id
int64 59
4.83M
| tag
stringlengths 1
12.4k
| cite
stringlengths 1
4.52k
| fullcite
stringlengths 1
105k
| summary
stringlengths 1
62.2k
| spoken
stringlengths 1
35k
| fulltext
stringlengths 4
388k
| textLength
int64 4
388k
| markup
stringlengths 35
397k
| pocket
stringlengths 1
8k
⌀ | hat
stringlengths 1
7.13k
⌀ | block
stringlengths 1
16.2k
⌀ | bucketId
int64 1
1.95M
| duplicateCount
int64 1
5.63k
| fileId
int64 1
172k
| filePath
stringlengths 49
182
| roundId
float64 565k
998k
⌀ | side
stringclasses 2
values | tournament
stringlengths 1
95
⌀ | round
stringclasses 56
values | opponent
stringlengths 1
65
⌀ | judge
stringlengths 1
128
⌀ | report
stringlengths 1
53.7k
⌀ | opensourcePath
stringlengths 37
170
⌀ | caselistUpdatedAt
stringlengths 19
19
⌀ | teamId
float64 48.4k
86.5k
⌀ | teamName
stringlengths 2
8
⌀ | teamDisplayName
stringlengths 6
45
⌀ | notes
stringclasses 631
values | debater1First
stringclasses 269
values | debater1Last
stringclasses 306
values | debater2First
stringclasses 224
values | debater2Last
stringclasses 259
values | schoolId
float64 18.7k
28.2k
⌀ | schoolName
stringlengths 3
35
⌀ | schoolDisplayName
stringlengths 3
40
⌀ | state
stringclasses 49
values | chapterId
float64 23
114k
⌀ | caselistId
float64 1k
2.01k
⌀ | caselistName
stringclasses 40
values | caselistDisplayName
stringclasses 39
values | year
float64 2.01k
2.02k
⌀ | event
stringclasses 3
values | level
stringclasses 2
values | teamSize
float64 1
2
⌀ |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
4,482,245 | Emerging tech doesn’t cause war | Talmadge 19 | Talmadge 19
(Caitlin Talmadge is Associate Professor of Security Studies in the School of Foreign at Georgetown University, as well as Senior Non-Resident Fellow in Foreign Policy at the Brookings Institution. "Emerging technology and intra-war escalation risks: Evidence from the Cold War, implications for today." https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/full/10.1080/01402390.2019.1631811) | the relationship between emerging tech and escalation may not be as straightforward The debate tends to portray them as a powerful independent variable an exogenous factor that is both necessary and sufficient to cause conflict escalation This paper argues emerging tech are more likely to function as intervening variables they may be necessary in some cases, but they alone are not sufficient and sometimes not necessary The strongest drivers of escalation will actually lie elsewhere, in the realms of politics and strategy concern is warranted, but determinism is not overemphasis on the dangers ignores the critical role of political and strategic choices in shaping the impact of tech and also could lead to a misplaced faith in arms control or other means of trying to stuff the technological genie back in the bottle | relationship between emerging tech and escalation may not be straightforward debate portray them as an exogenous factor necessary and sufficient to cause conflict This argues emerging tech are intervening variables they are not sufficient, and sometimes not necessary strongest drivers of escalation lie elsewhere overemphasis on dangers ignores strategic choices and lead to a misplaced faith in arms control | Yet the future relationship between emerging technologies and escalation may not be as straightforward as these statements imply. The debate about emerging technologies tends to portray them as a powerful independent variable – an exogenous factor that is both necessary and sufficient to cause conflict escalation. This paper argues instead that emerging technologies are more likely to function as intervening variables; they may be necessary for escalation to happen in some cases, but they alone are not sufficient, and sometimes they will not even be necessary. The strongest drivers of escalation will actually lie elsewhere, in the realms of politics and strategy. As a result, concern about new technologies is warranted, but determinism is not. An overemphasis on the dangers of technology alone ignores the critical role of political and strategic choices in shaping the impact of technology, and also could lead to a misplaced faith in arms control or other means of trying to stuff the technological genie back in the bottle.5 | 1,038 | <h4>Emerging tech doesn’t <u>cause war</u> </h4><p><strong>Talmadge 19</strong> </p><p>(Caitlin Talmadge is Associate Professor of Security Studies in the School of Foreign at Georgetown University, as well as Senior Non-Resident Fellow in Foreign Policy at the Brookings Institution. "Emerging technology and intra-war escalation risks: Evidence from the Cold War, implications for today." https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/full/10.1080/01402390.2019.1631811)</p><p>Yet <u>the</u> future <u><mark>relationship between</u> <u><strong>emerging tech</u></strong></mark>nologies <u><mark>and escalation may not be</mark> as <strong><mark>straightforward</u></strong></mark> as these statements imply. <u>The <mark>debate</u></mark> about emerging technologies <u>tends to <mark>portray them as</mark> a powerful independent variable</u> – <u><mark>an</u> <u><strong>exogenous</mark> <mark>factor</u></strong></mark> <u>that is both <strong><mark>necessary</strong> and <strong>sufficient</strong> to cause conflict</mark> <strong>escalation</u></strong>. <u><mark>This</mark> paper <mark>argues</u></mark> instead that <u><mark>emerging tech</u></mark>nologies <u><mark>are</mark> more likely to function as <mark>intervening variables</u></mark>; <u>they may be necessary</u> for escalation to happen <u>in some cases, but <mark>they</mark> alone <mark>are not <strong>sufficient</u></strong>, <u>and</u></mark> <u><mark>sometimes</u></mark> they will <u><mark>not</u></mark> even be <u><strong><mark>necessary</u></strong></mark>. <u>The <mark>strongest <strong>drivers of escalation</strong></mark> will actually <mark>lie elsewhere</mark>, in the realms of <strong>politics</strong> and <strong>strategy</u></strong>. As a result, <u>concern</u> about new technologies <u>is warranted, but <strong>determinism is not</u></strong>. An <u><mark>overemphasis on</mark> the <mark>dangers</u></mark> of technology alone <u><mark>ignores</mark> the critical role of political and <mark>strategic choices</mark> in shaping the impact of tech</u>nology, <u><mark>and</mark> also could <mark>lead to a <strong>misplaced faith in arms control</strong></mark> or other means of trying to stuff the technological genie <strong>back in the bottle</u></strong>.5</p> | 1NC | Procurement | 1NC---No Emerging Tech War | 320,818 | 118 | 146,942 | ./documents/ndtceda22/Liberty/BeHo/Liberty-BeHo-Neg-Crowe-Warken-Debates-at-USNA-Round-6.docx | 964,972 | N | Crowe Warken Debates at USNA | 6 | Minnesota PP | O'Gorman | 1AC - AWS
1NC - DA rights creep, K cap, CP executive
2NR - K | ndtceda22/Liberty/BeHo/Liberty-BeHo-Neg-Crowe-Warken-Debates-at-USNA-Round-6.docx | 2023-01-16 14:18:32 | 82,663 | BeHo | Liberty BeHo | null | Ca..... | Be..... | Ka..... | Ho..... | 26,918 | Liberty | Liberty | null | null | 2,001 | ndtceda22 | NDT/CEDA College 2022-23 | 2,022 | cx | college | 2 |
1,047,539 | Extinction---stressors cascade to nuke war. | Cribb 19 | Julian Cribb 19. Author, Journalist, Editor and Science Communicator, Principal of Julian Cribb & Associates who Provide Specialist Consultancy in the Communication of Science, Agriculture, Food, Mining, Energy and the Environment, More Than Thirty Awards for Journalism. 10/03/2019. “6 - Food as an Existential Risk.” Food or War, 1st ed., Cambridge University Press. DOI.org (Crossref), doi:10.1017/9781108690126. | Detonating just 50 nuclear weapons would suffice to end civilisation in a nuclear winter, causing worldwide famine and economic collapse affecting even distant nations Eight nations have the power to terminate civilisation and two have the power to extinguish the human species
the danger of nuclear conflict in fact increased in the first two decades of the twenty-first century due to modernisation new tech such as robot delivery systems, hypersonic missiles, a i and e w and continuing leakage of nuclear materials and knowhow
if humanity is to be wiped out, it will most likely be as a result of an atomic conflict
in the twenty-first century with world resources of food, land and water under growing stress, nothing can be ruled out chemical weapons have frequently been deployed in the Syrian civil war, which had drought ag failure and hunger among its early drivers nuclear conflict remains a distinct possibility in South Asia and the Middle East as these regions are stressed in terms of food, land and water, and their nuclear firepower is multiplying
panicking regimes in Russia, the USA or even France would deploy atomic weapons in an attempt to quell invasion by desperate refugees, fleeing famine and climate chaos
nuclear war cannot be excluded as a political consequence of Food insecurity
that, as the hands of the ‘Doomsday Clock’ so eloquently admonish, is the most likely scenario for the premature termination of the human species | 50 nuc s end civilisation in nuclear winter
the danger increased
with food under stress, nothing can be ruled out chem weapons in Syria had hunger among its drivers nuclear conflict remains possibil in South Asia and Mid East regions are stressed in food and firepower is multiplying
panicking regimes in Russia, US or France would deploy atomic weapons to quell refugees, fleeing famine
Food insecurity
is the most likely scenario for termination of the species | Weapons of Mass Destruction
Detonating just 50–100 out of the global arsenal of nearly 15,000 nuclear weapons would suffice to end civilisation in a nuclear winter, causing worldwide famine and economic collapse affecting even distant nations, as we saw in the previous chapter in the section dealing with South Asia. Eight nations now have the power to terminate civilisation should they desire to do so – and two have the power to extinguish the human species. According to the nuclear monitoring group Ploughshares, this arsenal is distributed as follows:
– Russia, 6600 warheads (2500 classified as ‘retired’)
– America, 6450 warheads (2550 classified as ‘retired’)
– France, 300 warheads
– China, 270 warheads
– UK, 215 warheads
– Pakistan, 130 warheads
– India, 120 warheads
– Israel, 80 warheads
– North Korea, 15–20 warheads.11
Although actual numbers of warheads have continued to fall from its peak of 70,000 weapons in the mid 1980s, scientists argue the danger of nuclear conflict in fact increased in the first two decades of the twenty-first century. This was due to the modernisation of existing stockpiles, the adoption of dangerous new technologies such as robot delivery systems, hypersonic missiles, artificial intelligence and electronic warfare, and the continuing leakage of nuclear materials and knowhow to nonnuclear nations and potential terrorist organisations.
In early 2018 the hands of the ‘Doomsday Clock’, maintained by the Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists, were re-set at two minutes to midnight, the highest risk to humanity that it has ever shown since the clock was introduced in 1953. This was due not only to the state of the world’s nuclear arsenal, but also to irresponsible language by world leaders, the growing use of social media to destabilise rival regimes, and to the rising threat of uncontrolled climate change (see below).12
In an historic moment on 17 July 2017, 122 nations voted in the UN for the first time ever in favour of a treaty banning all nuclear weapons. This called for comprehensive prohibition of “a full range of nuclear-weapon-related activities, such as undertaking to develop, test, produce, manufacture, acquire, possess or stockpile nuclear weapons or other nuclear explosive devices, as well as the use or threat of use of these weapons.”13 However, 71 other countries – including all the nuclear states – either opposed the ban, abstained or declined to vote. The Treaty vote was nonetheless interpreted by some as a promising first step towards abolishing the nuclear nightmare that hangs over the entire human species.
In contrast, 192 countries had signed up to the Chemical Weapons Convention to ban the use of chemical weapons, and 180 to the Biological Weapons Convention. As of 2018, 96 per cent of previous world stocks of chemical weapons had been destroyed – but their continued use in the Syrian conflict and in alleged assassination attempts by Russia indicated the world remains at risk.14
As things stand, the only entities that can afford to own nuclear weapons are nations – and if humanity is to be wiped out, it will most likely be as a result of an atomic conflict between nations. It follows from this that, if the world is to be made safe from such a fate it will need to get rid of nations as a structure of human self-organisation and replace them with wiser, less aggressive forms of self-governance. After all, the nation state really only began in the early nineteenth century and is by no means a permanent feature of self-governance, any more than monarchies, feudal systems or priest states. Although many people still tend to assume it is. Between them, nations have butchered more than 200 million people in the past 150 years and it is increasingly clear the world would be a far safer, more peaceable place without either nations or nationalism. The question is what to replace them with.
Although there may at first glance appear to be no close linkage between weapons of mass destruction and food, in the twenty-first century with world resources of food, land and water under growing stress, nothing can be ruled out. Indeed, chemical weapons have frequently been deployed in the Syrian civil war, which had drought, agricultural failure and hunger among its early drivers. And nuclear conflict remains a distinct possibility in South Asia and the Middle East, especially, as these regions are already stressed in terms of food, land and water, and their nuclear firepower or access to nuclear materials is multiplying.
It remains an open question whether panicking regimes in Russia, the USA or even France would be ruthless enough to deploy atomic weapons in an attempt to quell invasion by tens of millions of desperate refugees, fleeing famine and climate chaos in their own homelands – but the possibility ought not to be ignored.
That nuclear war is at least a possible outcome of food and climate crises was first flagged in the report The Age of Consequences by Kurt Campbell and the US-based Centre for Strategic and International Studies, which stated ‘it is clear that even nuclear war cannot be excluded as a political consequence of global warming’. 15 Food insecurity is therefore a driver in the preconditions for the use of nuclear weapons, whether limited or unlimited.
A global famine is a likely outcome of limited use of nuclear weapons by any country or countries – and would be unavoidable in the event of an unlimited nuclear war between America and Russia, making it unwinnable for either. And that, as the mute hands of the ‘Doomsday Clock’ so eloquently admonish, is also the most likely scenario for the premature termination of the human species.
Such a grim scenario can be alleviated by two measures: the voluntary banning by the whole of humanity of nuclear weapons, their technology, materials and stocks – and by a global effort to secure food against future insecurity by diverting the funds now wasted on nuclear armaments into building the sustainable food and water systems of the future (see Chapters 8 and 9). | 6,057 | <h4><u>Extinction</u>---stressors <u>cascade</u> to <u>nuke war</u>.</h4><p>Julian <strong>Cribb 19</strong>. Author, Journalist, Editor and Science Communicator, Principal of Julian Cribb & Associates who Provide Specialist Consultancy in the Communication of Science, Agriculture, Food, Mining, Energy and the Environment, More Than Thirty Awards for Journalism. 10/03/2019. “6 - Food as an Existential Risk.” Food or War, 1st ed., Cambridge University Press. DOI.org (Crossref), doi:10.1017/9781108690126.</p><p>Weapons of Mass Destruction</p><p><u>Detonating just</u> <u><strong><mark>50</u></strong></mark>–100 out of the global arsenal of nearly 15,000 <u><strong><mark>nuc</strong></mark>lear weapon<strong><mark>s</u></strong></mark> <u>would</u> <u><strong>suffice to <mark>end civilisation</strong> in</mark> a <strong><mark>nuclear winter</strong></mark>, causing</u> <u><strong>worldwide famine</u></strong> <u>and</u> <u><strong>economic collapse</u></strong> <u>affecting even</u> <u><strong>distant</u></strong> <u>nations</u>, as we saw in the previous chapter in the section dealing with South Asia. <u><strong>Eight nations</u></strong> now <u>have the power to</u> <u><strong>terminate civilisation</u></strong> should they desire to do so – <u>and</u> <u><strong>two</u></strong> <u>have the power to</u> <u><strong>extinguish the human species</u></strong>. According to the nuclear monitoring group Ploughshares, this arsenal is distributed as follows:</p><p>– Russia, 6600 warheads (2500 classified as ‘retired’)</p><p>– America, 6450 warheads (2550 classified as ‘retired’)</p><p>– France, 300 warheads</p><p>– China, 270 warheads</p><p>– UK, 215 warheads</p><p>– Pakistan, 130 warheads</p><p>– India, 120 warheads</p><p>– Israel, 80 warheads</p><p>– North Korea, 15–20 warheads.11</p><p>Although actual numbers of warheads have continued to fall from its peak of 70,000 weapons in the mid 1980s, scientists argue <u><mark>the</u> <u><strong>danger</u></strong></mark> <u>of nuclear conflict in fact</u> <u><strong><mark>increased</u></strong></mark> <u>in the first two decades of the twenty-first century</u>. This was <u>due to</u> the <u><strong>modernisation</u></strong> of existing stockpiles, the adoption of dangerous <u>new</u> <u><strong>tech</u></strong>nologies <u>such as robot delivery systems, hypersonic missiles,</u> <u><strong>a</u></strong>rtificial <u><strong>i</u></strong>ntelligence <u>and</u> <u><strong>e</u></strong>lectronic <u><strong>w</u></strong>arfare, <u>and</u> the <u>continuing <strong>leakage</u></strong> <u>of nuclear</u> <u><strong>materials</u></strong> <u>and</u> <u><strong>knowhow</u></strong> to nonnuclear nations and potential terrorist organisations.</p><p>In early 2018 the hands of the ‘Doomsday Clock’, maintained by the Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists, were re-set at two minutes to midnight, the highest risk to humanity that it has ever shown since the clock was introduced in 1953. This was due not only to the state of the world’s nuclear arsenal, but also to irresponsible language by world leaders, the growing use of social media to destabilise rival regimes, and to the rising threat of uncontrolled climate change (see below).12</p><p>In an historic moment on 17 July 2017, 122 nations voted in the UN for the first time ever in favour of a treaty banning all nuclear weapons. This called for comprehensive prohibition of “a full range of nuclear-weapon-related activities, such as undertaking to develop, test, produce, manufacture, acquire, possess or stockpile nuclear weapons or other nuclear explosive devices, as well as the use or threat of use of these weapons.”13 However, 71 other countries – including all the nuclear states – either opposed the ban, abstained or declined to vote. The Treaty vote was nonetheless interpreted by some as a promising first step towards abolishing the nuclear nightmare that hangs over the entire human species.</p><p>In contrast, 192 countries had signed up to the Chemical Weapons Convention to ban the use of chemical weapons, and 180 to the Biological Weapons Convention. As of 2018, 96 per cent of previous world stocks of chemical weapons had been destroyed – but their continued use in the Syrian conflict and in alleged assassination attempts by Russia indicated the world remains at risk.14</p><p>As things stand, the only entities that can afford to own nuclear weapons are nations – and <u><strong>if humanity is to be wiped out</strong>, it</u> <u>will</u> <u><strong>most likely</u></strong> <u>be as a <strong>result of an atomic conflict</u></strong> between nations. It follows from this that, if the world is to be made safe from such a fate it will need to get rid of nations as a structure of human self-organisation and replace them with wiser, less aggressive forms of self-governance. After all, the nation state really only began in the early nineteenth century and is by no means a permanent feature of self-governance, any more than monarchies, feudal systems or priest states. Although many people still tend to assume it is. Between them, nations have butchered more than 200 million people in the past 150 years and it is increasingly clear the world would be a far safer, more peaceable place without either nations or nationalism. The question is what to replace them with.</p><p>Although there may at first glance appear to be no close linkage between weapons of mass destruction and food, <u>in the twenty-first century <mark>with</mark> world resources of <strong><mark>food</strong></mark>, land and water <mark>under</mark> growing <strong><mark>stress, nothing can be ruled out</u></strong></mark>. Indeed, <u><strong><mark>chem</mark>ical <mark>weapons</strong></mark> have</u> <u><strong>frequently</u></strong> <u>been deployed <mark>in</mark> the <strong><mark>Syria</strong></mark>n civil war, which <mark>had</mark> <strong>drought</u></strong>, <u><strong>ag</u></strong>ricultural <u><strong>failure</u></strong> <u>and</u> <u><strong><mark>hunger</u></strong> <u>among its</u></mark> <u><strong>early <mark>drivers</u></strong></mark>. And <u><strong><mark>nuclear conflict</u></strong> <u>remains</mark> a</u> <u><strong>distinct <mark>possibil</strong></mark>ity <mark>in <strong>South Asia</u></strong> <u>and</mark> the</u> <u><strong><mark>Mid</strong></mark>dle <strong><mark>East</u></strong></mark>, especially, <u>as these <mark>regions are</u></mark> already <u><strong><mark>stressed</u></strong> <u>in</mark> terms of <mark>food</mark>, land and water, <mark>and</mark> their</u> <u><strong>nuclear <mark>firepower</u></strong></mark> or access to nuclear materials <u><mark>is</u> <u><strong>multiplying</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>It remains an open question whether <u><strong><mark>panicking regimes</u></strong> <u>in</u> <u><strong>Russia,</mark> the <mark>US</strong></mark>A</u> <u><strong><mark>or</strong></mark> even <strong><mark>France</u></strong> <u>would</u></mark> be ruthless enough to <u><strong><mark>deploy atomic weapons</u></strong></mark> <u>in an attempt <mark>to</u> <u><strong>quell</mark> invasion</u></strong> <u>by</u> tens of millions of <u><strong>desperate <mark>refugees</strong>, fleeing</u> <u><strong>famine</mark> and climate chaos</u></strong> in their own homelands – but the possibility ought not to be ignored.</p><p>That nuclear war is at least a possible outcome of food and climate crises was first flagged in the report The Age of Consequences by Kurt Campbell and the US-based Centre for Strategic and International Studies, which stated ‘it is clear that even <u>nuclear war</u> <u><strong>cannot be excluded</u></strong> <u>as a</u> <u><strong>political consequence</u></strong> <u>of</u> global warming’. 15 <u><strong><mark>Food insecurity</u></strong></mark> is therefore a driver in the preconditions for the use of nuclear weapons, whether limited or unlimited.</p><p>A global famine is a likely outcome of limited use of nuclear weapons by any country or countries – and would be unavoidable in the event of an unlimited nuclear war between America and Russia, making it unwinnable for either. And <u><strong>that</strong>, as the</u> mute <u>hands of the ‘Doomsday Clock’ so eloquently admonish, <mark>is</u></mark> also <u><mark>the</u> <u><strong>most likely scenario</u></strong> <u>for</mark> the</u> <u><strong>premature <mark>termination of the</mark> human <mark>species</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>Such a grim scenario can be alleviated by two measures: the voluntary banning by the whole of humanity of nuclear weapons, their technology, materials and stocks – and by a global effort to secure food against future insecurity by diverting the funds now wasted on nuclear armaments into building the sustainable food and water systems of the future (see Chapters 8 and 9).</p> | 1AC | 1AC---PTD | 1AC---Water Resources ADV | 3,772 | 1,142 | 25,323 | ./documents/hspolicy21/Alpharetta/NaTh/Alpharetta-Nayak-Thatiparthi-Aff-UK-Round1.docx | 743,322 | A | UK | 1 | Hawken MT | Jake Melton | 1AC - NEW Public Trust Doctrine
2NR - Afropessimism K Schlag K | hspolicy21/Alpharetta/NaTh/Alpharetta-Nayak-Thatiparthi-Aff-UK-Round1.docx | null | 63,312 | NaTh | Alpharetta NaTh | null | An..... | Na..... | An..... | Th..... | 21,871 | Alpharetta | Alpharetta | GA | null | 1,020 | hspolicy21 | HS Policy 2021-22 | 2,021 | cx | hs | 2 |
1,598,502 | Trade solves great power competition – regionalism causes militarized crises. | Lake 18 | Lake 18. [(David Lake is a Professor of Social Sciences and Distinguished Professor of Political Science at the University of California, San Diego. "Economic Openness and Great Power Competition: Lessons for China and the United States,” April 30, 2018. https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=3171196/] TDI | historically, great power competition has been driven primarily by exclusion or fears of exclusion from each power’s international economic zone, other great powers are compelled to develop or expand their own exclusive economic zones. The “race” for economic privilege can quickly divide the world up into economic blocs. great powers need not actually exclude one another from their zones; the fear of exclusion alone is enough to ignite the process of division. The race for privilege then draws great powers into over-expanding into unprofitable regions and, more important, militarized competition. Economic and military competition are thus linked, with the former usually driving the latter. The most significant military crises have, been over where to draw the boundaries between economic zones and subsequent challenges to those boundaries Economic closure and fear of closure have been consistent sources of great power conflict If so, great power competition could break out in the twenty-first century not because of bipolarity or any inevitable tendency toward conflict, but because neither great power can control its own protectionist forces . The British-U.S. case, again, suggests that exclusion and competition are not inevitable, but the current danger of economic closure is real and increasing. Protectionism can sour great power relations, but it is the desire for exclusive economic zones that drives great power competition and, given the possibility of coercion, influences grand strategy | great power competition has been driven primarily by exclusion The “race” for econ privilege divide the world into blocs. the fear of exclusion ignite division. privilege draws great powers and, militarized competition Economic closure have been sources of great power conflict great power competition break out because neither great power can control protectionist forces exclusion are not inevitable, but economic closure is increasing. | I develop two central arguments. First, historically, great power competition has been driven primarily by exclusion or fears of exclusion from each power’s international economic zone, including its domestic market. Great powers in the past have often used their international influence to build zones in which subordinate polities – whether these be colonies or simply states within a sphere of influence – are integrated into their economies. These economic zones, in turn, are typically biased in favor of the great power’s firms and investors, with the effect of excluding (in whole or part) the economic agents of other great powers. These other great powers, in response, are then compelled to develop or expand their own exclusive economic zones. The “race” for economic privilege can quickly divide the world up into economic blocs. Like the security dilemma, great powers need not actually exclude one another from their zones; the fear of exclusion alone is enough to ignite the process of division. The race for privilege then draws great powers into over-expanding into unprofitable regions and, more important, militarized competition. Economic and military competition are thus linked, with the former usually driving the latter. The most significant military crises have, historically, been over where to draw the boundaries between economic zones and subsequent challenges to those boundaries. Economic closure and fear of closure have been consistent sources of great power conflict in the past – and possibly will be in the future. The major exception to this trend was the peaceful transfer of dominance in Latin America from Britain to the United States in the late nineteenth century. This suggests that economic closure and great power competition is not inevitable, but a choice of the great powers themselves. Second, this international competition is driven, in turn, by domestic, rent-seeking groups and their economic interests. In all countries, scarce factors of production, import competing sectors, and domestically-oriented firms have concentrated and intense preferences for market restricting policies, including tariffs and the formation of exclusive economic zones. Consumers and free trade-oriented groups have diffuse preferences for market enhancing policies, and thus tend to lose at the ballot box and in the making of national policy. This inequality in preference intensity does not mean protectionists always win; after 1934, the United States insulated itself by shifting authority to the executive and negotiating reductions through broad, multi-product international agreements.8 Yet, as the recent return to economic nationalism of the Trump administration suggests, protectionism often wins out. Rent-seeking is a central tendency, not an inevitable success. Contemporary great power relations are at a critical juncture. As China’s influence expands, the role of special economic interests in China is especially worrisome. In pursuit of stability, political support, or private gains, the government will always be tempted to create economic zones that favor its nationals. In this way, China will be no different than the majority of great powers before it. But, given the expansive role of the state in the Chinese economy, especially its backing of outward foreign investments by its state-owned enterprises (SOEs), and the close ties between business elites and its authoritarian political leaders, however, it will be even harder for China to resist biasing any future economic zone to benefit its own firms. Although China has gained greatly from economic openness, its domestic political system will be prone to rent-seeking demands by important constituents in areas of future influence. Critically, the United States is also moving toward economic closure with the election of President Trump on a platform of economic nationalism. Demands for protection against Chinese goods have been growing over time.9 The “China shock” that followed Beijing’s joining the World Trade Organization was a huge disruption to the international division of labor, U.S. comparative advantage, and especially U.S. industry.10 The Trans-Pacific Partnership, though now defunct, was “marketed” by President Barak Obama as a means of “containing” China, both economically and militarily, but was opposed by virtually all of the candidates in the 2016 presidential election for its trade-enhancing potential. President Trump has already signaled a much more hostile and protectionist stance toward China – as well as calling for the repeal of NAFTA and even questioning the utility of the European Union. Not only has he imposed tariffs on washing machines, solar panels, steel and aluminum, dangerously declaring the latter two issues of national security, he is making exceptions on these tariffs for friends and allies. 11 Implicitly targeting China, these protectionist moves by the administration risk creating preferential trading blocs not seen since the 1930s. He has also now proposed punitive tariffs on over $60 billions of imports from China into the United States.12 Acknowledging his inconsistencies on many policy issues, Trump’s economic nationalism has remained the core of his political agenda. The threat to the liberal international economy is not only that China might seek an economic bloc in the future, but that the United States itself is turning more exclusionary. For each great power to fear that the other might seek to exclude it from its economic zone is not unreasonable. If so, great power competition could break out in the twenty-first century not because of bipolarity or any inevitable tendency toward conflict, but because neither great power can control its own protectionist forces nor signal to the other that it would not exclude it from its economic zone. The British-U.S. case, again, suggests that exclusion and competition are not inevitable, but the current danger of economic closure is real and increasing. This article is synthetic in its theory and merely suggestive in its use of historical evidence. The theory aims to integrate current work on political economy and national security, not to develop a completely original take on this relationship. In turn, rather than testing the theory in any rigorous sense or delving into particular cases to show the theoretical mechanisms at work, so to speak, it surveys selected historical episodes to illustrate central tendencies. It is the recurring pattern across multiple cases that suggests why we should worry today. The remainder of this essay is divided in three primary sections. Section I briefly outlines the analytics of economic openness and great power competition. Section II focuses on historical instances of great power competition, highlighting the role of economic openness as a central cleavage in international politics. Section III examines contemporary policies in and between China and the United States. The conclusion suggests ways that the potential for conflict may be mitigated. The Open Economy Politics of Great Power Competition All states have a tendency towards protectionism at home and exclusive economic zones abroad. A tendency, though, is not an inevitability. The pursuit of protection and economic zones by domestic interests is conditioned by the political coalition in power at any given time and institutions that aggregate and bias the articulation of social groups. 13 The tendency is also influenced, however, by the actions of other countries. Protectionism can sour great power relations, but it is the desire for exclusive economic zones that drives great power competition and, given the possibility of coercion, influences grand strategy. Thus, the theory sketched here integrates insights from international political economy (see below), the literature on domestic politics and grand strategy,14 and systemic theories of international relations.15 | 7,938 | <h4>Trade solves great power competition – regionalism causes militarized crises.</h4><p><strong>Lake 18</strong>. [(David Lake is a Professor of Social Sciences and Distinguished Professor of Political Science at the University of California, San Diego. "Economic Openness and Great Power Competition: Lessons for China and the United States,” April 30, 2018. https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=3171196/] TDI</p><p>I develop two central arguments. First, <u><strong>historically, <mark>great power competition</mark> <mark>has</mark> <mark>been driven primarily by</mark> <mark>exclusion</mark> or fears of exclusion from each power’s international economic zone,</u></strong> including its domestic market. Great powers in the past have often used their international influence to build zones in which subordinate polities – whether these be colonies or simply states within a sphere of influence – are integrated into their economies. These economic zones, in turn, are typically biased in favor of the great power’s firms and investors, with the effect of excluding (in whole or part) the economic agents of other great powers. These <u>other great powers</u>, in response, <u>are</u> then <u>compelled to develop or expand their own exclusive economic zones.</u> <u><strong><mark>The “race” for econ</mark>omic <mark>privilege</mark> can quickly <mark>divide the world</mark> up <mark>into</mark> economic <mark>blocs.</mark> </u></strong>Like the security dilemma, <u>great powers need not actually exclude one another from their zones; <strong><mark>the fear of exclusion</mark> alone is enough to <mark>ignite</mark> the process of <mark>division.</mark> </strong>The race for <mark>privilege</mark> then <mark>draws great powers</mark> into over-expanding into unprofitable regions <mark>and,</mark> more important, <strong><mark>militarized competition</strong></mark>. <strong>Economic and military competition are thus linked, with the former usually driving the latter.</u></strong> <u>The most significant military crises have, </u>historically, <u>been over where to draw the boundaries between economic zones and subsequent challenges to those boundaries</u>. <u><strong><mark>Economic closure</mark> and fear of closure <mark>have been</mark> consistent <mark>sources of great power conflict</u></strong></mark> in the past – and possibly will be in the future. The major exception to this trend was the peaceful transfer of dominance in Latin America from Britain to the United States in the late nineteenth century. This suggests that economic closure and great power competition is not inevitable, but a choice of the great powers themselves. Second, this international competition is driven, in turn, by domestic, rent-seeking groups and their economic interests. In all countries, scarce factors of production, import competing sectors, and domestically-oriented firms have concentrated and intense preferences for market restricting policies, including tariffs and the formation of exclusive economic zones. Consumers and free trade-oriented groups have diffuse preferences for market enhancing policies, and thus tend to lose at the ballot box and in the making of national policy. This inequality in preference intensity does not mean protectionists always win; after 1934, the United States insulated itself by shifting authority to the executive and negotiating reductions through broad, multi-product international agreements.8 Yet, as the recent return to economic nationalism of the Trump administration suggests, protectionism often wins out. Rent-seeking is a central tendency, not an inevitable success. Contemporary great power relations are at a critical juncture. As China’s influence expands, the role of special economic interests in China is especially worrisome. In pursuit of stability, political support, or private gains, the government will always be tempted to create economic zones that favor its nationals. In this way, China will be no different than the majority of great powers before it. But, given the expansive role of the state in the Chinese economy, especially its backing of outward foreign investments by its state-owned enterprises (SOEs), and the close ties between business elites and its authoritarian political leaders, however, it will be even harder for China to resist biasing any future economic zone to benefit its own firms. Although China has gained greatly from economic openness, its domestic political system will be prone to rent-seeking demands by important constituents in areas of future influence. Critically, the United States is also moving toward economic closure with the election of President Trump on a platform of economic nationalism. Demands for protection against Chinese goods have been growing over time.9 The “China shock” that followed Beijing’s joining the World Trade Organization was a huge disruption to the international division of labor, U.S. comparative advantage, and especially U.S. industry.10 The Trans-Pacific Partnership, though now defunct, was “marketed” by President Barak Obama as a means of “containing” China, both economically and militarily, but was opposed by virtually all of the candidates in the 2016 presidential election for its trade-enhancing potential. President Trump has already signaled a much more hostile and protectionist stance toward China – as well as calling for the repeal of NAFTA and even questioning the utility of the European Union. Not only has he imposed tariffs on washing machines, solar panels, steel and aluminum, dangerously declaring the latter two issues of national security, he is making exceptions on these tariffs for friends and allies. 11 Implicitly targeting China, these protectionist moves by the administration risk creating preferential trading blocs not seen since the 1930s. He has also now proposed punitive tariffs on over $60 billions of imports from China into the United States.12 Acknowledging his inconsistencies on many policy issues, Trump’s economic nationalism has remained the core of his political agenda. The threat to the liberal international economy is not only that China might seek an economic bloc in the future, but that the United States itself is turning more exclusionary. For each great power to fear that the other might seek to exclude it from its economic zone is not unreasonable. <u>If so, <mark>great power competition</mark> could <mark>break out</mark> in the twenty-first century not because of bipolarity or any inevitable tendency toward conflict, <strong>but <mark>because neither great power can control </mark>its own <mark>protectionist forces</u></strong></mark> nor signal to the other that it would not exclude it from its economic zone<u><strong>. The British-U.S. case, again, suggests that <mark>exclusion</mark> and competition <mark>are not inevitable, but</mark> the current danger of <mark>economic closure is</mark> real and <mark>increasing.</mark> </u></strong>This article is synthetic in its theory and merely suggestive in its use of historical evidence. The theory aims to integrate current work on political economy and national security, not to develop a completely original take on this relationship. In turn, rather than testing the theory in any rigorous sense or delving into particular cases to show the theoretical mechanisms at work, so to speak, it surveys selected historical episodes to illustrate central tendencies. It is the recurring pattern across multiple cases that suggests why we should worry today. The remainder of this essay is divided in three primary sections. Section I briefly outlines the analytics of economic openness and great power competition. Section II focuses on historical instances of great power competition, highlighting the role of economic openness as a central cleavage in international politics. Section III examines contemporary policies in and between China and the United States. The conclusion suggests ways that the potential for conflict may be mitigated. The Open Economy Politics of Great Power Competition All states have a tendency towards protectionism at home and exclusive economic zones abroad. A tendency, though, is not an inevitability. The pursuit of protection and economic zones by domestic interests is conditioned by the political coalition in power at any given time and institutions that aggregate and bias the articulation of social groups. 13 The tendency is also influenced, however, by the actions of other countries. <u>Protectionism can sour great power relations, but it is the desire for exclusive economic zones that drives great power competition and, given the possibility of coercion, influences grand strategy</u>. Thus, the theory sketched here integrates insights from international political economy (see below), the literature on domestic politics and grand strategy,14 and systemic theories of international relations.15</p> | 1AC | 1AC | 1AC – WTO Credibility | 44,846 | 186 | 46,382 | ./documents/hsld21/StrathHaven/Ma/Strath%20Haven-Manaker-Aff-Greenhill-Round1.docx | 900,766 | A | Greenhill | 1 | Mercer Island KS | Jharick Shields | 1AC - COVID Vax
1NC - Innovation DA Supply Chain CP case
1AR - all
2NR - all
2AR - all | hsld21/StrathHaven/Ma/Strath%20Haven-Manaker-Aff-Greenhill-Round1.docx | null | 75,384 | AvMa | Strath Haven AvMa | null | Av..... | Ma..... | null | null | 25,179 | StrathHaven | Strath Haven | PA | null | 1,029 | hsld21 | HS LD 2021-22 | 2,021 | ld | hs | 1 |
994,370 | It turns terror, disease, and every other scenario. | Torres 16 | Torres 16 (Phil Torres; author, Affiliate Scholar @ Institute for Ethics and Emerging Technologies, founder of the X-Risks Institute, published articles for Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists, Salon, Journal of Future Studies, and the Journal of Evolution and Technology; 7-22-2016, "Op-ed: Climate Change Is the Most Urgent Existential Risk," FLI - Future of Life Institute, http://futureoflife.org/2016/07/22/climate-change-is-the-most-urgent-existential-risk/, accessed 8-9-2016) | according to the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change, the effects of climate change will be “severe and “irreversible a 2016 study published in Nature and authored by over twenty scientists the consequences of climate change “will extend longer than the entire history of human civilization thus far.” confirms we could be approaching a sudden, irreversible, catastrophic collapse of the global ecosystem it could result in “widespread social unrest, economic instability and loss of human life.” Given the potential for environmental degradation to elevate the likelihood of nuclear wars, nuclear terror , engineered pandemics, takeover it ought to take precedence over all other risk concerns in the near-term | according to the I P C C climate change will be “irreversible. result in widespread unrest instability nuclear terror pandemics takeover it ought to take precedence over all other concerns near-term | For example, according to the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change, the effects of climate change will be “severe,” “pervasive,” and “irreversible.” Or, as a 2016 study published in Nature and authored by over twenty scientists puts it, the consequences of climate change “will extend longer than the entire history of human civilization thus far.” Furthermore, a recent article in Science Advances confirms that humanity has already escorted the biosphere into the sixth mass extinction event in life’s 3.8 billion year history on Earth. Yet another study suggests that we could be approaching a sudden, irreversible, catastrophic collapse of the global ecosystem. If this were to occur, it could result in “widespread social unrest, economic instability and loss of human life.” Given the potential for environmental degradation to elevate the likelihood of nuclear wars, nuclear terrorism, engineered pandemics, a superintelligence takeover, and perhaps even an impact winter, it ought to take precedence over all other risk concerns — at least in the near-term. Let’s make sure we get our priorities straight. | 1,118 | <h4>It turns terror, disease, and <u>every other scenario</u>.</h4><p><u><strong>Torres 16</u></strong> (Phil Torres; author, Affiliate Scholar @ Institute for Ethics and Emerging Technologies, founder of the X-Risks Institute, published articles for Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists, Salon, Journal of Future Studies, and the Journal of Evolution and Technology; 7-22-2016, "Op-ed: Climate Change Is the Most Urgent Existential Risk," FLI - Future of Life Institute, http://futureoflife.org/2016/07/22/climate-change-is-the-most-urgent-existential-risk/, accessed 8-9-2016)</p><p>For example, <u><strong><mark>according to the</u></strong> <u><strong>I</mark>ntergovernmental <mark>P</mark>anel on <mark>C</mark>limate <mark>C</mark>hange, the effects of <mark>climate change will be</mark> “severe</u></strong>,” “pervasive,” <u><strong>and <mark>“irreversible</u></strong>.</mark>” Or, as <u><strong>a 2016 study published in Nature and authored by over twenty scientists </u></strong>puts it, <u><strong>the consequences of climate change “will extend longer than the entire history of human civilization thus far.” </u></strong>Furthermore, a recent article in Science Advances <u><strong>confirms</u></strong> that humanity has already escorted the biosphere into the sixth mass extinction event in life’s 3.8 billion year history on Earth. Yet another study suggests that <u><strong>we could be approaching a sudden, irreversible, catastrophic collapse of the global ecosystem</u></strong>. If this were to occur, <u><strong>it could <mark>result in</mark> “<mark>widespread </mark>social <mark>unrest</mark>, economic <mark>instability</mark> and loss of human life.” Given the potential for environmental degradation to elevate the likelihood of nuclear wars, <mark>nuclear terror</u></strong></mark>ism<u><strong>, engineered <mark>pandemics</mark>,</u></strong> a superintelligence<u><strong><mark> takeover</u></strong></mark>, and perhaps even an impact winter, <u><strong><mark>it ought to take precedence over all other </mark>risk <mark>concerns</u></strong></mark> — at least <u><strong>in the <mark>near-term</u></strong></mark>. Let’s make sure we get our priorities straight.</p> | 1NR | BBB DA | null | 11,648 | 1,042 | 23,999 | ./documents/ndtceda21/Minnesota/JoSu/Minnesota-Johnson-Sun-Neg-UMN-Round3.docx | 626,129 | N | UMN | 3 | Iowa PS | Jenna Bauer | 1AC - False Advertising
1NC - T Prohibit States CP Cap K Overstretch DA Floodgates DA BBB DA FTC Collapse CP on case
2NR - BBB DA States CP | ndtceda21/Minnesota/JoSu/Minnesota-Johnson-Sun-Neg-UMN-Round3.docx | null | 52,796 | JoSu | Minnesota JoSu | null | No..... | Jo..... | Ke..... | Su..... | 19,401 | Minnesota | Minnesota | null | null | 1,011 | ndtceda21 | NDT/CEDA 2021-22 | 2,021 | cx | college | 2 |
4,016,462 | Talmadge 17 writes, | Talmadge 17 | Caitlin Talmadge, xx-xx-2017, “Would China Go Nuclear?,” International Security,
[Talmadge is an Assistant Professor of Political Science and International Affairs at the George Washington University. Dr. Caitlin Talmadge is the author of TheDictator’s Army: Battlefield Effectiveness in Authoritarian Regimes (Cornell University Press, 2015) and co-author of U.S. Defense Politics: the Origins of Security Policy (Routledge, 2014). Her other writings have appeared in International Security, Security Studies, The Journal of Conflict Resolution, The Non-Proliferation Review, The Washington Quarterly, The New York Times, and The Washington Post, among other outlets. Dr. Talmadge previously worked at the Center for Strategic and International Studies, and as a consultant to the Office of Net Assessment at the U.S. Department of Defense] | https://muse-jhu-edu.proxy.library.cornell.edu/article/657918 recut//cheung
Chinese nuclear escalation in the event of a conventional war with the United States is a significant risk the fear that the United States might be attempting conventional counterforce could lead China to engage in limited nuclear escalation to gain military advantage or coercive leverage—despite China's no-first-use policy. | Chinese nuclear escalation in the event of a conventional war is a significant risk the fear that the United States might be attempting conventional counterforce could lead China to engage in limited nuclear escalation to gain military advantage or coercive leverage | https://muse-jhu-edu.proxy.library.cornell.edu/article/657918 recut//cheung
Conclusion Chinese nuclear escalation in the event of a conventional war with the United States is a significant risk, although for reasons not fully surfaced in the existing debate. A U.S. conventional campaign would indeed pose a large, though not total, threat to China's nuclear arsenal. More important than the purely military-technical implications of the U.S. campaign, however, is what China is likely to believe the campaign signals about U.S. intentions in a world where conventional deterrence has just failed. Reasonable Chinese fears that the United States might be attempting conventional counterforce, or considering or preparing for nuclear counterforce, could lead China to engage in limited nuclear escalation to gain military advantage or coercive leverage—despite China's no-first-use policy. | 888 | <h4>Talmadge 17 writes, </h4><p>Caitlin <u><strong>Talmadge</u></strong>, xx-xx-20<u><strong>17</u></strong>, “Would China Go Nuclear?,” International Security, </p><p>[Talmadge is an Assistant Professor of Political Science and International Affairs at the George Washington University. Dr. Caitlin Talmadge is the author of TheDictator’s Army: Battlefield Effectiveness in Authoritarian Regimes (Cornell University Press, 2015) and co-author of U.S. Defense Politics: the Origins of Security Policy (Routledge, 2014). Her other writings have appeared in International Security, Security Studies, The Journal of Conflict Resolution, The Non-Proliferation Review, The Washington Quarterly, The New York Times, and The Washington Post, among other outlets. Dr. Talmadge previously worked at the Center for Strategic and International Studies, and as a consultant to the Office of Net Assessment at the U.S. Department of Defense] </p><p><u><strong>https://muse-jhu-edu.proxy.library.cornell.edu/article/657918 recut//cheung</p><p></u></strong>Conclusion <u><strong><mark>Chinese nuclear escalation in the event of a conventional war</mark> with the United States <mark>is a significant risk</u></strong></mark>, although for reasons not fully surfaced in the existing debate. A U.S. conventional campaign would indeed pose a large, though not total, threat to China's nuclear arsenal. More important than the purely military-technical implications of the U.S. campaign, however, is what China is likely to believe <u><strong><mark>the</u></strong></mark> campaign signals about U.S. intentions in a world where conventional deterrence has just failed. Reasonable Chinese <u><strong><mark>fear</u></strong></mark>s <u><strong><mark>that the United States might be attempting conventional counterforce</u></strong></mark>, or considering or preparing for nuclear counterforce, <u><strong><mark>could lead China to engage in limited nuclear escalation to gain military advantage or coercive leverage</mark>—despite China's no-first-use policy.</p></u></strong> | null | null | null | 27,311 | 361 | 136,349 | ./documents/hspf21/Summit/ToJa/Summit-Tobon-Jain-Neg-Tournament%20of%20Champions%20Gold-Round3.docx | 913,739 | N | Tournament of Champions Gold | 3 | Glen Rock OS | Amrit Ammanamanchi | 1NC China economy
1AC gray-zone conflicts PKOs
2NR Taiwan turns
2AR China turns
NS Collapse on economy
AS Collapse on PKOs | hspf21/Summit/ToJa/Summit-Tobon-Jain-Neg-Tournament%20of%20Champions%20Gold-Round3.docx | null | 77,637 | ToJa | Summit ToJa | null | Ma..... | To..... | Ri..... | Ja..... | 26,062 | Summit | Summit | NJ | null | 1,034 | hspf21 | HS PF 2021-22 | 2,021 | pf | hs | 2 |
4,717,677 | Immigration decks wage growth | Borjas ‘16 | Borjas ‘16 [George Borjas is the Robert W. Scrivner Professor of Economics and Social Policy at the Harvard Kennedy School. He was awarded the IZA Prize in Labor Economics in 2011. Professor Borjas is a Research Associate at the National Bureau of Economic Research and a Research Fellow at IZA. Professor Borjas is the author of several books on immigration economics, 2016 “Yes, Immigration Hurts American Workers”, Poltico, September/ October, https://www.politico.com/magazine/story/2016/09/trump-clinton-immigration-economy-unemployment-jobs-214216, accessed 8/17/18, MJ] | When the supply of workers goes up, the price that firms have to pay to hire workers goes down. Wage trends over the past half-century suggest that a 10 percent increase in the number of workers with a particular set of skills probably lowers the wage of that group by at least 3 percent. Even after the economy has fully adjusted, those skill groups that received the most immigrants will still offer lower pay relative to those that received fewer immigrants.
Both low- and high-skilled natives are affected by the influx of immigrants. But because a disproportionate percentage of immigrants have few skills, it is low-skilled American workers, including many blacks and Hispanics, who have suffered most from this wage dip As a result, the earnings of this particularly vulnerable group dropped by between $800 and $1,500 each year. | supply of workers goes up the price to hire workers goes down 10 percent increase in the number of workers with a particular set of skills probably lowers the wage of that group by at least 3 percent
Both low- and high-skilled natives are affected by the influx of immigrants | This second message might be hard for many Americans to process, but anyone who tells you that immigration doesn’t have any negative effects doesn’t understand how it really works. When the supply of workers goes up, the price that firms have to pay to hire workers goes down. Wage trends over the past half-century suggest that a 10 percent increase in the number of workers with a particular set of skills probably lowers the wage of that group by at least 3 percent. Even after the economy has fully adjusted, those skill groups that received the most immigrants will still offer lower pay relative to those that received fewer immigrants.
Both low- and high-skilled natives are affected by the influx of immigrants. But because a disproportionate percentage of immigrants have few skills, it is low-skilled American workers, including many blacks and Hispanics, who have suffered most from this wage dip. The monetary loss is sizable. The typical high school dropout earns about $25,000 annually. According to census data, immigrants admitted in the past two decades lacking a high school diploma have increased the size of the low-skilled workforce by roughly 25 percent. As a result, the earnings of this particularly vulnerable group dropped by between $800 and $1,500 each year. | 1,286 | <h4>Immigration decks wage growth</h4><p><strong>Borjas ‘16 </strong>[George Borjas is the Robert W. Scrivner Professor of Economics and Social Policy at the Harvard Kennedy School. He was awarded the IZA Prize in Labor Economics in 2011. Professor Borjas is a Research Associate at the National Bureau of Economic Research and a Research Fellow at IZA. Professor Borjas is the author of several books on immigration economics, 2016 “Yes, Immigration Hurts American Workers”, Poltico, September/ October, https://www.politico.com/magazine/story/2016/09/trump-clinton-immigration-economy-unemployment-jobs-214216<u>, accessed 8/17/18, MJ]</p><p></u>This second message might be hard for many Americans to process, but anyone who tells you that immigration doesn’t have any negative effects doesn’t understand how it really works. <u>When the <mark>supply of workers goes up</mark>, <mark>the price</mark> that firms have to pay <mark>to hire workers goes down</mark>. Wage trends over the past half-century suggest that a <strong><mark>10 percent increase</strong> in the number of workers with a particular set of skills probably lowers the wage of that group by at least <strong>3 percent</strong></mark>. Even after the economy has fully adjusted, those skill groups that received the most immigrants will still offer lower pay relative to those that received fewer immigrants.</p><p><mark>Both low- and high-skilled natives are affected by the influx of immigrants</mark>. But because a disproportionate percentage of immigrants have few skills, it is low-skilled American workers, including many blacks and Hispanics, who have suffered most from this wage dip</u>. The monetary loss is sizable. The typical high school dropout earns about $25,000 annually. According to census data, immigrants admitted in the past two decades lacking a high school diploma have increased the size of the low-skilled workforce by roughly 25 percent. <u>As a result, the earnings of this particularly vulnerable group dropped by between $800 and $1,500 each year.</p></u> | 1NC vs Vestavia Hills EP | Case | AT: C2 | 96,073 | 462 | 164,651 | ./documents/hsld22/King/ChPa/King-ChPa-Neg-Aaron-Thomas-Memorial-Invitational-at-Cypress-Bay-Round-1.docx | 965,594 | N | Aaron Thomas Memorial Invitational at Cypress Bay | 1 | Vestavia Hills EP | Xia, Qian | 1AC - Structural Violence + Econ
1NC - Util, Disease DA, Brain Drain DA, Terror DA, Case
1AR - All
2NR - All
2AR - All | hsld22/King/ChPa/King-ChPa-Neg-Aaron-Thomas-Memorial-Invitational-at-Cypress-Bay-Round-1.docx | 2023-01-21 00:13:55 | 79,340 | ChPa | King ChPa | Hey y'all I'm Chan! (they/them) or (he/him)
Contact Info
Email: [email protected]
Messanger: https://www.facebook.com/chanh.park.167/
Please ask for consent to spread!
