text
stringlengths 0
1.71k
|
---|
without thereby sacrifi cing anything of comparable moral importance, we
|
ought, morally, to do it. By β without sacrifi cing anything of comparable moral
|
importance β I mean without causing anything else comparably bad to happen,
|
or doing something that is wrong in itself, or failing to promote some moral
|
good, comparable in signifi cance to the bad thing that we can prevent. This
|
principle seems almost as uncontroversial as the last one [ . . . but . . . ] The
|
uncontroversial appearance of the principle just stated is deceptive. If it were
|
acted upon [ . . . ] our lives, our society, and our world would be fundamentally
|
changed. [ . . . ] The traditional distinction between duty and charity cannot
|
be drawn, or at least, not in the place we normally draw it. [ . . . ] When we
|
buy new clothes not to keep ourselves warm but to look β well - dressed β we
|
are not providing for any important need. We would not be sacrifi cing anything
|
signifi cant if we were to continue to wear our old clothes, and give the
|
money to famine relief. By doing so, we would be preventing another person
|
from starving. It follows from what I have said earlier that we ought to give
|
money away, rather than spend it on clothes which we do not need to keep
|
us warm. To do so is not charitable, or generous. Nor is it the kind of act
|
which philosophers and theologians have called β supererogatory β β an act
|
which it would be good to do, but not wrong not to do. On the contrary, we
|
ought to give the money away, and it is wrong not to do so. (Singer β Famine, β
|
231 β 5)
|
P1. Suffering and death from lack of food, shelter, and medical care are
|
bad.
|
P2. If it is in one β s power to prevent something bad from happening, without
|
thereby sacrifi cing anything of comparable moral importance, one ought,
|
morally, to do it.
|
C1. If it is in one β s power to prevent suffering and death from lack of
|
food, shelter, and medical care, without thereby sacrifi cing anything
|
of comparable moral importance, one ought, morally, to do it (instantiation
|
& modus ponens , P1, P2).
|
P3. By giving money to humanitarian aid agencies, one can prevent suffering
|
and death from lack of food, shelter, and medical care.
|
246 Joakim Sandberg
|
C2. If one can give money to humanitarian aid agencies without thereby
|
sacrifi cing anything of comparable moral importance (to suffering and
|
death from lack of food, shelter, and medical care) one ought, morally,
|
to do it (instantiation and modus ponens , C1, P3).
|
P4. We can give a substantial amount of our money away by simply giving
|
up buying things that we do not really need; that is, without sacrifi cing
|
anything of moral importance comparable to suffering and death from
|
lack of food, shelter, and medical care.
|
C3. We ought, morally, to give a substantial amount of our money to
|
humanitarian aid agencies ( modus ponens , C2, P4).
|
64
|
The Repugnant Conclusion
|
Joakim Sandberg
|
Parfi t , Derek. Reasons and Persons . Oxford : Clarendon Press , 1984 .
|
Ryberg , Jesper , and Torbj ΓΆ rn T Γ€ nnsj ΓΆ (eds.). The Repugnant Conclusion:
|
Essays on Population Ethics . Dordrecht : Kluwer , 2004 .
|
When philosophers think about future generations and what sort of world
|
we should try to create, they sometimes ponder issues in so - called population
|
ethics. For example, β Would it be better if, in the future, a greater
|
rather than fewer number of people lived? β and β Does the answer to this
|
question depend further on who these people are and/or their quality of
|
life? β The seminal work in this fi eld is Derek Parfi t β s Reasons and Persons ,
|
and the present argument is its undisputed highlight. The argument addresses
|
the issue of what the relative values are of the quantity of lives lived versus
|
the quality of these lives and a seemingly straightforward position on this
|
issue β the position that classical utilitarians take β is that quantity and
|
quality should be given equal value.
|
Utilitarians typically compound these two factors into a measure of the
|
overall utility, or β quantity of whatever makes life worth living, β in a population.
|
Parfi t β s argument against this view, however, takes the form of a
|
reductio ad absurdum : If any loss in the quality of lives can be compensated
|
for by a suffi cient increase in the quantity of lives lived, then the best
|
outcome could well be one in which an enormous amount of people lived
|
lives that are barely worth living. This is what Parfi t calls the β Repugnant
|
Conclusion. β Many ways of trying to get around the conclusion can be
|
found in the literature. However, it may be noted that it has been surprisingly
|
diffi cult to develop a theory that avoids this conclusion and at the
|
same time doesn β t imply equally counterintuitive conclusions. The fi eld of
|
population ethics thus continues to be challenging.
|
Just the Arguments: 100 of the Most Important Arguments in Western Philosophy,
|
First Edition. Edited by Michael Bruce and Steven Barbone.
|
Β© 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. Published 2011 by Blackwell Publishing Ltd.
|
248 Joakim Sandberg
|
In B there are twice as many people living as in A, and these people are
|
all worse off than everyone in A. But the lives of those in B, compared with
|
those in A, are more than half as much worth living. [ . . . ] Which would be
|
the better outcome? [ . . . ] I can now state the [ . . . ] Impersonal Total Principle:
|
If other things are equal, the best outcome is the one in which there would
|
be the greatest quantity of whatever makes life worth living. [ . . . ] Z is some
|
enormous population whose members have lives that are not much above the
|
level where life ceases to be worth living. [ . . . ] In each of these lives there is
|
very little happiness. But, if the numbers are large enough, this is the outcome
|
with the greatest total sum of happiness. [ . . . ] The Impersonal Total Principle
|
then implies The Repugnant Conclusion: For any possible population of at
|
least ten billion people, all with a very high quality of life, there must be some
|
much larger imaginable population whose existence, if other things are equal,
|
would be better, even though its members have lives that are barely worth
|
living. As my choice of name suggests, I fi nd this conclusion very hard to
|
accept. [ . . . ] If we are convinced that Z is worse than A, we have strong
|
grounds for resisting principles which imply that Z is better. We have strong
|
grounds for resisting the Impersonal Total Principle. (Parfi t, 385 β 90)
|
P1. The β quantity of whatever makes life worth living β in a given population
|
is a function of the quantity of its members and their quality of life.
|
P2. One can increase the quantity of whatever makes life worth living in a
|
given population by simply adding people whose lives are worth living.
|
P3. If in one of two outcomes the quality of lives in a population is lower,
|
the quantity of whatever makes life worth living can still be higher if
|
Subsets and Splits
No community queries yet
The top public SQL queries from the community will appear here once available.