. <u><strong><mark>The</u></strong></mark> <u>company</u> <u><strong><mark>founders</u></strong></mark> <u>came from a variety of industries including aerospace and defense, computer and electronics, healthcare and services but were</u> <u><strong><mark>highly concentrated in technology sectors</u></strong></mark> <u>with <strong><mark>77 percent</strong> <strong>indicating</strong> </mark>their current company made <strong><mark>computer hardware</strong></mark>/software or other forms of technology products and services. <strong><mark>Other sectors included biotech, medical</strong></mark>, military and other (non-technology). </u>Although this survey can be generalized to the entire population of tech entrepreneurs in the United States, it is more reliable if it is considered to be illustrative of the backgrounds of entrepreneurs in high growth industries (because a significant proportion of the company founders focused on such industries). Unfortunately, like most research in this area, the results are affected by a survivorship bias, in that we are only able to reach entrepreneurs whose companies were still in existence. Nevertheless, this survey has yielded a unique and important primary data set that is particularly valuable because prior studies in this area have relied on secondary data. Analysis of this unusual primary data set done in this study can provide a fresh and unique perspective, new insights and an independent confirmation (or refutation) of prior findings. 4. Empirical Findings This nation-wide survey of company founders used an extensive questionnaire and yielded a rich trove of primary data about entrepreneurs. In this paper we focus on how entrepreneurship is influenced by the availability of health insurance. However, as a start we also provide a brief overview of the other findings of this survey to form the backdrop to our findings on the impact of health insurance on entrepreneurship (these findings are not published but are available in the working papers of Wadhwa et al. (2009a,b) 4.1. General background of entrepreneurs As a start, it is interesting to note here briefly, that the widely held stereotype of an entrepreneur (at least as portrayed in the media) is that of a recent college graduate or a college drop-out living a monastic life, sleeping in the office and going to a venture capitalist for start-up funds. Further this stereotype seems to include the fact that such an individual has rarely worked for other companies or other people. However, this stereotype is really a caricature and is not even true according the findings from this survey. The average entrepreneur or founder of a fast-growing technology or knowledge industry company is middle-aged, married, has children and worked for many years at a company or for someone else before branching out and starting his or her own business. Company founders tend to be middle-aged, well-educated and did better in high-school than in college. The average and median age of company founders when they started their current company was 40 years. 95.1 percent of the founders had earned Bachelor’s degrees and 47 percent had more advanced degrees.f Most had significant industry experience when starting their companies. The majority of respondents (75 percent) had worked as an employee at a company for more than six years before launching their own company and nearly half (48 percent) launched their first company with more than ten years of work experience. Significant percentages of respondents started their first company after working for someone else for 11–15 years (23%), 16–20 years (14 percent), or greater than 20 years (10 percent). Company founders tend to come from middle-class backgrounds, are better educated and more entrepreneurial than their parents. 72 percent of the founders came from middle class backgrounds and less than 1 percent came from extremely rich or extremely poor backgrounds. The fathers of 50 percent of the company founders held bachelors or advanced degrees as did 34 percent of the mothers. The average birth order of respondents in their family was 2.2 and the average number of siblings was 3.1. More than half (52%) of respondents were the first in their family to launch a business but 39 percent, 7 percent and 15 percent respectively had a father, mother or siblings who had previously started businesses. Most founders were married and had children and 70 percent of respondents indicated they were married when they launched their first business. Furthermore, 60 percent indicated they had at least one child when they launched their first business while 44 percent had two or more children. We asked company founders to rank the importance of a series of factors on the success of their most recent startups and to tell us what other factors were important. 96 percent ranked prior work experience as an important success factor with 58 percent ranking this as extremely important. 88 percent said that learning from previous successes and 78 percent said that learning from previous failures played an important role in their present successes. 40 percent said lessons from failures were extremely important. 82 percent said their management team was important to their success and 35 percent said this was extremely important. 73 percent said good fortune was an important factor in their success and 22 percent ranked this as extremely important. 70 percent said their university education was important. Ivy-league graduates valued this more, with 86 percent indicating this was important. Only 19 percent believed university or alumni networks were important but of the Ivy-league graduates, 29 percent ranked these as important. 73 percent said professional networks were important to the success of their current business and 62 percent of respondents felt the same way about personal networks. 68 percent of the overall sample considered availability of financing/capital as important. Of the entrepreneurs who received advice or assistance from their company’s investors, only 36 percent ranked it as important, 38 percent saying that it was not at all important. The vast majority (86%) of entrepreneurs ranked the assistance provided by the state or region as not at all or slightly important. Company founders were also asked to provide an opinion on the factors that may prevent others from starting their own business. We wanted to understand the barriers potential entrepreneurs may face from the perspective of those who had already faced these. The factor ranked as important most commonly—by 98 percent—was lack of willingness or of ability to take risks, 50 percent believing this to be an extremely important barrier to entrepreneurship. This clearly indicates these company founders considered entrepreneurship to be a risky endeavor. Regarding barriers, among company founders, 92 percent said the amount of time and effort required, 89 percent said business management skills, 84 percent said knowledge of how to start a business, 83 percent said knowledge about the industry and markets, and 73 percent believed family or financial pressures to keep a traditional, steady job. Further, 91 percent said difficulty in raising capital was an important inhibitor. The most significant source of funding for all businesses was their personal savings with 70 percent saying they had used personal savings as a main source of funding for their first business. Even in subsequent startups, more than half of the entrepreneurs relied on their personal savings. Venture capital and private/angel investments play a relatively small role in the startups of first-time entrepreneurs and only 11 percent received venture capital and 9 percent received angel financing for their first startups. But the percentage who took venture and angel funding increased with subsequent business launches, with 26 percent and 22 percent respectively of entrepreneurs’ most recent startups receiving such funding. Friends and family provided funding for 16 percent and banks provided funding for another 16 percent, while corporate investments played the major role in 7 percent of the startups. Thus, in summary, entrepreneurial company founders are generally in their 40s or 50s and are not bachelors (72.5% of entrepreneurs were married when they launched their first venture). Further, 61.1 percent of respondents indicated they had at least one child when they launched their first business. Many entrepreneurs are first-born (around 42%), but second- and later-borns are in the majority. Most entrepreneurs are not from wealthy backgrounds either with about 71 percent of our entrepreneurs coming from middle class backgrounds and a majority of them coming from lower-middle and mid-middle class backgrounds. A majority of company founders (53%) were found to be the first ones in their family to launch a business. Less than half of the parents of respondents had college or advanced degrees. More than three-quarters of the entrepreneurs we surveyed had worked for someone else for at least six years before launching their businesses. In contrast to the importance of venture capital in the media, reflecting the findings of other studies the most significant source of funding for the businesses started by respondents was their personal savings. In our surveys, 70 percent said they had used personal savings as a main source of funding for their first business, more than four times the number for any other category. Even in subsequent start ups, more than half of the entrepreneurs relied on their personal savings. Friends, family or bank loans were a source of funding for approximately 13 to 16 percent of our sample. Just 10.8 percent received venture capital, and 9.2 percent received angel financing.g The main obstacle entrepreneurs reported was lack of knowledge about starting a business, and fear of failure and its aftermath. As this brief review of the overall findings indicates, the findings of this survey paint a picture of an entrepreneur who is quite different from the widely held stereotypes. This survey also provides important new details of the backgrounds of company founders. Consequently, these findings have important policy implications for encouraging entrepreneurship, an important issue, given that the vast majority of new jobs in the United States are created by small new companies. 4.2. Health insurance and entrepreneurs 4.2.1. Importance of health insurance The surveyed entrepreneurs were asked two questions related to health insurance and its importance for the entrepreneurial decision. The first asked them about the importance of access to health insurance in their decision to become entrepreneurs. The second, a follow up, asked them about the importance of the challenges posed by the possible lack of health insurance. Figure 1 summarizes their responses. As the results presented in Panel A of Figure 1 indicate, a vast majority (88%) of the responding entrepreneurs indicated the availability of health insurance was an important factor in their decision to become entrepreneurs with only 12 percent indicating this was not a factor. This evidence is strong support for our first hypothesis. Further, as Panel B of Figure 1 indicates, the availability of health insurance was not only a factor in the entrepreneurial decision, it was a challenge (meaning a significant obstacle to be overcome) for about half the entrepreneurs. Overall, as expected, the availability of health insurance seems to be an important factor in the decision to become an entrepreneur. 4.2.2. Health insurance and entrepreneur marital status The marital status of an entrepreneur seems to make an important difference when it comes to the importance of health insurance. Responses to both the importance of access to health insurance in the decision to become an entrepreneur and the challenges posed by the possible lack of health insurance questions were cross tabulated with the entrepreneur’s marital status (almost all, 508 out of 540, or 94 percent, of the responders provided this information). Figure 2 summarizes the responses for single versus married respondents As these responses indicate in Panel A of Figure 2, the importance of losing health insurance was a somewhat more important factor in the entrepreneurial decision for married entrepreneurs. 89.2 percent of married entrepreneurs felt it was an important factor as compared to 86.2 percent of single entrepreneurs. However, this difference is not statistically significant (Z ¼ 0:98, p ¼ 33%). Yet, as the results shown in Panel B of Figure 2 indicate, the differences between single and married entrepreneurs were somewhat more important in terms of the challenges posed by the lack of health insurance. 50.4 percent of married entrepreneurs felt a lack of health insurance was a challenge versus only 45.4 percent of the single entrepreneurs; this difference is statistically significant at a better than two percent level (Z ¼ 1:47, p ¼ 1:4%). This evidence supports our hypothesis 2a. As the results in Figure 2 show, as can be expected, the availability of health insurance is a more significant challenge for married entrepreneurs. 4.2.3. Health insurance and entrepreneurs with children Analysis of the importance of the availability of health insurance for the entrepreneurial decision for those with children is presented in Figure 3. As the results presented in this exhibit for entrepreneurs with (296) and without (197) children indicate, a slightly higher proportion of those with children (88.85%) express concern about health insurance as compared to those without children (87.31%). However, these differences are not statistically significant (Z ¼ 1:54, p ¼ 60:4%). Similarly, analysis of the importance of the challenge of the lack of health insurance for the entrepreneur for those with (303) and without (202) children, indicates a higher proportion of those with children (54.13%) express concern about health insurance as compared to those without children (45.05%). However, these differences are again not statistically significant (Z ¼ 1:00, p ¼ 31%). The results regarding the impact of the number of children on entrepreneurship are presented in Figure 3 and we see that the differences discussed above become significant. For entrepreneurs with three or more children find the lack of health insurance is significant in the entrepreneurial decision. This evidence supports our hypothesis 2b. Panel B of Figure 4 shows the impact of health insurance on entrepreneurship by those with varying number of children. As this figure shows, the impact of health insurance on the entrepreneurial decision clearly increases in importance as the number of children increase. 4.2.4. Health insurance and entrepreneur socio-economic background Figure 4 presents results regarding the impact of the self-classified socio-economic background of the entrepreneur on the importance of health insurance. As these results show, entrepreneurs from less privileged backgrounds (below the upper middle class) were significantly more likely to consider health insurance in making their entrepreneurial decision (Z ¼ 1:84, p ¼ 6:7%).h Similarly, entrepreneurs from less privileged backgrounds were significantly more likely to consider health insurance to be a challenge (Z ¼ 2:73, p ¼ 0:7%). This evidence is strong support for our third hypothesis. A more detailed analysis of the impact of socio-economic background on the role of health insurance in the entrepreneurial decision is presented in Panel B of Figure 4. As this data show, the role of health insurance in the entrepreneurial decision increases in importance as the socio-economic background of an entrepreneur declines. 