And please give content warnings about discussions of ableist and anti-asian violence | Ch..... | Pa..... | null | null | 26,583 | King | King | FL | null | 2,003 | hsld22 | HS LD 2022-23 | 2,022 | ld | hs | 1 |
4,567,775 | Global economic improvement depends heavily on China’s economic recovery | Kotok 22 | Kotok 22 (David Kotok co-founded Cumberland Advisors in 1973 and has been its Chief Investment Officer since inception. David’s articles and financial market commentaries have appeared in The New York Times, The Wall Street Journal, Barron’s, and other publications, “Global Soft Landing Depends Heavily On China,” Seeking Alpha, 6/22/2022, https://seekingalpha.com/article/4519773-global-soft-landing-depends-heavily-on-china) - MP | Russia’s war in Ukraine and Covid-related shutdowns in China have led to both slower growth prospects and higher inflation for the global economy Worsening consumer and business sentiment, increased inflation, and central banks moving to tighten monetary policy, with the US Federal Reserve being the most aggressive, have increased the risk of a global recession recession in the UK, and Germany’s GDP likely declined in the current quarter a soft landing for the global economy may still be possible, depending on the strength of an anticipated recovery in the Chinese economy the central role that China plays in the global economy. It has the second largest economy, following the US, and is the world’s leading exporter, with critical supply chain connections to most economies the world economy remains heavily connected to the Chinese economy When China imposed widespread lockdowns in April in pursuit of its zero-Covid policy, its economy was dealt a major blow. In May, Covid restrictions were eased; supply disruptions were reduced; and economic policy stimulus measures were increased, The Chinese economy responded more robustly, than the market expected. Fallout from the Russia-Ukraine war will be a negative factor, causing a global supply shock to energy and food. China’s economy is projected to achieve an annual growth rate of about 4% this year. Economies in the Asia-Pacific region will benefit from a recovery in China. China has already had substantial success in its efforts to reduce logistics hurdles and otherwise support foreign trade. Chinese goods exports in US dollar terms increased 16.9% year/year If our expectations for a sustained recovery in China’s economy are in the ballpark, China’s stocks are likely to outperform | Worsening consumer and business sentiment a recession in the UK, and Germany’s GDP likely declined , a soft landing may still be possible depending on recovery in the Chinese economy It has the second largest economy is the world’s leading exporter, with critical supply chain connections to most economies Economies in the Asia-Pacific region will benefit from a recovery in China | Russia’s war in Ukraine and Covid-related shutdowns in China have led to both slower growth prospects and higher inflation for the global economy. What was expected to be a continued strong recovery has been transformed in the second quarter to a stalling global economy. Worsening consumer and business sentiment, increased inflation, and central banks moving to tighten monetary policy, with the US Federal Reserve being the most aggressive, have increased the risk of a global recession. The Bank of England is already predicting a recession in the UK, and Germany’s GDP likely declined in the current quarter. Nevertheless, a soft landing for the global economy may still be possible, depending on the strength of an anticipated recovery in the Chinese economy along with other large Asian economies. Positive global growth still looks likely to return in the second half of this year, with real GDP growth for the year 2022 at 3% and at a similar rate next year.We have written about the central role that China plays in the global economy. It has the second largest economy, following the US, and is the world’s leading exporter, with critical supply chain connections to most economies. While there has been a lot of talk about “decoupling” from China, the reality is that the world economy remains heavily connected to the Chinese economy. When China imposed widespread lockdowns in April in pursuit of its zero-Covid policy, its economy was dealt a major blow. Output in both the industrial and service sectors turned negative in April; port activity was disrupted; and retail sales fell some 11%.In May, Covid restrictions were eased; supply disruptions were reduced; and economic policy stimulus measures were increased, with promises of more to come. The Chinese economy responded more robustly, than the market expected. Industrial production returned to positive growth, led by automobile and electric machinery production. Fixed-asset investment rebounded, led by infrastructure investment. The decline in retail sales continued but at a slower pace, which beat market expectations. China’s Covid statistics improved dramatically. The seven-day average daily case numbers have dropped to about 200, compared with some 30,000 in April. Nevertheless, mass testing is being imposed in some areas; and there have been some new, limited shutdowns. The Chinese economy probably hit bottom in April. Economic momentum appears to be picking up in June as more of the economy comes back online, the Shanghai lockdown has been lifted, and policy stimulus measures are having an increasing effect. Monetary and fiscal measures are being targeted to support small and medium-sized enterprises, real estate, manufacturing, and infrastructure financing. “Normalization” of the supervision of technology companies, following a year of regulatory crackdowns, and an outright pledge of support for the sector are welcome news to investors. Such measures to shore up domestic demand and improve export potential will be critical for maintaining the recovery in the second half and in 2023, when external demand may continue to be weak. Fallout from the Russia-Ukraine war will be a negative factor, causing a global supply shock to energy and food. China’s economy is projected to achieve an annual growth rate of about 4% this year. That would be just half the growth rate of last year but still stronger than the growth of most other economies. Growth in 2023 may average over 5%. Future Covid outbreaks will continue to be a risk to this outlook, although the government has modified its anti-Covid policies to be somewhat less disruptive.Economies in the Asia-Pacific region will benefit from a recovery in China. Particularly important will be a reduction in the disruptions in Asia’s supply chains. China has already had substantial success in its efforts to reduce logistics hurdles and otherwise support foreign trade. Chinese goods exports in US dollar terms increased 16.9% year/year in May compared with just 3.9% in April. Supply delivery times also improved in May. Stronger growth in China and fewer restrictions on activity should have a healthy effect on the Chinese demand for the exports of other Asia-Pacific economies. South Korea’s exports to China stabilized in May. The region will be affected by the Russia-Ukraine war mainly through the impact of the war on the region’s export markets, particularly those in Europe. Nevertheless, growth rates in the region’s resilient economies are likely to remain among the globe’s strongest, with this year’s growth rates for India, Indonesia, Malaysia, Singapore, and the Philippines all likely to be above 5%. If our expectations for a sustained recovery in China’s economy are in the ballpark, China’s stocks are likely to outperform. That has already been the case over the past three months through June 17, an otherwise dismal period for global equity markets. During this period, the Shanghai market managed a gain of 2.0% while the S&P 500 lost 17.7% and the STOXX Europe 300 lost 11.1%. At Cumberland Advisors, we currently have a positive but underweight position in Chinese equities in our International and Global Equity ETF Portfolios. That position can change any day depending on developments. | 5,268 | <h4><strong>Global economic improvement depends heavily on China’s economic recovery</h4><p>Kotok 22 </strong>(David Kotok co-founded Cumberland Advisors in 1973 and has been its Chief Investment Officer since inception. David’s articles and financial market commentaries have appeared in The New York Times, The Wall Street Journal, Barron’s, and other publications, “Global Soft Landing Depends Heavily On China,” Seeking Alpha, 6/22/2022, https://seekingalpha.com/article/4519773-global-soft-landing-depends-heavily-on-china) - MP</p><p><u>Russia’s war in Ukraine and Covid-related shutdowns in China have led to both slower growth prospects and higher inflation for the global economy</u>. What was expected to be a continued strong recovery has been transformed in the second quarter to a stalling global economy. <u><mark>Worsening consumer and business sentiment</mark>, increased inflation, and central banks moving to tighten monetary policy, with the US Federal Reserve being the most aggressive, have increased the risk of a global recession</u>. The Bank of England is already predicting <mark>a <u>recession in the UK, and Germany’s GDP likely declined</mark> in the current quarter</u>. Nevertheless<mark>, <u>a soft landing</mark> for the global economy <mark>may still be possible</mark>, <mark>depending on</mark> the strength of an anticipated <mark>recovery in the Chinese economy</mark> </u>along with other large Asian economies. Positive global growth still looks likely to return in the second half of this year, with real GDP growth for the year 2022 at 3% and at a similar rate next year.We have written about <u>the central role that China plays in the global economy. <mark>It has the second largest economy</mark>, following the US, and <mark>is the world’s leading exporter, with critical supply chain connections to most economies</u></mark>. While there has been a lot of talk about “decoupling” from China, the reality is that <u>the world economy remains heavily connected to the Chinese economy</u>. <u>When China imposed widespread lockdowns in April in pursuit of its zero-Covid policy, its economy was dealt a major blow.</u> Output in both the industrial and service sectors turned negative in April; port activity was disrupted; and retail sales fell some 11%.<u>In May, Covid restrictions were eased; supply disruptions were reduced; and economic policy stimulus measures were increased,</u> with promises of more to come. <u>The Chinese economy responded more robustly, than the market expected.</u> Industrial production returned to positive growth, led by automobile and electric machinery production. Fixed-asset investment rebounded, led by infrastructure investment. The decline in retail sales continued but at a slower pace, which beat market expectations. China’s Covid statistics improved dramatically. The seven-day average daily case numbers have dropped to about 200, compared with some 30,000 in April. Nevertheless, mass testing is being imposed in some areas; and there have been some new, limited shutdowns. The Chinese economy probably hit bottom in April. Economic momentum appears to be picking up in June as more of the economy comes back online, the Shanghai lockdown has been lifted, and policy stimulus measures are having an increasing effect. Monetary and fiscal measures are being targeted to support small and medium-sized enterprises, real estate, manufacturing, and infrastructure financing. “Normalization” of the supervision of technology companies, following a year of regulatory crackdowns, and an outright pledge of support for the sector are welcome news to investors. Such measures to shore up domestic demand and improve export potential will be critical for maintaining the recovery in the second half and in 2023, when external demand may continue to be weak. <u>Fallout from the Russia-Ukraine war will be a negative factor, causing a global supply shock to energy and food. China’s economy is projected to achieve an annual growth rate of about 4% this year.</u> That would be just half the growth rate of last year but still stronger than the growth of most other economies. Growth in 2023 may average over 5%. Future Covid outbreaks will continue to be a risk to this outlook, although the government has modified its anti-Covid policies to be somewhat less disruptive.<u><mark>Economies in the Asia-Pacific region will benefit from a recovery in China</mark>.</u> Particularly important will be a reduction in the disruptions in Asia’s supply chains. <u>China has already had substantial success in its efforts to reduce logistics hurdles and otherwise support foreign trade. Chinese goods exports in US dollar terms increased 16.9% year/year</u> in May compared with just 3.9% in April. Supply delivery times also improved in May. Stronger growth in China and fewer restrictions on activity should have a healthy effect on the Chinese demand for the exports of other Asia-Pacific economies. South Korea’s exports to China stabilized in May. The region will be affected by the Russia-Ukraine war mainly through the impact of the war on the region’s export markets, particularly those in Europe. Nevertheless, growth rates in the region’s resilient economies are likely to remain among the globe’s strongest, with this year’s growth rates for India, Indonesia, Malaysia, Singapore, and the Philippines all likely to be above 5%. <u>If our expectations for a sustained recovery in China’s economy are in the ballpark, China’s stocks are likely to outperform</u><strong>. That has already been the case over the past three months through June 17, an otherwise dismal period for global equity markets. During this period, the Shanghai market managed a gain of 2.0% while the S&P 500 lost 17.7% and the STOXX Europe 300 lost 11.1%. At Cumberland Advisors, we currently have a positive but underweight position in Chinese equities in our International and Global Equity ETF Portfolios. That position can change any day depending on developments.</p></strong> | null | null | 4 | 505 | 112 | 151,042 | ./documents/hsld22/Marlborough/HoLe/Marlborough-HoLe-Neg-Damus-Hollywood-Invitational-Doubles.docx | 944,915 | N | Damus Hollywood Invitational | Doubles | Aragon ZA | Danielle Dosch, Nikki Aqui, Gordon Krauss | 1ac - dams
1nc - nuke disarm cp, transboundary rivers cp, econ da, t prioritize, case
1ar - all
2nr - t
2ar - case, t | hsld22/Marlborough/HoLe/Marlborough-HoLe-Neg-Damus-Hollywood-Invitational-Doubles.docx | 2022-11-13 17:26:59 | 80,412 | HoLe | Marlborough HoLe | null | Ho..... | Le..... | null | null | 26,925 | Marlborough | Marlborough | CA | null | 2,003 | hsld22 | HS LD 2022-23 | 2,022 | ld | hs | 1 |
4,799,444 | Borders entrench a neocolonial framework of dependent development that destroys human dignity – mass inequality, corruption, and state failure link turns every disad | Nwune 21 | Nwune 21 [Nwune, Udoka W., "Neocolonialism and Terrorist Activities in Africa: A Case Study of Nigeria." Georgia State University, 2021. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1096&context=political_science_theses] CT | He postulated that the neocolonialism of his days (the 1950s–1970s) represents imperialism in its final and perhaps its most dangerous stage. Ultimately, to Uzoigwe (2019) Nkrumah’s postulation suggests that those who practice neocolonialism exercise power without concern and those who suffer from it are exploited without remedy Therefore, neocolonialism is the nature of relations after independence between European powers and their former colonies of the non-European world To Uzoigwe (2019) neocolonialism is accomplished under three broad categories: political and geopolitical, economic, and sociocultural. Also, he failed to emphasize which major actors on the global stage (states, IOs, MNCs, NGOs, and individuals) assist in accomplishing neocolonialism under the three broad categories. From a political and geopolitical stance, Uzoigwe argues that neocolonialism has been used primarily to achieve foreign interests, for example through what he considers the divisive western concepts that destabilizes regions and entire continents such as sub-Saharan Africa. The foreign interests of hegemonic states that surged in Africa during the Cold war period validates Uzoigwe’s argument. post-colonial state is established in a way that it reflects and mainly caters to a narrow array of interests, mainly the interests of the selfcentered political elites acting as agents to foreign interests Uzoigwe’s article demonstrates that neocolonialism will not be able to operate effectively without the cooperation of the indigenous leaders. He argued that such relationship is intended to foster dependency, which in turn undermines the sovereignty of the states concerned. This was what Ali (2014) referred to as “illusion sovereignty”. Ali (2014) organized his study with the postcolonial theory while maintaining that the colonial powers left Africa physically after states attained independence, but remained politically, economically, and socially. Ultimately, the major pre-occupation colonial state was to create conditions under which accumulation of capital by both foreign and domestic bourgeoisie would take place through the exploitation of local human and other natural resources Hegemons like the U.S, France, and Britain have directly or indirectly overthrown regimes in Africa. In most other African states, few leaders managed to stay in power after all attempts to overthrow them failed, essentially because the support of the Soviet Union during the Cold War created internal and external hurdles that frustrated the African leaders’ policies and rendered them ineffectual oigwe rightly agreed that neocolonial powers operate by skillfully manipulating states by offering carrots to friendly states and sticks to enemies. In addition, Uzoigwe (2019) argued that there two versions of neocolonialism which he referred to as old and new neocolonialism. He argued that the old new colonialism was more transparent, while new neocolonialism more sophisticated and dangerous.
. They linked the origin and spread of corruption to the colonization of Africa, the long-lasting legacy of colonization and the actions and practices of major actors on the global stage which we reviewed as neocolonization in the previous section At independence, such client-patron ties between the groups favored by the colonial administration had an edge over those not favored (Leonard, 1991 as cited in Milinge, 1993). Consequently, these favored groups would constitute the earliest Nigerian elite class. The elite class was what Rodney (1972) called the ‘petty bourgeoisie', whose role was to dominate the political and economic life of most African states. According to Leonard (1991, as cited in Milinge et al., 2002) the gaining of independence for this group was merely intended for the breaking of the monopoly of the colonial administrator's political power so that they could further their own advancement and posterity. These groups replicated their British colonial master’s technique of divide and rule which involved the practice of favoring one tribe over others with the dual objective of securing loyalty of that group to the administration and encouraging rivalry between different tribes to prevent a sense of unity from evolving and threatening political interests Abada et al. (2019) argued that the nature of the Nigerian state was formed in huge extent by its colonial past and the nature of the state explains the nature of associational life within the society. Thus, the theory of postcolonial state and elite theory provide support to hypothesis that neocolonialism has induced corruption in Nigeria. No wonder, Agang (2016) argued that corruption is an indication of how the focus on materialism has led to the distortion of human dignity and the sanity of life and values. According to Agang (2016) the chances of oppression and marginalization of the majority by a peculiar social group is initiated by the fascination of the amassment of material wealth which reduces and equates human value to monetary value The consequences resulted in a pattern of scandalous wealth among the ruling class with growing poverty, unhappiness, and deprivation among many Nigerians Hadden (2016) suggests that resources acquired by corruption tend to be kept outside Nigeria by politicians instead of being invested in the local economy for its intended purpose, which therefore leaves a vacuum, depressing Nigeria’s development Therefore, corruption is a way of life in Nigeria abetted by hegemonic powers and is a way of life which existing governments neither wish to, nor can, control.
2.1.2 Bad Governance and Terrorism
However, scholars such Abada and Ngwu (2019) attempted to establish that bad governance and corruption in Nigeria has given rise to certain societal challenges that led to insurgency. For instance, in the study of Abada et al. (2019) which is anchored on the theory of post-colonial state, they argued that the misuse of public resources and the failure of governance have provoked mass poverty in Nigeria which has led to the advent of terrorist groups that resort to the use of force in the expression of their discontent have argued that the terrorist activities of Boko Haram are triggered by a combination of bad governance, including the prevalent failures of state policies, inefficient and wasteful parastatals, and endemic corruption, poverty, unemployment, and extensive underdevelopment in the northern Nigeria. Therefore, these elites are the perpetrators of bad governance in Nigeria, and they are also responsible for the frustration of the citizens of Nigeria. Okoro (2020) demonstrated that the Boko Haram insurgency is a retaliation against bad governance, notably in northern Nigeria where the epidemic of poverty led to frustration and recourse to terror activities among the people, particularly the youth. The elite’s private accumulation resources at the expense of the public destabilizes the state’s institutions therefore fostering inequality, underdevelopment, and endangering the lives of citizens whom these public institutions are meant to serve. Therefore, Okoro (2020) argued that the membership profile of Boko Haram reveals that poverty and economic inequality are at its roots. However, he failed denote a strong link on what exactly causes poverty and economic inequality that leads to terrorist activities. It could possibly be embedded in what Okoro recognized as the weak nature of governance. Importantly, he found that bad governance in Nigeria served as a broader function in the emergence and growth of terrorist activities of Boko Haram. | neocolonialism represents imperialism in its most dangerous stage those who suffer are exploited without remedy neocolonialism destabilizes entire continents political elites act as agents to foreign interests foster dependency colonial powers remained politically, accumulation by foreign bourgeoisie through exploitation natural resources Hegemons have overthrown regimes in Africa
At independence groups replicated colonial divide and rule neocolonialism induced corruption materialism led to the distortion of dignity oppression equates human to monetary value scandalous wealth among the ruling
mass poverty i led to terrorist groups Boko Haram triggered by endemic corruption, poverty private accumulation destabilizes state institutions fostering inequality, underdevelopment, and endangering lives poverty and inequality are its roots | 2.1 The Manifestation of Neocolonialism
To understand the variables under investigation, it is imperative to understand the phenomenon, neocolonialism. Many other scholars have had various emotive definitions of neocolonialism, thereby arousing debates within the social sciences. A notable example of an emotive definition of neocolonialism is the Ghanaian nationalist and first President of Ghana, Kwame Nkrumah's definition. He postulated that the neocolonialism of his days (the 1950s–1970s) represents imperialism in its final and perhaps its most dangerous stage. Ultimately, to Uzoigwe (2019) Nkrumah’s postulation suggests that those who practice neocolonialism exercise power without concern and those who suffer from it are exploited without remedy. He disagrees with Colin Leys (1975) who believed that neocolonialism was temporary and transitional, and instead sees neocolonialism as a continuous process. Therefore, neocolonialism is the nature of relations after independence between European powers and their former colonies of the non-European world (Uzoigwe, 2019). To Uzoigwe (2019) neocolonialism is accomplished under three broad categories: political and geopolitical, economic, and sociocultural. He argues that these broad categories have both negative and positive aspects. Perhaps what he tried to recognize as the positive aspects of manifestation of neocolonialism is what I consider as the positive tenets of globalization. Also, he failed to emphasize which major actors on the global stage (states, IOs, MNCs, NGOs, and individuals) assist in accomplishing neocolonialism under the three broad categories. From a political and geopolitical stance, Uzoigwe argues that neocolonialism has been used primarily to achieve foreign interests, for example through what he considers the divisive western concepts that destabilizes regions and entire continents such as sub-Saharan Africa. The foreign interests of hegemonic states that surged in Africa during the Cold war period validates Uzoigwe’s argument. While emphasizing on historical events, Uzoigwe’s argument did not utilize significant theories to critically interrogate the phenomenon of neocolonialism. Perhaps an inclusion of relevant theories like postcolonial theory and realism would have made a huge difference in his study. For instance, adopting postcolonial theory in his study would broadly have clarified the effects of colonialism on cultures and societies, and its creation of elitism. The post-colonial state is established in a way that it reflects and mainly caters to a narrow array of interests, mainly the interests of the selfcentered political elites acting as agents to foreign interests (Ake, 1985 as cited by Abada et al, 2019). Uzoigwe’s article demonstrates that neocolonialism will not be able to operate effectively without the cooperation of the indigenous leaders. He argued that such relationship is intended to foster dependency, which in turn undermines the sovereignty of the states concerned. This was what Ali (2014) referred to as “illusion sovereignty”. Ali (2014) organized his study with the postcolonial theory while maintaining that the colonial powers left Africa physically after states attained independence, but remained politically, economically, and socially. In a similar study like Uzoigwe’s, Wyss (2016) emphasized that the ‘defense agreement’ between Britain and Nigeria demonstrated a clear manifestation of neocolonialism. Wyss (2016) argued that the British military personnel sought to ensure military facilities in Nigeria through the ‘defense agreement’ to sustain and strengthen Britain’s hegemony which was driven by the struggle between the Western and Eastern blocs during the Cold War. Perhaps, this was what Rondey (1973) in his book "How Europe Underdeveloped Africa," attempted to emphasize as a cynical short-hand expression for the strengthening of foreign exploitation in Africa to develop capitalist Europe. Certainly, indigenous elites play a role in the strengthening of foreign exploitation in Nigeria. The first Prime Minister of Nigeria, Tafawa Balewa was clearly an advocate for the defense agreement. However, Wyss (2016) in his study failed to pinpoint if this could have probably been because of the interests of the self-centered political elites that represents foreign interests. For instance, the appointment of Balewa as Prime Minister in 1957 by the British Governor General, Sir James Wilson Robertson, and his retainment of the position during independence over other preferred candidates alarmed many Nigerians, and subsequently made some Nigerians considered him pro-western. Hence, he supported the defense agreement between Nigeria and Britain and claimed that it was in Nigeria’s interest against the continued charges from the opposition in parliament, led by the AG (Action Group party), and many. According to Wyss (2016. P. 14) “In late November 1960, around 800 students descended into the streets of Lagos to demonstrate against the agreement. They carried placards that read, among other things, ‘Away with Anglo-Balewa Pact’, ‘Down with Colonial Mentality’ and ‘Keep us out of NATO’.” Ultimately, the major pre-occupation colonial state was to create conditions under which accumulation of capital by both foreign and domestic bourgeoisie would take place through the exploitation of local human and other natural resources (Ekekwe, 1985). Abada & Ngwu (2019) made a powerful theoretical framework in the study through the utilization of postcolonial theory. The theoretical framework in their study synthesizes with Uzoigwe’s stance in his study that the political rulers that emerged in postcolonial states were individuals that were specifically chosen by the departing colonial powers. Many progressive indigenous leaders who attempted to challenge the will of previous colonial powers met unfortunate fates. Hegemons like the U.S, France, and Britain have directly or indirectly overthrown regimes in Africa. For instance, in the enormous mineral wealthy Democratic Republic Congo, the C.I.A and Belgium authorities maneuvered colonel Mobutu's rise to power in 1966 in Democratic Republic Congo, by capturing, torturing, and tragically assassinating the first prime minister of Congo, Lumumba on 17th January 1961 because Lumumba refused to become an ally of the West but rather ally with East bloc. In most other African states, few leaders managed to stay in power after all attempts to overthrow them failed, essentially because the support of the Soviet Union during the Cold War created internal and external hurdles that frustrated the African leaders’ policies and rendered them ineffectual (Uzoigwe, 2019). Uzoigwe rightly agreed that neocolonial powers operate by skillfully manipulating states by offering carrots to friendly states and sticks to enemies. In addition, Uzoigwe (2019) argued that there two versions of neocolonialism which he referred to as old and new neocolonialism. He argued that the old new colonialism was more transparent, while new neocolonialism more sophisticated and dangerous. Unlike Uzoigwe, this study rejects that there was an old version of neocolonialism that was beneficial in any respects because there is absolutely nothing beneficial about neocolonialism since it interferes in the sovereignty of developing states and makes them dependent on hegemonic states. Nigeria has been affected by the shackles of neocolonialism to the extent that the state is helpless to help itself especially because neocolonialism fostered corruption and bad governance.
2.1.1 Corruption
Corruption is found in states globally. Regardless of the endemic and universal nature of corruption, there is no single generally accepted definition of corruption because countries differ in their point of view as to its meaning, causes and effects (Mulinge et al., 2002). Abada et al, (2019) opined that corruption is indeed a contested concept. They described corruption as a ‘hydraheaded monster’ that has tormented Nigeria for a long time to the extent that top ranking members of Nigeria’s ruling elite have been incapable to reach a consensus on its meaning, let alone the approaches to fight it. Unsurprising, in Mulinge et al. (2002) essay, they defined corruption after Osoba (1996: p 372) as “a form of antisocial behavior by an individual or social group which confers unjust or fraudulent benefits on its perpetrators, is inconsistent with the established legal norms and prevailing moral ethos of the land and is likely to subvert or diminish the capacity of the legitimate authorities to provide fully for the material and spiritual well-being of all members of society in a just and equitable manner.” This definition failed to distinguish what social group is responsible or more likely to perpetuate this antisocial behavior. Could this social group Osaba (1996) referred to be the upper class which this study considers the Nigerian political elites? Or could it have been the middle or lower class? Notwithstanding, Mulinge et al. (2002) presented a holistic analysis of the genesis and entrenchment of corruption in sub-Saharan Africa by incorporating the historical and international contexts of the problem. They linked the origin and spread of corruption to the colonization of Africa, the long-lasting legacy of colonization and the actions and practices of major actors on the global stage which we reviewed as neocolonization in the previous section (section 2.1). Tignor (1993) observed that most of the literature on political corruption seeks to define the term and to understand why and how it arises, what effects it has on polity and economy, and how it may possibly be brought under control. Tignor (1993) focused on the debate that took place during the late colonial period to identify when corruption emerged on the political scene, and how it eventually assumed such prominence. Tignor (1993) found that corruption had long existed prior to the period Nigeria gained its independence from Britain. The political elites in power amass wealth through overwhelming corruption either as Nigerian antagonists or corroborate with colonial administrators. Tignor (1993) argued that prior to Nigeria’s independence the country had been a common place where the activities of competing nationalists were based on using the resources at their disposal to build political alliances. Clearly, these alliances were built amongst political elites and were sometimes based on patron-client ties and strengthening bonds of ethnicity. At independence, such client-patron ties between the groups favored by the colonial administration had an edge over those not favored (Leonard, 1991 as cited in Milinge, 1993). Consequently, these favored groups would constitute the earliest Nigerian elite class. The elite class was what Rodney (1972) called the ‘petty bourgeoisie', whose role was to dominate the political and economic life of most African states. According to Leonard (1991, as cited in Milinge et al., 2002) the gaining of independence for this group was merely intended for the breaking of the monopoly of the colonial administrator's political power so that they could further their own advancement and posterity. These groups replicated their British colonial master’s technique of divide and rule which involved the practice of favoring one tribe over others with the dual objective of securing loyalty of that group to the administration and encouraging rivalry between different tribes to prevent a sense of unity from evolving and threatening political interests (Mulinge et al., 2002). This voids the arguments of some scholars who were convinced that corruption stemmed primarily from electoral politics in Nigeria’s first republic (1960 – 1966). Tignor (1993) argued that the failure of the military regime that emerged after the first republic undercut the argument that corruption stemmed primarily from electoral politics through stressing the norms and values of the Nigerian elites over more structural explanations. For this study, we will adopt Mulinge et al (2002) normative definition of corruption. Mulinge et al., (2002) normatively defined corruption as the misuse of public authority or resources for personal benefit. Abada et al. (2019) argued that the nature of the Nigerian state was formed in huge extent by its colonial past and the nature of the state explains the nature of associational life within the society. Thus, the theory of postcolonial state and elite theory provide support to hypothesis that neocolonialism has induced corruption in Nigeria. The impacts of neocolonialism have kept Nigeria in ideologically westernized and material modernity. No wonder, Agang (2016) argued that corruption is an indication of how the focus on materialism has led to the distortion of human dignity and the sanity of life and values. According to Agang (2016) the chances of oppression and marginalization of the majority by a peculiar social group is initiated by the fascination of the amassment of material wealth which reduces and equates human value to monetary value. Hence, this has been the case of Nigeria since a gained independence from Britain. Osoba 1996 found that all regimes in Nigeria both military and civilian, have been encompassed by corruption. He argued that the oil boom and its revenues aided and created a deepening crisis of kleptocracy, shown in its greatest form since 1984. The consequences resulted in a pattern of scandalous wealth among the ruling class with growing poverty, unhappiness, and deprivation among many Nigerians (Osoba, 1996). Hadden (2016) suggests that resources acquired by corruption tend to be kept outside Nigeria by politicians instead of being invested in the local economy for its intended purpose, which therefore leaves a vacuum, depressing Nigeria’s development. Over the years, Nigerian elitists would not have been able to invest capital in western states without the help of foreign governments and multinational companies. Therefore, corruption is a way of life in Nigeria abetted by hegemonic powers and is a way of life which existing governments neither wish to, nor can, control. Abada et al. (2019) echoed that the government has failed to combat corruption. In fact, the January 1966 coup, which was the first military coup in Nigeria that terminated the First Republic, was due to elite corruption and the inconsistency in governance. In the words of the officer, Nzeogwu who orchestrated the coup: “We wanted to get rid of rotten and corrupt ministers, political parties, trades unions and the whole clumsy apparatus of the federal system. We wanted to gun down all the bigwigs on our way. This was the only way. We could not afford to let them live if this was to work. We got some but not all. General Ironsi was to have been shot, but we were not ruthless enough. As a result, he and the other compromisers were able to supplant us.” (Sahara Reporters, 2009) However, transition of power to the military did not solve the epidemic of bad governance and corruption. Suleiman & Karim, (2015) found that the military regime resulted in the abuse of office, corruption, human right violations, and total neglect for the rule of law. Mulinge et al (2002) argued that corruption is not driven by internal factors alone. They argued that corruption is also a consequence of external factors driven by the activities of foreign governments, aid organizations and MNCs seeking to further their own economic interests through actions and practices that condone corrupt practices or that are corrupt in themselves (Mulingeet al., 2002). According to Galtung (1998: 118 as cited in Mulinge et al., 2002) instances of massive corruption have an international dimension where the bribe giver could perhaps be a MNC, or in certain instance a corrupt politician might seek refuge abroad from prosecution in their home country, and the earnings of corruption can be concealed to private accounts in foreign destinations. The elite theory demonstrates that there is the concentration of power in the hands of the few. The autonomy of elites makes it both advantageous and possible for the governing elite strategize and use state resources to control through manipulation and corruption (Etzioni‐Halevy, 1989). This was the case right from Nigeria’s First Republic (government after independence), the country has been tormented by rampant public sector corruption manifesting in poor governance outcomes and severe developmental pathologies. Consequently, this is the reason corruption and bad governance are correlated in this study. In subsequent sections, this study will utilize corruption and bad governance together since in the case of Nigeria they are conceptually intertwined.
2.1.2 Bad Governance and Terrorism
Many scholars have defined governance from various perspectives. According to Okoro (2020) the concept governance implies to the procedure of exercising political power to oversee the activities of the state. According to the UNICEF (2020, as cited in Okoro, 2020) governance constitutes of making and implementing decisions based on considerations like popular participation, respect for the rule of law, observance of human rights, transparency, free access to information, prompt responses to human needs, accommodation of diverse interests, equity, inclusiveness, effective results, and accountability. According to the Mo Ibrahim Foundation (as cited in Okoro, 2020) governance is the provision of the political, social, and economic public goods and services which is a state’s responsibility to deliver to its citizens, and which is a citizen’s right to expect from the government. Also, Fukuyama (2013) defined governance as the capacity of a government to make and implement rules, and to provide services, irrespective of whether that government is democratic or not. Therefore, if a government is unable to fulfil responsibilities such as making and implementing rules then it should be considered bad at governance. Rose et al (2019) argued that bad governance is frequently caused by corruption. Thus, many scholars such as Ibeanu (1998), Abada & Ngwu (2019), and Mbah (2017) have argued that bad governance and corruption go hand in hand. In reviewing existing literatures, the previous section (section 2.1.1) of this study examine corruption separately for clarity because in many countries bad governance can occur without corruption. Nevertheless, in Nigeria bad governance occurs with corruption since the country attained independence in 1960. Thus, in subsequent sections of this study bad governance and corruption will be combined textually. As much as there are several literatures on corruption in Africa, especially in Nigeria, there is a literature on bad governance in Nigeria. However, much of this literature has not tried to connect neocolonialism to bad governance as well as determine the extent to which a linear causal relationship between the two factors has exacerbated terrorist activities in Nigeria. Suleiman et al (2015) found that literature covering terrorist activities in the northern part of Nigeria dwelled mostly on the origin and activities of the groups through their radicalization on a religious platform. Most analyses of these existing literature have been based on the emergence of terrorist groups and activities through a religious prism (Suleiman et al., 2015). However, scholars such Abada and Ngwu (2019) attempted to establish that bad governance and corruption in Nigeria has given rise to certain societal challenges that led to insurgency. For instance, in the study of Abada et al. (2019) which is anchored on the theory of post-colonial state, they argued that the misuse of public resources and the failure of governance have provoked mass poverty in Nigeria which has led to the advent of terrorist groups that resort to the use of force in the expression of their discontent. Uzodike et al (2012) have argued that the terrorist activities of Boko Haram are triggered by a combination of bad governance, including the prevalent failures of state policies, inefficient and wasteful parastatals, and endemic corruption, poverty, unemployment, and extensive underdevelopment in the northern Nigeria. Essentially, Uzodike et al. (2012) failed to emphasize that inefficient and wasteful parastatals, poverty, unemployment, and extensive underdevelopment will not be feasible without bad governance and corruption. As a result, Nigeria is institutionally constituted so that it enjoys limited independence from the elite class highlighted in section 2.1.1. Therefore, these elites are the perpetrators of bad governance in Nigeria, and they are also responsible for the frustration of the citizens of Nigeria. Okoro (2020) demonstrated that the Boko Haram insurgency is a retaliation against bad governance, notably in northern Nigeria where the epidemic of poverty led to frustration and recourse to terror activities among the people, particularly the youth. He found weaknesses in previous justifications of scholars and analysts who opined that Islamic fundamentalism, and the emergence of an elite violent political competition between northern and southern Nigeria especially after Goodluck Jonathan emerged as president was responsible for the Boko Haram activities. The elite’s private accumulation resources at the expense of the public destabilizes the state’s institutions therefore fostering inequality, underdevelopment, and endangering the lives of citizens whom these public institutions are meant to serve. Therefore, Okoro (2020) argued that the membership profile of Boko Haram reveals that poverty and economic inequality are at its roots. However, he failed denote a strong link on what exactly causes poverty and economic inequality that leads to terrorist activities. It could possibly be embedded in what Okoro recognized as the weak nature of governance. Importantly, he found that bad governance in Nigeria served as a broader function in the emergence and growth of terrorist activities of Boko Haram. | 22,126 | <h4><strong>Borders entrench a neocolonial framework of dependent development that destroys human dignity – mass inequality, corruption, and state failure link turns <u>every disad</u> </h4><p>Nwune 21</strong> [Nwune, Udoka W., "Neocolonialism and Terrorist Activities in Africa: A Case Study of Nigeria." Georgia State University, 2021. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1096&context=political_science_theses] CT</p><p>2.1 The Manifestation of Neocolonialism</p><p>To understand the variables under investigation, it is imperative to understand the phenomenon, neocolonialism. Many other scholars have had various emotive definitions of neocolonialism, thereby arousing debates within the social sciences. A notable example of an emotive definition of neocolonialism is the Ghanaian nationalist and first President of Ghana, Kwame Nkrumah's definition. <u>He postulated that the <strong><mark>neocolonialism</strong></mark> of his days (the 1950s–1970s) <strong><mark>represents imperialism in its </mark>final and</strong> perhaps its <strong><mark>most dangerous stage</strong></mark>.</u> <u>Ultimately, to Uzoigwe (2019) Nkrumah’s postulation suggests that those who practice <strong>neocolonialism exercise power without concern and <mark>those who suffer</strong></mark> from it <strong><mark>are exploited without remedy</u></strong></mark>. He disagrees with Colin Leys (1975) who believed that neocolonialism was temporary and transitional, and instead sees neocolonialism as a continuous process. <u>Therefore, neocolonialism is the nature of relations after independence between European powers and their former colonies of the non-European world</u> (Uzoigwe, 2019). <u>To Uzoigwe (2019) neocolonialism is accomplished under three broad categories: political and geopolitical, economic, and sociocultural. </u>He argues that these broad categories have both negative and positive aspects. Perhaps what he tried to recognize as the positive aspects of manifestation of neocolonialism is what I consider as the positive tenets of globalization. <u>Also, he failed to emphasize which <strong>major actors on the global stage (states, IOs,</strong> MNCs, <strong>NGOs</strong>, and individuals) <strong>assist in accomplishing neocolonialism</strong> under the three broad categories.</u> <u>From a political and geopolitical stance, Uzoigwe argues that <strong><mark>neocolonialism</strong></mark> has been <strong>used</strong> primarily <strong>to achieve foreign interests</strong>, for example through what he considers the divisive western concepts that <strong><mark>destabilizes </mark>regions and <mark>entire continents </mark>such as sub-Saharan Africa</strong>. The foreign interests of hegemonic states that surged in Africa during the Cold war period validates Uzoigwe’s argument. </u>While emphasizing on historical events, Uzoigwe’s argument did not utilize significant theories to critically interrogate the phenomenon of neocolonialism. Perhaps an inclusion of relevant theories like postcolonial theory and realism would have made a huge difference in his study. For instance, adopting postcolonial theory in his study would broadly have clarified the effects of colonialism on cultures and societies, and its creation of elitism. The <u><strong>post-colonial state</strong> is established in a way that it reflects and mainly <strong>caters to</strong> a <strong>narrow array of interests</strong>, mainly the interests of the selfcentered <strong><mark>political elites</strong> act</mark>ing <strong><mark>as agents to foreign interests</u></strong></mark> (Ake, 1985 as cited by Abada et al, 2019). <u>Uzoigwe’s article demonstrates that neocolonialism will not be able to operate effectively without the cooperation of the indigenous leaders. He argued that such relationship is <strong>intended to <mark>foster dependency</strong></mark>, which in turn <strong>undermines</strong> the <strong>sovereignty</strong> of the states concerned.</u> <u>This was what Ali (2014) referred to as <strong>“illusion sovereignty</strong>”.</u> <u>Ali (2014) organized his study with the postcolonial theory while maintaining that the <strong><mark>colonial powers </mark>left Africa physically</strong> after states attained independence, <strong>but <mark>remained politically, </mark>economically, and socially</strong>.</u> In a similar study like Uzoigwe’s, Wyss (2016) emphasized that the ‘defense agreement’ between Britain and Nigeria demonstrated a clear manifestation of neocolonialism. Wyss (2016) argued that the British military personnel sought to ensure military facilities in Nigeria through the ‘defense agreement’ to sustain and strengthen Britain’s hegemony which was driven by the struggle between the Western and Eastern blocs during the Cold War. Perhaps, this was what Rondey (1973) in his book "How Europe Underdeveloped Africa," attempted to emphasize as a cynical short-hand expression for the strengthening of foreign exploitation in Africa to develop capitalist Europe. Certainly, indigenous elites play a role in the strengthening of foreign exploitation in Nigeria. The first Prime Minister of Nigeria, Tafawa Balewa was clearly an advocate for the defense agreement. However, Wyss (2016) in his study failed to pinpoint if this could have probably been because of the interests of the self-centered political elites that represents foreign interests. For instance, the appointment of Balewa as Prime Minister in 1957 by the British Governor General, Sir James Wilson Robertson, and his retainment of the position during independence over other preferred candidates alarmed many Nigerians, and subsequently made some Nigerians considered him pro-western. Hence, he supported the defense agreement between Nigeria and Britain and claimed that it was in Nigeria’s interest against the continued charges from the opposition in parliament, led by the AG (Action Group party), and many. According to Wyss (2016. P. 14) “In late November 1960, around 800 students descended into the streets of Lagos to demonstrate against the agreement. They carried placards that read, among other things, ‘Away with Anglo-Balewa Pact’, ‘Down with Colonial Mentality’ and ‘Keep us out of NATO’.” <u>Ultimately, the major pre-occupation colonial state was to create conditions under which <strong><mark>accumulation </mark>of capital <mark>by</mark> both <mark>foreign</mark> and domestic <mark>bourgeoisie</strong></mark> would take place <strong><mark>through </mark>the <mark>exploitation </mark>of local human and</strong> other <strong><mark>natural resources</u></strong></mark> (Ekekwe, 1985). Abada & Ngwu (2019) made a powerful theoretical framework in the study through the utilization of postcolonial theory. The theoretical framework in their study synthesizes with Uzoigwe’s stance in his study that the political rulers that emerged in postcolonial states were individuals that were specifically chosen by the departing colonial powers. Many progressive indigenous leaders who attempted to challenge the will of previous colonial powers met unfortunate fates. <u><strong><mark>Hegemons</strong></mark> like the U.S, France, and Britain <strong><mark>have </mark>directly or indirectly <mark>overthrown regimes in Africa</strong></mark>. </u>For instance, in the enormous mineral wealthy Democratic Republic Congo, the C.I.A and Belgium authorities maneuvered colonel Mobutu's rise to power in 1966 in Democratic Republic Congo, by capturing, torturing, and tragically assassinating the first prime minister of Congo, Lumumba on 17th January 1961 because Lumumba refused to become an ally of the West but rather ally with East bloc. <u>In most other African states, few leaders managed to stay in power after all attempts to overthrow them failed, essentially because the support of the Soviet Union during the Cold War created internal and external hurdles that frustrated the African leaders’ policies and rendered them ineffectual</u> (Uzoigwe, 2019). Uz<u>oigwe rightly agreed <strong>that neocolonial powers operate by skillfully manipulating states </strong>by <strong>offering carrots</strong> to friendly states <strong>and sticks </strong>to enemies. In addition, Uzoigwe (2019) argued that there two versions of neocolonialism which he referred to as old and new neocolonialism. He argued that the old new colonialism was more transparent, while new neocolonialism more sophisticated and dangerous. </u>Unlike Uzoigwe, this study rejects that there was an old version of neocolonialism that was beneficial in any respects because there is absolutely nothing beneficial about neocolonialism since it interferes in the sovereignty of developing states and makes them dependent on hegemonic states. Nigeria has been affected by the shackles of neocolonialism to the extent that the state is helpless to help itself especially because neocolonialism fostered corruption and bad governance.</p><p>2.1.1 Corruption</p><p>Corruption is found in states globally. Regardless of the endemic and universal nature of corruption, there is no single generally accepted definition of corruption because countries differ in their point of view as to its meaning, causes and effects (Mulinge et al., 2002). Abada et al, (2019) opined that corruption is indeed a contested concept. They described corruption as a ‘hydraheaded monster’ that has tormented Nigeria for a long time to the extent that top ranking members of Nigeria’s ruling elite have been incapable to reach a consensus on its meaning, let alone the approaches to fight it. Unsurprising, in Mulinge et al. (2002) essay, they defined corruption after Osoba (1996: p 372) as “a form of antisocial behavior by an individual or social group which confers unjust or fraudulent benefits on its perpetrators, is inconsistent with the established legal norms and prevailing moral ethos of the land and is likely to subvert or diminish the capacity of the legitimate authorities to provide fully for the material and spiritual well-being of all members of society in a just and equitable manner.” This definition failed to distinguish what social group is responsible or more likely to perpetuate this antisocial behavior. Could this social group Osaba (1996) referred to be the upper class which this study considers the Nigerian political elites? Or could it have been the middle or lower class? Notwithstanding, Mulinge et al. (2002) presented a holistic analysis of the genesis and entrenchment of corruption in sub-Saharan Africa by incorporating the historical and international contexts of the problem<u>. They linked the origin and spread of <strong>corruption</strong> to the colonization of Africa, <strong>the long-lasting legacy of colonization</strong> <strong>and</strong> the actions and practices of <strong>major actors on the global stage</strong> which we reviewed as neocolonization in the previous section</u> (section 2.1). Tignor (1993) observed that most of the literature on political corruption seeks to define the term and to understand why and how it arises, what effects it has on polity and economy, and how it may possibly be brought under control. Tignor (1993) focused on the debate that took place during the late colonial period to identify when corruption emerged on the political scene, and how it eventually assumed such prominence. Tignor (1993) found that corruption had long existed prior to the period Nigeria gained its independence from Britain. The political elites in power amass wealth through overwhelming corruption either as Nigerian antagonists or corroborate with colonial administrators. Tignor (1993) argued that prior to Nigeria’s independence the country had been a common place where the activities of competing nationalists were based on using the resources at their disposal to build political alliances. Clearly, these alliances were built amongst political elites and were sometimes based on patron-client ties and strengthening bonds of ethnicity. <u><strong><mark>At independence</strong></mark>, such <strong>client-patron ties between the groups favored by the colonial administration had an edge</strong> over those not favored (Leonard, 1991 as cited in Milinge, 1993). Consequently, these favored groups would constitute the earliest Nigerian elite class. The elite class was what Rodney (1972) called the ‘petty bourgeoisie', whose role was to dominate the political and economic life of most African states. According to Leonard (1991, as cited in Milinge et al., 2002) the gaining of independence for this group was merely intended for the breaking of the monopoly of the colonial administrator's political power so that they could further their own advancement and posterity. <strong>These <mark>groups replicated</strong></mark> their British <strong><mark>colonial </mark>master’s technique of <mark>divide and rule</mark> </strong>which involved the practice of favoring one tribe over others with the dual objective of securing loyalty of that group to the administration and encouraging rivalry between different tribes to prevent a sense of unity from evolving and threatening political interests </u>(Mulinge et al., 2002). This voids the arguments of some scholars who were convinced that corruption stemmed primarily from electoral politics in Nigeria’s first republic (1960 – 1966). Tignor (1993) argued that the failure of the military regime that emerged after the first republic undercut the argument that corruption stemmed primarily from electoral politics through stressing the norms and values of the Nigerian elites over more structural explanations. For this study, we will adopt Mulinge et al (2002) normative definition of corruption. Mulinge et al., (2002) normatively defined corruption as the misuse of public authority or resources for personal benefit. <u>Abada et al. (2019) argued that the nature of the Nigerian state was formed in huge extent by its colonial past and the nature of the state explains the nature of associational life within the society. Thus, the theory of postcolonial state and elite theory provide support to hypothesis that <strong><mark>neocolonialism </mark>has <mark>induced corruption</strong></mark> in Nigeria. </u>The impacts of neocolonialism have kept Nigeria in ideologically westernized and material modernity. <u>No wonder, Agang (2016) argued that <strong>corruption is an indication of how the focus on <mark>materialism </mark>has <mark>led to the distortion of </mark>human <mark>dignity </mark>and the sanity of life</strong> and values. According to Agang (2016) the chances of <strong><mark>oppression</mark> and marginalization</strong> of the majority by a peculiar social group is <strong>initiated</strong> by the fascination of the amassment of material wealth <strong>which reduces and <mark>equates human </mark>value <mark>to monetary value</u></strong></mark>. Hence, this has been the case of Nigeria since a gained independence from Britain. Osoba 1996 found that all regimes in Nigeria both military and civilian, have been encompassed by corruption. He argued that the oil boom and its revenues aided and created a deepening crisis of kleptocracy, shown in its greatest form since 1984. <u>The consequences resulted in <strong>a pattern of <mark>scandalous</mark> <mark>wealth</mark> <mark>among</mark> <mark>the</mark> <mark>ruling</mark> class with growing poverty</strong>, unhappiness, <strong>and deprivation</strong> among many Nigerians</u> (Osoba, 1996). <u>Hadden (2016) suggests that resources acquired by corruption tend to be kept outside Nigeria by politicians instead of being invested in the local economy for its intended purpose, which therefore leaves a vacuum, depressing Nigeria’s development</u>. Over the years, Nigerian elitists would not have been able to invest capital in western states without the help of foreign governments and multinational companies. <u>Therefore, <strong>corruption is a way of life in Nigeria abetted by hegemonic powers and is a way of life which existing governments neither wish to, nor can, control.</strong> </u>Abada et al. (2019) echoed that the government has failed to combat corruption. In fact, the January 1966 coup, which was the first military coup in Nigeria that terminated the First Republic, was due to elite corruption and the inconsistency in governance. In the words of the officer, Nzeogwu who orchestrated the coup: “We wanted to get rid of rotten and corrupt ministers, political parties, trades unions and the whole clumsy apparatus of the federal system. We wanted to gun down all the bigwigs on our way. This was the only way. We could not afford to let them live if this was to work. We got some but not all. General Ironsi was to have been shot, but we were not ruthless enough. As a result, he and the other compromisers were able to supplant us.” (Sahara Reporters, 2009) However, transition of power to the military did not solve the epidemic of bad governance and corruption. Suleiman & Karim, (2015) found that the military regime resulted in the abuse of office, corruption, human right violations, and total neglect for the rule of law. Mulinge et al (2002) argued that corruption is not driven by internal factors alone. They argued that corruption is also a consequence of external factors driven by the activities of foreign governments, aid organizations and MNCs seeking to further their own economic interests through actions and practices that condone corrupt practices or that are corrupt in themselves (Mulingeet al., 2002). According to Galtung (1998: 118 as cited in Mulinge et al., 2002) instances of massive corruption have an international dimension where the bribe giver could perhaps be a MNC, or in certain instance a corrupt politician might seek refuge abroad from prosecution in their home country, and the earnings of corruption can be concealed to private accounts in foreign destinations. The elite theory demonstrates that there is the concentration of power in the hands of the few. The autonomy of elites makes it both advantageous and possible for the governing elite strategize and use state resources to control through manipulation and corruption (Etzioni‐Halevy, 1989). This was the case right from Nigeria’s First Republic (government after independence), the country has been tormented by rampant public sector corruption manifesting in poor governance outcomes and severe developmental pathologies. Consequently, this is the reason corruption and bad governance are correlated in this study. In subsequent sections, this study will utilize corruption and bad governance together since in the case of Nigeria they are conceptually intertwined.</p><p><u>2.1.2 Bad Governance and Terrorism</p><p></u>Many scholars have defined governance from various perspectives. According to Okoro (2020) the concept governance implies to the procedure of exercising political power to oversee the activities of the state. According to the UNICEF (2020, as cited in Okoro, 2020) governance constitutes of making and implementing decisions based on considerations like popular participation, respect for the rule of law, observance of human rights, transparency, free access to information, prompt responses to human needs, accommodation of diverse interests, equity, inclusiveness, effective results, and accountability. According to the Mo Ibrahim Foundation (as cited in Okoro, 2020) governance is the provision of the political, social, and economic public goods and services which is a state’s responsibility to deliver to its citizens, and which is a citizen’s right to expect from the government. Also, Fukuyama (2013) defined governance as the capacity of a government to make and implement rules, and to provide services, irrespective of whether that government is democratic or not. Therefore, if a government is unable to fulfil responsibilities such as making and implementing rules then it should be considered bad at governance. Rose et al (2019) argued that bad governance is frequently caused by corruption. Thus, many scholars such as Ibeanu (1998), Abada & Ngwu (2019), and Mbah (2017) have argued that bad governance and corruption go hand in hand. In reviewing existing literatures, the previous section (section 2.1.1) of this study examine corruption separately for clarity because in many countries bad governance can occur without corruption. Nevertheless, in Nigeria bad governance occurs with corruption since the country attained independence in 1960. Thus, in subsequent sections of this study bad governance and corruption will be combined textually. As much as there are several literatures on corruption in Africa, especially in Nigeria, there is a literature on bad governance in Nigeria. However, much of this literature has not tried to connect neocolonialism to bad governance as well as determine the extent to which a linear causal relationship between the two factors has exacerbated terrorist activities in Nigeria. Suleiman et al (2015) found that literature covering terrorist activities in the northern part of Nigeria dwelled mostly on the origin and activities of the groups through their radicalization on a religious platform. Most analyses of these existing literature have been based on the emergence of terrorist groups and activities through a religious prism (Suleiman et al., 2015). <u>However, scholars such Abada and Ngwu (2019) attempted to establish that <strong>bad governance and corruption</strong> in Nigeria has <strong>given rise to</strong> certain societal challenges that led to <strong>insurgency</strong>. For instance, in the study of Abada et al. (2019) which is anchored on the theory of post-colonial state, they argued that <strong>the misuse of public resources and the failure of governance have provoked <mark>mass poverty i</strong></mark>n Nigeria <strong>which has <mark>led to </mark>the advent of <mark>terrorist groups</strong></mark> that resort to the use of force in the expression of their discontent</u>. Uzodike et al (2012) <u>have argued that the terrorist activities of <strong><mark>Boko Haram</strong></mark> are <strong><mark>triggered by </mark>a combination of bad governance</strong>, including the prevalent failures of state policies, inefficient and wasteful parastatals, and <strong><mark>endemic corruption, poverty</strong></mark>, unemployment, and extensive underdevelopment in the northern Nigeria. </u>Essentially, Uzodike et al. (2012) failed to emphasize that inefficient and wasteful parastatals, poverty, unemployment, and extensive underdevelopment will not be feasible without bad governance and corruption. As a result, Nigeria is institutionally constituted so that it enjoys limited independence from the elite class highlighted in section 2.1.1. <u>Therefore, these elites are the perpetrators of bad governance in Nigeria, and they are also responsible for the frustration of the citizens of Nigeria. Okoro (2020) demonstrated that the Boko Haram insurgency is a retaliation against bad governance, notably in northern Nigeria where the epidemic of poverty led to frustration and recourse to terror activities among the people, particularly the youth.</u> He found weaknesses in previous justifications of scholars and analysts who opined that Islamic fundamentalism, and the emergence of an elite violent political competition between northern and southern Nigeria especially after Goodluck Jonathan emerged as president was responsible for the Boko Haram activities. <u>T<strong>he elite’s <mark>private accumulation </mark>resources at the expense of the public <mark>destabilizes</strong></mark> the <strong><mark>state</strong></mark>’s <strong><mark>institutions</strong></mark> therefore <strong><mark>fostering inequality, underdevelopment, and endangering</strong></mark> the <strong><mark>lives</strong></mark> of citizens whom these public institutions are meant to serve. Therefore, Okoro (2020) argued that the membership profile of Boko Haram reveals that <strong><mark>poverty and </mark>economic <mark>inequality are </mark>at <mark>its roots</mark>. However, he failed denote a strong link on what exactly causes poverty and economic inequality that leads to terrorist activities. It could possibly be embedded in what Okoro recognized as the weak nature of governance. Importantly, he found that bad governance in Nigeria served as a broader function in the emergence and growth of terrorist activities of Boko Haram.</p></u></strong> | AC | null | Colonialism | 1,704,181 | 134 | 168,171 | ./documents/hsld22/StrakeJesuitCollegePreparatory/OlZh/StrakeJesuitCollegePreparatory-OlZh-Aff-49th-Harvard-National-Forensics-Tournament-Round-1.docx | 978,226 | A | 49th Harvard National Forensics Tournament | 1 | Edina DS | Piliero | AC - Africa
NC - Cap K
AR - case
NR - all
AR - same | hsld22/StrakeJesuitCollegePreparatory/OlZh/StrakeJesuitCollegePreparatory-OlZh-Aff-49th-Harvard-National-Forensics-Tournament-Round-1.docx | 2023-02-18 17:17:04 | 80,561 | OlZh | Strake Jesuit College Preparatory OlZh | Hi.
If I don't meet any of your theory interpretations, please message me what to change. Like you, I also want to set the best norms for debate. If not, then by default I meet these theory interpretations. | Ol..... | Zh..... | null | null | 27,049 | StrakeJesuitCollegePreparatory | Strake Jesuit College Preparatory | TX | 36,501 | 2,003 | hsld22 | HS LD 2022-23 | 2,022 | ld | hs | 1 |
1,394,826 | ***Extinction first – always VTL | Bernstein ‘2 | Bernstein ‘2 | There is a basic value inherent in organic being, a basic affirmation, "The Yes' of Life" (IR 81). 15 "The self-affirmation of being becomes emphatic in the opposition of life to death this affirmation of life that is in all organic being has a binding obligatory force upon human beings. This blindly self-enacting "yes" gains obligating force in the seeing freedom of man, who as the supreme outcome of nature's purposive labor is no longer its automatic executor but, with the power obtained from knowledge, can become its destroyer as well. He must adopt the "yes" into his will and impose the "no" to not-being on his power Modern technology has transformed the nature and consequences of human action so radically that the underlying premises of traditional ethics are no longer valid. For the first time in history human beings possess the knowledge and the power to destroy life on this planet, including human life. Not only is there the new possibility of total nuclear disaster; there are the even more invidious and threatening possibilities that result from the unconstrained use of technologies that can destroy the environment required for life. We need a new categorical imperative that might be as follows: Act so that the effects of your action are compatible with the permanence of genuine human life"; or expressed negatively Do not compromise the conditions for an indefinite continuation of humanity on earth"; or again turned positive: | There is a basic value inherent in being emphatic in the opposition to death this affirmation has a binding obligatory force Modern technology transformed consequences of human action so traditional ethics are no longer valid human beings possess power to destroy this planet a new categorical imperative might be Do not compromise an indefinite continuation of humanity on earth | (Richard J., Vera List Prof. Phil. – New School for Social Research, “Radical Evil: A Philosophical Interrogation”, p. 188-192)
There is a basic value inherent in organic being, a basic affirmation, "The Yes' of Life" (IR 81). 15 "The self-affirmation of being becomes emphatic in the opposition of life to death. Life is the explicit confrontation of being with not-being. . . . The 'yes' of all striving is here sharpened by the active `no' to not-being" (IR 81-2). Furthermore — and this is the crucial point for Jonas — this affirmation of life that is in all organic being has a binding obligatory force upon human beings. This blindly self-enacting "yes" gains obligating force in the seeing freedom of man, who as the supreme outcome of nature's purposive labor is no longer its automatic executor but, with the power obtained from knowledge, can become its destroyer as well. He must adopt the "yes" into his will and impose the "no" to not-being on his power. But precisely this transition from willing to obligation is the critical point of moral theory at which attempts at laying a foundation for it come so easily to grief. Why does now, in man, that become a duty which hitherto "being" itself took care of through all individual willings? (IR 82). We discover here the transition from is to "ought" — from the self-affirmation of life to the binding obligation of human beings to preserve life not only for the present but also for the future. But why do we need a new ethics? The subtitle of The Imperative of Responsibility — In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age — indicates why we need a new ethics. Modern technology has transformed the nature and consequences of human action so radically that the underlying premises of traditional ethics are no longer valid. For the first time in history human beings possess the knowledge and the power to destroy life on this planet, including human life. Not only is there the new possibility of total nuclear disaster; there are the even more invidious and threatening possibilities that result from the unconstrained use of technologies that can destroy the environment required for life. The major transformation brought about by modern technology is that the consequences of our actions frequently exceed by far anything we can envision. Jonas was one of the first philosophers to warn us about the unprecedented ethical and political problems that arise with the rapid development of biotechnology. He claimed that this was happening at a time when there was an "ethical vacuum," when there did not seem to be any effective ethical principles to limit ot guide our ethical decisions. In the name of scientific and technological "progress," there is a relentless pressure to adopt a stance where virtually anything is permissible, includ-ing transforming the genetic structure of human beings, as long as it is "freely chosen." We need, Jonas argued, a new categorical imperative that might be formulated as follows: "Act so that the effects of your action are compatible with the permanence of genuine human life"; or expressed negatively: "Act so that the effects of your action are not destructive of the future possibility of such a life"; or simply: "Do not compromise the conditions for an indefinite continuation of humanity on earth"; or again turned positive: "In your present choices, include the future wholeness of Man among the objects of your will." | 3,438 | <h4><strong>***Extinction first – always VTL</h4><p>Bernstein ‘2</p><p></strong>(Richard J., Vera List Prof. Phil. – New School for Social Research, “Radical Evil: A Philosophical Interrogation”, p. 188-192)</p><p><u><strong><mark>There is a basic value inherent in</mark> organic <mark>being</mark>, a basic affirmation, "The Yes' of Life" (IR 81). 15 "The self-affirmation of being becomes <mark>emphatic in the opposition</strong></mark> <strong>of life <mark>to death</u></strong></mark>. Life is the explicit confrontation of being with not-being. . . . The 'yes' of all striving is here sharpened by the active `no' to not-being" (IR 81-2). Furthermore — and this is the crucial point for Jonas — <u><strong><mark>this affirmation</mark> of life that is in </strong>all organic<strong> being <mark>has a binding obligatory force</mark> upon human beings. This blindly self-enacting "yes" gains obligating force in the seeing freedom of man, who as the supreme outcome of nature's purposive labor is no longer its automatic executor but, with the power obtained from knowledge, can become its destroyer as well. He must adopt the "yes" into his will and impose the "no" to not-being on his power</u></strong>. But precisely this transition from willing to obligation is the critical point of moral theory at which attempts at laying a foundation for it come so easily to grief. Why does now, in man, that become a duty which hitherto "being" itself took care of through all individual willings? (IR 82). We discover here the transition from is to "ought" — from the self-affirmation of life to the binding obligation of human beings to preserve life not only for the present but also for the future. But why do we need a new ethics? The subtitle of The Imperative of Responsibility — In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age — indicates why we need a new ethics. <u><strong><mark>Modern technology</mark> has <mark>transformed</mark> the nature and <mark>consequences of human action so</mark> radically that the underlying premises of <mark>traditional ethics are no longer valid</mark>. For the first time in history <mark>human beings possess</mark> the knowledge and the <mark>power to destroy</mark> </strong>life on <strong><mark>this planet</mark>, including human life. Not only is there the new possibility of total nuclear disaster; there are the even more invidious and threatening possibilities that result from the unconstrained use of technologies that can destroy the environment required for life. </u></strong>The major transformation brought about by modern technology is that the consequences of our actions frequently exceed by far anything we can envision. Jonas was one of the first philosophers to warn us about the unprecedented ethical and political problems that arise with the rapid development of biotechnology. He claimed that this was happening at a time when there was an "ethical vacuum," when there did not seem to be any effective ethical principles to limit ot guide our ethical decisions. In the name of scientific and technological "progress," there is a relentless pressure to adopt a stance where virtually anything is permissible, includ-ing transforming the genetic structure of human beings, as long as it is "freely chosen." <u><strong>We need</u></strong>, Jonas argued, <u><strong><mark>a new categorical imperative</mark> that <mark>might be</mark> </u></strong>formulated <u><strong>as follows: </u></strong>"<u><strong>Act so that the effects of your action are compatible with the permanence of genuine human life"; or expressed negatively</u></strong>: "Act so that the effects of your action are not destructive of the future possibility of such a life"; or simply: "<u><strong><mark>Do not compromise</mark> the conditions for <mark>an indefinite continuation of humanity on earth</mark>"; or again turned positive:</u></strong> "In your present choices, include the future wholeness of Man among the objects of your will."</p> | null | null | K | 92,494 | 202 | 37,205 | ./documents/hspolicy14/NewTrier/ByLo/New%20Trier-Byrne-Lowe-Aff-Iowa%20Caucus-Round4.docx | 635,744 | A | Iowa Caucus | 4 | Wayzata GA | Ian Miller | 1AC- NOPP (MSL and No War)
1NC2NR- Blow Up Debate | hspolicy14/NewTrier/ByLo/New%20Trier-Byrne-Lowe-Aff-Iowa%20Caucus-Round4.docx | null | 53,679 | ByLo | New Trier ByLo | null | AJ..... | By..... | Wi..... | Lo..... | 19,615 | NewTrier | New Trier | null | null | 1,013 | hspolicy14 | HS Policy 2014-15 | 2,014 | cx | hs | 2 |
843,398 | Reps don’t cause war – remember the AFF said ME presence is bad | Reiter 95 | Reiter 95 DAN REITER is a Professor of Political Science at Emory University and has been an Olin post-doctoral fellow in security studies at Harvard “Exploring the Powder Keg Myth” International Security v20 No2 Autumn 1995 pp 5-34 JSTOR | Therefore, if preemptive wars seem infrequent within the set of wars alone, then this would have to be considered strong evidence in favor of the most skeptical view of preemptive war even when the sample is rigged to make preemptive wars seem frequent they are still rare events The rarity of preemptive wars offers preliminary support for the view, that the preemption scenario does not tell us much about how war breaks out Closer examination casts doubt on the validity of hypotheses that hostile images of the enemy increase the chances of preemption such fears may not be sufficient to cause war the conditions hypothesized to stimulate preemption—hostile images of the adversary are present to a very high degree these are insubstantial causal forces This reduces even further the significance of these forces as causes of war. a relationship is not demonstrated by the results of such a test. | if preemptive wars seem infrequent this would be most skeptical view Close examination casts doubt on the validity of hypotheses that hostile images of the enemy increase the chances fears may not be sufficient to cause war hostile images are present to a very high degree. these are insubstantial causal forces This reduces significance of these as causes of war | A criticism of assessing the frequency of preemptive wars by looking only at wars themselves is that this misses the non-events, that is, instances in which preemption would be predicted but did not occur. However, excluding non-events should bias the results in favor of finding that preemptive war is an important path to war, as the inclusion of non-events could only make it seem that the event was less frequent. Therefore, if preemptive wars seem infrequent within the set of wars alone, then this would have to be considered strong evidence in favor of the third, most skeptical view of preemptive war, because even when the sample is rigged to make preemptive wars seem frequent (by including only wars), they are still rare events. Below, a few cases in which preemption did not occur are discussed to illustrate factors that constrain preemption. The rarity of preemptive wars offers preliminary support for the third, most skeptical view, that the preemption scenario does not tell us much about how war breaks out. Closer examination of the three cases of preemption, set forth below, casts doubt on the validity of the two preemption hypotheses discussed earlier: that hostile images of the enemy increase the chances of preemption, and that belief in the dominance of the offense increases the chances of preemption. In each case there are motives for war aside from fear of an imminent attack, indicating that such fears may not be sufficient to cause war. In addition, in these cases of war the two conditions hypothesized to stimulate preemption—hostile images of the adversary and belief in the military advantages of striking first—are present to a very high degree. This implies that these are insubstantial causal forces, as they are associated with the outbreak of war only when they are present to a very high degree. This reduces even further the significance of these forces as causes of war. To illustrate this point, consider an analogy: say there is a hypothesis that saccharin causes cancer. Discovering that rats who were fed a lot of saccharin and also received high levels of X-ray exposure, which we know causes cancer, had a higher risk for cancer does not, however, set off alarm bells about the risks of saccharin. Though there might be a relationship between saccharin consumption and cancer, this is not demonstrated by the results of such a test. | 2,385 | <h4>Reps don’t cause war – remember the AFF said ME presence is bad</h4><p><strong>Reiter 95</strong> DAN REITER is a Professor of Political Science at Emory University and has been an Olin post-doctoral fellow in security studies at Harvard “Exploring the Powder Keg Myth” International Security v20 No2 Autumn 1995 pp<u> 5-34 JSTOR</p><p></u>A criticism of assessing the frequency of preemptive wars by looking only at wars themselves is that this misses the non-events, that is, instances in which preemption would be predicted but did not occur. However, excluding non-events should bias the results in favor of finding that preemptive war is an important path to war, as the inclusion of non-events could only make it seem that the event was less frequent. <u><strong>There</strong>fore, <mark>if preemptive wars seem infrequent</mark> within the set of wars alone, then <mark>this would</mark> have to <mark>be</mark> considered strong evidence in favor of the</u> third, <u><strong><mark>most skeptical view</mark> of preemptive war</u></strong>, because <u>even when the sample is rigged to make preemptive wars seem frequent</u> (by including only wars), <u>they are still rare events</u>. Below, a few cases in which preemption did not occur are discussed to illustrate factors that constrain preemption. <u>The rarity of preemptive wars offers preliminary support for the</u> third, most skeptical <u>view, that the preemption scenario does not tell us much about how war breaks out</u>. <u><strong><mark>Close</mark>r <mark>examination</u></strong></mark> of the three cases of preemption, set forth below, <u><strong><mark>casts doubt on the validity of</u></strong></mark> the two preemption <u><strong><mark>hypotheses</u></strong></mark> discussed earlier: <u><strong><mark>that hostile images of the enemy increase the chances</mark> of preemption</u></strong>, and that belief in the dominance of the offense increases the chances of preemption. In each case there are motives for war aside from fear of an imminent attack, indicating that <u><strong>such <mark>fears may not be sufficient to cause war</u></strong></mark>. In addition, in these cases of war <u><strong>the</u></strong> two <u><strong>conditions hypothesized to stimulate preemption—<mark>hostile images </mark>of the adversary</u></strong> and belief in the military advantages of striking first—<u><strong><mark>are present to a very high degree</u></strong>.</mark> This implies that <u><strong><mark>these are insubstantial causal forces</u></strong></mark>, as they are associated with the outbreak of war only when they are present to a very high degree. <u><strong><mark>This reduces</mark> even further the <mark>significance of these</mark> forces <mark>as causes of war</mark>.</u></strong> To illustrate this point, consider an analogy: say there is a hypothesis that saccharin causes cancer. Discovering that rats who were fed a lot of saccharin and also received high levels of X-ray exposure, which we know causes cancer, had a higher risk for cancer does not, however, set off alarm bells about the risks of saccharin. Though there might be <u><strong>a relationship</u></strong> between saccharin consumption and cancer, this <u><strong>is not demonstrated by the results of such a test.</p></u></strong> | 2ac | case | Reps | 18,253 | 126 | 20,098 | ./documents/ndtceda15/Kentucky/HaRo/Kentucky-Hampton-Roman-Aff-GSU-Round8.docx | 583,048 | A | GSU | 8 | West Georgia MS | Brass | 1ac - same as round 4
1nc
white supremacy k
2nr
white supremacy k | ndtceda15/Kentucky/HaRo/Kentucky-Hampton-Roman-Aff-GSU-Round8.docx | null | 49,802 | HaRo | Kentucky HaRo | null | Ho..... | Ha..... | Ma..... | Ro..... | 18,958 | Kentucky | Kentucky | null | null | 1,005 | ndtceda15 | NDT/CEDA 2015-16 | 2,015 | cx | college | 2 |
1,412,379 | No chance of war from economic decline---best and most recent data | Drezner 12 | Drezner 12, | The final outcome addresses the effect of the Great Recession on cross-border conflict analysts asserted the financial crisis would lead states to increase use of force internal repression, diversionary wars, arms races, or great power conflict
aggregate data suggests otherwise The average level of peacefulness in 2012 is the same as 2007 Interstate violence has declined since the start of the financial crisis as have military expenditures studies confirm the Great Recession has not triggered any increase in violent conflict the crisis has not generated protectionist nationalism or ethnic exclusion that might have been expected
Given the severity, reach and depth of the 2008 financial crisis the proper comparison is with Great Depression by that standard, the outcome variables look impressive | analysts asserted crisis would lead states to use force diversionary wars or great power conflict
aggregate data suggests otherwise, average peacefulness in 2012 is the same as 07 Interstate violence has declined since the financial crisis studies confirm the Recession has not triggered any increase in violent conflict not generated protectionist nationalism or ethnic exclusion
Given the severity, reach and depth of the 08 crisis, the proper comparison is with Depression by that standard, the outcome look impressive | Daniel W. Professor, The Fletcher School of Law and Diplomacy, Tufts University, October 2012, “The Irony of Global Economic Governance: The System Worked,” http://www.globaleconomicgovernance.org/wp-content/uploads/IR-Colloquium-MT12-Week-5_The-Irony-of-Global-Economic-Governance.pdf
The final outcome addresses a dog that hasn’t barked: the effect of the Great Recession on cross-border conflict and violence. During the initial stages of the crisis, multiple analysts asserted that the financial crisis would lead states to increase their use of force as a tool for staying in power.37 Whether through greater internal repression, diversionary wars, arms races, or a ratcheting up of great power conflict, there were genuine concerns that the global economic downturn would lead to an increase in conflict. Violence in the Middle East, border disputes in the South China Sea, and even the disruptions of the Occupy movement fuel impressions of surge in global public disorder.
