text
stringlengths 0
1.71k
|
---|
First Edition. Edited by Michael Bruce and Steven Barbone. |
Β© 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. Published 2011 by Blackwell Publishing Ltd. |
Gettier and the Traditional Account of Knowledge 157 |
fi ed belief, one β s good reasons do not necessarily need to guarantee that the |
belief is true. For example, one may be justifi ed in believing that one is |
seeing a zebra based on the evidence of a black - and - white - striped - equine |
sensory experience, and one would still be justifi ed, in believing one is seeing |
a zebra, even if the animal were not a zebra but a cleverly painted mule |
instead. Consequently, for a belief to be justifi ed, it is not necessary for the |
belief to be true. As (P2) states, it is possible for one to be justifi ed in believing |
a false proposition. |
The next part of Gettier β s counterexample follows from the principle |
expressed by (P3): if one is justifi ed in believing some proposition, then one |
is justifi ed (at least to the same degree) in believing any proposition that |
one competently deduces from the original one. Since when deductive reasoning |
is performed competently it preserves truth infallibly, one β s justifi cation |
does not diminish across deductive inference. Perhaps this is best |
illustrated by a variation from one of Gettier β s examples. Imagine a case |
where a trustworthy friend, Mr. Nogot, provides suffi ciently strong evidence |
to his friend Jackson for being justifi ed in believing that he (Nogot) owns |
a Ford. For example, imagine that in addition to his typically trustworthy |
testimony, Mr. Nogot shows Jackson his registration papers, he takes |
Jackson for a ride in the Ford, and Jackson has no reason to doubt his |
testimony or any of the additional evidence that he has to support the |
proposition that Mr. Nogot owns a Ford. Now, Mr. Nogot does not own |
a Ford (unbeknownst to Jackson), but this does not prevent Jackson from |
being justifi ed in believing that Mr. Nogot owns a Ford, since according to |
(P2) it is possible for a person to be justifi ed in believing a false proposition. |
And now to the part relevant to (P3) β suppose that as Jackson is pondering |
his justifi ed belief (that Mr. Nogot owns a Ford) with Mr. Nogot in the |
room, he deductively reasons that if Mr. Nogot owns a Ford, then someone |
in the room owns a Ford; therefore, Jackson concludes, someone in the |
room owns a Ford. On the basis of (P3), Jackson is at least as justifi ed in |
believing that someone in the room owns a Ford as he is for the proposition |
that Mr. Nogot owns a Ford since he deduced the former from the latter, |
which is stated in (C1). |
The fi nal claim needed to underwrite Gettier β s counterexample is stated |
in (P4): If a person is justifi ed in believing a proposition that is true by |
accident or luck, then her justifi ed true belief is not knowledge. It has |
already been stipulated that Mr. Nogot does not own a Ford. Now let β s |
suppose that at the time that Jackson deductively reasons from the proposition |
that Mr. Nogot owns a Ford to the proposition that someone in the |
room owns a Ford, Mr. Havit happens to be the room. Mr. Havit β a person |
Jackson has never met or has any justifi cation for believing what kind of |
car he owns β is sitting quietly in the corner of the room, and he happens |
to own a Ford. So, it turns out that Jackson β s belief that someone in the |
158 John M. DePoe |
room owns a Ford is both justifi ed and true. Recall that it is justifi ed because |
he deduced it from a proposition that he is justifi ed in believing. The belief |
is true since Mr. Havit owns a Ford and he is in the room. But since Jackson |
has no beliefs whatsoever about Mr. Havit, the truth of his justifi ed belief |
appears to be accidental or lucky. After all, Jackson would have still believed |
that someone in the room owns a Ford even if Mr. Havit wasn β t in the |
room. Thus, it seems that Jackson β s justifi ed belief is true by luck or accident. |
In other words, the belief β s being true has nothing to do with the |
justifi cation Jackson has for holding the belief. For this reason, it would be |
wrong to accept that Jackson β s justifi ed true belief (that someone in the |
room owns a Ford) counts as knowledge. |
Since Jackson β s belief that someone in the room owns a Ford is a justifi ed |
true belief (C2), and it is plainly wrong to think that it counts as knowledge, |
Gettier β s argument is widely accepted as demonstrating why knowledge |
cannot be defi ned as justifi ed true belief (C3). |
These [ . . . ] examples show that defi nition (a) [knowledge is justifi ed true |
belief] does not state a suffi cient condition for someone β s knowing a given |
proposition. (Gettier, 123) |
P1. If knowledge is justifi ed true belief, then it is not possible for a person |
to have a justifi ed true belief that isn β t knowledge. |
P2. A person can be justifi ed in believing a false proposition. |
P3. If a person is justifi ed in believing some proposition, then she is justifi ed |
(at least to the same degree) in believing any proposition that she competently |
deduces from the original. |
C1. A person is justifi ed (at least to the same degree) in believing any |
proposition that she competently deduces from the original ( modus |
ponens , P2, P3). |
P4. If a person is justifi ed in believing a proposition that is true by accident |
or luck, then his justifi ed true belief is not knowledge. |
P5. Jackson is justifi ed in believing that someone in the room owns a Ford, |
which is true by accident or luck. |
C2. It is possible for a person to have a justifi ed true belief that isn β t |
knowledge ( modus ponens , P4, P5). |
C3. It is not the case that knowledge is justifi ed true belief ( modus tollens , |
P1, C2). |
42 |
Putnam β s Argument against |
Cultural Imperialism |
Maria Caama Γ± o |
Putnam , Hilary . β Why Reason Can β t Be Naturalized , β in Epistemology: An |
Anthology , edited by Ernest Sosa , Jaegwon Kim , and Mathew McGrath , |
314 β 24 . Malden, MA : Blackwell , 1999 . |
Putnam introduces this argument in the context of criticizing the different |
attempts to naturalize reason by reducing it to those standards accepted by |
a culture. According to Putnam, reason always results from a balance |
between immanence to culture and traditions and transcendence to them. |
The fi rst would be manifest in the inherited cultural background in which |
any reasoning always takes place; the second would become obvious in our |
ability to criticize such cultural background. Both cultural relativism and |
cultural imperialism would break the above balance as a result of their |
emphasis on immanence. However, facts related to the transcendent side of |
reason are precisely the ones that would show the self - refutability of both |
views. Cultural relativism would need to make, inconsistently, a transcendent |
Subsets and Splits
No community queries yet
The top public SQL queries from the community will appear here once available.