4.2.5. Health insurance and other entrepreneur characteristics The first entrepreneur characteristic we examined for impact on the importance of health care for the entrepreneurial decision was the nature of funding used for the first venture founded by the entrepreneur. As the data in Panel A of Figure 5 show, analysis of the importance of the availability of health insurance for the entrepreneurship decision between entrepreneurs with (277) and those without (219) outside institutional funding indicates a higher proportion of those with self funding (87.21%) express concern about health insurance as compared to those with outside funding (85.49%). However, these differences are not statistically significant (Z ¼ 0:67, p ¼ 50%). Similarly, analysis of the importance of the challenge of the lack of health insurance for the entrepreneur for those with (285) outside institutional funding and those with self funding (223), indicates a higher proportion of those with self funding (55.16%) express concern about health insurance as compared to those with outside funding (46.67%) with these differences being statistically significant (Z ¼1.90, p ¼ 5:8%). Next, we examine the role of education in moderating the impact of health insurance availability on entrepreneurship. The results are shown in Panel B of Figure 5. As these results indicate, all entrepreneurs thought the availability of health insurance is an important factor in the entrepreneurial decision, entrepreneurs with advanced (graduate) degrees were less likely to think so than those with a bachelor’s degree or less education. These differences were statistically significant (Z ¼ 2:93, p ¼ 0:4%). Similarly, all entrepreneurs thought the availability of health insurance is an important challenge for entrepreneurs, but entrepreneurs with just a bachelor’s degree or less education were significantly more likely to think so than those with advanced college degrees (Z ¼ 3:52, p ¼ 0:0%). Analysis of the self-reported performance in college on the importance of health insurance for entrepreneurs is presented in Panel C of Figure 5. As these results show, entrepreneurs with above average performance in college were slightly less likely to consider health insurance to be important but these differences were not statistically significant (Z ¼ 0:58, p ¼ 56:4%). However, entrepreneurs with lower self-reported performance in college were significantly more likely to consider health insurance to be a continuing challenge (Z ¼ 1:82, p ¼ 7:0%). The analysis of the role of prior work experience on the importance of health insurance is presented in Panel D of Figure 5. As these results show, entrepreneurs with ten or more years of work experience prior to starting their business were significantly more likely to consider health insurance in making their entrepreneurial decision (Z ¼ 1:98, p ¼ 4:9%). Similarly, entrepreneurs with long prior work experience were somewhat more likely to consider health insurance to be a challenge but the difference was not statistically significant (Z ¼ 1:07, p ¼ 28:5%). 4.2.6. Discussion Overall, the results presented here show that health insurance is an important factor in the entrepreneurial decision and has been a continuing challenge for entrepreneurs. The importance of health insurance availability increases for entrepreneurs who are self-funded, married, have children, are from less privileged backgrounds and are in advanced stages of their lives as indicated by having advanced degrees or long work experience when they become entrepreneurs. These results are important for not only understanding the nature of entrepreneurship but also for formulating public policy in this area, especially because entrepreneurship is perhaps the most important source of job creation and economic growth in the United States and other countries. Thus, public policy that improves the availability of health insurance for the self-employed is likely to pay large and significant dividends in the form of economic growth and job creation. To encourage and facilitate entrepreneurship in the United States and other countries, we recommend that, for example, health insurance reform should make it easier for the self-employed to obtain health insurance. Fortunately, steps are already being taken by the United States and many other governments to make progress in this regard. 5. Conclusions Concern has long been expressed that lack of appropriate health insurance alternatives has deterred entrepreneurship. In spite of the interest in this topic, there are few direct studies based on primary data of the impact of a lack of health insurance alternatives for the self employed. This concern has become more salient with recent changes such as the political and legal challenges to the new health care bill (PPACA) signed into law by President Obama. This paper examines the role of health insurance availability on U.S. entrepreneurs. Unlike prior studies that have analyzed secondary data, this paper uses a unique primary data set from a representative, recent survey of entrepreneurs to complement and supplement the results of prior studies. Given that prior studies in this area have mostly relied on macroeconomic and demographic secondary data, analysis of this unusual primary data set provides an opportunity for a fresh and unique perspective, new insights and an independent confirmation (or refutation) of prior findings based on secondary data. <u><strong><mark>Our results are very strong and significant</u></strong></mark> <u>and provide fresh insights into the role of health insurance on entrepreneurs. We document that the</u> <u><strong><mark>lack of health insurance has</u></strong></mark> <u>a strong and</u> <u><strong><mark>significant inhibiting impact on U.S. entrepreneurs. This paper also documents that the importance of health insurance availability increases</u></strong></mark> <u>for entrepreneurs that are self-funded, married, have children, are from less privileged backgrounds and are in advanced stages of their lives as indicated by having advanced degrees or long work experience when they become entrepreneurs.</u> Generally, entrepreneurs are deterred from company formation and job creation by the lack of access to health insurance. This paper also reports on the backgrounds of company founders <u><strong><mark>based on primary data</u></strong></mark> collected in a survey directly <u><strong><mark>from a representative sample of</u></strong></mark> founders of <u><strong><mark>high technology companies</u></strong></mark>. The results show that most company <u><strong><mark>founders are</u></strong></mark> not young college drop-outs but are generally <u><strong><mark>older</u></strong></mark>, <u><strong><mark>experienced</u></strong></mark> <u>and married with children who often have more than one college degree</u>. <u>The most frequent source of funding used in these business start-ups was personal savings supplemented by investments from friends and family</u>. This summary of the self-reported socio-economic background of entrepreneurs provides a fresh portrait that is different from popular and media stereotypes. The results presented here are important for not only understanding the nature of entrepreneurship but also for formulating public policy in this area. It has been widely noted that entrepreneurship is perhaps the most important source of jobs and economic growth in the United States and other economies. Thus, anything that can be done to improve the availability of health insurance for entrepreneurs is likely to pay large and significant dividends in the form of economic growth and job creation. To encourage and facilitate entrepreneurship in the United States and other countries, we recommend that, for example, health insurance reform should make it easier for the self-employed to get health insurance. Fortunately, steps are already being taken by the United States and other governments to make progress in this regard.</p> | null | null | 1AC: Job Lock | 327,095 | 196 | 139,577 | ./documents/hsld22/SanMateo/YeRa/SanMateo-YeRa-Aff-Greenhill-Round-Robin-Round-4.docx | 930,547 | A | Greenhill Round Robin | 4 | Harker RM | Sims,Etienne | 1ac - stock
1nc - set col, t, case
1ar - all
2nr - k
2ar - case, k | hsld22/SanMateo/YeRa/SanMateo-YeRa-Aff-Greenhill-Round-Robin-Round-4.docx | 2022-09-30 19:32:28 | 80,665 | YeRa | San Mateo YeRa | null | Ye..... | Ra..... | null | null | 27,080 | SanMateo | San Mateo | CA | null | 2,003 | hsld22 | HS LD 2022-23 | 2,022 | ld | hs | 1 |
4,735,345 | Ethnic factionalization ensures mass civil wars that outweigh cumulatively | Chelwa 13 | Chelwa 13— [Grieve Chelwais currently a PhD student in economics at the University of Cape Town in South Africa, “The Scramble for Africa, fractionalization and open borders,” Open Borders: The Case, 2013, https://openborders.info/blog/tag/conflict/, accessed 12-13-2022; MJen] | The effects of Africa’s arbitrary border formation have not been benign, Africa’s dismal post-independence economic performance was largely driven by the high degree of ethnic fractionalization. ethnic [fractionalization] was closely associated with low schooling, underdeveloped financial systems, distorted foreign exchange markets, and insufficient infrastructure” fractionalization leads to rent-seeking behavior and reduces the consensus for public goods, creating long-run growth tragedies” the random partitioning of ethnic groups explains much of the continent’s civil wars “civil conflict intensity, as reflected in casualties and duration, is approximately 25% higher in areas where partitioned ethnicities reside (as compared to the homelands of ethnicities that have not been separated)” effects are not only limited to partitioned ethnic groups: “Tribal areas adjacent to the ethnic homeland of partitioned groups also experience more civil wars, which tend to last longer and be more devastating an ethnic group residing adjacent to a partitioned ethnic homeland is on average 5% more likely to experience civil conflict”. civil conflicts have led to the death of millions of people in Africa and to the displacement of many more. open borders can go a long way in rectifying some of the consequences of the Scramble for Africa. individuals belonging to certain ethnic groups or entire ethnic groups can easily relocate Currently the costs of emigrating, even within Africa, are substantial. | Africa’s economic performance was driven by ethnic fractionalization underdeveloped financial systems and infrastructure fractionalization reduces public goods explains civil wars intensity, is 25% higher where partitioned ethnicities reside effects are not only limited to ethnic groups: “ conflicts led to the death and displacement open borders can rectify Scramble for Africa individuals belonging can relocate Currently costs of emigrating, are substantial. | The effects of Africa’s arbitrary border formation have not been benign, as one would expect. In a now famous scholarly article from 1997, Easterly and Levine showed that Africa’s dismal post-independence economic performance was largely driven by the high degree of ethnic fractionalization. The authors showed that “ethnic [fractionalization] was closely associated with low schooling, underdeveloped financial systems, distorted foreign exchange markets, and insufficient infrastructure”. And this was driven by the fact that “[ethnic fractionalization] leads to rent-seeking behavior and reduces the consensus for public goods, creating long-run growth tragedies” (my italics). Even more tragic, recent work by Michalopoulos and Papaioannou shows that the random partitioning of ethnic groups explains much of the continent’s civil wars since the 1960s. Their work shows that “civil conflict intensity, as reflected in casualties and duration, is approximately 25% higher in areas where partitioned ethnicities reside (as compared to the homelands of ethnicities that have not been separated)”. The groups that have been particularly impacted by this are “the Afar and the Esa, which during the period from 1970 to 2005 have experienced five civil wars…[T]he Afar being partitioned between Ethiopia, Eritrea and Djibouti, and the Esa being split between Ethiopia and Somalia”. And the effects are not only limited to partitioned ethnic groups: “Tribal areas adjacent to the ethnic homeland of partitioned groups also experience more civil wars, which tend to last longer and be more devastating. [E]stimates imply that an ethnic group residing adjacent to a partitioned ethnic homeland is on average 5% more likely to experience civil conflict”. And civil conflicts have led to the death of millions of people in Africa and to the displacement of many more. One can easily imagine that a different border configuration that, for instance took into account the historical interests of different ethnic groups, might have kept at a minimum some of the problems highlighted in the previous paragraph. And this is why I believe that global open borders can go a long way in rectifying some of the consequences of the Scramble for Africa. Under open borders, individuals belonging to certain ethnic groups or entire ethnic groups can easily relocate to countries that the individual or the ethnic group indentifies with or to countries that are likely to guarantee the safety of the individual or his group. (In this post, I showed that the fact that the US has open borders between states made it easier for targetted ethnic/racial groups to migrate elsewhere). Currently the costs of emigrating, even within Africa, are substantial. Very often those on the receiving end of ethnic conflicts are not allowed to easily intergrate into the neighbouring countries to which they run to but are instead placed in refugee camps known for their notoriety. Similarly, those individuals or groups seeking a better life economically in a neighbouring country are required to obtain a dossier of documents, most of which are costly to obtain, before crossing the border to begin the employment search. Those who are unable to obtain these documents resort to risky methods to get themselves across (Update: for more on this last point, see John Lee’s post titled Risking death to get into South Africa). | 3,392 | <h4>Ethnic factionalization ensures mass civil wars that outweigh <u>cumulatively</h4><p></u><strong>Chelwa 13</strong>— [Grieve Chelwais currently a PhD student in economics at the University of Cape Town in South Africa, “The Scramble for Africa, fractionalization and open borders,” Open Borders: The Case, 2013, https://openborders.info/blog/tag/conflict/, accessed 12-13-2022; MJen]</p><p><u>The effects of Africa’s arbitrary border formation have not been benign,</u> as one would expect. In a now famous scholarly article from 1997, Easterly and Levine showed that <u><mark>Africa’s</mark> dismal post-independence <mark>economic</mark> <mark>performance was </mark>largely <mark>driven by</mark> the high degree of <mark>ethnic fractionalization</mark>. </u>The authors showed that “<u>ethnic [fractionalization] was closely associated with low schooling, <mark>underdeveloped</mark> <mark>financial</mark> <mark>systems</mark>, distorted foreign exchange markets, <mark>and </mark>insufficient <mark>infrastructure</mark>”</u>. And this was driven by the fact that “[ethnic <u><mark>fractionalization</u></mark>] <u>leads to rent-seeking behavior and <mark>reduces </mark>the consensus for <mark>public</mark> <mark>goods</mark>, creating long-run growth tragedies” </u>(my italics). Even more tragic, recent work by Michalopoulos and Papaioannou shows that <u>the random partitioning of ethnic groups <mark>explains</mark> much of the <strong>continent’s <mark>civil</mark> <mark>wars</u></strong></mark> since the 1960s. Their work shows that <u>“civil conflict <mark>intensity,</mark> as reflected in casualties and duration, <mark>is</mark> approximately <strong><mark>25% higher </mark>in areas <mark>where partitioned ethnicities reside</strong></mark> (as compared to the homelands of ethnicities that have not been separated)”</u>. The groups that have been particularly impacted by this are “the Afar and the Esa, which during the period from 1970 to 2005 have experienced five civil wars…[T]he Afar being partitioned between Ethiopia, Eritrea and Djibouti, and the Esa being split between Ethiopia and Somalia”. And the <u><mark>effects are not only</mark> <mark>limited to </mark>partitioned <mark>ethnic groups: “</mark>Tribal areas adjacent to the ethnic homeland of partitioned groups also experience more civil wars, which tend to last longer and be more devastating</u>. [E]stimates imply that <u>an ethnic group residing adjacent to a partitioned ethnic homeland is on average 5% more likely to experience civil conflict”.</u> And <u><strong>civil <mark>conflicts </mark>have <mark>led to the death </mark>of millions of people in Africa <mark>and</mark> to the <mark>displacement </mark>of many more.</u></strong> One can easily imagine that a different border configuration that, for instance took into account the historical interests of different ethnic groups, might have kept at a minimum some of the problems highlighted in the previous paragraph. And this is why I believe that global <u><mark>open borders</mark> <mark>can</mark> go a long way in <mark>rectify</mark>ing some of the consequences of the <mark>Scramble for Africa</mark>.</u> Under open borders, <u><mark>individuals</mark> <mark>belonging </mark>to certain ethnic groups or entire ethnic groups <mark>can </mark>easily <mark>relocate</mark> </u>to countries that the individual or the ethnic group indentifies with or to countries that are likely to guarantee the safety of the individual or his group. (In this post, I showed that the fact that the US has open borders between states made it easier for targetted ethnic/racial groups to migrate elsewhere). <u><mark>Currently</mark> the <mark>costs of emigrating, </mark>even within Africa, <mark>are substantial.</u></mark> Very often those on the receiving end of ethnic conflicts are not allowed to easily intergrate into the neighbouring countries to which they run to but are instead placed in refugee camps known for their notoriety. Similarly, those individuals or groups seeking a better life economically in a neighbouring<strong> country are required to obtain a dossier of documents, most of which are costly to obtain, before crossing the border to begin the employment search. Those who are unable to obtain these documents resort to risky methods to get themselves across (Update: for more on this last point, see John Lee’s post titled Risking death to get into South Africa).</p></strong> | LF AC | null | Colonialism | 377,192 | 335 | 165,613 | ./documents/hsld22/Marlborough/LeFi/Marlborough-LeFi-Aff-Golden-Desert-Debate-Tournament-2023-at-UNLV-Round-1.docx | 971,422 | A | Golden Desert Debate Tournament 2023 at UNLV | 1 | Peninsula KN | Dosch | 1ac-african union
