|
{ |
|
"paper_id": "P83-1010", |
|
"header": { |
|
"generated_with": "S2ORC 1.0.0", |
|
"date_generated": "2023-01-19T09:19:26.019404Z" |
|
}, |
|
"title": "A FOUNDATION FOR SEMANTIC INTERPRETATION", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Graeme", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Hirst", |
|
"suffix": "", |
|
"affiliation": { |
|
"laboratory": "", |
|
"institution": "Brown University Providence", |
|
"location": { |
|
"postCode": "02912", |
|
"region": "RI" |
|
} |
|
}, |
|
"email": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": "", |
|
"venue": null, |
|
"identifiers": {}, |
|
"abstract": "Traditionally, translation from the parse tree representing a sentence to a semantic representation (such as frames or procedural semantics) has a/ways been the most ad hoc part of natural language understand-\u2022ng (NLU) systems. However, recent advances in linguistics, most notably the system of formal semantics known as Montague semantics, suggest ways of putting NLU semantics onto a cleaner and firmer foundation. We are using a Montague-inspired approach to semantics in an integrated NL U and pro blem-solving system that we are building. Like Montague's, our semantics are compositional by design and strongly typed, with semantic rules in one-to-one correspondence with the meaning-affecting rules of a Marcus-style parser. We have replaced Montague's semantic objects, functors and truth conditions, with the elements of the frame language Frail, and added a word sense and case slot disambiguation system. The result is a foundation for semantic interpretation that we believe to be superior ~o previous approaches.", |
|
"pdf_parse": { |
|
"paper_id": "P83-1010", |
|
"_pdf_hash": "", |
|
"abstract": [ |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Traditionally, translation from the parse tree representing a sentence to a semantic representation (such as frames or procedural semantics) has a/ways been the most ad hoc part of natural language understand-\u2022ng (NLU) systems. However, recent advances in linguistics, most notably the system of formal semantics known as Montague semantics, suggest ways of putting NLU semantics onto a cleaner and firmer foundation. We are using a Montague-inspired approach to semantics in an integrated NL U and pro blem-solving system that we are building. Like Montague's, our semantics are compositional by design and strongly typed, with semantic rules in one-to-one correspondence with the meaning-affecting rules of a Marcus-style parser. We have replaced Montague's semantic objects, functors and truth conditions, with the elements of the frame language Frail, and added a word sense and case slot disambiguation system. The result is a foundation for semantic interpretation that we believe to be superior ~o previous approaches.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Abstract", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"body_text": [ |
|
{ |
|
"text": "By semantic interpretation we mean the process of mapping from a syntactically analyzed sentence of natural language to a representation of its meaning. We exclude from semantic interpretation any consideration of discourse pragmatics; rather, discourse pragmatics operate upon the output of the semantic interpreter. We also exclude syntactic analysis; the integration of syntactic and semantic analysis becomes very messy when complex syntactic constructions are considered, and, moreover, it is our observation that those who argue for the integration of the two are usually arguing for subordinating the role of syntax, a position we reject. This is not to say that parsing can get by without semantic help; indirect object finding, and prepositional phrase and relative clause attachment, for example, often require semantic knowledge.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "I. Introduction", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Below we will show that syntax and semantics may work well together while remaining distinct modules.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "I. Introduction", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Research on semantic interpretation in artificial intelligence goes back to Woods's dissertation (1967 Woods's dissertation ( , 1968 , which introduced procedural semantics in a natural-language front-end for an airline reservation system. Woods's system had rules with patterns that, when they matched part of the parsed input sentence, contributed a string to the semantic representation of the sentence. This string was usually constructed from the terminals of the matched parse tree fragment. The strings were combined to form a procedure call that, when evaluated, entered or retrieved the appropriate database information. This approach is still the predominant one today, and even though it has been refined over the years, semantic interpretation remains perhaps the least understood and most ad hoc area of natural language understanding (NLU).I However, recent advances in linguistics, most notably Montague semantics (Montague 1973; Dowry, Wall and Peters 1981) , suggest ways of putting NLU semantic interpretation on a cleaner and firmer foundation than it now is. In this paper, we describe such a foundation. 2", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 76, |
|
"end": 102, |
|
"text": "Woods's dissertation (1967", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 103, |
|
"end": 132, |
|
"text": "Woods's dissertation ( , 1968", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 929, |
|
"end": 944, |
|
"text": "(Montague 1973;", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF29" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 945, |
|
"end": 973, |
|
"text": "Dowry, Wall and Peters 1981)", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "I. Introduction", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "In his well-known \"PTQ\" paper (Montague 1973) , Richard Montague presented the complete syntax and semantics for a small fragment of English. Although it was limited in vocabulary and syntactic complexity, Montague's fragment dealt with such imporlit is also philosophically controversial. For discussion, see Fodor 1978 , Johnson-Laird 1978 , Fodor 1979 , and Wilks 1982 is not the only current work with this Ko~tl; in Section 7 we discuse other similarly motivated work, tant semantic problems as opaque contexts, different types of predication with the word be, and the \"the temperature is 90\" problem; 3 for details of these, see Dowty, Wall and Peters (1981) .", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 30, |
|
"end": 45, |
|
"text": "(Montague 1973)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF29" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 48, |
|
"end": 55, |
|
"text": "Richard", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 310, |
|
"end": 320, |
|
"text": "Fodor 1978", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF7" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 321, |
|
"end": 341, |
|
"text": ", Johnson-Laird 1978", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF25" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 342, |
|
"end": 354, |
|
"text": ", Fodor 1979", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF8" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 355, |
|
"end": 371, |
|
"text": ", and Wilks 1982", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF42" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 635, |
|
"end": 664, |
|
"text": "Dowty, Wall and Peters (1981)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF6" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Montague semantics", |
|
"sec_num": "2." |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Montague's semantic rules correspond to what we have been calling semantic interpretation. That is, in conjunction with a syntactic process, they produce a semantic representation, or translation, of a sentence.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Montague semantics", |
|
"sec_num": "2." |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "There are four important properties of Montague semantics that we will examine here.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Montague semantics", |
|
"sec_num": "2." |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Below, we will carry three of these properties over into our own semantics.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Montague semantics", |
|
"sec_num": "2." |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "The first property, the one that we will later drop, is that for Montague, semantic objects, the results of the semantic translation, were such things as individual concepts (which are functions to individuals from the cartesian product of points in time and possible worlds), properties of individual concepts, and functions of functions of functions of functions. At the top level, the meaning, of a sentence was a truth condition relative to a possible world and point in time. These semantic objects were represented by expressions of intensional logic; that is, instead of translating English directly into these objects, a sentence was first translated to an expression of intensional logic, for which, in turn, there existed an interpretation in terms of these semantic objects.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Montague semantics", |
|
"sec_num": "2." |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Second, Montague had a strong theory of types for his semantic objects: a set of types that corresponded to types of syntactic constituents. Thus, given a particular syntactic category, such as proper noun or adverb, Montague was able to say that the meaning of a constituent of that category was a semantic object of such and such a type. 4 Montague's system of types was recursively defined, with entities, truth values and intensions as primitives, and other types defined as functions from one type to another in such a manner that if syntactic category X was formed by adding category Y to category Z, then the type corresponding to g would be functions from senses of the type of 3That is, to ensure that \"The temperature is ~0 and the temperature is rising* cannot lead to the inference that \"90 is rising\". Y to the type of X. The first alternative is that the meaning of the whole is a function of not just the parts but also the situation in which the sentence is uttered. For example, the possessive in English is highly dependent upon pragmatics; the phrase Nadia's penguin could refer, in different circumstances, to the penguin that Nadia owns, to the one that she is carrying but doesn't actually own, or to the one that she just bet on at the penguin races. Our definition above of semantic interpretation excluded this sort of consideration, but this should not be regarded as uncontroversial.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Montague semantics", |
