text
stringlengths 0
1.71k
|
---|
absolute rule, or an assessment of its consequences. Pacifists |
have usually regarded the use of violence as absolutely wrong, |
irrespective of its consequences. This, like other 'no matter what' |
prohibitions, assumes the validity of the distinction between |
acts and omissions. Without this distinction, pacifists who refuse |
to use violence when it is the only means of preventing greater |
violence would be responsible for the greater violence they fail |
to prevent. |
307 |
Practical Ethics |
Suppose we have an opportunity to assassinate a tyrant who |
is systematically murdering his opponents and anyone else he |
dislikes. We know that if the tyrant dies he will be replaced by |
a popular opposition leader, now in exile, who will restore the |
rule of law. If we say that violence is always wrong, and refuse |
to carry out the assassination, mustn't we bear some responsibility |
for the tyrant's future murders? |
If the objections made to the acts and omissions distinction |
in Chapter 7 were sound, those who do not use violence to |
prevent greater violence have to take responsibility for the violence |
they could have prevented, Thus the rejection of the acts |
and omissions distinction makes a crucial difference to the discussion |
of violence, for it opens the door to a plausible argument |
in defence of violence. |
Marxists have often used this argument to rebut attacks on |
their doctrine of the need for violent revolution. In his classic |
indictment of the social effects of nineteenth -century capitalism, |
The Condition of the Working Class in England, Engels wrote: |
If one individual inflicts a bodily injury upon another which |
leads to the death of the person attacked we call it manslaughter; |
on the other hand, if the attacker knows beforehand that the |
blow will be fatal we call it murder. Murder has also been committed |
if society places hundreds of workers in such a position |
that they inevitably come to premature and unnatural ends. Their |
death is as violent as if they had been stabbed or shot .... Murder |
has been committed if thousands of workers have been deprived |
ofthe necessities oflife or if they have been forced into a situation |
in which it is impossible for them to survive .... Murder has been |
committed if society knows perfectly well that thousands of |
workers cannot avoid being sacrificed so long as these conditions |
are allowed to continue. Murder of this sort is just as culpable |
as the murder committed by an individual. At first sight it does |
not appear to be murder at all because responsibility for the death |
ofthe victim cannot be pinned on any individual assailant. Everyone |
is responsible and yet no one is responsible, because it appears |
as if the victim has died from natural causes. If a worker |
dies no one places the responsibility for his death on society, |
308 |
Ends and Means |
though some would realize that society has failed to take steps |
to prevent the victim from dying. But it is murder all the same. |
One might object to Engels's use of the term 'murder'. The |
objection would resemble the arguments discussed in Chapter |
8, when we considered whether our failure to aid the starving |
makes us murderers. We saw that there is no intrinsic significance |
in the distinction between acts and omissions; but from |
the point 'of view of motivation and the appropriateness of |
blame, most cases of failing to prevent death are not equivalent |
to murder. The same would apply to the cases Engels describes. |
Engels tries to pin the blame on 'society', but 'society' is not a |
person or a moral agent, and cannot be held responsible in the |
wayan individual can. |
Still, this is nit-picking. Whether or not 'murder' is the right |
term, whether or not we are prepared to describe as 'violent' |
the deaths of malnourished workers in unhealthy and unsafe |
factories, Engels's fundamental point stands. These deaths are |
a wrong of the same order of magnitude as the deaths of |
hundreds of people in a terrorist bombing would be. It would |
be one-sided to say that violent revolution is always absolutely |
wrong, without taking account of the evils that the revolutionaries |
are trying to stop. If violent means had been the only way |
of changing the conditions Engels describes, those who opposed |
the use of violent means would have been responsible for the |
continuation of those conditions. |
Some of the practices we have been discussing in this book |
are violent, either directly or by omission. In the case of nonhuman |
animals, our treatment is often violent by any description. |
Those who regard the human fetus as a moral subject will |
obviously consider abortion to be a violent act against it. In the |
case of humans at or after birth, what are we to say of an |
avoidable situation in which some countries have infant mortality |
rates eight times higher than others, and a person born |
in one country can expect to live twenty years more than someone |
born in another country? Is this violence? Again, it doesn't |
309 |
Practical Ethics |
really matter whether we call it violence or not. In its effects it |
is as terrible as violence. |
Absolutist condemnations of violence stand or fall with the |
distinction between acts and omissions. Therefore they fall. |
There are, however, strong consequentialist objections to the |
use of violence. We have been premising our discussion on the |
assumption that violence might be the only means of changing |
things for the better. Absolutists have no interest in challenging |
this assumption because they reject violence whether the assumption |
is true or false. Consequentialists must ask whether |
violence ever is the only means to an important end, or, if not |
the only means, the swiftest means. They must also ask about |
the long-term effects of pursuing change by violent means. |
Could one defend, on consequentialist grounds, a condemnation |
Subsets and Splits
No community queries yet
The top public SQL queries from the community will appear here once available.