text
stringlengths 0
1.71k
|
---|
assumption regarding the symmetry of the epistemic situation between |
different cultures. Cultural imperialism, on the other hand, would require |
us to assume an immanent agreement that is contradicted by experience. |
So while the argument for cultural relativism turns out to be analytically |
fl awed, the one to support cultural imperialism proves empirically faulty. |
In this context, Putnam formulates his argument against cultural imperialism |
and continues by pointing out two of its important features: fi rst, its |
contingent character, since the goodness of the argument depends on the |
Just the Arguments: 100 of the Most Important Arguments in Western Philosophy, |
First Edition. Edited by Michael Bruce and Steven Barbone. |
Β© 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. Published 2011 by Blackwell Publishing Ltd. |
160 Maria CaamaΓ±o |
contingent fact that people disagree about something β that is, about truth β s |
dependency on cultural standards (P2 below); and second, its extensibility |
to all theories which equate truth or right assertability with what people |
(would) agree. The importance of the argument, therefore, does not only |
lie on its rebuttal of cultural imperialism but also on its more general refutation |
of any defi nition of truth in terms of (possible) agreement among |
people. The argument follows a reductio ad absurdum strategy, by refl exively |
applying the requirement established in the principle of cultural imperialisms |
to that very principle and thereby showing that the assumption |
violates the very requirement that it establishes. Finally, a more general aim |
of Putnam β s argument consists in supporting the view that modern European |
and American culture does not have β norms β that decide philosophical |
questions, as would happen in totalitarian or theocratic cultures. |
A statement is true (rightly assertable) only if it is assertable according to |
the norms of modern European and American culture is itself neither assertable |
nor refutable in a way that requires assent by everyone who does not |
deviate from the norms of modern European and American culture. So, if this |
statement is true, it follows that it is not true QED. (Putnam, 319) |
P1. A statement P is true (rightly assertable) only if it is assertable according |
to the norms of modern European and American culture (assumption for |
reductio ). |
C1. If β A statement is true (rightly assertable) only if it is assertable |
according to the norms of modern European and American culture β |
is true (rightly assertable), then it is assertable according to the norms |
of modern European and American culture (substitution of β P β with |
β A statement is true (rightly assertable) only if it is assertable according |
to the norms of modern European and American culture β in P1). |
P2. β A statement is true (rightly assertable) only if it is assertable according |
to the norms of modern European and American culture β is not assertable |
according to the norms of modern European and American culture. |
C2. β A statement is true (rightly assertable) only if it is assertable according |
to the norms of modern European and American culture β is not |
true, that is, rightly assertable ( modus tollens , C1, P2). |
C3. A statement is true (rightly assertable) only if it is assertable according |
to the norms of modern European and American culture and it is |
not the case that a statement is true (rightly assertable) only if it is |
assertable according to the norms of modern European and American |
culture (conjunction, P1, C2). |
C4. It is not the case that a statement is true (rightly assertable) only if |
it is assertable according to the norms of modern European and |
American culture ( reductio , P1 β C3). |
Putnamβs Argument against Cultural Imperialism 161 |
Extension of Putnam β s Argument |
In order to bring Putnam β s discussion of his own argument to completion, |
it may be interesting to show how it naturally extends to arguments equating |
truth with what people (would) agree. Let us see how the refutation |
would work in that case: |
P1. A statement P is true (rightly assertable) only if everybody agrees with |
it (assumption for reductio ). |
C1. If β A statement is true (rightly assertable) only if everybody agrees |
with it β is true (rightly assertable), then everybody agrees with it |
(Substitution of β P β by β A statement is true (rightly assertable) only if |
everybody agrees with it β in P1). |
P2. Not everybody agrees that β A statement is true (rightly assertable) only |
if everybody agrees with it. β |
C2. β A statement is true (rightly assertable) only if everybody agrees with |
it β is not true, that is, rightly assertable ( modus tollens , C1, P2). |
C3. A statement is true (rightly assertable) only if everybody agrees with |
it and it is not the case that a statement is true (rightly assertable) |
only if everybody agrees with it (conjunction, P1, C2). |
C4. It is not the case that a statement is true (rightly assertable) only if |
everybody agrees with it ( reductio , P1 β C3). |
43 |
Davidson on the Very Idea of a |
Conceptual Scheme |
George Wrisley |
Davidson , Donald . β On the Very Idea of a Conceptual Scheme . β Proceedings |
and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 47 ( 1974 ): |
5 β 20 ; reprinted in Davidson (2001). |
Davidson , Donald . Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation , 2nd edn. Oxford : |
Clarendon Press , 2001 . |
Case , Jennifer . β On the Right Idea of a Conceptual Scheme . β Southern |
Journal of Philosophy 35 ( 1997 ): 1 β 18 . |
Malpas , Jeff . β Donald Davidson . β The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |
(Fall 2009 edn.), edited by Edward N. Zalta , available at http:// |
plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2009/entries/Davidson |
One of Immanuel Kant β s (1724 β 1804) central philosophical concerns was |
the relationship between mind and world. He famously inverted the idea |
that in knowing the world the mind attempts to mirror a β mind - independent β |
world, claiming instead that the world we experience necessarily conforms |
to certain categories of the mind. While such categories were essentially |
universal for Kant, later philosophers replaced the idea of the world β s conforming |
to the categories of the mind with the idea of the world β s conforming |
to linguistic or conceptual categories. This change allowed for the idea |
of a very strong conceptual/linguistic relativism whereby either the content |
of experience or the world itself is relativized to conceptual frameworks or |
Just the Arguments: 100 of the Most Important Arguments in Western Philosophy, |
First Edition. Edited by Michael Bruce and Steven Barbone. |
Subsets and Splits
No community queries yet
The top public SQL queries from the community will appear here once available.