text
stringlengths 0
1.71k
|
---|
or inference or logical construction or conceptual analysis, or any combination
|
of these, will provide a satisfactory answer; β a special sort of intuition β
|
is a lame answer, but it is the one to which the clear - headed objectivist is
|
compelled to resort. ( Ethics , 38)
|
P1. If ordinary language, commonsense morality, and philosophical theories
|
indicate belief in objective moral facts, then there is a presumptive belief
|
that objective moral facts exist.
|
P2. Ordinary language, commonsense morality, and philosophical theories
|
indicate belief that objective moral facts exist.
|
C1. There is a presumptive belief that objective moral facts exist ( modus
|
ponens , P1, P2).
|
P3. There is moral relativity among different societies and historical eras.
|
P4. Moral relativity is explained by either but not both of explanations (i)
|
or (ii):
|
(i) People participate in different ways of life that lead them to believe
|
that distinct moral rules are correct.
|
(ii) People apply objective moral principles to different circumstances.
|
P5. Explanation (i) is a better explanation of moral relativity than explanation
|
(ii).
|
236 Robert L. Muhlnickel
|
P6. If (i) explains moral relativity better than (ii), then the belief that objective
|
moral facts exist is not justifi ed.
|
C2. The belief that objective moral facts exist is not justifi ed ( modus
|
ponens , P5, P6).
|
P7. If there are objective moral values, then they are specifi cally moral entities
|
or relations and we know of their existence by a specifi cally moral
|
cognitive ability.
|
P8. There are no specifi cally moral entities or relations, and we have no
|
specifi cally moral cognitive ability.
|
C3. There are no objective moral values ( modus tollens , P7, P8).
|
C4. There are no objective moral values and the belief that objective
|
moral facts exist is not justifi ed (conjunction, C3, C2).
|
P9. If there are no objective values and the belief that objective moral facts
|
exist is not justifi ed, then the presumptive belief that objective moral
|
facts exist is in error.
|
C5. The presumptive belief that objective moral facts exist is in error
|
( modus ponens , C4, P9).
|
P6 * . If (i) explains moral disagreement better than (ii), then disbelief that
|
objective moral facts exist is better justifi ed than belief that moral facts
|
exist.
|
C2 * . Disbelief that objective moral facts exist is better justifi ed than
|
belief that moral facts exist ( modus ponens , C2, P5).
|
60
|
Moore β s Open Question
|
Argument
|
Bruno Verbeek
|
Moore , George E. Principia Ethica . Cambridge, UK : Cambridge University
|
Press , 1903 .
|
Frankena , W. K. β The Naturalistic Fallacy . β Mind 48 , 192 ( 1939 ): 464 β 77 .
|
Miller , Alexander . An Introduction to Contemporary Metaethics . Cambridge,
|
UK : Polity Press , 2003 .
|
The Open Question Argument was fi rst formulated by G. E. Moore in his
|
Principia Ethica (1903). It marks the beginning of a branch of ethical theory
|
now referred to as metaethics. One of the central problems in metaethics
|
β or indeed the central problem for this sub - discipline β is an analysis of
|
the central concepts and terms in ethics, such as β ought β and β good β . Moore
|
argued that the property of goodness is an undefi nable property. The
|
reason, according to Moore, is that goodness is a simple, unanalyzable
|
property. So - called β real defi nitions β of β good β , which attempt to defi ne
|
β good β in terms of a kind with specifi c characteristics, will fail. Anyone who
|
claims to give a defi nition of β goodness β is attributing goodness to something
|
rather than identifying what goodness is. Moral naturalists β that is, those
|
philosophers who believe that moral properties exist and can be studied by
|
the sciences β are particularly guilty of this fallacy: hence the name β naturalistic
|
fallacy. β As a result, the argument is typically invoked to reject
|
moral naturalism. However, Moore was quick to point out that theists who
|
Just the Arguments: 100 of the Most Important Arguments in Western Philosophy,
|
First Edition. Edited by Michael Bruce and Steven Barbone.
|
Β© 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. Published 2011 by Blackwell Publishing Ltd.
|
238 Bruno Verbeek
|
claim that good is what God commands are prone to the same fallacy. (Note
|
that a common misunderstanding is to think that the naturalistic fallacy is
|
the invalid inference of an β ought β statement from factual [ β is β ] premises.)
|
The test that Moore proposed to determine whether an attempt at defi ning
|
β good β is correct and not an attribution in disguise is the so - called β Open
|
Question Argument. β The basic idea is that a correct defi nition of a term
|
cannot be rephrased as a question without betraying conceptual incompetence.
|
For example, the defi nition of a β bachelor β is β unmarried man of the
|
marriageable age. β If I rephrase this defi nition as an open question ( β Is a
|
bachelor an unmarried man of the marriageable age? β ), it shows that I don β t
|
know what a bachelor is (or β man β or β married β , etc.). However, suppose
|
somebody offers the following defi nition of β good β : β the property we refer
|
to as β good β is the property of being pleasurable, β or β good is pleasurable β
|
for short. If you rephrase this as an open question: β Is good pleasurable? β
|
this does not indicate that I don β t know what β good β or what β pleasurable β
|
is. I am asking a meaningful question. This demonstrates, according to
|
Moore, that the proposed defi nition is (at best) in fact an attribution of
|
goodness to all pleasurable things.
|
My point is that β good β is a simple notion, just as β yellow β is a simple
|
notion; that, just as you cannot, by any manner of means, explain to any one
|
who does not already know it, what yellow is, so you cannot explain what
|
good is. Defi nitions of the kind that I was asking for, defi nitions which
|
describe the real nature of the object or notion denoted by a word, and
|
which do not merely tell us what the word is used to mean, are only possible
|
when the object or notion in question is something complex. (Moore, 7)
|
When a man confuses two natural objects with one another, defi ning the
|
one by the other, if for instance, he confuses himself, who is one natural
|
object, with β pleased β or with β pleasure β which are others, then there is no
|
reason to call the fallacy naturalistic. But if he confuses β good, β which is not
|
in the same sense a natural object, with any natural object whatever, then
|
Subsets and Splits
No community queries yet
The top public SQL queries from the community will appear here once available.