The aggregate data suggests otherwise, however. The Institute for Economics and Peace has constructed a “Global Peace Index” annually since 2007. A key conclusion they draw from the 2012 report is that “The average level of peacefulness in 2012 is approximately the same as it was in 2007.”38 Interstate violence in particular has declined since the start of the financial crisis – as have military expenditures in most sampled countries. Other studies confirm that the Great Recession has not triggered any increase in violent conflict; the secular decline in violence that started with the end of the Cold War has not been reversed.39 Rogers Brubaker concludes, “the crisis has not to date generated the surge in protectionist nationalism or ethnic exclusion that might have been expected.”40
None of these data suggest that the global economy is operating swimmingly. Growth remains unbalanced and fragile, and has clearly slowed in 2012. Transnational capital flows remain depressed compared to pre-crisis levels, primarily due to a drying up of cross-border interbank lending in Europe. Currency volatility remains an ongoing concern. Compared to the aftermath of other postwar recessions, growth in output, investment, and employment in the developed world have all lagged behind. But the Great Recession is not like other postwar recessions in either scope or kind; expecting a standard “V”-shaped recovery was unreasonable. One financial analyst characterized the post-2008 global economy as in a state of “contained depression.”41 The key word is “contained,” however. Given the severity, reach and depth of the 2008 financial crisis, the proper comparison is with Great Depression. And by that standard, the outcome variables look impressive. As Carmen Reinhart and Kenneth Rogoff concluded in This Time is Different: “that its macroeconomic outcome has been only the most severe global recession since World War II – and not even worse – must be regarded as fortunate.”42 | 2,963 | <h4><u>No</u> chance of war from economic decline---<u>best</u> and <u>most recent</u> data </h4><p><strong>Drezner 12</strong>,</p><p>Daniel W. Professor, The Fletcher School of Law and Diplomacy, Tufts University, October 2012, “The Irony of Global Economic Governance: The System Worked,” http://www.globaleconomicgovernance.org/wp-content/uploads/IR-Colloquium-MT12-Week-5_The-Irony-of-Global-Economic-Governance.pdf</p><p><u><strong>The final outcome addresses</u></strong> a dog that hasn’t barked: <u><strong>the effect of the Great Recession on cross-border conflict</u></strong> and violence. During the initial stages of the crisis, multiple <u><strong><mark>analysts asserted</u></strong></mark> that <u><strong>the financial <mark>crisis would lead states to</mark> increase</u></strong> their <u><strong><mark>use</mark> of <mark>force</u></strong></mark> as a tool for staying in power.37 Whether through greater <u><strong>internal repression, <mark>diversionary wars</mark>, arms races, <mark>or</u></strong></mark> a ratcheting up of <u><strong><mark>great power conflict</u></strong></mark>, there were genuine concerns that the global economic downturn would lead to an increase in conflict. Violence in the Middle East, border disputes in the South China Sea, and even the disruptions of the Occupy movement fuel impressions of surge in global public disorder. </p><p>The <u><strong><mark>aggregate data suggests otherwise</u></strong>,</mark> however. The Institute for Economics and Peace has constructed a “Global Peace Index” annually since 2007. A key conclusion they draw from the 2012 report is that “<u><strong>The <mark>average</mark> level of <mark>peacefulness in 2012 is</u></strong></mark> approximately <u><strong><mark>the same as</u></strong></mark> it was in <u><strong>20<mark>07</u></strong></mark>.”38 <u><strong><mark>Interstate violence</u></strong></mark> in particular <u><strong><mark>has</u></strong> <u><strong>declined</u></strong> <u><strong>since the</mark> start of the <mark>financial crisis</u></strong></mark> – <u><strong>as have military expenditures</u></strong> in most sampled countries. Other <u><strong><mark>studies confirm</u></strong></mark> that <u><strong><mark>the</mark> Great <mark>Recession has</u></strong> <u><strong>not triggered any increase in violent conflict</u></strong></mark>; the secular decline in violence that started with the end of the Cold War has not been reversed.39 Rogers Brubaker concludes, “<u><strong>the crisis has <mark>not</u></strong></mark> to date <u><strong><mark>generated</u></strong></mark> the surge in <u><strong><mark>protectionist nationalism or ethnic exclusion</mark> that might have been expected</u></strong>.”40</p><p>None of these data suggest that the global economy is operating swimmingly. Growth remains unbalanced and fragile, and has clearly slowed in 2012. Transnational capital flows remain depressed compared to pre-crisis levels, primarily due to a drying up of cross-border interbank lending in Europe. Currency volatility remains an ongoing concern. Compared to the aftermath of other postwar recessions, growth in output, investment, and employment in the developed world have all lagged behind. But the Great Recession is not like other postwar recessions in either scope or kind; expecting a standard “V”-shaped recovery was unreasonable. One financial analyst characterized the post-2008 global economy as in a state of “contained depression.”41 The key word is “contained,” however. <u><strong><mark>Given the severity, reach and depth of the</mark> 20<mark>08</mark> financial <mark>crisis</u></strong>, <u><strong>the proper comparison is with</mark> Great <mark>Depression</u></strong></mark>. And <u><strong><mark>by that standard, the outcome</mark> variables <mark>look impressive</u></strong></mark>. As Carmen Reinhart and Kenneth Rogoff concluded in This Time is Different: “that its macroeconomic outcome has been only the most severe global recession since World War II – and not even worse – must be regarded as fortunate.”42</p> | Round 4 | 2AC | Ex-Im Politics DA | 36,454 | 444 | 38,387 | ./documents/ndtceda15/Wyoming/MaMc/Wyoming-Marcum-McFarland-Aff-Harvard-Round4.docx | 586,471 | A | Harvard | 4 | Kentucky Grasse-Noparstak | DeLong | 1AC - CSGs
Advantages- Crisis Instability SLOCS
1NC - T Power Projection Consult JOC CMR DA Assurance DA Ex-Im Politics DA Security K
2N - Assurance DA | ndtceda15/Wyoming/MaMc/Wyoming-Marcum-McFarland-Aff-Harvard-Round4.docx | null | 50,103 | MaMc | Wyoming MaMc | null | Ma..... | Ma..... | Hu..... | Mc..... | 19,005 | Wyoming | Wyoming | null | null | 1,005 | ndtceda15 | NDT/CEDA 2015-16 | 2,015 | cx | college | 2 |
1,147,158 | Zero impact – perceived vulnerability isn’t true – no impact on national security even from massive blackouts | Clark 12 | Paul Clark 12, MA Candidate, Intelligence/Terrorism Studies, American Military University; Senior Analyst, Chenega Federal Systems, 4/28/12, “The Risk of Disruption or Destruction of Critical U.S. Infrastructure by an Offensive Cyber Attack,” http://blog.havagan.com/wp-content/uploads/2012/05/The-Risk-of-Disruption-or-Destruction-of-Critical-U.S.-Infrastructure-by-an-Offensive-Cyber-Attack.pdf | In 2003, a physical breakdown occurred This singular occurrence has been used as evidence that the grid is fragile and subject to severe disruption through cyber-attack, This perceived fragility is not real when viewed in the context of the robustness of the electrical grid intelligence chief of U.S. Cyber Command stated an attack was unlikely to succeed because of the "huge amounts of resiliency built into the [electrical] system that makes that kind of catastrophic thing very difficult This is supported by a grid that has proven robust in the face of large natural catastrophes the U.S. grid fails frequently Power outages have occurred steadily the effect is mitigated by policies and procedures that are meant to restore services as quickly as possible The electrical grid suffers service interruptions regularly and yet commerce does not collapse the economy is affected but does not collapse and even after massive damage national security is not affected because U.S. military capability is not degraded increased focus on cyber-security has led to concern that the perceived risk is greater than the actual risk cyber-war is "more hype than hazard" most cyber-attacks are categorized as information theft, network compromise, or website defacement Even the high profile threat of an "Electronic Pearl Harbor despite being repeated by senior government officials has been found to be only a slight possibility | perceived fragility is not real when viewed in the context of the robustness of the grid an attack was unlikely to succeed because of huge amounts of resiliency built in grid has proven robust in the face of large catastrophes Power outage is mitigated by policies that restore services quickly The grid suffers service interruptions regularly yet commerce does not collapse the economy does not collapse national security is not affected because U.S. military capability is not degraded cyber-war is " hype a slight possibility | In 2003, a simple physical breakdown occurred - trees shorted a power line and caused a fault - that had a cascading effect and caused a power blackout across the Northeast (Lewis 2010). This singular occurrence has been used as evidence that the electrical grid is fragile and subject to severe disruption through cyber-attack, a disruption that could cost billions of dollars, brings business to a halt, and could even endanger lives - if compounded by other catastrophic events (Brennan 2012). A power disruption the size of the 2003 blackout, the worst in American history at that time (Minkel 2008), is a worst case scenario and used as an example of the fragility of the U.S. energy grid. This perceived fragility is not real when viewed in the context of the robustness of the electrical grid.¶ When asked about cyber-attacks against the electrical grid in April of 2012. the intelligence chief of U.S. Cyber Command Rear Admiral Samuel Cox stated that an attack was unlikely to succeed because of the "huge amounts of resiliency built into the [electrical] system that makes that kind of catastrophic thing very difficult" (Capaccio 2012). This optimistic view is supported by an electrical grid that has proven to be robust in the face of large natural catastrophes. Complex systems like the electrical grid in the U.S. are prone to failures and the U.S. grid fails frequently. Despite efforts to reduce the risk out power outages, the risk is always present. Power outages that affect more than 50.000 people have occurred steadily over the last 20 years at a rate of 12% annually and the frequency of large catastrophes remains relatively high and outages the size of the 2003 blackout are predicted to occur every 25 years (Minkel 2008). In a complex system that is always at risk of disruption, the effect is mitigated by policies and procedures that are meant to restore services as quickly as possible. The most visible of these policies is the interstate Emergency Management Assistance Compact, a legally binding agreement allowing combined resources to be quickly deployed in response to a catastrophic disaster such as power outages following a severe hurricane (Kapucu, Augustin and Garayev 2009).¶ The electrical grid suffers service interruptions regularly, it is a large and complex system supporting the largest economy in the world, and yet commerce does not collapse (Lewis 2010). Despite blizzards, earthquakes, fires, and hurricanes that cause blackouts, the economy is affected but does not collapse and even after massive damage like that caused by Hurricane Katrina, national security is not affected because U.S. military capability is not degraded (Lewis 2010).¶ Cyber-security is an ever-increasing concern in an increasingly electronic and interconnected world. Cyber-security is a high priority "economic and national security challenge" (National Security Council n.d.) because cyber-attacks are expected to become the top national security threat (Robert S. Mueller 2012). In response to the threat Congress is crafting legislation to enhance cyber-security (Brito and Watkins 2012) and the Department of Homeland Security budget for cyber-security has been significantly increased (U.S. Senate Committee on Homeland Security and Governmental Affairs 2012).¶ This increased focus on cyber-security has led to concern that the perceived risk is greater than the actual risk, a situation that has resulted in an imbalance between security and privacy and civil liberties (American Civil Liberties Union 2012). In 1993 a Rand Corporation paper predicted that "cyberwar is coming" and twenty years later the prediction is the same and critics argue that cyber-war is "more hype than hazard" (Rid 2012). A review of high profile cyber-attacks shows that, with the exception of Stuxnet and the limited Israeli disruption of Syrian air defense networks, most cyber-attacks are categorized as information theft, network compromise, or website defacement (Lewis 2012). Even the high profile threat of an "Electronic Pearl Harbor" (Bronk 2009). despite being repeated by senior government officials like U.S. Defense Secretary Leon Panetta (Rid 2012) , has been found to be only a slight possibility (Wilson 2005). | 4,242 | <h4>Zero impact – <u>perceived</u> vulnerability isn’t true – no impact on national security even from massive blackouts </h4><p>Paul <strong>Clark 12</strong>, MA Candidate, Intelligence/Terrorism Studies, American Military University; Senior Analyst, Chenega Federal Systems, 4/28/12, “The Risk of Disruption or Destruction of Critical U.S. Infrastructure by an Offensive Cyber Attack,” http://blog.havagan.com/wp-content/uploads/2012/05/The-Risk-of-Disruption-or-Destruction-of-Critical-U.S.-Infrastructure-by-an-Offensive-Cyber-Attack.pdf</p><p><u>In 2003, a</u> simple <u>physical breakdown occurred</u> - trees shorted a power line and caused a fault - that had a cascading effect and caused a power blackout across the Northeast (Lewis 2010). <u>This</u> <u>singular occurrence</u> <u>has been used as evidence that the</u> electrical <u>grid is fragile and subject to severe disruption through cyber-attack,</u> a disruption that could cost billions of dollars, brings business to a halt, and could even endanger lives - if compounded by other catastrophic events (Brennan 2012). A power disruption the size of the 2003 blackout, the worst in American history at that time (Minkel 2008), is a worst case scenario and used as an example of the fragility of the U.S. energy grid. <u>This</u> <u><mark>perceived fragility</u> <u>is</u> <u>not real</u> <u>when viewed in the context of the</u> <u>robustness of the </mark>electrical <mark>grid</u></mark>.¶ When asked about cyber-attacks against the electrical grid in April of 2012. the <u>intelligence chief of U.S. Cyber Command</u> Rear Admiral Samuel Cox <u>stated</u> that <u><mark>an attack was unlikely to succeed</u> <u>because of</mark> the</u> <u>"<mark>huge amounts of resiliency</u> <u>built in</mark>to the [electrical] system that makes that kind of catastrophic thing very difficult</u>" (Capaccio 2012). <u>This</u> optimistic view <u>is supported by a</u>n electrical <u><mark>grid</mark> that <mark>has proven</u></mark> to be <u><mark>robust in the face of large </mark>natural <mark>catastrophes</u></mark>. Complex systems like the electrical grid in the U.S. are prone to failures and <u>the U.S. grid fails frequently</u>. Despite efforts to reduce the risk out power outages, the risk is always present. <u><mark>Power outage</mark>s</u> that affect more than 50.000 people <u>have occurred steadily</u> over the last 20 years at a rate of 12% annually and the frequency of large catastrophes remains relatively high and outages the size of the 2003 blackout are predicted to occur every 25 years (Minkel 2008). In a complex system that is always at risk of disruption, <u>the effect <mark>is mitigated by policies</mark> and procedures <mark>that</mark> are meant to <mark>restore services</mark> as <mark>quickly</mark> as possible</u>. The most visible of these policies is the interstate Emergency Management Assistance Compact, a legally binding agreement allowing combined resources to be quickly deployed in response to a catastrophic disaster such as power outages following a severe hurricane (Kapucu, Augustin and Garayev 2009).¶ <u><mark>The</mark> electrical <mark>grid suffers service interruptions regularly</u></mark>, it is a large and complex system supporting the largest economy in the world, <u>and <mark>yet <strong>commerce does not collapse</u></strong></mark> (Lewis 2010). Despite blizzards, earthquakes, fires, and hurricanes that cause blackouts, <u><mark>the</mark> <mark>economy</mark> is affected but</u> <u><strong><mark>does not collapse</u></strong></mark> <u>and even after massive damage</u> like that caused by Hurricane Katrina, <u><strong><mark>national security is not affected</u></strong> <u>because</u> <u><strong>U.S. military capability is not degraded</u></strong></mark> (Lewis 2010).¶ Cyber-security is an ever-increasing concern in an increasingly electronic and interconnected world. Cyber-security is a high priority "economic and national security challenge" (National Security Council n.d.) because cyber-attacks are expected to become the top national security threat (Robert S. Mueller 2012). In response to the threat Congress is crafting legislation to enhance cyber-security (Brito and Watkins 2012) and the Department of Homeland Security budget for cyber-security has been significantly increased (U.S. Senate Committee on Homeland Security and Governmental Affairs 2012).¶ This <u>increased focus on cyber-security has led to concern that the</u> <u>perceived risk is greater than the actual risk</u>, a situation that has resulted in an imbalance between security and privacy and civil liberties (American Civil Liberties Union 2012). In 1993 a Rand Corporation paper predicted that "cyberwar is coming" and twenty years later the prediction is the same and critics argue that <u><mark>cyber-war is <strong>"</mark>more <mark>hype </mark>than hazard" </u></strong>(Rid 2012). A review of high profile cyber-attacks shows that, with the exception of Stuxnet and the limited Israeli disruption of Syrian air defense networks, <u>most cyber-attacks are categorized as information theft, network compromise, or website defacement</u> (Lewis 2012). <u>Even the high profile threat of an "Electronic Pearl Harbor</u>" (Bronk 2009). <u>despite being repeated by senior government officials</u> like U.S. Defense Secretary Leon Panetta (Rid 2012) , <u>has been found to be</u> <u><strong>only <mark>a slight possibility</u></strong></mark> (Wilson 2005).</p> | 1NC | Case | 1NC – Russia ADV | 37,079 | 211 | 28,185 | ./documents/hspolicy21/Mamaroneck/DaTr/Mamaroneck-Davis-Tretiak-Neg-Michigan-Round6.docx | 750,673 | N | Michigan | 6 | Maine East TS | Sonny Patel | 1AC - Cyber Infrastructure
2NR - States CP Infrastructure DA | hspolicy21/Mamaroneck/DaTr/Mamaroneck-Davis-Tretiak-Neg-Michigan-Round6.docx | null | 64,039 | DaTr | Mamaroneck DaTr | null | Jo..... | Da..... | Ki..... | Tr..... | 22,044 | Mamaroneck | Mamaroneck | NY | null | 1,020 | hspolicy21 | HS Policy 2021-22 | 2,021 | cx | hs | 2 |
3,673,262 | No risk of food wars – empirics prove | Allouche 11 | Jeremy Allouche 11, Research Fellow at the Institute of Development Studies at the University of Sussex, "The sustainability and resilience of global water and food systems: Political analysis of the interplay between security, resource scarcity, political systems and global trade" Food PolicyVolume 36, Supplement 1, January 2011, Pages S3-S8 Accessed via: Science Direct Sciverse | The question of resource scarcity has led to many debates on whether scarcity ) will lead to conflict and war. underlining reasoning comes from the Malthusian belief that there is an imbalance between the economic availability of natural resources and population growth Following this reasoning, neo-Malthusians claim that finite natural resources place a strict limit on the growth of human population if these limits are exceeded, social breakdown, conflict and wars result. most empirical studies do not support any of these neo-Malthusian arguments. Technological change and greater inputs of capital have dramatically increased labour productivity in agriculture the neo-Malthusian view has suffered because during the last two centuries humankind has breached many resource barriers that seemed unchallengeable In a so-called age of uncertainty, a number of alarmist scenarios have linked the increasing use of water resources and food insecurity with wars. The idea of water wars is a dominant discourse in the media this type of discourse has an instrumental purpose; security and conflict are here used for raising water/food as key policy priorities In the Middle East, presidents, prime ministers and foreign ministers have also used this bellicose rhetoric. Boutrous Boutros-Gali said; ‘the next war in the Middle East will be over water, not politics’ The question is not whether the sharing of transboundary water sparks political tension and alarmist declaration, but rather to what extent water has been a principal factor in international conflicts. The evidence seems quite weak none of these declarations have been followed up by military action None of the various and extensive databases on the causes of war show water as a c b Using the International Crisis Behavior (ICB) data set and supplementary data from the University of Alabama on water conflicts, Hewitt, Wolf and Hammer found only seven disputes where water seems to have been at least a partial cause for conflict As shown in The Basins At Risk (BAR) water event database, more than two-thirds of over 1800 water-related ‘events’ fall on the ‘cooperative’ scale Indeed, if one takes into account a much longer period, the following figures clearly demonstrate this argument organized political bodies signed between the year 805 and 1984 more than 3600 water-related treaties The fear around water wars have been driven by a Malthusian outlook which equates scarcity with violence, conflict and war. There is however no direct correlation between water scarcity and transboundary conflict scarcity drives the process of co-operation among riparians In terms of international relations, the threat of water wars due to increasing scarcity does not make much sense in the light of the recent historical record. Overall, the water war rationale expects conflict to occur over water, and appears to suggest that violence is a viable means of securing national water supplies, an argument which is highly contestable.¶ Despite growing concern that climate change will lead to instability and violent conflict, the evidence base to substantiate the connections is thin | empirical studies do not support any Malthusian arguments. Tech and capital increased productivity humankind breached barriers that seemed unchallengeable alarmist scenarios linked resources with wars this has an instrumental purpose ministers used bellicose rhetoric The evidence seems weak none have been followed by military action None of the databases on causes of war show water as a c b water events’ fall on the ‘cooperative’ scale political bodies signed between 3600 treaties There is no correlation between scarcity and conflict the threat does not make sense in the light of historical record | Water/food resources, war and conflict¶ The question of resource scarcity has led to many debates on whether scarcity (whether of food or water) will lead to conflict and war. The underlining reasoning behind most of these discourses over food and water wars comes from the Malthusian belief that there is an imbalance between the economic availability of natural resources and population growth since while food production grows linearly, population increases exponentially. Following this reasoning, neo-Malthusians claim that finite natural resources place a strict limit on the growth of human population and aggregate consumption; if these limits are exceeded, social breakdown, conflict and wars result. Nonetheless, it seems that most empirical studies do not support any of these neo-Malthusian arguments. Technological change and greater inputs of capital have dramatically increased labour productivity in agriculture. More generally, the neo-Malthusian view has suffered because during the last two centuries humankind has breached many resource barriers that seemed unchallengeable.¶ Lessons from history: alarmist scenarios, resource wars and international relations¶ In a so-called age of uncertainty, a number of alarmist scenarios have linked the increasing use of water resources and food insecurity with wars. The idea of water wars (perhaps more than food wars) is a dominant discourse in the media (see for example Smith, 2009), NGOs (International Alert, 2007) and within international organizations (UNEP, 2007). In 2007, UN Secretary General Ban Ki-moon declared that ‘water scarcity threatens economic and social gains and is a potent fuel for wars and conflict’ (Lewis, 2007). Of course, this type of discourse has an instrumental purpose; security and conflict are here used for raising water/food as key policy priorities at the international level.¶ In the Middle East, presidents, prime ministers and foreign ministers have also used this bellicose rhetoric. Boutrous Boutros-Gali said; ‘the next war in the Middle East will be over water, not politics’ (Boutros Boutros-Gali in Butts, 1997, p. 65). The question is not whether the sharing of transboundary water sparks political tension and alarmist declaration, but rather to what extent water has been a principal factor in international conflicts. The evidence seems quite weak. Whether by president Sadat in Egypt or King Hussein in Jordan, none of these declarations have been followed up by military action.¶ The governance of transboundary water has gained increased attention these last decades. This has a direct impact on the global food system as water allocation agreements determine the amount of water that can used for irrigated agriculture. The likelihood of conflicts over water is an important parameter to consider in assessing the stability, sustainability and resilience of global food systems.¶ None of the various and extensive databases on the causes of war show water as a casus belli. Using the International Crisis Behavior (ICB) data set and supplementary data from the University of Alabama on water conflicts, Hewitt, Wolf and Hammer found only seven disputes where water seems to have been at least a partial cause for conflict (Wolf, 1998, p. 251). In fact, about 80% of the incidents relating to water were limited purely to governmental rhetoric intended for the electorate (Otchet, 2001, p. 18).¶ As shown in The Basins At Risk (BAR) water event database, more than two-thirds of over 1800 water-related ‘events’ fall on the ‘cooperative’ scale (Yoffe et al., 2003). Indeed, if one takes into account a much longer period, the following figures clearly demonstrate this argument. According to studies by the United Nations Food and Agriculture Organization (FAO), organized political bodies signed between the year 805 and 1984 more than 3600 water-related treaties, and approximately 300 treaties dealing with water management or allocations in international basins have been negotiated since 1945 ([FAO, 1978] and [FAO, 1984]).¶ The fear around water wars have been driven by a Malthusian outlook which equates scarcity with violence, conflict and war. There is however no direct correlation between water scarcity and transboundary conflict. Most specialists now tend to agree that the major issue is not scarcity per se but rather the allocation of water resources between the different riparian states (see for example [Allouche, 2005], [Allouche, 2007] and [Rouyer, 2000]). Water rich countries have been involved in a number of disputes with other relatively water rich countries (see for example India/Pakistan or Brazil/Argentina). The perception of each state’s estimated water needs really constitutes the core issue in transboundary water relations. Indeed, whether this scarcity exists or not in reality, perceptions of the amount of available water shapes people’s attitude towards the environment (Ohlsson, 1999). In fact, some water experts have argued that scarcity drives the process of co-operation among riparians ([Dinar and Dinar, 2005] and [Brochmann and Gleditsch, 2006]).¶ In terms of international relations, the threat of water wars due to increasing scarcity does not make much sense in the light of the recent historical record. Overall, the water war rationale expects conflict to occur over water, and appears to suggest that violence is a viable means of securing national water supplies, an argument which is highly contestable.¶ The debates over the likely impacts of climate change have again popularised the idea of water wars. The argument runs that climate change will precipitate worsening ecological conditions contributing to resource scarcities, social breakdown, institutional failure, mass migrations and in turn cause greater political instability and conflict ([Brauch, 2002] and [Pervis and Busby, 2004]). In a report for the US Department of Defense, Schwartz and Randall (2003) speculate about the consequences of a worst-case climate change scenario arguing that water shortages will lead to aggressive wars (Schwartz and Randall, 2003, p. 15). Despite growing concern that climate change will lead to instability and violent conflict, the evidence base to substantiate the connections is thin ([Barnett and Adger, 2007] and [Kevane and Gray, 2008]). | 6,315 | <h4>No risk of food wars – empirics prove</h4><p>Jeremy <strong>Allouche 11</strong>, Research Fellow at the Institute of Development Studies at the University of Sussex, "The sustainability and resilience of global water and food systems: Political analysis of the interplay between security, resource scarcity, political systems and global trade" Food PolicyVolume 36, Supplement 1, January 2011, Pages S3-S8 Accessed via: Science Direct Sciverse</p><p>Water/food resources, war and conflict¶ <u>The question of resource scarcity has led to many debates on whether scarcity</u> (whether of food or water<u>) will lead to conflict and war.</u> The <u>underlining reasoning</u> behind most of these discourses over food and water wars <u>comes from the Malthusian belief that there is an imbalance between the economic availability of natural resources and population growth</u> since while food production grows linearly, population increases exponentially. <u>Following this reasoning, neo-Malthusians claim that finite natural resources place a strict limit on the growth of human population</u> and aggregate consumption; <u>if these limits are exceeded, social breakdown, conflict and wars result.</u> Nonetheless, it seems that <u><strong>most <mark>empirical studies do not support any</mark> of these neo-<mark>Malthusian arguments.</u></strong></mark> <u><strong><mark>Tech</mark>nological change <mark>and </mark>greater inputs of <mark>capital</strong></mark> have <strong>dramatically <mark>increased</mark> labour <mark>productivity</mark> in agriculture</u>.</strong> More generally, <u>the neo-Malthusian view has suffered because during the last two centuries <strong><mark>humankind</mark> has <mark>breached</mark> many resource <mark>barriers that seemed unchallengeable</u></strong></mark>.¶ Lessons from history: alarmist scenarios, resource wars and international relations¶ <u>In a so-called age of uncertainty, a number of <mark>alarmist scenarios</mark> have <mark>linked</mark> the increasing use of water <mark>resources</mark> and food insecurity <mark>with wars</mark>. The idea of water wars</u> (perhaps more than food wars) <u>is a dominant discourse in the media</u> (see for example Smith, 2009), NGOs (International Alert, 2007) and within international organizations (UNEP, 2007). In 2007, UN Secretary General Ban Ki-moon declared that ‘water scarcity threatens economic and social gains and is a potent fuel for wars and conflict’ (Lewis, 2007). Of course, <u><mark>this</mark> type of discourse <mark>has an <strong>instrumental purpose</strong></mark>; security and conflict are here used for raising water/food as key policy priorities</u> at the international level.¶ <u>In the Middle East, presidents, prime ministers and foreign <mark>ministers</mark> have also <mark>used</mark> this <mark>bellicose rhetoric</mark>. Boutrous Boutros-Gali said; ‘the next war in the Middle East will be over water, not politics’</u> (Boutros Boutros-Gali in Butts, 1997, p. 65). <u>The question is not whether the sharing of transboundary water sparks political tension and alarmist declaration, but rather to what extent water has been a principal factor in international conflicts. <strong><mark>The evidence seems</mark> quite <mark>weak</u></strong></mark>. Whether by president Sadat in Egypt or King Hussein in Jordan, <u><strong><mark>none</mark> of these declarations <mark>have been followed</mark> up <mark>by military action</u></strong></mark>.¶ The governance of transboundary water has gained increased attention these last decades. This has a direct impact on the global food system as water allocation agreements determine the amount of water that can used for irrigated agriculture. The likelihood of conflicts over water is an important parameter to consider in assessing the stability, sustainability and resilience of global food systems.¶ <u><strong><mark>None of the</mark> various and extensive <mark>databases</strong> on</mark> the <mark>causes of war show water as a c</u></mark>asus<u><mark> b</u></mark>elli. <u>Using the International Crisis Behavior (ICB) data set and supplementary data from the University of Alabama on water conflicts, Hewitt, Wolf and Hammer found only seven disputes where water seems to have been at least a partial cause for conflict</u> (Wolf, 1998, p. 251). In fact, about 80% of the incidents relating to water were limited purely to governmental rhetoric intended for the electorate (Otchet, 2001, p. 18).¶ <u>As shown in The Basins At Risk (BAR) water event database, <strong>more than two-thirds of over 1800 <mark>water</mark>-related ‘<mark>events’ fall on the ‘cooperative’ scale</u></mark> </strong>(Yoffe et al., 2003). <u>Indeed, if one takes into account a much longer period, the following figures clearly demonstrate this argument</u>. According to studies by the United Nations Food and Agriculture Organization (FAO), <u>organized <mark>political bodies signed</u> <u>between</mark> the year 805 and 1984 more than</u> <u><mark>3600</mark> water-related <mark>treaties</u></mark>, and approximately 300 treaties dealing with water management or allocations in international basins have been negotiated since 1945 ([FAO, 1978] and [FAO, 1984]).¶ <u>The fear around water wars have been driven by a Malthusian outlook which equates scarcity with violence, conflict and war. <mark>There is</mark> however <strong><mark>no</mark> direct <mark>correlation between</mark> water <mark>scarcity and</mark> transboundary <mark>conflict</u></strong></mark>. Most specialists now tend to agree that the major issue is not scarcity per se but rather the allocation of water resources between the different riparian states (see for example [Allouche, 2005], [Allouche, 2007] and [Rouyer, 2000]). Water rich countries have been involved in a number of disputes with other relatively water rich countries (see for example India/Pakistan or Brazil/Argentina). The perception of each state’s estimated water needs really constitutes the core issue in transboundary water relations. Indeed, whether this scarcity exists or not in reality, perceptions of the amount of available water shapes people’s attitude towards the environment (Ohlsson, 1999). In fact, some water experts have argued that <u>scarcity drives the process of co-operation among riparians</u> ([Dinar and Dinar, 2005] and [Brochmann and Gleditsch, 2006]).¶ <u>In terms of international relations, <mark>the threat </mark>of water wars due to increasing scarcity <strong><mark>does not make</mark> much <mark>sense in the light of</mark> the recent <mark>historical record</strong></mark>. Overall, the water war rationale expects conflict to occur over water, and appears to suggest that violence is a viable means of securing national water supplies, an argument which is highly contestable.¶ </u>The debates over the likely impacts of climate change have again popularised the idea of water wars. The argument runs that climate change will precipitate worsening ecological conditions contributing to resource scarcities, social breakdown, institutional failure, mass migrations and in turn cause greater political instability and conflict ([Brauch, 2002] and [Pervis and Busby, 2004]). In a report for the US Department of Defense, Schwartz and Randall (2003) speculate about the consequences of a worst-case climate change scenario arguing that water shortages will lead to aggressive wars (Schwartz and Randall, 2003, p. 15). <u>Despite growing concern that climate change will lead to instability and violent conflict, <strong>the evidence base to substantiate the connections is thin</u></strong> ([Barnett and Adger, 2007] and [Kevane and Gray, 2008]).</p> | null | null | Fridge | 28,932 | 766 | 122,977 | ./documents/ndtceda16/Iowa/JaPh/Iowa-Jackson-Phalen-Neg-Indiana-Round4.docx | 589,373 | N | Indiana | 4 | Indiana PS | Mia Bonitto | 1AC- Ratify Kigali Amendment
1NC- Climate Conflict K T-Restrict Politics China DA Case
2NR- China Da K Case | ndtceda16/Iowa/JaPh/Iowa-Jackson-Phalen-Neg-Indiana-Round4.docx | null | 50,309 | JaPh | Iowa JaPh | null | Ch..... | Ja..... | La..... | Ph..... | 19,035 | Iowa | Iowa | null | null | 1,006 | ndtceda16 | NDT/CEDA 2016-17 | 2,016 | cx | college | 2 |
3,660,540 | Adaptation solves in the interim – warming takes centuries | Mendelsohn 15 | Mendelsohn 15
Robert Mendelsohn is the Edwin Weyerhaeuser Davis Professor at the Yale School of Forestry and Environmental Studies, “Climate Change Demands We Change. Why Aren't We?: An Economic Perspective”, Social Research, Fall2015, Vol. 82 Issue 3, p727 | literature on climate change rife with claims that climate change is equivalent to an apocalypse. Whether climate change leads to an apocalypse depends on many factors, including no mitigation no adaptation and unlucky uncertain events have droughts, floods, and tropical cyclones. The question is, how will these things change?
emissions of greenhouse gases are expected to double the concentrations of greenhouse gases by 2040–2050. It will take more than another 100 years to double concentrations in the absence of mitigation. So despite the fact that fossil fuel consumption is causing a vast quantity of annual emissions it takes a very long time for concentrations of greenhouse gases in the atmosphere to double.
there is a long lag between an increase in concentrations and the resulting temperature increase. One must warm the ocean to warm the climate. It takes several decades just to warm the upper layers of the ocean It takes centuries for the long-run temperature to be reached.
studies suggest more modest effects of less than 2 percent of income Yet other studies suggest impacts may be closer to 0.2 percent of income
Although some authors speculate about exponentially increasing damage empirical analysis suggests most sectors respond to temperature in a hill-shaped fashion For each sector, there is an ideal temperature where the net value of that sector is highest
warming will be beneficial to relatively cool countries and harmful to relatively warm countries. Warming will not have the same universal effect on everybody
a large fraction of the damage will not occur until far into the future
Adaptation is very effective at lowering climate damage Firms, farms, and people will all change their behavior as climate changes. They will subtly adjust their timing, their choices, and their management to take into account the climate that they actually live in Adaptation makes them better off assuming zero adaptation is not realistic The damage is much lower when people adjust. It may be more difficult to predict what will happen with adaptation but simply assuming it away leads to overly pessimistic predictions of damage Predictions of impacts from climate change must take private adaptation into account in order to provide accurate measures of future damages | , it takes a very long time for concentrations of greenhouse gases to double
there is a long lag It takes centuries for long-run temperature to be reached
studies suggest modest effects less than 2 percent of income
some speculate about exponentially increasing damage empirical analysis suggests most sectors respond in a hill-shaped fashion
a large fraction of the damage will not occur until far into the future
Adaptation is very effective at lowering climate damage Firms, farms, and people will all change their behavior Adaptation makes them better off assuming zero adaptation is not realistic simply assuming it away leads to overly pessimistic predictions | The Benefits of Mitigation Are Modest and Delayed
The popular literature on climate change is rife with claims that climate change is equivalent to an apocalypse. Whether climate change leads to an apocalypse depends on many factors, including no mitigation, no adaptation, and unlucky uncertain events. Probably the three most frightening images of climate change are tropical cyclones, floods, and droughts. Although all these events are likely to occur in a future climate, they are also an integral component of the current climate. We already have droughts, floods, and tropical cyclones. The question is, how will these things change?
According to economic models of fossil fuel consumption, emissions of greenhouse gases are expected to double the concentrations of greenhouse gases from preindustrial levels of 275 part per million equivalent (ppme) to 550 ppme by 2040–2050. It will take more than another 100 years to double concentrations again to 1,100 ppme in the absence of mitigation. So despite the fact that fossil fuel consumption is causing a vast quantity of annual emissions, it takes a very long time for the concentrations of greenhouse gases in the atmosphere to double.
According to climate models, a doubling of concentrations is expected to increase long-run average global temperature by 3°C, with a range between 1.5 and 4.5 degrees (IPCC 2014a). However, there is a long lag between an increase in concentrations and the resulting temperature increase. One must warm the ocean to warm the climate. It takes several decades just to warm the upper layers of the ocean. It takes centuries for the long-run temperature to be reached.
The rising temperature is expected to increase the speed of the hydrological cycle. This will lead to an increase in evaporation, an increase in precipitation, and an increase in the amount of water in the atmosphere. Water vapor itself is a greenhouse gas. It represents a positive feedback mechanism and it contributes significantly to the prediction of a 3°C increase from doubling greenhouse gases. So the expectation of increased rainfall is part of the explanation why there is such a large temperature increase. That does not mean there will be increased rainfall everywhere. It simply means that average global rainfall will increase.
The level of CO2 has a direct effect on ecosystems. All plants respond to higher CO2 levels in a positive fashion. Grasses respond only slightly to CO2 fertilization, whereas the yields of most crops respond vigorously. Hundreds of laboratory studies reveal an average increase in crop yields of 30 percent as CO2 concentrations double (Kimball 2007).
Climate change is expected to melt ice formations. Many glaciers on land have already shrunk in response to warming, increasing flows in nearby rivers. The Arctic ice covering the sea in the North Pole is shrinking rapidly, exposing the Arctic air to the warm sea underneath and causing the most rapid warming on the planet (IPCC 2014a). Large remaining glaciers in Greenland and Antarctica might melt over the next thousand years (IPCC 2014a). The melting of the large ice deposits in Greenland and Antarctica would cause the oceans to rise to new levels never before experienced by mankind.
Climate change is expected to have one final impact. In addition to the mean temperature and precipitation levels rising, there may be a change in the distribution of weather. Seasonal patterns may change with more warming in winter than summer. Interannual variance might change. Diurnal variance may drop as nights become warmer relative to days. Tropical cyclones may become more powerful. The pattern of global winds may change, shifting moisture from one place to another. More is known about global mean changes than these other changes in the distribution. It is more difficult to study variance and even more difficult to study extreme events. But it is likely that the distribution of weather events will change.
What then is the consequence of climate change if greenhouse gases cause all these changes? What sectors of the economy are vulnerable? What nonmarket goods and services are at risk?
The literature on impacts has long identified most of the sectors likely to be affected by climate change (Pearce et al. 1996). The vulnerable economic sectors include agriculture, coasts, forests, water, and energy. Important sectors outside the economy that would be affected include recreation, ecosystem change, human health, and aesthetics. The controversy about impacts does not concern what will be affected. The controversy is measuring the magnitude of the impact. Some studies report damages to mankind equal to 20 percent of total income (Stern 2007). Other studies suggest more modest effects of less than 2 percent of income (Pearce et al. 1996; Nordhaus 1991). Yet other studies suggest impacts may be closer to 0.2 percent of income (Mendelsohn et al. 2006). What explains estimates that vary by orders of magnitude?
Although some authors speculate about exponentially increasing damage (Stern 2007), empirical analysis suggests that most sectors respond to temperature in a hill-shaped fashion (Mendelsohn and Schlesinger 1999; Tol 2002a). For each sector, there is an ideal temperature where the net value of that sector is highest. If temperatures are either colder or warmer than this ideal, warming will be either beneficial or harmful, respectively.
Three important insights follow from this result. First, warming will be beneficial to relatively cool countries and harmful to relatively warm countries. Warming will not have the same universal effect on everybody. Low-latitude countries may well suffer 60 to 80 percent of the global damage (Mendelsohn et al. 2006). This is problematic because these low-latitude countries collectively contribute only a small fraction of global emissions. A large fraction of the damage from climate change is not suffered by the countries causing the emissions. There is an inherent inequity in the distribution of the costs and benefits of greenhouse gas emissions.
Second, the warmer the planet gets, the more damage that warming will cause. More and more countries will be pushed beyond the ideal temperature range, and the more local temperatures exceed that range, the greater the damage will be. Third, because the most serious damage requires relatively high temperatures, a large fraction of the damage will not occur until far into the future. The present value of damage is consequently quite small.
The literature also contains one other important insight. Adaptation is very effective at lowering climate damage (Mendelsohn and Neumann 1999; Mendelsohn and Dinar 2009). Firms, farms, and people will all change their behavior as climate changes. They will subtly adjust their timing, their choices, and their management to take into account the climate that they actually live in. One can see this today by comparing the behavior of people who happen to live in different climates. Farmers in warmer places plant crops suitable for that climate. People wear clothing appropriate to their climate and season. Buildings have heating and cooling systems appropriate for each climate. People and firms adapt to climate because it is in their interest to do so. Adaptation makes them better off. That does not imply there are no damages. It simply points out that assuming zero adaptation is not realistic. The damage is much lower when people adjust. It may be more difficult to predict what will happen with adaptation, but simply assuming it away leads to overly pessimistic predictions of damage. Predictions of impacts from climate change must take private adaptation into account in order to provide accurate measures of future damages (Mendelsohn 2000). | 7,780 | <h4><u><strong>Adaptation solves in the interim – warming takes centuries</h4><p>Mendelsohn 15</p><p></u></strong>Robert Mendelsohn is the Edwin Weyerhaeuser Davis Professor at the Yale School of Forestry and Environmental Studies, “Climate Change Demands We Change. Why Aren't We?: An Economic Perspective”, Social Research, Fall2015, Vol. 82 Issue 3, p727</p><p>The Benefits of Mitigation Are Modest and Delayed</p><p>The popular <u>literature on climate change</u> is <u>rife with claims that climate change is equivalent to an apocalypse. Whether climate change leads to an apocalypse depends on many factors, including</u> <u><strong>no mitigation</u></strong>, <u><strong>no adaptation</u></strong>, <u><strong>and unlucky uncertain events</u></strong>. Probably the three most frightening images of climate change are tropical cyclones, floods, and droughts. Although all these events are likely to occur in a future climate, they are also an integral component of the current climate. We already<u><strong> have droughts, floods, and tropical cyclones. The question is, how will these things change?</p><p></u></strong>According to economic models of fossil fuel consumption, <u>emissions of greenhouse gases are expected to double the concentrations of greenhouse gases</u> from preindustrial levels of 275 part per million equivalent (ppme) to 550 ppme <u>by 2040–2050. It will take more than another 100 years to double concentrations</u> again to 1,100 ppme <u>in the absence of mitigation. So despite the fact that fossil fuel consumption is causing a vast quantity of annual emissions</u><mark>, <u><strong>it takes a very long time for</u></strong></mark> the <u><strong><mark>concentrations of greenhouse gases</mark> in the atmosphere <mark>to double</mark>.</p><p></u></strong>According to climate models, a doubling of concentrations is expected to increase long-run average global temperature by 3°C, with a range between 1.5 and 4.5 degrees (IPCC 2014a). However, <u><mark>there is a</u> <u><strong>long lag</u></strong></mark> <u>between an increase in concentrations and the resulting temperature increase. One must warm the ocean to warm the climate. It takes several decades just to warm the upper layers of the ocean</u>. <u><strong><mark>It takes centuries for</mark> the <mark>long-run temperature to be reached</mark>. </p><p></u></strong>The rising temperature is expected to increase the speed of the hydrological cycle. This will lead to an increase in evaporation, an increase in precipitation, and an increase in the amount of water in the atmosphere. Water vapor itself is a greenhouse gas. It represents a positive feedback mechanism and it contributes significantly to the prediction of a 3°C increase from doubling greenhouse gases. So the expectation of increased rainfall is part of the explanation why there is such a large temperature increase. That does not mean there will be increased rainfall everywhere. It simply means that average global rainfall will increase.</p><p>The level of CO2 has a direct effect on ecosystems. All plants respond to higher CO2 levels in a positive fashion. Grasses respond only slightly to CO2 fertilization, whereas the yields of most crops respond vigorously. Hundreds of laboratory studies reveal an average increase in crop yields of 30 percent as CO2 concentrations double (Kimball 2007).</p><p>Climate change is expected to melt ice formations. Many glaciers on land have already shrunk in response to warming, increasing flows in nearby rivers. The Arctic ice covering the sea in the North Pole is shrinking rapidly, exposing the Arctic air to the warm sea underneath and causing the most rapid warming on the planet (IPCC 2014a). Large remaining glaciers in Greenland and Antarctica might melt over the next thousand years (IPCC 2014a). The melting of the large ice deposits in Greenland and Antarctica would cause the oceans to rise to new levels never before experienced by mankind.</p><p>Climate change is expected to have one final impact. In addition to the mean temperature and precipitation levels rising, there may be a change in the distribution of weather. Seasonal patterns may change with more warming in winter than summer. Interannual variance might change. Diurnal variance may drop as nights become warmer relative to days. Tropical cyclones may become more powerful. The pattern of global winds may change, shifting moisture from one place to another. More is known about global mean changes than these other changes in the distribution. It is more difficult to study variance and even more difficult to study extreme events. But it is likely that the distribution of weather events will change.</p><p>What then is the consequence of climate change if greenhouse gases cause all these changes? What sectors of the economy are vulnerable? What nonmarket goods and services are at risk?</p><p>The literature on impacts has long identified most of the sectors likely to be affected by climate change (Pearce et al. 1996). The vulnerable economic sectors include agriculture, coasts, forests, water, and energy. Important sectors outside the economy that would be affected include recreation, ecosystem change, human health, and aesthetics. The controversy about impacts does not concern what will be affected. The controversy is measuring the magnitude of the impact. Some studies report damages to mankind equal to 20 percent of total income (Stern 2007). Other <u><strong><mark>studies suggest</mark> more <mark>modest effects</mark> of <mark>less than 2 percent of income</u></strong></mark> (Pearce et al. 1996; Nordhaus 1991). <u>Yet other studies suggest impacts may be closer to 0.2 percent of income</u> (Mendelsohn et al. 2006). What explains estimates that vary by orders of magnitude?</p><p><u>Although <mark>some</mark> authors</u> <u><strong><mark>speculate about exponentially increasing damage</u></strong></mark> (Stern 2007), <u><strong><mark>empirical analysis suggests</u></strong></mark> that <u><strong><mark>most sectors respond</mark> to temperature <mark>in a hill-shaped fashion</u></strong></mark> (Mendelsohn and Schlesinger 1999; Tol 2002a). <u>For each sector, there is an ideal temperature where the net value of that sector is highest</u>. If temperatures are either colder or warmer than this ideal, warming will be either beneficial or harmful, respectively.</p><p>Three important insights follow from this result. First, <u>warming will be beneficial to relatively cool countries and harmful to relatively warm countries. Warming will not have the same universal effect on everybody</u>. Low-latitude countries may well suffer 60 to 80 percent of the global damage (Mendelsohn et al. 2006). This is problematic because these low-latitude countries collectively contribute only a small fraction of global emissions. A large fraction of the damage from climate change is not suffered by the countries causing the emissions. There is an inherent inequity in the distribution of the costs and benefits of greenhouse gas emissions.</p><p>Second, the warmer the planet gets, the more damage that warming will cause. More and more countries will be pushed beyond the ideal temperature range, and the more local temperatures exceed that range, the greater the damage will be. Third, because the most serious damage requires relatively high temperatures, <u><strong><mark>a large fraction of the damage will not occur until far into the future</u></strong></mark>. The present value of damage is consequently quite small.</p><p>The literature also contains one other important insight. <u><strong><mark>Adaptation is very effective at lowering climate damage</u></strong></mark> (Mendelsohn and Neumann 1999; Mendelsohn and Dinar 2009). <u><strong><mark>Firms, farms, and people will all change their behavior</mark> as climate changes.</u></strong> <u>They will subtly adjust their timing, their choices, and their management to take into account the climate that they actually live in</u>. One can see this today by comparing the behavior of people who happen to live in different climates. Farmers in warmer places plant crops suitable for that climate. People wear clothing appropriate to their climate and season. Buildings have heating and cooling systems appropriate for each climate. People and firms adapt to climate because it is in their interest to do so. <u><strong><mark>Adaptation makes them better off</u></strong></mark>. That does not imply there are no damages. It simply points out that <u><strong><mark>assuming zero adaptation is not realistic</u></strong></mark>. <u>The damage is much lower when people adjust. It may be more difficult to predict what will happen with adaptation</u>, <u><strong>but <mark>simply assuming it away leads to overly pessimistic predictions</mark> of damage</u></strong>. <u>Predictions of impacts from climate change must take private adaptation into account in order to provide accurate measures of future damages</u> (Mendelsohn 2000).</p> | warrming d | cyber | null | 572,726 | 181 | 122,468 | ./documents/ndtceda16/Georgetown/MiSh/Georgetown-Mills-Shepherd-Neg-USC-Round6.docx | 588,391 | N | USC | 6 | Kansas HW | Will Repko | 1AC - new kigali
2NR - oil da | ndtceda16/Georgetown/MiSh/Georgetown-Mills-Shepherd-Neg-USC-Round6.docx | null | 50,253 | MiSh | Georgetown MiSh | null | Ch..... | Mi..... | Cl..... | Sh..... | 19,027 | Georgetown | Georgetown | null | null | 1,006 | ndtceda16 | NDT/CEDA 2016-17 | 2,016 | cx | college | 2 |
1,945,894 | No burnout | Bar-Yam, 16 | Bar-Yam, 16 - SB and PhD in physics from MIT, president of the New England Complex Systems Institute (Yaneer Bar-Yam, "Transition to extinction: Pandemics in a connected world," Medium, 7-3-2016, https://medium.com/complex-systems-channel/transition-to-extinction-pandemics-in-a-connected-world-153867fe98f4#.2bxv2alfc) | When we introduce long range transportation into the model, the success of more aggressive strains changes They can use the long range transportation to and the more transportation routes the
there is a at which pathogens become so aggressive that the entire host population dies The pathogens die at the same time but that is not exactly a consolation to the hosts With increasing levels of global transportation human civilization may be approaching such a
it is really about which pathogens will be found in a system that is and Ebola can spread in a
traditional approach uses historical evidence to assess the impacts of a disease , many were surprised by the spread of Ebola through West Africa in 2014 As the connectivity of the world increases to future events
Even a system that seems stable can be by a few more long-range connections and connectivity is continuing to increase
As the world becomes more connected,
the U.S. have of social interactions with some that can be events like a mass outbreak pose a much greater risk if they do happen If a sick food service worker in an airport infects 100 passengers or a contagion event happens in mass transportation an outbreak could very well prove
Long range transportation will continue to pose a threat of pandemic if its impacts cannot be contained. | aggressive strains use long range transportation to find new hosts and escape local extinction the more transportation the more pathogens survive and spread
With increasing levels of global transportation civilization may be approaching a critical threshold
past experience is not a good guide to future events
the U.S. have highly skewed networks of social interactions with highly connected individuals that can be superspreaders an outbreak could prove unstoppable
Long range transportation will pose a threat if its impacts cannot be contained | When we introduce long range transportation into the model, the success of more aggressive strains changes. They can use the long range transportation to find new hosts and escape local extinction. Figure 3 shows that the more transportation routes introduced into the model, the more higher aggressive pathogens are able to survive and spread.
As we add more long range transportation, there is a critical point at which pathogens become so aggressive that the entire host population dies. The pathogens die at the same time, but that is not exactly a consolation to the hosts. We call this the phase transition to extinction (Figure 4). With increasing levels of global transportation, human civilization may be approaching such a critical threshold.
In the paper we wrote in 2006 about the dangers of global transportation for pathogen evolution and pandemics [8], we mentioned the risk from Ebola. Ebola is a horrendous disease that was present only in isolated villages in Africa. It was far away from the rest of the world only because of that isolation. Since Africa was developing, it was only a matter of time before it reached population centers and airports. While the model is about evolution, it is really about which pathogens will be found in a system that is highly connected, and Ebola can spread in a highly connected world.
The traditional approach to public health uses historical evidence analyzed statistically to assess the potential impacts of a disease. As a result, many were surprised by the spread of Ebola through West Africa in 2014. As the connectivity of the world increases, past experience is not a good guide to future events.
A key point about the phase transition to extinction is its suddenness. Even a system that seems stable, can be destabilized by a few more long-range connections, and connectivity is continuing to increase.
So how close are we to the tipping point? We don’t know but it would be good to find out before it happens.
While Ebola ravaged three countries in West Africa, it only resulted in a handful of cases outside that region. One possible reason is that many of the airlines that fly to west Africa stopped or reduced flights during the epidemic [9]. In the absence of a clear connection, public health authorities who downplayed the dangers of the epidemic spreading to the West might seem to be vindicated.
As with the choice of airlines to stop flying to west Africa, our analysis didn’t take into consideration how people respond to epidemics. It does tell us what the outcome will be unless we respond fast enough and well enough to stop the spread of future diseases, which may not be the same as the ones we saw in the past. As the world becomes more connected, the dangers increase.