nc-nebel t, eritrea pic, populism da
1ar-all
nr-PIC
2ar-case pic | hsld22/Marlborough/LeFi/Marlborough-LeFi-Aff-Golden-Desert-Debate-Tournament-2023-at-UNLV-Round-1.docx | 2023-02-04 19:42:04 | 80,515 | LeFi | Marlborough LeFi | null | Le..... | Fi..... | null | null | 26,925 | Marlborough | Marlborough | CA | null | 2,003 | hsld22 | HS LD 2022-23 | 2,022 | ld | hs | 1 |
4,607,013 | “Justice” must be immediate. | Luthra ’21 | Luthra ’21 [Jannat; 3-13-22; student of BA LLB (Hons.), Chandigarh University; ““Justice delayed is justice denied” – how can we deal with the inefficiency of courts in a fast-changing society” https://blog.ipleaders.in/justice-delayed-justice-denied-can-deal-inefficiency-courts-fast-changing-society/] brett | Justice delayed is justice denied is a legal maxim meaning that if a legal remedy is available for a party that has suffered some injury, but is not forthcoming promptly, it is effectively the same as having no remedy at all the basis for rights a slogan for legal reformers who view governments as acting too slowly in resolving legal issues either because the existing system is too complex or overburdened, or because the issue or party in question lacks political favour | Justice delayed is justice denied if remedy is available but not forthcoming it is effectively no remedy | “Justice delayed is justice denied” is a legal maxim meaning that if a legal remedy is available for a party that has suffered some injury, but is not forthcoming promptly, it is effectively the same as having no remedy at all. This principle is the basis for the right to a speedy trial and similar rights which are meant to expedite the legal system because it is unfair for the victim to have to sustain the injury with little hope for resolution. The phrase has become a slogan for legal reformers who view courts or governments as acting too slowly in resolving legal issues either because the existing system is too complex or overburdened, or because the issue or party in question lacks political favour. | 712 | <h4>“<u>Justice</u>” must be <u>immediate</u>.</h4><p><strong>Luthra ’21</strong> [Jannat; 3-13-22; student of BA LLB (Hons.), Chandigarh University; ““Justice delayed is justice denied” – how can we deal with the inefficiency of courts in a fast-changing society” https://blog.ipleaders.in/justice-delayed-justice-denied-can-deal-inefficiency-courts-fast-changing-society/] brett</p><p>“<u><strong><mark>Justice delayed is justice denied</u></strong></mark>” <u>is <strong>a legal maxim</strong> meaning that <mark>if</mark> a legal <mark>remedy is available</mark> for a party that has suffered some injury, <mark>but</mark> is <mark>not forthcoming</mark> promptly, <mark>it is effectively</mark> the same as having <strong><mark>no remedy</strong></mark> at all</u>. This principle is <u>the basis for </u>the right to a speedy trial and similar <u><strong>rights</u></strong> which are meant to expedite the legal system because it is unfair for the victim to have to sustain the injury with little hope for resolution. The phrase has become <u>a slogan for legal reformers who view</u> courts or <u><strong>governments</u></strong> <u>as acting too slowly in resolving legal issues either because the existing system is too complex or overburdened, or because the issue or party in question lacks political favour</u>.</p> | 1NC | null | 1NC - CP | 1,704,553 | 136 | 152,785 | ./documents/hsld22/StAgnesAcademy/ElHu/StAgnesAcademy-ElHu-Neg-Harvard-Westlake-Debates-Round-5.docx | 964,694 | N | Harvard Westlake Debates | 5 | Harker NA | Moon | 1AC Africa
1NC T v2 T - Spec exemptions Cap K Consult Civil society stakeholders CP Populism DA Case
1AR Same
2NR CP Case
2AR Same | hsld22/StAgnesAcademy/ElHu/StAgnesAcademy-ElHu-Neg-Harvard-Westlake-Debates-Round-5.docx | 2023-01-15 20:48:23 | 79,345 | ElHu | St Agnes Academy ElHu | null | El..... | Hu..... | null | null | 26,587 | StAgnesAcademy | St Agnes Academy | TX | 8,005 | 2,003 | hsld22 | HS LD 2022-23 | 2,022 | ld | hs | 1 |
2,661,553 | Their theory reifies a totalizing understanding of settlerism that doom alt solvency and perpetuates the violence of labor exploitation. | Busbridge 18 | Busbridge 18—Research Fellow at the Centre for Dialogue, La Trobe University (Rachel, “Israel-Palestine and the Settler Colonial ‘Turn’: From Interpretation to Decolonization,” Theory, Culture & Society Vol 35, Issue 1, 2018, dml) | The prescription for decolonisation a normative project committed to the liberation of the colonised and the overturning of colonial relationships of power is one of the most counterhegemonic implications of the settler colonial paradigm potentially shifting it from a diagnostic frame to a prognostic one which offers a ‘proposed solution to the problem, or at least a plan of attack’ What does the settler colonial paradigm offer by way of envisioning decolonisation? there is a ‘narrative deficit’ when it comes to imagining settler decolonisation the structural perspective of the paradigm closes down possibilities of imagining the type of social and political transformation to which the notion of decolonisation aspires there is a worrying tendency if not tautological discrepancy in settler colonial studies, where the only solution to settler colonialism is decolonisation—which a faithful adherence to the paradigm renders largely unachievable, if not impossible structuralism has immense power as a means of mapping forms of injustice and indignity as well as strategies of resistance and refusal Yet, in seeking to elucidate the logic of elimination as the overarching historical force guiding settler-native relations there is an operational weakness in the theory, whereby such a logic is simply there, omnipresent and manifest even when (and perhaps especially when) it appears not to be; the settler colonial studies scholar need only read it into a situation or context. It hurtles from the past to the present into the future, never to be fully extinguished until the native is, or until history itself ends. There is thus a powerful ontological dimension where there is such thing as a ‘settler will’ that inherently desires the elimination of the native and the distinction between the settler and native can only ever be categorical, founded as it is on the ‘primal binarism of the frontier’ settler seeks to destroy and replace the native, and native can only ever push back if the settler colonial paradigm views history in teleological terms it does not offer the same hopeful vision of a liberated future settler colonialism has only one story to tell—‘either total victory or total failure’ the categorical distinction between settler and native obstructs the ‘possibility of a genuinely decolonised relationship’ yet is a necessary political strategy to guard against the absorption of Indigenous people into the settler fold, which would represent settler colonialism’s final victory The battle here is between a ‘settler colonialism [that] is designed to produce a fundamental discontinuity as its “logic of elimination” runs its course until it actually extinguishes the settler colonial relation’ and an anti-colonial struggle that ‘must aim to keep the settler-indigenous relationship going’ the categorical distinction produced by the frontier must be maintained in order to struggle against its effects Given the generally dreadful circumstances facing many Indigenous peoples it could be argued that there is good reason for pessimism Nonetheless, the fatalism of the settler colonial paradigm has come under considerable critique for reifying settler colonialism as a transhistorical meta-structure where colonial relations of domination are inevitable Not only does ontology erase contingency, heterogeneity and (crucially) agency but its polarised framework effectively ‘puts politics to death’ the totalising logic of structure of invasion rests on a disciplinary gesture where ‘any discussion which does not insist on the polarity of the [settler] colonial project’ is assimilationist, worse still, genocidal in effect if not intent. Any attempt to ‘explore the dialogical or hybrid nature of colonial subjectivity’—which would entail working beyond the bounds of absolute polarity—is disciplined as complicit in the settler colonial project itself, leaving ‘the only nonassimilationist position one that adheres strictly and solely to a critique of [settler] state discourse’. This gesture not only disallows the possibility of counter-publics and strategic alliances (even limited ones), but also comes dangerously close to ‘resistance as acquiescence’ insofar as the settler colonial studies scholar may malign the structures set in play by settler colonialism, but only from a safe distance unsullied by the messiness of ambivalences and contradictions of settler and Native subjectivities and relations. Opposition is thus left as our only option, but opposition is not decolonisation | there is a ‘narrative deficit’ when imagining decolonisation the structural paradigm closes down the type of social and political transformation to which decolonisation aspires in seeking to elucidate the logic of elimination as the overarching force guiding settler-native relations there is an operational weakness whereby such a logic is simply there, omnipresent even when it appears not to be There is a powerful ontological dimension where there is a ‘settler will’ that inherently desires the elimination of the native native can only ever push back it does not offer the hopeful vision of a liberated future settler colonialism has only one story either total victory or total failure’ fatalism has come under critique for reifying settler colonialism as a meta-structure where colonial relations are inevitable Not only does ontology erase contingency and agency but its framework puts politics to death’ the totalising logic rests on a disciplinary gesture where ‘any discussion which does not insist on polarity is assimilationist genocidal working beyond polarity is disciplined as complicit leaving ‘the only nonassimilationist position strictly and solely critique This not only disallows the possibility of counter-publics and strategic alliances but comes close to ‘resistance as acquiescence’ the scholar may malign the structures but only from a safe distance Opposition is left as our only option but opposition is not decolonisation | The prescription for decolonisation—that is, a normative project committed to the liberation of the colonised and the overturning of colonial relationships of power (Kohn & McBride, 2011: 3)—is indeed one of the most counterhegemonic implications of the settler colonial paradigm as applied to IsraelPalestine, potentially shifting it from a diagnostic frame to a prognostic one which offers a ‘proposed solution to the problem, or at least a plan of attack’ (Benford & Snow, 2000: 616). What, however, does the settler colonial paradigm offer by way of envisioning decolonisation? As Veracini (2007) notes, while settler colonial studies scholars have sought to address the lack of attention paid to the experiences of Indigenous peoples in conventional historiographical accounts of decolonisation (which have mostly focused on settler independence and the loosening of ties to the ‘motherland’), there is nevertheless a ‘narrative deficit’ when it comes to imagining settler decolonisation. While Veracini (2007) relates this deficit to a matter of conceptualisation, it is apparent that the structural perspective of the paradigm in many ways closes down possibilities of imagining the type of social and political transformation to which the notion of decolonisation aspires. In this regard, there is a worrying tendency (if not tautological discrepancy) in settler colonial studies, where the only solution to settler colonialism is decolonisation—which a faithful adherence to the paradigm renders largely unachievable, if not impossible. To understand why this is the case, it is necessary to return to Wolfe’s (2013a: 257) account of settler colonialism as guided by a ‘zero-sum logic whereby settler societies, for all their internal complexities, uniformly require the elimination of Native alternatives’. The structuralism of this account has immense power as a means of mapping forms of injustice and indignity as well as strategies of resistance and refusal, and Wolfe is careful to show how transmutations of the logic of elimination are complex, variable, discontinuous and uneven. Yet, in seeking to elucidate the logic of elimination as the overarching historical force guiding settler-native relations there is an operational weakness in the theory, whereby such a logic is simply there, omnipresent and manifest even when (and perhaps especially when) it appears not to be; the settler colonial studies scholar need only read it into a situation or context. It thus hurtles from the past to the present into the future, never to be fully extinguished until the native is, or until history itself ends. There is thus a powerful ontological (if not metaphysical) dimension to Wolfe’s account, where there is such thing as a ‘settler will’ that inherently desires the elimination of the native and the distinction between the settler and native can only ever be categorical, founded as it is on the ‘primal binarism of the frontier’ (2013a: 258). It is here that the differences between earlier settler colonial scholarship on Israel-Palestine and the recent settler colonial turn come into clearest view. While Jamal Hilal’s (1976) Marxist account of the conflict, for instance, engaged Palestinians and Jewish Israelis in terms of their relations to the means of production, Wolfe’s account brings its own ontology: the bourgeoisie/proletariat distinction becomes that of settler/native, and the class struggle the struggle between settler, who seeks to destroy and replace the native, and native, who can only ever push back. Indeed, if the settler colonial paradigm views history in similar teleological terms to the Marxist framework, it does not offer the same hopeful vision of a liberated future. After all, settler colonialism has only one story to tell—‘either total victory or total failure’ (Veracini, 2007). Veracini’s attempt to disaggregate different forms of settler decolonisation is revealing of the difficulties that come along with this zero-sum perspective. It is significant to note that beyond settler evacuation (which may decolonise territory, he cautions, but not