text
stringlengths 0
1.71k
|
---|
P1. An agent is morally responsible for what he has done only if he could |
have done otherwise (PAP). |
P2. If PAP is true, then a Frankfurt - style case will absolve its subject from |
moral responsibility. |
P3. Frankfurt - style cases do not absolve their subjects from moral |
responsibility. |
C1. PAP is false ( modus tollens , P2, P3). |
32 |
Van Inwagen β s Consequence |
Argument against Compatibilism |
Grant Sterling |
van Inwagen , Peter . An Essay on Free Will . Oxford : Clarendon Press , 1983 . |
One of the most famous recent arguments in the free will and determinism |
debate is Peter van Inwagen β s consequence argument, which aims to show |
that compatibilism is false. Compatibilism is the view that all our actions |
could be fully determined by the laws of physics and yet at the same time |
we could have free will in the sense necessary for moral responsibility. Van |
Inwagen introduces the essence of this argument near the beginning of his |
book on free will and then goes on to gives three detailed technical versions |
of the argument. Included here is the simple version and the fi rst technical |
formalization (which aims to show that under determinism we could never |
act in any way other than the way in which we do act). |
If determinism is true, then our acts are consequences of the laws of nature |
and events in the remote past. But it is not up to us what went on before we were |
born, and neither is it up to us what the laws of nature are. Therefore, the consequences |
of these things (including our present acts) are not up to us. (16) |
Consider any act that (logically) someone might have performed. If it |
should turn out that this act was incompatible with the state of the world |
before that person β s birth taken together with the laws of nature, then it |
follows that that person could not have performed that act. Moreover, if |
determinism is true, then just any deviation from the actual course of events |
would be incompatible with any past state of the world taken together with |
the laws of nature. Therefore, if determinism is true, it never has been within |
Just the Arguments: 100 of the Most Important Arguments in Western Philosophy, |
First Edition. Edited by Michael Bruce and Steven Barbone. |
Β© 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. Published 2011 by Blackwell Publishing Ltd. |
124 Grant Sterling |
my power to deviate from the actual course of events that has constituted my |
history. (75) |
P1. If determinism is true, then our acts are consequences of the laws of |
nature and events in the remote past. |
P2. The laws of nature and events in the remote past are not up to us. |
P3. If something is not up to us, then its consequences are not up to us. |
C1. If the laws of nature and events in the remote past are not up to us, |
then their consequences are not up to us (substitution, P2, P3). |
C2. Consequences of the laws of nature and events in the remote past |
are not up to us ( modus ponens , P2, C1). |
C3. If determinism is true, then our acts are not up to us (in our control, |
within our ability) (substitution, C2, P1). |
P4. If our acts are not up to us, then we β re not responsible for them. |
C4. If determinism is true, we β re not responsible for any of our acts |
(hypothetical syllogism, C3, P4). |
Van Inwagen β s First Formalization |
Defi nitions: |
Let β U β be a complete description of the state of the universe right now. |
Let β U β 1 β be a complete description of the state of the universe the day |
before some person β X β was born. |
Let β A β be some action that X did not perform. |
Let β L β be the laws of nature. |
P1. X cannot change U β 1 (no one can change the past state of the universe |
at a time before she was even born). |
P2. X cannot change L (no one can change the laws of nature). |
P3. If determinism is true, then {(U β 1 plus L), entails U} (follows from the |
concept of determinism). |
P4. If X had done A, then not - U (A is an action that didn β t occur, so if it |
had occurred the universe wouldn β t be exactly the same as it is now). |
C1. If X could have done A, X could have made U false (follows semantically |
from P4). |
C2. If X could have made U false, then X could have made (U β 1 plus |
L) false (transposition, P3). |
C3. If X could have made (U β 1 plus L) false, then X could have made |
L false (De Morgan β s, C2, P1, and disjunctive syllogism). |
C4. X could not have made L false (P2). |
C5. X could not do A ( modus tollens , C3, C4, and a series of implicit |
hypothetical syllogisms). |
33 |
Fatalism |
Fernando Migura and Agustin Arrieta |
Aquinas , Thomas . Summa Theologiae , translated by Fathers of the English |
Dominican Province, The Summa Theologiae , 2nd rev. edn., 22 vols. |
London : Burns, Oates & Washbourne , 1912 β 36. Reprinted in 5 vols., |
Westminster: Christian Classics, 1981 . E - text in HTML available at |
www.newadvent.org/summa |
Aristotle . Aristotle Categories and De Interpretatione , translated with notes |
and glossary by J. L. Ackrill. Oxford : Clarendon Press , 1961 . |
Augustine , Saint . On Free Choice of the Will , translated, with introduction |
by Thomas Williams. Indianapolis : Hackett , 1993 . |
Rice , Hugh . β Fatalism . β The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy ( Fall |
2009 edn.), edited by Edward N. Zalta , available at http:// |
plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2009/entries/fatalism |
According to the philosophical doctrine called β fatalism, β everything that |
happens does so inevitably. Suppose that something is going to happen |
tomorrow; let β s say that it is going to rain. If it is true now that tomorrow |
it is going to rain, then it can β t be true that it won β t rain tomorrow, so it is |
necessary to rain tomorrow. On the other hand, if it is false now that tomorrow |
it is going to rain, then it can β t be true that it will rain tomorrow, so |
it is impossible to rain tomorrow; that is, it is necessary that it won β t rain |
tomorrow. Since the same reasoning can be applied to every event, everything |
that happens does so necessarily and inevitably. |
Just the Arguments: 100 of the Most Important Arguments in Western Philosophy, |
Subsets and Splits
No community queries yet
The top public SQL queries from the community will appear here once available.