text
stringlengths 0
1.71k
|
---|
all cases (logical pluralism, hypothesis to be reduced). |
C1. Since they are different collections of valid inferences, there is an |
inference X => Y belonging to one of the collections but not to the other |
( modus ponens , P4, P5). |
C2. If X => Y is a valid inference, then it holds in all cases (equivalence, |
simplifi cation, P2). |
C3. If X => Y is not a valid inference, then it does not hold in all cases |
(equivalence, simplifi cation, P2 β² ). |
C4. X => Y holds in all cases ( modus ponens , C1, C2). |
C5. X => Y does not hold in all cases ( modus ponens , C1, C3). |
C6. X => Y holds in all cases and X => Y does not hold in all cases (conjunction, |
C4, C5). |
C7. There are not even two collections of inferences that are different |
and hold in all cases ( reductio , P5 β C6). |
C8. There is exactly one collection of inferences holding in all cases |
(disjunctive syllogism, P3, C7). |
29 |
The Maximality Paradox |
Nicola Ciprotti |
Adams , Robert . β Theories of Actuality , β No Γ» s 8 ( 1974 ): 211 β 31 . Reprinted |
in The Possible and the Actual. Readings in the Metaphysics of Modality , |
edited by Michael Loux , 190 β 209 . Ithaca, NY : Cornell University Press , |
1979 . (All subsequent references are to this edition.) |
Chihara , Charles . The Worlds of Possibility: Modal Realism and the Semantics |
of Modal Logic . Oxford : Clarendon Press , 1998 . |
Davies , Martin . Meaning, Quantifi cation, Necessity: Themes in Philosophical |
Logic . London : Routledge & Kegan Paul , 1981 . |
Divers , John . Possible Worlds . London : Routledge , 2002 . |
Grim , Patrick . The Incomplete Universe. Totality, Knowledge, and Truth . |
Cambridge, MA : The MIT Press , 1991 . |
The suggested label for the argument to follow, the β maximality paradox, β |
is tentative. As a matter of fact, there currently is no consensus as to what |
the most appropriate label might be; what β s more, there is not even consensus |
as to who fi rst formulated it. Robert Adams is credited with having |
been the fi rst to touch on it in print, while the fi rst detailed formulation is |
due to Martin Davies. |
Such uncertainties about name and origin have possibly to do with the |
fact that the maximality paradox is actually a family of closely related, yet |
distinct, arguments. For, while each argument relies on a common body of |
tenets, namely, well - established facts of standard set theory, it nevertheless |
is the case that the salient targets of maximality paradox can, and do, differ. |
What is common to each argument, and so what the maximality paradox |
essentially consists in, is that a reductio of the hypothesis that a set A exists |
of a given sort, namely a totality - set, is arrived at. Different maximality |
Just the Arguments: 100 of the Most Important Arguments in Western Philosophy, |
First Edition. Edited by Michael Bruce and Steven Barbone. |
Β© 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. Published 2011 by Blackwell Publishing Ltd. |
116 Nicola Ciprotti |
paradox - style arguments can be wielded, however, against the existence of |
distinct set - theoretic (or set - like) totalities, such as, for example, the set of |
all possible worlds, the set of all truths, or the set of all states of affairs |
(whether or not the maximality paradox also threatens the existence of the |
members of such sets, not only the sets themselves, is an issue we shall |
briefl y address in closing). |
In what follows, we shall focus on Adams β original outline of maximality |
paradox as subsequently given rigorous shape by John Divers. This version |
of the maximality paradox is specifi cally concerned with a particular conception |
of possible worlds as world - stories, namely, peculiar sets of propositions. |
After due modifi cations, however, the argument can be conferred |
wider in scope so as to apply to set - like totalities including elements that |
are different from possible worlds. |
According to a good deal of philosophers (#99), abstract entities of |
various sorts exist. Among them are sets, numbers, states of affairs, propositions, |
and properties, to name the ones referred to most often. The majority |
of philosophers who believe in abstract objects also include possible worlds |
among them. In particular, the suggestion is that possible worlds can be |
analyzed as world - stories, that is, sets of propositions that are both (i) |
consistent and (ii) maximal collections thereof. |
Generally speaking, a set A is consistent if and only if it is possible for |
its members to be jointly true (or jointly obtain); a set A is maximal if and |
only if, for every proposition p , either A includes p or A includes the contradiction |
of p . Such two conditions seem constitutive of the notion of a |
possible world: a possible world ought to be possible, that is, a contradiction - |
free entity; a possible world ought to be maximal, that is, a complete |
alternative way things might be, or have been β one fi lled in up to the |
minutest detail. |
According to this conception, then, the explicit defi nition of β possible |
world β is as follows: |
(DF) w is a possible world = df w is a set A of propositions such that: (i) |
for every proposition p , either p is an element A or p is not an element |
A (maximality condition); (ii) the conjunction of the members of A is |
consistent (consistency condition). |
The main asset of (DF) is that, through it, the existence of possible worlds |
is made compatible with an ontology that eschews quantifi cation over |
nonactual objects, generally regarded as entia non grata . Qua sets of propositions, |
in fact, it is alleged that no more than actually existing abstract |
objects β indeed, sets and propositions β is needed for accommodating possible |
worlds within a respectable actualist ontology; that is, one free of mere |
possibilia . (DF), though, gives rise to the maximality paradox. |
The Maximality Paradox 117 |
Notoriously, the development of a satisfactory logic theory of propositions |
[ . . . ] is also beset by formal problems and threats of paradox. One such threat |
particularly concerns the [ . . . ] theory [of possible worlds as maximal sets of |
propositions]. The theory seems to imply that there are consistent sets composed |
of one member of every pair of mutually contradictory propositions. |
Furthermore, it follows from the theory, with the assumption that every possible |
world is actual in itself, that every world - story, s , has among its members |
the proposition that all the members of s are true. Here we are teetering on |
the brink of paradox [ . . . ]. This may give rise to a suspicion that the [ . . . ] |
theory could not be precisely formulated without engendering some analogue |
Subsets and Splits
No community queries yet
The top public SQL queries from the community will appear here once available.