text
stringlengths 0
1.71k
|
---|
happens to inhabit.
|
Descartes applies the equivalent of Leibniz β Law β in particular, that half
|
of the equivalence that is the conditional principle now often referred to as
|
the β indiscernibility of identicals β β in a widely imitated general strategy
|
for demonstrating the nonidentity of two distinct things by arguing for a
|
difference in their properties. What is ahistorically called β Leibniz β indiscernibility
|
of identicals principle β holds that for any A and B, if A = B, then
|
A and B have all of their properties in common. Certainly Descartes would
|
not have known the principle by either of these names but takes it for
|
granted that distinctions between objects are drawn on the basis of a distinction
|
among their properties. Descartes has the same intuitive grasp of
|
the idea that identicals must have identical properties, and that any discrepancy
|
among the properties of distinctly designated objects implies that the
|
objects themselves are not identical. In order to prove that mind β body in
|
Meditation 2, Descartes claims to have found a difference in the properties
|
of his mind and body, a property that his mind has but his body does not
|
have, or conversely.
|
Descartes singles out the property that he argues distinguishes his body
|
from his mind in two ways. He speaks of his mind as being β better knowable
|
β or β more easily knowable β than his body and of his body as being
|
such that its existence can be rationally doubted under the assumptions of
|
a methodological skepticism while his mind is such that its existence cannot
|
be rationally doubted, since entertaining doubt is a conscious state and in
|
some cases an act of mind. The conclusion that Descartes can rationally
|
doubt the existence of his body but not of his mind is supported, in turn,
|
by Descartes β consideration that there might be an evil demon who systematically
|
deceives him concerning the reality of any of his sense impressions
|
that appear to reveal the existence and nature of an external world outside
|
of, but correctly representing, the contents of his thoughts (the evil demon
|
hypothesis). Descartes on pain of contradiction cannot consistently doubt
|
the existence of his mind, since the actual entertainment of doubt would
|
necessarily be an event actually occurring in and hence presupposing the
|
existence of his mind ( Cogito, sum , in Latin; or β When I think [including
|
when I doubt], I exist β ) (#35, #36).
|
Descartes motivates his discussion of mind β body nonidentity in
|
Meditation 2 by considering the sensible properties of a piece of wax that
|
he invites the reader to imagine him describing as he holds and observes it
|
in his hand. Descartes believes that the wax is better known to the intellect
|
than by the senses because when the sensible properties of the wax all
|
292 Dale Jacquette
|
undergo change as the wax is gradually introduced to the heat of a fl ame,
|
the senses alone do not tell us that it was the same wax that has undergone
|
changes to its shape, size, color, smell, and other empirically perceivable
|
properties. From this, Descartes draws the general conclusion that things
|
known by the mind, including the mind itself, are better knowable than
|
things, such as the body, known primarily or only with the aid of the senses.
|
Descartes β proposition that his body but not his mind has the property of
|
being such that its existence can be rationally doubted by his mind reinforces
|
the argument β s assumption that Descartes β mind is better knowable
|
than his body, in the sense that he must infer the existence of his body from
|
the evidence of the senses, while the existence of mind upon refl ection is
|
immediately known to itself and knows itself self - refl ectively and introspectively,
|
directly and without the intermediary of logical or inductive
|
inference.
|
Descartes β fi rst or Meditations 2 β s mind β body argument has nevertheless
|
been criticized as subject to a fatal dilemma. The kind of property
|
Descartes maintains his mind has but his body does not have (better or
|
easier knowability) or that his body has but his mind does not have (such
|
that its existence is capable of being rationally doubted by his own mind)
|
seems to involve a mistaken, excessively general, application of what with
|
appropriate qualifi cations we shall continue to call β Leibniz β principle of
|
the indiscernibility of identicals. β Descartes β fi rst or Meditation 2 β s argument
|
for mind β body depends on what is sometimes called a β converse
|
intentional property, β a property that belongs to an object by virtue of the
|
intentional attitude that a thinking subject adopts or might adopt toward
|
it. If I love Lisbon, then I have the intentional property of loving Lisbon,
|
and Lisbon has the converse intentional property of being loved by me. If
|
I doubt the existence of my body, then I have the intentional property of
|
doubting the existence of my body, and my body has the converse intentional
|
property of being such that its existence is doubted by me. Entities
|
are distinguished when they can be shown not to share all of their properties.
|
If it is a property of Lisbon that it is loved by me, and if I do not
|
equally love London, then, if converse intentional properties are included
|
among the shared properties of identical objects prescribed by Leibniz β Law,
|
it should follow in this case that Lisbon β London. If I equally loved
|
London and Lisbon, then fortunately there would still remain many differences
|
between them by which their nonidentity could be established as a
|
consequence of Leibniz β Law. Lisbon and London have many things in
|
common despite being different cities, so why shouldn β t they have my equal
|
love for each of them in common?
|
Descartes β fi rst mind β body (Meditation 2) argument makes a philosophically
|
more unfortunate use of converse intentional properties in applying
|
the indiscernibility of identicals principle. His argument is sometimes
|
Descartesβ Arguments for the MindβBody Distinction 293
|
said to commit an β intensional fallacy. β The objection is that by defi nition
|
converse intentional properties do not belong intrinsically to objects but
|
only as a consequence of the extrinsic circumstance of being thought of
|
in a certain way by certain thinking subjects. Changes in object A β s and
|
object B β s converse intentional properties as a result would seem to leave
|
the object itself completely untouched as to the satisfaction or not of its
|
intrinsic identity conditions. We know that 1 + 1 = 2, for example, even
|
though someone might doubt that 1 + 1 is a prime number despite not
|
doubting that 2 is a prime number. We know that Mark Twain = Samuel
|
Clemens, regardless of whether or not someone happens to believe that
|
Mark Twain wrote Tom Sawyer while doubting that Samuel Clemens wrote
|
Tom Sawyer . Converse intentional properties invalidate Leibniz β Law as a
|
universal identity principle, which means that extrinsic converse intentional
|
properties should be barred from its applications. Unfortunately, Descartes β
|
fi rst (Meditation 2) mind β body argument commits precisely the β intensional
|
fallacy β of deducing the nonidentity of body and mind on the basis
|
Subsets and Splits
No community queries yet
The top public SQL queries from the community will appear here once available.