text
stringlengths 0
1.71k
|
---|
kitchen table, which look exactly alike and are made of the same material, |
may be qualitatively identical, but they are not numerically identical. |
Contrast this with the one chair in my room. If someone paints that chair |
while my eyes are closed, then the chair I see when I open my eyes will |
be qualitatively different from but numerically the same as the chair I saw |
before. |
Apply this to persons. When a relative tells you that you have changed |
over the years, he recognizes that you are still numerically the same person. |
He does not think that you have passed away. But he sees that you are |
qualitatively a bit different now. |
There is more debate over whether someone is still numerically the same |
person when complete loss of memory and radical change of character |
occur. Philosophers disagree over whether the resulting person is only qualitatively |
different or also numerically different than the person before having |
a brain hemorrhage. Philosophers, such as Derek Parfi t, who hold that we |
are only the same as long as there is psychological continuity, say that we |
would in such a case be confronted with a numerically different entity. |
Philosophers, such as Bernard Williams, who state that someone stays the |
same as long as there is bodily continuity, claim the opposite. |
How do we decide what determines the numerical identity of someone? |
We will fi rst have to agree on how the concept β person β gets its meaning. |
John Locke ( An Essay , 148 II.xxvii.26) stated that the concept β person β is |
a forensic concept. β Forensic β is often equivocated with β legal β , but its |
meaning stretches further than this. The term is derived from the Latin term |
β forum β and means β public β . Locke refers to β person β as a public concept |
because he takes its meaning to be determined by how we use it β or, to be |
more precise, by how we ought to use it if we want our speaking to be in |
accordance with our common beliefs, attitudes, and practices. The meaning |
of the word β person β in a legal context is one instance of this. It has, for |
example, been held that, in this context, someone cannot be found guilty |
of committing a crime unless he remembers committing it. One idea behind |
this is that it only makes sense to penalize someone for doing something if |
he can take responsibility for doing this. Remembering what you did is |
supposed to be a precondition for the latter. |
However, not all philosophers agree on whether the meaning of the |
concept β person β is determined by our common use of it. Derek Parfi t, for |
instance, contests this assumption. He warns that our use of this term may |
be wrongheaded and holds that philosophers are in a position to assess this. |
They can unveil inconsistencies in our use of this concept, examine whether |
there is a real entity in the world to which it refers, as well as determine |
A Reductionist Account of Personal Identity 81 |
whether this concept names what matters when we are concerned about |
our survival β as we usually think it does. 2 |
This being said, philosophers will mostly start their examination of what |
the concept β person β refers to with an assessment of how we commonly |
use this concept. They will either describe our use of this concept as precisely |
as possible and let this description function as a determination of the |
meaning of this term, or they will explain why our application of this |
concept is not entirely accurate. |
This has led to two main philosophical approaches to the questions of |
what persons are and what makes a person maintain her numerical identity |
over time: the reductionist and the nonreductionist approach. |
There are different versions of reductionism. Constitutive reductionism 3 |
is likely to be the most defensible version of reductionism with regard to |
persons. Constitutive reductionists admit that persons exist but argue that |
they are fully constituted by their physical and/or psychological continuity, |
and nothing over and above these continuities. |
To say that persons are fully constituted by their physical and/or psychological |
continuity is not to say that persons are nothing but this continuity. |
According to Sydney Shoemaker, the case is analogous to the relationship |
between a statue and the lump of clay of which it is made. The statue is |
constituted by the clay and has no separate existence apart from the clay. |
Yet it is not the same as the lump of clay. For, if this lump loses its shape, |
it will still be there, but the statue will not be. 4 |
Constitutive reductionists are metaphysical reductionists, not conceptual |
reductionists. 5 They claim that persons are not separately existing entities |
over and above their physical and/or psychological continuity, even though |
we may not be able to get rid of the term β person β when we want to give |
a complete description of the world. It is possible that we ascribe experiences |
to subjects and that we should call these subjects β persons β not |
β physical β and/or β psychological continuities. β |
Another way to state what constitutive reductionists hold is this. They |
claim that what makes different experiences belong to one person is not the |
fact that they belong to a single separately existing entity. Rather, what |
makes experiences intrapersonal should be explained in terms of other facts, |
such as the fact that they are psychologically continuous with one another |
or the fact that they are associated with a single body. |
3 For the term β constitutive reductionism, β see Parfi t β Experiences β and Parfi t β Is Personal β . |
2 This is why Parfi t calls for a revisionary metaphysics, rather than a descriptive metaphysics: |
he claims that we have to revise the use of certain of our concepts (see, e.g., Parfi t |
Reasons, ix). |
5 For a distinction between these two kinds of reductionism, see Parfi t β Experiences β (223). |
4 For this reference to Shoemaker, see Parfi t β Experiences β (268 n.9). |
82 Fauve Lybaert |
A metaphysical nonreductionist, on the other hand, claims that persons |
are separately existing entities over and above their physical and psychological |
continuity. An example of a metaphysical nonreductionist would be |
someone who identifi es persons in accordance with their soul and does not |
take this soul to be fully constituted by any combination of further entities. |
This metaphysical nonreductionist could believe in the transmigration of |
the soul: perhaps she believes that she is identical to some past person from |
whom her soul has migrated, even though that person β s body is not continuous |
with her current body, that person β s character is radically different, and |
she has no memory of that person β s experiences. |
Let β s return to reductionism. Within constitutive reductionism, there is |
still one big division to be made. Some reductionists, such as Bernard |
Williams and Thomas Nagel, argue that a person stays the same person as |
long as there is a certain degree of physical continuity. Other reductionists, |
such as Sydney Shoemaker and Parfi t, hold that a person stays the same as |
long as there is a certain degree of nonbranched psychological continuity. |
Subsets and Splits
No community queries yet
The top public SQL queries from the community will appear here once available.