Are people in western countries safe because of higher quality health systems? Countries like the U.S. have highly skewed networks of social interactions with some very highly connected individuals that can be “superspreaders.” The chances of such an individual becoming infected may be low but events like a mass outbreak pose a much greater risk if they do happen. If a sick food service worker in an airport infects 100 passengers, or a contagion event happens in mass transportation, an outbreak could very well prove unstoppable.
Watch this mock video of a pathogen spreading globally through land and air transportation. Long range transportation will continue to pose a threat of pandemic if its impacts cannot be contained. | 3,485 | <h4>No burnout </h4><p><strong>Bar-Yam, 16</strong> - SB and PhD in physics from MIT, president of the New England Complex Systems Institute (Yaneer Bar-Yam, "Transition to extinction: Pandemics in a connected world," Medium, 7-3-2016, https://medium.com/complex-systems-channel/transition-to-extinction-pandemics-in-a-connected-world-153867fe98f4#.2bxv2alfc)</p><p><u><strong>When we introduce long range transportation into the model, the success of more <mark>aggressive strains</mark> changes</u></strong>. <u><strong>They can <mark>use</mark> the <mark>long range transportation to</mark> </u></strong><mark>find new hosts<u><strong></mark> <mark>and</mark> </u></strong><mark>escape local extinction</mark>. Figure 3 shows that <u><strong><mark>the more transportation</mark> routes</u></strong> introduced into the model, <u><strong><mark>the</mark> </u></strong><mark>more</mark> higher aggressive <mark>pathogens</mark> are able to <mark>survive and spread</mark>.</p><p>As we add more long range transportation, <u><strong>there is a </u></strong>critical point <u><strong>at which pathogens become so aggressive that the entire host population dies</u></strong>. <u><strong>The pathogens die at the same time</u></strong>, <u><strong>but that is not exactly a consolation to the hosts</u></strong>. We call this the phase transition to extinction (Figure 4). <u><strong><mark>With increasing levels of global transportation</u></strong></mark>, <u><strong>human <mark>civilization may be approaching</mark> such <mark>a</mark> </u></strong><mark>critical threshold</mark>.</p><p>In the paper we wrote in 2006 about the dangers of global transportation for pathogen evolution and pandemics [8], we mentioned the risk from Ebola. Ebola is a horrendous disease that was present only in isolated villages in Africa. It was far away from the rest of the world only because of that isolation. Since Africa was developing, it was only a matter of time before it reached population centers and airports. While the model is about evolution, <u><strong>it is really about which pathogens will be found in a system that is </u></strong>highly connected, <u><strong>and Ebola can spread in a </u></strong>highly connected world.</p><p>The <u><strong>traditional approach</u></strong> to public health <u><strong>uses historical evidence</u></strong> analyzed statistically <u><strong>to assess the</u></strong> potential <u><strong>impacts of a disease</u></strong>. As a result<u><strong>, many were surprised by the spread of Ebola through West Africa in 2014</u></strong>. <u><strong>As the connectivity of the world increases</u></strong>, <mark>past experience is not a good guide</mark> <u><strong><mark>to future events</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>A key point about the phase transition to extinction is its suddenness. <u><strong>Even a system that seems stable</u></strong>, <u><strong>can be </u></strong>destabilized<u><strong> by a few more long-range connections</u></strong>, <u><strong>and connectivity is continuing to increase</u></strong>.</p><p>So how close are we to the tipping point? We don’t know but it would be good to find out before it happens.</p><p>While Ebola ravaged three countries in West Africa, it only resulted in a handful of cases outside that region. One possible reason is that many of the airlines that fly to west Africa stopped or reduced flights during the epidemic [9]. In the absence of a clear connection, public health authorities who downplayed the dangers of the epidemic spreading to the West might seem to be vindicated.</p><p>As with the choice of airlines to stop flying to west Africa, our analysis didn’t take into consideration how people respond to epidemics. It does tell us what the outcome will be unless we respond fast enough and well enough to stop the spread of future diseases, which may not be the same as the ones we saw in the past. <u><strong>As the world becomes more connected, </u></strong>the dangers increase.</p><p>Are people in western countries safe because of higher quality health systems? Countries like <u><strong><mark>the U.S. have</mark> </u></strong><mark>highly skewed networks<u><strong></mark> <mark>of social interactions with</mark> some </u></strong>very <mark>highly connected individuals<u><strong></mark> <mark>that can be</u></strong></mark> “<mark>superspreaders</mark>.” The chances of such an individual becoming infected may be low but <u><strong>events like a mass outbreak pose a much greater risk if they do happen</u></strong>. <u><strong>If a sick food service worker in an airport infects 100 passengers</u></strong>, <u><strong>or a contagion event happens in mass transportation</u></strong>, <u><strong><mark>an outbreak could</mark> very well <mark>prove</mark> </u></strong><mark>unstoppable</mark>.</p><p>Watch this mock video of a pathogen spreading globally through land and air transportation. <u><strong><mark>Long range transportation will</mark> continue to <mark>pose a threat</mark> of pandemic <mark>if its impacts cannot be contained</mark>.</p></u></strong> | 1AC | null | null | 2,190 | 1,636 | 57,392 | ./documents/hspolicy20/Mamaroneck/MiRa/Mamaroneck-Miller-Rahman-Aff-GBX-Round1.docx | 733,961 | A | GBX | 1 | Niles West BB | Jordan Di | 1AC - Forensics
2NR - ESR Stim | hspolicy20/Mamaroneck/MiRa/Mamaroneck-Miller-Rahman-Aff-GBX-Round1.docx | null | 62,629 | MiRa | Mamaroneck MiRa | null | Ja..... | Mi..... | Ra..... | Ra..... | 21,706 | Mamaroneck | Mamaroneck | NY | null | 1,019 | hspolicy20 | HS Policy 2020-21 | 2,020 | cx | hs | 2 |
3,494,181 | Discrediting Trumpian populism’s key to avoid extinction | de Waal 16 | Alex de Waal 16, Executive Director of the World Peace Foundation at the Fletcher School at Tufts University, 12/5/16, “Garrison America and the Threat of Global War,” http://bostonreview.net/war-security-politics-global-justice/alex-de-waal-garrison-america-and-threat-global-war | Trump’s supporters will wake up to the fact that they have been duped, or realize the futility of voting for a wrecker out of a sense of alienated desperation The progressives’ silver lining to 2016 is had Clinton won, the Trump constituency would have been back in four years’ with a more ruthless and ideological candidate. Better for plutocratic populism to fail early
economic and financial crisis led to global calamity. Something similar could happen today we are in a steady unpicking of the liberal peace the historic decline in wars appears to have been reversed
What does a world in global, generalized war look like? deep states are strangling liberalism emboldened middle powers and revanchist powers (such as Russia) rearming and taking unilateral military action regional rivals threatening one another, some with nuclear weapons and others with possibilities of acquiring them
generalized war is a conflict of destabilization a global political market of rival plutocracies comes into view. Add virulent reactionary populism and it resembles a war on democracy
If we see punitive trade wars territorial disputes are in prospect
Liberal multilateralism is seeking common wins through peaceful negotiation We may see regional arms races, nuclear proliferation
A cabal of plutocratic populists would applaud one another’s readiness to tear up cosmopolitan liberalism Garrison America could collude with regimes in Russia, China, Turkey bringing a façade of stability for as long as they collude—and war when they fall out
the plutocratic populist order is a future that does not work
The importance of maintaining a commitment to public goods and the global commons—including the future of the planet remain evergreen. We need to find a new global political settlement without having to suffer the catastrophic traumas of trying everything else first | Better for populism to fail early
we are liberal peace
What does a world in global war look like? states emboldened middle and revanchist powers threatening with nuclear weapons
Add reactionary populism it resembles war on democracy
punitive trade wars territorial disputes
Liberal multilat is seeking common wins through peaceful negotiation
cabal of populists would tear up cosmopolitan liberalism Russia, China, Turkey bring a façade of stability and war when they fall out | Trump’s promises have been so vague that it will be hard for him to disappoint. Nonetheless, many of his supporters will wake up to the fact that they have been duped, or realize the futility of voting for a wrecker out of a sense of alienated desperation. The progressives’ silver lining to the 2016 election is that, had Clinton won, the Trump constituency would have been back in four years’ time, probably with a more ruthless and ideological candidate. Better for plutocratic populism to fail early. But the damage inflicted in the interim could be terrible—even irredeemable if it were to include swinging a wrecking ball at the Paris Climate Agreement out of simple ignorant malice.
Polanyi recounts how economic and financial crisis led to global calamity. Something similar could happen today. In fact we are already in a steady unpicking of the liberal peace that glowed at the turn of the millennium. Since approximately 2008, the historic decline in the number and lethality of wars appears to have been reversed. Today’s wars are not like World War I, with formal declarations of war, clear war zones, rules of engagement, and definite endings. But they are wars nonetheless.
What does a world in global, generalized war look like? We have an unwinnable “war on terror” that is metastasizing with every escalation, and which has blurred the boundaries between war and everything else. We have deep states—built on a new oligarchy of generals, spies, and private-sector suppliers—that are strangling liberalism. We have emboldened middle powers (such as Saudi Arabia) and revanchist powers (such as Russia) rearming and taking unilateral military action across borders (Ukraine and Syria). We have massive profiteering from conflicts by the arms industry, as well as through the corruption and organized crime that follow in their wake (Afghanistan). We have impoverishment and starvation through economic warfare, the worst case being Yemen. We have “peacekeeping” forces fighting wars (Somalia). We have regional rivals threatening one another, some with nuclear weapons (India and Pakistan) and others with possibilities of acquiring them (Saudi Arabia and Iran).
Above all, today’s generalized war is a conflict of destabilization, with big powers intervening in the domestic politics of others, buying influence in their security establishments, bribing their way to big commercial contracts and thereby corroding respect for government, and manipulating public opinion through the media. Washington, D.C., and Moscow each does this in its own way. Put the pieces together and a global political market of rival plutocracies comes into view. Add virulent reactionary populism to the mix and it resembles a war on democracy.
What more might we see? Economic liberalism is a creed of optimism and abundance; reactionary protectionism feeds on pessimistic scarcity. If we see punitive trade wars and national leaders taking preemptive action to secure strategic resources within the walls of their garrison states, then old-fashioned territorial disputes along with accelerated state-commercial grabbing of land and minerals are in prospect. We could see mobilization against immigrants and minorities as a way of enflaming and rewarding a constituency that can police borders, enforce the new political rightness, and even become electoral vigilantes.
Liberal multilateralism is a system of seeking common wins through peaceful negotiation; case-by-case power dealing is a zero-sum calculus. We may see regional arms races, nuclear proliferation, and opportunistic power coalitions to exploit the weak. In such a global political marketplace, we would see middle-ranking and junior states rewarded for the toughness of their bargaining, and foreign policy and security strategy delegated to the CEOs of oil companies, defense contractors, bankers, and real estate magnates.
The United Nations system appeals to leaders to live up to the highest standards. The fact that they so often conceal their transgressions is the tribute that vice pays to virtue. A cabal of plutocratic populists would revel in the opposite: applauding one another’s readiness to tear up cosmopolitan liberalism and pursue a latter-day mercantilist naked self-interest. Garrison America could opportunistically collude with similarly constituted political-military business regimes in Russia, China, Turkey, and elsewhere for a new realpolitik global concert, redolent of the early nineteenth-century era of the Congress of Vienna, bringing a façade of stability for as long as they collude—and war when they fall out.
And there is a danger that, in response to a terrorist outrage or an international political crisis, President Trump will do something stupid, just as Europe’s leaders so unthinkingly strolled into World War I. The multilateral security system is in poor health and may not be able to cope.
Underpinning this is a simple truth: the plutocratic populist order is a future that does not work. If illustration were needed of the logic of hiding under the blanket rather than facing difficult realities, look no further than Trump’s readiness to deny climate change.
We have been here before, more or less, and from history we can gather important lessons about what we must do now. The importance of defending civility with democratic deliberation, respecting human rights and values, and maintaining a commitment to public goods and the global commons—including the future of the planet—remain evergreen. We need to find our way to a new 1945—and the global political settlement for a tamed and humane capitalism—without having to suffer the catastrophic traumas of trying everything else first. | 5,701 | <h4>Discrediting Trumpian populism’s key to avoid extinction </h4><p>Alex <u><strong>de Waal 16</u></strong>, Executive Director of the World Peace Foundation at the Fletcher School at Tufts University, 12/5/16, “Garrison America and the Threat of Global War,” http://bostonreview.net/war-security-politics-global-justice/alex-de-waal-garrison-america-and-threat-global-war</p><p><u><strong>Trump’s</u></strong> promises have been so vague that it will be hard for him to disappoint. Nonetheless, many of his <u><strong>supporters will wake up to the fact that they have been duped, or realize the futility of voting for a wrecker out of a sense of alienated desperation</u></strong>. <u><strong>The progressives’ silver lining to</u></strong> the <u><strong>2016</u></strong> election <u><strong>is</u></strong> that, <u><strong>had Clinton won, the Trump constituency would have been back in four years’</u></strong> time, probably <u><strong>with a more ruthless and ideological candidate. <mark>Better for</mark> plutocratic <mark>populism to fail early</u></strong></mark>. But the damage inflicted in the interim could be terrible—even irredeemable if it were to include swinging a wrecking ball at the Paris Climate Agreement out of simple ignorant malice.</p><p>Polanyi recounts how <u><strong>economic and financial crisis led to global calamity. Something similar could happen today</u></strong>. In fact <u><strong><mark>we are</u></strong></mark> already <u><strong>in a steady unpicking of the <mark>liberal peace</u></strong></mark> that glowed at the turn of the millennium. Since approximately 2008, <u><strong>the historic decline in</u></strong> the number and lethality of <u><strong>wars appears to have been reversed</u></strong>. Today’s wars are not like World War I, with formal declarations of war, clear war zones, rules of engagement, and definite endings. But they are wars nonetheless.</p><p><u><strong><mark>What does a world in global</mark>, generalized <mark>war look like?</u></strong></mark> We have an unwinnable “war on terror” that is metastasizing with every escalation, and which has blurred the boundaries between war and everything else. We have <u><strong>deep <mark>states</u></strong></mark>—built on a new oligarchy of generals, spies, and private-sector suppliers—that <u><strong>are strangling liberalism</u></strong>. We have <u><strong><mark>emboldened middle</mark> powers</u></strong> (such as Saudi Arabia) <u><strong><mark>and revanchist powers</mark> (such as Russia) rearming and taking unilateral military action</u></strong> across borders (Ukraine and Syria). We have massive profiteering from conflicts by the arms industry, as well as through the corruption and organized crime that follow in their wake (Afghanistan). We have impoverishment and starvation through economic warfare, the worst case being Yemen. We have “peacekeeping” forces fighting wars (Somalia). We have <u><strong>regional rivals <mark>threatening</mark> one another, some <mark>with nuclear weapons</u></strong></mark> (India and Pakistan) <u><strong>and others with possibilities of acquiring them</u></strong> (Saudi Arabia and Iran).</p><p>Above all, today’s <u><strong>generalized war is a conflict of destabilization</u></strong>, with big powers intervening in the domestic politics of others, buying influence in their security establishments, bribing their way to big commercial contracts and thereby corroding respect for government, and manipulating public opinion through the media. Washington, D.C., and Moscow each does this in its own way. Put the pieces together and <u><strong>a global political market of rival plutocracies comes into view. <mark>Add</mark> virulent <mark>reactionary populism</u></strong></mark> to the mix <u><strong>and <mark>it resembles</mark> a <mark>war on democracy</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>What more might we see? Economic liberalism is a creed of optimism and abundance; reactionary protectionism feeds on pessimistic scarcity. <u><strong>If we see <mark>punitive trade wars</u></strong> </mark>and national leaders taking preemptive action to secure strategic resources within the walls of their garrison states, then old-fashioned <u><strong><mark>territorial disputes</u></strong> </mark>along with accelerated state-commercial grabbing of land and minerals <u><strong>are in prospect</u></strong>. We could see mobilization against immigrants and minorities as a way of enflaming and rewarding a constituency that can police borders, enforce the new political rightness, and even become electoral vigilantes.</p><p><u><strong><mark>Liberal multilat</mark>eralism <mark>is</u></strong></mark> a system of <u><strong><mark>seeking common wins through peaceful negotiation</u></strong></mark>; case-by-case power dealing is a zero-sum calculus. <u><strong>We may see regional arms races, nuclear proliferation</u></strong>, and opportunistic power coalitions to exploit the weak. In such a global political marketplace, we would see middle-ranking and junior states rewarded for the toughness of their bargaining, and foreign policy and security strategy delegated to the CEOs of oil companies, defense contractors, bankers, and real estate magnates.</p><p>The United Nations system appeals to leaders to live up to the highest standards. The fact that they so often conceal their transgressions is the tribute that vice pays to virtue. <u><strong>A <mark>cabal of</mark> plutocratic <mark>populists would</u></strong></mark> revel in the opposite: <u><strong>applaud</u></strong>ing <u><strong>one another’s readiness to <mark>tear up cosmopolitan liberalism</u></strong></mark> and pursue a latter-day mercantilist naked self-interest. <u><strong>Garrison America could</u></strong> opportunistically <u><strong>collude with</u></strong> similarly constituted political-military business <u><strong>regimes in <mark>Russia, China, Turkey</u></strong></mark>, and elsewhere for a new realpolitik global concert, redolent of the early nineteenth-century era of the Congress of Vienna, <u><strong><mark>bring</mark>ing <mark>a façade of stability</mark> for as long as they collude—<mark>and war when they fall out</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>And there is a danger that, in response to a terrorist outrage or an international political crisis, President Trump will do something stupid, just as Europe’s leaders so unthinkingly strolled into World War I. The multilateral security system is in poor health and may not be able to cope.</p><p>Underpinning this is a simple truth: <u><strong>the plutocratic populist order is a future that does not work</u></strong>. If illustration were needed of the logic of hiding under the blanket rather than facing difficult realities, look no further than Trump’s readiness to deny climate change.</p><p>We have been here before, more or less, and from history we can gather important lessons about what we must do now. <u><strong>The importance of</u></strong> defending civility with democratic deliberation, respecting human rights and values, and <u><strong>maintaining a commitment to public goods and the global commons—including the future of the planet</u></strong>—<u><strong>remain evergreen. We need to find</u></strong> our way to <u><strong>a new</u></strong> 1945—and the <u><strong>global political settlement</u></strong> for a tamed and humane capitalism—<u><strong>without having to suffer the catastrophic traumas of trying everything else first</u></strong>.</p> | 1AR | Off | Their M | 72,513 | 398 | 116,161 | ./documents/ndtceda17/Minnesota/AsLe/Minnesota-Asirvatham-Leburu-Aff-Pitt%20RR-Round1.docx | 598,893 | A | Pitt RR | 1 | Northwestern Jankovsky-Weideman | Bunas | 1AC - Cost Coverage Cartels
2NR - DeDev Case | ndtceda17/Minnesota/AsLe/Minnesota-Asirvatham-Leburu-Aff-Pitt%20RR-Round1.docx | null | 50,976 | AsLe | Minnesota AsLe | null | Ro..... | As..... | Te..... | Le..... | 19,128 | Minnesota | Minnesota | null | null | 1,007 | ndtceda17 | NDT/CEDA 2017-18 | 2,017 | cx | college | 2 |
2,402,438 | [5] Solutions to oppression need to be grounded in policy rather than abstraction. K’s must be tied to an implementable, political solution to be effective. | Bryant 12: | Bryant 12: Left,” Larval Subjects—Levi R. Bryant’s philosophy blog, November 11th, Available Online at http://larvalsubjects.wordpress.com/2012/11/11/underpants-gnomes-a-critique-of-the-academic-left/, Accessed 02-21-2014) | Unfortunately, the academic left falls prey to its own form of abstraction. It’s good at carrying out critiques that denounce various social formations, yet very poor at proposing any sort of realistic constructions of alternatives This type of “revolutionary” is the greatest friend of the reactionary and capitalist because they do more to drive people into the embrace of reigning ideology we’re like underpants gnomes, saying “revolution is the answer!” without addressing any of the infrastructural questions We’re intoxicated with critique because it’s easy and safe. We best every opponent with critique. We occupy a position of moral superiority with critique. But this system is destructive | the left falls prey to abstraction. It’s poor at proposing realistic alternatives “revolutionary” is the greatest friend of the reactionary because they drive people into the reigning ideology we’re saying “revolution is the answer!” without addressing infrastructural questions We’re intoxicated with critique because it’s easy and safe. But this system is destructive | Unfortunately, the academic left falls prey to its own form of abstraction. It’s good at carrying out critiques that denounce various social formations, yet very poor at proposing any sort of realistic constructions of alternatives. This because it thinks abstractly in its own way, ignoring how networks, assemblages, structures, or regimes of attraction would have to be remade to create a workable alternative. Here I’m reminded by the “underpants gnomes” depicted in South Park: The underpants gnomes have a plan for achieving profit that goes like this: Phase 1: Collect Underpants Phase 2: ? Phase 3: Profit! They even have a catchy song to go with their work: Well this is sadly how it often is with the academic left. Our plan seems to be as follows: Phase 1: Ultra-Radical Critique Phase 2: ? Phase 3: Revolution and complete social transformation! Our problem is that we seem perpetually stuck at phase 1 without ever explaining what is to be done at phase 2. Often the critiques articulated at phase 1 are right, but there are nonetheless all sorts of problems with those critiques nonetheless. In order to reach phase 3, we have to produce new collectives. In order for new collectives to be produced, people need to be able to hear and understand the critiques developed at phase 1. Yet this is where everything begins to fall apart. Even though these critiques are often right, we express them in ways that only an academic with a PhD in critical theory and post-structural theory can understand. How exactly is Adorno to produce an effect in the world if only PhD’s in the humanities can understand him? Who are these things for? We seem to always ignore these things and then look down our noses with disdain at the Naomi Kleins and David Graebers of the world. To make matters worse, we publish our work in expensive academic journals that only universities can afford, with presses that don’t have a wide distribution, and give our talks at expensive hotels at academic conferences attended only by other academics. Again, who are these things for? Is it an accident that so many activists look away from these things with contempt, thinking their more about an academic industry and tenure, than producing change in the world? If a tree falls in a forest and no one is there to hear it, it doesn’t make a sound! Seriously dudes and dudettes, what are you doing? But finally, and worst of all, us Marxists and anarchists all too often act like assholes. We denounce others, we condemn them, we berate them for not engaging with the questions we want to engage with, and we vilify them when they don’t embrace every bit of the doxa that we endorse. We are every bit as off-putting and unpleasant as the fundamentalist minister or the priest of the inquisition (have people yet understood that Deleuze and Guattari’s Anti-Oedipus was a critique of the French communist party system and the Stalinist party system, and the horrific passions that arise out of parties and identifications in general?). This type of “revolutionary” is the greatest friend of the reactionary and capitalist because they do more to drive people into the embrace of reigning ideology than to undermine reigning ideology. These are the people that keep Rush Limbaugh in business. Well done! But this isn’t where our most serious shortcomings lie. Our most serious shortcomings are to be found at phase 2. We almost never make concrete proposals for how things ought to be restructured, for what new material infrastructures and semiotic fields need to be produced, and when we do, our critique-intoxicated cynics and skeptics immediately jump in with an analysis of all the ways in which these things contain dirty secrets, ugly motives, and are doomed to fail. How, I wonder, are we to do anything at all when we have no concrete proposals? We live on a planet of 6 billion people. These 6 billion people are dependent on a certain network of production and distribution to meet the needs of their consumption. That network of production and distribution does involve the extraction of resources, the production of food, the maintenance of paths of transit and communication, the disposal of waste, the building of shelters, the distribution of medicines, etc., etc., etc. What are your proposals? How will you meet these problems? How will you navigate the existing mediations or semiotic and material features of infrastructure? Marx and Lenin had proposals. Do you? Have you even explored the cartography of the problem? Today we are so intellectually bankrupt on these points that we even have theorists speaking of events and acts and talking about a return to the old socialist party systems, ignoring the horror they generated, their failures, and not even proposing ways of avoiding the repetition of these horrors in a new system of organization. Who among our critical theorists is thinking seriously about how to build a distribution and production system that is responsive to the needs of global consumption, avoiding the problems of planned economy, ie., who is doing this in a way that gets notice in our circles? Who is addressing the problems of micro-fascism that arise with party systems (there’s a reason that it was the Negri & Hardt contingent, not the Badiou contingent that has been the heart of the occupy movement). At least the ecologists are thinking about these things in these terms because, well, they think ecologically. Sadly we need something more, a melding of the ecologists, the Marxists, and the anarchists. We’re not getting it yet though, as far as I can tell. Indeed, folks seem attracted to yet another critical paradigm, Laruelle. I would love, just for a moment, to hear a radical environmentalist talk about his ideal high school that would be academically sound. How would he provide for the energy needs of that school? How would he meet building codes in an environmentally sound way? How would she provide food for the students? What would be her plan for waste disposal? And most importantly, how would she navigate the school board, the state legislature, the federal government, and all the families of these students? What is your plan? What is your alternative? I think there are alternatives. I saw one that approached an alternative in Rotterdam. If you want to make a truly revolutionary contribution, this is where you should start. Why should anyone even bother listening to you if you aren’t proposing real plans? But we haven’t even gotten to that point. Instead we’re like underpants gnomes, saying “revolution is the answer!” without addressing any of the infrastructural questions of just how revolution is to be produced, what alternatives it would offer, and how we would concretely go about building those alternatives. Masturbation. “Underpants gnome” deserves to be a category in critical theory; a sort of synonym for self-congratulatory masturbation. We need less critique not because critique isn’t important or necessary– it is –but because we know the critiques, we know the problems. We’re intoxicated with critique because it’s easy and safe. We best every opponent with critique. We occupy a position of moral superiority with critique. But do we really do anything with critique? What we need today, more than ever, is composition or carpentry. Everyone knows something is wrong. Everyone knows this system is destructive and stacked against them. Even the Tea Party knows something is wrong with the economic system, despite having the wrong economic theory. None of us, however, are proposing alternatives. Instead we prefer to shout and denounce. Good luck with that. | 7,641 | <h4>[5] Solutions to oppression need to be grounded in policy rather than abstraction. K’s must be tied to an implementable, political solution to be effective. </h4><p><strong>Bryant 12:</strong> Left,” Larval Subjects—Levi R. Bryant’s philosophy blog, November 11th, Available Online at http://larvalsubjects.wordpress.com/2012/11/11/underpants-gnomes-a-critique-of-the-academic-left/, Accessed 02-21-2014)</p><p><u><strong>Unfortunately, <mark>the</mark> academic <mark>left falls prey to</mark> its own form of <mark>abstraction. It’s</mark> good at carrying out critiques that denounce various social formations, yet very <mark>poor at proposing</mark> any sort of <mark>realistic</mark> constructions of <mark>alternatives</u></strong></mark>. This because it thinks abstractly in its own way, ignoring how networks, assemblages, structures, or regimes of attraction would have to be remade to create a workable alternative. Here I’m reminded by the “underpants gnomes” depicted in South Park: The underpants gnomes have a plan for achieving profit that goes like this: Phase 1: Collect Underpants Phase 2: ? Phase 3: Profit! They even have a catchy song to go with their work: Well this is sadly how it often is with the academic left. Our plan seems to be as follows: Phase 1: Ultra-Radical Critique Phase 2: ? Phase 3: Revolution and complete social transformation! Our problem is that we seem perpetually stuck at phase 1 without ever explaining what is to be done at phase 2. Often the critiques articulated at phase 1 are right, but there are nonetheless all sorts of problems with those critiques nonetheless. In order to reach phase 3, we have to produce new collectives. In order for new collectives to be produced, people need to be able to hear and understand the critiques developed at phase 1. Yet this is where everything begins to fall apart. Even though these critiques are often right, we express them in ways that only an academic with a PhD in critical theory and post-structural theory can understand. How exactly is Adorno to produce an effect in the world if only PhD’s in the humanities can understand him? Who are these things for? We seem to always ignore these things and then look down our noses with disdain at the Naomi Kleins and David Graebers of the world. To make matters worse, we publish our work in expensive academic journals that only universities can afford, with presses that don’t have a wide distribution, and give our talks at expensive hotels at academic conferences attended only by other academics. Again, who are these things for? Is it an accident that so many activists look away from these things with contempt, thinking their more about an academic industry and tenure, than producing change in the world? If a tree falls in a forest and no one is there to hear it, it doesn’t make a sound! Seriously dudes and dudettes, what are you doing? But finally, and worst of all, us Marxists and anarchists all too often act like assholes. We denounce others, we condemn them, we berate them for not engaging with the questions we want to engage with, and we vilify them when they don’t embrace every bit of the doxa that we endorse. We are every bit as off-putting and unpleasant as the fundamentalist minister or the priest of the inquisition (have people yet understood that Deleuze and Guattari’s Anti-Oedipus was a critique of the French communist party system and the Stalinist party system, and the horrific passions that arise out of parties and identifications in general?). <u><strong>This type of <mark>“revolutionary” is the greatest friend of the reactionary</mark> and capitalist <mark>because they</mark> do more to <mark>drive people into the</mark> embrace of <mark>reigning ideology</u></strong></mark> than to undermine reigning ideology. These are the people that keep Rush Limbaugh in business. Well done! But this isn’t where our most serious shortcomings lie. Our most serious shortcomings are to be found at phase 2. We almost never make concrete proposals for how things ought to be restructured, for what new material infrastructures and semiotic fields need to be produced, and when we do, our critique-intoxicated cynics and skeptics immediately jump in with an analysis of all the ways in which these things contain dirty secrets, ugly motives, and are doomed to fail. How, I wonder, are we to do anything at all when we have no concrete proposals? We live on a planet of 6 billion people. These 6 billion people are dependent on a certain network of production and distribution to meet the needs of their consumption. That network of production and distribution does involve the extraction of resources, the production of food, the maintenance of paths of transit and communication, the disposal of waste, the building of shelters, the distribution of medicines, etc., etc., etc. What are your proposals? How will you meet these problems? How will you navigate the existing mediations or semiotic and material features of infrastructure? Marx and Lenin had proposals. Do you? Have you even explored the cartography of the problem? Today we are so intellectually bankrupt on these points that we even have theorists speaking of events and acts and talking about a return to the old socialist party systems, ignoring the horror they generated, their failures, and not even proposing ways of avoiding the repetition of these horrors in a new system of organization. Who among our critical theorists is thinking seriously about how to build a distribution and production system that is responsive to the needs of global consumption, avoiding the problems of planned economy, ie., who is doing this in a way that gets notice in our circles? Who is addressing the problems of micro-fascism that arise with party systems (there’s a reason that it was the Negri & Hardt contingent, not the Badiou contingent that has been the heart of the occupy movement). At least the ecologists are thinking about these things in these terms because, well, they think ecologically. Sadly we need something more, a melding of the ecologists, the Marxists, and the anarchists. We’re not getting it yet though, as far as I can tell. Indeed, folks seem attracted to yet another critical paradigm, Laruelle. I would love, just for a moment, to hear a radical environmentalist talk about his ideal high school that would be academically sound. How would he provide for the energy needs of that school? How would he meet building codes in an environmentally sound way? How would she provide food for the students? What would be her plan for waste disposal? And most importantly, how would she navigate the school board, the state legislature, the federal government, and all the families of these students? What is your plan? What is your alternative? I think there are alternatives. I saw one that approached an alternative in Rotterdam. If you want to make a truly revolutionary contribution, this is where you should start. Why should anyone even bother listening to you if you aren’t proposing real plans? But we haven’t even gotten to that point. Instead <u><strong><mark>we’re</mark> like underpants gnomes, <mark>saying “revolution is the answer!” without addressing</mark> any of the <mark>infrastructural questions</u></strong></mark> of just how revolution is to be produced, what alternatives it would offer, and how we would concretely go about building those alternatives. Masturbation. “Underpants gnome” deserves to be a category in critical theory; a sort of synonym for self-congratulatory masturbation. We need less critique not because critique isn’t important or necessary– it is –but because we know the critiques, we know the problems. <u><strong><mark>We’re intoxicated with critique because it’s easy and safe.</mark> We best every opponent with critique. We occupy a position of moral superiority with critique. <mark>But</u></strong></mark> do we really do anything with critique? What we need today, more than ever, is composition or carpentry. Everyone knows something is wrong. Everyone knows <u><strong><mark>this system is destructive</u></strong></mark> and stacked against them. Even the Tea Party knows something is wrong with the economic system, despite having the wrong economic theory. None of us, however, are proposing alternatives. Instead we prefer to shout and denounce. Good luck with that.</p> | 1AC | Advocacy | Underview | 50,698 | 1,048 | 77,218 | ./documents/hsld20/WestRanch/ve/West%20Ranch-venkatasuramanian-Aff-Isidore%20Newman-Doubles.docx | 877,003 | A | Isidore Newman | Doubles | Giovanni Cutri | forgot | 1aC Stock
1nc Black Nihlism performance DA
1ar ALL
2nr K
2a4 ROB | hsld20/WestRanch/ve/West%20Ranch-venkatasuramanian-Aff-Isidore%20Newman-Doubles.docx | null | 73,906 | shve | West Ranch shve | null | sh..... | ve..... | null | null | 24,771 | WestRanch | West Ranch | CA | null | 1,028 | hsld20 | HS LD 2020-21 | 2,020 | ld | hs | 1 |
2,851,956 | Resolved denotes a proposal to be enacted by law | Words and Phrases 1964 | Words and Phrases 1964 Permanent Edition | to express an opinion or determination by resolution or vote; as ‘it was resolved by the legislature; similar to the word “enact,” defined as to establish by law | to express determination by resolution or legislature to establish by law”. | Definition of the word “resolve,” given by Webster is “to express an opinion or determination by resolution or vote; as ‘it was resolved by the legislature;” It is of similar force to the word “enact,” which is defined by Bouvier as meaning “to establish by law”. | 263 | <h4><strong>Resolved denotes a proposal to be enacted by law </h4><p>Words and Phrases 1964 </strong>Permanent Edition </p><p>Definition of the word “resolve,” given by Webster is “<u><strong><mark>to express</mark> an opinion or <mark>determination by resolution or </mark>vote; as ‘it was resolved by the <mark>legislature</mark>;</u></strong>” It is of <u><strong>similar</u></strong> force <u><strong>to the word “enact,”</u></strong> which is <u><strong>defined</u></strong> by Bouvier <u><strong>as</u></strong> meaning “<u><strong><mark>to establish by law</u></strong>”.<strong></mark> </p></strong> | nr v elijah pitt | null | null | 1,125 | 2,415 | 90,550 | ./documents/hsld19/BergenCounty/Sa/Bergen%20County-Savransky-Neg-blue%20key-Round5.docx | 833,845 | N | blue key | 5 | elijah pitt | ethan uhlig | null | hsld19/BergenCounty/Sa/Bergen%20County-Savransky-Neg-blue%20key-Round5.docx | null | 71,262 | MaSa | Bergen County MaSa | null | Ma..... | Sa..... | null | null | 24,002 | BergenCounty | Bergen County | NJ | null | 1,027 | hsld19 | HS LD 2019-20 | 2,019 | ld | hs | 1 |
1,258,057 | Extinction---executive flexibility is key to respond to terror, rogue states, and prolif. | Yoo 17 | John Yoo 17. Professor of Law at the University of California, Berkeley, and a visiting scholar at the American Enterprise Institute. “Trump’s Syria Strike Was Constitutional.” National Review. 4/13/2017. https://www.nationalreview.com/2017/04/trump-syria-strike-constitutional-presidents-have-broad-war-powers | The Framers realized the obvious Foreign affairs are unpredictable and involve the highest of stakes, making them unsuitable to regulation by preexisting legislation they demand swift, decisive action sometimes under pressured or even emergency circumstances that is best carried out by a branch of government that does not suffer from multiple vetoes or that is delayed by disagreements Congress is too large and unwieldy to take the swift and decisive action required Even when it has access to the same intelligence as the executive branch, Congress’s loose, decentralized structure would paralyze American policy while foreign threats grew While pro-Congress critics worry about a president’s foreign adventurism, the real threat to our national security could come from inaction and isolationism the War Powers Resolution No federal court has ever upheld the resolution Even Congress has never enforced it Our Constitution has succeeded because it favors swift presidential action in war, later checked by Congress’s funding power A radical change in the system might appease critics of presidential power. But it could also seriously threaten American national security In order to forestall another 9/11 attack, or take advantage of a window of opportunity to strike terrorists or rogue nations, the executive branch needs flexibility Time for congressional deliberation, which can lead to passivity and isolation and not smarter decisions, will come at the price of speed and secrecy The Constitution creates a presidency that can respond forcefully to prevent serious threats to our national security As we confront the new challenges of terrorism, rogue nations, and WMD proliferation, now is not the time to introduce sweeping, untested changes | Foreign affairs are unpredictable unsuitable to regulation by legislation they demand swift, decisive action under pressured or emergency circumstances War Powers No court has ever upheld Congress has never enforced it A radical change in the system could seriously threaten national security to take advantage of a window of opportunity to strike the executive needs flexibility deliberation can lead to passivity at the price of speed and secrecy The presidency can respond to prevent terrorism, rogue nations, and WMD prolif | The Framers realized the obvious. Foreign affairs are unpredictable and involve the highest of stakes, making them unsuitable to regulation by preexisting legislation. Instead, they can demand swift, decisive action — sometimes under pressured or even emergency circumstances — that is best carried out by a branch of government that does not suffer from multiple vetoes or that is delayed by disagreements. Congress is too large and unwieldy to take the swift and decisive action required in wartime. Our Framers replaced the Articles of Confederation, which had failed in the management of foreign relations because they had no single executive, with the Constitution’s single president for precisely this reason. Even when it has access to the same intelligence as the executive branch, Congress’s loose, decentralized structure would paralyze American policy while foreign threats grew. Congress has no political incentive to mount and see through its own wartime policy. Members of Congress, who are interested in keeping their seats at the next election, do not want to take stands on controversial issues where the future is uncertain. They will avoid like the plague any vote that will anger large segments of the electorate. They prefer that the president take the political risks and be held accountable for failure. Congress is too large and unwieldy to take the swift and decisive action required in wartime. Congress’s track record when it has opposed presidential leadership has not been a happy one. Perhaps the most telling example was the Senate’s rejection of the Treaty of Versailles at the end of World War I. Congress’s isolationist urge kept the United States out of Europe at a time when democracies fell and Fascism grew in their place. Even as Europe and Asia plunged into war, Congress passed the Neutrality Acts designed to keep the United States out of the conflict. President Franklin Roosevelt violated those laws to help the Allies and draw the nation into war against the Axis. While pro-Congress critics worry about a president’s foreign adventurism, the real threat to our national security could come from inaction and isolationism. Many point to the Vietnam War as an example of the faults of the “imperial presidency.” Vietnam, however, could not have continued without the consistent support of Congress in raising a large military and paying for hostilities. And Vietnam ushered in a period of congressional dominance that witnessed American setbacks in the Cold War and the passage of the ineffectual War Powers Resolution. Congress passed the resolution in 1973 over President Richard Nixon’s veto, and no president has ever accepted the constitutionality of its 60-day limit on the use of troops abroad. No federal court has ever upheld the resolution. Even Congress has never enforced it. Despite the record of practice and the Constitution’s institutional design, critics nevertheless argue that we should radically remake the American way of war. They typically base their claim on Congress’s power to “declare war.” But these observers read the 18th-century constitutional text through a modern lens by interpreting “declare war” to mean “start war.” When the Constitution was written, however, a declaration of war served diplomatic notice about a change in legal relations between nations. It had little to do with launching hostilities. In the century before the Constitution, for example, Great Britain — where the Framers got the idea of declaring war — fought numerous major conflicts but declared war only once beforehand. Our Constitution sets out specific procedures for passing laws, appointing officers, and making treaties. There are none for waging war because the Framers expected the president and Congress to struggle over war through the national political process. In fact, other parts of the Constitution, properly read, support this reading. Article I, Section 10, for example, declares that the states shall not “engage” in war “without the consent of Congress” unless “actually invaded, or in such imminent danger as will not admit of delay.” This provision creates exactly the limits desired by anti-war critics, complete with an exception for self-defense. If the Framers had wanted to require congressional permission before the president could wage war, they simply could have repeated this provision and applied it to the executive. Presidents, of course, do not have complete freedom to take the nation to war. Congress has ample powers to control presidential policy, if it wants to. Only Congress can raise the military, which gives it the power to block, delay, or modify war plans. Before 1945, the United States had such a small peacetime military that presidents who started a war would have to go hat in hand to Congress to build an army to fight it. Since World War II, Congress has authorized and funded our large standing military, one primarily designed to conduct offensive, not defensive, operations (as we learned all too tragically on 9/11) and to swiftly project power worldwide. If Congress wanted to discourage presidential initiative in war, it could build a smaller, less offense-minded military. A radical change in the system for making war might appease critics of presidential power. But it could also seriously threaten American national security. Congress’s check on the presidency lies not just in the long-term raising of the military. It can also block any immediate armed conflict through the power of the purse. If Congress feels it has been misled in authorizing war, or it disagrees with the president’s decisions, all it need do is cut off funds, either all at once or gradually. It can reduce the size of the military, shrink or eliminate units, or freeze supplies. Using the power of the purse does not even require affirmative congressional action. Congress can just sit on its hands and refuse to pass a law funding the latest presidential adventure, and the war will end quickly. Even the Kosovo war, which lasted little more than two months and involved no ground troops, required special funding legislation. The Framers expected Congress’s power of the purse to serve as the primary check on presidential war. During the 1788 Virginia ratifying convention. Patrick Henry attacked the Constitution for failing to limit executive militarism. James Madison responded: “The sword is in the hands of the British king; the purse is in the hands of the Parliament. It is so in America, as far as any analogy can exist.” Congress ended America’s involvement in Vietnam by cutting off all funds for the war. Our Constitution has succeeded because it favors swift presidential action in war, later checked by Congress’s funding power. If a president continues to wage war without congressional authorization, as in Libya, Kosovo, or Korea, it is only because Congress has chosen not to exercise its easy check. We should not confuse a desire to escape political responsibility for a defect in the Constitution. A radical change in the system for making war might appease critics of presidential power. But it could also seriously threaten American national security. In order to forestall another 9/11 attack, or take advantage of a window of opportunity to strike terrorists or rogue nations, the executive branch needs flexibility. It is not hard to think of situations where congressional consent cannot be obtained in time to act. Time for congressional deliberation, which can lead to passivity and isolation and not smarter decisions, will come at the price of speed and secrecy. The Constitution creates a presidency that can respond forcefully to prevent serious threats to our national security. Presidents can take the initiative, and Congress can use its funding power to check presidents. Instead of demanding a legalistic process to begin war, the Framers left war to politics. As we confront the new challenges of terrorism, rogue nations, and WMD proliferation, now is not the time to introduce sweeping, untested changes in the way we make war. | 8,066 | <h4>Extinction---executive flexibility is key to respond to terror, rogue states, and prolif.</h4><p>John <strong>Yoo</strong> <strong>17</strong>. Professor of Law at the University of California, Berkeley, and a visiting scholar at the American Enterprise Institute. “Trump’s Syria Strike Was Constitutional.” National Review. 4/13/2017. https://www.nationalreview.com/2017/04/trump-syria-strike-constitutional-presidents-have-broad-war-powers</p><p><u>The Framers realized the <strong>obvious</u></strong>. <u><mark>Foreign affairs are <strong>unpredictable</mark> and involve the highest of stakes</strong>, making them <strong><mark>unsuitable to regulation by</mark> preexisting <mark>legislation</u></strong></mark>. Instead, <u><mark>they</u></mark> can <u><mark>demand <strong>swift, decisive action</strong></mark> </u>— <u>sometimes <mark>under <strong>pressured</strong> or</mark> even <strong><mark>emergency circumstances</u></strong></mark> — <u>that is best carried out by a branch of government that does not suffer from multiple vetoes or that is delayed by disagreements</u>. <u>Congress is too large and unwieldy to take the swift and decisive action required</u> in wartime. Our Framers replaced the Articles of Confederation, which had failed in the management of foreign relations because they had no single executive, with the Constitution’s single president for precisely this reason. <u>Even when it has access to the same intelligence as the executive branch, Congress’s loose, decentralized structure would paralyze American policy while foreign threats grew</u>. Congress has no political incentive to mount and see through its own wartime policy. Members of Congress, who are interested in keeping their seats at the next election, do not want to take stands on controversial issues where the future is uncertain. They will avoid like the plague any vote that will anger large segments of the electorate. They prefer that the president take the political risks and be held accountable for failure. Congress is too large and unwieldy to take the swift and decisive action required in wartime. Congress’s track record when it has opposed presidential leadership has not been a happy one. Perhaps the most telling example was the Senate’s rejection of the Treaty of Versailles at the end of World War I. Congress’s isolationist urge kept the United States out of Europe at a time when democracies fell and Fascism grew in their place. Even as Europe and Asia plunged into war, Congress passed the Neutrality Acts designed to keep the United States out of the conflict. President Franklin Roosevelt violated those laws to help the Allies and draw the nation into war against the Axis. <u>While pro-Congress critics worry about a president’s foreign adventurism, the real threat to our national security could come from <strong>inaction and isolationism</u></strong>. Many point to the Vietnam War as an example of the faults of the “imperial presidency.” Vietnam, however, could not have continued without the consistent support of Congress in raising a large military and paying for hostilities. And Vietnam ushered in a period of congressional dominance that witnessed American setbacks in the Cold War and the passage of <u>the</u> ineffectual <u><mark>War Powers</mark> Resolution</u>. Congress passed the resolution in 1973 over President Richard Nixon’s veto, and no president has ever accepted the constitutionality of its 60-day limit on the use of troops abroad. <u><strong><mark>No</mark> federal <mark>court has ever upheld</mark> the resolution</u></strong>. <u>Even <strong><mark>Congress has never enforced it</u></strong></mark>. Despite the record of practice and the Constitution’s institutional design, critics nevertheless argue that we should radically remake the American way of war. They typically base their claim on Congress’s power to “declare war.” But these observers read the 18th-century constitutional text through a modern lens by interpreting “declare war” to mean “start war.” When the Constitution was written, however, a declaration of war served diplomatic notice about a change in legal relations between nations. It had little to do with launching hostilities. In the century before the Constitution, for example, Great Britain — where the Framers got the idea of declaring war — fought numerous major conflicts but declared war only once beforehand. Our Constitution sets out specific procedures for passing laws, appointing officers, and making treaties. There are none for waging war because the Framers expected the president and Congress to struggle over war through the national political process. In fact, other parts of the Constitution, properly read, support this reading. Article I, Section 10, for example, declares that the states shall not “engage” in war “without the consent of Congress” unless “actually invaded, or in such imminent danger as will not admit of delay.” This provision creates exactly the limits desired by anti-war critics, complete with an exception for self-defense. If the Framers had wanted to require congressional permission before the president could wage war, they simply could have repeated this provision and applied it to the executive. Presidents, of course, do not have complete freedom to take the nation to war. Congress has ample powers to control presidential policy, if it wants to. Only Congress can raise the military, which gives it the power to block, delay, or modify war plans. Before 1945, the United States had such a small peacetime military that presidents who started a war would have to go hat in hand to Congress to build an army to fight it. Since World War II, Congress has authorized and funded our large standing military, one primarily designed to conduct offensive, not defensive, operations (as we learned all too tragically on 9/11) and to swiftly project power worldwide. If Congress wanted to discourage presidential initiative in war, it could build a smaller, less offense-minded military. A radical change in the system for making war might appease critics of presidential power. But it could also seriously threaten American national security. Congress’s check on the presidency lies not just in the long-term raising of the military. It can also block any immediate armed conflict through the power of the purse. If Congress feels it has been misled in authorizing war, or it disagrees with the president’s decisions, all it need do is cut off funds, either all at once or gradually. It can reduce the size of the military, shrink or eliminate units, or freeze supplies. Using the power of the purse does not even require affirmative congressional action. Congress can just sit on its hands and refuse to pass a law funding the latest presidential adventure, and the war will end quickly. Even the Kosovo war, which lasted little more than two months and involved no ground troops, required special funding legislation. The Framers expected Congress’s power of the purse to serve as the primary check on presidential war. During the 1788 Virginia ratifying convention. Patrick Henry attacked the Constitution for failing to limit executive militarism. James Madison responded: “The sword is in the hands of the British king; the purse is in the hands of the Parliament. It is so in America, as far as any analogy can exist.” Congress ended America’s involvement in Vietnam by cutting off all funds for the war. <u>Our Constitution has succeeded because it <strong>favors swift presidential action</strong> in war, later checked by Congress’s funding power</u>. If a president continues to wage war without congressional authorization, as in Libya, Kosovo, or Korea, it is only because Congress has chosen not to exercise its easy check. We should not confuse a desire to escape political responsibility for a defect in the Constitution. <u><mark>A radical change in the system</u></mark> for making war <u>might appease critics of presidential power. But it <mark>could</mark> also <strong><mark>seriously threaten</mark> American <mark>national security</u></strong></mark>. <u>In order <mark>to</mark> forestall another 9/11 attack, or <mark>take advantage of a <strong>window of opportunity</strong> to strike</mark> <strong>terrorists</strong> or <strong>rogue nations</strong>, <mark>the executive</mark> branch <mark>needs <strong>flexibility</u></strong></mark>. It is not hard to think of situations where congressional consent cannot be obtained in time to act. <u>Time for congressional <mark>deliberation</mark>, which <mark>can lead to <strong>passivity</mark> and isolation and not smarter decisions</strong>, will <strong>come <mark>at the price of speed and secrecy</u></strong></mark>. <u><mark>The</mark> Constitution creates a <mark>presidency</mark> that <mark>can <strong>respond </mark>forcefully</strong> <mark>to prevent</mark> serious threats to our national security</u>. Presidents can take the initiative, and Congress can use its funding power to check presidents. Instead of demanding a legalistic process to begin war, the Framers left war to politics. <u>As we confront the <strong>new challenges</strong> of <strong><mark>terrorism</strong>, <strong>rogue nations</strong>, and <strong>WMD</mark> <mark>prolif</mark>eration</strong>, now is not the time to introduce sweeping, untested changes</u> in the way we make war.</p> | null | 1NC | Adv 2---1NC | 7,349 | 996 | 30,970 | ./documents/hspolicy21/Westminster/SaYa/Westminster-Sayers-Yao-Neg-Kentucky-Semis.docx | 756,587 | N | Kentucky | Semis | Eagan LS | Panel | 1AC - Ag Subsidies
1NC - T Protection States CP Politics DA Settler Colonialism K Uncooperative Federalism CP Steal the Funding CP Exec Flex turn
2NC - T Protection States Case
1NR - Exec Flex Turn
2NR - T Protection | hspolicy21/Westminster/SaYa/Westminster-Sayers-Yao-Neg-Kentucky-Semis.docx | null | 64,596 | SaYa | Westminster SaYa | null | Be..... | Sa..... | Br..... | Ya..... | 22,174 | Westminster | Westminster | GA | null | 1,020 | hspolicy21 | HS Policy 2021-22 | 2,021 | cx | hs | 2 |
3,145,638 | Even a small war causes extinction. | Cribb 17 | Cribb 17 Julian Cribb, Emeritus Faculty, Australian National University and Fellow, Australian Academy of Technology, Science and Engineering, SURVIVING THE 21ST CENTURY: HUMANITY’S TEN GREAT CHALLENGES AND HOW WE CAN OVERCOME THEM, Switzerland: Springer International, 2017, p. 67-68. | even a limited conflict among lesser actors in the arms race, for example between Pakistan and India could still imperil the entire world things will spiral out of control as communications fail and panic spreads, mushrooming into general conflict over a much wider region. Firestorms throw up a shocking amount of smoke it would block out sunlight, chilling the planet enough to cause crop-killing frosts first round effects of the war would be worldwide panic and financial collapse as food supplies give out . A billion would perish within weeks, and billions more over the months nations, on this calculus, have the tools to terminate civilisation, and possibly the human species | even a limited conflict between Pakistan and India could imperil the world things will spiral out of control as communications fail and panic spreads mushrooming into general conflict over a much wider region Firestorms throw up smoke it would block sunlight, chilling the planet enough to cause crop-killing frosts first round effects would be worldwide panic and financial collapse as food supplies give out A billion would perish within weeks, and billions more over the months nations have the tools to terminate the human species | How large a nuclear release is required to precipitate a nuclear winter is still subject to technical debate, but with the greatly improved models developed for climate science, recent estimates suggest as few as 50 Hiroshima-sized bombs (15 kilotonnes each) would do it—or the use of only one weapon in every 200 from the global nuclear arsenal (Robock 2009 ). This puts a very different complexion on the contemporary risks facing humanity. First, it suggests that even a limited conflict among lesser actors in the arms race, for example between Pakistan and India, India and China or Israel and Iran, and involving mainly the use of “battlefield” nukes could still imperil the entire world. In Lights Out: how it all ends , nuclear experts Alan Robock and Brian Toon examined the effects of a regional war (Robock and Toon 2012 ). To begin with, they argue, a ‘limited nuclear war’ is highly unlikely as, with the release of a handful of battlefield nukes, things will very quickly spiral out of control as communications fail and panic spreads, mushrooming into a more general conflict involving dozens of weapons spread over a much wider region. Firestorms in the megacities would throw up a shocking amount of smoke, ash and dust—around 70 billion tonnes is the estimate for an India/Pakistan clash. Running this through climate models they found it would block out sunlight, chilling the planet by an average 1.25° for up to 10 years—enough to cause crop-killing frosts , even in midsummer. This would sharply reduce and in some regions eliminate farm production for several years. Normal world grain stocks are sufficient to feed humanity for only about 2–3 months, so one of the first round effects of the war would be worldwide panic and financial collapse as food supplies give out and grain prices soar astronomically. A billion people living on the margins of hunger would probably perish within weeks, and billions more over the ensuing months. In the early twenty-first century at least eight nations, on this calculus, have the tools to terminate civilisation, and possibly the human species, on their own, while at least two more aspire to the power to do so. Meanwhile the shadow of possible nuclear and chemical terrorism, and their consequences, is lengthening. | 2,282 | <h4><strong>Even a <u>small war</u> causes extinction.</h4><p><u>Cribb 17</u></strong> Julian Cribb, Emeritus Faculty, Australian National University and Fellow, Australian Academy of Technology, Science and Engineering, SURVIVING THE 21ST CENTURY: HUMANITY’S TEN GREAT CHALLENGES AND HOW WE CAN OVERCOME THEM, Switzerland: Springer International, 2017, p. 67-68.</p><p>How large a nuclear release is required to precipitate a nuclear winter is still subject to technical debate, but with the greatly improved models developed for climate science, recent estimates suggest as few as 50 Hiroshima-sized bombs (15 kilotonnes each) would do it—or the use of only one weapon in every 200 from the global nuclear arsenal (Robock 2009 ). This puts a very different complexion on the contemporary risks facing humanity. First, it suggests that<u><strong> <mark>even a limited conflict</mark> among lesser actors in the arms race, for example <mark>between Pakistan and India</u></strong></mark>, India and China or Israel and Iran, and involving mainly the use of “battlefield” nukes<u><strong> <mark>could</mark> still <mark>imperil the </mark>entire<mark> world</u></strong></mark>. In Lights Out: how it all ends , nuclear experts Alan Robock and Brian Toon examined the effects of a regional war (Robock and Toon 2012 ). To begin with, they argue, a ‘limited nuclear war’ is highly unlikely as, with the release of a handful of battlefield nukes,<u><strong> <mark>things will </u></strong></mark>very quickly <u><strong><mark>spiral out of control as communications fail and panic spreads</mark>, <mark>mushrooming into </u></strong></mark>a<u><strong><mark> </u></strong></mark>more <u><strong><mark>general conflict</mark> </u></strong>involving dozens of weapons spread<u><strong><mark> over a much wider region</mark>. <mark>Firestorms</mark> </u></strong>in the megacities would<u><strong><mark> throw up</mark> a shocking amount of <mark>smoke</u></strong></mark>, ash and dust—around 70 billion tonnes is the estimate for an India/Pakistan clash. Running this through climate models they found <u><strong><mark>it would block </mark>out<mark> sunlight, chilling the planet</u></strong></mark> by an average 1.25° for up to 10 years—<u><strong><mark>enough to cause crop-killing frosts</u></strong></mark> , even in midsummer. This would sharply reduce and in some regions eliminate farm production for several years. Normal world grain stocks are sufficient to feed humanity for only about 2–3 months, so one of the<u><strong><mark> first round effects</mark> of the war<mark> would be worldwide panic and financial collapse as food supplies</mark> <mark>give out </u></strong></mark>and grain prices soar astronomically<u><strong>. <mark>A billion </u></strong></mark>people living on the margins of hunger<u><strong> <mark>would</mark> </u></strong>probably <u><strong><mark>perish within weeks, and billions more over the </u></strong></mark>ensuing <u><strong><mark>months</u></strong></mark>. In the early twenty-first century at least eight<u><strong> <mark>nations</mark>, on this calculus, <mark>have the tools to terminate </mark>civilisation, and possibly <mark>the human species</u></strong></mark>, on their own, while at least two more aspire to the power to do so. Meanwhile the shadow of possible nuclear and chemical terrorism, and their consequences, is lengthening. </p> | 1AC | NFU Aff – Policy v14 | Norms | 340,044 | 513 | 102,146 | ./documents/ndtceda18/Minnesota/RaLa/Minnesota-Rao-Lamet-Aff-7%20-%20Navy-Round2.docx | 606,711 | A | 7 - Navy | 2 | George Mason LR | Judd Kimball | 1AC - NFU
