|
<<1>>HLF 2016, Sep. 22, 2016, Heidelberg. UniMath by Vladimir |
|
Voevodsky from the Institute for Advanced Study in Princeton, NJ. |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
<<2>>Part 1. Univalent foundations 2 |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
<<3>>[[file:Unimath-3_1.png]] [[file:Unimath-3_2.png]] Univalent Foundations |
|
UniMath library Today we face a problem that involves two difficult to |
|
satisfy conditions. On the one hand we have to find a way for computer |
|
assisted verification of mathematical proofs. This is necessary, first |
|
of all, because we have to stop the dissolution of the concept of |
|
proof in mathematics. |
|
|
|
On the other hand we have to preserve the intimate connection between |
|
mathematics and the world of human intuition. This connection is what |
|
moves mathematics forward and what we often experience as the beauty |
|
of mathematics. |
|
|
|
3 |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
<<4>>[[file:Unimath-4_1.png]] [[file:Unimath-4_2.png]] Univalent Foundations |
|
UniMath library The Univalent Foundations (UF) is, a yet imperfect, |
|
solution to this problem. In their original form, the UF combined |
|
three components: • the view of mathematics as the study of structures |
|
on sets and their higher analogs, • the idea that the higher analogs |
|
of sets are reflected in the set-based mathematics as homotopy types, • |
|
the idea that one can formalize our intuition about structures on |
|
these higher analogs using the Martin-Lof Type Theory (MLTT) extended |
|
with the Law of Excluded Middle for propositions (LEM) , the Axiom of |
|
Choice for sets (AC), the Univalence Axiom (UA) and the Resizing Rules |
|
(RR). 4 |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
<<5>>[[file:Unimath-5_1.png]] [[file:Unimath-5_2.png]] Univalent Foundations |
|
UniMath library The main new concepts that were since added to these |
|
are the following: • the understanding that a lot of mathematics can |
|
be formalized in the MLTT without the LEM and the AC and that |
|
excluding these two axioms one obtains foundations for a /new form of |
|
constructive mathematics/, • the understanding that classical |
|
mathematics appears as a subset of this new constructive mathematics, |
|
• the understanding that the MLTT extended with the UA is an imperfect |
|
formalization system for this constructive mathematics and that it |
|
should be possible to integrate the UA into the MLTT obtaining a new |
|
type theory with better computational properties. 5 |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
<<6>>[[file:Unimath-6_1.png]] [[file:Unimath-6_2.png]] Univalent Foundations |
|
UniMath library What does it mean for a formalization system to be |
|
constructive? Some expressions in type theory are said to be in |
|
normal form. Any expression can be automatically and deterministically |
|
“normalized”, that is, an equivalent expression in normal form can be |
|
computed. In type theory there are type expressions and element |
|
expressions. If “T” is a type (expression) and “o” is an element |
|
(expression) one writes “o:T” if the type of “o” is “T”. 6 |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
<<7>>[[file:Unimath-7_1.png]] [[file:Unimath-7_2.png]] Univalent Foundations |
|
UniMath library In most type systems there is the type of natural |
|
numbers. In the UniMath it is written as “nat”. There is the zero |
|
element “O:nat” and the successor function “S” from “nat” to “nat” |
|
that intuitively corresponds to the function that takes “n” to “1+n”. |
|
A constructive system satisfies the /canonicity property/ for “nat”, |
|
which asserts that the normal form of any expression “o:nat” has the |
|
form “S(S(....(SO)..))”. By counting how many “S” there is in the |
|
normal form one obtains an actual natural number from any element |
|
expression of type “nat”. 7 |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
<<8>>[[file:Unimath-8_1.png]] [[file:Unimath-8_2.png]] Univalent Foundations |
|
UniMath library This is a tremendously strong property. Consider the |
|
example: a set “X:hSet” is defined to be finite if there exists an |
|