|
"sec_num": "2." |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "The second alternative to compositional semantics is that the meaning of the whole is not a systematic function of the parts in any reasonable sense of the word. This is exemplified by the interpretation of the word depart in Woods's original system, which varied greatly depending on the preposition it dominated (Woods 1967 :A-43-A-46). For example, the interpretation of the sentence:", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 314, |
|
"end": 325, |
|
"text": "(Woods 1967", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF45" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Montague semantics", |
|
"sec_num": "2." |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "AA-57 departs from Boston. That is, the semantic object into which depart is translated is the procedure depart. (AA-57 is an airline Right.) However, the addition of a prepositional phrase changes this; Table 1 shows the interpretation of the same sentence after wrious prepositional phrases have been appended. For example, the addition of ~o Chicago changes the translation of depart;", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 204, |
|
"end": 211, |
|
"text": "Table 1", |
|
"ref_id": "TABREF1" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Montague semantics", |
|
"sec_num": "2." |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "to connect, though the intended sense of the word is clearly unchanged, s This is necessitated by the particular set of database primitives that Woods used, selected for their being %tom/c\" (1967:7-4-7-11) rather than for promoting compositions/Sty. Rules in the system axe able to generate non-compositional representations because they have the power to set an arbitrarily complex parse tree as their trigger, and to return an axbitrary representation that could modify or completely ignore the components of the parse trees they are supposed to be interpreting/ For example, a rule can say (1967:A-44):", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Montague semantics", |
|
"sec_num": "2." |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "If you have a sentence whose subject is a flight, whose verb is leave or depart, and which has two (or more) prepositional phrases modifying the verb, one with /from and a place name, the other with a~ and a time, then the interpretation is equal (dtime (a, b), c), where a is the flight, b is the place, and c is the time.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Montague semantics", |
|
"sec_num": "2." |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Thus while Woods's semantics could probably be made \u2022 reasonably compositional simply by appropriate adjustment of the procedure calls into which sentences are translated, it would still not be compositional by design the way Montague semantics is.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Montague semantics", |
|
"sec_num": "2." |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "8~Ve have simplified a Little here in order to make our point. In fact, sentences like those in Table I with prepositional phrases will ~ctually cause the execution of two semantic rules: one for the complete sentence, and one for the sentence it happens to contain, A.A-57 depcrts from 8os~o~. The resulting interpretation will be the conjunction of the output from each rule (Woods 1967~9-5): AA-57 depLrts from Boston to Chicago.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 96, |
|
"end": 103, |
|
"text": "Table I", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Montague semantics", |
|
"sec_num": "2." |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Woods leaves it open (1967:9-7) a,s to how the semantic redundancy in such expressions should be handled, thou~,h one of hie suggestions is a filter that would remove conjuncts implied by others, giving, in this case, the interpretation shown in Table 1. 7Nor is there &nything that prevents the construction of rules that would result in conjunctions with conflicting, rather than merely redund~tnt, terms. AA-57 departs from Boston at 8:00am. equal (dtlme (aa-5T. boston), 8:00am) AA-57 departs from Boston after 8:00am. greater (dtime (aa-5T, boston), 8:00am) A.A-57 departs from Boston before 8:00am. greater (8:00am, dtlme (aa-5T. boston)) Although Montague semantics has much to recommend it, it is not possible, ho~vever, to implement it directly in a practical NLU system, for two reasons. The first is that Montague semantics as currently formulated is computationally impractical. It throws around huge sets, infinite objects, functions of functions, and piles of possible worlds with great abandon. Friedman, Moran and Warren (1978a) point out that in the smallest possible Montague system, one with. two entities and two points of reference, there are, for example, 22\"s= elements in the class of possible denotations of prepositions, each element being a set containing 2512 ordered pairs, s", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 1010, |
|
"end": 1044, |
|
"text": "Friedman, Moran and Warren (1978a)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF9" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 246, |
|
"end": 254, |
|
"text": "Table 1.", |
|
"ref_id": "TABREF1" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "depar~ (aa-ST, boston) and connec~ (aa-57. boston, c~icago)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "The second reason we can't use Montague semantics directly is that truth-conditional semantics are not useful in AI; A/uses know/edge semant.ics (Tarnawksy 1982) in which semantic objects tend to be symbols or expressions in a declarative or procedural knowledge representation system. Moreover, truth-conditional semantics really only deals with declarative sentences (Dowry eC al 1981:13) (though there has been work attempting to extend Montague's work to questions; e.g. Hamblin 1973 ); a practical NLU system needs to be able to deal with commands and questions as well as declarative sentences.", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 145, |
|
"end": 161, |
|
"text": "(Tarnawksy 1982)", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 475, |
|
"end": 487, |
|
"text": "Hamblin 1973", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF20" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "depar~ (aa-ST, boston) and connec~ (aa-57. boston, c~icago)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "There have, however, been attempts to take the intensional logic that Montague uses as an intermediate step in his translations, and give it a new interpretation in terms of AI-type semantic objects, thus preserving all other aspects of Montague's approach; see, for example, Hobbs and Rosenschein 1977, and Smith's (1979) objections to their approach. There has also been interest in using the intensional logic itself (or something similar) as an AI representation ~ (e.g. Moore 1981 ). But while it may be possible to make limited use of intensional logic expressions, I\u00b0 there are many problems that need to be solved before intensional logic or other flavors of logical forms could support the type of inference and problem solving that AI requires of its semantic representations; see Moore 1981 for a useful discussion. Moreover, Gallin (1975) has shown Montague's intensional logic to be incomplete. (See also the discussion in Section 7 of work using logical forms.)", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 276, |
|
"end": 285, |
|
"text": "Hobbs and", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF24" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 286, |
|
"end": 307, |
|
"text": "Rosenschein 1977, and", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF24" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 308, |
|
"end": 322, |
|
"text": "Smith's (1979)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF40" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 475, |
|
"end": 485, |
|
"text": "Moore 1981", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF30" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 837, |
|
"end": 850, |
|
"text": "Gallin (1975)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF14" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "depar~ (aa-ST, boston) and connec~ (aa-57. boston, c~icago)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Nevertheless, it is possible to use many aspects of Montague's approach in semantics in AI. The semantic interpreter that we describe below maintains three of the four properties of Montague semantics that we described above, and we therefore refer to it as \"Montague-inspired\". Our semantic interpreter is a component of a system that uses a frame-like representation for both story comprehension and problem-solving. The system includes a frame language, named Frail, a problem solver, and a discourse pragmatics component; further details may be found in , Wong 1981a , and Wong 1981b . The natural language front-end includes Paragram, a deterministic parser based on that of Marcus (1980) . Unlike Marcus's parser, Paragram has two types of rule: base phrase structure rules and transformational rules. It is also able to parse ungrammatical sentences; it always uses the rule that matches best, even if none match exactly. Paragram is described in Charniak 1983. 91tonically, Montague regarded intensional logic merely as a convenience in specifyin K his translation, and one that was completely irrelevant to the substance of his semantic theories. lOGodden (1981) in f~ct uses them for simple translation between Thai and English. aThe queJtion-m~rk prefix indicates & variable. Whenever a free v~iable in a frame is bound to a v~iable in a frame determiner, a unique new name is generated for that variable and its bindings. In this paper, we shall assume for simplicity that vaxiable names ~re maKically ~correct\" from the start.", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 558, |
|
"end": 570, |
|
"text": ", Wong 1981a", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 571, |
|
"end": 587, |
|
"text": ", and Wong 1981b", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF44" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 680, |
|
"end": 693, |
|
"text": "Marcus (1980)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF28" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 954, |
|
"end": 968, |
|
