text
stringlengths 0
1.71k
|
---|
is Kant β s insistence that the only acts of will that deserve respect are
|
those acts of will that are truly free (according to Kant β s understanding of
|
β freedom β ). It should quickly be added that Kant understood the concept
|
of β respect β in a very robust way: according to Kant, to say that something
|
deserves respect is to say that it is an object of true and proper esteem.
|
Moreover, it is important to note that for Kant, what it means for a person
|
to be free is for that person not to be dominated by his or her inclinations
|
or desires but rather to will and to act in accordance with universal laws
|
of reason. Lastly, it should be noted that a number of philosophers have
|
agreed with Kant that autonomy deserves respect but have disagreed with
|
Kant about what autonomy fundamentally is. More specifi cally, some philosophers
|
have claimed that it is possible for autonomous acts of will to
|
contain, or to be based on, inclinations.
|
For an object as the effect of my proposed action I can indeed have inclination
|
but never respect, just because it is merely an effect and not an activity
|
of the will. In the same way I cannot have respect for inclination as such,
|
whether it is mine or that of another; I can at most in the fi rst case approve
|
it and in the second sometimes even love it, that is, regard it as favorable to
|
my advantage. Only what it connected with my will solely as ground and
|
never as effect, what does not serve my inclination but outweighs it or at least
|
excludes it altogether from calculations in making a choice β hence the mere
|
law for itself β can be an object of respect and so a command. (Kant AK
|
4:400)
|
P1. If an act of will is free, then it deserves respect.
|
P2. If an act of will is not free, then it does not deserve respect.
|
P3. If an act of will is dependent on an object of desire, then it is not a free
|
act of will.
|
P4. If an act of will is in no way infl uenced by any object of desire but is
|
rather exercised in accordance with its own law, then it is a free act of
|
will.
|
P5. An inclination is dependent on objects of desire.
|
C1. Inclinations are not free acts of will ( modus ponens , P3, P5)
|
C2. Inclinations do not deserve respect ( modus ponens , P2, C1).
|
P6. An autonomous act of will is in no way infl uenced by any object of
|
desire but is rather exercised in accordance with its own law.
|
C3. Autonomous acts of will are free acts of will ( modus ponens , P4,
|
P6).
|
C4. Autonomous acts of will deserve respect ( modus ponens , P1, C3).
|
57
|
Mill β s Proof of Utilitarianism
|
A. T. Fyfe
|
Mill , John Stuart . β Of What Sort of Proof the Principle of Utility Is
|
Susceptible , β in Utilitarianism . London : Parker, Son, and Bourn , 1863 .
|
___. β Excerpt from a Letter to Henry Jones , β in The Classical Utilitarians:
|
Bentham and Mill , edited by John Troyer . Indianapolis : Hackett , 2003 .
|
Millgram , Elijah . β Mill β s Proof of the Principle of Utility . β Ethics 110 ( 2000 ):
|
282 β 310 .
|
Sayre - McCord , Geoffrey . β Mill β s β Proof β of the Principle of Utility: A More
|
than Half - Hearted Defense . β Social Philosophy & Policy 18 , 2 ( 2001 ):
|
330 β 60 .
|
Utilitarianism, as summarized by one of its chief proponents, John Stuart
|
Mill (1806 β 73), is the moral theory that β actions are right in proportion
|
as they tend to promote happiness, wrong as they tend to produce the
|
reverse of happiness. β Therefore, viewing matters as Mill would, Robin
|
Hood is not immoral for stealing from the rich to give to the poor, because
|
in doing so he is able to produce more happiness in the world than would
|
have otherwise existed. Likewise, if I possess excess wealth, it would be
|
immoral of me to withhold that wealth from others for whom it would do
|
more good. If, for example, I am considering new shoes when my present
|
pair is fully functional, I should instead donate that excess wealth to famine
|
relief. In both instances, Mill would have the agent in question perform
|
whichever available action would best reduce unhappiness and promote
|
happiness in the world.
|
Just the Arguments: 100 of the Most Important Arguments in Western Philosophy,
|
First Edition. Edited by Michael Bruce and Steven Barbone.
|
Β© 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. Published 2011 by Blackwell Publishing Ltd.
|
224 A. T. Fyfe
|
Utilitarianism is generally understood to be the combination of two
|
separate moral theories. First, utilitarianism is a form of β consequentialism,
|
β since it holds that the rightness or wrongness of an action depends
|
solely upon the goodness or badness of that action β s consequences. Second,
|
utilitarianism is a form of β welfarism, β since it holds that the goodness or
|
badness of an action β s consequences depends solely upon the amount of
|
happiness and unhappiness brought about by that action (i.e., the action β s
|
effect on people β s welfare). Therefore, any argument for utilitarianism must
|
aim to prove not one but two separate claims: a consequentialist β theory
|
of the right β (i.e., what is right and wrong) and a welfarist β theory of the
|
good β (i.e., what is good and bad).
|
Examining J. S. Mill β s famous argument for utilitarianism, it is clear that
|
Mill simply takes for granted a consequentialist theory of the right rather
|
than providing an argument for it. As a result, even if Mill β s argument for
|
utilitarianism succeeds, it will only prove half of what utilitarianism consists
|
in, a welfarist theory of value. Taking what Mill says at face value, his
|
argument begins with the claim that the only way we come to know that
|
something is visible or audible is through seeing or hearing it. Mill then
|
concludes, by analogy, that the only way to prove that something is desirable
|
(i.e., worth desiring; good) is by appealing to what we actually do
|
desire. After using this analogy with audibility and visibility to establish the
|
only method for proving that something is desirable, Mill argues that happiness
|
is the only intrinsic good in existence since (1) people do desire it,
|
and (2) it is the only thing that people desire for its own sake. With this
|
result in hand, Mill then concludes his argument for utilitarianism β or at
|
least utilitarianism β s welfarist aspect β by inferring that since an increase in
|
a person β s happiness is good for that person, an increase in all persons β
|
happiness is good for all persons.
|
This is a notoriously bad argument. If this straightforward reading accurately
|
refl ects the argument Mill means to give, then he has committed a
|
number of elementary logical mistakes. In the fi rst part of his argument,
|
Mill states that because people desire happiness, it follows that happiness
|
must be β desirable. β However, β desirable β has two possible meanings, and
|
Subsets and Splits
No community queries yet
The top public SQL queries from the community will appear here once available.