necessarily relationships) the picture he paints is a relatively bleak one. For Veracini (2011: 5), claims for decolonisation from Indigenous peoples in settler societies can take two broad forms: an ‘anticolonial rhetoric expressing a demand for indigenous sovereign independence and self-determination… and an “ultra”-colonial one that seeks a reconstituted partnership with the [settler state] and advocates a return to a relatively more respectful middle ground and “treaty” conditions’. While both, he suggests, are tempting strategies in the struggle for change, though ‘ultimately ineffective against settler colonial structures of domination’ (2011: 5), it is the latter strategy that invites Veracini’s most scathing assessment. As he writes, under settler colonial conditions the independent polity is the settler polity and sanctioning the equal rights of indigenous peoples has historically been used as a powerful weapon in the denial of indigenous entitlement and in the enactment of various forms of coercive assimilation. This decolonisation actually enhances the subjection of indigenous peoples… it is at best irrelevant and at worst detrimental to indigenous peoples in settler societies (2011: 6-7). The ‘primal binarism of the frontier’ plays a particularly ambivalent role in Veracini’s (2011: 6) formulation, where the categorical distinction between settler and native obstructs the ‘possibility of a genuinely decolonised relationship’ (by virtue of its lopsidedness) yet is a necessary political strategy to guard against the absorption of Indigenous people into the settler fold, which would represent settler colonialism’s final victory. The battle here is between a ‘settler colonialism [that] is designed to produce a fundamental discontinuity as its “logic of elimination” runs its course until it actually extinguishes the settler colonial relation’ and an anti-colonial struggle that ‘must aim to keep the settler-indigenous relationship going’ (2011: 7). In other words, the categorical distinction produced by the frontier must be maintained in order to struggle against its effects. Given the lack of options presented to Indigenous peoples by Veracini (2014: 315), his conclusion that settler decolonisation demands a ‘radical, post-settler colonial passage’ is perhaps not surprising – although he has ‘no suggestion as to how this may be achieved and [is] pessimistic about its feasibility’. Scholars have long reckoned with the ambivalence of the settler colonial situation, which is simultaneously colonial and postcolonial, colonising and decolonising (Curthoys, 1999: 288). Given the generally dreadful Fourth World circumstances facing many Indigenous peoples in settler societies, it could be argued that there is good reason for such pessimism. The settler colonial paradigm, in this sense, offers an important caution against celebratory narratives of progress. Wolfe (1994), it must be recalled, wrote the original articulation of his thesis precisely against the idea of ‘historical rupture’ that dominated in Australia post-Mabo, and was thus as much a scholarly intervention as it was a political challenge to the idea of Australia having broken with its colonial past. Nonetheless, the fatalism of the settler colonial paradigm—whereby decolonisation is by and large put beyond the realms of possibility—has seen it come under considerable critique for reifying settler colonialism as a transhistorical meta-structure where colonial relations of domination are inevitable (Macoun & Strakosch, 2013: 435; Snelgrove et al., 2014: 9). Not only does Wolfe’s ontology erase contingency, heterogeneity and (crucially) agency (Merlan, 1997; Rowse, 2014), but its polarised framework effectively ‘puts politics to death’ (Svirsky, 2014: 327). In response to such critiques, Wolfe (2013a: 213) suggests that ‘the repudiation of binarism’ may just represent a ‘settler perspective’. However, as Elizabeth Povinelli (1997: 22) has astutely shown, it is in this regard that the totalising logic of Wolfe’s structure of invasion rests on a disciplinary gesture where ‘any discussion which does not insist on the polarity of the [settler] colonial project’ is assimilationist, worse still, genocidal in effect if not intent. Any attempt to ‘explore the dialogical or hybrid nature of colonial subjectivity’—which would entail working beyond the bounds of absolute polarity—is disciplined as complicit in the settler colonial project itself, leaving ‘the only nonassimilationist position one that adheres strictly and solely to a critique of [settler] state discourse’. This gesture not only disallows the possibility of counter-publics and strategic alliances (even limited ones), but also comes dangerously close to ‘resistance as acquiescence’ insofar as the settler colonial studies scholar may malign the structures set in play by settler colonialism, but only from a safe distance unsullied by the messiness of ambivalences and contradictions of settler and Native subjectivities and relations. Opposition is thus left as our only option, but, as we know from critical anti-colonial and postcolonial scholarship, opposition in itself is not decolonisation. | 9,306 | <h4>Their theory reifies a totalizing understanding of settlerism that doom alt solvency and perpetuates the violence of labor exploitation.</h4><p><strong>Busbridge 18</strong>—Research Fellow at the Centre for Dialogue, La Trobe University (Rachel, “Israel-Palestine and the Settler Colonial ‘Turn’: From Interpretation to Decolonization,” Theory, Culture & Society Vol 35, Issue 1, 2018, dml)</p><p><u>The prescription for decolonisation</u>—that is, <u>a normative project committed to the <strong>liberation of the colonised</strong> and the <strong>overturning of colonial relationships of power</u></strong> (Kohn & McBride, 2011: 3)—<u>is</u> indeed <u>one of the <strong>most counterhegemonic implications</strong> of the settler colonial paradigm</u> as applied to IsraelPalestine, <u>potentially shifting it from a diagnostic frame to a prognostic one which offers a ‘proposed solution to the problem, or at least a plan of attack’</u> (Benford & Snow, 2000: 616). <u>What</u>, however, <u>does the settler colonial paradigm offer by way of <strong>envisioning decolonisation</strong>?</u> As Veracini (2007) notes, while settler colonial studies scholars have sought to address the lack of attention paid to the experiences of Indigenous peoples in conventional historiographical accounts of decolonisation (which have mostly focused on settler independence and the loosening of ties to the ‘motherland’), <u><mark>there is</u></mark> nevertheless <u><mark>a ‘<strong>narrative deficit</strong>’ when </mark>it comes to <strong><mark>imagining</mark> settler <mark>decolonisation</u></strong></mark>. While Veracini (2007) relates this deficit to a matter of conceptualisation, it is apparent that <u><mark>the <strong>structural </mark>perspective</strong> of the <mark>paradigm</u></mark> in many ways <u><strong><mark>closes down</mark> possibilities</strong> of <strong>imagining <mark>the type of social</strong> and <strong>political transformation</strong> to which</mark> the <strong>notion of <mark>decolonisation aspires</u></strong></mark>. In this regard, <u>there is a <strong>worrying tendency</u></strong> (<u>if not <strong>tautological discrepancy</u></strong>) <u>in settler colonial studies, where the <strong>only solution to settler colonialism is decolonisation</strong>—which a faithful adherence to the paradigm <strong>renders largely unachievable</strong>, if not <strong>impossible</u></strong>. To understand why this is the case, it is necessary to return to Wolfe’s (2013a: 257) account of settler colonialism as guided by a ‘zero-sum logic whereby settler societies, for all their internal complexities, uniformly require the elimination of Native alternatives’. The <u>structuralism</u> of this account <u>has <strong>immense power</strong> as a means of mapping forms of injustice and indignity as well as strategies of resistance and refusal</u>, and Wolfe is careful to show how transmutations of the logic of elimination are complex, variable, discontinuous and uneven. <u>Yet, <mark>in seeking to <strong>elucidate the logic of elimination</strong> as the <strong>overarching</mark> historical <mark>force</strong> guiding settler-native relations there is an <strong>operational weakness</strong></mark> in the theory, <mark>whereby such a logic is <strong>simply there</strong>, <strong>omnipresent</strong></mark> and <strong>manifest</strong> <mark>even when</mark> (and perhaps especially when) <mark>it <strong>appears not to be</strong></mark>; the settler colonial studies scholar need only <strong>read it into a situation</strong> or <strong>context</strong>. It</u> thus <u><strong>hurtles from the past</strong> to the <strong>present</strong> into the <strong>future</strong>, never to be fully extinguished until the native is, or until history itself ends. <mark>There is</mark> thus <mark>a <strong>powerful ontological</u></strong></mark> (if not metaphysical) <u><strong><mark>dimension</u></strong></mark> to Wolfe’s account, <u><mark>where there is</mark> such thing as <mark>a ‘<strong>settler will</strong>’ that <strong>inherently desires the elimination of the native</strong></mark> and the distinction between the settler and native <strong>can only ever be categorical</strong>, founded as it is on the ‘primal binarism of the frontier’</u> (2013a: 258). It is here that the differences between earlier settler colonial scholarship on Israel-Palestine and the recent settler colonial turn come into clearest view. While Jamal Hilal’s (1976) Marxist account of the conflict, for instance, engaged Palestinians and Jewish Israelis in terms of their relations to the means of production, Wolfe’s account brings its own ontology: the bourgeoisie/proletariat distinction becomes that of settler/native, and the class struggle the struggle between <u>settler</u>, who <u>seeks to <strong>destroy</strong> and <strong>replace the native</strong>, and <mark>native</u></mark>, who <u><strong><mark>can only ever push back</u></strong></mark>. Indeed, <u>if the settler colonial paradigm views history in</u> similar <u>teleological terms</u> to the Marxist framework, <u><mark>it <strong>does not offer</strong> the</mark> same <mark>hopeful vision of a liberated future</u></mark>. After all, <u><mark>settler colonialism has <strong>only one story</mark> to tell</strong>—‘<mark>either <strong>total victory</strong> or <strong>total failure</strong>’</u></mark> (Veracini, 2007). Veracini’s attempt to disaggregate different forms of settler decolonisation is revealing of the difficulties that come along with this zero-sum perspective. It is significant to note that beyond settler evacuation (which may decolonise territory, he cautions, but not necessarily relationships) the picture he paints is a relatively bleak one. For Veracini (2011: 5), claims for decolonisation from Indigenous peoples in settler societies can take two broad forms: an ‘anticolonial rhetoric expressing a demand for indigenous sovereign independence and self-determination… and an “ultra”-colonial one that seeks a reconstituted partnership with the [settler state] and advocates a return to a relatively more respectful middle ground and “treaty” conditions’. While both, he suggests, are tempting strategies in the struggle for change, though ‘ultimately ineffective against settler colonial structures of domination’ (2011: 5), it is the latter strategy that invites Veracini’s most scathing assessment. As he writes, under settler colonial conditions the independent polity is the settler polity and sanctioning the equal rights of indigenous peoples has historically been used as a powerful weapon in the denial of indigenous entitlement and in the enactment of various forms of coercive assimilation. This decolonisation actually enhances the subjection of indigenous peoples… it is at best irrelevant and at worst detrimental to indigenous peoples in settler societies (2011: 6-7). The ‘primal binarism of the frontier’ plays a particularly ambivalent role in Veracini’s (2011: 6) formulation, where <u>the <strong>categorical distinction</strong> between settler and native <strong>obstructs</strong> the ‘possibility of a genuinely decolonised relationship’</u> (by virtue of its lopsidedness) <u>yet is a <strong>necessary political strategy</strong> to <strong>guard against the absorption</strong> of Indigenous people into the settler fold, which would <strong>represent settler colonialism’s final victory</u></strong>. <u>The battle here is between a ‘settler colonialism [that] is designed to produce a fundamental discontinuity as its “logic of elimination” runs its course until it actually extinguishes the settler colonial relation’ and an anti-colonial struggle that ‘<strong>must aim to keep the settler-indigenous relationship going</strong>’</u> (2011: 7). In other words, <u>the categorical distinction produced by the frontier <strong>must be maintained in order to struggle against its effects</u></strong>. Given the lack of options presented to Indigenous peoples by Veracini (2014: 315), his conclusion that settler decolonisation demands a ‘radical, post-settler colonial passage’ is perhaps not surprising – although he has ‘no suggestion as to how this may be achieved and [is] pessimistic about its feasibility’. Scholars have long reckoned with the ambivalence of the settler colonial situation, which is simultaneously colonial and postcolonial, colonising and decolonising (Curthoys, 1999: 288). <u>Given the generally dreadful</u> Fourth World <u>circumstances facing many Indigenous peoples</u> in settler societies, <u>it <strong>could be argued</strong> that there is good reason for</u> such <u><strong>pessimism</u></strong>. The settler colonial paradigm, in this sense, offers an important caution against celebratory narratives of progress. Wolfe (1994), it must be recalled, wrote the original articulation of his thesis precisely against the idea of ‘historical rupture’ that dominated in Australia post-Mabo, and was thus as much a scholarly intervention as it was a political challenge to the idea of Australia having broken with its colonial past. <u><strong>Nonetheless</strong>, the <strong><mark>fatalism</strong></mark> of the settler colonial paradigm</u>—whereby decolonisation is by and large put beyond the realms of possibility—<u><mark>has</u></mark> seen it <u><mark>come under</mark> <strong>considerable <mark>critique</strong> for <strong>reifying settler colonialism</strong> as a</mark> transhistorical <mark>meta-structure where colonial relations</mark> of domination <mark>are <strong>inevitable</u></strong></mark> (Macoun & Strakosch, 2013: 435; Snelgrove et al., 2014: 9). <u><mark>Not only does</u></mark> Wolfe’s <u><mark>ontology <strong>erase contingency</strong></mark>, <strong>heterogeneity</strong> <mark>and</mark> (crucially) <strong><mark>agency</u></strong></mark> (Merlan, 1997; Rowse, 2014), <u><mark>but its</mark> polarised <mark>framework</mark> effectively ‘<strong><mark>puts politics to death</strong>’</u></mark> (Svirsky, 2014: 327). In response to such critiques, Wolfe (2013a: 213) suggests that ‘the repudiation of binarism’ may just represent a ‘settler perspective’. However, as Elizabeth Povinelli (1997: 22) has astutely shown, it is in this regard that <u><mark>the <strong>totalising logic</strong></mark> of</u> Wolfe’s <u>structure of invasion <strong><mark>rests on a disciplinary gesture</strong> where ‘<strong>any discussion</strong> which <strong>does not insist</strong> on</mark> the <mark>polarity</mark> of the [settler] colonial project’ <mark>is <strong>assimilationist</strong></mark>, worse still, <strong><mark>genocidal</strong></mark> in effect if not intent. <strong>Any attempt</strong> to ‘explore the <strong>dialogical</strong> or <strong>hybrid nature</strong> of colonial subjectivity’—which would entail <strong><mark>working beyond</mark> the bounds of absolute <mark>polarity</strong></mark>—<mark>is <strong>disciplined as complicit</strong></mark> in the settler colonial project itself, <mark>leaving ‘the <strong>only nonassimilationist position</strong></mark> one that <strong>adheres <mark>strictly</strong> and <strong>solely</strong></mark> to a <strong><mark>critique</strong></mark> of [settler] state discourse’. <mark>This</mark> gesture <mark>not only <strong>disallows the possibility of counter-publics</strong> and <strong>strategic alliances</strong></mark> (even limited ones), <mark>but</mark> also <strong><mark>comes</mark> dangerously <mark>close</strong> to ‘<strong>resistance as acquiescence</strong>’</mark> insofar as <mark>the</mark> settler colonial studies <mark>scholar may <strong>malign the structures</mark> set in play</strong> by settler colonialism, <mark>but <strong>only from a safe distance</mark> unsullied by the messiness</strong> of ambivalences and contradictions of settler and Native subjectivities and relations. <strong><mark>Opposition</strong> is</mark> thus <mark>left as our <strong>only option</strong></mark>, <mark>but</u></mark>, as we know from critical anti-colonial and postcolonial scholarship, <u><mark>opposition</u></mark> in itself <u><mark>is <strong>not decolonisation</u></strong></mark>.</p> | 1NC Round 3 MBA | Case | Busbridge---1NC | 22,868 | 562 | 84,584 | ./documents/hspolicy19/Alpharetta/DiSa/Alpharetta-Di-Sandhu-Neg-MBA-Round3.docx | 706,127 | N | MBA | 3 | BVSW HP | Tim Ellis | 1AC - Rhetorical Unhinging