"text": "Charniak 1983.", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF4" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "depar~ (aa-ST, boston) and connec~ (aa-57. boston, c~icago)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "bDo not be misled by the fact that frames and frame determiners look similar. They He actually very different: the first is a gtatic data structure; the second is a frame retrieva~l procedure.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "depar~ (aa-ST, boston) and connec~ (aa-57. boston, c~icago)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "CAn instance is the result of evaluating a frame statement in Frail. It is a symbol that denotes the object referenced by the frame statement. To Absity, there is no distinction between the two; ~n instan.ce can be used wherever ~ frame Itatement c~n.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "depar~ (aa-ST, boston) and connec~ (aa-57. boston, c~icago)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "The semantic interpreter is named Absity (for reasons too obscure to burden the reader with). As we mentioned above, it retains three of the four properties of Montague semantics that we discussed. The property that we have dropped is, of course, truth conditionality and Montague's associated treasury of semantic objects. We have replaced them with AIstyle semantics, and our own repertory of objects, which are components of the frame language Frail. 11", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "depar~ (aa-ST, boston) and connec~ (aa-57. boston, c~icago)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "We do, however, retain a strong typing upon our semantic objects, that is, each syntactic category has an associated semantic type. Table 2 shows the types of components of Frail, how they may be combined, and examples of each; the nature of the components listed will become clearer with the examples in the next section. Table 3 gives the component of Frail that corresponds to each syntactic type. As a consequence of the kind of semantic objects we are dealing with, the system of types is not recursively defined in the Montague style, but we retain the idea that the type of a semantic object should be a function of the types of the components of that object.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 132, |
|
"end": 139, |
|
"text": "Table 2", |
|
"ref_id": "TABREF2" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 323, |
|
"end": 330, |
|
"text": "Table 3", |
|
"ref_id": "TABREF3" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "depar~ (aa-ST, boston) and connec~ (aa-57. boston, c~icago)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "We have also carried over from Montague semantics the operation of syntactic and semantic rules in tandem upon corresponding objects. However, it is not possible to maintain the one-to-one correspondence of rules when we replace Montague's simple syntax with the much larger English grammar of the Paragram parser. This is because in Montague's system each syntactic rule either creates a new node from old ones-for example, forming an intransitive verb phrase from a transitive verb and a noun phrase--or places a new llAlthou~h the object that represents a Sentence is \u2022 procedure call in Frail upon a knowledge basej this is not procedur~l sem~ntics in the strict Woods sense, as the mes~aing inheres not in the procedures but in the objects they manipulate.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "depar~ (aa-ST, boston) and connec~ (aa-57. boston, c~icago)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "node under an existing one--such as adding an adverb to an existing intransitive verb phrase. These are\" actions that clearly have semantic counterparts. When we start to add movement rules such as passivizatioa and dative movement to the grammar, we find ourselves with rules that have no clear semantic counterpart; indeed with rules that, it is often claimed (e.g. Chomsky 1965:132) , leave the meaning of a sentence quite unchanged.", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 368, |
|
"end": 385, |
|
"text": "Chomsky 1965:132)", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "depar~ (aa-ST, boston) and connec~ (aa-57. boston, c~icago)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "We therefore distinguish between parser rules that should have corresponding semantic rules and those that should not. As the above discussion suggests, rules that attach nodes are the ones that have semantic counterparts. In Paragram, these are the base structure rules. For this subset of the syntactic rules, semantic rules run in tandem, just as in Montague's semantics, m It is a consequence of the above properties of our semantic interpreter that we have also retained the property of compositionaiity by design. This follows from the uniform typing; the correspondence between syntactic and semantic rules that maintains this uniformity; and there being a unique semantic object corresponding to each word of English i~ (see Dowty e~ al 1981:180-181) . Unlike those of Woods's (1967) airline reservation system front-end discussed in Section 2, our semantic rules are very weak: they cannot change or ignore the components upon which they operate, nor can more than one rule volunteer an interpretation for any node of the parse tree. The power of the system comes from the nature of the semantic objects and the syntax-directed application of semantic rules, rather than from the semantic rules themselves.", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 353, |
|
"end": 376, |
|
"text": "Montague's semantics, m", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 733, |
|
"end": 758, |
|
"text": "Dowty e~ al 1981:180-181)", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 777, |
|
"end": 791, |
|
"text": "Woods's (1967)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF45" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "depar~ (aa-ST, boston) and connec~ (aa-57. boston, c~icago)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Some examples will make our semantic interpreter clearer. First, let's consider a simple noun phrase, the book. From Table 3 , the semantic type for the determiner She is a frame determiner function, in this case (the ?x), and the type for the noun book is a kind of frame, here (book ?x). These are combined 12In her synthesis of transformationa.l syntax with Monta6,ue acrostics, Partee (1973, 1975) observes that the semantic rule corresponding to many transformations will simply be the identity mapping.", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 389, |
|
"end": 395, |
|
"text": "(1973,", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 396, |
|
"end": 401, |
|
"text": "1975)", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 117, |
|
"end": 124, |
|
"text": "Table 3", |
|
"ref_id": "TABREF3" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Examples", |
|
"sec_num": "4." |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "13We show in Section 6 how this may be reconciled with lexical ambiguity.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Examples", |
|
"sec_num": "4." |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "in the canonical way--the frame name is added as an argument to the frame determiner function--and the result, (the ?x (book ?x)), is a Frail frame statement (which evaluates to an instance) that represents the unique book referred to. 14 A descriptive adjective corresponds to a slot-filler pair; for example, red is represented by (color=red), where color is the name of a slot and red is a frame instance, the name of a frame. A slot-filler pair can be added as an argument to a frame, so the red book would have the semantic interpretation (the ?x (book ?x (color=red))).", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Examples", |
|
"sec_num": "4." |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Now let's consider a complete sentence:", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Examples", |
|
"sec_num": "4." |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Nadia bought the book from a store in the mall. each word is unambiguous (we discuss our disambiguation procedures in Section 6); we also ignore the tense cn the verb. Table 5 shows the next four stages in the interpretation. First, noun phrases and their prepositions are combined, forming slot-filler pairs. Then the prepositional phrase in the mall can be attached to a store (since a noun phrase, being a frame, can have a slot-filler pair added to it), and the prepositional phrase from a store in the marl is formed. The third stage shown in the Table is the attachment of the slotfiller pairs for the three top-level prepositional phrases to the frame representing the verb. Finally, the period, which is translated as a frame determiner function, causes instantiation of the buy frame, and the translation is complete.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 168, |
|
"end": 175, |
|
"text": "Table 5", |
|
"ref_id": "TABREF6" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Examples", |
|
"sec_num": "4." |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "As we mentioned earlier, any parser will occasionally need semantic help. In Marcus-type parsers, this need occurs in rules that have the form \"If semantics prefers 14Note ~hat it is the responsibility\" of the frame system to determine with the help of the pragmatics module which one of the books that it m~ty know about is the correct one in context. ", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Semantic help for the parser", |
|
"sec_num": "5." |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "One problem that Montague semantics does not address is that of word disambiguation. Rather, there is assumed to exist a function that maps each word to a unique sense, and the semantic formalism operates on the values of this function.Is Clearly, however, a practical NLU system must take account of word sense ambiguity, and so we must add a disambiguation facility to our interpreter. Fortunately, the word translation function allows us to ~dd this facility transparently.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Word sense disambiguation", |
|
"sec_num": "6." |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Instead of simply mapping a word to an invariant unique sense, the function can map it to whatever sense is correct for a particular instance.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Word sense disambiguation", |
|
"sec_num": "6." |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Our disambiguation facility is called Polaroid Words. Is Each word in the system is represented by 16polaroid is a trademark of the Polaroid Corporation. ", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Word sense disambiguation", |
|
