text
stringlengths 0
1.71k
|
---|
Many medical professionals and others think that active euthanasia, even
|
when it is done at the request of the person who dies, is morally wrong.
|
They also think that passive euthanasia is morally right, at least when it is
|
done following the wishes of the person who dies. This idea that the two
|
are ethically different is refl ected in the law in many countries. The law
|
makes it a crime to commit active euthanasia but not a crime to perform
|
passive euthanasia when the person who dies doesn β t want to be kept alive.
|
Is this idea about the ethical difference between active and passive euthanasia
|
sound? According to Rachels β argument, it isn β t.
|
One reason why so many people think that there is an important moral
|
difference between active and passive euthanasia is that they think killing
|
someone is morally worse than letting someone die. But is it? Is killing, in
|
itself, worse than letting die? To investigate this issue, two cases may be considered
|
that are exactly alike except that one involves killing whereas the other
|
involves letting someone die. Then, it can be asked whether this difference
|
makes any difference to the moral assessments. It is important that the cases
|
be exactly alike, except for this one difference, since otherwise one cannot be
|
confi dent that it is this difference and not some other that accounts for any
|
variation in the assessments of the two cases. So, let us consider this pair of
|
cases:
|
In the fi rst, Smith stands to gain a large inheritance if anything should
|
happen to his six - year - old cousin. One evening while the child is taking his
|
bath, Smith sneaks into the bathroom and drowns the child, and then arranges
|
things so that it will look like an accident.
|
In the second, Jones also stands to gain if anything should happen to his
|
six - year - old cousin. Like Smith, Jones sneaks in planning to drown the child
|
in his bath. However, just as he enters the bathroom Jones sees the child slip
|
and hit his head, and fall face down in the water. Jones is delighted; he stands
|
by, ready to push the child β s head back under if it is necessary, but it is not
|
necessary. With only a little thrashing about, the child drowns all by himself,
|
β accidentally, β as Jones watches and does nothing.
|
Now Smith killed the child, whereas Jones β merely β let the child die. That
|
is the only difference between them. Did either man behave better, from a
|
moral point of view? If the difference between killing and letting die were in
|
itself a morally important matter, one should say that Jones β s behavior was
|
less reprehensible than Smith β s. But does one really want to say that? I think
|
not. In the fi rst place, both men acted from the same motive, personal gain,
|
and both had exactly the same end in view when they acted. It may be inferred
|
from Smith β s conduct that he is a bad man, although that judgment may be
|
withdrawn or modifi ed if certain further facts are learned about him β for
|
example, that he is mentally deranged. But would not the very same thing be
|
inferred about Jones from his conduct? And would not the same further
|
considerations also be relevant to any, modifi cation of this judgment?
|
Moreover, suppose Jones pleaded, in his own defense, β After all, I didn β t do
|
anything except just stand there and watch the child drown. I didn β t kill him;
|
Rachels on Euthanasia 279
|
I only let him die. β Again, if letting die were in itself less bad than killing,
|
this defense should have at least some weight. But it does not. Such a
|
β defense β can only be regarded as a grotesque perversion of moral reasoning.
|
Morally speaking, it is no defense at all. [ β¦ ] I have argued that killing is not
|
in itself any worse than letting die; if my contention is right, it follows that
|
active euthanasia is not any worse than passive euthanasia. (Rachels,
|
78 β 80)
|
P1. Smith β s killing the child is exactly like Jones β s letting the child die except
|
that Smith kills someone and Jones allows someone to die.
|
P2. What Smith did is morally as bad as what Jones did.
|
P3. If killing in itself is morally worse than letting die and Smith β s killing
|
the child is exactly like Jones β letting the child die except that Smith kills
|
someone and Jones allows someone to die, then Smith β s behavior should
|
be more reprehensible than Jones β .
|
C1. Not both killing in itself is morally worse than letting die and Smith β s
|
killing the child is exactly like Jones β letting the child die except that
|
Smith kills someone and Jones allows someone to die ( modus tollens ,
|
P2, P3).
|
C2. Not killing in itself is morally worse than letting die or not Smith β s
|
killing the child is exactly like Jones β s letting the child die except that
|
Smith kills someone and Jones allows someone to die (De Morgan β s,
|
C1).
|
C3. Not not Smith β s killing the child is exactly like Jones β letting the child
|
die except that Smith kills someone and Jones allows someone to die
|
(double negation, P1).
|
C4. Killing is not in itself morally worse than letting die (disjunctive
|
syllogism, C2, C3).
|
P4. If there is an important moral difference between active and passive
|
euthanasia, then killing someone is morally worse than letting someone
|
die.
|
C5. Active euthanasia is not any worse β ethically speaking β than passive
|
euthanasia ( modus tollens , P4, C4).
|
There is some ambiguity in the way some parts of the argument are
|
stated. Formalizing the statements in a language for quantifi ed fi rst - order
|
logic would bring out these ambiguities. For example, the fi nal conclusion
|
could mean that active euthanasia is never ethically worse than passive
|
euthanasia, or it could mean that active euthanasia is not always ethically
|
worse than passive euthanasia. It is pretty clear that Rachels has in the mind
|
the second of these two. Again, the intermediate conclusion C1 might mean
|
that killing is never ethically worse than otherwise identical instances of
|
letting die. But Rachels does not intend this. All that he means is that killing
|
is not always worse, morally speaking, than similar cases of letting die.
|
280 Leslie Burkholder
|
So long as these ambiguities are removed in a consistent way, this argument
|
is deductively valid. So if there is anything wrong with the reasoning,
|
it must be that one or more of the premises are false. If the ambiguities are
|
not cleared up in the same way, then the argument will turn out to be
|
invalid.
|
Part V
|
Philosophy of Mind
|
75
|
Leibniz β Argument for
|
Innate Ideas
|
Byron Kaldis
|
Subsets and Splits
No community queries yet
The top public SQL queries from the community will appear here once available.