2NR - Russia DA Shift DA Allies DA | ndtceda18/Minnesota/RaLa/Minnesota-Rao-Lamet-Aff-7%20-%20Navy-Round2.docx | null | 51,467 | RaLa | Minnesota RaLa | null | Br..... | Ra..... | Jo..... | La..... | 19,202 | Minnesota | Minnesota | null | null | 1,008 | ndtceda18 | NDT/CEDA 2018-19 | 2,018 | cx | college | 2 |
660,987 | Nuclear war causes extinction | Ward 18 https://www.vox.com/future-perfect/2018/10/19/17873822/nuclear-war-weapons-bombs-how-kill | Alex Ward 18. Staff writer @ Vox covering international security and defense issues, co-host of Vox's "Worldly" podcast, formerly an associate director in the Atlantic Council's Brent Scowcroft Center on International Security where he worked on military issues and US foreign policy, wrote the #NatSec2016 newsletter for War on the Rocks. 12-26-18. “This is exactly how a nuclear war would kill you.” Vox. https://www.vox.com/future-perfect/2018/10/19/17873822/nuclear-war-weapons-bombs-how-kill | . That means Trump could theoretically decide to launch a nuclear strike before an adversary’s nukes go off in America. In the heat of battle, the US military might detect an incoming nuclear attack from No Ko and the president could decide to respond with a similar strike. potential nuclear conflict between the U S and No Ko worries most experts Trump and Kim spent most of 2017 threatening to bomb each other with nuclear weapons there remains a genuine fear — perhaps slightly allayed now following Washington and Pyongyang’s diplomatic thaw — that the leaders might escalate their public squabble into a nuclear conflict. “a full-blown war with North Korea wouldn’t be as bad as you think. It would be much, much worse millions would die the US would likely have to send in around 200,000 troops to destroy Kim’s nuclear arsenal. Seoul would already — lie in ruins due to North Korea’s large artillery capabilities. Kim would launch nukes at the U S Washington would almost certainly respond in kind, leading to one of the worst wars in world history the roughly 140-kiloton explosive North Korea tested in September 2017 in the heart of Washington, DC 220,000 would die from this one attack alone while another 450,000 would sustain injuries It’s very likely that North Korea wouldn’t launch just one bomb, but multiple at DC and likely some at New York City, the West Coast, and possibly US military bases in Guam and/or Hawaii. Radiation poisoning is a horrible way to die It’s worth reiterating that all of the above are estimates for one strike on one location. An actual nuclear war would have much wider and more devastating consequences. And if that war spiraled out of control, the effects after the conflict would be much worse than the attacks themselves It’s possible you have an idea of what a post-nuclear hellscape looks like. After all, disaster movies are obsessed with that kind of world. But scientists and other nuclear experts care deeply about this issue too — and their research shows the movies may be too optimistic. The most devastating long-term effects of a nuclear war actually come down to the black smoke that attacks produce In a nuclear war, cities and industrial areas would be targeted, thereby producing tons of smoke as they burn. Some of that smoke would make it into the stratosphere — above the weather — where it would stay for years because there’s no rain to wash it out. That smoke would expand around the world as it heats up, blocking out sunlight over much of Earth. As a result, the world would experience colder temperatures and less precipitation, depleting much of the globe’s agricultural output. That, potentially, would lead to widespread famine in a matter of years If the scenario came to pass “almost everybody on the planet would die.” | Trump could theoretically launch before nukes go off In the heat of battle, the military might detect an attack the U S and No Ko worries experts leaders might escalate squabble into nuclear conflict millions would die Seoul in ruins Kim would launch nukes leading to the worst wars in history in DC 220,000 would die from one attack alone if that war spiraled the effects would be much worse black smoke would block out sunlight experience cold depleting ag lead to widespread famine “almost everybody on the planet would die.” | But the United States has consistently refused to adopt a “no first use” policy — a policy not to be the first one in a conflict to use a nuclear weapon, and to use them only if the other side uses them first. That means Trump could theoretically decide to launch a nuclear strike before an adversary’s nukes go off in America. In the heat of battle, the US military might detect an incoming nuclear attack from North Korea and the president could decide to respond with a similar strike. Either way, the president is the one who ultimately decides to put the process of launching a nuclear strike in motion — but he still has a few steps to complete. 2) A US military officer opens the “football” Once the president has decided the situation requires a nuclear strike, the military officer who is always by the president’s side opens the “football.” The leather-clad case contains an outline of the nuclear options available to the president — including possible targets, like military installations or cities, that the US’s roughly 800 nuclear weapons ready to launch within minutes can hit — and instructions for contacting US military commanders and giving them orders to launch the missiles with warheads on them. 3) Trump talks with military and civilian advisers The president is the sole decision-maker, but he would consult with civilian and military advisers before he issues the order to launch a nuclear weapon. A key person Trump must talk to is the Pentagon’s deputy director of operations in charge of the National Military Command Center, or “war room,” the heart of the Defense Department that directs nuclear command and control. The president can include whomever else he wants in the conversation. He would almost certainly consult Gen. John Hyten, commander of US Strategic Command, since Hyten is responsible for knowing what the US can hit with its nuclear weapons. But Trump would likely also include Defense Secretary James Mattis, National Security Adviser John Bolton, and Gen. Joseph Dunford, chairman of the Joint Chiefs of Staff, in that conversation as well. The chat also doesn’t have to be held in the White House’s Situation Room; it can happen anywhere over a secured phone line. If any of the advisers felt such an attack would be illegal — like if Trump simply wanted to nuke Pyongyang despite no apparent threat — they could advise the president against going ahead with the strike. Last November, Hyten publicly said he wouldn’t accept an illegal order from Trump to launch a nuclear attack. “He’ll tell me what to do, and if it’s illegal, guess what’s going to happen?” Hyten told an audience at the Halifax International Security Forum last year. “I’m gonna say, ‘Mr. President, that’s illegal.’” He continued by outlining what the military could consider an illegal order: if a nuclear attack isn’t proportional to the actual threat, for instance, or if the attack would cause unnecessary suffering. However, what does and doesn’t constitute a “legal” order is still up for debate and was the focus of a congressional hearing last November. Either way, if Hyten refused to follow the order, Trump could fire him and replace him with someone who would carry it out. 4) The president gives the official order to strike After the conversation, a senior officer in the “war room” has to formally verify that the command is coming from the president. The officers recite a code — “Bravo Charlie,” for example — and the president must then respond with a code printed on the “biscuit,” the card with the codes on it. Then members of the “war room” communicate with the people who will initiate and launch the attack. Depending on the plan chosen by the president, the command will go to US crews operating the submarines carrying nuclear missiles, warplanes that can drop nuclear bombs, or troops overseeing intercontinental ballistic missiles on land. 5) Launch crews prepare to attack The launch crews receive the plan and prepare for attack. This involves unlocking various safes, entering a series of codes, and turning keys to launch the missiles. Crews must “execute the order, not question it,” Cirincione told Maizland. 6) Missiles fly toward the enemy It could take as little as five minutes for intercontinental ballistic missiles to launch from the time the president officially orders a strike. Missiles launched from submarines take about 15 minutes. And then the president waits to see if they hit their target. The three main risks of nuclear war — and one wild card Those that have nuclear weapons, many have argued, will never use them. The destruction and human devastation is so unimaginable that it’s hard to believe a world leader will launch them again, they say. But no one can guarantee they won’t be used at least once more — and that possibility keeps most nuclear experts up at night. They disagree wildly as to what the next nuclear use might look like or how it might happen, but they almost unanimously cite the same three risks. 1) US vs. North Korea war The potential nuclear conflict between the United States and North Korea worries most experts — and likely most people on Earth. That makes sense: Trump and Kim, the North Korean premier, spent most of 2017 threatening to bomb each other with nuclear weapons. Kim actually gained a missile capable enough of reaching the entirety of the United States, although questions remain about whether it could make it all the way with a warhead on top and detonate. Still, there remains a genuine fear — perhaps slightly allayed now following Washington and Pyongyang’s diplomatic thaw — that the leaders might escalate their public squabble into a nuclear conflict. In February, Yochi Dreazen wrote for Vox that “a full-blown war with North Korea wouldn’t be as bad as you think. It would be much, much worse,” in part because “millions — plural — would die.” As Dreazen recounts, the US would likely have to send in around 200,000 troops to destroy Kim’s nuclear arsenal. Seoul, South Korea’s capital, would soon — if not already — lie in ruins due to North Korea’s large artillery capabilities. None of that may even be the worst part: Bruce Klingner, a 20-year veteran of the CIA who spent years studying North Korea, told me that Iraqi leader Saddam Hussein had stood by in 2002 as the US methodically built up the forces it used to invade the country — and oust Hussein — the following year. He said there was little chance that Kim would follow in Hussein’s footsteps and patiently allow the Pentagon to deploy the troops and equipment it would need for a full-on war with North Korea. “The conventional wisdom used to be that North Korea would use only nuclear weapons as part of a last gasp, twilight of the gods, pull the temple down upon themselves kind of move,” said Klingner, who now works for the conservative Heritage Foundation. “But we have to prepare for the real possibility that Kim would use nuclear weapons in the early stages of a conflict, not the latter ones.” In effect, any attempt to overthrow the Kim regime would prompt North Korea to launch nukes at the United States. Washington would almost certainly respond in kind, leading to one of the worst wars in world history. 2) US vs. Russia war Few experts discounted the idea that the US and Russia could yet engage in a nuclear war despite a decades-long standoff. After all, they’ve come close a few times. Here are just two examples: In September 1983, a missile attack system made it seem like the US had launched weapons at the Soviet Union. One man, Soviet Lt. Col. Stanislav Petrov, decided it was a false alarm and didn’t report the alert. Had he done so, Moscow likely would’ve responded with an actual nuclear strike. Stanislav Petrov, a former Soviet military officer known in the West as “The man who saved the world’’ for his role in averting a nuclear war over a false missile alarm, died in May, 2015 at age 77. Stanislav Petrov, a former Soviet military officer known in the West as “The man who saved the world’’ for his role in averting a nuclear war over a false missile alarm, died in May 2015 at age 77. Pavel Golovkin/AP Two months later, a too-real NATO war game — Able Archer 83 — made the Soviets believe Western forces were preparing for an actual attack. Moscow put its nuclear arsenal on high alert, but ultimately, neither side came to nuclear blows. Today, two main reasons explain why a US-Russia nuclear fight is a major concern. The first is the most obvious: Moscow just has so many nuclear weapons. Russia is the only country that could match the US bomb-for-bomb in any conflict. The longer Moscow has its weapons, the thinking goes, the higher the chance it uses them on the US — or vice versa. The second reason is the most troublesome: Washington and Moscow may be on a collision course. Russia is expanding further into Europe and encroaching on NATO territory. There’s even fear that Putin might authorize an invasion of a Baltic country that once was a part of the Soviet Union but is now in NATO. If that happens, the US would be treaty-bound to defend the Baltic country, almost assuredly setting up a shooting war with Moscow. Experts disagree on what would happen next. Some, including the Trump administration, claim Russia would use nuclear weapons early in a fight as a way to “escalate to deescalate” — do something so brash at the start of a conflict that it has to end before it gets even worse. Others say Russia would use the weapons only if its forces are on the brink of defeat. Magnets depicting Russian President Putin and President Trump on sale in Helsnki, Finland. Magnets depicting Russian President Putin and President Trump on sale in Helsnki, Finland. Alexander Demianchuk\TASS via Getty Images But Olga Oliker and Andrey Baklitskiy, experts on Russia’s nuclear strategy, wrote at War on the Rocks in February that Moscow’s “military doctrine clearly states that nuclear weapons will be used only in response to an adversary using nuclear or other weapons of mass destruction,” or if the country’s survival is in doubt. In other words, they say Russia would only use nukes in retaliation or to avoid certain extinction. Washington, of course, would likely respond with its own nuclear strikes after Moscow dropped its bombs. At that point, they’d be in a full-blown nuclear war with the potential to destroy each other and much of the world (more on that below). 3) India vs. Pakistan war India and Pakistan have gone to war four times since 1947, when Britain partitioned what had been a single colony into Hindu-majority India and Muslim-majority Pakistan. The worry today, though, is that a fifth conflict could go nuclear. Protesters hurl stones towards police and paramilitary men during clashes on the outskirts of Srinagar, India, on October 16, 2018. Protesters hurl stones towards police and paramilitary men during clashes on the outskirts of Srinagar, India, on October 16, 2018. Waseem Andrabi/Hindustan Times via Getty Images After decades of testing, India officially became a nuclear power in 1998. Islamabad, which had started a uranium enrichment program in the 1970s, soon joined New Delhi in the nuclear club. Two of their fights — the 1999 Kargil War and the 2001-’02 Twin Peaks Crisis — happened with fully functioning nuclear arsenals, but ultimately, neither country chose to use them. But the opportunity keeps presenting itself. Each side claims the other has violated an ongoing ceasefire in the contested, but India-administered, Kashmir region. The region continues to be roiled by violence; for instance, six people were killed in separate instances on September 27. The dispute over Kashmir is a key reason for current India-Pakistan tensions — and has the potential to spiral out of control. Javier Zarracina/Vox Some fear that India and Pakistan may reach for the proverbial nuclear button sooner rather than later. Here’s just one reason why, according to an April report by Tom Hundley for Vox: The Pakistan navy is likely to soon place nuclear-tipped cruise missiles on up to three of its five French-built diesel-electric submarines. ... Even more disturbing, Pakistani military authorities say they are considering the possibility of putting nuclear-tipped cruise missiles on surface vessels. ... Pakistan says its decision to add nuclear weapons to its navy is a direct response to India’s August 2016 deployment of its first nuclear submarine, the Arihant. A second, even more advanced Indian nuclear submarine, the Arighat, began sea trials last November, and four more boats are scheduled to join the fleet by 2025. That will give India a complete “nuclear triad,” which means the country will have the ability to deliver a nuclear strike by land-based missiles, by warplanes, and by submarines. In effect, India and Pakistan are in a nuclear arms race, and historical enemies will soon patrol dangerous waters in close proximity with nuclear weapons aboard their vessels. While there’s no real indication a fifth India-Pakistan war is on the horizon, it’s possible one flare-up puts both countries on the path to a nuclear crisis. Wild card: Trump’s temperament Cirincione, the head of the Ploughshares Fund, told me the risk of nuclear war is increasing because of one factor: Trump. “He is the greatest nuclear risk in the world, more than any person, any group, or any nation,” he said. “The policies he is pursuing are making most of our nuclear risks worse, and he is tearing down the global institutions that have reduced and restrained nuclear risks over the last few decades.” Activists marches with a model of a nuclear rocket during a demonstration against nuclear weapons on in Berlin, Germany, on November 18, 2017. About 700 demonstrators protested against the escalation of threat of nuclear attack between the US and North Ko Activists marches with a model of a nuclear rocket during a demonstration against nuclear weapons on in Berlin, Germany, on November 18, 2017. About 700 demonstrators protested against the escalation of threat of nuclear attack between the US and North Korea. Adam Berry/Getty Images Here’s what he means: The administration’s Nuclear Posture Review, released in February, lowered the threshold for dropping a bomb on an enemy. Basically, the US said that it would launch low-yield nuclear weapons — smaller, less deadly bombs — in response to nonnuclear strikes, such as a major cyberattack. That was in contrast with previous US administrations, which said they would respond with a nuke only in the event of the most egregious threats against the US, like the possible use of a biological weapon. The document also calls for more, smaller weapons on submarines and other platforms to attack enemies. Many experts worry that having tinier nukes makes them more usable, thereby increasing the chance of a skirmish turning into a full-blown nuclear war. (Think, for example, of the US-China trade war escalating to the point that Trump thinks his only option is to launch a smaller nuke, or how Trump could respond to Beijing after a devastating cyberattack on US infrastructure.) Plus, increasing the arsenal in this way would partially undo decades of the US’s work to stop nuclear proliferation around the world. Some experts, like Georgetown’s Kroenig, say having smaller tactical weapons is actually a good idea. Our current arsenal, which prioritizes older and bigger nukes, leads adversaries to think we would never use it. Having smaller bombs that America might use, then, makes the chance of a nuclear conflict less likely. “It gives us more options to threaten that limited response,” Kroenig told me. “We raise the bar with these lower-yield weapons.” But the Trump risk may have less to do with what kinds of bombs he has and more to do with his temperament. Take his tweet from January 2 toward the end of his spat with Kim Jong Un, the North Korean leader: Donald J. Trump ✔ @realDonaldTrump North Korean Leader Kim Jong Un just stated that the “Nuclear Button is on his desk at all times.” Will someone from his depleted and food starved regime please inform him that I too have a Nuclear Button, but it is a much bigger & more powerful one than his, and my Button works! 475K 7:49 PM - Jan 2, 2018 Twitter Ads info and privacy 324K people are talking about this While tensions with North Korea were high early on in Trump’s presidency, he has yet to face a situation, like his predecessors did, where it seemed nuclear war was likely. The 13-day Cuban missile crisis in October 1962, where the Soviet Union had secretly placed missiles in Cuba — just 90 miles from the US mainland — comes to mind. Members of President John F. Kennedy’s team, especially his military advisers, called for airstrikes on Cuba and even an invasion. But Kennedy decided to set up a blockade of the island and try to work out a diplomatic settlement with the Soviets, in part because a military confrontation might turn nuclear. Ultimately, the situation ended when they agreed on a deal: The Soviets would withdraw the missiles from the island, and the US would take out its missiles in Turkey. Before that conclusion, both sides came as close to nuclear war as ever. Customers gather to watch President John F. Kennedy as he delivers a televised address to the nation on the subject of the Cuban Missile Crisis, on October 22, 1962. Customers gather to watch President John F. Kennedy as he delivers a televised address to the nation on the subject of the Cuban Missile Crisis, on October 22, 1962. Ralph Crane/The LIFE Picture Collection/Getty Images How would Trump handle himself in a similar situation? Would he resist the urges of some in his military brass to strike an enemy — perhaps with a lower-yield nuke — or would he simply tweet out a threat in a hair-trigger moment? The fact is we don’t know — but what we do know about Trump makes his demeanor in such a situation a potential, even if very small, nuclear risk. Here’s what happens in a nuclear attack The theory around whether someone might drop a nuclear bomb takes away from the most serious matter in these discussions: the human and physical toll. Simply put, a nuclear strike of any magnitude would unleash suffering on a scale not seen since World War II. And with the advances in nuclear technology since then, it’s possible the devastation of the next nuclear strike would be far, far worse. It’s hard to picture what the effect of a modern-day nuclear attack would actually look like. But Wellerstein, the nuclear historian, created a website called Nukemap that allows users to “drop” a specific bomb — say, the roughly 140-kiloton explosive North Korea tested in September 2017 — on any target. So I did just that, detonating that North Korean device on the Capitol building in the heart of Washington, DC — and, well, see for yourself: Christina Animashaun/Vox Roughly 220,000 people would die from this one attack alone, according to the Nukemap estimate, while another 450,000 would sustain injuries. By comparison, America’s two nuclear attacks on Japan in 1945 killed and injured a total of around 200,000 people (granted, Hiroshima and Nagasaki had smaller populations than the Washington metro area). It’s very likely that North Korea wouldn’t launch just one bomb, but multiple at DC and likely some at New York City, the West Coast, and possibly US military bases in Guam and/or Hawaii. But for simplicity’s sake, let’s focus on the effects of this one horrible attack. The center yellow circle is the fireball radius — that is, the mushroom cloud — which would extend out about 0.25 square miles. Those within the green circle, approximately a 1.2-square-mile area, would face the heaviest dose of radiation. “Without medical treatment, there can be expected between 50% and 90% mortality from acute effects alone. Dying takes between several hours and several weeks,” according to the website. Radiation poisoning is a horrible way to die. Here are just some of the symptoms people sick with radiation get: Nausea and vomiting Spontaneous bleeding Diarrhea, sometimes bloody Severely burnt skin that may peel off The dark grey circle in the middle is where a shock wave does a lot of damage. In that 17-square-mile area, the bomb would flatten residential buildings, certainly killing people in or near them. Debris and fire would be everywhere. People in the bigger yellow circle, a 33.5-square-mile area, would receive third-degree burns. “There’s a bright flash of light,” Brian Toon, a scientist and expert on nuclear disasters at the University of Colorado Boulder, told me about when the bomb goes off. Those exposed to the light, which would stretch for miles, would get those burns if their skin were exposed. The light would also “easily ignite fires with flammable objects like leaves, twigs, paper, or your clothing,” he added. The victims may not feel much pain, however, because the burn will destroy pain nerves. Still, some will suffer major scarring or have the inability to use certain limbs, and others might require amputation, according to Wellerstein’s site. A mother tends her injured child, a victim of the atomic bomb blast at Hiroshima. A mother tends her injured child, a victim of the atomic bomb blast at Hiroshima. Keystone/Getty Images The biggest circle encompasses the near entirety of the air-blast zone: a 134-square-mile area. People can still die, or at least receive severe injuries, in that location. The blast would break windows, and those standing near the glass might be killed by shards, or at least shed blood from myriad cuts. Those who survive the bombing and its effects will have to walk through burning rubble and pass lifeless, charred bodies to reach safety. Some of them will ultimately survive, but others will succumb to sustained injuries or radiation. The wind, meanwhile, will carry the irradiated debris and objects — known as fallout because they drop from the sky — far outside the blast zone and sicken countless others. As for Washington, it will likely take decades and billions of dollars not only to rebuild the city but clean it of radiation entirely. It’s worth reiterating that all of the above are estimates for one strike on one location. An actual nuclear war would have much wider and more devastating consequences. And if that war spiraled out of control, the effects after the conflict would be much worse than the attacks themselves — and change the course of human history. “Almost everybody on the planet would die” It’s possible you have an idea of what a post-nuclear hellscape looks like. After all, disaster movies are obsessed with that kind of world. But scientists and other nuclear experts care deeply about this issue too — and their research shows the movies may be too optimistic. Alan Robock, an environmental sciences professor at Rutgers University, has spent decades trying to understand what a nuclear war would do to the planet. The sum of his work, along with other colleagues’, is based on economic, scientific, and agricultural models. Here’s what he found: The most devastating long-term effects of a nuclear war actually come down to the black smoke, along with the dust and particulates in the air, that attacks produce. People walking through the ruins of Hiroshima in the weeks following the atomic bomb blast. People walking through the ruins of Hiroshima in the weeks following the atomic bomb blast. Bernard Hoffman/The LIFE Picture Collection/Getty Images In a nuclear war, cities and industrial areas would be targeted, thereby producing tons of smoke as they burn. Some of that smoke would make it into the stratosphere — above the weather — where it would stay for years because there’s no rain to wash it out. That smoke would expand around the world as it heats up, blocking out sunlight over much of Earth. As a result, the world would experience colder temperatures and less precipitation, depleting much of the globe’s agricultural output. That, potentially, would lead to widespread famine in a matter of years. The impact on the world, however, depends on the amount of rising smoke. While scientists’ models and estimates vary, it’s believed that around 5 million to 50 millions tons of black smoke could lead to a so-called “nuclear autumn,” while 50 million to 150 millions tons of black smoke might plunge the world into a “nuclear winter.” If the latter scenario came to pass, Robock told me, “almost everybody on the planet would die.” | 24,484 | <h4><strong>Nuclear war causes extinction</h4><p></strong>Alex <strong>Ward 18</strong>. Staff writer @ Vox covering international security and defense issues, co-host of Vox's "Worldly" podcast, formerly an associate director in the Atlantic Council's Brent Scowcroft Center on International Security where he worked on military issues and US foreign policy, wrote the #NatSec2016 newsletter for War on the Rocks. 12-26-18. “This is exactly how a nuclear war would kill you.” Vox. <u><strong>https://www.vox.com/future-perfect/2018/10/19/17873822/nuclear-war-weapons-bombs-how-kill</p><p></u></strong>But the United States has consistently refused to adopt a “no first use” policy — a policy not to be the first one in a conflict to use a nuclear weapon, and to use them only if the other side uses them first<u>. That means <mark>Trump</mark> <strong><mark>could theoretically</u></strong></mark> <u>decide to <mark>launch</mark> a nuclear strike <strong><mark>before</mark> an adversary’s <mark>nukes go off</mark> in America</strong>. <mark>In the <strong>heat of battle</strong>, the</mark> US <mark>military might <strong>detect</strong> an</mark> incoming nuclear <mark>attack</mark> from</u> <u><strong>No</u></strong>rth <u><strong>Ko</u></strong>rea <u>and the president could <strong>decide to respond with a similar strike. </u></strong>Either way, the president is the one who ultimately decides to put the process of launching a nuclear strike in motion — but he still has a few steps to complete. 2) A US military officer opens the “football” Once the president has decided the situation requires a nuclear strike, the military officer who is always by the president’s side opens the “football.” The leather-clad case contains an outline of the nuclear options available to the president — including possible targets, like military installations or cities, that the US’s roughly 800 nuclear weapons ready to launch within minutes can hit — and instructions for contacting US military commanders and giving them orders to launch the missiles with warheads on them. 3) Trump talks with military and civilian advisers The president is the sole decision-maker, but he would consult with civilian and military advisers before he issues the order to launch a nuclear weapon. A key person Trump must talk to is the Pentagon’s deputy director of operations in charge of the National Military Command Center, or “war room,” the heart of the Defense Department that directs nuclear command and control. The president can include whomever else he wants in the conversation. He would almost certainly consult Gen. John Hyten, commander of US Strategic Command, since Hyten is responsible for knowing what the US can hit with its nuclear weapons. But Trump would likely also include Defense Secretary James Mattis, National Security Adviser John Bolton, and Gen. Joseph Dunford, chairman of the Joint Chiefs of Staff, in that conversation as well. The chat also doesn’t have to be held in the White House’s Situation Room; it can happen anywhere over a secured phone line. If any of the advisers felt such an attack would be illegal — like if Trump simply wanted to nuke Pyongyang despite no apparent threat — they could advise the president against going ahead with the strike. Last November, Hyten publicly said he wouldn’t accept an illegal order from Trump to launch a nuclear attack. “He’ll tell me what to do, and if it’s illegal, guess what’s going to happen?” Hyten told an audience at the Halifax International Security Forum last year. “I’m gonna say, ‘Mr. President, that’s illegal.’” He continued by outlining what the military could consider an illegal order: if a nuclear attack isn’t proportional to the actual threat, for instance, or if the attack would cause unnecessary suffering. However, what does and doesn’t constitute a “legal” order is still up for debate and was the focus of a congressional hearing last November. Either way, if Hyten refused to follow the order, Trump could fire him and replace him with someone who would carry it out. 4) The president gives the official order to strike After the conversation, a senior officer in the “war room” has to formally verify that the command is coming from the president. The officers recite a code — “Bravo Charlie,” for example — and the president must then respond with a code printed on the “biscuit,” the card with the codes on it. Then members of the “war room” communicate with the people who will initiate and launch the attack. Depending on the plan chosen by the president, the command will go to US crews operating the submarines carrying nuclear missiles, warplanes that can drop nuclear bombs, or troops overseeing intercontinental ballistic missiles on land. 5) Launch crews prepare to attack The launch crews receive the plan and prepare for attack. This involves unlocking various safes, entering a series of codes, and turning keys to launch the missiles. Crews must “execute the order, not question it,” Cirincione told Maizland. 6) Missiles fly toward the enemy It could take as little as five minutes for intercontinental ballistic missiles to launch from the time the president officially orders a strike. Missiles launched from submarines take about 15 minutes. And then the president waits to see if they hit their target. The three main risks of nuclear war — and one wild card Those that have nuclear weapons, many have argued, will never use them. The destruction and human devastation is so unimaginable that it’s hard to believe a world leader will launch them again, they say. But no one can guarantee they won’t be used at least once more — and that possibility keeps most nuclear experts up at night. They disagree wildly as to what the next nuclear use might look like or how it might happen, but they almost unanimously cite the same three risks. 1) US vs. North Korea war The <u>potential nuclear conflict between <mark>the</u> <u><strong>U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates <u><mark>and</u> <u><strong>No</u></strong></mark>rth <u><strong><mark>Ko</u></strong></mark>rea <u><strong><mark>worries</mark> most <mark>experts</u></strong></mark> — and likely most people on Earth. That makes sense: <u>Trump and Kim</u>, the North Korean premier, <u>spent most of 2017</u> <u><strong>threatening to bomb each other with nuclear weapons</u></strong>. Kim actually gained a missile capable enough of reaching the entirety of the United States, although questions remain about whether it could make it all the way with a warhead on top and detonate. Still, <u>there remains a genuine fear — perhaps slightly <strong>allayed</u></strong> <u>now following Washington and Pyongyang’s <strong>diplomatic thaw</u></strong> <u>— that the <mark>leaders might</u> <u><strong>escalate</mark> their public <mark>squabble into</mark> a <mark>nuclear conflict</mark>. </u></strong>In February, Yochi Dreazen wrote for Vox that <u>“a full-blown war with North Korea wouldn’t be as bad as you think. It would be</u> <u><strong>much, much worse</u></strong>,” in part because “<u><strong><mark>millions</u></strong></mark> — plural — <u><mark>would die</u></mark>.” As Dreazen recounts, <u>the US would likely have to send in around 200,000 troops to destroy Kim’s nuclear arsenal. <strong><mark>Seoul</u></strong></mark>, South Korea’s capital, <u>would</u> soon — if not <u><strong>already</u></strong> <u>— lie <mark>in</u> <u><strong>ruins</u></strong></mark> <u>due to North Korea’s large artillery capabilities. </u>None of that may even be the worst part: Bruce Klingner, a 20-year veteran of the CIA who spent years studying North Korea, told me that Iraqi leader Saddam Hussein had stood by in 2002 as the US methodically built up the forces it used to invade the country — and oust Hussein — the following year. He said there was little chance that Kim would follow in Hussein’s footsteps and patiently allow the Pentagon to deploy the troops and equipment it would need for a full-on war with North Korea. “The conventional wisdom used to be that North Korea would use only nuclear weapons as part of a last gasp, twilight of the gods, pull the temple down upon themselves kind of move,” said Klingner, who now works for the conservative Heritage Foundation. “But we have to prepare for the real possibility that Kim would use nuclear weapons in the early stages of a conflict, not the latter ones.” In effect, any attempt to overthrow the <u><mark>Kim</u></mark> regime <u><mark>would</u></mark> prompt North Korea to <u><strong><mark>launch nukes</mark> at the U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates. <u>Washington would almost certainly</u> <u><strong>respond in kind</strong>, <mark>leading to</mark> one of <mark>the</u> <u><strong>worst wars in</mark> world <mark>history</u></strong></mark>. 2) US vs. Russia war Few experts discounted the idea that the US and Russia could yet engage in a nuclear war despite a decades-long standoff. After all, they’ve come close a few times. Here are just two examples: In September 1983, a missile attack system made it seem like the US had launched weapons at the Soviet Union. One man, Soviet Lt. Col. Stanislav Petrov, decided it was a false alarm and didn’t report the alert. Had he done so, Moscow likely would’ve responded with an actual nuclear strike. Stanislav Petrov, a former Soviet military officer known in the West as “The man who saved the world’’ for his role in averting a nuclear war over a false missile alarm, died in May, 2015 at age 77. Stanislav Petrov, a former Soviet military officer known in the West as “The man who saved the world’’ for his role in averting a nuclear war over a false missile alarm, died in May 2015 at age 77. Pavel Golovkin/AP Two months later, a too-real NATO war game — Able Archer 83 — made the Soviets believe Western forces were preparing for an actual attack. Moscow put its nuclear arsenal on high alert, but ultimately, neither side came to nuclear blows. Today, two main reasons explain why a US-Russia nuclear fight is a major concern. The first is the most obvious: Moscow just has so many nuclear weapons. Russia is the only country that could match the US bomb-for-bomb in any conflict. The longer Moscow has its weapons, the thinking goes, the higher the chance it uses them on the US — or vice versa. The second reason is the most troublesome: Washington and Moscow may be on a collision course. Russia is expanding further into Europe and encroaching on NATO territory. There’s even fear that Putin might authorize an invasion of a Baltic country that once was a part of the Soviet Union but is now in NATO. If that happens, the US would be treaty-bound to defend the Baltic country, almost assuredly setting up a shooting war with Moscow. Experts disagree on what would happen next. Some, including the Trump administration, claim Russia would use nuclear weapons early in a fight as a way to “escalate to deescalate” — do something so brash at the start of a conflict that it has to end before it gets even worse. Others say Russia would use the weapons only if its forces are on the brink of defeat. Magnets depicting Russian President Putin and President Trump on sale in Helsnki, Finland. Magnets depicting Russian President Putin and President Trump on sale in Helsnki, Finland. Alexander Demianchuk\TASS via Getty Images But Olga Oliker and Andrey Baklitskiy, experts on Russia’s nuclear strategy, wrote at War on the Rocks in February that Moscow’s “military doctrine clearly states that nuclear weapons will be used only in response to an adversary using nuclear or other weapons of mass destruction,” or if the country’s survival is in doubt. In other words, they say Russia would only use nukes in retaliation or to avoid certain extinction. Washington, of course, would likely respond with its own nuclear strikes after Moscow dropped its bombs. At that point, they’d be in a full-blown nuclear war with the potential to destroy each other and much of the world (more on that below). 3) India vs. Pakistan war India and Pakistan have gone to war four times since 1947, when Britain partitioned what had been a single colony into Hindu-majority India and Muslim-majority Pakistan. The worry today, though, is that a fifth conflict could go nuclear. Protesters hurl stones towards police and paramilitary men during clashes on the outskirts of Srinagar, India, on October 16, 2018. Protesters hurl stones towards police and paramilitary men during clashes on the outskirts of Srinagar, India, on October 16, 2018. Waseem Andrabi/Hindustan Times via Getty Images After decades of testing, India officially became a nuclear power in 1998. Islamabad, which had started a uranium enrichment program in the 1970s, soon joined New Delhi in the nuclear club. Two of their fights — the 1999 Kargil War and the 2001-’02 Twin Peaks Crisis — happened with fully functioning nuclear arsenals, but ultimately, neither country chose to use them. But the opportunity keeps presenting itself. Each side claims the other has violated an ongoing ceasefire in the contested, but India-administered, Kashmir region. The region continues to be roiled by violence; for instance, six people were killed in separate instances on September 27. The dispute over Kashmir is a key reason for current India-Pakistan tensions — and has the potential to spiral out of control. Javier Zarracina/Vox Some fear that India and Pakistan may reach for the proverbial nuclear button sooner rather than later. Here’s just one reason why, according to an April report by Tom Hundley for Vox: The Pakistan navy is likely to soon place nuclear-tipped cruise missiles on up to three of its five French-built diesel-electric submarines. ... Even more disturbing, Pakistani military authorities say they are considering the possibility of putting nuclear-tipped cruise missiles on surface vessels. ... Pakistan says its decision to add nuclear weapons to its navy is a direct response to India’s August 2016 deployment of its first nuclear submarine, the Arihant. A second, even more advanced Indian nuclear submarine, the Arighat, began sea trials last November, and four more boats are scheduled to join the fleet by 2025. That will give India a complete “nuclear triad,” which means the country will have the ability to deliver a nuclear strike by land-based missiles, by warplanes, and by submarines. In effect, India and Pakistan are in a nuclear arms race, and historical enemies will soon patrol dangerous waters in close proximity with nuclear weapons aboard their vessels. While there’s no real indication a fifth India-Pakistan war is on the horizon, it’s possible one flare-up puts both countries on the path to a nuclear crisis. Wild card: Trump’s temperament Cirincione, the head of the Ploughshares Fund, told me the risk of nuclear war is increasing because of one factor: Trump. “He is the greatest nuclear risk in the world, more than any person, any group, or any nation,” he said. “The policies he is pursuing are making most of our nuclear risks worse, and he is tearing down the global institutions that have reduced and restrained nuclear risks over the last few decades.” Activists marches with a model of a nuclear rocket during a demonstration against nuclear weapons on in Berlin, Germany, on November 18, 2017. About 700 demonstrators protested against the escalation of threat of nuclear attack between the US and North Ko Activists marches with a model of a nuclear rocket during a demonstration against nuclear weapons on in Berlin, Germany, on November 18, 2017. About 700 demonstrators protested against the escalation of threat of nuclear attack between the US and North Korea. Adam Berry/Getty Images Here’s what he means: The administration’s Nuclear Posture Review, released in February, lowered the threshold for dropping a bomb on an enemy. Basically, the US said that it would launch low-yield nuclear weapons — smaller, less deadly bombs — in response to nonnuclear strikes, such as a major cyberattack. That was in contrast with previous US administrations, which said they would respond with a nuke only in the event of the most egregious threats against the US, like the possible use of a biological weapon. The document also calls for more, smaller weapons on submarines and other platforms to attack enemies. Many experts worry that having tinier nukes makes them more usable, thereby increasing the chance of a skirmish turning into a full-blown nuclear war. (Think, for example, of the US-China trade war escalating to the point that Trump thinks his only option is to launch a smaller nuke, or how Trump could respond to Beijing after a devastating cyberattack on US infrastructure.) Plus, increasing the arsenal in this way would partially undo decades of the US’s work to stop nuclear proliferation around the world. Some experts, like Georgetown’s Kroenig, say having smaller tactical weapons is actually a good idea. Our current arsenal, which prioritizes older and bigger nukes, leads adversaries to think we would never use it. Having smaller bombs that America might use, then, makes the chance of a nuclear conflict less likely. “It gives us more options to threaten that limited response,” Kroenig told me. “We raise the bar with these lower-yield weapons.” But the Trump risk may have less to do with what kinds of bombs he has and more to do with his temperament. Take his tweet from January 2 toward the end of his spat with Kim Jong Un, the North Korean leader: Donald J. Trump ✔ @realDonaldTrump North Korean Leader Kim Jong Un just stated that the “Nuclear Button is on his desk at all times.” Will someone from his depleted and food starved regime please inform him that I too have a Nuclear Button, but it is a much bigger & more powerful one than his, and my Button works! 475K 7:49 PM - Jan 2, 2018 Twitter Ads info and privacy 324K people are talking about this While tensions with North Korea were high early on in Trump’s presidency, he has yet to face a situation, like his predecessors did, where it seemed nuclear war was likely. The 13-day Cuban missile crisis in October 1962, where the Soviet Union had secretly placed missiles in Cuba — just 90 miles from the US mainland — comes to mind. Members of President John F. Kennedy’s team, especially his military advisers, called for airstrikes on Cuba and even an invasion. But Kennedy decided to set up a blockade of the island and try to work out a diplomatic settlement with the Soviets, in part because a military confrontation might turn nuclear. Ultimately, the situation ended when they agreed on a deal: The Soviets would withdraw the missiles from the island, and the US would take out its missiles in Turkey. Before that conclusion, both sides came as close to nuclear war as ever. Customers gather to watch President John F. Kennedy as he delivers a televised address to the nation on the subject of the Cuban Missile Crisis, on October 22, 1962. Customers gather to watch President John F. Kennedy as he delivers a televised address to the nation on the subject of the Cuban Missile Crisis, on October 22, 1962. Ralph Crane/The LIFE Picture Collection/Getty Images How would Trump handle himself in a similar situation? Would he resist the urges of some in his military brass to strike an enemy — perhaps with a lower-yield nuke — or would he simply tweet out a threat in a hair-trigger moment? The fact is we don’t know — but what we do know about Trump makes his demeanor in such a situation a potential, even if very small, nuclear risk. Here’s what happens in a nuclear attack The theory around whether someone might drop a nuclear bomb takes away from the most serious matter in these discussions: the human and physical toll. Simply put, a nuclear strike of any magnitude would unleash suffering on a scale not seen since World War II. And with the advances in nuclear technology since then, it’s possible the devastation of the next nuclear strike would be far, far worse. It’s hard to picture what the effect of a modern-day nuclear attack would actually look like. But Wellerstein, the nuclear historian, created a website called Nukemap that allows users to “drop” a specific bomb — say, <u>the roughly 140-kiloton explosive North Korea tested in September 2017</u> — on any target. So I did just that, detonating that North Korean device on the Capitol building <u><mark>in</mark> the heart of Washington, <mark>DC</u></mark> — and, well, see for yourself: Christina Animashaun/Vox Roughly <u><strong><mark>220,000</u></strong></mark> people <u><mark>would die from</mark> this</u> <u><strong><mark>one attack alone</u></strong></mark>, according to the Nukemap estimate, <u>while another 450,000 would sustain</u> <u><strong>injuries</u></strong>. By comparison, America’s two nuclear attacks on Japan in 1945 killed and injured a total of around 200,000 people (granted, Hiroshima and Nagasaki had smaller populations than the Washington metro area). <u>It’s very likely that North Korea wouldn’t launch just one bomb, but</u> <u><strong>multiple</u></strong> <u>at DC and likely some at New York City, the West Coast, and possibly US military bases in Guam and/or Hawaii. </u>But for simplicity’s sake, let’s focus on the effects of this one horrible attack. The center yellow circle is the fireball radius — that is, the mushroom cloud — which would extend out about 0.25 square miles. Those within the green circle, approximately a 1.2-square-mile area, would face the heaviest dose of radiation. “Without medical treatment, there can be expected between 50% and 90% mortality from acute effects alone. Dying takes between several hours and several weeks,” according to the website. <u>Radiation poisoning is a horrible way to die</u>. Here are just some of the symptoms people sick with radiation get: Nausea and vomiting Spontaneous bleeding Diarrhea, sometimes bloody Severely burnt skin that may peel off The dark grey circle in the middle is where a shock wave does a lot of damage. In that 17-square-mile area, the bomb would flatten residential buildings, certainly killing people in or near them. Debris and fire would be everywhere. People in the bigger yellow circle, a 33.5-square-mile area, would receive third-degree burns. “There’s a bright flash of light,” Brian Toon, a scientist and expert on nuclear disasters at the University of Colorado Boulder, told me about when the bomb goes off. Those exposed to the light, which would stretch for miles, would get those burns if their skin were exposed. The light would also “easily ignite fires with flammable objects like leaves, twigs, paper, or your clothing,” he added. The victims may not feel much pain, however, because the burn will destroy pain nerves. Still, some will suffer major scarring or have the inability to use certain limbs, and others might require amputation, according to Wellerstein’s site. A mother tends her injured child, a victim of the atomic bomb blast at Hiroshima. A mother tends her injured child, a victim of the atomic bomb blast at Hiroshima. Keystone/Getty Images The biggest circle encompasses the near entirety of the air-blast zone: a 134-square-mile area. People can still die, or at least receive severe injuries, in that location. The blast would break windows, and those standing near the glass might be killed by shards, or at least shed blood from myriad cuts. Those who survive the bombing and its effects will have to walk through burning rubble and pass lifeless, charred bodies to reach safety. Some of them will ultimately survive, but others will succumb to sustained injuries or radiation. The wind, meanwhile, will carry the irradiated debris and objects — known as fallout because they drop from the sky — far outside the blast zone and sicken countless others. As for Washington, it will likely take decades and billions of dollars not only to rebuild the city but clean it of radiation entirely. <u>It’s worth reiterating that all of the above are estimates for <strong>one strike on one location</strong>. An</u> <u><strong>actual nuclear war</u></strong> <u>would have</u> <u><strong>much wider and more devastating consequences.</u></strong> <u>And <mark>if that war</u> <u><strong>spiraled</u></strong></mark> <u>out of control, <mark>the effects</mark> <strong>after the conflict</u></strong> <u><mark>would be</u> <u><strong>much worse</mark> than the attacks themselves</u></strong> — and change the course of human history. “Almost everybody on the planet would die” <u>It’s possible you have an idea of what a post-nuclear hellscape looks like. After all, disaster movies are obsessed with that kind of world. But scientists and other nuclear experts care deeply about this issue too — and their research shows the <strong>movies may be too optimistic</strong>.</u> Alan Robock, an environmental sciences professor at Rutgers University, has spent decades trying to understand what a nuclear war would do to the planet. The sum of his work, along with other colleagues’, is based on economic, scientific, and agricultural models. Here’s what he found: <u>The most devastating long-term effects of a nuclear war actually come down to the</u> <u><strong><mark>black smoke</u></strong></mark>, along with the dust and particulates in the air, <u>that attacks produce</u>. People walking through the ruins of Hiroshima in the weeks following the atomic bomb blast. People walking through the ruins of Hiroshima in the weeks following the atomic bomb blast. Bernard Hoffman/The LIFE Picture Collection/Getty Images <u>In a nuclear war, cities and industrial areas would be targeted, thereby producing</u> <u><strong>tons of smoke</u></strong> <u>as they burn. Some of that smoke <mark>would</mark> make it into the stratosphere — above the weather — where it would stay for years because there’s</u> <u><strong>no rain to wash it out</strong>. That smoke would expand around the world as it heats up, <strong><mark>block</strong></mark>ing <strong><mark>out sunlight</u></strong></mark> <u>over much of Earth. As a result, the world would <mark>experience <strong>cold</strong></mark>er temperatures and less precipitation, <mark>depleting</mark> much of the globe’s <strong><mark>ag</strong></mark>ricultural output. That, potentially, would <mark>lead to <strong>widespread famine</mark> in a matter of years</u></strong>. The impact on the world, however, depends on the amount of rising smoke. While scientists’ models and estimates vary, it’s believed that around 5 million to 50 millions tons of black smoke could lead to a so-called “nuclear autumn,” while 50 million to 150 millions tons of black smoke might plunge the world into a “nuclear winter.” <u>If the</u> latter <u>scenario came to pass</u>, Robock told me, <u><strong><mark>“almost everybody on the planet would die.”</p></u></strong></mark> | 1AC | 1AC | 1AC Christmas Gift | 25,977 | 459 | 13,277 | ./documents/hsld19/DoughertyValley/Go/Dougherty%20Valley-Goel-Aff-CPS-Round1.docx | 835,920 | A | CPS | 1 | Golden State SS | forgot | 1ac - Noko
1nc - Chemical Shift and Deterrence
1ar - All
2NR - All
2AR - All | hsld19/DoughertyValley/Go/Dougherty%20Valley-Goel-Aff-CPS-Round1.docx | null | 71,451 | ArGo | Dougherty Valley ArGo | null | Ar..... | Go..... | null | null | 24,067 | DoughertyValley | Dougherty Valley | CA | null | 1,027 | hsld19 | HS LD 2019-20 | 2,019 | ld | hs | 1 |
575,186 | Collisions with high-value satellites guarantee nuclear escalation. | Egeli 21 | Egeli 21 [Sitki Egeli is an assistant professor in the Political Science and International Relations Department of Izmir University of Economics. He was previously a director for foreign affairs in Turkey’s Undersecretariat for Defense Industries (SSM) and vice president in charge of the defense and aerospace sectors of an international consulting firm.] “Space-to-Space Warfare and Proximity Operations: The Impact on Nuclear Command, Control, and Communications and Strategic Stability,” Published 25 Jun 2021, https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/full/10.1080/25751654.2021.1942681, VM | Amid increased tensions, perhaps even an imminent military confrontation between two nuclear-armed adversaries, a high-value satellite stops functioning or communicating instantly and inexplicably This may be the outcome of impact of a collision with a meteoroid or piece of space debris small enough to have evaded detection Could this perhaps be the harbinger of a wider nuclear or nonnuclear first strike, along with which the attacker is seeking to eliminate the possibility of retaliation by degrading the defender’s capacity to command, control, and communicate with its forces ? In the absence of a clear-cut picture of what actually has happened, there is a risk that impending decisions will be made on the basis of insufficient and potentially erroneous information The resulting ultimatums, responses, or counteractions could set off a dangerous cycle of escalation and tit-for-tat actions, whereby reactions and overreactions between adversaries lead to potentially catastrophic consequences , heightened tension in orbit would have the outcome of spilling down to Earth | Amid increased tensions between two nuclear-armed adversaries, a satellite stops functioning instantly may be the outcome of space debris small enough to have evaded detection the harbinger of a wider nuclear first strike the attacker is seeking to eliminate the possibility of retaliation In the absence of a clear picture of what has happened impending decisions will be made on insufficient and erroneous info | “Amid increased tensions, perhaps even an imminent military confrontation between two nuclear-armed adversaries, a high-value (for example, early-warning or strategic communication) satellite stops functioning or communicating instantly and inexplicably. SSA sensors do not pick up any anomalies. This may be the outcome of a technical malfunction or a natural phenomenon, such as the impact of a collision with a meteoroid or piece of space debris small enough to have evaded detection. Alternatively, the satellite perhaps becomes the victim of a deliberate, undetected attack. Earth-to-space kinetic, electronic, or directed energy attacks would leave behind some trails. A cyberattack, which is harder to detect and attribute, is a strong possibility. So is a stealthy attack by hostile spacecraft. In fact, the adversary is known to have experimented with ominous small spacecraft that could easily conceal or disguise themselves until conducting a final maneuver to neutralize their targets. The victim would also be aware that, especially at distant GEO and HEO altitudes, SSA is not sufficiently comprehensive to detect and give warning of all suspicious or threatening movements as they happen. As suspicions abound, decision makers are faced with hard choices. Could this perhaps be the harbinger of a wider nuclear or nonnuclear first strike, along with which the attacker is seeking to eliminate the possibility of retaliation by degrading the defender’s capacity to command, control, and communicate with its forces? Should the defender react immediately before the remaining space-enabled NC3 elements are also compromised and its control over nuclear and nonnuclear forces degrades even further? In the absence of a clear-cut picture of what actually has happened, there is a risk that impending decisions will be made on the basis of insufficient and potentially erroneous information, and the climate will be ripe for unfounded presumptions and predispositions. The resulting ultimatums, responses, or counteractions could set off a dangerous cycle of escalation and tit-for-tat actions, whereby reactions and overreactions between adversaries lead to potentially catastrophic consequences. At a minimum, heightened tension in orbit would have the outcome of spilling down to Earth so as to further aggravate an already tense situation.?” | 2,355 | <h4>Collisions with <u>high-value satellites</u> guarantee <u>nuclear escalation.</h4><p></u><strong>Egeli 21 </strong>[Sitki Egeli is an assistant professor in the Political Science and International Relations Department of Izmir University of Economics. He was previously a director for foreign affairs in Turkey’s Undersecretariat for Defense Industries (SSM) and vice president in charge of the defense and aerospace sectors of an international consulting firm.] “Space-to-Space Warfare and Proximity Operations: The Impact on Nuclear Command, Control, and Communications and Strategic Stability,” Published 25 Jun 2021, https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/full/10.1080/25751654.2021.1942681, VM</p><p>“<u><mark>Amid increased tensions</mark>, perhaps even an imminent military confrontation <mark>between <strong>two nuclear-armed adversaries</strong>, a</mark> high-value</u> (for example, early-warning or strategic communication) <u><strong><mark>satellite stops functioning</mark> </strong>or communicating <strong><mark>instantly</mark> and inexplicably</u></strong>. SSA sensors do not pick up any anomalies. <u><strong>This <mark>may be the outcome of</u></strong></mark> a technical malfunction or a natural phenomenon, such as the <u>impact of a collision with a meteoroid or piece of <strong><mark>space debris small enough to have evaded detection</u></strong></mark>. Alternatively, the satellite perhaps becomes the victim of a deliberate, undetected attack. Earth-to-space kinetic, electronic, or directed energy attacks would leave behind some trails. A cyberattack, which is harder to detect and attribute, is a strong possibility. So is a stealthy attack by hostile spacecraft. In fact, the adversary is known to have experimented with ominous small spacecraft that could easily conceal or disguise themselves until conducting a final maneuver to neutralize their targets. The victim would also be aware that, especially at distant GEO and HEO altitudes, SSA is not sufficiently comprehensive to detect and give warning of all suspicious or threatening movements as they happen. As suspicions abound, decision makers are faced with hard choices. <u>Could this perhaps be <mark>the harbinger of a wider nuclear</mark> or nonnuclear <strong><mark>first strike</strong></mark>, along with which <mark>the attacker is seeking to eliminate the <strong>possibility of retaliation</strong></mark> by degrading the defender’s capacity to command, control, and communicate with its forces</u>? Should the defender react immediately before the remaining space-enabled NC3 elements are also compromised and its control over nuclear and nonnuclear forces degrades even further<u>? <mark>In the absence of a clear</mark>-cut <mark>picture of what</mark> actually <mark>has happened</mark>, there is a risk that <mark>impending decisions will be made on</mark> the basis of <mark>insufficient and</mark> potentially <strong><mark>erroneous info</mark>rmation</u></strong>, and the climate will be ripe for unfounded presumptions and predispositions. <u>The resulting ultimatums, responses, or counteractions could <strong>set off a dangerous cycle of escalation</strong> and tit-for-tat actions, whereby reactions and overreactions between adversaries lead to potentially catastrophic consequences</u>. At a minimum<u>, heightened tension in orbit would <strong>have the outcome of spilling down to Earth</u></strong> so as to further aggravate an already tense situation.?”</p> | null | 1AC—Advantages | Advantage – Collisions | 346,879 | 1 | 9,080 | ./documents/hsld21/BergenCounty/Ki/Bergen%20County-Kim-Aff-penn-Doubles.docx | 883,523 | A | penn | Doubles | Ridge LA | Husain, Zahra Yin, Shubo Ambrose, Malachi | 1ac - asteroids
1nc - lay nc
1ar - all
2nr - all
2ar - all | hsld21/BergenCounty/Ki/Bergen%20County-Kim-Aff-penn-Doubles.docx | null | 74,390 | AnKi | Bergen County AnKi | null | An..... | Ki..... | null | null | 24,918 | BergenCounty | Bergen County | NJ | null | 1,029 | hsld21 | HS LD 2021-22 | 2,021 | ld | hs | 1 |
4,483,236 | The overall environment is resilient---‘existential’ threats are false | Bailey 20 [grammar edit] | Ronald Bailey 20, Science Correspondent at Reason, Member of the Society of Environmental Journalists and the American Society for Bioethics and Humanities, “The Global Environmental Apocalypse Has Been Canceled”, Reason Magazine, 8/1/2020, https://reason.com/2020/08/01/the-global-environmental-apocalypse-has-been-canceled/ [grammar edit] | According to activists humanity is beset on all sides by catastrophes that could kill off civilization Are they right?
Much of what people are being told about the environment is wrong the exaggeration, alarmism are the enemy of rational environmentalism environmental problems do not constitute inexorable existential threats growth and tech progress can ameliorate them
Climate change is happening. It's just not the end of the world
human[s] being are not causing a "sixth mass extinction," the Amazon rainforests are not the "lungs of the world," climate change is not making natural disasters worse, and fires have declined 25 percent around the world since 2003
humanity is already adapting to the ways climate change has been making weather patterns evolve, and that we will continue to adapt successfully in the future rising prosperity and increasing technological prowess will reverse most deleterious environmental trends | According to activists catastrophes could kill civilization
Much is wrong exaggeration environmental problems do not constitute existential threats growth and tech progress ameliorate them
Climate is not the end of the world
human[s] are not causing mass extinction Amazon are not the "lungs fires declined
humanity is adapting and will continue prosperity and tech prowess will reverse most trends | According to these activists and politicians, humanity is beset on all sides by catastrophes that could kill off civilization, and maybe even our species. Are they right?
Absolutely not, answers the longtime environmental activist Michael Shellenberger in an engaging new book, Apocalypse Never: Why Environmental Alarmism Hurts Us All. "Much of what people are being told about the environment, including the climate, is wrong, and we desperately need to get it right," he writes. "I decided to write Apocalypse Never after getting fed up with the exaggeration, alarmism, and extremism that are the enemy of positive, humanistic, and rational environmentalism." While fully acknowledging that significant global environmental problems exist, Shellenberger argues that they do not constitute inexorable existential threats. Economic growth and technological progress, he says, can ameliorate them.
Shellenberger's analysis relies on largely uncontroversial mainstream science, including reports from the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC) and the Food and Agriculture Organization. And as a longstanding activist, Shellenberger is in a good position to parse the motives behind the purveyors of doom.
Shellenberger's activism is the real deal. To raise a donation to the Rainforest Action Network, he charged his friends $5 to attend his 16th birthday party. At 17 he went to Nicaragua to experience the Sandinista revolution. In the 1990s he worked with the Landless Workers' Movement in Brazil.
In 2003, Shellenberger and allies launched the New Apollo Project to jumpstart a no-carbon energy revolution over the next 10 years. In 2008, Time named him "A Hero of the Environment." He co-founded the ecomodernist Breakthrough Institute, which advocates the use of advanced technologies such as nuclear power and agricultural biotechnology to decouple the economy from the ecology, allowing both humanity and the natural world to flourish. More recently, he founded Environmental Progress, which campaigns for, among other things, the deployment of clean modern nuclear power. He is an invited expert reviewer of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change's next assessment report.
Ohio Passes Controversial Conscience Clause for Doctors
So what does he say about climate change? "On behalf of environmentalists everywhere, I would like to formally apologize for the climate scare we created over the last 30 years," he wrote in an essay to promote his new book. "Climate change is happening. It's just not the end of the world. It's not even our most serious environmental problem." Needless to say, there are environmentalists everywhere who do not believe they have anything to apologize for. A group of six researchers assembled by the widely respected Climate Feedback fact-checking consortium rated his article as having low scientific credibility.
Shellenberger doesn't devote much of Apocalypse Never to the science behind man-made climate change. He basically accepts the consensus that it's a significant problem and instead focuses on various claims about the harms it is supposedly already causing. In that promotional essay, he argues that (1) human[s] being are not causing a "sixth mass extinction," (2) the Amazon rainforests are not the "lungs of the world," (3) climate change is not making natural disasters worse, and (4) fires have declined 25 percent around the world since 2003.
