text
stringlengths 0
118
|
---|
daub and to a masterpiece. In every such case the individual is entitled to
|
decide whether that which is his shall be given to the public. No other has
|
the right to publish his productions in any form, without his consent. This
|
right is wholly independent of the material on which, or the means by
|
which, the thought, sentiment, or emotion is expressed. It may exist
|
independently of any corporeal being, as in words spoken, a song sung, a
|
drama acted. Or if expressed on any material, as in a poem in writing, the
|
author may have parted with the paper, without forfeiting any proprietary
|
right in the composition itself. The right is lost only when the author
|
himself communicates his production to the public, — in other words,
|
publishes it. It is entirely independent of the copyright laws, and their
|
extension into the domain of art. The aim of those statutes is to secure to the
|
author, composer, or artist the entire profits arising from publication; but the
|
common-law protection enables him to control absolutely the act of
|
publication, and in the exercise of his own discretion, to decide whether
|
there shall be any publication at all. The statutory right is of no value,
|
unless there is a publication; the common-law right is lost as soon as there
|
is a publication.
|
What is the nature, the basis, of this right to prevent the publication of
|
manuscripts or works of art? It is stated to be the enforcement of a right of
|
property; and no difficulty arises in accepting this view, so long as we have
|
only to deal with the reproduction of literary and artistic compositions.
|
They certainly possess many of the attributes of ordinary property: they are
|
transferable; they have a value; and publication or reproduction is a use by
|
which that value is realized. But where the value of the production is found
|
not in the right to take the profits arising from publication, but in the peace
|
of mind or the relief afforded by the ability to prevent any publication at all,
|
it is difficult to regard the right as one of property, in the common
|
acceptation of that term. A man records in a letter to his son, or in his diary,
|
that he did not dine with his wife on a certain day. No one into whose hands
|
those papers fall could publish them to the world, even if possession of the
|
documents had been obtained rightfully; and the prohibition would not be
|
confined to the publication of a copy of the letter itself, or of the diary
|
entry; the restraint extends also to a publication of the contents. What is the
|
thing which is protected? Surely, not the intellectual act of recording the
|
fact that the husband did not dine with his wife, but that fact itself. It is not
|
the intellectual product, but the domestic occurrence. A man writes a dozen
|
letters to different people. No person would be permitted to publish a list of
|
the letters written. If the letters or the contents of the diary were protected
|
as literary compositions, the scope of the protection afforded should be the
|
same secured to a published writing under the copyright law. But the
|
copyright law would not prevent an enumeration of the letters, or the
|
publication of some of the facts contained therein. The copyright of a series
|
of paintings or etchings would prevent a reproduction of the paintings as
|
pictures; but it would not prevent a publication of list or even a description
|
of them. Yet in the famous case of Prince Albert v. Strange, the court held
|
that the common-law rule prohibited not merely the reproduction of the
|
etchings which the plaintiff and Queen Victoria had made for their own
|
pleasure, but also “the publishing (at least by printing or writing), though
|
not by copy or resemblance, a description of them, whether more or less
|
limited or summary, whether in the form of a catalogue or otherwise.”
|
Likewise, an unpublished collection of news possessing no element of a
|
literary nature is protected from piracy.
|
That this protection cannot rest upon the right to literary or artistic
|
property in any exact sense, appears the more clearly when the subject-
|
matter for which protection is invoked is not even in the form of intellectual
|
property, but has the attributes of ordinary tangible property. Suppose a man
|
has a collection of gems or curiosities which he keeps private: it would
|
hardly be contended that any person could publish a catalogue of them, and
|
yet the articles enumerated are certainly not intellectual property in the legal
|
sense, any more than a collection of stoves or of chairs.
|
The belief that the idea of property in its narrow sense was the basis of
|
the protection of unpublished manuscripts led an able court to refuse, in
|
several cases, injunctions against the publication of private letters, on the
|
ground that “letters not possessing the attributes of literary compositions are
|
not property entitled to protection;” and that it was “evident the plaintiff
|
could not have considered the letters as of any value whatever as literary
|
productions, for a letter cannot be considered of value to the author which
|
he never would consent to have published.” But those decisions have not
|
been followed, and it may now be considered settled that the protection
|
afforded by the common law to the author of any writing is entirely
|
independent of its pecuniary value, its intrinsic merits, or of any intention to
|
publish the same and, of course, also, wholly independent of the material, if
|
any, upon which, or the mode in which, the thought or sentiment was
|
expressed.
|
Although the courts have asserted that they rested their decisions on the
|
narrow grounds of protection to property, yet there are recognitions of a
|
more liberal doctrine. Thus in the case of Prince Albert v. Strange, already
|
referred to, the opinions both of the Vice-Chancellor and of the Lord
|
Chancellor, on appeal, show a more or less clearly defined perception of a
|
principle broader than those which were mainly discussed, and on which
|
they both placed their chief reliance. Vice-Chancellor Knight Bruce referred
|
to publishing of a man that he had “written to particular persons or on
|
particular subjects” as an instance of possibly injurious disclosures as to
|
private matters, that the courts would in a proper case prevent; yet it is
|
difficult to perceive how, in such a case, any right of privacy, in the narrow
|
sense, would be drawn in question, or why, if such a publication would be
|
restrained when it threatened to expose the victim not merely to sarcasm,
|
but to ruin, it should not equally be enjoined, if it threatened to embitter his
|
life. To deprive a man of the potential profits to be realized by publishing a
|
catalogue of his gems cannot per se be a wrong to him. The possibility of
|
future profits is not a right of property which the law ordinarily recognizes;
|
it must, therefore, be an infraction of other rights which constitutes the
|
wrongful act, and that infraction is equally wrongful, whether its results are
|
to forestall the profits that the individual himself might secure by giving the
|
matter a publicity obnoxious to him, or to gain an advantage at the expense
|
of his mental pain and suffering. . . .
|
These considerations lead to the conclusion that the protection afforded
|
to thoughts, sentiments, and emotions, expressed through the medium of
|
writing or of the arts, so far as it consists in preventing publication, is
|
Subsets and Splits
No community queries yet
The top public SQL queries from the community will appear here once available.