text
stringlengths 0
1.71k
|
---|
C4. If time is real, then it is not the case that moments and events are |
characterized only by B - series relations (transposition, C3). |
P4. If it is not the case that moments and events are characterized only by |
B - series relations, then moments and events have A - series properties. |
C5. If time is real, then moments and events have A - series properties |
(hypothetical syllogism, C4, P4). |
P5. A - series properties are mutually incompatible. |
P6. If A - series properties are mutually incompatible, then the attribution of |
A - series properties to moments and events entails a contradiction. |
C6. The attribution of A - series properties to moments and events entails |
a contradiction ( modus ponens , P5, P6). |
P7. If the attribution of A - series properties to moments and events entails |
a contradiction, then it is not the case that moments and events have |
A - series properties. |
C7. It is not the case that moments and events have A - series properties |
( modus ponens , C6, P7). |
C8. It is not the case that time is real ( modus tollens , C5, C7). |
16 |
Berkeley β s Master Argument for |
Idealism |
John M. DePoe |
Much of the philosophical writings of George Berkeley (1685 β 1753) is |
dedicated to arguing for metaphysical idealism, the position that everything |
that exists is composed of thought, mind, or God. As Berkeley understood |
it, being composed of thought is contrary to being composed of matter, and |
therefore he aimed to show that believing in the existence of matter is |
unreasonable, if not unintelligible. Matter, according to Berkeley, exists |
independently of thought. He described matter as inert, senseless, and |
having what the British empiricists called β primary qualities, β roughly |
defi ned as properties that exist independently of a mind β s perception of them |
(e.g., mass, extension, motion, etc.). |
One of Berkeley β s most famous arguments against the existence of matter |
is commonly called β the master argument β because if it is successful, it |
refutes the existence of matter with a single masterstroke. The argument |
can be summed up with a challenge: can you imagine or conceive of a tree β s |
(or any material object β s) existing without its being perceived (or thought |
about)? While you might think you have succeeded in conceiving of a tree |
that is not being perceived, a little refl ection will reveal that you haven β t |
done so, because in the process of conceiving of the tree, you are perceiving |
Berkeley , George . Principles of Human Knowledge and Three Dialogues , |
edited by R. S. Woolhouse . London : Penguin , 1988 . |
Just the Arguments: 100 of the Most Important Arguments in Western Philosophy, |
First Edition. Edited by Michael Bruce and Steven Barbone. |
Β© 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. Published 2011 by Blackwell Publishing Ltd. |
Berkeleyβs Master Argument for Idealism 69 |
it. So, it seems that it is impossible to conceive of something β s existing truly |
unperceived. But if it isn β t even possible to conceive of something existing |
unperceived, why should we think that matter can and does exist this way? |
Since it is impossible to conceive of matter β s unperceived existence, Berkeley |
concluded that the existence of matter is unreasonable. |
But say you, surely there is nothing easier than to imagine trees, for |
instance, in a park, or books existing in a closet, and no body by to perceive |
them. I answer, you may so, there is no diffi culty in it: but what is all this, I |
beseech you, more than framing in your mind certain ideas which you call |
books and trees, and at the same time omitting to frame the idea of any one |
that may perceive them? But do not you your self perceive or think of them |
all the while? This therefore is nothing to the purpose: it only shows you have |
the power of imagining or forming ideas in your mind; but it doth not shew |
that you can conceive it possible, the objects of your thought may exist |
without the mind: to make out this, it is necessary that you conceive them |
existing unconceived or unthought of, which is a manifest repugnancy. When |
we do our utmost to conceive the existence of external bodies, we are all the |
while only contemplating our own ideas. But the mind taking no notice of |
itself, is deluded to think it can and doth conceive bodies existing unthought |
of or without the mind; though at the same time they are apprehended by or |
exist in it self. (Berkeley, 60) |
P1. If material objects exist, then material objects exist independently of |
any mind β s thinking of them. |
P2. If material objects exist independently of any mind β s thinking of them, |
then it is conceivable for material objects to exist without any mind |
thinking of them. |
P3. It is not the case that it is conceivable for material objects to exist |
without any mind thinking of them. |
C1. It is not the case that material objects exist independently of any |
mind β s thinking of them ( modus tollens , P2, P3). |
C2. It is not the case that material objects exist ( modus tollens , P1, C1). |
17 |
Kant β s Refutation of Idealism |
Adrian Bardon |
In the second edition of his Critique of Pure Reason , Kant offers a refutation |
of Cartesian epistemological skepticism that draws (albeit somewhat |
cryptically) on his insights regarding the necessary conditions of time - |
consciousness. While the details remain under dispute, the key claim seems |
to be that we would be unable to order all or some of our subjective experiences |
in time unless we were relating their sequence in some way to changes |
in objects external to the mind. The contents of our perceptual states do |
not come marked with the time of their occurrence; further, all experience |
is successive in form regardless of whether it represents sequences of events |
or static states of affairs. Thus we need some guide to reconstructing past |
events beyond the mere subjective contents of perception and memory. Only |
objective states of affairs and events β conceived of as part of a law - |
governed system β could function as a guide to this reconstruction by dictating |
one interpretation over another. Consequently, the fact that we are |
Kant , Immanuel . Critique of Pure Reason , translated by Paul Guyer and |
Allen Wood. Cambridge, UK : Cambridge University Press , 1998 . |
Dicker , Georges . β Kant β s Refutation of Idealism , β No Γ» s 42 , 1 ( 2008 ): |
80 β 108 . |
Guyer , Paul . Kant . New York : Routledge , 2006 . |
Just the Arguments: 100 of the Most Important Arguments in Western Philosophy, |
First Edition. Edited by Michael Bruce and Steven Barbone. |
Subsets and Splits
No community queries yet
The top public SQL queries from the community will appear here once available.