1NC - T USFG Case
2NC - T
1NR - Case
2NR - T Case | hspolicy19/Alpharetta/DiSa/Alpharetta-Di-Sandhu-Neg-MBA-Round3.docx | null | 60,083 | DiSa | Alpharetta DiSa | null | Jo..... | Di..... | Ha..... | Sa..... | 21,077 | Alpharetta | Alpharetta | GA | null | 1,018 | hspolicy19 | HS Policy 2019-20 | 2,019 | cx | hs | 2 |
3,248,417 | no escalation – regional militaries too weak | Rovner 14 | Rovner 14 -- *John Goodwin Tower Distinguished Chair of International Politics and National Security, Associate Professor of Political Science, and Director of Studies at the Tower Center for Political Studies @ Southern Methodist University, **Assistant Professor of Political Science and International Affairs at the George Washington University | The major regional powers all suffer from serious shortcomings in conventional military power, meaning that none of them will be able to seriously threaten the balance for the foreseeable future Iran’s military has suffered greatly from decades of war and sanctions Iraq’s fledgling security services are exclusively focused on internal problems And Saudi Arabia seems content to rely on a dense network of defenses and proxies rather than pursue any real power projection capabilities there is very little chance of a major interstate war threats to oil shipping in the Gulf are real but not overwhelming | regional powers suffer from shortcomings in military power, none able to threaten the balance Iran’s military has suffered from decades of war and sanctions. Iraq’ focused on internal problems Saudi content to rely on proxies rather than projection there is little chance of interstate war | (*Joshua, **Caitlin Talmadge, Less is More: The Future of the U.S. Military in the Persian Gulf, The George Washington University, http://twq.elliott.gwu.edu/less-more-future-us-military-persian-gulf)
Happily, however, the situation for the United States today is more like the 1950s than the 1970s. The major regional powers all suffer from serious shortcomings in conventional military power, meaning that none of them will be able to seriously threaten the balance for the foreseeable future. Iran’s military has suffered greatly from decades of war and sanctions. Iraq’s fledgling security services are almost exclusively focused on internal problems. And Saudi Arabia, the richest country in the region, seems content to rely on a dense network of defenses and proxies rather than pursue any real power projection capabilities. While there are reasons to worry about internal stability, especially given the ongoing fight against ISIS (the Islamic State of Iraq and Syria), there is very little chance of a major interstate war. Moreover, threats to oil shipping in the Gulf are real but not overwhelming. All of this points to a simple and optimistic conclusion: the United States can protect its core interest in the free flow of oil without having to commit to a large and enduring naval or ground presence to the Gulf. | 1,327 | <h4>no escalation – regional militaries too weak</h4><p><strong>Rovner 14</strong> -- *John Goodwin Tower Distinguished Chair of International Politics and National Security, Associate Professor of Political Science, and Director of Studies at the Tower Center for Political Studies @ Southern Methodist University, **Assistant Professor of Political Science and International Affairs at the George Washington University</p><p>(*Joshua, **Caitlin Talmadge, Less is More: The Future of the U.S. Military in the Persian Gulf, The George Washington University, http://twq.elliott.gwu.edu/less-more-future-us-military-persian-gulf)</p><p>Happily, however, the situation for the United States today is more like the 1950s than the 1970s. <u>The major <mark>regional powers</mark> all <mark>suffer from</mark> serious <mark>shortcomings in </mark>conventional <mark>military power,</mark> meaning that <mark>none</mark> of them will be <mark>able to</mark> seriously <mark>threaten the balance</mark> for the foreseeable future</u>. <u><mark>Iran’s military has suffered </mark>greatly <mark>from decades of war and sanctions</u>. <u>Iraq’</mark>s fledgling security services are</u> almost <u>exclusively <mark>focused on internal problems</u></mark>. <u>And <mark>Saudi</mark> Arabia</u>, the richest country in the region, <u>seems <mark>content to rely on</mark> a dense network of defenses and <mark>proxies rather than</mark> pursue any real power <mark>projection</mark> capabilities</u>. While there are reasons to worry about internal stability, especially given the ongoing fight against ISIS (the Islamic State of Iraq and Syria), <u><strong><mark>there is</mark> very <mark>little chance of</mark> a major <mark>interstate war</u></strong></mark>. Moreover, <u>threats to oil shipping in the Gulf are real but not overwhelming</u>. All of this points to a simple and optimistic conclusion: the United States can protect its core interest in the free flow of oil without having to commit to a large and enduring naval or ground presence to the Gulf. </p> | null | 1nr | middle east adv | 45,902 | 169 | 105,203 | ./documents/hspolicy18/MontgomeryBellAcademy/HaPi/Montgomery%20Bell%20Academy-Hamilton-Pierce-Neg-Westy-Round2.docx | 697,615 | N | Westy | 2 | Westy FI | Zeppos | 1ac bomb the middle east more effectively
1nc bataille
2nr also bataille | hspolicy18/MontgomeryBellAcademy/HaPi/Montgomery%20Bell%20Academy-Hamilton-Pierce-Neg-Westy-Round2.docx | null | 59,324 | HaPi | Montgomery Bell Academy HaPi | null | Jo..... | Ha..... | Do..... | Pi..... | 20,916 | MontgomeryBellAcademy | Montgomery Bell Academy | null | null | 1,017 | hspolicy18 | HS Policy 2018-19 | 2,018 | cx | hs | 2 |
1,597,870 | Nuclear war. | Rogoway 15 | Rogoway 15 (Tyler; November 12; Defense Journalist and Editor of Time Inc’s The War Zone; Jalopnik, “These Are The Doomsday Satellites That Detected The Explosion Of Metrojet 9268,” https://foxtrotalpha.jalopnik.com/these-are-the-doomsday-satellites-that-detected-the-exp-1737434876) | the Pentagon has early warning satellites in orbit aimed at spotting launches of ballistic missiles, especially the intercontinental kind that can fly around the globe in less than 30 minutes and bring nuclear Armageddon at the height of the Cold War the first Missile Defense Alarm System was launched Six years later there was a constellation scanning the Soviet Union for the tell-tale sign of a ballistic missile or rocket launch. These satellites would be the basis for a missile surveillance system that would become more complex and capable as the years went by. If missile launches were detected and a threat, the decision to retaliate would mean the National Command Authority making the call to do so within half an hour, an act that could bring the end of humanity’s reign on Earth If something were detected information would immediately be data-linked to controllers on the ground 23 satellites have been launched with constant upgrades along the way famously, the constellation were used to detect launches of SCUD missiles during Desert Storm | early warning spott launches of missiles that bring Armageddon there was a constellation scanning for launch If launches were detected the decision to retaliate would call in half an hour that could end humanity info would immediately be data-linked to the ground | For over 50 years the Pentagon has had early warning satellites in orbit aimed at spotting launches of ballistic missiles, especially the big intercontinental kind that can fly around the globe in less than 30 minutes and bring about nuclear Armageddon. Recently, these satellites have made news for their “secondary capabilities,” spotting the downing of Metrojet Flight 9268 and Malaysian Airlines Flight 17. These are the shadowy satellites that are capable of such amazing feats, and an idea of how they work. In 1960, at the height of the Cold War and at the dawn of the space age, the first Missile Defense Alarm System (MiDAS) satellite was launched into low earth orbit. Six years later there was a constellation of nine of these satellites roaming the heavens, each scanning the Soviet Union for large infrared plumes, the tell-tale sign of a ballistic missile or rocket launch. These fairly crude, low-earth orbit satellites, along with the radar-based Ballistic Missile Early Warning System, would be the basis for a Cold War ballistic missile surveillance system that would become ever more complex and capable as the years went by. If ballistic missile launches were detected and deemed a threat, the decision to retaliate would mean the National Command Authority making the call to do so within half an hour, an act that could bring an the end of humanity’s reign on Earth, permanently. The first really reliable and full coverage space-based ballistic missile early warning capability came with the launch of the first Defense Support Program (DSP) satellite in 1970. These new satellites were much more capable than their MiDAS predecessors. Early DSP satellite design was relatively straight forward, with the satellites’ spinning around their center axis while in geosynchronous orbit. This allows their telescopic infrared sensor to continuously sweep an area of the planet in a relatively brief amount of time, around six times in one minute. If something were detected, the information would immediately be data-linked to controllers on the ground at the 460th Space Wing located at Buckley AFB in in Colorado. A total of 23 of these satellites have been launched over the program’s life, with constant upgrades made along the way. A DSP satellite was launched by the Space Shuttle on STS-44 in 1991, and the last one was launched by a Delta IV Heavy in 2007. Most famously, the Defense Support Program constellation of satellites were used to detect launches of SCUD missiles during Operation Desert Storm. | 2,529 | <h4><u>Nuclear war</u>. </h4><p><strong>Rogoway 15 </strong>(Tyler; November 12; Defense Journalist and Editor of Time Inc’s The War Zone; Jalopnik, “These Are The Doomsday Satellites That Detected The Explosion Of Metrojet 9268,” https://foxtrotalpha.jalopnik.com/these-are-the-doomsday-satellites-that-detected-the-exp-1737434876)</p><p>For over 50 years <u>the Pentagon has</u> had <u><mark>early <strong>warning</mark> satellites</strong> in orbit aimed at <strong><mark>spott</mark>ing <mark>launches</strong> of</mark> ballistic <mark>missiles</mark>, especially the</u> big <u><strong>intercontinental kind</strong> <mark>that</mark> can fly around the globe in less than 30 minutes and <mark>bring</u></mark> about <u><strong>nuclear <mark>Armageddon</u></strong></mark>. Recently, these satellites have made news for their “secondary capabilities,” spotting the downing of Metrojet Flight 9268 and Malaysian Airlines Flight 17. These are the shadowy satellites that are capable of such amazing feats, and an idea of how they work. In 1960, <u>at the height of the Cold War</u> and at the dawn of the space age, <u>the first Missile Defense Alarm System</u> (MiDAS) satellite <u>was launched</u> into low earth orbit. <u>Six years later <mark>there was a constellation</u></mark> of nine of these satellites roaming the heavens, each <u><mark>scanning</mark> the Soviet Union <mark>for</u></mark> large infrared plumes, <u>the tell-tale sign of a <strong>ballistic missile</strong> or <strong>rocket <mark>launch</strong></mark>. These</u> fairly crude, low-earth orbit <u>satellites</u>, along with the radar-based Ballistic Missile Early Warning System, <u>would be the basis for a</u> Cold War ballistic <u>missile surveillance system that would become</u> ever <u>more complex and capable as the years went by. <mark>If</u></mark> ballistic <u>missile <strong><mark>launches were detected</strong></mark> and</u> deemed <u>a threat, <mark>the <strong>decision to retaliate</strong> would</mark> mean the National Command Authority making the <mark>call</mark> to do so <strong>with<mark>in half an hour</strong></mark>, an act <mark>that could</mark> bring</u> an <u>the <strong><mark>end</mark> of <mark>humanity</mark>’s </strong>reign on Earth</u>, permanently. The first really reliable and full coverage space-based ballistic missile early warning capability came with the launch of the first Defense Support Program (DSP) satellite in 1970. These new satellites were much more capable than their MiDAS predecessors. Early DSP satellite design was relatively straight forward, with the satellites’ spinning around their center axis while in geosynchronous orbit. This allows their telescopic infrared sensor to continuously sweep an area of the planet in a relatively brief amount of time, around six times in one minute. <u>If something were detected</u>, the <u><mark>info</mark>rmation <mark>would <strong>immediately</strong> be <strong>data-linked</strong> to</mark> controllers on <mark>the ground</u></mark> at the 460th Space Wing located at Buckley AFB in in Colorado. A total of <u>23</u> of these <u>satellites have been launched</u> over the program’s life, <u>with constant upgrades</u> made <u>along the way</u>. A DSP satellite was launched by the Space Shuttle on STS-44 in 1991, and the last one was launched by a Delta IV Heavy in 2007. Most <u>famously, the</u> Defense Support Program <u>constellation</u> of satellites <u>were used to <strong>detect launches</strong> of <strong>SCUD missiles</strong> during</u> Operation <u>Desert Storm</u>.</p> | 1AC - Tourism | 1AC | 1AC - Advantage | 337,031 | 142 | 46,352 | ./documents/hsld21/StrathHaven/Ma/Strath%20Haven-Manaker-Aff-DebateLA%20RR-Round6.docx | 900,787 | A | DebateLA RR | 6 | Sequoia AS | Rodrigo Paramo, Derek Hilligoss | 1AC - Space Tourism
1NC - T-Appropriation T-Nebel Innovation DA Global Con Con CP Space Hotel PIC case
1AR - all condo bad PICs bad process CPs bad
2NR - T-Appropriation
2AR - same | hsld21/StrathHaven/Ma/Strath%20Haven-Manaker-Aff-DebateLA%20RR-Round6.docx | null | 75,384 | AvMa | Strath Haven AvMa | null | Av..... | Ma..... | null | null | 25,179 | StrathHaven | Strath Haven | PA | null | 1,029 | hsld21 | HS LD 2021-22 | 2,021 | ld | hs | 1 |
2,325,129 | US-China conventional war goes nuclear. | Talmadge 18 | [Caitlin Talmadge (10-15-2018), PhD in Political Science from MIT, BA in Government from Harvard, Professor of Security Studies at Georgetown University, “Beijing’s Nuclear Option,” Foreign Affairs, https://www.foreignaffairs.com/articles/china/2018-10-15/beijings-nuclear-option]//recut CHS PK | As China’s power has grown in recent years, so, too, has the risk of war with the United States. Under President Xi Jinping, China has increased its political and economic pressure on Taiwan and built military installations on coral reefs in the South China Sea, fueling Washington’s fears that Chinese expansionism will threaten U.S. allies and influence in the region. U.S. destroyers have transited the Taiwan Strait, to loud protests from Beijing. American policymakers have wondered aloud whether they should send an aircraft carrier through the strait as well. Chinese fighter jets have intercepted U.S. aircraft in the skies above the South China Sea. Meanwhile, U.S. President Donald Trump has brought long-simmering economic disputes to a rolling boil.