isomorphism between it and the standard finite set “stn n”. Here “n” is |
|
an expression of type “nat”. It is well defined and one obtains a |
|
function “fincard” from finite sets to “nat” called the cardinality - |
|
the number of elements of the set. Now suppose that I have proved, |
|
constructively, that “X” is finite. Then “(fincard X):nat” is defined. By |
|
normalizing “fincard X” I obtain an actual natural number. If I had a |
|
constructive proof of /Faltings's Theorem, /stating that the number of |
|
rational points on a curve of genus >1 is finite, I could find the |
|
actual number of points on any curve of genus >1. 8 |
|
|
|
-------------- |
|
|
|
<<9>>[[file:Unimath-9_1.png]] [[file:Unimath-9_2.png]] Univalent Foundations |
|
UniMath library We don't know whether such a proof exists. It is a |
|
very interesting and hard problem. The reason that the MLTT+UA is an |
|
imperfect system for constructive formalization is that while MLTT |
|
itself has the canonicity property MLTT+UA does not. Therefore, |
|
formalizing the proof of Faltings's Theorem in the UniMath, which is |
|
based on MLTT+UA, would not immediately give us an algorithm to |
|
compute the number of rational points on a curve of genus >1. This is |
|
where a new type theory that integrates the UA into the MLTT in such a |
|
way as to preserve the canonicity would help. 9 |
|
|
|
-------------- |
|
|
|
<<10>>[[file:Unimath-10_1.png]] [[file:Unimath-10_2.png]] Univalent |
|
Foundations UniMath library The search for such a type theory became |
|
one of the main driving forces in the development of the UF. Today |
|
several groups are working on the construction and implementation in a |
|
proof assistant of candidate type theories. The /cubical type theory/ |
|
and the prototype proof assistant /cubicaltt/ created by the group of |
|
Thierry Coquand with the help of many researchers from different parts |
|
of the world is at the most advanced stage of development today. A |
|
proof in the UniMath easily translates into a proof in the cubilatt. |
|
10 |
|
|
|
-------------- |
|
|
|
<<11>>[[file:Unimath-11_1.png]] [[file:Unimath-11_2.png]] Univalent |
|
Foundations UniMath library The new form of the UF that emerges can be |
|
seen as combining the following components: • the view of mathematics |
|
as the study of structures on sets and their higher analogs, • the |
|
view of mathematics as constructive with the classical mathematics |
|
being a subset consisting of the results that require LEM and/or AC |
|
among their assumptions, • the idea that the higher analogs of sets |
|
are reflected in the set-based mathematics as constructive homotopy |
|
types - objects of the new constructive homotopy theory that can so |
|
far be formulated only in terms of cubical sets, • the idea that one |
|
can formalize our intuition about structures on these higher analogs |
|
using Cubical Type Theory (CTT). 11 |
|
|
|
-------------- |
|
|
|
<<12>>[[file:Unimath-12_1.png]] [[file:Unimath-12_2.png]] Univalent |
|
Foundations UniMath library In addition to the understanding that to |
|
obtain a formal system for the new constructive mathematics the UA |
|
needs to be integrated into the MLTT constructively, several more |
|
things are felt as lacking in the MLTT+UA: • higher inductive types, • |
|
resizing rules, • a possible strict extensional equality combined with |
|
the “fibrancy discipline”, • as yet unknown mechanism to construct the |
|
types of structures that involve infinite hierarchies of coherence |
|
conditions. Surprisingly, it might be easier to add these features to |
|
the CTT than to the MLTT. The work in these directions is ongoing. 12 |
|
|
|
-------------- |
|
|
|
<<13>>Part 2. The UniMath library 13 |
|
|
|
-------------- |
|
|
|
<<14>>[[file:Unimath-14_1.png]] [[file:Unimath-14_2.png]] Univalent |
|
Foundations UniMath library In the development of the UniMath library |
|
we attempt to do something that might be compared with the effort by |
|
the Bourbaki group to write a systematic exposition of mathematics |
|
based on the set theory and the view of mathematics as studying |
|
structures on sets. The effort by Bourbaki stalled at some point |
|
