text
stringlengths 0
1.71k
|
---|
at all. |
We arrive at the same conclusion if we approach the question from the |
standpoint of self - suffi ciency. For the fi nal and perfect good seems to be self - |
suffi cient. (Aristotle, 1097a26 β 1097b8) |
P1. There is a supreme good for humanity, commonly referred to as |
happiness. |
P2. If a good is desired as an end in itself and is suffi cient for making life |
good, then that good constitutes happiness. |
P3. The virtuous life fulfi lls a human being β s function by actualizing that |
person β s full potential. |
216 Eric J. Silverman |
P4. If some good fulfi lls a human being β s function by actualizing that person |
β s full potential, then that good is desired as an end in itself. |
C1. The virtuous life is desired by human beings as an end in itself |
( modus ponens , P3, P4). |
P5. If some good fulfi lls a human being β s function, then it is suffi cient for |
making that being β s life good. |
C2. The virtuous life is suffi cient for making a human being β s life good |
( modus ponens , P3, P5). |
C3. The virtuous life is desired as an end in itself and is suffi cient for |
making life good (conjunction, C1, C2). |
C4. The virtuous life constitutes happiness, the supreme good for humanity |
( modus ponens , P2, C3). |
55 |
Categorical Imperative as the |
Source for Morality |
Joyce Lazier |
Kant , Immanuel . The Metaphysics of Morals , translated by Mary Gregor. |
New York : Cambridge University Press , 1991 . |
Kant β s deontological ethical theory relies on two assumptions used to |
deduce the categorical imperative. The fi rst is that morality is for all, or |
what is wrong for one to do is wrong for everyone to do. The second is |
that morality is grounded on reason and not experience. Combining these |
two assumptions, Kant arrives at the categorical imperative. The following |
reconstruction of Kant β s arguments for the categorical imperative brings to |
the forefront two major problems. First, the use of disjunction opens up |
Kant β s argument to the fallacy of the excluded middle, and second, the |
reconstruction also makes more apparent Kant β s reliance on teleology. Not |
many thinkers today believe that everything has a specifi c, defi ned end that |
belongs only to it. The arguments are taken from The Metaphysics of |
Morals, parts 216, 222, and 225. |
But it is different with the teachings of morality. They command for everyone, |
without taking account of his inclinations, merely because and insofar |
as he is free and has practical reason. He does not derive instruction in its |
laws from observing himself and his animal nature or from perceiving the |
ways of the world what happens and how men behave (although the German |
word Sitten , like the Latin mores , means only manners and customs). Instead, |
Just the Arguments: 100 of the Most Important Arguments in Western Philosophy, |
First Edition. Edited by Michael Bruce and Steven Barbone. |
Β© 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. Published 2011 by Blackwell Publishing Ltd. |
218 Joyce Lazier |
reason commands how men are to act even though no example of this could |
be found and it takes no account of the advantages we can thereby gain, |
which only experience could teach us. For although reason allows us to seek |
our advantage in every way possible to us and can even promise us, on the |
testimony of experience, that it will probably be more to our advantage on |
the whole to obey its commands than to transgress them especially if obedience |
is accompanied with prudence, still the authority of its precepts as commands |
is not based on these considerations. Instead it uses them (as counsels) |
only as a counterweight against inducements to the contrary, to offset in |
advance the error of biased scales in practical appraisal, and only then to |
ensure that the weight of a pure practical reason β s a priori grounds will turn |
the scales in favor of the authority of its precepts. (216) |
An imperative is a practical rule by which an action in itself contingent is |
made necessary. An imperative differs from a practical law in that a law |
indeed represents an action as necessary but takes no account of whether this |
action already inheres by an inner necessity in the acting subject (as in a holy |
being) or whether it is contingent (as in man); for where the former is the |
case there is no imperative. Hence an imperative is a rule the representation |
of which makes necessary an action that is subjectively contingent and thus |
represents the subject as one that must be constrained (necessitated) to |
conform with the rule. A categorical (unconditional) imperative is one that |
represents an action as objectively necessary and makes it necessary not indirectly |
through the representation of some end that can be attained by the |
action but through the mere representation of this action itself (its form), and |
hence directly. No other practical doctrine can furnish instances of such |
imperatives than that which prescribes obligation (the doctrine of morals). |
All other imperative are technical and are, one and all, conditional. The |
ground of the possibility of categorical imperative is this: that they refer to |
no other property of choice (by which some purpose can be ascribed to it) |
than simply to its freedom. (222) |
The categorical imperative, which as such only affi rms what obligation is, |
is: Act upon a maxim that can also hold as a universal law. You must therefore |
fi rst consider your actions in terms of their subjective principles; but you can |
know whether this principle also holds objectively only in this way: That |
when your reason subjects it to the test of conceiving yourself as also giving |
universal law through it, it qualifi es for such a giving of universal law. (225) |
P1. A human is free and has practical reason. |
P2. Either practical reason or experience uses perceptions of the ways of |
the world and actions of humans as sources of its laws. |
P3. Practical reason does not use the ways of the world and actions of |
humans as sources of its laws. |
C1. Experience uses perceptions of the ways of the world and actions of |
humans as sources of its laws (disjunctive syllogism, P2, P3). |
Categorical Imperative as the Source for Morality 219 |
P4. Either practical reason or experience teaches us how to act given the |
advantages we can gain. |
P5. Practical reason does not teach us how to act given the advantages we |
can gain. |
C2. Experience teaches us how to act given the advantages we can gain |
Subsets and Splits
No community queries yet
The top public SQL queries from the community will appear here once available.