"sec_num": "6." |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "SUBJ Nadia (agent,= (the ?x (thlng ?x (propername=\"Nadla\"))))", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "ABSITY EXAMPLE (CONTINUED)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "OSJ the book (patlenl;=(the ?y (book ?y))) in the mall (loca~lon:C1;he ?~ (mall ?w))) a store in the mall (a ?z (s~core ?z (loca~ion=C~he ?w (mall ?w))))) from a store in the mall (source=Ca ?z (s~ore ?z (locatlon=(the ?w (mall ?W))))))", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "ABSITY EXAMPLE (CONTINUED)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "NaSa bought the book from a storein the mall (buy ?u (agent=(the ?x (thlng ?x (propername=\"Sadia\")))) (patient=(the ?y (book ?y))) (source=(a ?z (store ?z (location=(the ?w (m~ll ?w)))))))", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "ABSITY EXAMPLE (CONTINUED)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Nadia bought the book from a store in the mail. (a ?u (buy ?u (agenr,=(the ?x (thing ?x (propername=\" N adla\" ) ) ) ) (patient= (the ?y (book ?y))) (source=(a ?z (store ?z (locatlon=(1;he ?w (marl ?w))))))) a separate process that, by talking to other processes and by looking at paths made by spreading activation in the knowledge base, figures out the word's meaning. Each word is like a self-developing photograph that can be manipulated by the semantic interpreter even while the picture is forming; and if some other process needs to look at the picture (e.g. if the Semantic Enquiry Desk has an \"if semantics prefers ~ question from the parser), then a half-developed picture may provide enough information. Exactly the same process, without the spreading-activation phase, is used to disambiguate case roles as well. Polaroid Words are described more fully in Hirst and Charniak 1982 and Hirst 1983. 7 . Comparison with other work", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 867, |
|
"end": 876, |
|
"text": "Hirst and", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF22" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 877, |
|
"end": 894, |
|
"text": "Charniak 1982 and", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF23" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 895, |
|
"end": 908, |
|
"text": "Hirst 1983. 7", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "ABSITY EXAMPLE (CONTINUED)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Our approach to semantic interpretation may usefully be compared with other recent work with similar goals to ours. One such project is that of Jones and Warren (1982) , who attempt a conciliation between Montague semantics and a conceptual dependency representation (Schank 1975) . Their approach is to modify Montague's translation from English to intensional logic so that the resulting expressions have a canonical interpretation in conceptual dependency.", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 144, |
|
"end": 167, |
|
"text": "Jones and Warren (1982)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF26" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 267, |
|
"end": 280, |
|
"text": "(Schank 1975)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF36" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "ABSITY EXAMPLE (CONTINUED)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "They do not address such issues as extending Montague's syntax, nor whether their approach can be extended to deal with more modern Schankian representations (e.g. Schank 1982 ). Nevertheless, their work, which they describe as a hesitant first step, is similar in spirit to ours, and it will be interesting to see how it develops.", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 45, |
|
"end": 67, |
|
"text": "Montague's syntax, nor", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 164, |
|
"end": 175, |
|
"text": "Schank 1982", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF37" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "ABSITY EXAMPLE (CONTINUED)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Important recent work that extends the syntactic complexity of Montague's work is that on generalized phrase structure grammar (GPSG) (Gazdar 1982) . Such grammars combine a complex transformationfree syntax with Montague's semantics, the rules again operating in tandem. Gawron et al (1982) have implemented a database interface based on GFSG. In their system, the intensional logic of the semantic component is replaced by a simplified extensional logic, which, in turn, is translated into a query for database access. Schubert and Peiletier (1982) have also sought to simplify the semantic output of a GPSG to a more ~conventional\" logical form; and Rosenschein and Shieber (1982) describe a similar translation process into extensional logical forms, using a context-free grammar intended to be similar to a GPSG. Iv The GPSG approaches differ from ours in that their output is a logical form rather than an immediate representation of a semantic object; that is, the output is not tied to any representation of knowledge. In Gawron et al's system, the database provides an interpretation of the logical form, but only in a weak sense, as the form must first pass through another (apparently somewhat ad hoc) translation and disambiguati0n process. Nor do these approaches provide any semantic feedback to the parset. is These differences, however, are independent of the choice of GPSG; it should be easy, at least in principle, to modify these approaches to give Frail output, or, conversely, to replace Paragram in our system with a GPSG parser. 19", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 134, |
|
"end": 147, |
|
"text": "(Gazdar 1982)", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 272, |
|
"end": 291, |
|
"text": "Gawron et al (1982)", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 521, |
|
"end": 550, |
|
"text": "Schubert and Peiletier (1982)", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 653, |
|
"end": 683, |
|
"text": "Rosenschein and Shieber (1982)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF35" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "ABSITY EXAMPLE (CONTINUED)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "The PSX-KLON~-system of Webber (1980a, 1980b) also has a close coupling between syntax and semantics. Rather than operating in tandem, though, the two are described as \"cascaded', with an ATN parser handing constituents to a semantic interpreter, which is allowed to return them (causing the ATN to back up) if the purser's choice is found to be semantically untenable. Otherwise, a process of incremental description refinement is used to interpret the constituent; this relies on the fact that the syntactic constituents are represented in the same formalism, KL-OSZ (Brachman 1978) , as the system's knowledge base. The semantic interpreter uses projection rules to form an interpretation in a language called JAaGON, which is then translated into KL-ONZ. Bobrow and Webber are particularly concerned with using this framework to determine the combinatoric relationship between quantifiers in a sentence.", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 24, |
|
"end": 45, |
|
"text": "Webber (1980a, 1980b)", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 569, |
|
"end": 584, |
|
"text": "(Brachman 1978)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF2" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "ABSITY EXAMPLE (CONTINUED)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Bobrow and Webber's approach addresses several of the issues that we do, in particular the relationship between syntax and semantics. The information feedback to the parser is similar to our Semantic Enquiry Desk, though in our system, because the parser is deterministic, semantic feedback cannot be con fluted with syntactic success or failure. Both approaches rely on the fact that the objects manipulated are objects of a knowledge representation that permits appropriate judgments to be made, though in rather a different manner. Hendler and Phillips (1981; Phillips and Hendler 1982) have implemented a control structure for NLU based on message passing, with the goal of running syntax and semantics in parallel and providing semantic feedback to the parser. A ~moderator\" translates between syntactic constructs and semantic representations. However, their approach to interpretation is essentially ad hoc (James Hendler, persoaoi cummunication), and they do not attempt to put syntactic and semantic rules in strict correspondence, nor type their semantic objects.", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 535, |
|
"end": 562, |
|
"text": "Hendler and Phillips (1981;", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF21" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 563, |
|
"end": 589, |
|
"text": "Phillips and Hendler 1982)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF34" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "ABSITY EXAMPLE (CONTINUED)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "None of the work mentioned above addresses issues of lexical ambiguity as ours does, though Bobrow and Webber's incremental description refinement could possibly be extended to cover it. Also, Gawron et al have a process to disambiguate case roles in the logical form after it is complete, which operates in a manner not dissimilar to the case-slot part of Polaroid Words.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "ABSITY EXAMPLE (CONTINUED)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "We have described a new approach to semantic interpretation, one suggested by the semantic formalism of Richard Montague. We believe this work to be a clean and elegant foundation for semantic interpretation, in contrast to previous ad hoc approaches. At the moment, though, the work is only a foundation; the test of a foundation is what can be constructed on top of it. We do not expect the construction to be unproblematic; here are some of the problems we will have to solve.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Conclusion", |
|
"sec_num": "8." |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "First, the approach is not just compositional but almost too compositional. At present, noun phrases are taken to be invariably and unalterably specific and extensional, that is to imply the existence of the unique entity or set of entities that they specify. In English, this is not always correct. A sentence such as:", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Conclusion", |
|
"sec_num": "8." |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Nadia owns a unicorn.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Conclusion", |
|
"sec_num": "8." |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "implies that a unicorn exists, but this is not true of:", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Conclusion", |
|
"sec_num": "8." |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Nadia talked abou~ a unicorn.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Conclusion", |
|