the prospect of a military confrontation going nuclear are higher than most policymakers and analysts think.
munity tend to dismiss such concerns. Likewise, U.S. studies of a potential war with China often exclude nuclear weapons from the analysis entirely, treating them as basically irrelevant to the course of a conflict. Asked about the issue in 2015, Dennis Blair, the former commander of U.S. forces in the Indo-Pacific, estimated the likelihood of a U.S.-Chinese nuclear crisis as “somewhere between nil and zero.”
assurance is misguided. If deployed against China, the Pentagon’s preferred style of conventional warfare would be a potential recipe for nuclear escalation. the United States’ signature approach to war has been punch deep into enemy territory in order to rapidly knock out the opponent’s key military assets at minimal cost. But the Pentagon developed this formula in wars against Afghanistan, Iraq, Libya, and Serbia, none of which was a nuclear power.
China not only has nuclear weapons; it has also intermingled them with its conventional military forces, making it difficult to attack one without attacking the other a major U.S. military campaign targeting China’s conventional forces would likely also threaten its nuclear arsenal Chinese leaders could decide to use their nuclear weapons while they were still able to.
A U.S. and Chinese conventional war could skid into a nuclear confrontation , its consequences for the region and the world would be devastating both sides should dispense with the illusion that they can easily fight a limited war | China’s power has grown so has risk of war with the U S
the prospect of a confrontation going nuclear are high
the Pentagon’s preferred style of warfare would be a recipe for nuclear escalation the Pentagon developed this formula in wars against non nuclear power
China has nuclear weapons intermingled with conventional forces making it difficult to attack one without the other a U.S. campaign targeting conventional forces would threaten its arsenal Chinese leaders could use their weapons while they were still able to.
its consequences would be devastating | As China’s power has grown in recent years, so, too, has the risk of war with the United States. Under President Xi Jinping, China has increased its political and economic pressure on Taiwan and built military installations on coral reefs in the South China Sea, fueling Washington’s fears that Chinese expansionism will threaten U.S. allies and influence in the region. U.S. destroyers have transited the Taiwan Strait, to loud protests from Beijing. American policymakers have wondered aloud whether they should send an aircraft carrier through the strait as well. Chinese fighter jets have intercepted U.S. aircraft in the skies above the South China Sea. Meanwhile, U.S. President Donald Trump has brought long-simmering economic disputes to a rolling boil.
A war between the two countries remains unlikely, but the prospect of a military confrontation—resulting, for example, from a Chinese campaign against Taiwan—no longer seems as implausible as it once did. And the odds of such a confrontation going nuclear are higher than most policymakers and analysts think.
Members of China’s strategic community tend to dismiss such concerns. Likewise, U.S. studies of a potential war with China often exclude nuclear weapons from the analysis entirely, treating them as basically irrelevant to the course of a conflict. Asked about the issue in 2015, Dennis Blair, the former commander of U.S. forces in the Indo-Pacific, estimated the likelihood of a U.S.-Chinese nuclear crisis as “somewhere between nil and zero.”
This assurance is misguided. If deployed against China, the Pentagon’s preferred style of conventional warfare would be a potential recipe for nuclear escalation. Since the end of the Cold War, the United States’ signature approach to war has been simple: punch deep into enemy territory in order to rapidly knock out the opponent’s key military assets at minimal cost. But the Pentagon developed this formula in wars against Afghanistan, Iraq, Libya, and Serbia, none of which was a nuclear power.
China, by contrast, not only has nuclear weapons; it has also intermingled them with its conventional military forces, making it difficult to attack one without attacking the other. This means that a major U.S. military campaign targeting China’s conventional forces would likely also threaten its nuclear arsenal. Faced with such a threat, Chinese leaders could decide to use their nuclear weapons while they were still able to.
As U.S. and Chinese leaders navigate a relationship fraught with mutual suspicion, they must come to grips with the fact that a conventional war could skid into a nuclear confrontation. Although this risk is not high in absolute terms, its consequences for the region and the world would be devastating. As long as the United States and China continue to pursue their current grand strategies, the risk is likely to endure. This means that leaders on both sides should dispense with the illusion that they can easily fight a limited war. They should focus instead on managing or resolving the political, economic, and military tensions that might lead to a conflict in the first place. | 3,131 | <h4>US-China conventional war goes nuclear.</h4><p>[Caitlin <u><strong>Talmadge</u></strong> (10-15-20<u><strong>18</u></strong>), PhD in Political Science from MIT, BA in Government from Harvard, Professor of Security Studies at Georgetown University, “Beijing’s Nuclear Option,” Foreign Affairs, <u>https://www.foreignaffairs.com/articles/china/2018-10-15/beijings-nuclear-option]//recut</u> CHS PK</p><p><u><strong>As <mark>China’s power has grown</mark> in recent years, <mark>so</mark>, too, <mark>has</mark> the <mark>risk of war with the U</mark>nited <mark>S</mark>tates. Under President Xi Jinping, China has increased its political and economic pressure on Taiwan and built military installations on coral reefs in the South China Sea, fueling Washington’s fears that Chinese expansionism will threaten U.S. allies and influence in the region. U.S. destroyers have transited the Taiwan Strait, to loud protests from Beijing. American policymakers have wondered aloud whether they should send an aircraft carrier through the strait as well. Chinese fighter jets have intercepted U.S. aircraft in the skies above the South China Sea. Meanwhile, U.S. President Donald Trump has brought long-simmering economic disputes to a rolling boil. </p><p></u></strong>A war between the two countries remains unlikely, but <u><strong><mark>the prospect of a</mark> military <mark>confrontation</u></strong></mark>—resulting, for example, from a Chinese campaign against Taiwan—no longer seems as implausible as it once did. And the odds of such a confrontation <u><strong><mark>going nuclear are high</mark>er than most policymakers and analysts think. </p><p></u></strong>Members of China’s strategic com<u><strong>munity tend to dismiss such concerns. Likewise, U.S. studies of a potential war with China often exclude nuclear weapons from the analysis entirely, treating them as basically irrelevant to the course of a conflict. Asked about the issue in 2015, Dennis Blair, the former commander of U.S. forces in the Indo-Pacific, estimated the likelihood of a U.S.-Chinese nuclear crisis as “somewhere between nil and zero.” </p><p></u></strong>This <u><strong>assurance is misguided. If deployed against China, <mark>the Pentagon’s preferred style of</mark> conventional <mark>warfare would</mark> <mark>be a</mark> potential <mark>recipe for nuclear escalation</mark>.</u></strong> Since the end of the Cold War, <u><strong>the United States’ signature approach to war has been</u></strong> simple: <u><strong>punch deep into enemy territory in order to rapidly knock out the opponent’s key military assets at minimal cost. But <mark>the Pentagon developed this formula in wars against</mark> Afghanistan, Iraq, Libya, and Serbia, <mark>non</mark>e of which was a <mark>nuclear power</mark>. </p><p><mark>China</u></strong></mark>, by contrast, <u><strong>not only <mark>has nuclear weapons</mark>; it has also <mark>intermingled</mark> them <mark>with</mark> its <mark>conventional</mark> military <mark>forces</mark>, <mark>making it difficult to attack one without</mark> attacking <mark>the other</u></strong></mark>. This means that <u><strong><mark>a</mark> major <mark>U.S.</mark> military <mark>campaign targeting</mark> China’s <mark>conventional forces would</mark> likely also <mark>threaten its</mark> nuclear <mark>arsenal</u></strong></mark>. Faced with such a threat, <u><strong><mark>Chinese leaders could</mark> decide to <mark>use their</mark> nuclear <mark>weapons while they were still able to.</mark> </p><p>A</u></strong>s <u><strong>U.S. and Chinese</u></strong> leaders navigate a relationship fraught with mutual suspicion, they must come to grips with the fact that a <u><strong>conventional war could skid into a nuclear confrontation</u></strong>. Although this risk is not high in absolute terms<u><strong>, <mark>its consequences</mark> for the region and the world <mark>would be devastating</u></strong></mark>. As long as the United States and China continue to pursue their current grand strategies, the risk is likely to endure. This means that leaders on <u><strong>both sides should dispense with the illusion that they can easily fight a limited war</u></strong>. They should focus instead on managing or resolving the political, economic, and military tensions that might lead to a conflict in the first place.</p> | null | null | 1AC—War | 560 | 2,191 | 73,634 | ./documents/hsld20/Proof/Ra/Proof-Raghavan-Aff-Harvard-Westlake-Round3.docx | 871,867 | A | Harvard-Westlake | 3 | L C Anderson AR | Kumail Zaidi | AC- China
NC- T Racialized neolib K
1ar- all
2nr- K
2ar- case K | hsld20/Proof/Ra/Proof-Raghavan-Aff-Harvard-Westlake-Round3.docx | null | 73,678 | DhRa | Proof DhRa | null | Dh..... | Ra..... | null | null | 24,687 | Proof | Proof | CA | null | 1,028 | hsld20 | HS LD 2020-21 | 2,020 | ld | hs | 1 |
1,710,217 | No spread AND no impact | Schneider 20 | Jonas Schneider 20. Senior researcher at the Center for Security Studies, held post-doctoral fellowships at the German Institute for International and Security Affairs (SWP) in Berlin and at the CSS and worked as a research associate at the Institute for Security Policy at the University of Kiel, holds a PhD in Political Science from the University of Kiel. 2020. “Chapter 26 Nuclear Proliferation and International Security.” Understanding Global Politics: Actors and Themes in International Affairs, edited by Klaus Larres and Ruth Wittlinger, Routledge, pp. 409–425. | a bomb held great potential for stabilising an unbalanced and volatile Middle East despite the risks of proliferation, nuclear weapons, and the deterrent they provide contribut to what has been labelled ‘the Long Peace’ among the great powers since 1945 because nuclear proliferation is such a rare phenomenon, and since robust nonprolif measures tend to be disruptive, the net destabilising effect of new nuclear countries is quite small and, therefore, manageable
The word ‘spread’ appears to suggest that the established powers have provided other interested nations with (at least a few) operational nuclear warheads. Yet such transfers have never been undertaken. Certainly, states that sought nuclear weapons have often received assistance sometimes in the form of tech Nonetheless, all remained well below the weapons threshold in reality, the spread of nuclear weapons has meant that merely the ambition to possess a nuclear arsenal has spread
Importantly, since a state’s national efforts to turn its desire into reality naturally span many) years prolif must be conceived of as a process 29 of 39 that have embarked upon that path have not acquired a arsenal
owing to the technological institutional and managerial challenges of the task nations simply failed in their efforts several states have undertaken a ‘nuclear reversal’, abandoning their weapons activities | bomb stabilising despite risks deterrent contribut to Long Peace’ prolif is rare and robust measures disrupt the net effect is small
‘spread’ never undertaken remained below weapons
efforts span years 29 of 39 that embarked not acquired
owing to tech institutional and managerial challenges nations failed several undertake nuclear reversal’, abandoning activities | Other analysts have sounded a much less alarmist tone, however. Some scholars even suggested that an Iranian bomb held great potential for stabilising an unbalanced and volatile Middle East (Waltz, 2012). Closer to the mainstream of Western strategic discourse, various experts have argued that despite the risks of proliferation, nuclear weapons, and the deterrent they provide should get (more) credit for contributing, in combination with other factors, to what has been labelled ‘the Long Peace’ among the great powers since 1945 (Gaddis, 1999, p. 268–271; Gavin, 2012a, p. 164; Acton 2010, pp. 16–17). Still others have contended that because nuclear proliferation is such a rare phenomenon, and since robust nonproliferation measures tend to be disruptive, the net destabilising effect of new nuclear countries is quite small and, therefore, manageable (Mueller 2010, pp. 95–99; Hymans 2013, pp. 293–296).
