text
stringlengths 0
1.71k
|
---|
features of V. The argument would be as follows: |
P1. If a subject, S, has the sensation, V, then V is a sensation of a subject - |
dependent entity, Z (weak content version). |
P2. By having V, S cannot introspect features of V, but just what V is about, |
that is, Z (strong transparency). |
C1. There are no perceptual intermediaries between S and Z (metaphysical |
inference * * ). |
The Transparency of Experience Argument 145 |
There is another version about content; this is a version of the weak |
content version. Call this the β property - content β version (iii): what fi gures |
as the content of a sensation are subject - dependent properties (say, colors) |
which look like being instantiated in subject - independent particulars (say, |
tables). This version can be coupled with weak transparency. We obtain a |
third version of TEA: call this β sense - data β TEA. |
P1. If a subject, S, has the sensation, V, then V is a sensation of a subject - |
dependent property, Q, looking like instantiated on a mind - independent |
particular X (property - content version). |
P2. By having a sensation, V, S could introspect Q (Weak Transparency). |
C1. There are perceptual intermediaries between S and X. |
Sense - data TEA differs from weak TEA since the former specifi es that |
perceptual intermediaries can only be sensory properties, say qualia , and |
cannot be concrete physical particulars (see Russell). The debate about |
transparency and the right comprehension of the content of sensations is |
far from being solved; however, there are many detailed theories trying to |
do it. |
38 |
The Regress Argument for |
Skepticism |
Scott Aikin |
Sextus Empiricus . Outlines of Scepticism . Translated by Julia Annas and |
Jonathan Barnes. Cambridge, UK : Cambridge University Press , 2000 . |
Oakley , I. T. β An Argument for Scepticism Concerning Justifi ed Beliefs . β |
American Philosophical Quarterly , 13 , 3 ( 1976 ): 221 β 8 . |
Cling , Andrew . β Reasons, Regresses and Tragedy . β American Philosophical |
Quarterly , 46 , 2 ( 2009 ): 333 β 46 . |
The basic thought behind the regress argument is familiar to anyone who |
has spoken with an inquisitive child, β Why? β is always a good question. |
Since the question can be asked of any answer, a recursive pattern very |
quickly emerges. For example, β Eat your vegetables. β β Why? β β Because |
they are good for you. β β Why? β β Because you want to he healthy. β β Why? β |
And then we are off to the races. Translated to an epistemological context, |
the regress problem arises because of the simple requirement that if you are |
to hold reasonably a belief, you must be able to answer satisfactorily a |
β why β question with another reasonably held belief or group of beliefs. |
This, of course, invites another β why β question, which requires another |
satisfactory and justifi ably held answer. And then the regress ensues (#49). |
It seems that the demand that we go on to infi nity is excessive, that answers |
that go in a circle are vicious, and that anytime someone says she does not |
need to give further answers, she is acting unreasonably. Skepticism seems |
to follow β if we cannot give the adequate backing for our claims, we do |
not know those claims to be true. |
Just the Arguments: 100 of the Most Important Arguments in Western Philosophy, |
First Edition. Edited by Michael Bruce and Steven Barbone. |
Β© 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. Published 2011 by Blackwell Publishing Ltd. |
The Regress Argument for Skepticism 147 |
Sextus Empiricus classically framed the regress problem in his Outlines |
of Pyrrhonism as the coordination of fi ve β modes, β or strategies, of skeptical |
argument. Two of these modes, sometimes called the β material modes, β |
are those to challenge someone who believes something to defend it. These |
are the modes of relativity and dispute. Once a believer starts to defend the |
belief, there are only three options for the argument to proceed: either in |
(i) a vicious regress, which Sextus calls β ad infi nitum , β (ii) a question - |
begging circle, which Sextus calls β reciprocality, β or (iii) unsupported dogmatic |
assertion, which Sextus calls β hypothesis. β These three fi nal modes |
for argument are called the β formal modes β or β the trilemma. β |
According to the mode deriving from dispute, we fi nd that undecidable |
dissension about the matter proposed has come about both in ordinary life |
and among philosophers. Because of this we are not able either to choose or |
to rule out anything, and we end up with suspension of judgment. In the mode |
of deriving from infi nite regress, we say that what is brought forward as a |
source of conviction for the matter proposed itself needs another source, |
which itself needs another, and so ad infi nitum, so that we have no point from |
which to begin to establish anything, and suspension of judgment follows. In |
the mode deriving from relativity, [ β¦ ] the existing object appears to be such - |
and - such relative to the subject judging and to the things observed together |
with it, but we suspend judgment on what it is like in its nature. We have the |
mode from hypothesis from the Dogmatists, being thrown back ad infi nitum, |
begin from something which they do not establish but claim to assume simply |
and without proof in virtue of a concession. The reciprocal mode occurs when |
what ought to be confi rmatory of the object under investigation needs to be |
made convincing by the object under investigation; then, being unable to take |
either in order to establish the other, we suspend judgment about both. |
(Empiricus PH I.165 β 9) |
Given the structural problems that come with knowing, we are forced |
to suspend judgment about our beliefs generally because they are not justifi |
ed. Justifi cation is structurally vexed, and as a consequence, something we |
cannot possess. General skepticism about knowledge, then, follows. The |
argument β s premises are all inherently plausible. The principle of inferential |
justifi cation is something that comes with being a responsible believer β if |
you believe something, then you should be able to explain why you do so; |
that is, you should be able to give a reason that counts in favor of the truth |
of your belief. This is simply what it is to be accountable for and in charge |
of your beliefs. The responsibility iterates, because the reasons we give must, |
themselves, pass this test. And so these chains of reasons are just part of |
what it is to be a rational being β we give justifying stories for what we do, |
what we say, and what we believe. Without those stories, it is hard to see |
ourselves as responsible, reasonable, or rational. |
148 Scott Aikin |
The principle of noncircular justifi cation comes from the informal argumentative |
thought that arguments that have their conclusions function in |
Subsets and Splits
No community queries yet
The top public SQL queries from the community will appear here once available.