around the middle of the 20th century, in part, because it was very |
|
complicated to describe the emerging category-theoretic constructions |
|
in set-theoretic terms. 14 |
|
|
|
-------------- |
|
|
|
<<15>>[[file:Unimath-15_1.png]] [[file:Unimath-15_2.png]] Univalent |
|
Foundations UniMath library One may however ask, is there any |
|
mathematical innovation in what we are doing? Is there a discovery of |
|
the unknown in the work on the UniMath? We have already seen how |
|
well-known problems in fields such as arithmetic algebraic geometry can |
|
be related to the search for a new foundation of constructive |
|
mathematics and for building proofs in the UniMath. Here is a |
|
different example. 15 |
|
|
|
-------------- |
|
|
|
<<16>>[[file:Unimath-16_1.png]] [[file:Unimath-16_2.png]] Univalent |
|
Foundations UniMath library Some years ago, at the IAS, I had a |
|
conversation at lunch with Armand Borel. I mentioned how I like |
|
Bourbaki “Algebra” and how it helped me to become a mathematician. I |
|
then mentioned that some places there were really dense. For example, |
|
said I, the description of the tensor product was hard to follow. Of |
|
course, said Borel, /we have invented tensor product to get a |
|
systematic exposition of multi-linear maps/. It was new research, |
|
this is why it was not very smoothly written. 16 |
|
|
|
-------------- |
|
|
|
<<17>>[[file:Unimath-17_1.png]] [[file:Unimath-17_2.png]] Univalent |
|
Foundations UniMath library I was amazed. It is hard to imagine |
|
today's mathematics without the concept of the tensor product. It |
|
would never occurred to me that it was invented by Bourbaki with the |
|
only purpose to obtain a more systematic exposition of multi-linear |
|
maps of vector spaces! This example shows how a major innovation can |
|
emerge from the work on systematization of knowledge. 17 |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
<<18>>[[file:Unimath-18_1.png]] [[file:Unimath-18_2.png]] Univalent |
|
Foundations UniMath library Finally, a few words to those |
|
mathematicians who will decide to understand UniMath and maybe to |
|
contribute to it. The UniMath library is being created using the |
|
proof assistant Coq. It is freely available on GitHub. The language |
|
of Coq is a very substantial extension of the MLTT and UniMath uses a |
|
very small subset of the full Coq language that approximately |
|
corresponds to the original MLTT. 18 |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
<<19>>[[file:Unimath-19_1.png]] [[file:Unimath-19_2.png]] |
|
[[file:Unimath-19_3.png]] Univalent Foundations UniMath library The |
|
first file in the UniMath after the /Basics/preamble.v/ is |
|
/Basics/PartA/.v. The first line in /Basics/PartA.v/ after the |
|
preamble section is as follows: |
|
|
|
It should be understood as a declaration of intent to define a constant |
|
called /fromempty /whose type is described by the expression that is |
|
written to the right of the colon. Following this line there is a |
|
paragraph that starts with /Proof./ and ends with /Defined. /where the |
|
constant is actually defined using the little sub-programs of Coq |
|
called tactics which help to build complex expressions of the |
|
underlying type theory language in simple steps. 19 |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
<<20>>[[file:Unimath-20_1.png]] [[file:Unimath-20_2.png]] Univalent |
|
Foundations UniMath library A mathematician who wants to understand |
|
UniMath should expect a very non-linear learning curve: • In the |
|
lectures that I gave in Oxford and in the similar lectures in the |
|
Hebrew University it took me the whole first lecture to explain what |
|
that first line and the following it paragraph really mean. • In the |
|
next lecture I was able to explain the next few hundred lines of |
|
PartA. • By the fourth lecture in Oxford, the video of which can be |
|
found on my website, I was explaining the invariant formalization of |
|
fibration sequences. 20 |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
<<21>>I hope that was able to show how important Univalent Foundations |
|
are and how important is the work on libraries such as UniMath. Thank |
|
you! 21 |
|
|
|
|
|
|