Shellenberger isn't denying the reality of man-made climate change. He's arguing that humanity is already adapting to the ways climate change has been making weather patterns evolve, and that we will continue to adapt successfully in the future. His book is ultimately a sustained argument that poverty is world's most important environmental problem, and that rising prosperity and increasing technological prowess will ameliorate or reverse most deleterious environmental trends. | 3,900 | <h4>The <u>overall</u> environment is <u>resilient</u>---‘existential’ threats are <u>false</h4><p></u>Ronald <u><strong>Bailey 20</u></strong>, Science Correspondent at Reason, Member of the Society of Environmental Journalists and the American Society for Bioethics and Humanities, “The Global Environmental Apocalypse Has Been Canceled”, Reason Magazine, 8/1/2020, https://reason.com/2020/08/01/the-global-environmental-apocalypse-has-been-canceled/<u><strong> [grammar edit]</p><p><mark>According to</u></strong></mark> these <u><strong><mark>activists</u></strong></mark> and politicians, <u><strong>humanity is beset on all sides by <mark>catastrophes</mark> that <mark>could kill</mark> off <mark>civilization</u></strong></mark>, and maybe even our species. <u><strong>Are they right?</p><p></u></strong>Absolutely not, answers the longtime environmental activist Michael Shellenberger in an engaging new book, Apocalypse Never: Why Environmental Alarmism Hurts Us All. "<u><strong><mark>Much</mark> of what people are being told about the environment</u></strong>, including the climate, <u><strong><mark>is wrong</u></strong></mark>, and we desperately need to get it right," he writes. "I decided to write Apocalypse Never after getting fed up with <u><strong>the <mark>exaggeration</mark>, alarmism</u></strong>, and extremism that <u><strong>are the enemy of</u></strong> positive, humanistic, and <u><strong>rational environmentalism</u></strong>." While fully acknowledging that significant global <u><strong><mark>environmental problems</u></strong></mark> exist, Shellenberger argues that they <u><strong><mark>do not constitute</mark> inexorable <mark>existential threats</u></strong></mark>. Economic <u><strong><mark>growth and tech</u></strong></mark>nological <u><strong><mark>progress</u></strong></mark>, he says, <u><strong>can <mark>ameliorate them</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>Shellenberger's analysis relies on largely uncontroversial mainstream science, including reports from the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC) and the Food and Agriculture Organization. And as a longstanding activist, Shellenberger is in a good position to parse the motives behind the purveyors of doom.</p><p>Shellenberger's activism is the real deal. To raise a donation to the Rainforest Action Network, he charged his friends $5 to attend his 16th birthday party. At 17 he went to Nicaragua to experience the Sandinista revolution. In the 1990s he worked with the Landless Workers' Movement in Brazil.</p><p>In 2003, Shellenberger and allies launched the New Apollo Project to jumpstart a no-carbon energy revolution over the next 10 years. In 2008, Time named him "A Hero of the Environment." He co-founded the ecomodernist Breakthrough Institute, which advocates the use of advanced technologies such as nuclear power and agricultural biotechnology to decouple the economy from the ecology, allowing both humanity and the natural world to flourish. More recently, he founded Environmental Progress, which campaigns for, among other things, the deployment of clean modern nuclear power. He is an invited expert reviewer of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change's next assessment report.</p><p>Ohio Passes Controversial Conscience Clause for Doctors</p><p>So what does he say about climate change? "On behalf of environmentalists everywhere, I would like to formally apologize for the climate scare we created over the last 30 years," he wrote in an essay to promote his new book. "<u><strong><mark>Climate</mark> change <mark>is</mark> happening. It's just <mark>not the end of the world</u></strong></mark>. It's not even our most serious environmental problem." Needless to say, there are environmentalists everywhere who do not believe they have anything to apologize for. A group of six researchers assembled by the widely respected Climate Feedback fact-checking consortium rated his article as having low scientific credibility.</p><p>Shellenberger doesn't devote much of Apocalypse Never to the science behind man-made climate change. He basically accepts the consensus that it's a significant problem and instead focuses on various claims about the harms it is supposedly already causing. In that promotional essay, he argues that (1) <u><strong><mark>human[s]</mark> being <mark>are not causing</mark> a "sixth <mark>mass extinction</mark>,"</u></strong> (2) <u><strong>the <mark>Amazon</mark> rainforests <mark>are not the "lungs</mark> of the world,"</u></strong> (3) <u><strong>climate change is not making natural disasters worse, and</u></strong> (4) <u><strong><mark>fires</mark> have <mark>declined</mark> 25 percent around the world since 2003</u></strong>.</p><p>Shellenberger isn't denying the reality of man-made climate change. He's arguing that <u><strong><mark>humanity is</mark> already <mark>adapting</mark> to the ways climate change has been making weather patterns evolve, <mark>and</mark> that we <mark>will continue</mark> to adapt successfully in the future</u></strong>. His book is ultimately a sustained argument that poverty is world's most important environmental problem, and that <u><strong>rising <mark>prosperity and</mark> increasing <mark>tech</mark>nological <mark>prowess will</u></strong></mark> ameliorate or <u><strong><mark>reverse most</mark> deleterious environmental <mark>trends</u></strong></mark>.</p> | 1NC vs George Mason BY | Advantage 1 | Environment D: Resilient—1NC | 5,517 | 173 | 146,975 | ./documents/ndtceda22/Minnesota/HaHe/Minnesota-HaHe-Neg-ADA-Fall-Championship-Round-1.docx | 944,167 | N | ADA Fall Championship | 1 | George Mason BY | Niki Brooks | 1ac-RoN, warming, water scarcity
1nc- court, Spillover, PTD CP, Fetus DA, Human duty CP, ag DA, Case,
2nr- scarcity turn, case, spillover | ndtceda22/Minnesota/HaHe/Minnesota-HaHe-Neg-ADA-Fall-Championship-Round-1.docx | 2022-11-16 16:37:39 | 82,290 | HaHe | Minnesota HaHe | null | Be..... | Ha..... | Ja..... | He..... | 27,133 | Minnesota | Minnesota | null | 6,285 | 2,001 | ndtceda22 | NDT/CEDA College 2022-23 | 2,022 | cx | college | 2 |
3,970,739 | New drains on resources undermine effective PFAS regulations | NAWCA, ’21 | NAWCA, ’21 — represents the interests of publicly owned wastewater treatment facilities, collection systems, and stormwater management agencies before the United States Congress, several Federal agencies, and in the courts. (National Association of Clean Water Agencies; “NACWA Sends Suite of Recommendations to EPA’s PFAS Council;” Published 17 June 2021; https://www.nacwa.org/news-publications/clean-water-current-archives/clean-water-current/2021/06/17/nacwa-sends-suite-of-recommendations-to-epa-s-pfas-council; //Mojica) | NACWA sent a letter on June 14 to EPC detailing specific recommendations for EPA to consider as it develops a multi-year strategy to address PFAS NACWA also hopes that the Agency will prioritize the most meaningful federal actions to reign in the seemingly endless use of a ubiquitous, nearly indestructible, anthropogenic suite of PFAS chemicals found in our everyday consumer products EPA can leverage existing environmental statutes and regulations to effectively protect human health and the environment while aggressively pursuing a “polluter pays” model Ensuring EPA has the tools and resources it needs to effectively eliminate these chemicals at the source is paramount state regulatory agencies and legislatures create a patchwork of compliance regimes that are nearly impossible to manage. NACWA encourages Accelerate Federal Research on PFAS Toxicity and Risk Continue Evaluating and Developing Regulatory Measures for Upstream Industrial Sources of PFAS under the CWA and TRI Continue to Develop CWA Analytical Methods Accelerate EPA’s Ongoing Efforts to Complete a Biosolids Risk Assessment Protect “Passive Receivers” Against CERCLA Liability Take an Aggressive Risk Management Approach Using TSCA NACWA will keep members up to speed on next steps | NACWA hopes the Agency prioritize most meaningful federal actions to reign in PFAS EPA can leverage statutes to protect health and environment Ensuring EPA has resources it needs to effectively eliminate these chemicals paramount state regimes impossible to manage NACWA encourages Federal Research Regulatory Measures CWA Methods Accelerate EPA’s Efforts to Complete a Biosolids Risk Assessment Take an Aggressive Approach | NACWA sent a letter on June 14 to EPA’s newly formed EPA PFAS Council (EPC) detailing specific recommendations for EPA to consider as it develops a multi-year strategy to address PFAS. Ultimately, EPC’s leadership in articulating a vision for addressing PFAS will not only provide greater certainty to the public at large and the regulated community, but NACWA also hopes that the Agency will prioritize the most meaningful federal actions to reign in the seemingly endless use of a ubiquitous, nearly indestructible, anthropogenic suite of PFAS chemicals found in our everyday consumer products. NACWA believes EPA can leverage existing environmental statutes and regulations to effectively protect human health and the environment while aggressively pursuing a “polluter pays” model. Due to the lack of clear federal direction, states are setting screening levels and imposing regulatory requirements – often with insufficient scientific basis or consideration of potential unintended consequences. Ensuring EPA has the tools and resources it needs to effectively eliminate these chemicals at the source is paramount to not only addressing this systemic issue but also so that state regulatory agencies and legislatures do not create a patchwork of compliance regimes that are nearly impossible to manage. NACWA encourages EPC to consider the following recommendations from the public clean water community: Accelerate Federal Research on PFAS Toxicity and Risk Continue Evaluating and Developing Regulatory Measures for Upstream Industrial Sources of PFAS under the CWA and TRI Continue to Develop CWA Analytical Methods Accelerate EPA’s Ongoing Efforts to Complete a Biosolids Risk Assessment Protect “Passive Receivers” Against CERCLA Liability Take an Aggressive Risk Management Approach Using TSCA NACWA will keep members up to speed on next steps and looks forward to participating in any public stakeholder opportunity to engage with the Agency on addressing PFAS in our environment. | 1,992 | <h4>New drains on resources undermine effective PFAS regulations</h4><p><strong>NAWCA, ’21</strong> — represents the interests of publicly owned wastewater treatment facilities, collection systems, and stormwater management agencies before the United States Congress, several Federal agencies, and in the courts. (National Association of Clean Water Agencies; “NACWA Sends Suite of Recommendations to EPA’s PFAS Council;” Published 17 June 2021; https://www.nacwa.org/news-publications/clean-water-current-archives/clean-water-current/2021/06/17/nacwa-sends-suite-of-recommendations-to-epa-s-pfas-council; //Mojica)</p><p><u>NACWA sent a letter on June 14 to</u> EPA’s newly formed EPA PFAS Council (<u>EPC</u>) <u>detailing specific recommendations for EPA to consider as it develops a multi-year strategy to address PFAS</u>. Ultimately, EPC’s leadership in articulating a vision for addressing PFAS will not only provide greater certainty to the public at large and the regulated community, but <u><mark>NACWA</mark> also <mark>hopes</mark> that <mark>the Agency </mark>will <strong><mark>prioritize </mark>the <mark>most meaningful federal actions</strong> to reign in</mark> the seemingly endless use of a ubiquitous, nearly indestructible, anthropogenic suite of <mark>PFAS </mark>chemicals found in our everyday consumer products</u>. NACWA believes <u><mark>EPA can leverage</mark> existing environmental <mark>statutes</mark> and regulations <mark>to</mark> effectively <mark>protect</mark> human <mark>health and </mark>the <mark>environment</mark> while aggressively pursuing a “polluter pays” model</u>. Due to the lack of clear federal direction, states are setting screening levels and imposing regulatory requirements – often with insufficient scientific basis or consideration of potential unintended consequences. <u><strong><mark>Ensuring EPA has </mark>the tools and <mark>resources it needs to effectively</mark> <mark>eliminate these chemicals</mark> at the source is <mark>paramount</u></strong></mark> to not only addressing this systemic issue but also so that <u><mark>state</mark> regulatory agencies and legislatures</u> do not <u>create a patchwork of compliance <mark>regimes</mark> that are nearly <mark>impossible to manage</mark>. <mark>NACWA encourages</u></mark> EPC to consider the following recommendations from the public clean water community: <u>Accelerate <strong><mark>Federal Research</strong></mark> on PFAS Toxicity and Risk Continue Evaluating and <strong>Developing <mark>Regulatory Measures</strong></mark> for Upstream Industrial Sources of PFAS under the CWA and TRI Continue to Develop <mark>CWA</mark> Analytical <mark>Methods</mark> <mark>Accelerate EPA’s</mark> Ongoing <mark>Efforts to Complete a Biosolids Risk Assessment</mark> Protect “Passive Receivers” Against CERCLA Liability <mark>Take an Aggressive</mark> Risk Management <mark>Approach</mark> Using TSCA NACWA will keep members up to speed on next steps</u> and looks forward to participating in any public stakeholder opportunity to engage with the Agency on addressing PFAS in our environment.</p> | 1NC—Lex Quarters | 1NC—OFF | 1NC—DA | 23,398 | 310 | 134,182 | ./documents/hspolicy21/ArchbishopMitty/KhBh/Archbishop%20Mitty-Kher-Bhadani-Neg-3%20-%20Lexington-Quarters.docx | 743,572 | N | 3 - Lexington | Quarters | Mamaroneck BT | Panel | null | hspolicy21/ArchbishopMitty/KhBh/Archbishop%20Mitty-Kher-Bhadani-Neg-3%20-%20Lexington-Quarters.docx | null | 63,328 | KhBh | Archbishop Mitty KhBh | null | Ta..... | Kh..... | An..... | Bh..... | 21,876 | ArchbishopMitty | Archbishop Mitty | CA | null | 1,020 | hspolicy21 | HS Policy 2021-22 | 2,021 | cx | hs | 2 |
4,092,014 | Economic superiority and resilience solves existential threats---specifically, conflict with China. | Sitaraman 20 | Sitaraman 20 [Ganesh is a professor of Law at Vanderbilt Law School, 8/11/20, A Grand Strategy of Resilience, Foreign Affairs, https://www.foreignaffairs.com/articles/united-states/2020-08-11/grand-strategy-resilience] Justin | The coming era will be one of health crises, climate shocks, cyberattacks, and geoeconomic competition This year, a pandemic Next year, it might be a drought The year after a cyberattack could take out the grid or cut of critical supply chains the U S is woefully underprepared for handling disruptions. What it needs is an economy that can prevent these challenges and bounce back the United States needs a grand strategy of resilience
The government’s goal should be to minimize disruptions—to build a system that can prevent economic disaster
Climate change could pose a threat. A sustained drought threaten the global food supply. Rising sea levels flood low-lying cities. Fires already disrupt life Climate-induced crises will lead to migrations globally and social unrest and violence
Cyberattacks have targeted U.S. Cyberattacks on the grid could “deny large regions access to bulk system power for months,”
All these challenges play out at a time of rivalry especially geoeconomic competition—among great powers the U S has been the world’s most powerful economy and safe from outside economic pressures as China’s economic strength grows, that is likely to change. China’s ability to exploit that dependence in a future crisis or conflict should be worrisome. A strategy based on resilience deter coercion and minimize disruption | coming era one of health climate cyber and geoeconomic competition the U S is underprepared for disruptions it needs an economy that can prevent challenges and bounce back
government’s should minimize disruptions a system that can prevent economic disaster
Climate change sustained drought threaten global food crises lead to migrations and violence
Cyberattacks on grid deny access to power
U S most powerful economy and safe from pressures as China’s economic strength grows, that change China exploit that in a conflict resilience minimize disruption | Every so often in the history of the United States, there are moments of political realignment—times when the consensus that defined an era collapses and a new paradigm emerges. The liberal era ushered in by President Franklin Roosevelt defined U.S. politics for a generation. So did the neoliberal wave that followed in the 1980s. Today, that era, too, is coming to a close, its demise hastened by the election of President Donald Trump and the chaos of the coronavirus pandemic.
The coming era will be one of health crises, climate shocks, cyberattacks, and geoeconomic competition among great powers. What unites those seemingly disparate threats is that each is not so much a battle to be won as a challenge to be weathered. This year, a pandemic is forcing hundreds of millions of Americans to stay at home. Next year, it might be a 1,000-year drought that devastates agriculture and food production. The year after that, a cyberattack could take out the power grid or cut of critical supply chains. If the current pandemic is any indication, the United States is woefully underprepared for handling such disruptions. What it needs is an economy, a society, and a democracy that can prevent these challenges when possible and endure, bounce back, and adapt when necessary—and do so without suffering thousands of deaths and seeing millions unemployed. What the United States needs is a grand strategy of resilience.
For psychologists who research child development, resilience is what enables some children to endure traumatic events and emerge stronger and better able to navigate future stresses. For ecologists, resilience is an ecosystem’s ability to resist, recover, and adapt to ires, loods, or invasive species. For emergency, disaster relief, and homeland security experts, a resilient system is flexible, adaptable, and can withstand an impact. The writer Maria Konnikova has summed up the concept with a single question: “Do you succumb or do you surmount?”
The highest goal for American policymakers should be to preserve and defend the country’s constitutional democracy while enabling Americans to thrive regardless of their race, gender, location, or origin. A society that achieves that goal will be better prepared to face the next crisis. A more equal and more just nation is a more resilient one.
Although Americans tend to think of grand strategy as an overarching foreign policy vision, any true grand strategy requires a solid domestic foundation. The United States’ Cold War policy of containment, for instance, had a domestic analog, although it is less emphasized in the foreign policy community. For a generation after World War II, Democrats and Republicans alike embraced a model of regulated capitalism, with high taxes, inancial regulations, strong unions, and social safety net programs, and thus charted a path between the totalitarian control of the Soviet Union and the laissez-faire approach that had plunged the United States into the Great Depression. Regulated capitalism and containment together were the grand strategy that deined the post–World War II era. A grand strategy of resilience, likewise, will not meet with success unless the United States addresses the many forms of inequality, fragility, and weakness that undermine the country’s preparedness from within.
AGE OF CRISES
“Grand strategy” is a slippery term, with perhaps as many deinitions as authors who invoke it. It can describe a framework that guides and focuses leaders and societies on their aims and priorities. Critics of the notion believe this is impossible: no paradigm, they say, can help navigate a chaotic, uncertain future, and in any case, U.S. society is too polarized to identify a consensus paradigm today. But the skeptics have it backward. Grand strategy is won, not found. It emerges from argument and debate. And it is useful precisely because it offers guidance in a complex world.
Start with pandemics. For hundreds of years, quarantines have been essential to preventing the spread of infectious diseases. But today’s stay-at-home orders have exacted a devastating social, eco-nomic, and psychological toll on individuals and communities. Small businesses that are closed may never reopen. Tens of millions of people are out of work. Families are struggling to juggle childcare, homeschooling, and working from home. The government’s goal should be to minimize those disruptions—to build a system that can prevent economic disaster, secure supply chains for essential materials, and massively scale up production and testing when needed.
Climate change could pose an even bigger threat. A sustained drought, akin to the one that created the Dust Bowl during the Great Depression, could threaten the global food supply. Rising sea levels, especially when coupled with storms, could flood low-lying cities. Fires already disrupt life in California every year. Climate-induced crises will also lead to population migrations globally and, with them, social unrest and violence. Part of the answer is aggressive action to limit increases in temperature. But in addition, the United States must be able to endure climate shocks when they arise.
Consider also the country’s dependence on technology and the vulnerabilities it entails. Cyberattacks have already targeted U.S. election systems, banks, the Pentagon, and even local governments. The city of Riviera Beach, Florida, was forced to pay a ransom to cybercriminals who had taken over its computer systems; big cities, such as Atlanta and Baltimore, have faced similar attacks. Cyberattacks on the U.S. power grid, akin to the one that led to blackouts in Ukraine in December 2015, could “deny large regions of the country access to bulk system power for weeks or even months,” according to the National Academy of Sciences.
All these challenges will play out at a time of growing rivalry—and especially geoeconomic competition—among great powers. Over the last half century, the United States has been the world’s most powerful economy and has thus been relatively safe from outside economic pressures. But as China’s economic strength grows, that is likely to change. The United States and other democracies have become dependent on China for essential and nonessential goods. China’s ability to exploit that dependence in a future crisis or conflict should be extremely worrisome. A strategy based on resilience would help deter such coercion and minimize the disruption if it does occur. | 6,476 | <h4><u>Economic superiority</u> and <u>resilience</u> solves <u>existential threats</u>---specifically, <u>conflict</u> with <u>China</u>.</h4><p><strong>Sitaraman 20</strong> [Ganesh is a professor of Law at Vanderbilt Law School, 8/11/20, A Grand Strategy of Resilience, Foreign Affairs, https://www.foreignaffairs.com/articles/united-states/2020-08-11/grand-strategy-resilience] Justin</p><p>Every so often in the history of the United States, there are moments of political realignment—times when the consensus that defined an era collapses and a new paradigm emerges. The liberal era ushered in by President Franklin Roosevelt defined U.S. politics for a generation. So did the neoliberal wave that followed in the 1980s. Today, that era, too, is coming to a close, its demise hastened by the election of President Donald Trump and the chaos of the coronavirus pandemic.</p><p><u>The <strong><mark>coming era</strong></mark> will be <mark>one of <strong>health</mark> crises</strong>, <strong><mark>climate</mark> shocks</strong>, <strong><mark>cyber</mark>attacks</strong>, <mark>and <strong>geoeconomic competition</u></strong></mark> among great powers. What unites those seemingly disparate threats is that each is not so much a battle to be won as a challenge to be weathered. <u>This year, a <strong>pandemic</u></strong> is forcing hundreds of millions of Americans to stay at home. <u>Next year, it might be a</u> 1,000-year <u><strong>drought</u></strong> that devastates agriculture and food production. <u>The year after</u> that, <u>a <strong>cyberattack</strong> could take out the</u> power <u>grid or cut of critical supply chains</u>. If the current pandemic is any indication, <u><mark>the U</u></mark>nited <u><mark>S</u></mark>tates <u><mark>is</mark> <strong>woefully <mark>underprepared</strong> for</mark> handling</u> such <u><strong><mark>disruptions</strong></mark>. What <mark>it needs</mark> is <mark>an <strong>economy</u></strong></mark>, a society, and a democracy <u><mark>that can <strong>prevent</mark> these <mark>challenges</u></strong></mark> when possible <u><mark>and</u></mark> endure, <u><strong><mark>bounce back</u></strong></mark>, and adapt when necessary—and do so without suffering thousands of deaths and seeing millions unemployed. What <u>the United States needs</u> is <u>a grand strategy of resilience</u>.</p><p>For psychologists who research child development, resilience is what enables some children to endure traumatic events and emerge stronger and better able to navigate future stresses. For ecologists, resilience is an ecosystem’s ability to resist, recover, and adapt to ires, loods, or invasive species. For emergency, disaster relief, and homeland security experts, a resilient system is flexible, adaptable, and can withstand an impact. The writer Maria Konnikova has summed up the concept with a single question: “Do you succumb or do you surmount?”</p><p>The highest goal for American policymakers should be to preserve and defend the country’s constitutional democracy while enabling Americans to thrive regardless of their race, gender, location, or origin. A society that achieves that goal will be better prepared to face the next crisis. A more equal and more just nation is a more resilient one.</p><p>Although Americans tend to think of grand strategy as an overarching foreign policy vision, any true grand strategy requires a solid domestic foundation. The United States’ Cold War policy of containment, for instance, had a domestic analog, although it is less emphasized in the foreign policy community. For a generation after World War II, Democrats and Republicans alike embraced a model of regulated capitalism, with high taxes, inancial regulations, strong unions, and social safety net programs, and thus charted a path between the totalitarian control of the Soviet Union and the laissez-faire approach that had plunged the United States into the Great Depression. Regulated capitalism and containment together were the grand strategy that deined the post–World War II era. A grand strategy of resilience, likewise, will not meet with success unless the United States addresses the many forms of inequality, fragility, and weakness that undermine the country’s preparedness from within.</p><p>AGE OF CRISES</p><p>“Grand strategy” is a slippery term, with perhaps as many deinitions as authors who invoke it. It can describe a framework that guides and focuses leaders and societies on their aims and priorities. Critics of the notion believe this is impossible: no paradigm, they say, can help navigate a chaotic, uncertain future, and in any case, U.S. society is too polarized to identify a consensus paradigm today. But the skeptics have it backward. Grand strategy is won, not found. It emerges from argument and debate. And it is useful precisely because it offers guidance in a complex world.</p><p>Start with pandemics. For hundreds of years, quarantines have been essential to preventing the spread of infectious diseases. But today’s stay-at-home orders have exacted a devastating social, eco-nomic, and psychological toll on individuals and communities. Small businesses that are closed may never reopen. Tens of millions of people are out of work. Families are struggling to juggle childcare, homeschooling, and working from home. <u>The <mark>government’s</mark> goal <mark>should</mark> be to <strong><mark>minimize</u></strong></mark> those <u><strong><mark>disruptions</strong></mark>—to build <mark>a system that can <strong>prevent economic disaster</u></strong></mark>, secure supply chains for essential materials, and massively scale up production and testing when needed.</p><p><u><mark>Climate change</mark> could pose a</u>n even bigger <u><strong>threat</strong>. A <strong><mark>sustained drought</u></strong></mark>, akin to the one that created the Dust Bowl during the Great Depression, could <u><mark>threaten</mark> the <strong><mark>global food</mark> supply</strong>. Rising <strong>sea</strong> levels</u>, especially when coupled with storms, could <u><strong>flood</strong> low-lying <strong>cities</strong>. <strong>Fires</strong> already disrupt life</u> in California every year. <u><strong>Climate-induced <mark>crises</strong></mark> will</u> also <u><mark>lead to</u></mark> population <u><strong><mark>migrations</mark> globally</strong> <mark>and</u></mark>, with them, <u><strong>social unrest and <mark>violence</u></strong></mark>. Part of the answer is aggressive action to limit increases in temperature. But in addition, the United States must be able to endure climate shocks when they arise.</p><p>Consider also the country’s dependence on technology and the vulnerabilities it entails. <u>Cyberattacks have</u> already <u>targeted U.S.</u> election systems, banks, the Pentagon, and even local governments. The city of Riviera Beach, Florida, was forced to pay a ransom to cybercriminals who had taken over its computer systems; big cities, such as Atlanta and Baltimore, have faced similar attacks. <u><strong><mark>Cyberattacks</strong> on</mark> the</u> U.S. power <u><mark>grid</u></mark>, akin to the one that led to blackouts in Ukraine in December 2015, <u>could “<strong><mark>deny</mark> large regions</u></strong> of the country <u><mark>access to</mark> <strong>bulk system <mark>power</strong></mark> for</u> weeks or even <u>months,”</u> according to the National Academy of Sciences.</p><p><u>All these challenges</u> will <u><strong>play out</strong> at a time of</u> growing <u><strong>rivalry</u></strong>—and <u>especially geoeconomic competition—among great powers</u>. Over the last half century, <u>the <mark>U</u></mark>nited <u><mark>S</u></mark>tates <u>has been the <strong>world’s <mark>most powerful</strong> <strong>economy</strong> and</u></mark> has thus been relatively <u><strong><mark>safe</strong> from</mark> outside <strong>economic <mark>pressures</u></strong></mark>. But <u><mark>as <strong>China’s</strong> economic strength <strong>grows</strong>, that</mark> is <strong>likely to <mark>change</mark>.</u></strong> The United States and other democracies have become dependent on China for essential and nonessential goods. <u><mark>China</mark>’s ability to <mark>exploit that</mark> dependence <mark>in a</mark> <strong>future crisis or <mark>conflict</strong></mark> should be</u> extremely <u><strong>worrisome</strong>. A strategy based on <mark>resilience</u></mark> would help <u><strong>deter</u></strong> such <u><strong>coercion</strong> and <strong><mark>minimize</u></strong></mark> the <u><strong><mark>disruption</u></strong></mark> if it does occur. </p> | null | 1AC | 1AC – Advantage | 317,822 | 177 | 140,295 | ./documents/hsld22/WilliamGEnloe/PhDa/WilliamGEnloe-PhDa-Aff-New-York-City-Invitational-Debate-and-Speech-Tournament-Round-3.docx | 935,409 | A | 03 - New York City Invitational Debate and Speech Tournament | 3 | Dallastown JK | Jenn Melin | 1AC-Kant
1NC-Lay
1AR-All
2NR-All
2AR-Kant
Melin votes aff | hsld22/WilliamGEnloe/PhDa/WilliamGEnloe-PhDa-Aff-New-York-City-Invitational-Debate-and-Speech-Tournament-Round-3.docx | 2023-03-08 13:16:01 | 79,901 | PhDa | William G Enloe PhDa | null | Ph..... | Da..... | null | null | 26,865 | WilliamGEnloe | William G Enloe | NC | null | 2,003 | hsld22 | HS LD 2022-23 | 2,022 | ld | hs | 1 |
4,747,743 | COVID is causing a food security crisis – only intra-African trade solves structural barriers | Akiwumi 20 | Paul Akiwumi 20 {Director for Africa and Least Developed Countries, UNCTAD} - ("COVID-19: A threat to food security in Africa," UNCTAD, published 8-1-2020, accessed 12-13-2022, https://unctad.org/news/covid-19-threat-food-security-africa)//marlborough-wr/ | a deep coronavirus-induced global recession threatens a nearly 4% drop in world GDP and could drag the GDP of African economies into a fall of about 1.4%, with smaller economies facing a contraction of up to 7.8%.
This decline is mainly a result of export adjustments affecting primary commodity exporters and associated tax revenue losses. This in turn, reduces governments’ capacity to extend the public services needed to respond effectively to the crisis.
UNCTAD estimates a regional average of about 5% in public revenue losses in Africa. Total merchandise exports are expected to contract by about 17% in 2020.
With at least 60% of the African population dependent on agriculture for their livelihoods and access to food, any trade-related distortions to the sector can threaten the food security of the continent’s poor.
there is a strong positive correlation between economic recession and food insecurity in Africa. Despite the continent’s huge resource endowments (including a wide availability of arable land, and a young, growing labour force, among other factors), the continent’s agricultural production alone, hampered by distribution, access, and affordability challenges, is insufficient to meet its food security needs.
Africa imported about 85% of its food from outside the continent This heavy reliance on world markets is detrimental to food security, especially at a time of acute crisis. A situation exacerbated by the current COVID-19 crisis through its direct impacts on trade, logistics, production and value chains. the disruption of marketing and trade activities, and COVID-19-related panic-buying, exacerbated food price increases
Administrative restrictions imposed by governments, such as lockdowns, travel restrictions and physical distancing measures have also worsened the risk of food insecurity.
In Africa 73 million people are acutely food insecure. A regional slump in food production and a fall in global demand may prolong the negative trade effects of COVID-19, with poverty and food insecurity expected to continue to rise
African net food exporters were among the hardest hit. They not only faced low export volumes due to depressed world demand, but also a productivity slump the impact on the food sector is disproportionately higher among smaller economies, which face a relatively deeper reduction in their food exports and resulting revenue
the key COVID-19 related shock to their economies is the collapse in demand for tourism services. heavy reliance on trade taxes and duties could lead to severe COVID-19 related revenue losses in African LDCs Revenue losses greatly undermine the ability to import productivity-enhancing inputs for domestic production and food exports.
In order to address the impact of COVID-19 on food security in the long term, Africa will need to build productive capacities to address underlying economic vulnerabilities African governments should ensure the movement of goods, including food, and related essential services (i.e. transportation) is guaranteed COVID-19 has clearly highlighted the degree of interconnectedness between countries and the importance of maintaining trade links to ensure minimal disruptions to food supply.
African countries also need to reduce their commodity dependence, which has been among the key factors increasing their vulnerability to food insecurity. The diversification of their commodity base and value addition will be critical if augmented by a significant increase in agricultural labour productivity and the full implementation of AfCFTA food security in African countries will benefit from the effective implementation of the AfCFTA This includes through greater economic diversification (value addition and intra-African trade), the creation of jobs and revenue to fight poverty and food insecurity. the AfCFTA can support the procurement of food from closer regional markets. All these factors could go a long way to enhance the continent’s food security and reduce vulnerability to current and emerging shocks. | a deep coronavirus induced recession could drag GDP of African economies
60% of the African population dependent on agriculture trade distortions threaten food security
the continent’s production hampered by distribution, access, and affordability is insufficient
Africa imported 85% of its food reliance is detrimental especially at a time of crisis
African exporters were among the hardest hit
African governments should ensure movement is guaranteed COVID highlighted importance of trade to ensure minimal disruptions
increase in labour and implementation of AfCFTA includes economic diversification ( intra-African trade) jobs regional markets | The International Monetary Fund has projected a deep coronavirus-induced global recession, which threatens a nearly 4% drop in world GDP and could drag the GDP of African economies into a fall of about 1.4%, with smaller economies facing a contraction of up to 7.8%.
This decline is mainly a result of export adjustments affecting primary commodity exporters and associated tax revenue losses. This in turn, reduces governments’ capacity to extend the public services needed to respond effectively to the crisis.
Overall, UNCTAD estimates a regional average of about 5% in public revenue losses in Africa. Total merchandise exports are expected to contract by about 17% in 2020.
These losses will have repercussions on Africa’s progress towards the Sustainable Development Goals and Africa’s Agenda 2063. With at least 60% of the African population dependent on agriculture for their livelihoods and access to food, any trade-related distortions to the sector can threaten the food security of the continent’s poor.
In addition to the impact of extreme climate shocks on agricultural productivity, there is a strong positive correlation between economic recession and food insecurity in Africa. Despite the continent’s huge resource endowments (including a wide availability of arable land, and a young, growing labour force, among other factors), the continent’s agricultural production alone, hampered by distribution, access, and affordability challenges, is insufficient to meet its food security needs.
Huge food importer
From 2016 to 2018, Africa imported about 85% of its food from outside the continent, leading to an annual food import bill of $35 billion, which is forecast to reach $110 billion by 2025. This heavy reliance on world markets is detrimental to food security, especially at a time of acute crisis. A situation exacerbated by the current COVID-19 crisis through its direct impacts on trade, logistics, production and value chains. In several African countries, the disruption of marketing and trade activities, and COVID-19-related panic-buying, exacerbated food price increases (especially cereals) between March and June.
National policy responses to limit the impact of COVID-19 on food markets in Africa have varied, from the removal of value-added taxes on food products to export restrictions on key food items. For example, on 26 March, Kenya reduced the value-added tax on all goods from 16% to 14%. Sudan introduced a ban on sorghum exports on 15 April to ensure domestic availability. Export restriction policies and hoarding short-circuit trade and distribution, thus exacerbating the risks of food insecurity, especially for the continent’s most vulnerable populations.
Administrative restrictions imposed by governments, such as lockdowns, travel restrictions and physical distancing measures have also worsened the risk of food insecurity. These restrictions are being felt particularly strongly by low-income households and those working in the informal economy, due to their loss of livelihoods and inability to access markets.
Worsening hunger
In Africa, recent estimates suggest that 73 million people are acutely food insecure. Furthermore, since last year, African regions, particularly the Sahel and southern Africa, have been severely affected by climate change. And the unprecedented locust outbreak in the Horn of Africa put additional pressure on regional food systems. The region is particularly at risk, given the prevalence of conflict and political instability. A regional slump in food production and a fall in global demand may prolong the negative trade effects of COVID-19, with poverty and food insecurity expected to continue to rise in 2021.
UNCTAD’s macro-econometric model assessing the possible effects of COVID-19 on African economies generates conservative estimates based only on global shocks that affected trade between Africa and the rest of the world. The results of the model show that African net food exporters were among the hardest hit. They not only faced low export volumes due to depressed world demand, but also a productivity slump. This will take time to return to equilibrium after 2020. However, the impact on the food sector is disproportionately higher among smaller economies, which face a relatively deeper reduction in their food exports and resulting revenue. In the worst-case scenario of a 4% drop in worldwide GDP, UNCTAD estimates that food exports from African countries could decline by about 3%. This could be accompanied by a total contraction in the region’s GDP of about 1.4%. At the country level, GDP contractions could reach 7.8% in Comoros, 6% in Guinea Bissau, 5.6 % in the Seychelles and 4.5% in Malawi, among others.
Although food exports are important, for small island developing states (SIDS) like Comoros and the Seychelles, the key COVID-19 related shock to their economies is the collapse in demand for tourism services. Furthermore, heavy reliance on trade taxes and duties could lead to severe COVID-19 related revenue losses in African LDCs. According to UNCTAD’s forthcoming model, revenue losses could reach 5.8% in Burundi, -7.6% in Comoros, -10% in The Gambia, -10.2% in Malawi, and -7% Sierra Leone. Revenue losses greatly undermine the ability to import productivity-enhancing inputs for domestic production and food exports. Furthermore, despite the favourability of lower fuel prices for net fuel importers, the recession in least developed countries and SIDS may also lead to reduced fuel imports, as production in other sectors remains depressed. For example, countries like Burundi (-26.6%), Cabo Verde (-8.5%), Comoros (-30%) and Malawi (-15%) are all expected to import less fuels during 2020 and 2021.
How to blunt the COVID-19 impact
In order to address the impact of COVID-19 on food security in the long term, Africa will need to build productive capacities to address underlying economic vulnerabilities, and strengthen continental capabilities to better manage food, pandemic and/or health-related crises. Unnecessary export restrictions on food can have far-reaching consequences for the multilateral trading system and African economies. Such measures will not only impede progress in managing the current crisis, but also compromise African countries’ longer-term efforts to tackle food insecurity and poverty. African governments should ensure the movement of goods, including food, and related essential services (i.e. transportation) is guaranteed. COVID-19 has clearly highlighted the degree of interconnectedness between countries and the importance of maintaining trade links to ensure minimal disruptions to food supply.
African countries also need to reduce their commodity dependence, which has been among the key factors increasing their vulnerability to food insecurity. The diversification of their commodity base and value addition will be critical in achieving this, particularly if effectively augmented by a significant increase in agricultural labour productivity and the full implementation of the African Continental Free Trade Area (AfCFTA). It is likely that food security in African countries will benefit from the effective implementation of the AfCFTA. This includes through greater economic diversification (value addition and intra-African trade), the creation of jobs and revenue to fight poverty and food insecurity. Moreover, the AfCFTA can support the procurement of food from closer regional markets. All these factors could go a long way to enhance the continent’s food security and reduce vulnerability to current and emerging shocks. | 7,605 | <h4>COVID is causing a <u>food security crisis</u> – only intra-African trade solves <u>structural barriers</h4><p></u>Paul <strong>Akiwumi 20</strong> {Director for Africa and Least Developed Countries, UNCTAD} - ("COVID-19: A threat to food security in Africa," UNCTAD, published 8-1-2020, accessed 12-13-2022, https://unctad.org/news/covid-19-threat-food-security-africa)//marlborough-wr/</p><p>The International Monetary Fund has projected <u><mark>a <strong>deep coronavirus</mark>-<mark>induced</mark> global <mark>recession</u></strong></mark>, which <u>threatens a nearly 4% drop in world GDP and <mark>could</mark> <mark>drag</mark> the <mark>GDP of African economies</mark> into a fall of about 1.4%, with smaller economies facing a contraction of up to 7.8%.</p><p>This decline is mainly a result of export adjustments affecting primary commodity exporters and associated tax revenue losses. This in turn, reduces governments’ capacity to extend the public services needed to respond effectively to the crisis.</p><p></u>Overall, <u>UNCTAD estimates a regional average of about 5% in public revenue losses in Africa. Total merchandise exports are expected to contract by about 17% in 2020.</p><p></u>These losses will have repercussions on Africa’s progress towards the Sustainable Development Goals and Africa’s Agenda 2063. <u>With at least <strong><mark>60% of the African population dependent on agriculture</strong></mark> for their livelihoods and access to food, any <mark>trade</mark>-related <mark>distortions</mark> to the sector can <strong><mark>threaten</mark> the <mark>food security</strong></mark> of the continent’s poor.</p><p></u>In addition to the impact of extreme climate shocks on agricultural productivity, <u>there is a <strong>strong positive correlation between economic recession and food insecurity</strong> in Africa. Despite the continent’s huge resource endowments (including a wide availability of arable land, and a young, growing labour force, among other factors), <mark>the</mark> <mark>continent’s</mark> agricultural <mark>production</mark> alone, <mark>hampered</mark> <mark>by distribution, access, and affordability</mark> challenges, <mark>is insufficient</mark> to meet its food security needs.</p><p></u>Huge food importer</p><p>From 2016 to 2018, <u><mark>Africa imported</mark> about <mark>85% of its food</mark> from outside the continent</u>, leading to an annual food import bill of $35 billion, which is forecast to reach $110 billion by 2025. <u>This heavy <mark>reliance</mark> on world markets <mark>is detrimental </mark>to food security, <mark>especially</mark> <mark>at</mark> <mark>a time of</mark> acute <mark>crisis</mark>. A situation exacerbated by the current COVID-19 crisis through its direct impacts on trade, logistics, production and value chains.</u> In several African countries, <u>the disruption of marketing and trade activities, and COVID-19-related panic-buying, exacerbated food price increases</u> (especially cereals) between March and June.</p><p>National policy responses to limit the impact of COVID-19 on food markets in Africa have varied, from the removal of value-added taxes on food products to export restrictions on key food items. For example, on 26 March, Kenya reduced the value-added tax on all goods from 16% to 14%. Sudan introduced a ban on sorghum exports on 15 April to ensure domestic availability. Export restriction policies and hoarding short-circuit trade and distribution, thus exacerbating the risks of food insecurity, especially for the continent’s most vulnerable populations.</p><p><u>Administrative restrictions imposed by governments, such as lockdowns, travel restrictions and physical distancing measures have also worsened the risk of food insecurity.</u> These restrictions are being felt particularly strongly by low-income households and those working in the informal economy, due to their loss of livelihoods and inability to access markets.</p><p>Worsening hunger</p><p><u>In Africa</u>, recent estimates suggest that <u>73 million people are acutely food insecure.</u> Furthermore, since last year, African regions, particularly the Sahel and southern Africa, have been severely affected by climate change. And the unprecedented locust outbreak in the Horn of Africa put additional pressure on regional food systems. The region is particularly at risk, given the prevalence of conflict and political instability. <u>A regional slump in food production and a fall in global demand may prolong the negative trade effects of COVID-19, with poverty and food insecurity expected to continue to rise </u>in 2021.</p><p>UNCTAD’s macro-econometric model assessing the possible effects of COVID-19 on African economies generates conservative estimates based only on global shocks that affected trade between Africa and the rest of the world. The results of the model show that <u><mark>African</mark> net food <mark>exporters</mark> <mark>were among the hardest hit</mark>. They not only faced low export volumes due to depressed world demand, but also a productivity slump</u>. This will take time to return to equilibrium after 2020. However, <u>the impact on the food sector is disproportionately higher among smaller economies, which face a relatively deeper reduction in their food exports and resulting revenue</u>. In the worst-case scenario of a 4% drop in worldwide GDP, UNCTAD estimates that food exports from African countries could decline by about 3%. This could be accompanied by a total contraction in the region’s GDP of about 1.4%. At the country level, GDP contractions could reach 7.8% in Comoros, 6% in Guinea Bissau, 5.6 % in the Seychelles and 4.5% in Malawi, among others.</p><p>Although food exports are important, for small island developing states (SIDS) like Comoros and the Seychelles, <u>the key COVID-19 related shock to their economies is the collapse in demand for tourism services.</u> Furthermore, <u>heavy reliance on trade taxes and duties could lead to severe COVID-19 related revenue losses in African LDCs</u>. According to UNCTAD’s forthcoming model, revenue losses could reach 5.8% in Burundi, -7.6% in Comoros, -10% in The Gambia, -10.2% in Malawi, and -7% Sierra Leone. <u>Revenue losses greatly undermine the ability to import productivity-enhancing inputs for domestic production and food exports. </u>Furthermore, despite the favourability of lower fuel prices for net fuel importers, the recession in least developed countries and SIDS may also lead to reduced fuel imports, as production in other sectors remains depressed. For example, countries like Burundi (-26.6%), Cabo Verde (-8.5%), Comoros (-30%) and Malawi (-15%) are all expected to import less fuels during 2020 and 2021.</p><p>How to blunt the COVID-19 impact</p><p><u>In order to address the impact of COVID-19 on food security in the long term, Africa will need to <strong>build productive capacities to address underlying economic vulnerabilities</u></strong>, and strengthen continental capabilities to better manage food, pandemic and/or health-related crises. Unnecessary export restrictions on food can have far-reaching consequences for the multilateral trading system and African economies. Such measures will not only impede progress in managing the current crisis, but also compromise African countries’ longer-term efforts to tackle food insecurity and poverty. <u><mark>African governments should ensure</mark> the <mark>movement</mark> of goods, including food, and related essential services (i.e. transportation) <mark>is guaranteed</u></mark>. <u><mark>COVID</mark>-19 has clearly <mark>highlighted</mark> the <strong>degree of interconnectedness between countries</strong> and the <strong><mark>importance</mark> <mark>of</mark> maintaining <mark>trade</mark> links</strong> <mark>to ensure</mark> <mark>minimal disruptions</mark> to food supply.</p><p>African countries also need to r<strong>educe their commodity dependence</strong>, which has been among the <strong>key factors increasing their vulnerability to food insecurity</strong>.</u> <u>The diversification of their commodity base and value addition will be critical</u> in achieving this, particularly <u>if</u> effectively <u>augmented by a significant <mark>increase in</mark> agricultural <mark>labour</mark> productivity <mark>and</mark> the full <mark>implementation of</u></mark> the African Continental Free Trade Area (<u><mark>AfCFTA</u></mark>). It is likely that <u>food security in African countries will benefit from the <strong>effective implementation of the AfCFTA</u></strong>. <u>This <mark>includes</mark> through greater <strong><mark>economic diversification</mark> <mark>(</mark>value addition and <mark>intra-African trade</strong>)</mark>, the creation of <mark>jobs</mark> and revenue to fight poverty and food insecurity.</u> Moreover, <u>the AfCFTA <strong>can support the procurement of food from closer <mark>regional</mark> <mark>markets</strong></mark>. All these factors <strong>could go a long way</strong> to enhance the continent’s food security and <strong>reduce vulnerability to current and emerging shocks</strong>.</p></u> | null | AC Shell | Econ | 1,704,182 | 207 | 166,016 | ./documents/hsld22/Marlborough/ShLe/Marlborough-ShLe-Aff-Golden-Desert-(UNLV)-Round-1.docx | 971,358 | A | Golden Desert (UNLV) | 1 | Sage Oak AK | Allyson Spurlock | FMP, colonialism, econ
nC- da, cp, case
AR- case, da, cp
Nr- dedev
2AR- case, dedev | hsld22/Marlborough/ShLe/Marlborough-ShLe-Aff-Golden-Desert-(UNLV)-Round-1.docx | 2023-02-04 18:01:54 | 81,659 | ShLe | Marlborough ShLe | null | Sh..... | Le..... | null | null | 26,925 | Marlborough | Marlborough | CA | null | 2,003 | hsld22 | HS LD 2022-23 | 2,022 | ld | hs | 1 |
4,743,807 | Reforms fail – only the plan solves | Chen 18 | Chen 18 [(Ashley, former President of the Brown Political Review and a Senior Staff Writer for the US Section.) “Bridging the Gap: Why China’s Hukou System Needs Reform” Brown Pollical Review, 5/28/2018. https://brownpoliticalreview.org/2018/05/bridging-gap-chinas-hukou-system-needs-reform/] BC | China’s meteoric economic rise has relied on hundreds of millions of rural migrants These migrants make incredible sacrifices for the economic opportunity of moving to a city, often leaving behind their children and their homes. , these workers’ struggles stem from a seemingly benign migration control policy called “hukou” a household registration system that controls the movements of Chinese residents and defines people by birthplace as either urban or rural. Hukou status cannot change, so even when rural migrant workers find employment in large cities such as Shanghai, they retain rural hukou status.
the hukou system only exacerbates the rural-urban divide."
Holding a non-local hukou in an urban area drastically hinders access to basic social services, such as public schooling, subsidized medical care, and unemployment insurance. In a country with widespread negative stereotypes about the rural poor, the hukou system only exacerbates the rural-urban divide. To improve the hukou system, the government must implement reforms that benefit those moving from the countryside and into cities.
Urbanites and government leaders have rendered past hukou reform attempts ineffective. Urban residents have an economic interest in pushing for the status quo and many possess prejudiced attitudes toward migrants. One-third of Shanghai urbanites claimed they would not want a rural neighbor; only one-tenth felt the same way about having a poor one.
the reforms that have managed to pass have just created new obstacles for rural migrants. For example, a 1996 law gave migrant children the right to attend elementary and middle school in the cities where their parents worked. Schools responded with temporary resident fees and additional verification requirements for the children of rural migrants, deterring migrants from bringing their children to urban areas. And since the law did not extend to high schools, the few children who did benefit had to return to the countryside to finish their education.
In 2013, the government tried to introduce more drastic changes e countryside and allows them to be subject to a more relaxed birth-control policy. Most migrants thought the perks of rural hukou outweighed the meager benefits of third-tier urban hukou, so the 2013 reforms failed to produce any substantial changes.
China’s most recent attempt to liberalize hukou has allowed rural hukou holders to apply for first-tier urban hukou based on a points system which takes into account adherence to the local birth-control policy, educational attainment, and employment seniority. These reforms help well-educated elites, but do little for China’s migrant underclass. The burdensome process of applying for urban hukou and the low likelihood of finding affordable housing in a first-tier city has discouraged many migrants from taking advantage of these reforms.
It’s important to acknowledge that the Chinese Communist Party (CCP) is unlikely to eradicate hukou which plays an important role in social control To produce any substantial impacts, future reforms should focus on equalizing treatment toward holders of different types of hukou, rather than providing more opportunities for migrants to apply for higher-tier hukou. | workers’ struggles stem from hukou a system that controls movements of Chinese residents Hukou status cannot change
hukou exacerbates rural-urban divide
drastically hinders access to social services
leaders have rendered reform attempts ineffective
reforms have created new obstacles for migrants
most recent points system help well-educated elites but do little for China’s underclass. The burdensome process has discouraged many migrants
the CCP is unlikely to eradicate hukou | China’s meteoric economic rise has relied on hundreds of millions of rural migrants. These migrants make incredible sacrifices for the economic opportunity of moving to a city, often leaving behind their children and their homes. In fact, these workers’ struggles stem from a seemingly benign migration control policy called “hukou”—a household registration system that controls the movements of Chinese residents and defines people by birthplace as either urban or rural. Hukou status cannot change, so even when rural migrant workers find employment in large cities such as Shanghai, they retain rural hukou status.
"In a country with widespread negative stereotypes about the rural poor, the hukou system only exacerbates the rural-urban divide."
Holding a non-local hukou in an urban area drastically hinders access to basic social services, such as public schooling, subsidized medical care, and unemployment insurance. In a country with widespread negative stereotypes about the rural poor, the hukou system only exacerbates the rural-urban divide. To improve the hukou system, the government must implement reforms that benefit those moving from the countryside and into cities.
Urbanites and government leaders have rendered past hukou reform attempts ineffective. Urban residents have an economic interest in pushing for the status quo and many possess prejudiced attitudes toward migrants. One-third of Shanghai urbanites claimed they would not want a rural neighbor; only one-tenth felt the same way about having a poor one.
Unfortunately, the reforms that have managed to pass have just created new obstacles for rural migrants. For example, a 1996 law gave migrant children the right to attend elementary and middle school in the cities where their parents worked. Schools responded with temporary resident fees and additional verification requirements for the children of rural migrants, deterring migrants from bringing their children to urban areas. And since the law did not extend to high schools, the few children who did benefit had to return to the countryside to finish their education.
In 2013, the government tried to introduce more drastic changes. New policies gave rural residents the ability to gain urban hukou in third-tier cities with smaller populations and fewer economic opportunities than first-tier cities. However, though rural status is associated with inconveniences and discrimination, it also comes with its share of benefits: A rural hukou guarantees its holder a small plot of land in the countryside and allows them to be subject to a more relaxed birth-control policy. Most migrants thought the perks of rural hukou outweighed the meager benefits of third-tier urban hukou, so the 2013 reforms failed to produce any substantial changes.
China’s most recent attempt to liberalize hukou has allowed rural hukou holders to apply for first-tier urban hukou based on a points system which takes into account adherence to the local birth-control policy, educational attainment, and employment seniority. These reforms help well-educated elites, but do little for China’s migrant underclass. The burdensome process of applying for urban hukou and the low likelihood of finding affordable housing in a first-tier city has discouraged many migrants from taking advantage of these reforms.
It’s important to acknowledge that the Chinese Communist Party (CCP) is unlikely to eradicate hukou, which plays an important role in social control. To produce any substantial impacts, future reforms should focus on equalizing treatment toward holders of different types of hukou, rather than providing more opportunities for migrants to apply for higher-tier hukou. | 3,692 | <h4><strong>Reforms fail – only the plan solves </h4><p>Chen 18 <u></strong>[(Ashley, former President of the Brown Political Review and a Senior Staff Writer for the US Section.) “Bridging the Gap: Why China’s Hukou System Needs Reform” Brown Pollical Review, 5/28/2018. https://brownpoliticalreview.org/2018/05/bridging-gap-chinas-hukou-system-needs-reform/] BC</p><p>China’s meteoric economic rise has relied on hundreds of millions of rural migrants</u>. <u>These migrants make incredible sacrifices for the economic opportunity of moving to a city, often leaving behind their children and their homes.</u> In fact<u><strong>, these <mark>workers’ struggles stem from</mark> a seemingly benign migration control policy called “<mark>hukou</mark>”</u></strong>—<u><mark>a</mark> household registration <mark>system that <strong>controls</mark> the <mark>movements of Chinese residents</strong></mark> and <strong>defines people by birthplace as either urban or rural</strong>. <mark>Hukou status cannot change</mark>, so even when rural migrant workers find employment in large cities such as Shanghai, they retain rural hukou status.</p><p></u>"In a country with widespread negative stereotypes about the rural poor, <u><strong>the <mark>hukou</mark> system only <mark>exacerbates</mark> the <mark>rural-urban divide</strong></mark>."</p><p><strong>Holding a non-local hukou in an urban area <mark>drastically hinders access to</mark> basic <mark>social services</mark>, such as public schooling, subsidized medical care, and unemployment insurance.</u></strong> <u>In a country with widespread negative stereotypes about the rural poor, <strong>the hukou system only exacerbates the rural-urban divide.</strong> To improve the hukou system, the government must implement reforms that benefit those moving from the countryside and into cities.</p><p><strong>Urbanites and government <mark>leaders have rendered</mark> past hukou <mark>reform attempts ineffective</strong></mark>. Urban residents have an economic interest in pushing for the status quo and many possess prejudiced attitudes toward migrants. One-third of Shanghai urbanites claimed they would not want a rural neighbor; only one-tenth felt the same way about having a poor one.</p><p></u>Unfortunately, <u><strong>the <mark>reforms</mark> that have managed to pass <mark>have</mark> just <mark>created new obstacles for</mark> rural <mark>migrants</mark>.</u></strong> <u>For example, a 1996 law gave migrant children the right to attend elementary and middle school in the cities where their parents worked<strong>. Schools responded with temporary resident fees and additional verification requirements for the children of rural migrants, deterring migrants from bringing their children to urban areas.</strong> And since the law did not extend to high schools, the few children who did benefit had to return to the countryside to finish their education.</p><p>In 2013, the government tried to introduce more drastic changes</u>. New policies gave rural residents the ability to gain urban hukou in third-tier cities with smaller populations and fewer economic opportunities than first-tier cities. However, though rural status is associated with inconveniences and discrimination, it also comes with its share of benefits: A rural hukou guarantees its holder a small plot of land in th<u>e countryside and allows them to be subject to a more relaxed birth-control policy. Most migrants thought the perks of rural hukou outweighed the meager benefits of third-tier urban hukou, so the 2013 reforms failed to produce any substantial changes.</p><p>China’s <mark>most recent</mark> attempt to liberalize hukou has allowed rural hukou holders to apply for first-tier urban hukou based on a <mark>points system</mark> which takes into account adherence to the local birth-control policy, educational attainment, and employment seniority<strong>. These reforms <mark>help well-educated elites</mark>, <mark>but do little for China’s</mark> migrant <mark>underclass.</u></strong> <u>The burdensome process</mark> of applying for urban hukou and the low likelihood of finding affordable housing in a first-tier city <mark>has discouraged many migrants</mark> from taking advantage of these reforms.</p><p><strong>It’s important to acknowledge that <mark>the</mark> Chinese Communist Party (<mark>CCP</mark>) <mark>is unlikely to eradicate hukou</u></strong></mark>, <u>which plays an important role in social control</u>. <u>To produce any substantial impacts, future reforms should focus on equalizing treatment toward holders of different types of hukou, rather than providing more opportunities for migrants to apply for higher-tier hukou.</p></u> | 1AC—Hukou | 1AC – Substance | FW | 1,700,315 | 152 | 166,083 | ./documents/hsld22/MercerIsland/AnWa/MercerIsland-AnWa-Aff-TOC-Digital-Speech-and-Debate-Series-3-Round-4.docx | 989,234 | A | TOC Digital Speech and Debate Series 3 | 4 | Montville SH | Heirigs | 1ac - hukou
1nc - cap da t
1ar - all
1nr - cap
2ar - same | hsld22/MercerIsland/AnWa/MercerIsland-AnWa-Aff-TOC-Digital-Speech-and-Debate-Series-3-Round-4.docx | 2023-03-13 21:25:11 | 81,608 | AnWa | Mercer Island AnWa | Hey - I'm Anthony (he/him).
Contact info is [email protected] or #4259002688, if you need to contact me for any reason | An..... | Wa..... | null | null | 26,963 | MercerIsland | Mercer Island | WA | null | 2,003 | hsld22 | HS LD 2022-23 | 2,022 | ld | hs | 1 |
3,702,120 | Addressing the anthropocene through policy actions and market solutions is productive—the world is getting better now but only continued investment in institutions prevents their impacts | Brook, et al, 15 | Brook, et al, 15—professor of environmental sustainability at the University of Tasmania (Barry, with John Asafu-Adjaye, University of Queensland, Linus Blomqvist, Breakthrough Institute, Stewart Brand, Long Now Foundation, Ruth DeFries, Columbia Univeristy, Erle Ellis, University of Maryland, Baltimore County, Christopher Foreman, University of Maryland School of Public Policy, David Keith, Harvard University School of Engineering and Applied Sciences, Martin Lewis, Stanford University, Mark Lynas, Cornell University, Ted Nordhaus, Breakthrough Institute, Roger Pielke, Jr., University of Colorado, Boulder, Rachel Pritzker, Pritzker Innovation Fund, Joyashree Roy, Jadavpur University, Mark Sagoff, George Mason University, Michael Shellenberger, Breakthrough Institute, Robert Stone, Filmmaker, and Peter Teague, Breakthrough Institute, “AN ECOMODERNIST MANIFESTO”, http://www.ecomodernism.org/manifesto/, dml) | Intensifying many human activities so that they use less land and interfere less with the natural world is the key to decoupling human development from environmental impacts. These socioeconomic and technological processes are central to economic modernization and environmental protection. Together they allow people to mitigate climate change, to spare nature, and to alleviate global poverty.
1.
Humanity has flourished over the past two centuries. Average life expectancy has increased Humanity has made extraordinary progress in reducing the incidence and impacts of infectious diseases, and it has become more resilient to extreme weather and other natural disasters.
Violence in all forms has declined significantly and is probably at the lowest per capita level ever experienced by the human species human beings have moved from autocratic government toward liberal democracy characterized by the rule of law and increased freedom.
liberties have spread worldwide Historically large numbers of humans both in percentage and in absolute terms — are free from insecurity, penury, and servitude.
human flourishing has taken a serious toll on natural, nonhuman environments and wildlife.
Given that humans are completely dependent on the living biosphere, how is it possible that people are doing so much damage to natural systems without doing more harm to themselves?
technologies have made humans less reliant upon the many ecosystems that once provided their only sustenance, even as those same ecosystems have often been left deeply damaged.
Despite frequent assertions of limits to growth there is little evidence that human population and economic expansion will outstrip the capacity to grow food or procure critical material resources in the foreseeable future
boundaries to consumption are so theoretical as to be functionally irrelevant Human civilization can flourish for millennia on energy delivered from a closed cycle With proper management, humans are at no risk of lacking sufficient agricultural land for food Given plentiful land and unlimited energy, substitutes for other material inputs to human well-being can easily be found
There remain serious long-term environmental threats to human well-being the evidence is clear that they could cause significant risk of catastrophic impacts on societies and ecosystems
2.
a range of long-term trends are driving significant decoupling of human well-being from environmental impacts.
Decoupling can be driven by both technological and demographic trends and usually results from a combination of the two.
growth rate of the population has already peaked population growth is down the size of the human population will peak this century and then start to decline.
cities both drive and symbolize the decoupling of humanity from nature, performing far better than rural economies in providing efficiently for material needs while reducing environmental impacts
modernization is not possible in a subsistence agrarian economy
rising harvest yields have for millennia reduced the amount of land required to feed the average person. The average per-capita use of land today is vastly lower Thanks to technological improvements in agriculture the amount of land required for growing declined by one-half
Agricultural intensification has allowed many parts of the world to experience net reforestation
Human use of many other resources is similarly peaking. The amount of water needed has declined nitrogen has declined significantly
in contradiction to the often-expressed fear of infinite growth colliding with a finite planet, demand for many material goods may be saturating as societies grow wealthier
As demand for material goods is met, developed economies see higher levels of spending directed to materially less-intensive service and knowledge sectors, which account for an increasing share of economic activity. This dynamic might be even more pronounced in today’s developing economies, which may benefit from being late adopters of resource-efficient technologies.
these trends mean that the total human impact on the environment can peak and decline this century. By understanding and promoting these emergent processes, humans have the opportunity to re-wild and re-green the Earth — even as developing countries achieve modern living standards, and material poverty ends.
early populations with much less advanced technologies had far larger individual land footprints than societies have today
The technologies that humankind’s ancestors used to meet their needs supported much lower living standards with much higher per-capita impacts on the environment. Absent a massive human die-off, any large-scale attempt at recoupling human societies to nature using these technologies would result in an unmitigated ecological and human disaster.
Ecosystems around the world are threatened today because people over-rely on them it is the continued dependence of humans on natural environments that is the problem for the conservation of nature.
modern technologies offer a real chance of reducing the totality of human impacts on the biosphere
The modernization processes are double-edged, since they have also degraded the natural environment. Fossil fuels, mechanization and manufacturing, synthetic fertilizers and pesticides, electrification and modern transportation and communication technologies, have made larger human populations and greater consumption possible in the first place. Had technologies not improved since the Dark Ages, no doubt the human population would not have grown much either.
It is also true that large, increasingly affluent urban populations have placed greater demands upon ecosystems But those same technologies have also made it possible for people to secure food, shelter, heat, light, and mobility through means that are vastly more resource- and land-efficient than at any previous time in human history.
