text
stringlengths 0
1.71k
|
---|
or potentiality that could remain unactualized. It never fails to activate its
|
tendency; that is, the dedicated effort to unearth, or be aware of, innate
|
notions and truths contained in it. Such a Leibnizian force ( β endeavor β ) is
|
predetermined never to fail to produce some actual activity, given the right
|
conditions. By dint of attention or sense - probing, it acquires awareness of
|
its otherwise unconscious innate mental contents. Second, and related to
|
this, Leibniz never fails to emphasize well before the Nouveaux essais that
|
by β idea β he does not understand an actualized occurrence or act of thought
|
but a disposition to think in a certain way: β an idea consists not in some
|
act, but in the faculty of thinking, and we are said to have an idea of a
|
thing even if we do not think of it, if only, on a given occasion, we can
|
think of it β ( Philosophical Papers , 207). Given all this, third, for Leibniz,
|
286 Byron Kaldis
|
thinking does not amount to a constantly conscious series of occurrent
|
mental acts with clarity and distinctness, since the soul β s always being
|
active qua substance can be said to still be active even during β confused β
|
(i.e., less that fully clear) states, either as potentially striving toward such
|
conscious attentive thinking episodes or as being most of the time at a
|
steady - state attenuated potentiality only. But what safeguards such an attenuated
|
state from being empty, thus threatening to undermine Leibniz β whole
|
position, is that it contains one of his most innovative elements, what he
|
famously called β petites perceptions β : innumerable minute imperceptible
|
sensations, each one of which escapes our awareness yet contributes to the
|
aggregate impression of which we are aware. The Leibnizean conception of
|
the unconscious is used against Descartes β doctrine of constant or permanent
|
thinking while at the same time avoiding on the other side Locke β s
|
doctrine that the mind can be, at periods, blank or inactive. That the
|
β petites perceptions β turn out to be the capital pillar of Leibniz β defence of
|
innateness in the Nouveaux essais becomes quickly apparent as he puts his
|
invention to work in almost the whole range of his philosophy.
|
In the Preface to the Nouveaux essais , Leibniz advances three arguments
|
corresponding to the following theses (suitably reconstructed in an organized
|
form): (1) only innate principles ground our knowledge with demonstrative
|
certainty of the modal status of specifi c truths as necessary and
|
universally valid; (2) in self - refl ection we become aware of possessing
|
certain intellectual ideas (see above) being (a) immediately related to, and
|
(b) always present to, the understanding, although we do not normally pay
|
constant attention to these, since our everyday distractions and needs
|
prevent our always being aware of them; and (3) as in a block of marble
|
its veins predetermine the shape it may take, similarly our soul contains in
|
an unconscious state innate items which it has the predetermined potentiality,
|
tendency, or disposition to unearth, that is, become aware of β in
|
support of this, the thesis of petites perceptions is employed. All these can
|
be seen to be replies directed at the three prongs of Locke β s attack on
|
innatism: (1) together with (3) answer Locke β s contention that necessary
|
truths do not receive universal assent as they ought to if they were truly
|
innate to all mankind; (2) together with (3) answer Locke β s contention that
|
our mind cannot possess something of which it is unaware; and (3) together
|
with Leibniz β metaphysical theses about the nature of the mind (see above)
|
answer Locke β s contention that since the mind does not think all the time,
|
it is possible for the mind to be empty. In the fi rst chapter of Book I of the
|
Nouveaux essais , Leibniz adds a new aspect to potentiality, this time regarding
|
not just ideas but also our knowledge of truths and use of inferences:
|
their enthymemic character.
|
The signifi cance of Leibniz β argumentation cannot be overstated given
|
the importance of the notion of the unconscious β something he did not
|
Leibnizβ Argument for Innate Ideas 287
|
invent but formulated in a novel and plausible manner, his infl uence on
|
subsequent developments in German idealism, and, perhaps more importantly,
|
its unnoticed relevance to recent discussions in the philosophy of
|
mind and evolutionary psychology regarding nativism and concept - innatism,
|
or current research in neurophysiology. It is worth pointing out that current
|
neurobiological fi ndings regarding motor cognition corroborate his view of
|
the unconscious petites perceptions as neural activity falling below a
|
minimum level or duration required to emerge into awareness. Similarly, in
|
β subconcious pre - processing β during sense perception, it has been shown
|
that we are not aware, for example, of the hairs of our inner ear that actually
|
hear sounds but of the resultant aggregate acoustic sensation.
|
(1) [N]ecessary truths, such as we fi nd in pure mathematics [ . . . ] must
|
have principles whose proof does not depend on instances nor [ . . . ] on the
|
testimony of the senses, even though without the senses it would never occur
|
to us to think of them [ . . . ]. [S]o the proof of them can only come from inner
|
principles described as innate. It would indeed be wrong to think that we can
|
easily read these eternal laws of reason in the soul, as the Praetor β s edict can
|
be read on his notice - board, without effort or inquiry; but it is enough that
|
they can be discovered within us by dint of attention [ . . . ] what shows the
|
existence of inner sources of necessary truths is also what distinguishes man
|
from beast. (2) [I]deas which do not originate in sensation come from refl ection.
|
But refl ection is nothing but attention to what is within us, and the senses
|
do not give us what we carry with us already [ . . . ] can it be denied that there
|
is a great deal that is innate in our minds since we are innate to ourselves
|
[ . . . ] and since we include Being, Unity, Substance [ . . . ] and hosts of other
|
objects of our intellectual ideas? [ . . . ] (3) I have also used the analogy of the
|
veined block of marble, as opposed to an entirely homogeneous block of
|
marble, or to a blank tablet [ . . . ] if there were veins in the block which
|
marked out the shape of Hercules rather than other shapes, then the block
|
would be more determined to that shape and Hercules would be innate to it
|
[ . . . ] even though labour would be required to expose the veins and to polish
|
them to clarity, removing everything that prevents them from being seen. This
|
is how ideas and truths are innate in us β as inclinations, dispositions, tendencies,
|
or natural potentialities and not as action; although these potentialities
|
are always accompanied by certain actions, often insensible ones, which correspond
|
to them. (5) [ . . . A]t every moment there is in us an infi nity of
|
perceptions unaccompanied by awareness or refl ection; that is alterations in
|
the soul itself, of which we are unaware because these impressions are either
|
too minute and too numerous or else too unvarying [ . . . ]. But when they are
|
combined with others they do nevertheless have their effect and make themselves
|
felt. (6) [A] special affi nity which the human mind has with [necessary
|
truths . . . ] is what makes us call them innate. So it is not a bare faculty [ . . . ]
|
a mere possibility of understanding those truths; it is rather a disposition [ . . . ]
|
Subsets and Splits
No community queries yet
The top public SQL queries from the community will appear here once available.