text
stringlengths 0
1.71k
|
---|
is, whether experience produces the idea by means of the understanding |
or of the imagination; whether we are determin β d by reason to make the |
transition, or by a certain association of perceptions. If reason determin β d us, |
it wou β d proceed upon that principle, that instances, of which we have had |
no experience must resemble those, of which we have had experience, and |
that the course of nature continues always uniformly the same. In order |
therefore to clear up this matter, let us consider all the arguments, upon which |
such a proposition may suppos β d to be founded β and as these must be deriv β d |
either from knowledge or probability, let us cast our eye on each of these |
degrees of evidence, and see whether they afford any just conclusion of this |
nature. (Hume, 1.3.6.3, 1.3.6.4) |
P1. When the mind makes what appears to be a necessary transition from |
a present impression, or a memory of an impression, to a given idea, we |
call that transition β cause and effect. β The question is, on what is this |
seemingly necessary transition founded? Of what is it a function: understanding |
(i.e., reason) or the imagination? |
P2. If reason does determine us to make these causal transitions, then this |
reasoning must proceed upon the principle that instances (e.g., particular |
associations of any two objects) that occurred in the past will continue |
to occur as such in the future (the principle of uniformity). |
P3. If causal necessity is a function of reason, where that reason is based |
on the principle of uniformity, then the principle of uniformity must, |
in some fashion or other, be justifi ed ; it too must be β founded β on |
Hume and the Problem of Induction 179 |
reason. In symbolic form, this reads (N β P) β J, where β N β stands for |
causal necessity is a function of reason, β P β stands for a principle of |
uniformity, and β J β stands for β the principle of uniformity is justifi ed by |
reason. β |
P4. There are only two kinds of reason that may justify a principle, including |
the principle of uniformity: (a) β knowledge β (demonstrative reasoning) |
or (b) β probable β reasoning. |
P5. Assume that the principle of uniformity is justifi ed by demonstrative |
reasoning. |
P6. If the principle of uniformity is justifi ed by demonstrative reasoning β in |
other words, it is an instance of demonstrative reasoning β then the |
principle of uniformity cannot be imagined otherwise. |
P7. We can imagine that nature will not continue uniformly in the future, |
while simultaneously imagining that nature has always continued the |
same in the past, without contradicting ourselves. |
C1. The principle of uniformity is not proved; that is, justifi ed by demonstrative |
reasoning ( modus tollens , P6, P7). |
P8. The principle of uniformity is justifi ed by probable reasoning (assumption |
for reductio ). |
P9. Probable reasoning is actually causal reasoning, since both are cases |
where we are automatically led to think of an idea in virtue of experiencing |
an impression or remembering an impression. |
P10. If the reasoning at hand is an instance of causal reasoning, then such |
reasoning is justifi ed by the principle of uniformity. |
C2. Probable reasoning is justifi ed by the principle of uniformity ( modus |
ponens , P9, P10). |
C3. The principle of uniformity is justifi ed by probable reasoning (i.e., |
causal reasoning) and justifi es probable reasoning (i.e., causal reasoning) |
(conjunction, P7, C2). |
C4. The principle of uniformity is not justifi ed by probable reason |
( reductio , P7 β C3). |
C5. The principle of uniformity is not justifi ed by either demonstrative |
or probable reasoning (conjunction C1, C4). |
P11. If the principle of uniformity is not justifi ed by either demonstrative |
or probable reasoning, then we must reject the claim that the principle |
of uniformity is justifi ed by reason. |
C6. We must reject the claim that the principle of uniformity is justifi ed |
by reason ( modus ponens , C5, P11). |
P12. If we must reject the claim that the principle of uniformity is justifi ed |
by reason, then we must reject the claim that the necessity that seems to |
accompany causal relations is a function of reason. |
C7. We must reject the claim that the necessity that seems to accompany |
causal relations is a function of reason ( modus ponens , P12, C6). |
46 |
Argument by Analogy in Thales |
and Anaximenes |
Giannis Stamatellos |
Aristotle . On the Heavens , translated by W. K. C. Guthrie. Cambridge, MA : |
Harvard University Press , 1939 . |
Barnes , Jonathan . The Presocratic Philosophers . London : Routledge , 1979 . |
Diels , Hermann . Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker , 6th edn. , revised with |
additions and index by W. Kranz . Berlin : Weidmann , 1951 β 52 . (DK) |
Kirk , Geoffrey Stephen , John Earl Raven , and Malcolm Schofi eld . The |
Presocratic Philosophers . Cambridge, UK : Cambridge University Press , |
1983 . |
Lloyd , Geoffrey Ernest Richard . Polarity and Analogy: Two Types of |
Argumentation in Early Greek Thought . Bristol : Bristol Classical Press , |
1992 . |
Pachenko , Dmitri . β Thales and the Origin of Theoretical Reasoning . β |
Confi gurations 3 ( 1993 ): 387 β 484 . |
Wright , M. R . The Presocratics . Bristol : Bristol Classical Press , 1985 . |
If x is P and Q , and y is P , we infer that y is also Q . |
An argument by analogy relies on inductive inference. Arguing by analogy |
is arguing that since things are similar or alike in certain respects, they are |
similar or alike in others. An analogical argument is based on hypothetical |
similarities between distinct cases: in other words, since things are similar |
in certain observable or identifi ed cases, they are also similar in some other |
unobservable or unidentifi ed cases. |
Just the Arguments: 100 of the Most Important Arguments in Western Philosophy, |
First Edition. Edited by Michael Bruce and Steven Barbone. |
Β© 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. Published 2011 by Blackwell Publishing Ltd. |
Argument by Analogy in Thales and Anaximenes 181 |
An argument by analogy is not deductively valid. It is considered as a |
weak form of argumentation due to the arbitrary presupposition of similarities |
between things. However, analogy is not only used in literal cases but |
also in cases of metaphor and explanatory purposes. Moreover, an argument |
Subsets and Splits
No community queries yet
The top public SQL queries from the community will appear here once available.