text
stringlengths 0
1.71k
|
---|
characteristic of psychopaths to work for a while at a job and |
then just when their ability and charm have taken them to the |
crest of success, commit some petty and easily detectable crime. |
A similar pattern occurs in their personal relationships. (There |
is support to be found here for Thomas Nagel's account of im- |
329 |
Practical Ethics |
prudence as rational only if one fails to see oneself as a person |
existing over time, with the present merely one among other |
times one will live through. Certainly psychopathic people live |
largely in the present and lack any coherent life plan.) |
Cleckley explains this erratic and to us inadequately motivated |
behaviour by likening the psychopath's life to that of |
children forced to sit through a performance of King Lear. Children |
are restless and misbehave under these conditions because |
they cannot enjoy the playas adults do. They act to relieve |
boredom. Similarly, Cleckley says, psychopaths are bored because |
their emotional poverty means that they cannot take interest |
in, or gain satisfaction from, what for others are the most |
important things in life: love, family, success in business or |
professional life, and the like. These things simply do not matter |
to them. Their unpredictable and antisocial behaviour is an |
attempt to relieve what would otherwise be a tedious existence. |
These claims are speculative and Cleckley admits that they may |
not be possible to establish scientifically. They do suggest, however, |
an aspect of the psychopath's life that undermines the |
otherwise attractive nature of the psychopath's free-wheeling |
life. Most reflective people, at some time or other, want their |
life to have some kind of meaning. Few of us could deliberately |
choose a way of life that we regarded as utterly meaningless. |
For this reason most of us would not choose to live a psychopathic |
life, however enjoyable it might be. |
Yet there is something paradoxical about criticising the psychopath's |
life for its meaninglessness. Don't we have to accept, |
in the absence of religious belief, that life really is meaningless, |
not just for the psychopath but for all of us? And if this is so, |
why should we not choose - if it were in our power to choose |
our personality - the life of a psychopath? But is it true that, |
religion aside, life is meaningless? Now our pursuit of reasons |
for acting morally has led us to what is often regarded as the |
ultimate philosophical question. |
330 |
Why Act Morally? |
HAS LIFE A MEANING? |
In what sense does rejection of belief in a god imply rejection |
of the view that life has any meaning? If this world had been |
created by some divine being with a particular goal in mind, it |
could be said to have a meaning, at least for that divine being. |
If we could know what the divine being's purpose in creating |
us was, we could then know what the meaning of our life was |
for our creator. If we accepted our creator's purpose (though |
why we should do that would need to be explained) we could |
claim to know the meaning of life. |
When we reject belief in a god we must give up the idea that |
life on this planet has some preordained meaning. Life as a whole |
has no meaning. Life began, as the best available theories tell |
us, in a chance combination of molecules; it then evolved |
through random mutations and natural selection. All this just |
happened; it did not happen for any overall purpose. Now that |
it has resulted in the existence of beings who prefer some states |
of affairs to others, however, it may be possible for particular |
lives to be meaningful. In this sense atheists can find meaning |
in life. |
Let us return to the comparison between the life of a psychopath |
and that of a more normal person. Why should the |
psychopath's life not be meaningful? We have seen that psychopaths |
are egocentric to an extreme: neither other people, |
nor worldly success, nor anything else really matters to them. |
But why is their own enjoyment of life not sufficient to give |
meaning to their lives? |
Most of us would not be able to find happiness by deliberately |
setting out to enjoy ourselves without caring about anyone or |
anything else. The pleasures we obtained in that way would |
seem empty and would soon pall. We seek a meaning for our |
lives beyond our own pleasures and find fulfilment and happiness |
in doing what we see to be meaningful. If our life has |
331 |
Practical Ethics |
no meaning other than our own happiness, we are likely to find |
that when we have obtained what we think we need to be |
happy, happiness itself still eludes us. |
That those who aim at happiness for happiness's sake often |
fail to find it, while others find happiness in pursuing altogether |
different goals, has been called 'the paradox of hedonism'. It is |
not, of course, a logical paradox but a claim about the way in |
which we come to be happy. Like other generalisations on this |
subject, it lacks empirical confirmation. Yet it matches our everyday |
observations and is consistent with our nature as evolved, |
purposive beings. Human beings survive and reproduce themselves |
through purposive action. We obtain happiness and fulfilment |
by working towards and achieving our goals. In |
evolutionary terms we could say that happiness functions as an |
internal reward for our achievements. Subjectively, we regard |
achieving the goal (or progressing towards it) as a reason for |
happiness. Our own happiness, therefore, is a by-product of |
aiming at something else, and not to be obtained by setting our |
sights on happiness alone. |
The psychopath's life can now be seen to be meaningless in |
a way that a normal life is not. It is meaningless because it looks |
inward to the pleasures of the present moment and not outward |
Subsets and Splits
No community queries yet
The top public SQL queries from the community will appear here once available.