text
stringlengths 0
1.71k
|
---|
First Edition. Edited by Michael Bruce and Steven Barbone. |
Β© 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. Published 2011 by Blackwell Publishing Ltd. |
120 Gerald Harrison |
name) have been presented by Thomas Reid, Randolph Clarke, Peter van |
Inwagen ( Essay ), and Peter Strawson, among others. |
Just as it is widely agreed that moral responsibility requires free will, it |
is also widely agreed that we are morally responsible for at least some of |
what we do some of the time. For Reid, it was a fi rst principle β that some |
aspects of human conduct deserve praise, others blame β (361). According |
to Peter Strawson, our commitment to moral responsibility is so deeply |
rooted that it is simply inconceivable that we could give it up, and thus the |
reality of moral responsibility sets a boundary condition for where rational |
argument can lead. |
If our moral responsibility is beyond reasonable doubt, then it must be |
beyond reasonable doubt that we possess free will, as the former presupposes |
the latter. Thus, we get our positive argument for free will. |
Not everyone accepts this argument. A signifi cant minority of philosophers |
deny that we are morally responsible. There are, after all, powerful |
arguments both for thinking that free will is incompatible with determinism |
and for thinking that it is incompatible with indeterminism. Such arguments |
can be used to raise doubts about whether we have free will, and so to raise |
doubts about moral responsibility. |
For most, however, the belief that we are morally responsible has greater |
initial plausibility than any of the premises of an argument leading to the |
denial of free will. Moral responsibility therefore provides the best positive |
argument for thinking that we do have free will. |
There are, moreover, seemingly unanswerable arguments that, if they are |
correct, demonstrate that the existence of moral responsibility entails the |
existence of free will, and, therefore, if free will does not exist, moral responsibility |
does not exist either. It is, however, evident that moral responsibility |
does exist: if there were no such thing as moral responsibility nothing would |
be anyone β s fault, and it is evident that there are states of affairs to which one |
can point and say, correctly, to certain people: That β s your fault. (van Inwagen |
β How to Think β ) |
P1. If we are morally responsible then we have free will. |
P2. We are morally responsible. |
C1. We have free will ( modus ponens , P1, P2). |
31 |
Frankfurt β s Refutation of |
the Principle of Alternative |
Possibilities |
Gerald Harrison |
Frankfurt , Harry . β Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility . β Journal |
of Philosophy 45 ( 1969 ): 829 β 39 . |
Fischer , John M. β Frankfurt - Style Compatibilism , β in Free Will , edited by |
Gary Watson , 190 β 211 . Oxford : Oxford University Press , 2003 . |
Widerker , David , and Michael McKenna , (eds.). Moral Responsibility and |
Alternative Possibilities . Farnham, UK : Ashgate , 2006 . |
Endorsed by Aristotle, Hume, Kant, and many others the β Principle of |
Alternative Possibilities β (PAP for short) states: |
PAP: A person is morally responsible for what she has done only if she |
could have done otherwise. |
Historically, PAP has been one of the most popular routes to β incompatibilism |
β about moral responsibility (incompatibilism is the view that |
moral responsibility and causal determinism β the thesis that there is only |
one future compatible with the past and the laws of nature β are incompatible). |
After all, if determinism is true, there β s a sense in which no one could |
ever have acted differently. β Compatibilists β (those who believe determinism |
and moral responsibility to be compatible) resisted this argument by |
arguing that PAP should be given a controversial β conditional β interpretation |
according to which an agent could have done otherwise if he would |
have done so had he desired. |
Just the Arguments: 100 of the Most Important Arguments in Western Philosophy, |
First Edition. Edited by Michael Bruce and Steven Barbone. |
Β© 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. Published 2011 by Blackwell Publishing Ltd. |
122 Gerald Harrison |
But in 1969, the philosopher Harry Frankfurt devised an argument to |
refute PAP. Frankfurt argued that it is possible for circumstances to arise |
in which it is clear that a person could not have done otherwise yet also |
clear that he is morally responsible for his deed. The defi ning feature of |
what has now become known as a β Frankfurt - style case β is that an intervention |
device does not intervene in a process leading to an action but |
would have intervened if the agent had been about to decide differently. |
The presence of the intervention mechanism rules out the possibility of the |
agent β s deciding differently, yet because the intervention mechanism plays |
no role in the agent β s deliberations and subsequent action, it seems clear |
that the agent is fully morally responsible for his action; hence PAP is |
refuted. |
By refuting PAP, Frankfurt β s argument closes off one of the major routes |
to incompatibilism and allows compatibilists to bypass the debate over the |
correct interpretation of PAP. |
Frankfurt β s argument remains the focus of considerable debate, with |
detractors arguing that it is impossible to construct a Frankfurt - style case |
in which all relevant alternative possibilities have been expunged. |
Suppose someone, Black, let us say wants Jones to perform a certain |
action. Black is prepared to go to considerable lengths to get his way, but he |
prefers to avoid showing his hand unnecessarily. So he waits until Jones is |
about to make up his mind what to do, and he does nothing unless it is clear |
to him (Black is an excellent judge of such things) that Jones is going to decide |
to do something other than what he wants him to do. If it does become clear |
that Jones is going to decide to do something else, Black takes effective steps |
to ensure that Jones decides to do, and that he does do, what he wants him |
to do. Whatever Jones β s initial preferences and inclinations, then, Black will |
have his way [ β¦ ]. |
Now suppose that Black never has to show his hand because Jones, for |
reasons of his own, decides to perform and does perform the very action Black |
wants him to perform. In that case, it seems clear, Jones will bear precisely |
the same moral responsibility for what he does as he would have borne if |
Black had not been ready to take steps to ensure that he do it. (Frankfurt, |
835 β 6) |
Subsets and Splits
No community queries yet
The top public SQL queries from the community will appear here once available.