"sec_num": "8." |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "which also has a non-specific reading. Montague's solution to this problem does not seem easily adaptable to Absity. 2\u00b0 Similarly, a sentence such as:", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Conclusion", |
|
"sec_num": "8." |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "The lion is not a beast to be trifled w/th. can be a generic statement intended to be true of all lions; Montague did not treat generics.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Conclusion", |
|
"sec_num": "8." |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Second, the approach is heavily dependent upon the expressive power of the underlying frame language. For example, our language, Frail, is yet deficient in its handling of time, and this is clearly reflected in Absity. Further, the approach makes certain claims about the nature of frame representations~that a descriptive adjective in some sense is a slot-filler pair, for example that might be shown to be untenable.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Conclusion", |
|
"sec_num": "8." |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "We will also have to deal with problems in quantification, anaphoric reference, and many other areas. Nevertheless, we believe that this approach to semantic interpretation shows considerable promise.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Conclusion", |
|
"sec_num": "8." |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "8Despite this problem,Friedman et \u00a2I (1978bFriedman et \u00a2I ( , 1978c have implemented Mont~gue semantics computationally by using techn/ques for maintaining partially specified models. However, their system is intended ~s ~ tool for understanding Montague semantics better, r~ther than &s ~ usable NLU system (1978b:26).", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Rosenschein and Shieber's semaxltic translation fonow~ parsing rather than running in parallel with it, but it iv strongly syntax-dLrected, and is, it seems, isomorphic to ~n in-t~ndem translation that provides no feedback to the p~rser.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"back_matter": [ |
|
{ |
|
"text": "I am grateful to Eugene Charniak, C~role Chaski, Jim Hendler, Polly Jacobson, and Nadia Talent for their comments upon earlier versions of this paper.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Acknowledgemems", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"bib_entries": { |
|
"BIBREF0": { |
|
"ref_id": "b0", |
|
"title": "=PSI-KLONE: Pa.rsing and semantic interpretation in the BBN natural language understa.nding system. ~ l~oceedings O~ th.c T~ird ~iennial Conference, Co.nadio.n Society /or Computational Studies o[ [nte|llgenee / Soei~t~ Canadienne pour ~t~des d'Inte~ligence par Ordinateur", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Robert", |
|
"middle": [ |
|
"J" |
|
], |
|
"last": "Bobrow", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Bonnie", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Webber", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Lynn", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1980, |
|
"venue": "", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "131--142", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "BOBROW, Robert J ~nd WEBBER, Bonnie Lynn (1980&). =PSI- KLONE: Pa.rsing and semantic interpretation in the BBN natural language understa.nding system. ~ l~oceedings O~ th.c T~ird ~iennial Conference, Co.nadio.n Society /or Computational Studies o[ [nte|llgenee / Soei~t~ Canadienne pour ~t~des d'Inte~ligence par Ordinateur, Victoria., Ma.y 1980. 131-142.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF1": { |
|
"ref_id": "b1", |
|
"title": "P~ociedin~s of ~&e First Anr~a~ lVationa~l Conference 0~ Artificial Intelligence", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Robert", |
|
"middle": [ |
|
"J" |
|
], |
|
"last": "Bobrow", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Bonnie", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Webber", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Lynn", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1980, |
|
"venue": "", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "316--323", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "BOBROW, Robert J and WEBBER, Bonnie Lynn (1980b). \"Knowledge representation for syntactic/semantic process- i~g.\" P~ociedin~s of ~&e First Anr~a~ lVationa~l Confer- ence 0~ Artificial Intelligence, Stanford, August 1980. 316-323.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF2": { |
|
"ref_id": "b2", |
|
"title": "=A structural pArs.ditto for representing knowledge", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Ronald", |
|
"middle": [ |
|
"J" |
|
], |
|
"last": "Brachman", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1978, |
|
"venue": "Report 3605, Bolt, Beranek and NewmaJ~", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "BRACHMAN, Ronald J (1978). =A structural pArs.ditto for rep- resenting knowledge. ~ Report 3605, Bolt, Beranek and NewmaJ~, Cambridge, MA 02138. May 1978.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF3": { |
|
"ref_id": "b3", |
|
"title": "A common representation for problem-solving and langua.ge-comprehension information", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Eugene", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Charniak", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1981, |
|
"venue": "Artificial [ntelli.gence", |
|
"volume": "16", |
|
"issue": "3", |
|
"pages": "225--255", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "CHARNIAK, Eugene (1981). \"A common representation for problem-solving and langua.ge-comprehension information.\" Artificial [ntelli.gence, 16(3), July 1981, 225-255.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF4": { |
|
"ref_id": "b4", |
|
"title": "~A p~urser with ~omething for everyone", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Eugene", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Charniak", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1981, |
|
"venue": "", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "CHARNIAK, Eugene (1983). ~A p~urser with ~omething for everyone. ~ [11 in: King, M~gaxet(editor). P~rsingnatt~ral language, London: Academic Press, 1983. [2] Tech~ic~l report CS-70, Department of Computer Science, Brown University, Providence, R[ 02912. April 1981.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF5": { |
|
"ref_id": "b5", |
|
"title": "Aspects of the theOr~l Of synta=. Ca.mbridge, MA: The MIT Press, 1965. 20He h~ndled such sentences by having two distinct parsee, one for each rea.dinK; a mea.ning postulate equa.tes the representations of the two parses where the verb ma", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Avr~m", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Chomsky", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Noa", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1965, |
|
"venue": "", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "CHOMSKY, Avr~m Noa.m (1965). Aspects of the theOr~l Of synta=. Ca.mbridge, MA: The MIT Press, 1965. 20He h~ndled such sentences by having two distinct parsee, one for each rea.dinK; a mea.ning postulate equa.tes the repre- sentations of the two parses where the verb ma.kes it appropriate to do so.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF6": { |
|
"ref_id": "b6", |
|
"title": "Synthese l~n~u~ge library 11). Dordrecht: D. Reidel", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "David R;", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Dowty", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Robert", |
|
"middle": [ |
|
"Eugene" |
|
], |
|
"last": "Wall", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Staaley", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Peters", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1981, |
|
"venue": "", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "DOWTY, David R; WALL, Robert Eugene and PETERS, Staaley (1981). [ntrodt*ction to Montague semantics (-~- Synthese l~n~u~ge library 11). Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1981.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF7": { |
|
"ref_id": "b7", |
|
"title": "Tom Swift and his procedural gr~nd~other", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Jerry", |
|
"middle": [ |
|
"Alan" |
|
], |
|
"last": "Fodor", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1978, |
|
"venue": "Cognition", |
|
"volume": "6", |
|
"issue": "3", |
|
"pages": "229--247", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "FODOR, Jerry AlAn (1978). \"Tom Swift and his procedural gr~nd~other.\" Cognition, 6(3), September 1978, 229-247.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF8": { |
|
"ref_id": "b8", |
|
"title": "reply to Philip", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Jerry Alaj1 ; Johnson-Laird", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Fodor", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1970, |
|
"venue": "", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "3--95", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "FODOR, Jerry AlaJ1 (1970). \"In reply to Philip Johnson-Laird.\" Cognition, T(1), Maxch 1979, 03-95.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF9": { |
|
"ref_id": "b9", |
|
"title": "Explicit finite intensional models for PTQ. ~ [I] American jo~rn\u00a2l o/ computational linguistics", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Joyce", |
|
"middle": [ |
|
";" |
|
], |
|
"last": "Friedman", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Dougla", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Moran", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Warren", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Bailey ~nd", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "De", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Scott", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1978, |
|
"venue": "", |
|
"volume": "74", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "3--22", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "FRIEDMAN, Joyce; MORAN, Dougla.s Bailey ~nd WARREN, De.rid Scott (1978a.). \"Explicit finite intensional models for PTQ. ~ [I] American jo~rn\u00a2l o/ computational linguistics, 1978:1, microfiche 74, 3-22. [2] Paper N-3, Computer S~udies in Formal Linguistics, Depzrtment of Computer amd Communion.lion Sciences, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, MI 48109.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF11": { |
|
"ref_id": "b11", |
|
"title": "11 American yournal of compurational linguistics", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Montague", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Kr", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": null, |
|
"venue": "", |
