text
stringlengths 0
1.71k
|
---|
matter. Conscientiousness is of value because of its consequences. |
Yet, unlike, say, benevolence, conscientiousness can |
be praised and encouraged only for its own sake. To praise a |
conscientious act for its consequences would be to praise not |
conscientiousn~ss, but something else altogether. If we appeal |
to sympathy or self-interest as a reason for doing one's duty, |
then we are not encouraging people to do their duty for its own |
sake. If conscientiousness is to be encouraged, it must be thought |
of as good for its own sake. |
It is different in the case of an act done from a motive that |
people act upon irrespective of praise and encouragement. The |
use of ethical language is then inappropriate. We do not normally |
say that people ought to do, or that it is their duty to do, |
whatever gives them the greatest pleasure, for most people are |
sufficiently motivated to do this anyway. So, whereas we praise |
good acts done for the sake of doing what is right, we withhold |
our praise when we believe the act was done from some motive |
like self-interest. |
This emphasis on motives and on the moral worth of doing |
right for its own sake is now embedded in our notion of ethics. |
To the extent that it is so embedded, we will feel that to provide |
324 |
Why Act Morally? |
considerations of self-interest for doing what is right is to empty |
the action of its moral worth. |
My suggestion is that our notion of ethics has become misleading |
to the extent that moral worth is attributed only to action |
done because it is right, without any ulterior motive. It is understandable, |
and from the point of view of society perhaps |
even desirable, that this attitude should prevail; nevertheless, |
those who accept this view of ethics, and are led by it to do |
what is right because it is right, without asking for any further |
reason, are falling victim to a kind of confidence trick - though |
not, of course, a consciously perpetrated one. |
That this view of ethics is unjustifiable has already been indicated |
by the failure of the argument discussed earlier in this |
chapter for a rational justification of ethics. In the history of |
Western philosophy, no one has urged more strongly than Kant |
that our ordinary moral consciousness finds moral worth only |
when duty is done for duty'S sake. Yet Kant himself saw that |
without a rational justification this common conception of ethics |
would be 'a mere phantom of the brain'. And this is indeed the |
case. If we reject - as in general terms we have done - the |
Kantian justification of the rationality of ethics, but try to retain |
the Kantian conception of ethics, ethics is left hanging without |
support. It becomes a closed system, a system that cannot be |
questioned because its first premise - that only action done |
because it is right has any moral worth - rules out the only |
remaining possible justification for accepting this very premise. |
Morality is, on this view, no more rational an end than any |
other allegedly self-justifying practice, like etiquette or the kind |
of religious faith that comes only to those who first set aside all |
sceptical doubts. |
Taken as a view of ethics as a whole, we should abandon this |
Kantian notion of ethics. This does not mean, however, that |
we should never do what we see to be right simply because we |
see it to be right, without further reasons. Here we need to |
325 |
Practical Ethics |
appeal to the distinction Hare has made between intuitive and |
critical thinking. When I stand back from my day-to-day ethical |
decisions and ask why I should act ethically, I should seek |
reasons in the broadest sense, and not allow Kantian preconceptions |
to deter me from considering self-interested reasons |
for living an ethical life. If my search is successful it will provide |
me with reasons for taking up the ethical point of view as a |
settled policy, a way of living. I would not then ask, in my dayto- |
day ethical decision making, whether each particular right |
action is in my interests. Instead I do it because I see myself as |
an ethical person. In everyday situations, I will simply assume |
that doing what is right is in my interests, and once I have |
decided what is right, I will go ahead and do it, without thinking |
about further reasons for doing what is right. To deliberate over |
the ultimate reasons for doing what is right in each case would |
impossibly complicate my life; it would also be inadvisable because |
in particular situations I might be too greatly influenced |
by strong but temporary desires and inclinations and so make |
decisions I would later regret. |
That, at least, is how a justification of ethics in terms of selfinterest |
might work, without defeating its own aim. We can |
now ask if such a justification exists. There is a daunting list of |
those who, following Plato's lead, have offered one: Aristotle, |
Aquinas, Spinoza, Butler, Hegel, even - for all his strictures |
against prostituting virtue - Bradley. Like Plato, these philosophers |
made broad claims about human nature and the conditions |
under which human beings can be happy. Some were |
also able to fall back on a belief that virtue will be rewarded |
and wicketlness punished in a life after our bodily death. Philosophers |
cannot use this argument if they want to carry conviction |
nowadays; nor can they adopt sweeping psychological |
theories on the basis of their own general experience of their |
fellows, as philosophers used to do when psychology was a |
branch of philosophy. |
It might be said that since philosophers are not empirical |
326 |
Why Act Morally? |
scientists, discussion of the connection between acting ethically |
and living a fulfilled and happy life should be left to psychologists, |
sociologists, and other appropriate experts. The question |
is not, however, dealt with by any other single discipline and |
Subsets and Splits
No community queries yet
The top public SQL queries from the community will appear here once available.