text
stringlengths 0
1.71k
|
---|
of some other entity β (ibid., 228). |
P12. We do not have good evidence for the belief in reincarnation (ibid.). |
Neither do we have evidence for the existence of Cartesian egos (i.e., |
thinking nonmaterial substances); it seems like they are neither β publicly |
observable β nor β privately introspectible facts β (ibid.). |
A Reductionist Account of Personal Identity 85 |
P13. There are no other reasons than the ones in P10, P11, and P12 to |
believe in the existence of a separately existing subject of experiences. |
C5. We have no evidence for the claim that we are separately existing |
entities (P10, P11, P12, P13). |
C6. We should reject the belief that persons exist as separately existing |
entities ( modus ponens , P9, C5). |
C7. The reductionist view is true ( modus ponens , P4, C1, C6). |
21 |
Split - Case Arguments about |
Personal Identity |
Ludger Jansen |
Parfi t , Derek . Reasons and Persons . Oxford : Oxford University Press , 1984 . |
Shoemaker , Sydney , and Richard Swinburne . Personal Identity (Great |
Debates in Philosophy) . Oxford : Blackwell 1984 . |
In the empiricist tradition, it is a common move to account for the diachronic |
identity of a person in terms of shared mental properties or continuity |
of memories (e.g., Locke) or in terms of shared matter, especially of |
the brain. But all these criteria allow for β split cases, β that is, for two or |
more candidates fulfi lling the requirements, which cause trouble with the |
formal properties of the identity relation (i.e., refl exivity, symmetry, and |
transitivity). For example, a brain can be divided and both halves implanted |
in different bodies: which of these, if any, is the same person as the original |
one? Two individuals could even share most of their memories β but this |
does not make them the same person. Thus, none of these criteria can be |
the decisive factor for personal identity. Some philosophers, such as Richard |
Swinburne (#24), argue for dualism and conclude that there must be some |
immaterial factor, the soul, that accounts for personal identity. Others, such |
as Derek Parfi t, conclude that we should discard the concept of personal |
identity altogether and rather replace it with a nonsymmetric successor |
relation that allows for such split cases. |
Just the Arguments: 100 of the Most Important Arguments in Western Philosophy, |
First Edition. Edited by Michael Bruce and Steven Barbone. |
Β© 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. Published 2011 by Blackwell Publishing Ltd. |
Split-Case Arguments about Personal Identity 87 |
There are no logical diffi culties in supposing that we could transplant one |
of [a person] P 1 β s [brain] hemispheres into the skull from which a brain had |
been removed, and the other hemisphere into another such skull, and that |
both transplants should take, and it may well be practically possible to do |
so. [ β¦ ] If these transplants took, clearly each of the resulting persons would |
behave to some extent like P 1 , and indeed both would probably have some |
of the apparent memories of P 1 . Each of the resulting persons would then be |
good candidates for being P 1 . After all, if one of P 1 β s hemispheres had been |
destroyed and the other remained intact and untransplanted, and the resulting |
person continued to behave and make memory claims somewhat like those |
of P 1 , we would have had little hesitation in declaring that person to be P 1 . |
The same applies, whichever hemisphere was preserved [ β¦ ]. But if it is, that |
other person will be just as good a candidate for being P 1 . [ β¦ ] But [ β¦ ] that |
cannot be β since the two persons are not identical with each other. (Shoemaker |
and Swinburne, 15) |
P1. A 1 and A 2 are two distinct persons. |
P2. At t 2 > t 1 , A 1 and A 2 are such that each of A 1 and A 2 share exactly the |
same amount of the X that A had at t 1 . |
P3. X is the decisive factor for personal identity (e.g., body mass, brain |
mass, memories, character traces), that is, for any persons A 1 and A 2 and |
any times t 1 and t 2 , if A 2 has at t 2 most of the X that A 1 had at t 1 , then |
A 1 and A 2 are the same person (assumption for reductio ). |
C1. A 1 is the same person as A ( modus ponens , P3, P2). |
C2. A 2 is the same person as A ( modus ponens , P3, P2). |
P4. If X is the same person as Y, then Y is the same person as X (symmetry |
of identity). |
C3. A is the same person as A 2 ( modus ponens , P4, C2). |
P5. If A 1 is the same person as A and A is the same person as A 2 , then A |
is the same person as A 2 (transitivity, C1, C3). |
C4. A 1 is the same person as A 2 ( modus ponens , conjunction, P5, C1, |
C3). |
C5. No such X can be the decisive factor for personal identity ( reductio , |
P1 β C4). |
22 |
The Ship of Theseus |
Ludger Jansen |
Hobbes , Thomas . β De corpore , β in The English Works of Thomas Hobbes , |
Vol. 1 , edited by Sir William Molesworth . London : John Bohn , 1839 . |
Plato . Phaedo , in Five Dialogues , 2nd edn. , translated by G. M. A. Grube, |
revised by J. M. Cooper, 93 β 154 . Indianapolis : Hackett , 2002 . |
Plutarch . β Life of Theseus , β in Lives , translated by Bernadotte Perrin, vol. |
I , 1 β 87 . Cambridge, MA : Harvard University Press , 1967 . |
The β Ship of Theseus β is an intriguing puzzle about identity through time. |
It is based on the custom of the Athenians to send Theseus β ship each year |
on a sacred voyage to Delos, because it was believed that Apollo once saved |
the lives of Theseus and his fourteen fellow - travellers. The ritual was annually |
repeated for a long time, and hence the ship needed continual repair, |
new planks being substituted for the old ones. Plutarch relates to us that |
already the Athenian philosophers had discussed whether the ship is still |
the same ship although it consists, after a while, entirely of new planks |
(Plutarch, β Life of Theseus β Β§ 22 β 3; cf., Plato, Phaedo 58a β c). Hobbes put |
a sophisticated twist to the story: Suppose, he said, that someone collected |
the old planks and put them together again in the end, thus restoring the |
old ship. The same ship, then, seems to exist twice, which is absurd. Hobbes |
used this argument to support his version of relative identity: the original |
ship T1 and the restored ship T2 share the same matter, whereas the original |
ship and the repaired ship T3 share the same form. |
Just the Arguments: 100 of the Most Important Arguments in Western Philosophy, |
First Edition. Edited by Michael Bruce and Steven Barbone. |
Β© 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. Published 2011 by Blackwell Publishing Ltd. |
Subsets and Splits
No community queries yet
The top public SQL queries from the community will appear here once available.