text
stringlengths 0
1.71k
|
---|
their premises fail because they beg the question. Reasoning should be a |
kind of progress, where we get somewhere, increase our knowledge, resolve |
disagreements, and answer questions. If we assume our conclusions at the |
beginning and tell our justifying stories for them in light of them, we have |
at most been consistent, but that is about as much as we can say in favor |
of the reasoning. |
The principle of fi nite justifi cation is simply that infi nite series of reasons |
are not completable by fi nite creatures such as us. We do not have infi nite |
time, nor do we have infi nite reasons for our beliefs β our minds are limited |
only to the things we β ve experienced, thought about, and learned. The |
requirement that knowledge be more than that is absurd. Further, it seems, |
as Sextus notes above, even were there an infi nite chain of reasons, we are |
unsure how reasoning on such a chain of reasons could either ever get |
started or ever fi nish. |
The corollaries of no unjustifi ed justifi ers and no unjustifi ed chain - enders |
are contrapositives of the principle of inferential justifi cation and the corollary |
of recursive justifi cation. The requirement of inferential justifi cation is |
that (in epistemology lingo) if S has a justifi ed belief that p, S has a justifi ed |
belief that q that justifi es p. The corollary is that without a justifi ed belief |
that q that justifi es p, S does not have a justifi ed belief that p. There are no |
unjustifi ed justifi ers. |
The trilemma is that once chains of reasons begin to be extended, there |
are only three options: they either (a) stop with some belief or other, without |
further support, (b) circle back on themselves, or (c) go on to infi nity. So |
long as we think that reasons must come in recursive chains, these are the |
only three options. |
Despite the fact that all the premises of the argument are each individually |
appealing, they together entail an unappealing conclusion, namely, that |
we have no justifi cation for any of our beliefs. This unacceptable conclusion |
has forced many to return to the premises of the argument with a more |
critical eye. One of the premises, if we do in fact know things, must be |
false. The project of anti - skepticism, in light of the regress problem, is that |
of making the case for the falsity of at least one of these premises. |
The oldest and most widely favored anti - skeptical strategy is called |
β foundationalism. β The foundationalist holds that premise 1 is false, or at |
least, that there are notable exceptions. There are some beliefs that stand |
on their own, and they can then serve as a foundation for further beliefs. |
Call these beliefs with autonomous justifi cation β basic beliefs. β The foundationalist |
accepts that reasons come in chains, but if the reasons are justifying, |
those chains of reasons all end with beliefs that are justifi ed |
independently of other reasons. Take three examples, your beliefs: (i) that |
The Regress Argument for Skepticism 149 |
you exist, (ii) that you have a book in front of you, and (iii) that 2 + 2 = 4. |
Each of these beliefs is justifi ed because you just see that they it is true. |
You, in believing (i), furnish the reason for its truth (it can β t be false if you |
believe it). Your visual experiences of this book in front of you give you a |
reason to believe (ii), and you don β t need more reasons for that. Your concepts |
of addition, equality, two, and four give you the understanding to |
make it so that you don β t need any more reason to believe (iii) than just |
that you understand it. Beliefs such as these are regress - enders. |
The β coherentist β accepts the principle of inferential justifi cation and |
holds that only justifi ed beliefs can justify beliefs. However, the coherentist |
denies the principle of the noncircularity of justifi cation. Justifying stories |
come as packages, in that we reasonably believe things when they fi t well |
enough with other things that we believe. And once these systems of belief |
are up and running, the beliefs in them are mutually supporting. For |
example, you believe that there are physical forces, such as gravity. You |
also believe that a bowling ball falling down on a fragile porcelain mouse |
will crush it. You also believe that the last time you dropped your keys, |
they fell on the ground. These beliefs all hang together, and they function, |
with many others, as a system for you to make sense of your past experiences |
and make predictions about future ones. Justifi cation emerges from |
these interdependent and mutually supporting systems of beliefs. |
The β contextualist, β like the foundationalist, holds that there are exceptions |
to the principle of inferential justifi cation. However, the beliefs that |
need no further reasons are dependent on what kinds of questions our |
justifi cations are out to answer. For example, if you β re trying to decide |
whether to go to Las Vegas for your holiday, it may be reasonable to doubt |
that your year - old information about hotel prices is accurate. So you may |
go to a recent source. But you β re not going to worry about whether they |
accept American dollars or whether you can expect that you can get service |
in English. But if you were thinking about going to Monte Carlo (in |
Monaco), instead, you β d not only want to get better information about |
hotel prices, but you β d also want to check into what kind of currency you β ll |
need and whether you β ll need to take a crash course in French. Depending |
on what β s at issue, some questions aren β t worth asking, because their |
answers are reasonably assumed in the context. But in others they are worth |
asking, because you cannot reasonably assume their answers. |
β Infi nitism β is a recent development in epistemology, as for the over |
2,000 years folks have been thinking about the regress problem, it wasn β t |
until the last 10 years that anyone β s tried to work this view out in any detail. |
The infi nitist denies the principle of fi nite justifi cation. And so the infi nitist |
holds that only an infi nite series of reasons can yield justifi ed belief. The |
basic thought is that the person who really knows something can answer |
β why β questions until there just aren β t any more. And, in principle, there |
150 Scott Aikin |
is no reason why such questions must end. This is certainly a heavy task, |
and it seems troublesome, because it is clear that we don β t ever actually give |
those very long arguments. But the infi nitist holds that one may not have |
to give those arguments but only be able to give them as far as they are |
needed by critical questioners. Persistent questioners are troublesome, but |
they are useful to us in that they allow us to plumb the depths of our |
reasons. They may break certain rules of context in questioning things we |
don β t normally question, but that is how we really know β we can answer |
questions that otherwise we β d just say we β d assumed. |
The success of the regress argument for skepticism hinges on whether |
these four anti - skeptical programs are correct in denying or modifying the |
argument β s premises. If these anti - skeptical programs are right, they must |
be able to answer some simple questions. The question for the foundationalist |
is whether, in arguing that there are regress - ending basic beliefs, the |
Subsets and Splits
No community queries yet
The top public SQL queries from the community will appear here once available.