|
"volume": "1078", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "23--96", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "Montague Kr,~mmar.\" [11 American yournal of compura- tional linguistics, 1078:1, microfiche 74, 23-96. (21 Pa.per N-4, Computer Studies in Formal Linguistics, Department of Computer ~nd Communication Sciences, University of Michigan , Ann Arbor, MI 48109.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF13": { |
|
"ref_id": "b13", |
|
"title": "A process version of Mont~gue ~am-max", |
|
"authors": [], |
|
"year": 1978, |
|
"venue": "{1] P~oceed~ngs of the 7th International Cor~ferene\u00a2 on Computational LingtListics", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "=EvMuatmg English sentences in a. logical mode[: A process version of Mont~gue ~am- max.\" {1] P~oceed~ngs of the 7th International Cor~ferene\u00a2 on Computational LingtListics, Bergen, Norway, August 1978. [2} Paper N-15, Computer Studies in Forma.l Linguistics, Depactment of Computer cud Communication Sciences, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, MI ~8109. August 1978.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF14": { |
|
"ref_id": "b14", |
|
"title": "and ~igher-order modal logic ~uith ~pplic~tions ~o Montague sernan~t'cs (~ North-Holland Mathematics Series 9)", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Daniel", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Gallin", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1972, |
|
"venue": "", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "GALLIN, Daniel (1975). [ntensional and ~igher-order modal logic ~uith ~pplic~tions ~o Montague sernan~t'cs (~ North- Holland Mathematics Series 9). Amsterdam: North- Holland, 1975. {Revised from the a.uthor's doctoral dissertation, Department of Mathematics, University of Caaifornia, Berkeley, September 1972.]", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF17": { |
|
"ref_id": "b17", |
|
"title": "Processing English with a. genera.lized phrase structure grammar", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "E", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Paulson", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": ";", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Anne", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Geoffrey", |
|
"middle": [ |
|
"K" |
|
], |
|
"last": "Pullum", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Ivan", |
|
"middle": [ |
|
"A" |
|
], |
|
"last": "Sag", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Wasow", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Thomas", |
|
"middle": [ |
|
"A" |
|
], |
|
"last": "", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1982, |
|
"venue": "\u00b0 Ii[ Proceedings, gOCh Ann~cL~ 3v[ee~t'ng of ihe Association for Computational Linguistics", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "74--81", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "PAULSON, E Anne; PULLUM, Geoffrey K; SAG, Ivan A and WASOW, Thomas A (1982). \"Processing English with a. genera.lized phrase structure grammar. \u00b0 Ii[ Proceedings, gOCh Ann~cL~ 3v[ee~t'ng of ihe Association for Computational Linguistics, Toronto, June 1982. 74--81. [21 Technical note CSL-82-5, Computer Science Labors.tory, Hewiett-Packard, Palo Alto, CA 94304. April ~982.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF18": { |
|
"ref_id": "b18", |
|
"title": "The ~attLre Of syntactic representation", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Gera~d", |
|
"middle": [ |
|
";" |
|
], |
|
"last": "Cazdar", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Pa", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Jacobson", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Pullum", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Ida", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Geoffrey", |
|
"middle": [ |
|
"K" |
|
], |
|
"last": "", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1982, |
|
"venue": "D. Reidel", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "CAZDAR, Gera~d (1982). \"Phrase structure grammar.\" in: JACOBSON, Pa.uline Ida and PULLUM, Geoffrey K. The ~attLre Of syntactic representation. Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1982.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF19": { |
|
"ref_id": "b19", |
|
"title": "Montag~\u00a2 grgmmar ~nd machine er~nslation between English and Thai. Doctoral dissertation", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Kurt", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Godden", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Sterling", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": null, |
|
"venue": "", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "GODDEN, Kurt Sterling (1081). Montag~\u00a2 grgmmar ~nd machine er~nslation between English and Thai. Doctoral dissertation, Department of Linguistics, University of K ansa.s, 1981.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF20": { |
|
"ref_id": "b20", |
|
"title": "=Questions in Montague English", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "C", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Hamblin", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": null, |
|
"venue": "", |
|
"volume": "10", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "247--259", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "HAMBLIN, C L (1973). =Questions in Montague English.\" [1[ Foundations o/ langt~=g\u00a2, 10(1), May 1073, 41-53. {2] in Partee 1976, 247-259.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF21": { |
|
"ref_id": "b21", |
|
"title": "=A flexible control structure for the conceptual analysis of natural l~nguage using message-passing", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Ja", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Hendler", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Alexander", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Brian", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Phillips", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1981, |
|
"venue": "Texas Instruments Incorporated", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "HENDLER, Ja.mes Alexander and PHILLIPS, Brian (1981). =A flexible control structure for the conceptual analysis of natural l~nguage using message-passing. ~ Technical report TR-08-81-03, Computer Science Labors.tory, Texas Instruments Incorporated, Define, TX 75266, 1981.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF22": { |
|
"ref_id": "b22", |
|
"title": "A fot~ndation for se~nantic interp~'etatlon, ~ith toord ~nd c~s\u00a2 disambigt~ation. Doctoral dissertation", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Graeme", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Hirst", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1983, |
|
"venue": "", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "HIRST, Graeme (1983). A fot~ndation for se~nantic interp~'eta- tlon, ~ith toord ~nd c~s\u00a2 disambigt~ation. Doctoral disser- tation, Department of Computer Science, Brown University (forthcoming t.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF23": { |
|
"ref_id": "b23", |
|
"title": "Word sense ~nd case slot disamb/g~ation", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Graeme", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Hirst", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Charniak", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Eugene", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1982, |
|
"venue": "Proceedings of the National Conference on Artificial Intelligence", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "95--98", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "HIRST, Graeme and CHARNIAK, Eugene (1982). \"Word sense ~nd case slot disamb/g~ation.\" Proceedings of the National Conference on Artificial Intelligence, Pittsburgh, August 1982. 95-98.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF24": { |
|
"ref_id": "b24", |
|
"title": "=Making computational sense of Monta4~ue'l intensional logic", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Jerry", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Hobbs", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Rosenschein", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Robert", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Stanley", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Joshua", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1977, |
|
"venue": "Artificial Intelligence", |
|
"volume": "9", |
|
"issue": "3", |
|
"pages": "287--306", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "HOBBS, Jerry Robert and ROSENSCHEIN, Stanley Joshua (1977). =Making computational sense of Monta4~ue'l inten- sional logic.\" Artificial Intelligence, 9(3), December 1977, 287-306.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF25": { |
|
"ref_id": "b25", |
|
"title": "What's wrong with Grandma's guide to procedural semantics: A reply to Jerry Fodor", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Johnson-Laird", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Philip", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Nicholas", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1978, |
|
"venue": "~ Cognition", |
|
"volume": "6", |
|
"issue": "3", |
|
"pages": "249--261", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "JOHNSON-LAIRD, Philip Nicholas (1978). \"What's wrong with Grandma's guide to procedural semantics: A reply to Jerry Fodor. ~ Cognition, 6(3), September 1978, 249-261.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF26": { |
|
"ref_id": "b26", |
|
"title": "Conceptual dependency and Montagne ~rammar: A step toward conciliation", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Mark", |
|
"middle": [ |
|
"A" |
|
], |
|
"last": "Jones", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "David", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Warren", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Scott", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1982, |
|
"venue": "Proceedings of the N~tion\u00a2l Conference on Artificial [n$elligence", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "79--83", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "JONES, Mark A ~nd WARREN, David Scott (1982). \"Concep- tual dependency and Montagne ~rammar: A step toward conciliation.\" Proceedings of the N~tion\u00a2l Conference on Artificial [n$elligence, Pittsburgh, Augnst 1982. 79-83.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF27": { |
|
"ref_id": "b27", |
|
