text
stringlengths 0
1.71k
|
---|
women, who would have been killed, are alive today.
|
290
|
Ends and Means
|
In 1976 Bob Brown, then a young medical practitioner, rafted
|
down the Franklin river, in Tasmania's southwest. The wild
|
beauty of the river and the peace of the undisturbed forests
|
around it impressed him deeply. Then, around a bend on the
|
lower reaches of the river, he came across workers for the
|
Hydro-Electric Commission, studying the feasibility of building
|
a dam across the river. Brown gave up his medical practice
|
and founded the Tasmanian Wilderness Society, with the object
|
of protecting the state's remaining wilderness areas. Despite
|
vigorous campaigning, the Hydro-Electric Commission recommended
|
the building of the dam, and after some vacillation the
|
state government, with support both from the business community
|
and the labour unions, decided to go ahead. The Tasmanian
|
Wilderness Society organized a non-violent blockade
|
of the road being built to the dam site. In 1982, Brown, along
|
with many others, was arrested and jailed for four days for
|
trespassing on land controlled by the Hydro-Electric Commission.
|
But the blockade became a focus of national attention,
|
and although the Australian federal government was not direcdy
|
responsible for the dam, it became an issue in the federal
|
election that was then due. The Australian Labor Party, in opposition
|
before the election, pledged to explore constitutional
|
means of preventing the dam from going ahead. The election
|
saw the Labor party elected to office, and legislation passed to
|
stop the dam. Though challenged by the Tasmanian government,
|
the legislation was upheld by a narrow majority of the
|
High Court of Australia on the grounds that the Tasmanian
|
southwest was a World Heritage area, and the federal government
|
had constitutional powers to uphold the international
|
treaty creating the World Heritage Commission. Today the
|
Franklin still runs free.
|
Do we have an overriding obligation to obey the law? Oskar
|
Schindler, the members of the Animal Liberation Front who
|
291
|
Practical Ethics
|
took Gennarelli's videotapes, Joan Andrews of Operation Rescue,
|
and Bob Brown and those who joined him in front of the
|
bulldozers in Tasmania's southwest were all breaking the law.
|
Were they all acting wrongly?
|
The question cannot be dealt with by invoking the simplistic
|
formula: 'the end never justifies the means'. For all but the
|
strictest adherent of an ethic of rules, the end sometimes does
|
justify the means. Most people think that lying is wrong, other
|
things being equal, yet think it right to lie in order to avoid
|
causing unnecessary offence or embarrassment - for instance,
|
when a well-meaning relative gives you a hideous vase for your
|
birthday, and then asks if you really like it. If this relatively
|
trivial end can justify lying, it is even more obvious that some
|
important end - preventing a murder, or saving animals from
|
great suffering - can justify lying. Thus the principle that the
|
end cannot justify the means is easily breached. The difficult
|
issue is not whether the end can ever justify the means, but
|
which means are justified by which ends.
|
INDIVIDUAL CONSCIENCE AND THE LAW
|
There are many people who are opposed to damming wild
|
rivers, to the exploitation of animals, or to abortion, but who
|
do not break the law in order to stop these activities. No doubt
|
some members of the more conventional conservation, animal
|
liberation, and anti-abortion organizations do not commit illegal
|
acts because they do not wish to be fined or imprisoned; but
|
others would be prepared to take the consequences of illegal
|
acts. They refrain only because they respect and obey the moral
|
authority of the law.
|
Who is right in this ethical disagreement? Are we under any
|
moral obligation to obey the law, if the law protects and sanctions
|
things we hold utterly wrong? A clear-cut answer to this
|
question was given by the nineteenth-century American radical,
|
292
|
Ends and Means
|
Henry Thoreau. In his essay entitled 'Civil Disobedience' - perhaps
|
the first use of this now-familiar phrase - he wrote:
|
Must the citizen ever for a moment, or in the least degree, resign
|
his conscience to the legislator? Why has every man a conscience,
|
then? I think we should be men first and subjects afterwards. It
|
is not desirable to cultivate a respect for the law, so much as for
|
the right. The only obligation which I have a right to assume, is
|
to do at any time what I think right.
|
The American philosopher Robert Paul Wolff has written in
|
similar vein:
|
The defining mark of the state is authority, the right to rule. The
|
primary obligation of man is autonomy, the refusal to be ruled,
|
It would seem, then, that there can be no resolution of the conflict
|
between the autonomy of the individual and the putative authority
|
of the state. Insofar as a man fulfills his obligation to
|
make himself the author of his decisions, he will resist the state's
|
claim to have authority over him.
|
Thoreau and Wolff resolve the conflict between individual and
|
society in favour of the individual. We should do as our conscience
|
dIctates, as we autonomously decide we ought to do:
|
not as the law directs. Anything else would be a denial of our
|
capacity for ethical choice.
|
Thus stated, the issue looks straightforward and the ThoreauWolff
|
answer obviously right. So Oskar Schindler, the Animal
|
Liberation Front, Joan Andrews, and Bob Brown were fully
|
justified in doing what they saw to be right, rather than what
|
the state laid down as lawful. But is it that simple? There is a
|
sense in which it is undeniable that, as Thoreau says, we ought
|
Subsets and Splits
No community queries yet
The top public SQL queries from the community will appear here once available.