Decoupling requires the conscious acceleration of emergent decoupling processes. In some cases, the objective is the development of technological substitutes. Reducing deforestation and indoor air pollution requires the substitution of wood and charcoal with modern energy.
humanity’s goal should be to use resources more productively. For example, increasing agricultural yields can reduce the conversion of forests and grasslands to farms. Humans should seek to liberate the environment from the economy.
Urbanization, agricultural intensification, nuclear power, aquaculture, and desalination are all processes with a demonstrated potential to reduce human demands on the environment
Climate change and other global ecological challenges are not the most important immediate concerns for the majority of the world's people. Nor should they be. A new coal-fired power station in Bangladesh may bring air pollution and rising carbon dioxide emissions but will also save lives. For millions living without light and forced to burn dung to cook their food, electricity and modern fuels, no matter the source, offer a pathway to a better life, even as they also bring new environmental challenges.
climate mitigation is a technological challenge even dramatic limits to per capita global consumption would be insufficient to achieve significant climate mitigation. Absent profound technological change there is no credible path to meaningful climate mitigation we are aware of no quantified climate mitigation scenario in which technological change is not responsible for the vast majority of emissions cuts.
that there have been consistent patterns associated with the ways that societies move toward cleaner sources of energy. Substituting higher-quality fuels for lower-quality ones is how virtually all societies have decarbonized, and points the way toward accelerated decarbonization in the future
solar and nuclear represent the most plausible pathways that transition will take time. During that transition, other energy technologies can provide important social and environmental benefits
The ethical and pragmatic path toward a just and sustainable global energy economy requires that human beings transition as rapidly as possible to energy sources that are cheap, clean, dense, and abundant. Such a path will require sustained public support for the development and deployment of clean energy technologies
We write this document out of deep love and emotional connection to the natural world. By appreciating, exploring, seeking to understand, and cultivating nature, many people get outside themselves. They connect with their deep evolutionary history. Even when people never experience these wild natures directly, they affirm their existence as important for their psychological and spiritual well-being.
Humans will always materially depend on nature to some degree. Even if a fully synthetic world were possible, many of us might still choose to continue to live more coupled with nature than human sustenance and technologies require. What decoupling offers is the possibility that humanity’s material dependence upon nature might be less destructive.
We affirm the need and human capacity for accelerated, active, and conscious decoupling. Technological progress is not inevitable The long arc of human transformation of natural environments through technologies began well before there existed anything resembling a market or a price signal
Too often, modernization is conflated with capitalism, corporate power, and laissez-faire economic policies. We reject such reductions modernization is the long-term evolution of social, economic, political, and technological arrangements in human societies
Modernization has liberated ever more people from lives of poverty Greater resource productivity associated with modern socio-technological systems has allowed human societies to meet human needs with fewer resource inputs and less impact on the environment. More-productive economies are wealthier economies, capable of better meeting human needs while committing more of their economic surplus to non-economic amenities, including better human health, greater human freedom and opportunity, arts, culture, and the conservation of nature.
Modernizing processes are far from complete, even in advanced developed economies. Material consumption has only just begun to peak in the wealthiest societies. Decoupling will require a sustained commitment to technological progress and the continuing evolution of social, economic, and political institutions alongside those changes.
Accelerated technological progress will require the active, assertive, and aggressive participation of private sector entrepreneurs, markets, civil society, and the state we continue to embrace a strong public role in addressing environmental problems and accelerating technological innovation, including research to develop better technologies, subsidies, and other measures to help bring them to market, and regulations to mitigate environmental hazards | Humanity has flourished
Violence is the lowest ever
limits to growth
are theoretical With management, humans are at no risk of lacking ag
environmental threats could cause catastrophic impacts
trends are driving decoupling
population growth is down
modernization is not possible in a subsistence agrarian economy
Ag has allowed reforestation
use of resources is peaking
in contradiction to the fear of infinite growth demand may be saturating
the human impact can decline this century. By promoting these processes, humans have the opportunity to re-green the Earth
climate is a technological challenge even dramatic limits to consumption would be insufficient Absent profound tech change there is no credible path to mitigation
Humans will always depend on nature to some degree
Tech is not inevitable human transformation of environments began before a market
Too often, modernization is conflated with capitalism modernization is the evolution of arrangements
Modernizing processes are far from complete Decoupling will require a sustained commitment to tech progress and
active participation of markets and the state | Intensifying many human activities — particularly farming, energy extraction, forestry, and settlement — so that they use less land and interfere less with the natural world is the key to decoupling human development from environmental impacts. These socioeconomic and technological processes are central to economic modernization and environmental protection. Together they allow people to mitigate climate change, to spare nature, and to alleviate global poverty.
Although we have to date written separately, our views are increasingly discussed as a whole. We call ourselves ecopragmatists and ecomodernists. We offer this statement to affirm and to clarify our views and to describe our vision for putting humankind’s extraordinary powers in the service of creating a good Anthropocene.
1.
Humanity has flourished over the past two centuries. Average life expectancy has increased from 30 to 70 years, resulting in a large and growing population able to live in many different environments. Humanity has made extraordinary progress in reducing the incidence and impacts of infectious diseases, and it has become more resilient to extreme weather and other natural disasters.
Violence in all forms has declined significantly and is probably at the lowest per capita level ever experienced by the human species, the horrors of the 20th century and present-day terrorism notwithstanding. Globally, human beings have moved from autocratic government toward liberal democracy characterized by the rule of law and increased freedom.
Personal, economic, and political liberties have spread worldwide and are today largely accepted as universal values. Modernization liberates women from traditional gender roles, increasing their control of their fertility. Historically large numbers of humans — both in percentage and in absolute terms — are free from insecurity, penury, and servitude.
At the same time, human flourishing has taken a serious toll on natural, nonhuman environments and wildlife. Humans use about half of the planet’s ice-free land, mostly for pasture, crops, and production forestry. Of the land once covered by forests, 20 percent has been converted to human use. Populations of many mammals, amphibians, and birds have declined by more than 50 percent in the past 40 years alone. More than 100 species from those groups went extinct in the 20th century, and about 785 since 1500. As we write, only four northern white rhinos are confirmed to exist.
Given that humans are completely dependent on the living biosphere, how is it possible that people are doing so much damage to natural systems without doing more harm to themselves?
The role that technology plays in reducing humanity’s dependence on nature explains this paradox. Human technologies, from those that first enabled agriculture to replace hunting and gathering, to those that drive today’s globalized economy, have made humans less reliant upon the many ecosystems that once provided their only sustenance, even as those same ecosystems have often been left deeply damaged.
Despite frequent assertions starting in the 1970s of fundamental “limits to growth,” there is still remarkably little evidence that human population and economic expansion will outstrip the capacity to grow food or procure critical material resources in the foreseeable future.
To the degree to which there are fixed physical boundaries to human consumption, they are so theoretical as to be functionally irrelevant. The amount of solar radiation that hits the Earth, for instance, is ultimately finite but represents no meaningful constraint upon human endeavors. Human civilization can flourish for centuries and millennia on energy delivered from a closed uranium or thorium fuel cycle, or from hydrogen-deuterium fusion. With proper management, humans are at no risk of lacking sufficient agricultural land for food. Given plentiful land and unlimited energy, substitutes for other material inputs to human well-being can easily be found if those inputs become scarce or expensive.
There remain, however, serious long-term environmental threats to human well-being, such as anthropogenic climate change, stratospheric ozone depletion, and ocean acidification. While these risks are difficult to quantify, the evidence is clear today that they could cause significant risk of catastrophic impacts on societies and ecosystems. Even gradual, non-catastrophic outcomes associated with these threats are likely to result in significant human and economic costs as well as rising ecological losses.
Much of the world’s population still suffers from more-immediate local environmental health risks. Indoor and outdoor air pollution continue to bring premature death and illness to millions annually. Water pollution and water-borne illness due to pollution and degradation of watersheds cause similar suffering.
2.
Even as human environmental impacts continue to grow in the aggregate, a range of long-term trends are today driving significant decoupling of human well-being from environmental impacts.
Decoupling occurs in both relative and absolute terms. Relative decoupling means that human environmental impacts rise at a slower rate than overall economic growth. Thus, for each unit of economic output, less environmental impact (e.g., deforestation, defaunation, pollution) results. Overall impacts may still increase, just at a slower rate than would otherwise be the case. Absolute decoupling occurs when total environmental impacts — impacts in the aggregate — peak and begin to decline, even as the economy continues to grow.
Decoupling can be driven by both technological and demographic trends and usually results from a combination of the two.
The growth rate of the human population has already peaked. Today’s population growth rate is one percent per year, down from its high point of 2.1 percent in the 1970s. Fertility rates in countries containing more than half of the global population are now below replacement level. Population growth today is primarily driven by longer life spans and lower infant mortality, not by rising fertility rates. Given current trends, it is very possible that the size of the human population will peak this century and then start to decline.
Trends in population are inextricably linked to other demographic and economic dynamics. For the first time in human history, over half the global population lives in cities. By 2050, 70 percent are expected to dwell in cities, a number that could rise to 80 percent or more by the century’s end. Cities are characterized by both dense populations and low fertility rates.
Cities occupy just 1 to 3 percent of the Earth’s surface and yet are home to nearly four billion people. As such, cities both drive and symbolize the decoupling of humanity from nature, performing far better than rural economies in providing efficiently for material needs while reducing environmental impacts.
The growth of cities along with the economic and ecological benefits that come with them are inseparable from improvements in agricultural productivity. As agriculture has become more land and labor efficient, rural populations have left the countryside for the cities. Roughly half the US population worked the land in 1880. Today, less than 2 percent does.
As human lives have been liberated from hard agricultural labor, enormous human resources have been freed up for other endeavors. Cities, as people know them today, could not exist without radical changes in farming. In contrast, modernization is not possible in a subsistence agrarian economy.
These improvements have resulted not only in lower labor requirements per unit of agricultural output but also in lower land requirements. This is not a new trend: rising harvest yields have for millennia reduced the amount of land required to feed the average person. The average per-capita use of land today is vastly lower than it was 5,000 years ago, despite the fact that modern people enjoy a far richer diet. Thanks to technological improvements in agriculture, during the half-century starting in the mid-1960s, the amount of land required for growing crops and animal feed for the average person declined by one-half.
Agricultural intensification, along with the move away from the use of wood as fuel, has allowed many parts of the world to experience net reforestation. About 80 percent of New England is today forested, compared with about 50 percent at the end of the 19th century. Over the past 20 years, the amount of land dedicated to production forest worldwide declined by 50 million hectares, an area the size of France. The “forest transition” from net deforestation to net reforestation seems to be as resilient a feature of development as the demographic transition that reduces human birth rates as poverty declines.
Human use of many other resources is similarly peaking. The amount of water needed for the average diet has declined by nearly 25 percent over the past half-century. Nitrogen pollution continues to cause eutrophication and large dead zones in places like the Gulf of Mexico. While the total amount of nitrogen pollution is rising, the amount used per unit of production has declined significantly in developed nations.
Indeed, in contradiction to the often-expressed fear of infinite growth colliding with a finite planet, demand for many material goods may be saturating as societies grow wealthier. Meat consumption, for instance, has peaked in many wealthy nations and has shifted away from beef toward protein sources that are less land intensive.
As demand for material goods is met, developed economies see higher levels of spending directed to materially less-intensive service and knowledge sectors, which account for an increasing share of economic activity. This dynamic might be even more pronounced in today’s developing economies, which may benefit from being late adopters of resource-efficient technologies.
Taken together, these trends mean that the total human impact on the environment, including land-use change, overexploitation, and pollution, can peak and decline this century. By understanding and promoting these emergent processes, humans have the opportunity to re-wild and re-green the Earth — even as developing countries achieve modern living standards, and material poverty ends.
3.
The processes of decoupling described above challenge the idea that early human societies lived more lightly on the land than do modern societies. Insofar as past societies had less impact upon the environment, it was because those societies supported vastly smaller populations.
In fact, early human populations with much less advanced technologies had far larger individual land footprints than societies have today. Consider that a population of no more than one or two million North Americans hunted most of the continent’s large mammals into extinction in the late Pleistocene, while burning and clearing forests across the continent in the process. Extensive human transformations of the environment continued throughout the Holocene period: as much as three-quarters of all deforestation globally occurred before the Industrial Revolution.
The technologies that humankind’s ancestors used to meet their needs supported much lower living standards with much higher per-capita impacts on the environment. Absent a massive human die-off, any large-scale attempt at recoupling human societies to nature using these technologies would result in an unmitigated ecological and human disaster.
Ecosystems around the world are threatened today because people over-rely on them: people who depend on firewood and charcoal for fuel cut down and degrade forests; people who eat bush meat for food hunt mammal species to local extirpation. Whether it’s a local indigenous community or a foreign corporation that benefits, it is the continued dependence of humans on natural environments that is the problem for the conservation of nature.
Conversely, modern technologies, by using natural ecosystem flows and services more efficiently, offer a real chance of reducing the totality of human impacts on the biosphere. To embrace these technologies is to find paths to a good Anthropocene.
The modernization processes that have increasingly liberated humanity from nature are, of course, double-edged, since they have also degraded the natural environment. Fossil fuels, mechanization and manufacturing, synthetic fertilizers and pesticides, electrification and modern transportation and communication technologies, have made larger human populations and greater consumption possible in the first place. Had technologies not improved since the Dark Ages, no doubt the human population would not have grown much either.
It is also true that large, increasingly affluent urban populations have placed greater demands upon ecosystems in distant places –– the extraction of natural resources has been globalized. But those same technologies have also made it possible for people to secure food, shelter, heat, light, and mobility through means that are vastly more resource- and land-efficient than at any previous time in human history.
Decoupling human well-being from the destruction of nature requires the conscious acceleration of emergent decoupling processes. In some cases, the objective is the development of technological substitutes. Reducing deforestation and indoor air pollution requires the substitution of wood and charcoal with modern energy.
In other cases, humanity’s goal should be to use resources more productively. For example, increasing agricultural yields can reduce the conversion of forests and grasslands to farms. Humans should seek to liberate the environment from the economy.
Urbanization, agricultural intensification, nuclear power, aquaculture, and desalination are all processes with a demonstrated potential to reduce human demands on the environment, allowing more room for non-human species. Suburbanization, low-yield farming, and many forms of renewable energy production, in contrast, generally require more land and resources and leave less room for nature.
These patterns suggest that humans are as likely to spare nature because it is not needed to meet their needs as they are to spare it for explicit aesthetic and spiritual reasons. The parts of the planet that people have not yet profoundly transformed have mostly been spared because they have not yet found an economic use for them — mountains, deserts, boreal forests, and other “marginal” lands.
Decoupling raises the possibility that societies might achieve peak human impact without intruding much further on relatively untouched areas. Nature unused is nature spared.
4.
Plentiful access to modern energy is an essential prerequisite for human development and for decoupling development from nature. The availability of inexpensive energy allows poor people around the world to stop using forests for fuel. It allows humans to grow more food on less land, thanks to energy-heavy inputs such as fertilizer and tractors. Energy allows humans to recycle waste water and desalinate sea water in order to spare rivers and aquifers. It allows humans to cheaply recycle metal and plastic rather than to mine and refine these minerals. Looking forward, modern energy may allow the capture of carbon from the atmosphere to reduce the accumulated carbon that drives global warming.
However, for at least the past three centuries, rising energy production globally has been matched by rising atmospheric concentrations of carbon dioxide. Nations have also been slowly decarbonizing — that is, reducing the carbon intensity of their economies — over that same time period. But they have not been doing so at a rate consistent with keeping cumulative carbon emissions low enough to reliably stay below the international target of less than 2 degrees Centigrade of global warming. Significant climate mitigation, therefore, will require that humans rapidly accelerate existing processes of decarbonization.
There remains much confusion, however, as to how this might be accomplished. In developing countries, rising energy consumption is tightly correlated with rising incomes and improving living standards. Although the use of many other material resource inputs such as nitrogen, timber, and land are beginning to peak, the centrality of energy in human development and its many uses as a substitute for material and human resources suggest that energy consumption will continue to rise through much if not all of the 21st century.
For that reason, any conflict between climate mitigation and the continuing development process through which billions of people around the world are achieving modern living standards will continue to be resolved resoundingly in favor of the latter.
Climate change and other global ecological challenges are not the most important immediate concerns for the majority of the world's people. Nor should they be. A new coal-fired power station in Bangladesh may bring air pollution and rising carbon dioxide emissions but will also save lives. For millions living without light and forced to burn dung to cook their food, electricity and modern fuels, no matter the source, offer a pathway to a better life, even as they also bring new environmental challenges.
Meaningful climate mitigation is fundamentally a technological challenge. By this we mean that even dramatic limits to per capita global consumption would be insufficient to achieve significant climate mitigation. Absent profound technological change there is no credible path to meaningful climate mitigation. While advocates differ in the particular mix of technologies they favor, we are aware of no quantified climate mitigation scenario in which technological change is not responsible for the vast majority of emissions cuts.
The specific technological paths that people might take toward climate mitigation remain deeply contested. Theoretical scenarios for climate mitigation typically reflect their creators’ technological preferences and analytical assumptions while all too often failing to account for the cost, rate, and scale at which low-carbon energy technologies can be deployed.
The history of energy transitions, however, suggests that there have been consistent patterns associated with the ways that societies move toward cleaner sources of energy. Substituting higher-quality (i.e., less carbon-intensive, higher-density) fuels for lower-quality (i.e., more carbon-intensive, lower-density) ones is how virtually all societies have decarbonized, and points the way toward accelerated decarbonization in the future. Transitioning to a world powered by zero-carbon energy sources will require energy technologies that are power dense and capable of scaling to many tens of terawatts to power a growing human economy.
Most forms of renewable energy are, unfortunately, incapable of doing so. The scale of land use and other environmental impacts necessary to power the world on biofuels or many other renewables are such that we doubt they provide a sound pathway to a zero-carbon low-footprint future.
High-efficiency solar cells produced from earth-abundant materials are an exception and have the potential to provide many tens of terawatts on a few percent of the Earth’s surface. Present-day solar technologies will require substantial innovation to meet this standard and the development of cheap energy storage technologies that are capable of dealing with highly variable energy generation at large scales.
Nuclear fission today represents the only present-day zero-carbon technology with the demonstrated ability to meet most, if not all, of the energy demands of a modern economy. However, a variety of social, economic, and institutional challenges make deployment of present-day nuclear technologies at scales necessary to achieve significant climate mitigation unlikely. A new generation of nuclear technologies that are safer and cheaper will likely be necessary for nuclear energy to meet its full potential as a critical climate mitigation technology.
In the long run, next-generation solar, advanced nuclear fission, and nuclear fusion represent the most plausible pathways toward the joint goals of climate stabilization and radical decoupling of humans from nature. If the history of energy transitions is any guide, however, that transition will take time. During that transition, other energy technologies can provide important social and environmental benefits. Hydroelectric dams, for example, may be a cheap source of low-carbon power for poor nations even though their land and water footprint is relatively large. Fossil fuels with carbon capture and storage can likewise provide substantial environmental benefits over current fossil or biomass energies.
The ethical and pragmatic path toward a just and sustainable global energy economy requires that human beings transition as rapidly as possible to energy sources that are cheap, clean, dense, and abundant. Such a path will require sustained public support for the development and deployment of clean energy technologies, both within nations and between them, though international collaboration and competition, and within a broader framework for global modernization and development.
5.
We write this document out of deep love and emotional connection to the natural world. By appreciating, exploring, seeking to understand, and cultivating nature, many people get outside themselves. They connect with their deep evolutionary history. Even when people never experience these wild natures directly, they affirm their existence as important for their psychological and spiritual well-being.
Humans will always materially depend on nature to some degree. Even if a fully synthetic world were possible, many of us might still choose to continue to live more coupled with nature than human sustenance and technologies require. What decoupling offers is the possibility that humanity’s material dependence upon nature might be less destructive.
The case for a more active, conscious, and accelerated decoupling to spare nature draws more on spiritual or aesthetic than on material or utilitarian arguments. Current and future generations could survive and prosper materially on a planet with much less biodiversity and wild nature. But this is not a world we want nor, if humans embrace decoupling processes, need to accept.
What we are here calling nature, or even wild nature, encompasses landscapes, seascapes, biomes and ecosystems that have, in more cases than not, been regularly altered by human influences over centuries and millennia. Conservation science, and the concepts of biodiversity, complexity, and indigeneity are useful, but alone cannot determine which landscapes to preserve, or how.
In most cases, there is no single baseline prior to human modification to which nature might be returned. For example, efforts to restore landscapes to more closely resemble earlier states (“indigeneity”) may involve removing recently arrived species (“invasives”) and thus require a net reduction in local biodiversity. In other circumstances, communities may decide to sacrifice indigeneity for novelty and biodiversity.
Explicit efforts to preserve landscapes for their non-utilitarian value are inevitably anthropogenic choices. For this reason, all conservation efforts are fundamentally anthropogenic. The setting aside of wild nature is no less a human choice, in service of human preferences, than bulldozing it. Humans will save wild places and landscapes by convincing our fellow citizens that these places, and the creatures that occupy them, are worth protecting. People may choose to have some services — like water purification and flood protection — provided for by natural systems, such as forested watersheds, reefs, marshes, and wetlands, even if those natural systems are more expensive than simply building water treatment plants, seawalls, and levees. There will be no one-size-fits-all solution.
Environments will be shaped by different local, historical, and cultural preferences. While we believe that agricultural intensification for land-sparing is key to protecting wild nature, we recognize that many communities will continue to opt for land-sharing, seeking to conserve wildlife within agricultural landscapes, for example, rather than allowing it to revert to wild nature in the form of grasslands, scrub, and forests. Where decoupling reduces pressure on landscapes and ecosystems to meet basic human needs, landowners, communities, and governments still must decide to what aesthetic or economic purpose they wish to dedicate those lands.
Accelerated decoupling alone will not be enough to ensure more wild nature. There must still be a conservation politics and a wilderness movement to demand more wild nature for aesthetic and spiritual reasons. Along with decoupling humankind’s material needs from nature, establishing an enduring commitment to preserve wilderness, biodiversity, and a mosaic of beautiful landscapes will require a deeper emotional connection to them.
6.
We affirm the need and human capacity for accelerated, active, and conscious decoupling. Technological progress is not inevitable. Decoupling environmental impacts from economic outputs is not simply a function of market-driven innovation and efficient response to scarcity. The long arc of human transformation of natural environments through technologies began well before there existed anything resembling a market or a price signal. Thanks to rising demand, scarcity, inspiration, and serendipity, humans have remade the world for millennia.
Technological solutions to environmental problems must also be considered within a broader social, economic, and political context. We think it is counterproductive for nations like Germany and Japan, and states like California, to shutter nuclear power plants, recarbonize their energy sectors, and recouple their economies to fossil fuels and biomass. However, such examples underscore clearly that technological choices will not be determined by remote international bodies but rather by national and local institutions and cultures.
Too often, modernization is conflated, both by its defenders and critics, with capitalism, corporate power, and laissez-faire economic policies. We reject such reductions. What we refer to when we speak of modernization is the long-term evolution of social, economic, political, and technological arrangements in human societies toward vastly improved material well-being, public health, resource productivity, economic integration, shared infrastructure, and personal freedom.
Modernization has liberated ever more people from lives of poverty and hard agricultural labor, women from chattel status, children and ethnic minorities from oppression, and societies from capricious and arbitrary governance. Greater resource productivity associated with modern socio-technological systems has allowed human societies to meet human needs with fewer resource inputs and less impact on the environment. More-productive economies are wealthier economies, capable of better meeting human needs while committing more of their economic surplus to non-economic amenities, including better human health, greater human freedom and opportunity, arts, culture, and the conservation of nature.
Modernizing processes are far from complete, even in advanced developed economies. Material consumption has only just begun to peak in the wealthiest societies. Decoupling of human welfare from environmental impacts will require a sustained commitment to technological progress and the continuing evolution of social, economic, and political institutions alongside those changes.
Accelerated technological progress will require the active, assertive, and aggressive participation of private sector entrepreneurs, markets, civil society, and the state. While we reject the planning fallacy of the 1950s, we continue to embrace a strong public role in addressing environmental problems and accelerating technological innovation, including research to develop better technologies, subsidies, and other measures to help bring them to market, and regulations to mitigate environmental hazards. And international collaboration on technological innovation and technology transfer is essential in the areas of agriculture and energy. | 28,410 | <h4><strong>Addressing the anthropocene through policy actions and market solutions is productive—the world is getting better now but only continued investment in institutions prevents</strong> their impacts</h4><p><strong>Brook, et al, 15</strong>—professor of environmental sustainability at the University of Tasmania (Barry, with John Asafu-Adjaye, University of Queensland, Linus Blomqvist, Breakthrough Institute, Stewart Brand, Long Now Foundation, Ruth DeFries, Columbia Univeristy, Erle Ellis, University of Maryland, Baltimore County, Christopher Foreman, University of Maryland School of Public Policy, David Keith, Harvard University School of Engineering and Applied Sciences, Martin Lewis, Stanford University, Mark Lynas, Cornell University, Ted Nordhaus, Breakthrough Institute, Roger Pielke, Jr., University of Colorado, Boulder, Rachel Pritzker, Pritzker Innovation Fund, Joyashree Roy, Jadavpur University, Mark Sagoff, George Mason University, Michael Shellenberger, Breakthrough Institute, Robert Stone, Filmmaker, and Peter Teague, Breakthrough Institute, “AN ECOMODERNIST MANIFESTO”, http://www.ecomodernism.org/manifesto/, dml<u>)</p><p><strong>Intensifying many human activities</u></strong> — particularly farming, energy extraction, forestry, and settlement — <u><strong>so that they use less land and interfere less with the natural world is the key to decoupling human development from environmental impacts</strong>. These socioeconomic and technological processes are central to economic modernization and environmental protection. Together they allow people to mitigate climate change, to spare nature, and to alleviate global poverty.</p><p></u>Although we have to date written separately, our views are increasingly discussed as a whole. We call ourselves ecopragmatists and ecomodernists. We offer this statement to affirm and to clarify our views and to describe our vision for putting humankind’s extraordinary powers in the service of creating a good Anthropocene.</p><p><u>1.</p><p><strong><mark>Humanity has flourished</mark> over the past two centuries</strong>. <strong>Average life expectancy has increased</u></strong> from 30 to 70 years, resulting in a large and growing population able to live in many different environments. <u>Humanity has made extraordinary progress in reducing the incidence and impacts of infectious diseases, and it has become more resilient to extreme weather and other natural disasters.</p><p><strong><mark>Violence</mark> in all forms has declined significantly and <mark>is</mark> probably at <mark>the lowest</mark> per capita level <mark>ever</mark> experienced by the human species</u></strong>, the horrors of the 20th century and present-day terrorism notwithstanding. Globally, <u>human beings have moved from autocratic government toward liberal democracy characterized by the rule of law and increased freedom.</p><p></u>Personal, economic, and political <u>liberties have spread worldwide</u> and are today largely accepted as universal values. Modernization liberates women from traditional gender roles, increasing their control of their fertility. <u>Historically large numbers of humans</u> — <u>both in percentage and in absolute terms — are free from insecurity, penury, and servitude.</p><p></u>At the same time, <u>human flourishing has taken a serious toll on natural, nonhuman environments and wildlife.</u> Humans use about half of the planet’s ice-free land, mostly for pasture, crops, and production forestry. Of the land once covered by forests, 20 percent has been converted to human use. Populations of many mammals, amphibians, and birds have declined by more than 50 percent in the past 40 years alone. More than 100 species from those groups went extinct in the 20th century, and about 785 since 1500. As we write, only four northern white rhinos are confirmed to exist.</p><p><u>Given that humans are completely dependent on the living biosphere, how is it possible that people are doing so much damage to natural systems without doing more harm to themselves? </p><p></u>The role that technology plays in reducing humanity’s dependence on nature explains this paradox. Human <u>technologies</u>, from those that first enabled agriculture to replace hunting and gathering, to those that drive today’s globalized economy, <u>have made humans less reliant upon the many ecosystems that once provided their only sustenance, even as those same ecosystems have often been left deeply damaged.</p><p>Despite frequent assertions</u> starting in the 1970s <u>of</u> fundamental “<u><mark>limits to growth</u></mark>,” <u><strong>there is</u></strong> still remarkably <u><strong>little evidence that human population and economic expansion will outstrip the capacity </strong>to grow food or procure critical material resources in the foreseeable future</u>.</p><p>To the degree to which there are fixed physical <u>boundaries to</u> human <u>consumption</u>, they <u><strong><mark>are</mark> so <mark>theoretical</mark> as to be functionally irrelevant</u></strong>. The amount of solar radiation that hits the Earth, for instance, is ultimately finite but represents no meaningful constraint upon human endeavors. <u>Human civilization can flourish for</u> centuries and <u>millennia on energy delivered from a closed</u> uranium or thorium fuel <u>cycle</u>, or from hydrogen-deuterium fusion. <u><strong><mark>With</mark> proper <mark>management, humans are at no risk of lacking</mark> sufficient <mark>ag</mark>ricultural land for food</u></strong>. <u>Given plentiful land and unlimited energy, substitutes for other material inputs to human well-being can easily be found</u> if those inputs become scarce or expensive.</p><p><u>There remain</u>, however, <u><strong>serious long-term <mark>environmental threats</mark> to human well-being</u></strong>, such as anthropogenic climate change, stratospheric ozone depletion, and ocean acidification. While these risks are difficult to quantify, <u>the evidence is clear</u> today <u><strong>that they <mark>could cause</mark> significant risk of <mark>catastrophic impacts</mark> on societies and ecosystems</u></strong>. Even gradual, non-catastrophic outcomes associated with these threats are likely to result in significant human and economic costs as well as rising ecological losses. </p><p>Much of the world’s population still suffers from more-immediate local environmental health risks. Indoor and outdoor air pollution continue to bring premature death and illness to millions annually. Water pollution and water-borne illness due to pollution and degradation of watersheds cause similar suffering. </p><p><u>2. </p><p></u>Even as human environmental impacts continue to grow in the aggregate, <u>a range of long-term <mark>trends are</u></mark> today <u><strong><mark>driving</mark> significant <mark>decoupling</mark> of human well-being from environmental impacts</strong>.</p><p></u>Decoupling occurs in both relative and absolute terms. Relative decoupling means that human environmental impacts rise at a slower rate than overall economic growth. Thus, for each unit of economic output, less environmental impact (e.g., deforestation, defaunation, pollution) results. Overall impacts may still increase, just at a slower rate than would otherwise be the case. Absolute decoupling occurs when total environmental impacts — impacts in the aggregate — peak and begin to decline, even as the economy continues to grow.</p><p><u>Decoupling can be driven by both technological and demographic trends and usually results from a combination of the two.</p><p></u>The <u>growth rate of the</u> human <u>population <strong>has already peaked</u></strong>. Today’s <u><mark>population growth</u></mark> rate <u><mark>is</u></mark> one percent per year, <u><mark>down</u></mark> from its high point of 2.1 percent in the 1970s. Fertility rates in countries containing more than half of the global population are now below replacement level. Population growth today is primarily driven by longer life spans and lower infant mortality, not by rising fertility rates. Given current trends, it is very possible that <u>the size of the human population will peak this century and then start to decline. </p><p></u>Trends in population are inextricably linked to other demographic and economic dynamics. For the first time in human history, over half the global population lives in cities. By 2050, 70 percent are expected to dwell in cities, a number that could rise to 80 percent or more by the century’s end. Cities are characterized by both dense populations and low fertility rates.</p><p>Cities occupy just 1 to 3 percent of the Earth’s surface and yet are home to nearly four billion people. As such, <u>cities both drive and symbolize the decoupling of humanity from nature, performing far better than rural economies in providing efficiently for material needs while reducing environmental impacts</u>. </p><p>The growth of cities along with the economic and ecological benefits that come with them are inseparable from improvements in agricultural productivity. As agriculture has become more land and labor efficient, rural populations have left the countryside for the cities. Roughly half the US population worked the land in 1880. Today, less than 2 percent does. </p><p>As human lives have been liberated from hard agricultural labor, enormous human resources have been freed up for other endeavors. Cities, as people know them today, could not exist without radical changes in farming. In contrast, <u><strong><mark>modernization is not possible in a subsistence agrarian economy</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>These improvements have resulted not only in lower labor requirements per unit of agricultural output but also in lower land requirements. This is not a new trend: <u>rising harvest yields have for millennia reduced the amount of land required to feed the average person. The average per-capita use of land today <strong>is vastly lower</u></strong> than it was 5,000 years ago, despite the fact that modern people enjoy a far richer diet. <u>Thanks to technological improvements in agriculture</u>, during the half-century starting in the mid-1960s, <u>the amount of land required for growing</u> crops and animal feed for the average person <u>declined by one-half</u>.</p><p><u><mark>Ag</mark>ricultural intensification</u>, along with the move away from the use of wood as fuel, <u><strong><mark>has allowed</mark> many parts of the world to experience net <mark>reforestation</u></strong></mark>. About 80 percent of New England is today forested, compared with about 50 percent at the end of the 19th century. Over the past 20 years, the amount of land dedicated to production forest worldwide declined by 50 million hectares, an area the size of France. The “forest transition” from net deforestation to net reforestation seems to be as resilient a feature of development as the demographic transition that reduces human birth rates as poverty declines.</p><p><u>Human <mark>use of</mark> many other <mark>resources is</mark> similarly <mark>peaking</mark>. The amount of water needed</u> for the average diet <u>has declined</u> by nearly 25 percent over the past half-century. Nitrogen pollution continues to cause eutrophication and large dead zones in places like the Gulf of Mexico. While the total amount of <u>nitrogen</u> pollution is rising, the amount used per unit of production <u>has declined significantly</u> in developed nations.</p><p>Indeed, <u><strong><mark>in contradiction to the</mark> often-expressed <mark>fear of infinite growth</mark> colliding with a finite planet</strong>, <strong><mark>demand </mark>for many material goods <mark>may be saturating</mark> as societies grow wealthier</u></strong>. Meat consumption, for instance, has peaked in many wealthy nations and has shifted away from beef toward protein sources that are less land intensive. </p><p><u>As demand for material goods is met, developed economies see higher levels of spending directed to materially less-intensive service and knowledge sectors, which account for an increasing share of economic activity. This dynamic might be even more pronounced in today’s developing economies, which may benefit from being late adopters of resource-efficient technologies.</p><p></u>Taken together, <u>these trends mean that <mark>the</mark> total <mark>human impact</mark> on the environment</u>, including land-use change, overexploitation, and pollution, <u><strong><mark>can</mark> peak and <mark>decline this century</strong>. <strong>By</mark> understanding and <mark>promoting these</mark> emergent <mark>processes, humans have the opportunity to</mark> re-wild and <mark>re-green the Earth</strong></mark> — even as developing countries achieve modern living standards, and material poverty ends.</p><p></u>3.</p><p>The processes of decoupling described above challenge the idea that early human societies lived more lightly on the land than do modern societies. Insofar as past societies had less impact upon the environment, it was because those societies supported vastly smaller populations. </p><p>In fact, <u>early</u> human <u>populations with much less advanced technologies had far larger individual land footprints than societies have today</u>. Consider that a population of no more than one or two million North Americans hunted most of the continent’s large mammals into extinction in the late Pleistocene, while burning and clearing forests across the continent in the process. Extensive human transformations of the environment continued throughout the Holocene period: as much as three-quarters of all deforestation globally occurred before the Industrial Revolution. </p><p><u>The technologies that humankind’s ancestors used to meet their needs supported much lower living standards with much higher per-capita impacts on the environment. Absent a massive human die-off, any large-scale attempt at recoupling human societies to nature using these technologies would result in an unmitigated ecological and human disaster.</p><p>Ecosystems around the world are threatened today because people over-rely on them</u>: people who depend on firewood and charcoal for fuel cut down and degrade forests; people who eat bush meat for food hunt mammal species to local extirpation. Whether it’s a local indigenous community or a foreign corporation that benefits, <u>it is the continued dependence of humans on natural environments that is the problem for the conservation of nature.</p><p></u>Conversely, <u>modern technologies</u>, by using natural ecosystem flows and services more efficiently, <u><strong>offer a real chance of reducing the totality of human impacts on the biosphere</u></strong>. To embrace these technologies is to find paths to a good Anthropocene.</p><p><u>The modernization processes</u> that have increasingly liberated humanity from nature <u>are</u>, of course, <u>double-edged, since they have also degraded the natural environment. Fossil fuels, mechanization and manufacturing, synthetic fertilizers and pesticides, electrification and modern transportation and communication technologies, have made larger human populations and greater consumption possible in the first place. Had technologies not improved since the Dark Ages, no doubt the human population would not have grown much either.</p><p>It is also true that large, increasingly affluent urban populations have placed greater demands upon ecosystems</u> in distant places –– the extraction of natural resources has been globalized. <u>But those same technologies have also made it possible for people to secure food, shelter, heat, light, and mobility through means that are vastly more resource- and land-efficient than at any previous time in human history.</p><p>Decoupling</u> human well-being from the destruction of nature <u><strong>requires the conscious acceleration of emergent decoupling processes</strong>. In some cases, the objective is the development of technological substitutes. Reducing deforestation and indoor air pollution requires the substitution of wood and charcoal with modern energy.</p><p></u>In other cases, <u>humanity’s goal should be to use resources more productively. For example, increasing agricultural yields can reduce the conversion of forests and grasslands to farms. Humans should seek to liberate the environment from the economy.</p><p>Urbanization, agricultural intensification, nuclear power, aquaculture, and desalination are all processes with a demonstrated potential to reduce human demands on the environment</u>, allowing more room for non-human species. Suburbanization, low-yield farming, and many forms of renewable energy production, in contrast, generally require more land and resources and leave less room for nature.</p><p>These patterns suggest that humans are as likely to spare nature because it is not needed to meet their needs as they are to spare it for explicit aesthetic and spiritual reasons. The parts of the planet that people have not yet profoundly transformed have mostly been spared because they have not yet found an economic use for them — mountains, deserts, boreal forests, and other “marginal” lands.</p><p>Decoupling raises the possibility that societies might achieve peak human impact without intruding much further on relatively untouched areas. Nature unused is nature spared.</p><p>4.</p><p>Plentiful access to modern energy is an essential prerequisite for human development and for decoupling development from nature. The availability of inexpensive energy allows poor people around the world to stop using forests for fuel. It allows humans to grow more food on less land, thanks to energy-heavy inputs such as fertilizer and tractors. Energy allows humans to recycle waste water and desalinate sea water in order to spare rivers and aquifers. It allows humans to cheaply recycle metal and plastic rather than to mine and refine these minerals. Looking forward, modern energy may allow the capture of carbon from the atmosphere to reduce the accumulated carbon that drives global warming.</p><p>However, for at least the past three centuries, rising energy production globally has been matched by rising atmospheric concentrations of carbon dioxide. Nations have also been slowly decarbonizing — that is, reducing the carbon intensity of their economies — over that same time period. But they have not been doing so at a rate consistent with keeping cumulative carbon emissions low enough to reliably stay below the international target of less than 2 degrees Centigrade of global warming. Significant climate mitigation, therefore, will require that humans rapidly accelerate existing processes of decarbonization.</p><p>There remains much confusion, however, as to how this might be accomplished. In developing countries, rising energy consumption is tightly correlated with rising incomes and improving living standards. Although the use of many other material resource inputs such as nitrogen, timber, and land are beginning to peak, the centrality of energy in human development and its many uses as a substitute for material and human resources suggest that energy consumption will continue to rise through much if not all of the 21st century.</p><p>For that reason, any conflict between climate mitigation and the continuing development process through which billions of people around the world are achieving modern living standards will continue to be resolved resoundingly in favor of the latter.</p><p><u>Climate change and other global ecological challenges are not the most important immediate concerns for the majority of the world's people. Nor should they be. A new coal-fired power station in Bangladesh may bring air pollution and rising carbon dioxide emissions but will also save lives. For millions living without light and forced to burn dung to cook their food, electricity and modern fuels, no matter the source, offer a pathway to a better life, even as they also bring new environmental challenges.</p><p></u>Meaningful <u><mark>climate</mark> mitigation <mark>is</u></mark> fundamentally <u><strong><mark>a technological challenge</u></strong></mark>. By this we mean that <u><strong><mark>even dramatic limits to</mark> per capita global <mark>consumption would be insufficient</mark> to achieve significant climate mitigation</strong>. <strong><mark>Absent profound tech</mark>nological <mark>change there is no credible path to</mark> meaningful climate <mark>mitigation</u></strong></mark>. While advocates differ in the particular mix of technologies they favor, <u>we are aware of no quantified climate mitigation scenario in which technological change is not responsible for the vast majority of emissions cuts.</p><p></u>The specific technological paths that people might take toward climate mitigation remain deeply contested. Theoretical scenarios for climate mitigation typically reflect their creators’ technological preferences and analytical assumptions while all too often failing to account for the cost, rate, and scale at which low-carbon energy technologies can be deployed.</p><p>The history of energy transitions, however, suggests <u>that there have been consistent patterns associated with the ways that societies move toward cleaner sources of energy. Substituting higher-quality</u> (i.e., less carbon-intensive, higher-density) <u>fuels for lower-quality</u> (i.e., more carbon-intensive, lower-density) <u>ones is how virtually all societies have decarbonized, and points the way toward accelerated decarbonization in the future</u>. Transitioning to a world powered by zero-carbon energy sources will require energy technologies that are power dense and capable of scaling to many tens of terawatts to power a growing human economy.</p><p>Most forms of renewable energy are, unfortunately, incapable of doing so. The scale of land use and other environmental impacts necessary to power the world on biofuels or many other renewables are such that we doubt they provide a sound pathway to a zero-carbon low-footprint future.</p><p>High-efficiency solar cells produced from earth-abundant materials are an exception and have the potential to provide many tens of terawatts on a few percent of the Earth’s surface. Present-day solar technologies will require substantial innovation to meet this standard and the development of cheap energy storage technologies that are capable of dealing with highly variable energy generation at large scales.</p><p>Nuclear fission today represents the only present-day zero-carbon technology with the demonstrated ability to meet most, if not all, of the energy demands of a modern economy. However, a variety of social, economic, and institutional challenges make deployment of present-day nuclear technologies at scales necessary to achieve significant climate mitigation unlikely. A new generation of nuclear technologies that are safer and cheaper will likely be necessary for nuclear energy to meet its full potential as a critical climate mitigation technology.</p><p>In the long run, next-generation <u>solar</u>, advanced nuclear fission, <u>and nuclear</u> fusion <u>represent the most plausible pathways</u> toward the joint goals of climate stabilization and radical decoupling of humans from nature. If the history of energy transitions is any guide, however, <u>that transition will take time. During that transition, other energy technologies can provide important social and environmental benefits</u>. Hydroelectric dams, for example, may be a cheap source of low-carbon power for poor nations even though their land and water footprint is relatively large. Fossil fuels with carbon capture and storage can likewise provide substantial environmental benefits over current fossil or biomass energies. </p><p><u>The ethical and pragmatic path toward a just and sustainable global energy economy requires that human beings transition as rapidly as possible to energy sources that are cheap, clean, dense, and abundant. Such a path will require sustained public support for the development and deployment of clean energy technologies</u>, both within nations and between them, though international collaboration and competition, and within a broader framework for global modernization and development.</p><p>5.</p><p><u>We write this document out of deep love and emotional connection to the natural world. By appreciating, exploring, seeking to understand, and cultivating nature, many people get outside themselves. They connect with their deep evolutionary history. Even when people never experience these wild natures directly, they affirm their existence as important for their psychological and spiritual well-being.</p><p><strong><mark>Humans will always</mark> materially <mark>depend on nature to some degree</strong></mark>. Even if a fully synthetic world were possible, many of us might still choose to continue to live more coupled with nature than human sustenance and technologies require. What decoupling offers is the possibility that humanity’s material dependence upon nature might be less destructive. </p><p></u>The case for a more active, conscious, and accelerated decoupling to spare nature draws more on spiritual or aesthetic than on material or utilitarian arguments. Current and future generations could survive and prosper materially on a planet with much less biodiversity and wild nature. But this is not a world we want nor, if humans embrace decoupling processes, need to accept.</p><p>What we are here calling nature, or even wild nature, encompasses landscapes, seascapes, biomes and ecosystems that have, in more cases than not, been regularly altered by human influences over centuries and millennia. Conservation science, and the concepts of biodiversity, complexity, and indigeneity are useful, but alone cannot determine which landscapes to preserve, or how.</p><p>In most cases, there is no single baseline prior to human modification to which nature might be returned. For example, efforts to restore landscapes to more closely resemble earlier states (“indigeneity”) may involve removing recently arrived species (“invasives”) and thus require a net reduction in local biodiversity. In other circumstances, communities may decide to sacrifice indigeneity for novelty and biodiversity. </p><p>Explicit efforts to preserve landscapes for their non-utilitarian value are inevitably anthropogenic choices. For this reason, all conservation efforts are fundamentally anthropogenic. The setting aside of wild nature is no less a human choice, in service of human preferences, than bulldozing it. Humans will save wild places and landscapes by convincing our fellow citizens that these places, and the creatures that occupy them, are worth protecting. People may choose to have some services — like water purification and flood protection — provided for by natural systems, such as forested watersheds, reefs, marshes, and wetlands, even if those natural systems are more expensive than simply building water treatment plants, seawalls, and levees. There will be no one-size-fits-all solution.</p><p>Environments will be shaped by different local, historical, and cultural preferences. While we believe that agricultural intensification for land-sparing is key to protecting wild nature, we recognize that many communities will continue to opt for land-sharing, seeking to conserve wildlife within agricultural landscapes, for example, rather than allowing it to revert to wild nature in the form of grasslands, scrub, and forests. Where decoupling reduces pressure on landscapes and ecosystems to meet basic human needs, landowners, communities, and governments still must decide to what aesthetic or economic purpose they wish to dedicate those lands.</p><p>Accelerated decoupling alone will not be enough to ensure more wild nature. There must still be a conservation politics and a wilderness movement to demand more wild nature for aesthetic and spiritual reasons. Along with decoupling humankind’s material needs from nature, establishing an enduring commitment to preserve wilderness, biodiversity, and a mosaic of beautiful landscapes will require a deeper emotional connection to them. </p><p>6.</p><p><u>We affirm the need and human capacity for accelerated, active, and conscious decoupling. <strong><mark>Tech</mark>nological progress <mark>is not inevitable</u></strong></mark>. Decoupling environmental impacts from economic outputs is not simply a function of market-driven innovation and efficient response to scarcity. <u>The long arc of <mark>human transformation of</mark> natural <mark>environments</mark> through technologies <strong><mark>began</mark> well <mark>before</mark> there existed anything resembling <mark>a market</mark> or a price signal</u></strong>. Thanks to rising demand, scarcity, inspiration, and serendipity, humans have remade the world for millennia.</p><p>Technological solutions to environmental problems must also be considered within a broader social, economic, and political context. We think it is counterproductive for nations like Germany and Japan, and states like California, to shutter nuclear power plants, recarbonize their energy sectors, and recouple their economies to fossil fuels and biomass. However, such examples underscore clearly that technological choices will not be determined by remote international bodies but rather by national and local institutions and cultures.</p><p><u><strong><mark>Too often, modernization is conflated</u></strong></mark>, both by its defenders and critics, <u><strong><mark>with capitalism</strong></mark>, corporate power, and laissez-faire economic policies. We reject such reductions</u>. What we refer to when we speak of <u><mark>modernization is the</mark> long-term <mark>evolution of</u></mark> <u>social, economic, political, and technological <mark>arrangements</mark> in human societies</u> toward vastly improved material well-being, public health, resource productivity, economic integration, shared infrastructure, and personal freedom.</p><p><u>Modernization has liberated ever more people from lives of poverty </u>and hard agricultural labor, women from chattel status, children and ethnic minorities from oppression, and societies from capricious and arbitrary governance. <u>Greater resource productivity associated with modern socio-technological systems has allowed human societies to meet human needs with fewer resource inputs and less impact on the environment. More-productive economies are wealthier economies<strong>, capable of better meeting human needs while committing more of their economic surplus to non-economic amenities, including better human health, greater human freedom and opportunity, arts, culture, and the conservation of nature.</p><p><mark>Modernizing processes are far from complete</strong></mark>, even in advanced developed economies. Material consumption has only just begun to peak in the wealthiest societies. <mark>Decoupling</u></mark> of human welfare from environmental impacts <u><strong><mark>will require a sustained commitment to tech</mark>nological <mark>progress and</mark> the continuing evolution of social, economic, and political institutions alongside those changes. </p><p>Accelerated technological progress will require the <mark>active</mark>, assertive, and aggressive <mark>participation of</mark> private sector entrepreneurs, <mark>markets</mark>, civil society, <mark>and the state</u></strong></mark>. While we reject the planning fallacy of the 1950s, <u><strong>we continue to embrace a strong public role</strong> <strong>in addressing environmental problems</strong> and accelerating technological innovation, including research to develop better technologies, subsidies, and other measures to help bring them to market, and regulations to mitigate environmental hazards</u>. And international collaboration on technological innovation and technology transfer is essential in the areas of agriculture and energy.</p> | Round 1—Neg vs Indiana HF | 1NC | Case | 14,533 | 506 | 123,857 | ./documents/ndtceda16/Michigan/MeDo/Michigan-MeyersLevy-Donovan-Neg-Gonzaga-Round1.docx | 590,937 | N | Gonzaga | 1 | Indiana HF | Justice | 1AC was baudrillard
it was all baudrillard fw | ndtceda16/Michigan/MeDo/Michigan-MeyersLevy-Donovan-Neg-Gonzaga-Round1.docx | null | 50,410 | MeDo | Michigan MeDo | null | Du..... | Me..... | To..... | Do..... | 19,047 | Michigan | Michigan | null | null | 1,006 | ndtceda16 | NDT/CEDA 2016-17 | 2,016 | cx | college | 2 |