"title": "Strategies for natural language processing", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Wendy", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Lehnert", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Ringle", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Grace ~nd", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "H ;", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Martin", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "N", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Hlllsdale", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1982, |
|
"venue": "", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "LEHNERT, Wendy Grace ~nd RINGLE, Martin H (1982). Strategies for natural language processing. Hlllsdale, N J: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1982.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF28": { |
|
"ref_id": "b28", |
|
"title": "A theory of sgntactic recognition for natv.ral l~nguag\u00a2. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Preu", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Mitchell", |
|
"middle": [ |
|
"P" |
|
], |
|
"last": "Marcus", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1980, |
|
"venue": "", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "MARCUS, Mitchell P (1980). A theory of sgntactic recognition for natv.ral l~nguag\u00a2. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Preu, 1980.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF29": { |
|
"ref_id": "b29", |
|
"title": "The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary English", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Richard", |
|
"middle": [ |
|
";" |
|
], |
|
"last": "Montague", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Ka~rlo", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Hintikka", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": ";", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Jaakko Jnhani", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Julius", |
|
"middle": [ |
|
"Matthew" |
|
], |
|
"last": "Moravcsik", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Suppes", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Emil ~nd", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Patrick", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Colonel", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1973, |
|
"venue": "Proceedings of tAe 1970 Stanford workshop on grammar ~nd semantics", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "247--270", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "MONTAGUE, Richard (1973). \"The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary English.\" [I I in: HINTIKKA, Ka~rlo Jaakko Jnhani; MORAVCSIK, Julius Matthew Emil ~nd SUPPES, Patrick Colonel (editors). Approaches to ~tur~l lang.~age: Proceedings of tAe 1970 Stanford workshop on grammar ~nd semantics. Dordrecht: D. Reide|, 1973. 221-242. [2] in: THOMASON, Richmond Hunt (editor). Formal philosophll: Selected papers of Richard Mont~gae. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1974. 247-270.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF30": { |
|
"ref_id": "b30", |
|
"title": "Problems in logical form. ~ l~'ocsedings, 191h Annual Meeting of th", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Robert", |
|
"middle": [ |
|
"C" |
|
], |
|
"last": "Moore", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1981, |
|
"venue": "", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "117--124", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "MOORE, Robert C (1981). \"Problems in logical form. ~ l~'ocsedings, 191h Annual Meeting of th, e Association for Computational Linguistics, Stanford, July 1981. 117-124.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF31": { |
|
"ref_id": "b31", |
|
"title": "Some transformational extensions of Montagne ~ammar", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Baabara", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Partee", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Hall", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1973, |
|
"venue": "11 J'o~rnal of Philosophical Logic", |
|
"volume": "2", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "51--76", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "PARTEE, Baabara Hall (1973). \"Some transformational exten- sions of Montagne ~ammar.\" [11 J'o~rnal of Philosophical Logic, 2, 1973, 509--534. [2] in Psatee 1976, 51-76.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF32": { |
|
"ref_id": "b32", |
|
"title": "Montagne grammar and trxns-form&tional 6rammar", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Barbara", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Partee", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Hall", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1975, |
|
"venue": "Linguistic [nquirF", |
|
"volume": "6", |
|
"issue": "2", |
|
"pages": "203--300", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "PARTEE, Barbara Hall (1975). \"Montagne grammar and trxns- form&tional 6rammar.\" Linguistic [nquirF, 6(2), Spring 1975, 203-300.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF33": { |
|
"ref_id": "b33", |
|
"title": "Montag~,e grammar", |
|
"authors": [], |
|
"year": 1976, |
|
"venue": "", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "PARTEE, Barbara Hall (editor) (1976) . Montag~,e grammar. New York: Academic Press, 1976.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF34": { |
|
"ref_id": "b34", |
|
"title": "=A message-passing control structure for text understandin8", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Brian", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Phillips", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Hendler", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "James", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Alexander", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1982, |
|
"venue": "COLING 8\u00a3: Proceedings of the NintA International Conference on Computational Linguistics", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "307--312", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "PHILLIPS, Brian and HENDLER, James Alexander (1982). =A message-passing control structure for text understandin8.\" in: HORECK~', J~n (editor). COLING 8\u00a3: Proceedings of the NintA International Conference on Computational Linguistics, Prague, July 5--10, 198\u00a3 (= North-Holland Linguistic Series 47). Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1982. 307-312.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF35": { |
|
"ref_id": "b35", |
|
"title": "Translating English into logical form", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Stanley", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Rosenschein", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Joshua", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Shieber", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "M", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Stuart", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1982, |
|
"venue": "P~oceedin~s, ~O~h Annual Meeting of the Association for Computational Linguistics", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "ROSENSCHEIN, Stanley Joshua ~nd SHIEBER, Stuart M (1982). \"Translating English into logical form.\" P~oceedin~s, ~O~h Annual Meeting of the Association for Computational Linguistics, Toronto, June 1982. i-8.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF36": { |
|
"ref_id": "b36", |
|
"title": "Conceptual information processing (~ Fundamental studies in computer science 3)", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Roger", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Schank", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Carl", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1975, |
|
"venue": "", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "SCHANK, Roger Carl (editor) (1975). Conceptual information processing (~ Fundamental studies in computer science 3). Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1975.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF37": { |
|
"ref_id": "b37", |
|
"title": "Reminding and memory organization: An introduction to MOPs", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Roger", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Schank", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Carl", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1982, |
|
"venue": "Lehnert and Ringle", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "455--494", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "SCHANK, Roger Carl (1982). \"Reminding and memory or- ganization: An introduction to MOPs.\" [I] in Lehnert and Ringle 1982, 455-494.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF39": { |
|
"ref_id": "b39", |
|
"title": "From English to logic: Context-free computation of 'conventional' logical translation", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Lenhaxt", |
|
"middle": [ |
|
"K" |
|
], |
|
"last": "Schubert", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Pelletier", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Francis", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Jeffry", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1982, |
|
"venue": "American Journal of Computational Linguistics", |
|
"volume": "8", |
|
"issue": "1", |
|
"pages": "26--44", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "SCHUBERT, Lenhaxt K and PELLETIER, Francis Jeffry (1982). \"From English to logic: Context-free computation of 'conventional' logical translation.\" American Journal of Computational Linguistics, 8(1), January-March 1982, 26--44.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF40": { |
|
"ref_id": "b40", |
|
"title": "Intensionality in computational contexts", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Brian", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Smith", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Cantwell", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1979, |
|
"venue": "", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "SMITH, Brian Cantwell (1979). \"Intensionality in computa- tional contexts.\" Unpublished MS, Artificial intelligence Laboratory, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Cam- bridge, MA 02139. December 1979.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF41": { |
|
"ref_id": "b41", |
|
"title": "Kno~oledgs semantics. Doctoral dissertation, Department of Linguistics", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "George", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Orest", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1982, |
|
"venue": "", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "George Orest (1982). Kno~oledgs semantics. Doctoral dissertation, Department of Linguistics, New York University, 1982.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF42": { |
|
"ref_id": "b42", |
|