The question of whether nuclear proliferation has stabilising or destabilising effects is not just fascinating for scholars of the nuclear age, but also highly consequential for practical policy issues. For in order to debate the merits of particular policy choices – such as preventive military strikes against nuclear facilities, grand bargains with potential proliferators or complete nuclear disarmament – we need to understand first how the spread of nuclear weapons impacts regional and global security.
The chapter proceeds in three steps. The first section provides the foundation for the other parts by summarising what we know about empirical patterns of proliferation and the utility of nuclear weapons for statecraft. The second section then engages the literature on the consequences of proliferation, focusing in particular on how proliferation has influenced international stability. The final section explores whether some states have been more affected than others, and what measures these states have taken to prevent proliferation, or at least mitigate its negative consequences.
Patterns of nuclear proliferation and the utility of nuclear weapons
Nuclear proliferation is commonly defined as the spread of nuclear weapons to states that did not previously have them. Within a broader conceptual framework that is rarely used by scholars, yet popular in the arms control community, this diffusion of nuclear weapons to additional states is labelled horizontal proliferation. It is conceptually accompanied by the notion of vertical proliferation, which refers to qualitative improvements and increases in the number of nuclear weapons in the stockpiles of existing nuclear weapon states. In accordance with the typical usage of the term in the scholarly debate, this chapter focuses only on how the horizontal proliferation of nuclear weapons affects international stability.
One important empirical pattern that has shaped how nuclear proliferation is understood concerns the way in which nuclear weapons have spread. The word ‘spread’ appears to suggest that the established nuclear powers have provided other interested nations with (at least a few) operational nuclear warheads. Yet such transfers have never been undertaken. Certainly, states that sought nuclear weapons have often received significant assistance from other nations (Schofield, 2014; Fuhrmann, 2012), sometimes in the form of highly sensitive technologies (Kroenig, 2010). Nonetheless, since all these transfers remained well below the weapons threshold, nations seeking nuclear weapons always had to build them indigenously. Hence, in reality, the spread of nuclear weapons has meant that merely the ambition to possess a nuclear arsenal has spread to additional states, each of which then had to pursue that goal primarily through indigenous efforts.
Importantly, since a state’s national efforts to turn its desire for nuclear weapons into reality naturally span several (and sometimes many) years, nuclear proliferation must be conceived of as a process, as opposed to just a single step (Meyer, 1986). This point is reinforced by the fact that 29 out of 39 states that have embarked upon that path (Müller and Schmidt, 2010, p. 157; Mikoyan, 2012; Santoro, 2017) have not acquired a nuclear arsenal. Hence, a lot of nuclear proliferation activity has been undertaken by nations that did not ultimately become nuclear weapon states. Three patterns explain this situation.
First, owing not just to the technological, but also the institutional and managerial challenges of the task, some nations simply failed in their efforts to build the bomb (Hymans, 2012; Braut-Hegghammer, 2016). Second, a few countries have chosen a nuclear ‘hedging’ strategy, intentionally confining their efforts to developing the technological capability to build an arsenal quickly while refraining from exercising that option (Narang, 2016–17, p. 134). Third, several states have undertaken a ‘nuclear reversal’, abandoning their nuclear weapons activities before developing nuclear explosive devices (Müller and Schmidt, 2010). | 5,014 | <h4>No spread AND no impact</h4><p>Jonas <strong>Schneider 20</strong>. Senior researcher at the Center for Security Studies, held post-doctoral fellowships at the German Institute for International and Security Affairs (SWP) in Berlin and at the CSS and worked as a research associate at the Institute for Security Policy at the University of Kiel, holds a PhD in Political Science from the University of Kiel. 2020. “Chapter 26 Nuclear Proliferation and International Security.” Understanding Global Politics: Actors and Themes in International Affairs, edited by Klaus Larres and Ruth Wittlinger, Routledge, pp. 409–425.</p><p>Other analysts have sounded a much less alarmist tone, however. Some scholars even suggested that <u><strong>a</u></strong>n Iranian <u><mark>bomb </mark>held great potential for <strong><mark>stabilising</u></strong></mark> <u>an</u> <u><strong>unbalanced</u></strong> <u>and</u> <u><strong>volatile</u></strong> <u>Middle East</u> (Waltz, 2012). Closer to the mainstream of Western strategic discourse, various experts have argued that <u><mark>despite</mark> the <strong><mark>risks</u></strong></mark> <u>of proliferation, nuclear weapons, and the <strong><mark>deterrent</strong></mark> they provide</u> should get (more) credit for <u><strong><mark>contribut</u></strong></mark>ing, in combination with other factors, <u><mark>to</mark> what has been labelled ‘the</u> <u><strong><mark>Long Peace’</u></strong></mark> <u>among the great powers since 1945</u> (Gaddis, 1999, p. 268–271; Gavin, 2012a, p. 164; Acton 2010, pp. 16–17). Still others have contended that <u>because nuclear <strong><mark>prolif</strong></mark>eration <mark>is</mark> such a <strong><mark>rare</strong></mark> phenomenon, <mark>and</mark> since <strong><mark>robust</mark> nonprolif</u></strong>eration <u><mark>measures</mark> <strong>tend</strong> to be</u> <u><strong><mark>disrupt</strong></mark>ive, <mark>the</u> <u><strong>net</mark> destabilising <mark>effect</u></strong></mark> <u>of new nuclear countries <mark>is</mark> <strong>quite <mark>small</u></strong></mark> <u>and, therefore,</u> <u><strong>manageable</u></strong> (Mueller 2010, pp. 95–99; Hymans 2013, pp. 293–296).</p><p>The question of whether nuclear proliferation has stabilising or destabilising effects is not just fascinating for scholars of the nuclear age, but also highly consequential for practical policy issues. For in order to debate the merits of particular policy choices – such as preventive military strikes against nuclear facilities, grand bargains with potential proliferators or complete nuclear disarmament – we need to understand first how the spread of nuclear weapons impacts regional and global security.</p><p>The chapter proceeds in three steps. The first section provides the foundation for the other parts by summarising what we know about empirical patterns of proliferation and the utility of nuclear weapons for statecraft. The second section then engages the literature on the consequences of proliferation, focusing in particular on how proliferation has influenced international stability. The final section explores whether some states have been more affected than others, and what measures these states have taken to prevent proliferation, or at least mitigate its negative consequences.</p><p>Patterns of nuclear proliferation and the utility of nuclear weapons</p><p>Nuclear proliferation is commonly defined as the spread of nuclear weapons to states that did not previously have them. Within a broader conceptual framework that is rarely used by scholars, yet popular in the arms control community, this diffusion of nuclear weapons to additional states is labelled horizontal proliferation. It is conceptually accompanied by the notion of vertical proliferation, which refers to qualitative improvements and increases in the number of nuclear weapons in the stockpiles of existing nuclear weapon states. In accordance with the typical usage of the term in the scholarly debate, this chapter focuses only on how the horizontal proliferation of nuclear weapons affects international stability.</p><p>One important empirical pattern that has shaped how nuclear proliferation is understood concerns the way in which nuclear weapons have spread. <u>The word</u> <u><strong><mark>‘spread’</u></strong></mark> <u>appears to suggest that the <strong>established</u></strong> nuclear <u>powers have</u> <u><strong>provide</strong>d</u> <u>other interested nations with (at least a few) operational nuclear warheads.</u> <u><strong>Yet such transfers have <mark>never</mark> been <mark>undertaken</mark>.</u></strong> <u>Certainly, states that sought nuclear weapons have often received</u> significant <u><strong>assistance</u></strong> from other nations (Schofield, 2014; Fuhrmann, 2012), <u>sometimes in the form of</u> highly sensitive <u><strong>tech</u></strong>nologies (Kroenig, 2010). <u>Nonetheless,</u> since <u><strong>all</u></strong> these transfers <u><mark>remained</u></mark> <u><strong>well <mark>below</u></strong></mark> <u>the</u> <u><strong><mark>weapons</mark> threshold</u></strong>, nations seeking nuclear weapons always had to build them indigenously. Hence, <u>in reality, the spread of nuclear weapons has meant that merely the <strong>ambition</u></strong> <u>to possess a nuclear arsenal has spread</u> to additional states, each of which then had to pursue that goal primarily through indigenous efforts.</p><p><u>Importantly, since a state’s national <mark>efforts</mark> to turn its</u> <u><strong>desire</u></strong> for nuclear weapons <u>into</u> <u><strong>reality</u></strong> <u>naturally <mark>span</u></mark> several (and sometimes <u><strong>many) <mark>years</u></strong></mark>, nuclear <u><strong>prolif</u></strong>eration <u>must be conceived of as a</u> <u><strong>process</u></strong>, as opposed to just a single step (Meyer, 1986). This point is reinforced by the fact that <u><strong><mark>29</u></strong></mark> out <u><strong><mark>of 39</u></strong></mark> states <u><mark>that</mark> have</u> <u><strong><mark>embarked</u></strong></mark> <u>upon that path</u> (Müller and Schmidt, 2010, p. 157; Mikoyan, 2012; Santoro, 2017) <u>have</u> <u><strong><mark>not acquired</mark> a</u></strong> nuclear <u><strong>arsenal</u></strong>. Hence, a lot of nuclear proliferation activity has been undertaken by nations that did not ultimately become nuclear weapon states. Three patterns explain this situation.</p><p>First, <u><mark>owing</u></mark> not just <u><mark>to</mark> the</u> <u><strong><mark>tech</mark>nological</u></strong>, but also the <u><strong><mark>institutional</u></strong> <u>and</u> <u><strong>managerial challenges</u></strong></mark> <u>of the task</u>, some <u><mark>nations</mark> simply <strong><mark>failed</mark> in their efforts</u></strong> to build the bomb (Hymans, 2012; Braut-Hegghammer, 2016). Second, a few countries have chosen a nuclear ‘hedging’ strategy, intentionally confining their efforts to developing the technological capability to build an arsenal quickly while refraining from exercising that option (Narang, 2016–17, p. 134). Third, <u><mark>several</mark> states have <strong><mark>undertake</strong></mark>n a ‘<mark>nuclear <strong>reversal’</strong>, <strong>abandoning</u></strong></mark> <u>their</u> nuclear <u>weapons <mark>activities</u></mark> before developing nuclear explosive devices (Müller and Schmidt, 2010).</p> | 2AC | OFF | AT: Prolif Impact | 5,629 | 191 | 50,809 | ./documents/ndtceda20/Kentucky/IvDi/Kentucky-Ivackovic-Di-Aff-Kentucky-Round2.docx | 619,197 | A | Kentucky | 2 | Johnson Community College BB | Shree Asware | 1AC Preemption
1NC T Defense Pact T With T Substantial Limits NFU CP Boost Phase CP Assurance DA Deterrence DA India DA Case
2NC T Defense Pact Case
1NR Assurances DA
2NR Assurance DA Case | ndtceda20/Kentucky/IvDi/Kentucky-Ivackovic-Di-Aff-Kentucky-Round2.docx | null | 52,344 | IvDi | Kentucky IvDi | null | Al..... | Iv..... | Jo..... | Di..... | 19,330 | Kentucky | Kentucky | null | null | 1,010 | ndtceda20 | NDT/CEDA 2020-21 | 2,020 | cx | college | 2 |
1,742,674 | Externally—Ukraine escalation spills over to Central Asia from refugee flows—extinction. | Lizan 15 | Lizan 15—(JD, National University Odesa Law Academy, article was originally published in Odnako, a Russian foreign policy magazine, URL is to a translation). Ivan Lizan. “Three Fronts For Russia: How Washington Will Fan The Flames of Chaos In Central Asia.” Information Clearinghouse. February 23. http://tinyurl.com/pn3kpgy. | If the war in Ukraine leads to millions of refugees, tens of thousands of deaths, and the destruction of cities, defrosting the Karabakh conflict will completely undermine Russia’s entire foreign policy in the Caucasus. Every city in Central Asia is under threat of explosions and attacks. So far “up-and-coming front” but this theater of war could be one of the most complex after the conflict in the Ukraine. widespread destabilization in Central Asia on the borders of Russia, India, China, and Iran start full-scale war which will inevitably follow once chaos engulfs the region involving a third of the world’s population and all the United States’ geopolitical rivals. an opportunity Washington will find too good to miss. if Ukraine is a fuse of war, Central Asia is a munitions depot. If it blows up, half the continent will be hit | If Ukraine leads to millions of refugees deaths, and destruction of cities, defrosting the Karabakh conflict will undermine Russia’s fo po in the Caucasus. Every city in Central Asia is under threat of attacks. So far “up-and-coming ” this theater could be one of the most complex after Ukraine. widespread destabilization on borders of Russia, India, China, and Iran start full-scale war involving a third of the world and all U S rivals. if Ukraine is a fuse of war, Central Asia is a munitions depot half the continent will be hit | If the war in Ukraine leads to millions of refugees, tens of thousands of deaths, and the destruction of cities, defrosting the Karabakh conflict will completely undermine Russia’s entire foreign policy in the Caucasus. Every city in Central Asia is under threat of explosions and attacks. So far this “up-and-coming front” has attracted the least media coverage – Novorossiya dominates on national television channels, in newspapers, and on websites –, but this theater of war could become one of the most complex after the conflict in the Ukraine. A subsidiary of the Caliphate under Russia’s belly The indisputable trend in Afghanistan – and the key source of instability