text
stringlengths 0
1.71k
|
---|
Wouldn β t the cultivation of the scientifi c spirit begin when one permitted |
oneself no more convictions? That is probably the case; only we need still |
ask: in order that this cultivation begin , must there not be some prior conviction |
β and indeed one so authoritative and unconditional that it sacrifi ces all |
other convictions to itself? We see that science, too, rests on a faith; there is |
simply no β presuppositionless β science. The question whether truth is necessary |
must get an answer in advance, the answer β yes β , and moreover this |
answer must be so fi rm that it takes the form of the statement, the belief, the |
conviction: β Nothing is more necessary than truth; and in relation to it, everything |
else has only secondary value. β [ β¦ ] But why not deceive? But why |
not allow oneself to be deceived? Note that the reasons for the former lie in |
a completely different area from those for the latter: one does not want to let |
oneself be deceived because one assumes it is harmful, dangerous, disastrous |
to be deceived; in this sense science would be a long - range prudence, caution, |
utility, and to this one could justifi ably object: How so? Is it really less |
harmful, dangerous, disastrous not to want to let oneself be deceived? [ β¦ ] |
Precisely this conviction could never have originated if truth and untruth had |
constantly made it clear that they were both useful, as they are. So, the faith |
in science, which after all undeniably exists, cannot owe its origin to such a |
calculus of utility; rather it must have originated in spite of the fact that the |
disutility and dangerousness of the β will to truth β or β truth at any price β is |
proved to it constantly. [ β¦ ] Consequently, β will to truth β does not mean β I |
do not want to let myself be deceived β but β there is no alternative β β I will |
not deceive, not even myself β ; and with that we stand on moral ground . |
( Β§ 344) |
Thus the question β Why science? β leads back to the moral problem: Why |
morality at all , if life, nature, and history are β immoral β ? No doubt, those |
who are truthful in that audacious and ultimate sense which faith in science |
presupposes thereby affi rm another world than that of life, nature, and |
history; [ β¦ ] it is still a metaphysical faith upon which our faith in science |
rests β that even we knowers of today, we godless anti - metaphysicians, still |
take our fi re, too, from the fl ame lit by the thousand - year old faith, the |
Christian faith which was also Plato β s faith, that God is truth; that truth is |
divine [ β¦ ] But what if this were to become more and more diffi cult to believe, |
if nothing more were to turn out to be divine except error, blindness, the lie |
β if God himself were to turn out to be our longest lie? ( Β§ 344) |
The opening part of this reconstructed argument is not Nietzsche β s but |
rather a standard motif of modernity, which Nietzsche takes to task: |
P1. If we accept or commit to something as an organizing principle of our |
lives, then it should be rational, true, or believable. |
Nietzscheβs Death of God 55 |
P2. God β s existence is not rational, true, or believable ( β The belief in the |
Christian God has become unbelievable, β Β§ 343). |
C1. We should not accept and commit to God as an organizing principle |
of our lives ( modus tollens , P1, P2). |
The majority of people are happy with this, Nietzsche thinks, because they |
substitute other, more believable principles β science, morality, and so on β in |
the place of β God β s existence β . P2 then becomes an affi rmation rather than a |
negation β β science is rational β , for example β albeit creating a fallacy of |
affi rming the consequent. It is these substitutions that Nietzsche sees as remnants |
of belief that are really challenged by the idea of the Death of God. |
Thus, Nietzsche is not interested in discussing the existence or nature of God |
(P2 or C1). His issue is rather with the claim made in P1: our desire to seek a |
β truth β in the world beyond our immediate sensations, or, as Nietzsche terms |
it, the Will to Truth, and why this conditions our lives in the way it does. |
P3. If science, morality, or religion contains assumptions, then these will |
affect the outcome of its inquiry. |
Again, here Nietzsche is using the principles of the Enlightenment (the |
β scientifi c spirit β ) that knowledge should be objective and without assumptions |
(or, in Nietzsche β s words, β convictions β ). β Wouldn β t the cultivation |
of the scientifi c spirit begin when one permitted oneself no more convictions? |
β But Nietzsche probes this premise, β we need still ask: in order that |
this cultivation begin , must there not be some prior conviction β and indeed |
one so authoritative and unconditional that it sacrifi ces all other convictions |
to itself? β ( Β§ 344). |
P4. Science, morality, and religion contain the same assumption: the Will |
to Truth (the unspoken assumption of science, for example, is that truth |
is worth discovering: the β yes β in advance); β There is simply no β presuppositionless |
β science. β |
C2. The Will to Truth affects the outcome of (moral, scientifi c, religious) |
inquiry ( modus ponens , P3, P4). |
Nietzsche is noting here that our understanding is conditioned by the |
need to discover a β truth β beyond our immediate perception, which he |
considers most moral, scientifi c, and religious understanding to do (he |
writes more on this in the section of Beyond Good and Evil entitled β On |
the prejudices of philosophers β ). |
P5. If the Will to Truth is essential to our understanding (i.e., we can have |
no knowledge without it), then we will have a reason for following it. |
P6. But we do not have a moral or utilitarian reason for following it. |
56 Tom Grimwood |
When Nietzsche asks whether it is β really less harmful, dangerous, disastrous |
not to want to let oneself be deceived? β we can see that lying and |
deception can, in fact, be very useful (e.g., when raising children, absolute |
truth is unnecessary and sometimes unhelpful). |
C3. The Will to Truth is not essential to our understanding ( modus |
tollens , P5, P6). |
As Nietzsche refl ects, β you only have to ask yourself carefully, β Why do |
you not want to deceive? β especially if it should seem β and it does seem! |
β as if [ β¦ ] life on the largest scale has actually always shown itself to be |
on the side of the most unscrupulous polytropoi . β (201) β Polytropoi β |
means devious, cunning, deceptive. It comes from The Odyssey , where it is |
used to describe the hero who uses these traits to survive the wrath of the |
gods. In other words, Nietzsche is suggesting that β life β in general does not |
favor truth in the way that scientifi c or moral knowledge seems to. |
The argument then makes two interrelated points surrounding the status |
of β truth β itself: |
P7. If we do not have moral or utilitarian reasons for following the Will to |
Truth, our reasons must be other than these. |
β Should both be necessary β a lot of trust as well as a lot of mistrust β |
then where might science get the unconditional belief or conviction one |
Subsets and Splits
No community queries yet
The top public SQL queries from the community will appear here once available.