"title": "Some thoughts on procedural semantics", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Yorick", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Wilks", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Alexander", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1980, |
|
"venue": "{21 Technical report CSCM-I, Cognitive Studies Centre", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "494--518", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "WILKS, Yorick Alexander (1982). \"Some thoughts on proce- dural semantics.\" [I] in Lehnert and Ringle 1982, 494- 518. {21 Technical report CSCM-I, Cognitive Studies Centre, University of Essex, Wivenhoe Park, Colchester. November 1980.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF43": { |
|
"ref_id": "b43", |
|
"title": "=Language comprehension in a problem solver", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Douglas", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Wong", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1981, |
|
"venue": "l~roceedings of the 7th International Joint Conference on Artificial", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "7--12", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "WONG, Douglas (1981~). =Language comprehension in a problem solver.\" l~roceedings of the 7th International Joint Conference on Artificial [ntelligence, Vancouver, August 1981. 7-12.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF44": { |
|
"ref_id": "b44", |
|
"title": "On the ~nifleation of language comprehension ~oitA problem solving. Doctoral dissertae tion", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Douglas", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Wong", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1981, |
|
"venue": "", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "WONG, Douglas (1981b). On the ~nifleation of language comprehension ~oitA problem solving. Doctoral dissertae tion [ava41able as technical report CS-78], Department of Computer Science, Brown University, 1981.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF45": { |
|
"ref_id": "b45", |
|
"title": "Semantics for a qucs~ion-~nstosring system", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "William", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Woods", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Aaron", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1967, |
|
"venue": "", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "WOODS, William Aaron Jr (1967). Semantics for a qucs~ion- ~nstosring system.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF46": { |
|
"ref_id": "b46", |
|
"title": "the series Outstanding dissertations in the Computer Sciences", |
|
"authors": [], |
|
"year": 1967, |
|
"venue": "", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "Doctoral dissertation, Harvard University, August 1967. [2] reprinted as a volume in the series Outstanding dissertations in the Computer Sciences, New York: Garland Publishing, 1979.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF47": { |
|
"ref_id": "b47", |
|
"title": "Procedural semantics for a question-answering machine", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "William", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Woods", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Aaron", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1968, |
|
"venue": "AFIPS conference proceedings, 33 (Fall Joint Computer Conference)", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "457--471", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "WOODS, William Aaron Jr (1968). \"Procedural semantics for a question-answering machine.\" AFIPS conference proceed- ings, 33 (Fall Joint Computer Conference), 1968. 457-471.", |
|
"links": null |
|
} |
|
}, |
|
"ref_entries": { |
|
"FIGREF0": { |
|
"text": "This work was supported by the Oflfice of Naval Research under contract number N00014-79-C-0592.", |
|
"uris": null, |
|
"type_str": "figure", |
|
"num": null |
|
}, |
|
"FIGREF1": { |
|
"text": "4To be precise: the semantic type of a proper noun is set of properties of individual concepts; that of an adverb is function between set~ v[ individual concepts (Dowry \u00a2~ al Ig81: 183, 187).", |
|
"uris": null, |
|
"type_str": "figure", |
|
"num": null |
|
}, |
|
"FIGREF2": { |
|
"text": "is, not unreasonably: 5For example, the semantic type of prepositions is functions mapping senses of the type of noun phrases to the semantic type of prepositional phrases.depar~(as-57, boston).", |
|
"uris": null, |
|
"type_str": "figure", |
|
"num": null |
|
}, |
|
"FIGREF3": { |
|
"text": "15This is not quite true. Specified unique translations axe given for proper names and for a few important function words, such as the and be; see Monta~e 197312]:261 , or Dowry ~ ~l 1981:192ff.", |
|
"uris": null, |
|
"type_str": "figure", |
|
"num": null |
|
}, |
|
"FIGREF4": { |
|
"text": "et al produce all poslible trees and their tranilations for the input sentence, s.nd then throw away any that don't make sense to the database. If'Our choice of Paragram was largely pragmatic~it w&s avL/l-\u2022 ble--and does not represent &ny particular commitment to transformational g~ammar s.", |
|
"uris": null, |
|
"type_str": "figure", |
|
"num": null |
|
}, |
|
"TABREF0": { |
|
"content": "<table><tr><td>operates on some syntactic elements to create a new</td></tr><tr><td>element, the other operates on the corresponding</td></tr><tr><td>semantic objects to create a new object that will cor-</td></tr><tr><td>respond to the new syntactic element. Thus the two</td></tr><tr><td>sets of rules operate in tandem.</td></tr><tr><td>Fourth, Montague's semantics is compositional,</td></tr><tr><td>which is to say that the meaning of the whole is a</td></tr><tr><td>systematic function of the meaning of the parts. At</td></tr><tr><td>first glance this sounds trivial; if the noun phrase my</td></tr><tr><td>pet penguin denotes by itself some particular entity,</td></tr><tr><td>namely the one sitting on my lap as I write this paper,</td></tr><tr><td>then we do not expect it to refer to a different entity</td></tr><tr><td>when it is embedded in the sentence [ love my pet</td></tr><tr><td>penguin, and a semantic system that did not reflect</td></tr><tr><td>this would be a loser indeed. Yet there are alternatives</td></tr><tr><td>to compositional semantics.</td></tr></table>", |
|
"type_str": "table", |
|
"num": null, |
|
"text": "5 Third, in Montague's system the syntactic rules and semantic rules are in one-to-one correspondence. Each time a particular syntactic rule applies, so does the corresponding semantic rule; while the one", |
|
"html": null |
|
}, |
|
"TABREF1": { |
|
"content": "<table/>", |
|
"type_str": "table", |
|
"num": null, |
|
"text": "NONCOMPOSITIONALITY IN WOODS'S SYSTEM AA-57 departs from Boston. (aa-57, bos~on) A.A-57 departs from Boston to Chicago. conltecT, (aa-5T, besT, on. chicago)AA-57 departs from Boston on Monday. dday(aa-57, boston, monday)", |
|
"html": null |
|
}, |
|
"TABREF2": { |
|
"content": "<table><tr><td>BASIC TYPES</td></tr><tr><td>Frame a</td></tr><tr><td>(penguin ?x), Clove ?x)</td></tr><tr><td>Slot</td></tr><tr><td>color, agent</td></tr><tr><td>Frame determiner b</td></tr><tr><td>(t~e ?x), Ca ?x)</td></tr><tr><td>OTHER TYPES</td></tr><tr><td>Slot-filler pair = slot ~ frame statement</td></tr><tr><td>(color=red), (agent=(the ?x (f\u00b1sh ?x)))</td></tr><tr><td>Frame descriptor = frame ~ slot-filler pair*</td></tr><tr><td>(pen~uln ?x (owner=Nadla)),</td></tr><tr><td>(love ?x (agent=Ross) (patient=Nadla)),</td></tr><tr><td>(dog ?x)</td></tr><tr><td>Frame statement [or instance c]</td></tr><tr><td>= frame determiner -~ frame descriptor</td></tr><tr><td>(the ?x (penguin ?x (owner=Nadla))),</td></tr><tr><td>(a ?x (love ?x (agent=Ross)</td></tr><tr><td>(pail ent=Nadl a) ) ),</td></tr><tr><td>(the ?x (dog ?x)).</td></tr><tr><td>pen~ln87 [an instancel</td></tr></table>", |
|
"type_str": "table", |
|
"num": null, |
|
"text": "TYPES IN THE AHSITY SEMANTIC INTERPRETER", |
|
"html": null |
|
}, |
|
"TABREF3": { |
|
"content": "<table><tr><td>SYNTACTIC TYPE</td><td>SEMANTIC TYPE</td></tr><tr><td>Major sentence</td><td>Frame statement, instance</td></tr><tr><td>Sentence</td><td>Frame descriptor</td></tr><tr><td>Noun</td><td>Frame</td></tr><tr><td>Adjective</td><td>Slot-filler pair</td></tr><tr><td>Determiner</td><td>Frame determiner</td></tr><tr><td>Noun phrase</td><td>Frame statement, instance</td></tr><tr><td>Preposition</td><td>Slot name</td></tr><tr><td>Prepositional Phrase</td><td>Slot-filler pair</td></tr><tr><td>Verb</td><td>(Action) frame</td></tr><tr><td>Adverb</td><td>Slot-filler pair</td></tr><tr><td>Auxiliary</td><td>Slot-filler pair</td></tr><tr><td>Verb phrase</td><td>Frame descriptor</td></tr><tr><td>Clause end</td><td>Frame determiner.</td></tr></table>", |
|
"type_str": "table", |
|
"num": null, |
|
"text": "TYPE CORRESPONDENCES IN ABSITY", |
|
"html": null |
|
}, |
|
"TABREF4": { |
|
"content": "<table><tr><td>shows the representation for each component</td></tr><tr><td>of the sentence; note that the basic noun phrases</td></tr><tr><td>have already been formed in the manner described</td></tr><tr><td>above. Note also that we have inserted the pseudo-</td></tr></table>", |
|
"type_str": "table", |
|
"num": null, |
|
"text": "", |
|
"html": null |
|
}, |
|
"TABREF5": { |
|
"content": "<table><tr><td/><td colspan=\"3\">ABSITY EXAMPL E</td></tr><tr><td>WORD</td><td>OR PHRASE</td><td>SEMANTIC</td><td>OBJECT</td></tr><tr><td>SUBJ</td><td/><td>agent</td><td/></tr><tr><td>Nadia</td><td/><td colspan=\"2\">(the ?x (thing ?x</td></tr><tr><td/><td/><td colspan=\"2\">(propername=\"Nadla\")))</td></tr><tr><td>bought</td><td/><td>(buy ?x)</td><td/></tr><tr><td>oBJ</td><td/><td>pa~len~</td><td/></tr><tr><td colspan=\"2\">the book</td><td colspan=\"2\">(the ?y (book ?y))</td></tr><tr><td>from</td><td/><td>source</td><td/></tr><tr><td colspan=\"2\">a store</td><td colspan=\"2\">(a ?z (el;ore ?z))</td></tr><tr><td>in</td><td/><td>loca~lon</td><td/></tr><tr><td colspan=\"2\">the mall</td><td colspan=\"2\">(the ?w (mall ?w))</td></tr><tr><td colspan=\"2\">\u2022 [period I</td><td>(a ?u)</td><td/></tr><tr><td colspan=\"4\">X over Y then do X'; otherwise do Y\". To answer</td></tr><tr><td colspan=\"4\">such questions, we have a Semantic Enquiry Desk r, hat</td></tr><tr><td colspan=\"4\">operates upon the same semantic objects as the seman-</td></tr><tr><td colspan=\"4\">tic interpreter. Because these objects are components</td></tr><tr><td colspan=\"4\">of the Frail frame language, the Enquiry Desk can</td></tr><tr><td colspan=\"4\">use the full retrieval and inference power of Frail in</td></tr><tr><td colspan=\"2\">answering the enquiry.</td><td/><td/></tr></table>", |
|
"type_str": "table", |
|
"num": null, |
|
"text": "", |
|
"html": null |
|
}, |
|
"TABREF6": { |
|
"content": "<table/>", |
|
"type_str": "table", |
|
"num": null, |
|
"text": "", |
|
"html": null |
|
} |
|
} |
|
} |
|
} |