in the region – is to an alliance between the Taliban and the Islamic State. Even so, the formation of their union is in its early days, references to it are scarce and fragmentary, and the true scale of the activities of the IS emissaries is unclear, like an iceberg whose tip barely shows above the surface of the water. But it has been established that IS agitators are active in Pakistan and in Afghanistan’s southern provinces, which are controlled by the Taliban. But, in this case, the first victim of chaos in Afghanistan is Pakistan, which at the insistence of, and with help from, the United States nurtured the Taliban in the 1980s. That project has taken on a life of its own and is a recurring nightmare for Islamabad, which has decided to establish a friendlier relationship China and Russia. This trend can be seen in the Taliban’s attacks on Pakistani schools, whose teachers now have the right to carry guns, regular arrests of terrorists in the major cities, and the start of activities in support of tribes hostile to the Taliban in the north. The latest legislative development in Pakistan is a constitutional amendment to expand military court jurisdiction [over civilians]. Throughout the country, terrorists, Islamists and their sympathizers are being detained. In the northwest alone, more than 8,000 arrests have been made, including members of the clergy. Religious organizations have been banned and IS emissaries are being caught. Since the Americans do not like putting all their eggs in one basket, they will provide support to the government in Kabul, which will allow them to remain in the country legitimately, and at the same time to the Taliban, which is transforming itself into IS. The outcome will be a state of chaos in which the Americans will not formally take part; instead, they will sit back on their military bases, waiting to see who wins. And then Washington will provide assistance to the victor. Note that its security services have been supporting the Taliban for a long time and quite effectively: some of the official security forces and police in Afghanistan are former Taliban and Mujahideen. Method of destruction The first way to destabilize Central Asia is to create problems on the borders, along with the threat that Mujahideen will penetrate the region. The testing of the neighbours has already started; problems have arisen in Turkmenistan, which has even had to ask Kabul to hold large-scale military operations in the border provinces. Tajikistan has forced the Taliban to negotiate the release of the border guards it abducted, and the Tajik border service reports that there is a large group of Mujahideen on its borders. In general, all the countries bordering Afghanistan have stepped up their border security. The second way is to send Islamists behind the lines. The process has already begun: the number of extremists in Tajikistan alone grew three-fold last year; however, even though they are being caught, it obviously will not be feasible to catch all of them. Furthermore, the situation is aggravated by the return of migrant workers from Russia, which will expand the recruiting base. If the stream of remittances from Russia dries up, the outcome may be popular discontent and managed riots. Kyrgyz expert Kadir Malikov reports that $70 million has been allocated to the IS military group Maverenahr, which includes representatives of all the Central Asian republics, to carry out acts of terrorism in the region. Special emphasis is placed on the Fergana Valley as the heart of Central Asia. Another point of vulnerability is Kyrgyzstan’s parliamentary elections, scheduled for this fall. The initiation of a new set of color revolutions will lead to chaos and the disintegration of countries. Self-supporting wars Waging war is expensive, so the destabilization of the region must be self-supporting or at least profitable for the U.S. military-industrial complex. And in this area Washington has had some success: it has given Uzbekistan 328 armored vehicles that Kiev had requested for its war with Novorossiya. At first glance, the deal isn’t profitable because the machines were a gift, but in reality Uzbekistan will be tied to U.S. spare parts and ammunition. Washington made a similar decision on the transfer of equipment and weapons to Islamabad. But the United States has not been successful in its attempts to impose its weapons systems on India: the Indians have not signed any contracts, and Obama was shown Russian military hardware when he attended a military parade. Thus the United States is drawing the countries in the region into war with its own protégés – the Taliban and Islamic State – and at the same time is supplying its enemies with weapons. *** So 2015 will be marked by preparations for widespread destabilization in Central Asia and the transformation of AfPak into an Islamic State subsidiary on the borders of Russia, India, China, and Iran. The start of full-scale war, which will inevitably follow once chaos engulfs the region, will lead to a bloodbath in the “Eurasian Balkans,” automatically involving more than a third of the world’s population and almost all the United States’ geopolitical rivals. It’s an opportunity Washington will find too good to miss. Russia’s response to this challenge has to be multifaceted: involving the region in the process of Eurasian integration, providing military, economic, and political assistance, working closely with its allies in the Shanghai Cooperation Organization and the BRICS, strengthening the Pakistani army, and of course assisting with the capture of the bearded servants of the Caliphate. But the most important response should be the accelerated modernization of its armed forces as well as those of its allies and efforts to strengthen the Collective Security Treaty Organization and give it the right to circumvent the highly inefficient United Nations. The region is extremely important: if Ukraine is a fuse of war, then Central Asia is a munitions depot. If it blows up, half the continent will be hit. | 6,754 | <h4>Externally—Ukraine escalation <u>spills over</u> to Central Asia from <u>refugee flows</u>—<u>extinction</u>.</h4><p><u><strong>Lizan 15</u></strong>—(JD, National University Odesa Law Academy, article was originally published in Odnako, a Russian foreign policy magazine, URL is to a translation). Ivan Lizan. “Three Fronts For Russia: How Washington Will Fan The Flames of Chaos In Central Asia.” Information Clearinghouse. February 23. http://tinyurl.com/pn3kpgy.</p><p><u><strong><mark>If</mark> the war in <mark>Ukraine leads to millions of refugees</mark>, tens of thousands of <mark>deaths, and</mark> the <mark>destruction of cities, defrosting the Karabakh conflict will </mark>completely <mark>undermine Russia’s </mark>entire <mark>fo</mark>reign <mark>po</mark>licy <mark>in the Caucasus. Every city in</u></strong></mark> <u><strong><mark>Central Asia</u></strong> <u><strong>is under threat of</mark> explosions and <mark>attacks. So far </u></strong></mark>this<u><strong><mark> “up-and-coming </mark>front<mark>”</u></strong></mark> has attracted the least media coverage – Novorossiya dominates on national television channels, in newspapers, and on websites –, <u><strong>but <mark>this</u></strong> <u><strong>theater </mark>of war <mark>could be</u></strong></mark>come<u><strong><mark> one of the most complex after</mark> the conflict in the <mark>Ukraine.</mark> </u></strong>A subsidiary of the Caliphate under Russia’s belly The indisputable trend in Afghanistan – and the key source of instability in the region – is to an alliance between the Taliban and the Islamic State. Even so, the formation of their union is in its early days, references to it are scarce and fragmentary, and the true scale of the activities of the IS emissaries is unclear, like an iceberg whose tip barely shows above the surface of the water. But it has been established that IS agitators are active in Pakistan and in Afghanistan’s southern provinces, which are controlled by the Taliban. But, in this case, the first victim of chaos in Afghanistan is Pakistan, which at the insistence of, and with help from, the United States nurtured the Taliban in the 1980s. That project has taken on a life of its own and is a recurring nightmare for Islamabad, which has decided to establish a friendlier relationship China and Russia. This trend can be seen in the Taliban’s attacks on Pakistani schools, whose teachers now have the right to carry guns, regular arrests of terrorists in the major cities, and the start of activities in support of tribes hostile to the Taliban in the north. The latest legislative development in Pakistan is a constitutional amendment to expand military court jurisdiction [over civilians]. Throughout the country, terrorists, Islamists and their sympathizers are being detained. In the northwest alone, more than 8,000 arrests have been made, including members of the clergy. Religious organizations have been banned and IS emissaries are being caught. Since the Americans do not like putting all their eggs in one basket, they will provide support to the government in Kabul, which will allow them to remain in the country legitimately, and at the same time to the Taliban, which is transforming itself into IS. The outcome will be a state of chaos in which the Americans will not formally take part; instead, they will sit back on their military bases, waiting to see who wins. And then Washington will provide assistance to the victor. Note that its security services have been supporting the Taliban for a long time and quite effectively: some of the official security forces and police in Afghanistan are former Taliban and Mujahideen. Method of destruction The first way to destabilize Central Asia is to create problems on the borders, along with the threat that Mujahideen will penetrate the region. The testing of the neighbours has already started; problems have arisen in Turkmenistan, which has even had to ask Kabul to hold large-scale military operations in the border provinces. Tajikistan has forced the Taliban to negotiate the release of the border guards it abducted, and the Tajik border service reports that there is a large group of Mujahideen on its borders. In general, all the countries bordering Afghanistan have stepped up their border security. The second way is to send Islamists behind the lines. The process has already begun: the number of extremists in Tajikistan alone grew three-fold last year; however, even though they are being caught, it obviously will not be feasible to catch all of them. Furthermore, the situation is aggravated by the return of migrant workers from Russia, which will expand the recruiting base. If the stream of remittances from Russia dries up, the outcome may be popular discontent and managed riots. Kyrgyz expert Kadir Malikov reports that $70 million has been allocated to the IS military group Maverenahr, which includes representatives of all the Central Asian republics, to carry out acts of terrorism in the region. Special emphasis is placed on the Fergana Valley as the heart of Central Asia. Another point of vulnerability is Kyrgyzstan’s parliamentary elections, scheduled for this fall. The initiation of a new set of color revolutions will lead to chaos and the disintegration of countries. Self-supporting wars Waging war is expensive, so the destabilization of the region must be self-supporting or at least profitable for the U.S. military-industrial complex. And in this area Washington has had some success: it has given Uzbekistan 328 armored vehicles that Kiev had requested for its war with Novorossiya. At first glance, the deal isn’t profitable because the machines were a gift, but in reality Uzbekistan will be tied to U.S. spare parts and ammunition. Washington made a similar decision on the transfer of equipment and weapons to Islamabad. But the United States has not been successful in its attempts to impose its weapons systems on India: the Indians have not signed any contracts, and Obama was shown Russian military hardware when he attended a military parade. Thus the United States is drawing the countries in the region into war with its own protégés – the Taliban and Islamic State – and at the same time is supplying its enemies with weapons. *** So 2015 will be marked by preparations for <u><strong><mark>widespread destabilization </mark>in Central Asia</u></strong> and the transformation of AfPak into an Islamic State subsidiary <u><strong><mark>on </mark>the <mark>borders of Russia, India, China, and Iran</u></strong></mark>. The <u><strong><mark>start</u></strong></mark> of <u><strong><mark>full-scale war</u></strong></mark>, <u><strong>which will inevitably follow</u></strong> <u><strong>once chaos engulfs the region</u></strong>, will lead to a bloodbath in the “Eurasian Balkans,” automatically <u><strong><mark>involving</u></strong></mark> more than <u><strong><mark>a third of the world</mark>’s population<mark> and</u></strong></mark> almost <u><strong><mark>all</mark> the <mark>U</mark>nited <mark>S</mark>tates’ geopolitical <mark>rivals.</mark> </u></strong>It’s <u><strong>an opportunity Washington will find too good to miss.</u></strong> Russia’s response to this challenge has to be multifaceted: involving the region in the process of Eurasian integration, providing military, economic, and political assistance, working closely with its allies in the Shanghai Cooperation Organization and the BRICS, strengthening the Pakistani army, and of course assisting with the capture of the bearded servants of the Caliphate. But the most important response should be the accelerated modernization of its armed forces as well as those of its allies and efforts to strengthen the Collective Security Treaty Organization and give it the right to circumvent the highly inefficient United Nations. The region is extremely important: <u><strong><mark>if Ukraine is a fuse of war,</u></strong></mark> then <u><strong><mark>Central Asia is a munitions depot</mark>. If it blows up, <mark>half the continent will be hit</u></strong></mark>.</p> | Ukraine/Georgia: 1AC | null | Ukraine: 1AC | 8,864 | 232 | 51,570 | ./documents/ndtceda20/Minnesota/AmSu/Minnesota-Amundsen-Sun-Aff-9-MN-Round2.docx | 620,418 | A | 9-MN | 2 | Samford EG | Heather Hall | 1AC-Ukraine Georgia
1NC-T Iran Da Consult CP EU Da
2NR-Iran Da | ndtceda20/Minnesota/AmSu/Minnesota-Amundsen-Sun-Aff-9-MN-Round2.docx | null | 52,400 | AmSu | Minnesota AmSu | null | Ab..... | Am..... | Ke..... | Su..... | 19,336 | Minnesota | Minnesota | null | null | 1,010 | ndtceda20 | NDT/CEDA 2020-21 | 2,020 | cx | college | 2 |