text
stringlengths 0
1.71k
|
---|
which allows atheists to use deontic language meaningfully without believing |
in God. God would, moreover, retain moral prerogatives that human |
beings wouldn β t, so God β s behavior, though ultimately recognizable as |
moral, need not be exactly like human morality (contrary to John Stuart |
Mill β s claim to the contrary). Although God β s issuing irremediably evil commands |
is vaguely conceivable, it wouldn β t be genuinely possible; reconciling |
God β s commands with ineliminable moral intuitions may be diffi cult but |
The Euthyphro Dilemma 51 |
can β t be impossible if it β s rational to believe in God β s moral perfection; and |
our grasp of necessary moral facts is an epistemic issue that would underdetermine |
the metaphysical foundations of morality. And fi nally, the dependence |
of morality on God does not entail God β s volitional control over the |
contents of morality to make it just anything at all; divine impeccability |
would rule some things out. Armed with such distinctions, the theistic ethicist |
and divine command theorist has not been shown to be irrational in |
light of the Euthyphro Dilemma. |
Is what is holy holy because the gods approve it, or do they approve it |
because it is holy? (Plato, 10a) |
P1. What is moral is either moral because God commands it or it is not. |
P2. If what is moral is moral because God commands it, then morality is |
arbitrary and vacuous. |
P3. If what is moral is moral for reasons other than that God commands |
it, then God is superfl uous from the standpoint of morality. |
C1. Either morality is arbitrary and vacuous or God is superfl uous to |
morality (constructive dilemma, P1, P2, P3). |
12 |
Nietzsche β s Death of God |
Tom Grimwood |
While Nietzsche resists easy logical formulation, the signifi cance of his |
critique of the ideas of truth and morality in Western philosophy makes |
him one of the most important thinkers in modern times. Perhaps no other |
philosopher has been defi ned through his legacy as has been Nietzsche: the |
assault on the metaphysical nature of truth in this argument not only lays |
foundations for existentialism, poststructuralism, and postmodernism, but |
it also provides moral philosophy with an emblematic fi gure of moral skepticism |
(in the work of MacIntyre or Williams, for example). |
For Nietzsche, the contemporary age (Northern Europe at the end of the |
nineteenth century) was witnessing a radical undermining of its philosophical |
foundations. On the one hand, the traditional beliefs in God were |
rendered unbelievable by developments in science. But on the other hand, |
the gap this left in existence had merely being fi lled by a substitute, science |
itself, which for Nietzsche maintained the same illusory suppositions over |
the sacred nature of β truth. β On the one hand, the rise of the middle classes |
in the industrial age was undermining traditional structures of society, |
revealing the importance and malleability of power to the development of |
humanity. On the other hand, Nietzsche saw that this great shift had produced |
not radical change but only apathy. The real problem, Nietzsche |
argued, was not that God had ceased to be believable, but β given the way |
Nietzsche , Friedrich . The Gay Science , translated by Josefi ne Nauckhoff. |
Cambridge, UK : Cambridge University Press , 2001 . |
Just the Arguments: 100 of the Most Important Arguments in Western Philosophy, |
First Edition. Edited by Michael Bruce and Steven Barbone. |
Β© 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. Published 2011 by Blackwell Publishing Ltd. |
Nietzscheβs Death of God 53 |
in which science seamlessly slotted into the same foundational space β |
nobody had really noticed the signifi cance of the event. Nietzsche is not a |
nihilist: for him, the death of God is the greatest event of recent times, |
enabling β Free Spirits β to throw off their metaphysical shackles and embrace |
a genuinely open future (although Nietzsche β s β necessary β ambiguity over |
the precise nature of this future has undeniably led to such diverse readings |
of his work). |
Hence, despite its subject matter, Nietzsche does not argue for the Death |
of God itself in his work in a way that would engage traditionally with the |
philosophy of religion β it is, rather, a proclamation of an event which is |
witnessed or reported (for example, in The Gay Science, Β§ 125, Β§ 343, and |
in the prologue to Thus Spoke Zarathustra ). He is more interested in how |
we, as humans, react to the event: whether we embrace its full signifi cance |
or continue to place a similar β faith β in concepts that remain dependent |
upon the same metaphysical assumptions, such as science and/or morality. |
Central to these assumptions is the affi rmation of β another world, β that of |
β truth, β which lies behind our immediate world of experience (for |
Christianity, this is β heaven β ; for morality, the abstract β good β ; for science, |
atomic structures; and so on). This β beyond β removes us from our own |
sensibilities and retains us in a quasi - religious state in reverence to the |
scientifi c and/or the moral. Given that such an ordering of the world infects |
both our language and practice, Nietzsche consequently views the importance |
of truth as metaphorical rather than rational: the sense we make of |
the world is always limited by our perspective (indeed, in his early work he |
argues that truth is itself a mixed metaphorical construction, a point much |
elaborated on by later poststructuralists), and as such images, fi gures, and |
motifs authorize this sense long before we construct a justifi catory logic for |
it. Nietzsche β s style of arguing is at once rigorously philological, tracing |
the historical development of concepts with intense academic skill, and |
at the same time almost hopelessly generalizing, aiming broad shots across |
the bows of our expectations of what a philosophical argument should be. |
This style must be borne in mind when approaching the logic of Nietzsche β s |
argument: his argument over the Death of God is far more a polemic than |
it is an exercise in close reasoning, and at least one of its aims is to open |
our eyes to a world without fi xed parameters of meaning and truth, and in |
its place, a raw fl ux of energy and power. |
The greatest recent event β that β God is dead β ; that the belief in the |
Christian God has become unbelievable β is already starting to cast its fi rst |
shadow over Europe. [ β¦ ] But in the main one might say: for many people β s |
power of comprehension, the event is itself far too great, distant, and out of |
the way even for its tidings to be thought of as having arrived yet. Even less |
may one suppose many to know at all what this even really means β and, |
54 Tom Grimwood |
now that this faith has been undermined, how much must collapse because |
it was built on this faith, leaned on it, had grown on it β for example, our |
entire European morality. ( Β§ 343) |
Subsets and Splits
No community queries yet
The top public SQL queries from the community will appear here once available.