3,241,047 | Growth is unsustainable AND innovation can’t solve---shifting away from productivism is key to avoid extinction. | Büchs & Koch 17 | Milena Büchs & Max Koch 17. Milena Büchs is Associate Professor in Sustainability, Economics and Low Carbon Transitions at the University of Leeds, UK. Max Koch is Professor of Social Policy at Lund University (School of Social Work), Sweden. 2017. Postgrowth and Wellbeing. Springer International Publishing. CrossRef, doi:10.1007/978-3-319-59903-8. | economic growth is regarded as a prime policy aim because it is thought to be essential for reducing poverty rising living standards and stable employment support for growth is intertwined with advocating social progress and with an optimistic view of humans’ ingenuity to solve problems Since GDP measures monetary value it excludes environmental costs as long as there is no cost associated with emitting greenhouse gases the cost for the environmental and social damage following from this is not reflected in GDP figures. GDP increases as a consequence of some types of environmental damage if deforestation and timber trade increase or if natural disasters or industrial accidents require expenditures for clean-up and reconstruction, GDP figures will rise economic growth cannot, be the main goal of economic activity because it requires increasing resource inputs, some of which are non-renewable, and generates wastes, including greenhouse gases, that disturb various ecosystems, severely threatening human and planetary functioning in the short and long term. Historically speaking, economic growth is a fairly recent phenomenon it has gone hand in hand with an exponentially increasing use of non-renewable resources such as fossil fuels While we are not yet close to running out of non-renewable resources, over time they will become more difficult and hence more expensive to recover This idea is captured by the concept of “energy returned on energy invested” EROEI In relation to oil it has been shown that the easily recoverable fields have been targeted first and that therefore greater energy and financial inputs will be required to produce more oil. the ratio of energy returned on energy invested will decrease reducing the financial incentive to invest further in the recovery of these non-renewable resources Relevant to this is also the debate about peak oil the point at which the rate of global conventional oil production reaches its maximum which is expected to take place roughly once half of global oil reserves have been produced oil prices will rise in the long term if conventional oil availability diminishes, while global demand for oil increases with continuing economic and population growth. Since economic growth in the second half of the twentieth century required increasing inputs higher prices would have a negative impact on growth the impacts of climate change are immanent and may accelerate within the very near future remaining resources could be exploited However, this would be devastating as greenhouse gas emissions need to turn net-zero by the second half of this century for there to be a good chance to limit global warming to 2° Celsius (and ideally, below that) limits of sinks to absorb gases and regenerat vital ecosystems are now attracting greater concern growth threatens soil freshwater and forests as well as the functioning of vital ecosystems and ecosystems services such as the purification of air and water, water absorption and storage and the related mitigation of droughts and floods decomposition and detoxification and absorption of wastes, pollination and pest control Recent research on planetary boundaries has started to identify thresholds of environmental pollution or disturbance of a range of ecosystems services beyond which the functioning of human life on earth will be put at risk One controversial question in the debate about economic growth and environmental impacts has been whether growth can be decoupled from the damage it causes Important to this is the theory of the Environmental Kuznets Curve this theory does not take into account the difference between relative and absolute decoupling Relative decoupling refers to the environmental impacts generated over time per unit of economic output In contrast, absolute decoupling would examine aggregate environmental impact, compared to total economic output over time. there is no evidence for absolute decoupling as total environmental impacts are still rising partly due to rebound effects Substantial environmental impacts related to everything that is consumed in rich countries occur in developing countries from which goods are imported. A focus on production-based environmental impacts would be misleading as it ignores the [and] environmental impacts that relate to a country’s living standards and that occur outside of that country. Since greenhouse gas emissions are driven by economic growth, the development of alternative economic models that do not depend on growth is urgent since continued growth “threatens the ability of the Earth to support life” | growth is intertwined with an optimistic view of ingenuity to solve problems GDP increases defo natural or industrial accidents resource inputs are non-renewable, and generates wastes disturb ecosystems, severely threatening human and planetary functioning in the short term EROEI will decrease, reducing the incentive to invest in recovery peak oil while demand increases would impact growth climate change may accelerate in the near future growth threatens soil water and forests, ecosystem services such as purification of air and water mitigation of droughts and floods detox of waste pollination and pest control Recent research identify thresholds beyond which life on earth will be at risk Important is the E K C do not take into account the difference between relative and absolute decoupling there is no ev for absolute decoupling due to rebound effects [and] impacts that occur outside that country development of alternative models that do not depend on growth is urgent since growth “threatens the ability of Earth to support life | As the previous chapters have shown, economic growth is regarded as a prime policy aim by policy makers and economists because it is thought to be essential for reducing poverty and generating rising living standards and stable levels of employment (Ben-Ami 2010: 19–20). More generally, support for economic growth is usually intertwined with advocating social progress based on scientific rationality and reason and hence with an optimistic view of humans’ ingenuity to solve problems (ibid.: 17, 20, Chap. 5). Growth criticism thus tends to be portrayed as anti-progress and inherently conservative (ibid.: Chap. 8). While it is important to acknowledge and discuss this view, it needs to be emphasised that growth criticism is formulated with long-term human welfare in mind which advocates alternative types of social progress (Barry 1998). This chapter first outlines ecological and social strands of growth critiques and then introduces relevant concepts of and positions within the postgrowth debate. Ecological Critiques of G rowth Generally speaking, two types of growth criticism can be distinguished: the first focuses on limitations of GDP as a measure of economic performance; the second goes beyond this by highlighting the inappropriateness of growth as the ultimate goal of economic activity and its negative implications for environment and society. Since GDP measures the monetary value of all final goods and services in an economy, it excludes the environmental costs generated by production. For instance, as long as there is no cost associated with emitting greenhouse gases , the cost for the environmental and social damage following from this is not reflected in GDP figures. Worse even, GDP increases as a consequence of some types of environmental damage: if deforestation and timber trade increase or if natural disasters or industrial accidents require expenditures for clean-up and reconstruction, GDP figures will rise (Douthwaite 1999: 18; Leipert 1986). Several critics of GDP as a measure of progress have proposed alternative indicators of welfare such as the Genuine Progress Indicator, Green GDPs or other approaches which factor in environmental costs (see Chap. 5 for more details), but they do not necessarily object to economic growth being the primary goal of economic activity (van den Bergh 2011). In contrast, the idea of ecological limits to growth goes beyond the critique of GDP as a measure of economic performance. Instead, it maintains that economic growth should not, and probably cannot, be the main goal of economic activity because it requires increasing resource inputs, some of which are non-renewable, and generates wastes, including greenhouse gases, that disturb various ecosystems, severely threatening human and planetary functioning in the short and long term. 4 CRITIQUES OF GROWTH 41 Resources are regarded as non-renewable if they cannot be naturally replaced at the rate of consumption (Daly and Farley 2011: 75–76). Examples include fossil fuels, earth minerals and metals, and some nuclear materials like uranium (Daly and Farley 2011: 77; Meadows et al. 2004: 87–107). Based on work by Georgescu-Roegen (1971), many ecological economists also assume that non-renewable resources cannot be fully recycled because they become degraded in the process of economic activity. Historically speaking, economic growth is a fairly recent phenomenon (Fig. 2.1). Since its onset in the late seventeenth century in Europe and mid-eighteenth century in the US (Gordon 2012), it has gone hand in hand with an exponentially increasing use of non-renewable resources such as fossil fuels (Fig. 4.1). While we are not yet close to running out of non-renewable resources, over time they will become more difficult and hence more expensive to recover. This idea is captured by the concept of “energy returned on energy invested” (EROEI). In relation to oil for instance, it has been shown that the easily recoverable fields have been targeted first and that therefore greater energy (and hence financial) inputs will be required to produce more oil. Over time, the ratio of energy returned on energy invested will decrease, reducing the financial incentive to invest further in the recovery of these non-renewable resources (Dale et al. 2011; Brandt et al. 2015: 2). Relevant to this is also the debate about peak oil—a concept coined by Shell Oil geologist Marion King Hubbert in the 1950s—the point at which the rate of global conventional oil production reaches its maximum which is expected to take place roughly once half of global oil reserves have been produced. There is still controversy about whether global peak oil will occur, and if so when, as it is difficult to predict, or get reliable data on, the rate at which alternative types of energy will replace oil (if this was to happen fast enough, peak oil might not be reached, if it has not yet occurred), the size of remaining oil reserves and the future efficiency of oil extraction technologies (Chapman 2014). However, it is plausible to assume that oil prices will rise in the long term if conventional oil availability diminishes, while global demand for oil increases with continuing economic and population growth. Since economic growth in the second half of the twentieth century required increasing inputs of conventional oil, higher oil prices would have a negative impact on growth unless alternative technologies are developed that can generate equivalent liquid fuels at lower prices (Murphy and Hall 2011). Some scholars have criticised the focus on physical/energy resource limitations as initially highlighted in the “limits to growth” debate (Meadows et al. 1972) and state that instead catastrophic climate change is likely to be a more serious and immanent threat to humanity (Schwartzman 2012). The main arguments here are first that much uncertainty remains about the potential and timing of peak oil, future availability of other fossil fuels and development of alternative low energy resources, while the impacts of climate change are already immanent and may accelerate within the very near future. Second, even if peaks in fossil fuel production occurred in the near future, remaining resources could still be exploited to their maximum. However, this would be devastating from a climate change perspective as, according to the latest IPCC scenarios, greenhouse gas emissions need to turn net-zero by the second half of this century for there to be a good chance to limit global warming to 2° Celsius (and ideally, below that) (Anderson and Peters 2016). It is telling that some of the more recent debates about ecological limits to growth put much more emphasis on environmental impacts of growth, rather than on peak oil or other resource limitations (Dietz and O’Neill 2013). Differently put, limits of sinks, especially to absorb greenhouse gases, and to the regeneration of vital ecosystems are now attracting greater concern, compared to limits of resources. Growing economic production generates increasing pressures on the environment due to pollution of air, water and soil, the destruction of natural habitats and landscapes, for instance, through deforestation and the extraction of natural resources. Therefore, growth often also threatens the regeneration of renewable resources such as healthy soil, freshwater and forests, as well as the functioning of vital ecosystems and ecosystems services such as the purification of air and water, water absorption and storage and the related mitigation of droughts and floods, decomposition and detoxification and absorption of wastes, pollination and pest control (Meadows et al. 2004: 83–84). Recent research on planetary boundaries has started to identify thresholds of environmental pollution or disturbance of a range of ecosystems services beyond which the functioning of human life on earth will be put at risk. Rockström and colleagues have identified nine such “planetary boundaries”—“climate change; rate of biodiversity loss (terrestrial and marine); interference with the nitrogen and phosphorus cycles; stratospheric ozone depletion; ocean acidification; global freshwater use; change in land use; chemical pollution; and atmospheric aerosol loading” (Rockström et al. 2009: 472). They also present evidence according to which three of these boundaries—climate change, rate of biodiversity loss and the nitrogen cycle—have already reached their limits (Rockström et al. 2009). Of those three thresholds, climate change has received most attention. The 5th Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC 2014) concluded that global temperatures have risen by an average of 0.85° since the 1880s (while local temperature increases can be much higher than that) and that the concentration of greenhouse gases in the atmosphere has reached unprecedented levels over the last 800,000 years—that of CO2 has now reached 405.6 parts per million (NASA, January 2017, Fig. 4.2), far surpassing the level of 350 ppm which is considered safe by many scientists (Rockström et al. 2009). The IPCC report also maintained that humans very likely contributed to at least 50% of global warming that occurred since the 1950s (IPCC 2014: 5). A range of climate change impacts can already be observed, including a 26% increase of ocean acidification since industrialisation; shrinking of glaciers, Greenland and Antarctic ice sheets, as well as arctic sea ice; and the rise of sea levels of 19 cm since 1901. This is projected to increase by an additional 82 cm by the end of this century at current levels of greenhouse gas emissions (ibid.: 13). Climate change impacts are already felt with increased occurrences of heat waves, heavy rain fall, increased risk of flooding and impacts on food and water security in a number of regions around the world. It is projected that with a rise of 2° of global temperatures, 280 million people worldwide (with greatest numbers in China, India and Bangladesh) would be affected by sea level rise, escalating to a projected 627 million people under a 4° scenario (Strauss et al. 2015: 10). At the 21st Conference of Parties of the United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change in Paris in 2015, representatives agreed that action should be taken to limit rise of global temperatures to 2° and Fig. 4.2 Concentration of CO2 in the atmosphere. Source NASA, available from https://climate.nasa.gov/vital-signs/carbon-dioxide/. The CO2 levels have been reconstructed from measures of trapped air in polar cap ice cores 4 CRITIQUES OF GROWTH 45 to “pursue efforts” to limit it to 1.5°. This has been adopted by 196 countries, but immense efforts and very radical reductions of greenhouse gas emissions will be required to comply with the agreement. Even if net greenhouse gas emissions were reduced to zero, surface temperatures would remain constant at their increased levels for hundreds of years to come and climate change impacts such as ocean acidification and rising sea levels would continue for hundreds or even thousands of years once global temperatures are stabilised; moreover, a range of climate change impacts are deemed irreversible (IPCC 2014: 16). One controversial question in the debate about economic growth and environmental impacts has been whether growth can be decoupled from the damage it causes. Important to this debate is the theory of the Environmental Kuznets Curve which applies Simon Kuznets’ hypothesised inverted u-shaped relationship between economic development and income inequality to the relationship between economic development and environmental degradation. According to this theory, environmental degradation is low in the early phases of economic development, then rises with increasing development up to a certain point, beyond which it falls again with advancing development because more resources can be invested to render production and consumption more efficient and less polluting. Therefore, this theory suggests that it is possible to decouple economic growth (measured in GDP) from its environmental implications. The counter-argument to this theory is that it does not take into account the difference between relative and absolute decoupling. Relative decoupling refers to the environmental impacts generated over time per unit of economic output, for instance CO2 emissions per million of US$. In contrast, absolute decoupling would examine aggregate environmental impact, compared to total economic output over time. Here it has been argued that while relative decoupling may be possible as the environmental impact per unit of economic output decreases over time due to efficiency gains, absolute decoupling is much harder to achieve while growth continues. Indeed, there is no evidence for absolute decoupling as total environmental impacts, for instance total global CO2 emissions, are still rising with rising global GDP (Jackson 2011: 67–86). This is partly due to rebound effects which we discussed in Chap. 2: rising consumption because the increase in efficiency has made it cheaper to produce/consume (Jackson 2011: 67–86; see also Czech 2013: Chap. 8 criticising “green growth”). Furthermore, if decoupling is examined at the country level, one would need to take consumptionbased resource use/emissions into account rather than productionbased impacts. Substantial environmental impacts related to everything that is consumed in rich countries occur in developing countries from which goods are imported. A focus on production-based environmental impacts would hence be misleading as it ignores the [and] environmental impacts that relate to a country’s living standards and that occur outside of that country. Social Critiques of Growth Economic growth has not only been criticised from an ecological perspective, but also from an individual and social wellbeing point of view. Here, we can again distinguish a critique of GDP as a measure of wellbeing and a wider critique which highlights potential negative consequences of economic growth for human wellbeing. Several scholars have argued that GDP is an inadequate measure of prosperity or wellbeing because it only includes market transactions and ignores activities of the informal economy in households and the volunteering sector which make an important contribution to individual and social wellbeing (Stiglitz et al. 2011; van den Bergh 2009; Jackson 2011). It also excludes the contribution of certain government services that are provided for free (Douthwaite 1999: 14; Stiglitz et al. 2011: 23), and the roles of capital stocks and of leisure in generating welfare (Costanza et al. 2015: 137). Furthermore, all market transactions make a positive contribution to GDP, regardless of whether expenditures increase or decrease welfare. Similar to the way in which environmental costs of growth are either excluded from GDP or even increase it, expenditures that arise from road accidents, divorces, crime, etc., contribute positively to GDP (ibid.: 133). The focus on market transactions also means that an increasing marketisation (or “commodification”) of an economy will be reflected in a rise of GDP, which may or may not be related to actual “welfare” outcomes (Stiglitz et al. 2011: 49). It also implies that GDP is an insufficient cross-national comparator for the quality of life, as it does not take into account the different sizes of the informal economy across countries (ibid.: 15). Furthermore, GDP does not indicate how income and consumption are distributed in society (Stiglitz et al. 2011: 44). This implies that a rise of GDP can be consistent with a rise of inequality of income and wealth. 4 CRITIQUES OF GROWTH 47 However, if greater inequality has negative impacts on social wellbeing (Wilkinson and Pickett 2009), this would be masked by rising GDP figures (Douthwaite 1999: 17). An even more fundamental criticism of GDP as a measure of wellbeing is that it focuses on the accumulation of money or wealth and thus on the material aspects of wellbeing. Such a narrow conception of the goals of economic activity and wellbeing has been criticised early on in the history of economic thought, e.g. by Aristotle’s distinction between oikonomia and chrematistics. The latter refers to the accumulation of wealth and was regarded by him as an “unnatural” activity which did not contribute to the generation of use value and wellbeing (Cruz et al. 2009: 2021). The argument that wider conceptions of wellbeing and prosperity are required has also become relevant for contemporary critiques of economic growth (Jackson 2011; Paech 2013; Schneider et al. 2010) as we will discuss this in more detail in Chap. 5. Arguments About the Psychological and S ocial Costs of G rowth The broader social critique of economic growth highlights potential “social limits” to or even negative consequences of economic growth for individual and collective wellbeing. The term “social limits to growth” was coined by Fred Hirsch (1976). He argued that the benefits of growth are initially exclusive to small elites and that these benefits disappear as soon as they spread more widely through mass consumption. For instance, only few people can own a Rembrandt painting; holiday destinations are more enjoyable when they are not overrun by hordes of other tourists; there are only few leadership positions, etc. From this perspective, there are “social limits” to the extent to which the benefits of growth can be socially expanded and equally shared. Other scholars have expressed concern about individual and collective social costs of economic growth. First, there is the argument that the need to keep up with ever-rising living standards and new consumer habits, “keeping up with the Joneses”—a lot of which is seen to be driven by advertisement and social pressure rather than real needs, for instance fashionable clothing or gadgets—can generate stress and increase the occurrence of mental disorders (James 2007; Offer 2006; Kasser 2002). 48 M. BÜCHS AND M. KOCH Second, it has been argued that economic growth can imply wider social costs. For instance, with its emphasis on individual gain, market relations and competition, and the need that it generates for spatial mobility (e.g. for successful participation in education and labour markets), it is feared to undermine moral and social capital and put a strain on family and community relations, potentially even leading to increasing divorce and crime rates (Douthwaite 1999; Daly and Cobb 1989: 50–51; Hirsch 1976). Social costs of technological development and industrialisation also include industrial workplace and traffic accidents and time lost in traffic jams and for commuting (Czech 2013: Chap. 2; Stiglitz et al. 2011: 24). Technological innovation which arises from growth can also act as a factor for job losses and increasing job insecurity (Douthwaite 1999), especially if growth rates are not sufficiently high to compensate gains in productivity. It is often assumed that growth will benefit the many because of assumed “trickle-down” effects which promise to improve the lot of the poor simply because the “cake” of available wealth is growing. While progress has been made in reducing extreme global poverty and inequality (Sala-i-Martin 2006; Rougoor and van Marrewijk 2015), the number of people living in poverty across the globe remains high.1 At the same time, income inequality in a range of countries has been rising and the situation of many of the people living in extreme poverty is not improving which means the fruits of economic growth remain to be unequally distributed (Collier 2007; Piketty and Saez 2014). The post-development debate goes even further than that in arguing that not only may growth not have reached the global poor to the extent that had been predicted by neoclassical economists, but that it can also have negative impacts on indigenous communities in developing countries, especially those who rely on local natural resources for their livelihoods which often suffer exploitation, pollution or even destruction through the inclusion of local economies into global value chains (Rahnema and Bawtree 1997). While the distinction between critiques of growth that focus on its problematic ecological and social consequences is useful for analytic purposes, the two dimensions are of course closely linked. Ecological consequences of growth have the potential to severely impact or even undermine human wellbeing. Local livelihoods are already affected by current climate change impacts such as ocean acidification and its impact on marine organisms, draughts, floods and severe weather events, the 4 CRITIQUES OF GROWTH 49 frequency of which has been rising. Accordingly, it is estimated that crop and fish yields are already diminishing in several regions (Stern 2015; IPCC 2014) and that millions of people are already being displaced and forced to migrate due to climate change and other environmental impacts (Black et al. 2011). While the overall long-term impacts of climate change and the surpassing of other planetary boundaries are difficult to predict, they clearly have the potential to substantially undermine human wellbeing. Since greenhouse gas emissions are driven by economic growth, the development of alternative economic models that do not depend on growth is urgent since continued growth “threatens to alter the ability of the Earth to support life” (Daly and Farley 2011: 12). | 21,496 | <h4>Growth is unsustainable AND innovation <u>can’t solve</u>---shifting away from productivism is key to avoid <u>extinction</u>. </h4><p>Milena <strong>Büchs &</strong> Max <strong>Koch 17</strong>. Milena Büchs is Associate Professor in Sustainability, Economics and Low Carbon Transitions at the University of Leeds, UK. Max Koch is Professor of Social Policy at Lund University (School of Social Work), Sweden. 2017. Postgrowth and Wellbeing. Springer International Publishing. CrossRef, doi:10.1007/978-3-319-59903-8.</p><p>As the previous chapters have shown, <u>economic growth is regarded as a prime policy aim</u> by policy makers and economists <u>because it is thought to be essential for reducing poverty </u>and generating <u>rising living standards and stable</u> levels of <u>employment</u> (Ben-Ami 2010: 19–20). More generally, <u>support for</u> economic <u><mark>growth is</u></mark> usually <u><mark>intertwined with</mark> advocating social progress</u> based on scientific rationality and reason <u>and</u> hence <u>with <mark>an <strong>optimistic view</strong> of</mark> humans’ <strong><mark>ingenuity to solve problems</u></strong></mark> (ibid.: 17, 20, Chap. 5). Growth criticism thus tends to be portrayed as anti-progress and inherently conservative (ibid.: Chap. 8). While it is important to acknowledge and discuss this view, it needs to be emphasised that growth criticism is formulated with long-term human welfare in mind which advocates alternative types of social progress (Barry 1998). This chapter first outlines ecological and social strands of growth critiques and then introduces relevant concepts of and positions within the postgrowth debate. Ecological Critiques of G rowth Generally speaking, two types of growth criticism can be distinguished: the first focuses on limitations of GDP as a measure of economic performance; the second goes beyond this by highlighting the inappropriateness of growth as the ultimate goal of economic activity and its negative implications for environment and society. <u>Since GDP measures</u> the <u>monetary value</u> of all final goods and services in an economy, <u>it excludes</u> the <u>environmental costs</u> generated by production. For instance, <u>as long as there is no cost associated with <strong>emitting</strong> greenhouse gases</u> , <u>the cost for the environmental and social damage following from this is not reflected in GDP figures.</u> Worse even, <u><mark>GDP <strong>increases</strong></mark> as a consequence of some types of environmental damage</u>: <u>if <strong><mark>defo</strong></mark>restation and timber trade increase or if <strong><mark>natural</strong></mark> disasters <mark>or <strong>industrial</strong></mark> <strong><mark>accidents</strong></mark> require expenditures for clean-up and reconstruction, <strong>GDP figures will rise</u></strong> (Douthwaite 1999: 18; Leipert 1986). Several critics of GDP as a measure of progress have proposed alternative indicators of welfare such as the Genuine Progress Indicator, Green GDPs or other approaches which factor in environmental costs (see Chap. 5 for more details), but they do not necessarily object to economic growth being the primary goal of economic activity (van den Bergh 2011). In contrast, the idea of ecological limits to growth goes beyond the critique of GDP as a measure of economic performance. Instead, it maintains that <u>economic growth</u> should not, and probably <u><strong>cannot</strong>, be the main goal of economic activity because it <strong>requires increasing <mark>resource inputs</strong></mark>, some of which <mark>are <strong>non-renewable</strong>, and generates <strong>wastes</strong></mark>, including greenhouse gases, that <strong><mark>disturb</mark> various <mark>ecosystems</strong>, <strong>severely threatening human and planetary functioning in the short</mark> and long <mark>term</mark>. </u></strong>4 CRITIQUES OF GROWTH 41 Resources are regarded as non-renewable if they cannot be naturally replaced at the rate of consumption (Daly and Farley 2011: 75–76). Examples include fossil fuels, earth minerals and metals, and some nuclear materials like uranium (Daly and Farley 2011: 77; Meadows et al. 2004: 87–107). Based on work by Georgescu-Roegen (1971), many ecological economists also assume that non-renewable resources cannot be fully recycled because they become degraded in the process of economic activity. <u>Historically speaking, economic growth is a fairly recent phenomenon</u> (Fig. 2.1). Since its onset in the late seventeenth century in Europe and mid-eighteenth century in the US (Gordon 2012), <u>it has gone hand in hand with an <strong>exponentially</strong> increasing use of non-renewable resources such as fossil fuels</u> (Fig. 4.1). <u>While we are not yet close to <strong>running out</strong> of non-renewable resources, over time they will become <strong>more difficult and hence more expensive to recover</u></strong>. <u>This idea is captured by the concept of “<strong>energy returned on energy invested</strong>”</u> (<u><strong><mark>EROEI</u></strong></mark>). <u>In relation to oil</u> for instance, <u>it has been shown that the easily recoverable fields have been targeted first and that therefore <strong>greater energy</u></strong> (<u>and</u> hence <u><strong>financial</u></strong>) <u>inputs will be required to produce more oil.</u> Over time, <u>the ratio of energy returned on energy invested <mark>will <strong>decrease</u></strong>, <u>reducing the</mark> financial <mark>incentive to invest</mark> further <mark>in</mark> the <mark>recovery</mark> of these non-renewable resources</u> (Dale et al. 2011; Brandt et al. 2015: 2). <u>Relevant to this is also the debate about <strong><mark>peak oil</u></strong></mark>—a concept coined by Shell Oil geologist Marion King Hubbert in the 1950s—<u>the point at which the rate of global conventional oil production reaches its <strong>maximum</strong> which is expected to take place roughly once half of global oil reserves have been produced</u>. There is still controversy about whether global peak oil will occur, and if so when, as it is difficult to predict, or get reliable data on, the rate at which alternative types of energy will replace oil (if this was to happen fast enough, peak oil might not be reached, if it has not yet occurred), the size of remaining oil reserves and the future efficiency of oil extraction technologies (Chapman 2014). However, it is plausible to assume that <u>oil prices <strong>will rise in the long term</strong> if conventional oil availability diminishes, <mark>while</mark> global <strong><mark>demand</strong></mark> for oil <strong><mark>increases</strong></mark> with continuing economic and population growth.</u> <u>Since economic growth in the second half of the twentieth century required <strong>increasing inputs</u></strong> of conventional oil, <u>higher</u> oil <u>prices <mark>would</mark> have a <strong>negative <mark>impact</mark> on <mark>growth</u></strong></mark> unless alternative technologies are developed that can generate equivalent liquid fuels at lower prices (Murphy and Hall 2011). Some scholars have criticised the focus on physical/energy resource limitations as initially highlighted in the “limits to growth” debate (Meadows et al. 1972) and state that instead catastrophic climate change is likely to be a more serious and immanent threat to humanity (Schwartzman 2012). The main arguments here are first that much uncertainty remains about the potential and timing of peak oil, future availability of other fossil fuels and development of alternative low energy resources, while <u>the impacts of</u> <u><strong><mark>climate change</u></strong></mark> <u>are</u> already <u>immanent and <mark>may accelerate</mark> with<mark>in the</mark> <strong>very <mark>near future</u></strong></mark>. Second, even if peaks in fossil fuel production occurred in the near future, <u>remaining resources could </u>still <u>be exploited</u> to their maximum. <u>However, this would be <strong>devastating</strong> </u>from a climate change perspective <u>as</u>, according to the latest IPCC scenarios, <u>greenhouse gas emissions <strong>need to turn net-zero</strong> by the second half of this century for there to be a good chance to limit global warming to 2° Celsius (and ideally, below that)</u> (Anderson and Peters 2016). It is telling that some of the more recent debates about ecological limits to growth put much more emphasis on environmental impacts of growth, rather than on peak oil or other resource limitations (Dietz and O’Neill 2013). Differently put, <u>limits of <strong>sinks</u></strong>, especially <u>to absorb</u> greenhouse <u>gases</u>, <u>and</u> to the <u>regenerat</u>ion of <u>vital ecosystems</u> <u>are now attracting <strong>greater concern</u></strong>, compared to limits of resources. Growing economic production generates increasing pressures on the environment due to pollution of air, water and soil, the destruction of natural habitats and landscapes, for instance, through deforestation and the extraction of natural resources. Therefore, <u><mark>growth</u></mark> often also <u><mark>threatens</u></mark> the regeneration of renewable resources such as healthy <u><strong><mark>soil</u></strong></mark>, <u><strong>fresh<mark>water</u></strong> <u>and</u> <u><strong>forests</u></strong>,</mark> <u>as well as the functioning of vital <strong><mark>ecosystem</strong></mark>s and ecosystems <mark>services such as</mark> the <mark>purification of <strong>air and water</strong></mark>, water</u> <u><strong>absorption</u></strong> <u>and</u> <u><strong>storage</u></strong> <u>and the related <mark>mitigation of <strong>droughts</strong> and</u> <u><strong>floods</u></strong></mark>, <u>decomposition and <strong><mark>detox</strong></mark>ification and absorption <mark>of <strong>waste</strong></mark>s, <strong><mark>pollination</u></strong> <u>and</u> <u><strong>pest control</u></strong></mark> (Meadows et al. 2004: 83–84). <u><mark>Recent research</mark> on planetary boundaries has started to <mark>identify <strong>thresholds</strong></mark> of environmental pollution or disturbance of a range of ecosystems services <mark>beyond which</mark> the functioning of human <strong><mark>life on earth</strong> will be</mark> put <mark>at risk</u></mark>. Rockström and colleagues have identified nine such “planetary boundaries”—“climate change; rate of biodiversity loss (terrestrial and marine); interference with the nitrogen and phosphorus cycles; stratospheric ozone depletion; ocean acidification; global freshwater use; change in land use; chemical pollution; and atmospheric aerosol loading” (Rockström et al. 2009: 472). They also present evidence according to which three of these boundaries—climate change, rate of biodiversity loss and the nitrogen cycle—have already reached their limits (Rockström et al. 2009). Of those three thresholds, climate change has received most attention. The 5th Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC 2014) concluded that global temperatures have risen by an average of 0.85° since the 1880s (while local temperature increases can be much higher than that) and that the concentration of greenhouse gases in the atmosphere has reached unprecedented levels over the last 800,000 years—that of CO2 has now reached 405.6 parts per million (NASA, January 2017, Fig. 4.2), far surpassing the level of 350 ppm which is considered safe by many scientists (Rockström et al. 2009). The IPCC report also maintained that humans very likely contributed to at least 50% of global warming that occurred since the 1950s (IPCC 2014: 5). A range of climate change impacts can already be observed, including a 26% increase of ocean acidification since industrialisation; shrinking of glaciers, Greenland and Antarctic ice sheets, as well as arctic sea ice; and the rise of sea levels of 19 cm since 1901. This is projected to increase by an additional 82 cm by the end of this century at current levels of greenhouse gas emissions (ibid.: 13). Climate change impacts are already felt with increased occurrences of heat waves, heavy rain fall, increased risk of flooding and impacts on food and water security in a number of regions around the world. It is projected that with a rise of 2° of global temperatures, 280 million people worldwide (with greatest numbers in China, India and Bangladesh) would be affected by sea level rise, escalating to a projected 627 million people under a 4° scenario (Strauss et al. 2015: 10). At the 21st Conference of Parties of the United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change in Paris in 2015, representatives agreed that action should be taken to limit rise of global temperatures to 2° and Fig. 4.2 Concentration of CO2 in the atmosphere. Source NASA, available from https://climate.nasa.gov/vital-signs/carbon-dioxide/. The CO2 levels have been reconstructed from measures of trapped air in polar cap ice cores 4 CRITIQUES OF GROWTH 45 to “pursue efforts” to limit it to 1.5°. This has been adopted by 196 countries, but immense efforts and very radical reductions of greenhouse gas emissions will be required to comply with the agreement. Even if net greenhouse gas emissions were reduced to zero, surface temperatures would remain constant at their increased levels for hundreds of years to come and climate change impacts such as ocean acidification and rising sea levels would continue for hundreds or even thousands of years once global temperatures are stabilised; moreover, a range of climate change impacts are deemed irreversible (IPCC 2014: 16). <u>One controversial question in the debate about economic growth and environmental impacts has been whether growth can be <strong>decoupled from the damage it causes</u></strong>. <u><mark>Important</mark> to this</u> debate <u><mark>is the</mark> theory of the <strong><mark>E</strong></mark>nvironmental <strong><mark>K</strong></mark>uznets <strong><mark>C</strong></mark>urve</u> which applies Simon Kuznets’ hypothesised inverted u-shaped relationship between economic development and income inequality to the relationship between economic development and environmental degradation. According to this theory, environmental degradation is low in the early phases of economic development, then rises with increasing development up to a certain point, beyond which it falls again with advancing development because more resources can be invested to render production and consumption more efficient and less polluting. Therefore, this theory suggests that it is possible to decouple economic growth (measured in GDP) from its environmental implications. The counter-argument to <u>this theory</u> is that it <u><mark>do</mark>es <mark>not take into</mark> <mark>account the difference between <strong>relative and absolute decoupling</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong>Relative</u></strong> <u>decoupling refers to the environmental impacts generated over time <strong>per unit of economic output</u></strong>, for instance CO2 emissions per million of US$. <u>In contrast, absolute decoupling would examine <strong>aggregate environmental impact</strong>, compared to total economic output over time. </u>Here it has been argued that while relative decoupling may be possible as the environmental impact per unit of economic output decreases over time due to efficiency gains, absolute decoupling is much harder to achieve while growth continues. Indeed, <u><mark>there is <strong>no ev</strong></mark>idence <strong><mark>for absolute decoupling</strong></mark> as <strong>total</strong> environmental impacts</u>, for instance total global CO2 emissions, <u>are</u> <u><strong>still rising</u></strong> with rising global GDP (Jackson 2011: 67–86). This is <u>partly <mark>due to <strong>rebound effects</u></strong></mark> which we discussed in Chap. 2: rising consumption because the increase in efficiency has made it cheaper to produce/consume (Jackson 2011: 67–86; see also Czech 2013: Chap. 8 criticising “green growth”). Furthermore, if decoupling is examined at the country level, one would need to take consumptionbased resource use/emissions into account rather than productionbased impacts. <u>Substantial environmental impacts related to everything that is consumed in rich countries occur in <strong>developing countries from which goods are imported</strong>. A focus on production-based environmental impacts would</u> hence <u>be</u> <u><strong>misleading</u></strong> <u>as it <strong>ignores the <mark>[and]</mark> environmental <mark>impacts</u></strong></mark> <u>that relate to a country’s living standards and <mark>that occur</mark> <strong><mark>outside</strong></mark> of <strong><mark>that country</strong></mark>. </u>Social Critiques of Growth Economic growth has not only been criticised from an ecological perspective, but also from an individual and social wellbeing point of view. Here, we can again distinguish a critique of GDP as a measure of wellbeing and a wider critique which highlights potential negative consequences of economic growth for human wellbeing. Several scholars have argued that GDP is an inadequate measure of prosperity or wellbeing because it only includes market transactions and ignores activities of the informal economy in households and the volunteering sector which make an important contribution to individual and social wellbeing (Stiglitz et al. 2011; van den Bergh 2009; Jackson 2011). It also excludes the contribution of certain government services that are provided for free (Douthwaite 1999: 14; Stiglitz et al. 2011: 23), and the roles of capital stocks and of leisure in generating welfare (Costanza et al. 2015: 137). Furthermore, all market transactions make a positive contribution to GDP, regardless of whether expenditures increase or decrease welfare. Similar to the way in which environmental costs of growth are either excluded from GDP or even increase it, expenditures that arise from road accidents, divorces, crime, etc., contribute positively to GDP (ibid.: 133). The focus on market transactions also means that an increasing marketisation (or “commodification”) of an economy will be reflected in a rise of GDP, which may or may not be related to actual “welfare” outcomes (Stiglitz et al. 2011: 49). It also implies that GDP is an insufficient cross-national comparator for the quality of life, as it does not take into account the different sizes of the informal economy across countries (ibid.: 15). Furthermore, GDP does not indicate how income and consumption are distributed in society (Stiglitz et al. 2011: 44). This implies that a rise of GDP can be consistent with a rise of inequality of income and wealth. 4 CRITIQUES OF GROWTH 47 However, if greater inequality has negative impacts on social wellbeing (Wilkinson and Pickett 2009), this would be masked by rising GDP figures (Douthwaite 1999: 17). An even more fundamental criticism of GDP as a measure of wellbeing is that it focuses on the accumulation of money or wealth and thus on the material aspects of wellbeing. Such a narrow conception of the goals of economic activity and wellbeing has been criticised early on in the history of economic thought, e.g. by Aristotle’s distinction between oikonomia and chrematistics. The latter refers to the accumulation of wealth and was regarded by him as an “unnatural” activity which did not contribute to the generation of use value and wellbeing (Cruz et al. 2009: 2021). The argument that wider conceptions of wellbeing and prosperity are required has also become relevant for contemporary critiques of economic growth (Jackson 2011; Paech 2013; Schneider et al. 2010) as we will discuss this in more detail in Chap. 5. Arguments About the Psychological and S ocial Costs of G rowth The broader social critique of economic growth highlights potential “social limits” to or even negative consequences of economic growth for individual and collective wellbeing. The term “social limits to growth” was coined by Fred Hirsch (1976). He argued that the benefits of growth are initially exclusive to small elites and that these benefits disappear as soon as they spread more widely through mass consumption. For instance, only few people can own a Rembrandt painting; holiday destinations are more enjoyable when they are not overrun by hordes of other tourists; there are only few leadership positions, etc. From this perspective, there are “social limits” to the extent to which the benefits of growth can be socially expanded and equally shared. Other scholars have expressed concern about individual and collective social costs of economic growth. First, there is the argument that the need to keep up with ever-rising living standards and new consumer habits, “keeping up with the Joneses”—a lot of which is seen to be driven by advertisement and social pressure rather than real needs, for instance fashionable clothing or gadgets—can generate stress and increase the occurrence of mental disorders (James 2007; Offer 2006; Kasser 2002). 48 M. BÜCHS AND M. KOCH Second, it has been argued that economic growth can imply wider social costs. For instance, with its emphasis on individual gain, market relations and competition, and the need that it generates for spatial mobility (e.g. for successful participation in education and labour markets), it is feared to undermine moral and social capital and put a strain on family and community relations, potentially even leading to increasing divorce and crime rates (Douthwaite 1999; Daly and Cobb 1989: 50–51; Hirsch 1976). Social costs of technological development and industrialisation also include industrial workplace and traffic accidents and time lost in traffic jams and for commuting (Czech 2013: Chap. 2; Stiglitz et al. 2011: 24). Technological innovation which arises from growth can also act as a factor for job losses and increasing job insecurity (Douthwaite 1999), especially if growth rates are not sufficiently high to compensate gains in productivity. It is often assumed that growth will benefit the many because of assumed “trickle-down” effects which promise to improve the lot of the poor simply because the “cake” of available wealth is growing. While progress has been made in reducing extreme global poverty and inequality (Sala-i-Martin 2006; Rougoor and van Marrewijk 2015), the number of people living in poverty across the globe remains high.1 At the same time, income inequality in a range of countries has been rising and the situation of many of the people living in extreme poverty is not improving which means the fruits of economic growth remain to be unequally distributed (Collier 2007; Piketty and Saez 2014). The post-development debate goes even further than that in arguing that not only may growth not have reached the global poor to the extent that had been predicted by neoclassical economists, but that it can also have negative impacts on indigenous communities in developing countries, especially those who rely on local natural resources for their livelihoods which often suffer exploitation, pollution or even destruction through the inclusion of local economies into global value chains (Rahnema and Bawtree 1997). While the distinction between critiques of growth that focus on its problematic ecological and social consequences is useful for analytic purposes, the two dimensions are of course closely linked. Ecological consequences of growth have the potential to severely impact or even undermine human wellbeing. Local livelihoods are already affected by current climate change impacts such as ocean acidification and its impact on marine organisms, draughts, floods and severe weather events, the 4 CRITIQUES OF GROWTH 49 frequency of which has been rising. Accordingly, it is estimated that crop and fish yields are already diminishing in several regions (Stern 2015; IPCC 2014) and that millions of people are already being displaced and forced to migrate due to climate change and other environmental impacts (Black et al. 2011). While the overall long-term impacts of climate change and the surpassing of other planetary boundaries are difficult to predict, they clearly have the potential to substantially undermine human wellbeing. <u>Since greenhouse gas emissions are driven by economic growth, the <mark>development of <strong>alternative</mark> economic <mark>models that do not depend on growth</strong> is <strong>urgent</strong> since</mark> <strong>continued <mark>growth “threatens</mark> </u></strong>to alter <u><strong><mark>the ability of</mark> the <mark>Earth to support life</mark>”</u></strong> (Daly and Farley 2011: 12).</p> | Open source cal r2 | 2AC | Debt Ceiling DA | 60,135 | 169 | 105,137 | ./documents/hspolicy18/MontgomeryBellAcademy/GlBr/Montgomery%20Bell%20Academy-Glen-Bradford-Aff-berkeley-Round2.docx | 697,678 | A | berkeley | 2 | asian debate league pt | tanzil chowdhury | 1ac - hospitality
2nr - neolib k | hspolicy18/MontgomeryBellAcademy/GlBr/Montgomery%20Bell%20Academy-Glen-Bradford-Aff-berkeley-Round2.docx | null | 59,327 | GlBr | Montgomery Bell Academy GlBr | null | At..... | Gl..... | Wi..... | Br..... | 20,916 | MontgomeryBellAcademy | Montgomery Bell Academy | null | null | 1,017 | hspolicy18 | HS Policy 2018-19 | 2,018 | cx | hs | 2 |
953,690 | CP Pics out of USFG – only uses congress. “The” implies all parts | Merriam-Webster's 5 | Merriam-Webster's Online Collegiate Dictionary, 5 | the used as a function word before a noun to indicate reference to a group as a whole | used to indicate reference to a group as a whole | http://www.m-w.com/cgi-bin/dictionary
the 4 -- used as a function word before a noun or a substantivized adjective to indicate reference to a group as a whole <the elite> | 171 | <h4>CP Pics out of USFG – only uses congress. <strong>“The” implies all parts</h4><p>Merriam-Webster's</strong> Online Collegiate Dictionary, <strong>5 </p><p></strong>http://www.m-w.com/cgi-bin/dictionary </p><p><u>the</u> 4 -- <u><mark>used</mark> as a function word before a noun</u> or a substantivized adjective <u><mark>to indicate reference to a group as a whole</u></mark> <the elite></p> | 2NC | CP – Sunsets | 2NC – AT: Perm do CP | 164,379 | 39 | 23,168 | ./documents/ndtceda21/Dartmouth/ShVe/Dartmouth-Shankar-Vergho-Neg-4%20-%20DRR-Round4.docx | 623,260 | N | 4 - DRR | 4 | Emory GK | Jackie Poapst | 1AC
- Religious Freedom
1NC
- Court CP
- Politics DA
- Regulate CP
- Sunsets CP
- CIL CP
- T-Prohibit
- LPE K
- Biz Con DA
- States CP
- FTC Tradeoff DA
2NC
- Sunsets CP
- Court CP
1NR
- Politics DA
2NR
- Sunsets CP
- Politics DA
2AR
- Condo | ndtceda21/Dartmouth/ShVe/Dartmouth-Shankar-Vergho-Neg-4%20-%20DRR-Round4.docx | null | 52,618 | ShVe | Dartmouth ShVe | null | Ar..... | Sh..... | Ty..... | Ve..... | 19,377 | Dartmouth | Dartmouth | null | null | 1,011 | ndtceda21 | NDT/CEDA 2021-22 | 2,021 | cx | college | 2 |
1,433,747 | It’s key to CCS – link-turns every impact. | Graciela ‘16 | Graciela ‘16 (/16 – Professor of Economics and of Statistics at Columbia University and Visiting Professor at Stanford University, and was the architect of the Kyoto Protocol carbon market (being interviewed by Marcus Rolle, freelance journalist specializing in environmental issues and global affairs, “Reversing Climate Change: Interview with Graciela Chichilnisky,” http://www.globalpolicyjournal.com/blog/01/09/2016/reversing-climate-change-interview-graciela-chichilnisky)//cmr | Green Capitalism requires the creation of property rights nation by nation for the use of the atmosphere, and the creation of new markets to trade these rights Green Capitalism is needed now to help avert climate change the building blocks for Green Capitalism are Global limits nation by nation New global markets to trade these limits The new market create new measures of economic values and update the concept of GDP. Efficient use of Carbon Negative Tech new generation tech can capture CO2 from the air a 400 MW coal plant that emits 1 million tons of CO2 per year can become a carbon sink absorbing a net amount of 1 million tons of CO2 instead Carbon capture from air can be done anywhere and at any time, and so inexpensively that the CO2 can be sold for industrial or commercial uses such as plastics, food and beverages, greenhouses, bio-fertilizers, building materials and even enhanced oil recovery This means more energy, more jobs, and it also means economic growth in developing nations, all of this while cleaning the CO2 in the atmosphere. Carbon negative tech can literally transform the world economy long-run strategies do not work in the short run economic incentives are needed. the fossil fuel power plant infrastructure is 87% of the power plant infrastructure and about $45-55 trillion globally. This infrastructure cannot be replaced quickly, certainly not in the short time period in which we need to take action to avert catastrophic climate change. CO2 once emitted remains hundreds of years in the atmosphere and we have emitted so much that unless we actually remove the CO2 that is already there, we cannot remain within the carbon budget we face significant time pressure IPCC indicates we must actually remove the carbon that is already in the atmosphere in massive quantities This is what I called a carbon negative approach, Renewable energy is too slow for a short run resolution since replacing a $45-55 trillion power plant infrastructure with renewable plants could take decades. We need action sooner than that. trees and other natural sinks are too slow for what we need today. must be part of the blueprint for Green Capitalism while in the long run renewable sources of energy suffice These are in limited supply and cannot replace fossil fuels Global energy today is 87% fossil 10% nuclear, geothermal, and hydroelectric, and less than 1% is solar we need a short-term strategy that accelerates long run renewable energy In the short term as the IPCC validates, we need carbon negative tech The short run is the next 20 or 30 years There is no time in this period of time to transform the entire fossil infrastructure The solution is to combine air capture of CO2 with storage of CO2 into stable materials that replace other materials It is possible to combine CO2 to produce renewable gasoline, new tech using algae make synthetic fuel commercially feasible at competitive rates the blueprint offered here is a private/public approach based on new industrial tech financial markets self-funded and using profitable greenmarkets a carbon negative economy represents green capitalism resolving the North–South Divide Green Capitalism means economic growth that is harmonious with the Earth resources | Green Capitalism is needed to avert climate change coal plant can absorb 1 million tons long-run strategies do not work economic incentives are needed fossil fuel infrastructure is 87% globally. This cannot be replaced in time to avert climate change we must remove carbon solution is to air capture of CO2 with storage to combine CO2 to produce renewable gasoline make synthetic fuel commercially feasible blueprint is a private/public approach, based on new industrial tech financial markets, and using profitable greenmarkets | GC: Green capitalism is a new economic system that values the natural resources on which human survival depends. It fosters a harmonious relationship with our planet, its resources and the many species it harbors. It is a new type of market economics that addresses both equity and efficiency. Using carbon negative technology™ it helps reduce carbon in the atmosphere while fostering economic development in rich and developing nations, for example in the U S., EU, China and India. How does this work? In a nutshell Green Capitalism requires the creation of global limits or property rights nation by nation for the use of the atmosphere, the bodies of water and the planet’s biodiversity, and the creation of new markets to trade these rights from which new economic values and a new concept of economic progress emerges updating GDP as is now generally agreed is needed. Green Capitalism is needed now to help avert climate change and achieve the goals of the 2015 UN Paris Agreement, which are very ambitious and universally supported but have no way to be realized within the Agreement itself. The Carbon Market and its CDM play critical roles in the foundation of Green Capitalism, creating values to redefine GDP. These are needed to remain within the world’s “CO2 budget” and avoid catastrophic climate change. As I see it, the building blocks for Green Capitalism are then as follows; (1) Global limits nation by nation in the use of the planet’s atmosphere, its water bodies and biodiversity - these are global public goods. (2) New global markets to trade these limits, based on equity and efficiency. These markets are relatives of the Carbon Market and the SO2 market. The new market create new measures of economic values and update the concept of GDP. (3) Efficient use of Carbon Negative Technologies to avert catastrophic climate change by providing a smooth transition to clean energy and ensuring economic prosperity in rich and poor nations. These building blocks have immediate practical implications in reversing climate change and can assist the ambitious aims of Paris COP21 become a reality. MR: What is the greatest advantage of the new generation technologies that can capture CO2 from the air? GC: These technologies build carbon negative power plants, such as Global Thermostat, that clean the atmosphere of CO2 while producing electricity. Global Thermostat is a firm that is commercializing a technology that takes CO2 out of air and uses mostly low cost residual heat rather than electricity to drive the capture process, making the entire process of capturing CO2 from the atmosphere very inexpensive. There is enough residua heat in a coal power plant that it can be used to capture twice as much CO2 as the plant emits, thus transforming the power plant into a “carbon sink.” For example, a 400 MW coal plant that emits 1 million tons of CO2 per year can become a carbon sink absorbing a net amount of 1 million tons of CO2 instead. Carbon capture from air can be done anywhere and at any time, and so inexpensively that the CO2 can be sold for industrial or commercial uses such as plastics, food and beverages, greenhouses, bio-fertilizers, building materials and even enhanced oil recovery, all examples of large global markets and profitable opportunities. Carbon capture is powered mostly by low (85°C) residual heat that is inexpensive, and any source will do. In particular, renewable (solar) technology can power the process of carbon capture. This can help advance solar technology and make it more cost-efficient. This means more energy, more jobs, and it also means economic growth in developing nations, all of this while cleaning the CO2 in the atmosphere. Carbon negative technologies can literally transform the world economy. MR: One final question. You distinguish between long-run and short-run strategies in the effort to reverse climate change. Would carbon negative technologies be part of a short-run strategy? GC: Long-run strategies are quite different from strategies for the short-run. Often long-run strategies do not work in the short run and different policies and economic incentives are needed. In the long run the best climate change policy is to replace fossil fuel sources of energy that by themselves cause 45% of the global emissions, and to plant trees to restore if possible the natural sources and sinks of CO2. But the fossil fuel power plant infrastructure is about 87% of the power plant infrastructure and about $45-55 trillion globally. This infrastructure cannot be replaced quickly, certainly not in the short time period in which we need to take action to avert catastrophic climate change. The issue is that CO2 once emitted remains hundreds of years in the atmosphere and we have emitted so much that unless we actually remove the CO2 that is already there, we cannot remain long within the carbon budget, which is the concentration of CO2 beyond which we fear catastrophic climate change. In the short run, therefore, we face significant time pressure. The IPCC indicates in its 2014 5th Assessment Report that we must actually remove the carbon that is already in the atmosphere and do so in massive quantities, this century (p. 191 of 5th Assessment Report). This is what I called a carbon negative approach, which works for the short run. Renewable energy is the long run solution. Renewable energy is too slow for a short run resolution since replacing a $45-55 trillion power plant infrastructure with renewable plants could take decades. We need action sooner than that. For the short run we need carbon negative technologies that capture more carbon than what is emitted. Trees do that and they must be conserved to help preserve biodiversity. Biochar does that. But trees and other natural sinks are too slow for what we need today. Therefore, negative carbon is needed now as part of a blueprint for transformation. It must be part of the blueprint for Sustainable Development and its short term manifestation that I call Green Capitalism, while in the long run renewable sources of energy suffice, including Wind, Biofuels, Nuclear, Geothermal, and Hydroelectric energy. These are in limited supply and cannot replace fossil fuels. Global energy today is roughly divided as follows: 87% is fossil, namely natural gas, coal, oil; 10% is nuclear, geothermal, and hydroelectric, and less than 1% is solar power — photovoltaic and solar thermal. Nuclear fuel is scarce and nuclear technology is generally considered dangerous as tragically experienced by the Fukushima Daichi nuclear disaster in Japan, and it seems unrealistic to seek a solution in the nuclear direction. Only solar energy can be a long term solution: Less than 1% of the solar energy we receive on earth can be transformed into 10 times the fossil fuel energy used in the world today. Yet we need a short-term strategy that accelerates long run renewable energy, or we will defeat long-term goals. In the short term as the IPCC validates, we need carbon negative technology, carbon removals. The short run is the next 20 or 30 years. There is no time in this period of time to transform the entire fossil infrastructure — it costs $45-55 trillion (IEA) to replace and it is slow to build. We need to directly reduce carbon in the atmosphere now. We cannot use traditional methods to remove CO2 from smokestacks (called often Carbon Capture and Sequestration, CSS) because they are not carbon negative as is required. CSS works but does not suffice because it only captures what power plants currently emit. Any level of emissions adds to the stable and high concentration we have today and CO2 remains in the atmosphere for years. We need to remove the CO2 that is already in the atmosphere, namely air capture of CO2 also called carbon removals. The solution is to combine air capture of CO2 with storage of CO2 into stable materials such as biochar, cement, polymers, and carbon fibers that replace a number of other construction materials such as metals. The most recent BMW automobile model uses only carbon fibers rather than metals. It is also possible to combine CO2 to produce renewable gasoline, namely gasoline produced from air and water. CO2 can be separated from air and hydrogen separated from water, and their combination is a well-known industrial process to produce gasoline. Is this therefore too expensive? There are new technologies using algae that make synthetic fuel commercially feasible at competitive rates. Other policies would involve combining air capture with solar thermal electricity using the residual solar thermal heat to drive the carbon capture process. This can make a solar plant more productive and efficient so it can out-compete coal as a source of energy. In summary, the blueprint offered here is a private/public approach, based on new industrial technology and financial markets, self-funded and using profitable greenmarkets, with securities that utilize carbon credits as the “underlying” asset, based on the KP CDM, as well as new markets for biodiversity and water providing abundant clean energy to stave off impending and actual energy crisis in developing nations, fostering mutually beneficial cooperation for industrial and developing nations. The blueprint proposed provides the two sides of the coin, equity and efficiency, and can assign a critical role for women as stewards for human survival and sustainable development. My vision is a carbon negative economy that represents green capitalism in resolving the Global Climate negotiations and the North–South Divide. Carbon negative power plants and capture of CO2 from air and ensure a clean atmosphere together innovation and more jobs and exports: the more you produce and create jobs the cleaner becomes the atmosphere. In practice, Green Capitalism means economic growth that is harmonious with the Earth resources. | 9,891 | <h4>It’s key to CCS – link-turns <u>every</u> impact. </h4><p><strong>Graciela ‘16 </strong>(/16 – Professor of Economics and of Statistics at Columbia University and Visiting Professor at Stanford University, and was the architect of the Kyoto Protocol carbon market (being interviewed by Marcus Rolle, freelance journalist specializing in environmental issues and global affairs, “Reversing Climate Change: Interview with Graciela Chichilnisky,” http://www.globalpolicyjournal.com/blog/01/09/2016/reversing-climate-change-interview-graciela-chichilnisky)//cmr </p><p>GC: Green capitalism is a new economic system that values the natural resources on which human survival depends. It fosters a harmonious relationship with our planet, its resources and the many species it harbors. It is a new type of market economics that addresses both equity and efficiency. Using carbon negative technology™ it helps reduce carbon in the atmosphere while fostering economic development in rich and developing nations, for example in the U S., EU, China and India. How does this work? In a nutshell <u><strong>Green Capitalism requires the creation of </u></strong>global limits or <u><strong>property rights nation by nation for the use of the atmosphere, </u></strong>the bodies of water and the planet’s biodiversity, <u><strong>and the creation of new markets to trade these rights</u></strong> from which new economic values and a new concept of economic progress emerges updating GDP as is now generally agreed is needed. <u><strong><mark>Green Capitalism is needed</mark> now <mark>to</mark> help <mark>avert climate change</mark> </u></strong>and achieve the goals of the 2015 UN Paris Agreement, which are very ambitious and universally supported but have no way to be realized within the Agreement itself. The Carbon Market and its CDM play critical roles in the foundation of Green Capitalism, creating values to redefine GDP. These are needed to remain within the world’s “CO2 budget” and avoid catastrophic climate change. As I see it, <u><strong>the building blocks for Green Capitalism are</u></strong> then as follows; (1) <u><strong>Global limits nation by nation</u></strong> in the use of the planet’s atmosphere, its water bodies and biodiversity - these are global public goods. (2) <u><strong>New global markets to trade these limits</u></strong>, based on equity and efficiency. These markets are relatives of the Carbon Market and the SO2 market. <u><strong>The new market create new measures of economic values and update the concept of GDP. </u></strong>(3) <u><strong>Efficient use of Carbon Negative Tech</u></strong>nologies to avert catastrophic climate change by providing a smooth transition to clean energy and ensuring economic prosperity in rich and poor nations. These building blocks have immediate practical implications in reversing climate change and can assist the ambitious aims of Paris COP21 become a reality. MR: What is the greatest advantage of the <u><strong>new generation tech</u></strong>nologies that <u><strong>can capture CO2 from the air</u></strong>? GC: These technologies build carbon negative power plants, such as Global Thermostat, that clean the atmosphere of CO2 while producing electricity. Global Thermostat is a firm that is commercializing a technology that takes CO2 out of air and uses mostly low cost residual heat rather than electricity to drive the capture process, making the entire process of capturing CO2 from the atmosphere very inexpensive. There is enough residua heat in a coal power plant that it can be used to capture twice as much CO2 as the plant emits, thus transforming the power plant into a “carbon sink.” For example, <u><strong>a 400 MW <mark>coal plant </mark>that emits 1 million tons of CO2 per year <mark>can</mark> become a carbon sink <mark>absorb</mark>ing a net amount of <mark>1 million tons</mark> of CO2 instead</u></strong>. <u><strong>Carbon capture from air can be done anywhere and at any time, and so inexpensively that the CO2 can be sold for industrial or commercial uses such as plastics, food and beverages, greenhouses, bio-fertilizers, building materials and even enhanced oil recovery</u></strong>, all examples of large global markets and profitable opportunities. Carbon capture is powered mostly by low (85°C) residual heat that is inexpensive, and any source will do. In particular, renewable (solar) technology can power the process of carbon capture. This can help advance solar technology and make it more cost-efficient. <u><strong>This means more energy, more jobs, and it also means economic growth in developing nations, all of this while cleaning the CO2 in the atmosphere. Carbon negative tech</u></strong>nologies <u><strong>can literally transform the world economy</u></strong>. MR: One final question. You distinguish between long-run and short-run strategies in the effort to reverse climate change. Would carbon negative technologies be part of a short-run strategy? GC: Long-run strategies are quite different from strategies for the short-run. Often <u><strong><mark>long-run strategies do not work </mark>in the short run</u></strong> and different policies and <u><strong><mark>economic incentives are needed</mark>.</u></strong> In the long run the best climate change policy is to replace fossil fuel sources of energy that by themselves cause 45% of the global emissions, and to plant trees to restore if possible the natural sources and sinks of CO2. But <u><strong>the <mark>fossil fuel</mark> power plant <mark>infrastructure is</u></strong></mark> about <u><strong><mark>87%</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>of the power plant infrastructure and about $45-55 trillion <mark>globally.</u></strong> <u><strong>This</mark> infrastructure <mark>cannot be replaced</mark> quickly, certainly not <mark>in </mark>the short <mark>time</mark> period in which we need <mark>to</mark> take action to <mark>avert</mark> catastrophic <mark>climate change</mark>.</u></strong> The issue is that <u><strong>CO2 once emitted remains hundreds of years in the atmosphere and we have emitted so much that unless we actually remove the CO2 that is already there, we cannot remain</u></strong> long <u><strong>within the carbon budget</u></strong>, which is the concentration of CO2 beyond which we fear catastrophic climate change. In the short run, therefore, <u><strong>we face significant time pressure</u></strong>. The <u><strong>IPCC indicates</u></strong> in its 2014 5th Assessment Report that <u><strong><mark>we must</mark> actually <mark>remove</mark> the <mark>carbon</mark> that is already in the atmosphere</u></strong> and do so <u><strong>in massive quantities</u></strong>, this century (p. 191 of 5th Assessment Report). <u><strong>This is what I called a carbon negative approach,</u></strong> which works for the short run. Renewable energy is the long run solution. <u><strong>Renewable energy is too slow for a short run resolution since replacing a $45-55 trillion power plant infrastructure with renewable plants could take decades.</u></strong> <u><strong>We need action sooner than that.</u></strong> For the short run we need carbon negative technologies that capture more carbon than what is emitted. Trees do that and they must be conserved to help preserve biodiversity. Biochar does that. But <u><strong>trees and other natural sinks are too slow for what we need today.</u></strong> Therefore, negative carbon is needed now as part of a blueprint for transformation. It <u><strong>must be part of the blueprint for</u></strong> Sustainable Development and its short term manifestation that I call <u><strong>Green Capitalism</u></strong>, <u><strong>while in the long run renewable sources of energy suffice</u></strong>, including Wind, Biofuels, Nuclear, Geothermal, and Hydroelectric energy. <u><strong>These are in limited supply and cannot replace fossil fuels</u></strong>. <u><strong>Global energy today is</u></strong> roughly divided as follows: <u><strong>87%</u></strong> is <u><strong>fossil</u></strong>, namely natural gas, coal, oil; <u><strong>10%</u></strong> is <u><strong>nuclear, geothermal, and hydroelectric, and less than 1% is solar </u></strong>power — photovoltaic and solar thermal. Nuclear fuel is scarce and nuclear technology is generally considered dangerous as tragically experienced by the Fukushima Daichi nuclear disaster in Japan, and it seems unrealistic to seek a solution in the nuclear direction. Only solar energy can be a long term solution: Less than 1% of the solar energy we receive on earth can be transformed into 10 times the fossil fuel energy used in the world today. Yet <u><strong>we need a short-term strategy that accelerates long run renewable energy</u></strong>, or we will defeat long-term goals. <u><strong>In the short term as the IPCC validates, we need carbon negative tech</u></strong>nology, carbon removals. <u><strong>The short run is the next 20 or 30 years</u></strong>. <u><strong>There is no time in this period of time to transform the entire fossil infrastructure</u></strong> — it costs $45-55 trillion (IEA) to replace and it is slow to build. We need to directly reduce carbon in the atmosphere now. We cannot use traditional methods to remove CO2 from smokestacks (called often Carbon Capture and Sequestration, CSS) because they are not carbon negative as is required. CSS works but does not suffice because it only captures what power plants currently emit. Any level of emissions adds to the stable and high concentration we have today and CO2 remains in the atmosphere for years. We need to remove the CO2 that is already in the atmosphere, namely air capture of CO2 also called carbon removals. <u><strong>The <mark>solution is to</mark> combine <mark>air capture of CO2</mark> <mark>with storage</mark> of CO2 into stable materials</u></strong> such as biochar, cement, polymers, and carbon fibers <u><strong>that replace</u></strong> a number of <u><strong>other</u></strong> construction <u><strong>materials</u></strong> such as metals. The most recent BMW automobile model uses only carbon fibers rather than metals. <u><strong>It is</u></strong> also <u><strong>possible <mark>to combine CO2 to produce renewable gasoline</mark>,</u></strong> namely gasoline produced from air and water. CO2 can be separated from air and hydrogen separated from water, and their combination is a well-known industrial process to produce gasoline. Is this therefore too expensive? There are <u><strong>new tech</u></strong>nologies <u><strong>using algae</u></strong> that <u><strong><mark>make synthetic fuel commercially feasible</mark> at competitive rates</u></strong>. Other policies would involve combining air capture with solar thermal electricity using the residual solar thermal heat to drive the carbon capture process. This can make a solar plant more productive and efficient so it can out-compete coal as a source of energy. In summary, <u><strong>the <mark>blueprint </mark>offered here <mark>is a private/public approach</u></strong>, <u><strong>based on new industrial tech</u></strong></mark>nology and <u><strong><mark>financial markets</u></strong>, <u><strong></mark>self-funded</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>and using profitable greenmarkets</u></strong></mark>, with securities that utilize carbon credits as the “underlying” asset, based on the KP CDM, as well as new markets for biodiversity and water providing abundant clean energy to stave off impending and actual energy crisis in developing nations, fostering mutually beneficial cooperation for industrial and developing nations. The blueprint proposed provides the two sides of the coin, equity and efficiency, and can assign a critical role for women as stewards for human survival and sustainable development. My vision is <u><strong>a carbon negative economy</u></strong> that <u><strong>represents green capitalism</u></strong> in <u><strong>resolving</u></strong> the Global Climate negotiations and <u><strong>the North–South Divide</u></strong>. Carbon negative power plants and capture of CO2 from air and ensure a clean atmosphere together innovation and more jobs and exports: the more you produce and create jobs the cleaner becomes the atmosphere. In practice, <u><strong>Green Capitalism means economic growth that is harmonious with the Earth resources</u></strong>. </p> | null | 1NC | Climate | 32,641 | 320 | 39,274 | ./documents/hsld21/ImmaculateHeart/La/Immaculate%20Heart-Lay-Neg-Peninsula%20Invitational-Round4.docx | 889,970 | N | Peninsula Invitational | 4 | Sage Hill JS | Krishna Akshantala | AC- No privatization Debris Cap bad
NC- Heg Good (needs private sector) Cap Good
1AR
2NR
2AR | hsld21/ImmaculateHeart/La/Immaculate%20Heart-Lay-Neg-Peninsula%20Invitational-Round4.docx | null | 74,800 | EmLa | Immaculate Heart EmLa | null | Em..... | La..... | null | null | 25,023 | ImmaculateHeart | Immaculate Heart | CA | null | 1,029 | hsld21 | HS LD 2021-22 | 2,021 | ld | hs | 1 |
3,047,321 | Saudi prolif goes nuclear | Edelman ‘11 | Edelman ‘11 | (Jan/Feb, Distinguished Fellow at the Center for Strategic and Budgetary Assessments & Former U.S. Undersecretary of Defense for Policy, Foreign Affairs, http://www.foreignaffairs.com/articles/67162/eric-s-edelman-andrew-f-krepinevich-jr-and-evan-braden-montgomer/the-dangers-of-a-nuclear-iran)
The Saudi government is already pursuing a nuclear power capability, which could be the first step along a slow road to nuclear weapons development. There are still rumors that Riyadh and Islamabad have had discussions involving nuclear weapons Pakistan could sell operational nuclear weapons and delivery systems to Saudi Arabia, or it could provide the Saudis with the infrastructure to produce nuclear weapons themselves within a matter of The Islamabad option raises a host of difficult issues, perhaps the most worrisome being how India would respond. Would it target Pakistan’s weapons in Saudi Arabia with its own conventional or nuclear weapons? any decision by the Saudi government to seek out nuclear weapons, by whatever means, would be highly destabilizing. It would increase the incentives of other nations in the Middle East to pursue nuclear weapons of their own. And it could increase their ability to do so by eroding the remaining barriers to nuclear proliferation: each additional state that acquires nuclear weapons weakens the nonproliferation regime, even if its particular method of acquisition only circumvents, rather than violates, the NPT. Were Saudi Arabia to acquire nuclear weapons, the Middle East would count three nuclear-armed states, and perhaps more before long. the interaction among three or more nuclear-armed powers would be more prone to miscalculation and escalation Multi- polar systems are generally considered to be less stable than bipolar systems because coalitions can shift quickly, upsetting the balance of power and creating incentives for an attack. More important, emerging nuclear powers in the Middle East might not take the costly steps necessary to preserve regional stability and avoid a nuclear exchange. emerging nuclear powers might not invest in expensive but survivable capabilities such as hardened missile silos or submarine- based nuclear forces. Given this likely vulnerability, the close proximity of states in the Middle East, and the very short flight times of ballistic missiles in the region, any new nuclear powers might be compelled to “launch on warning” of an attack , a nuclear attack might be unattributable or attributed incorrectly this uncertainty, when combined with the pressure to respond quickly, would create a significant risk that it would retaliate against the wrong party, potentially triggering a regional nuclear war. there is no guarantee that emerging nuclear powers would be willing or able to implement these measures, creating a significant risk that their governments might lose control over the weapons or nuclear material and that nonstate actors could gain access to these items The ability of existing nuclear powers and other technically advanced military states to shape the emerging nuclear competition in the Middle East could lead to a new Great Game, with unpredictable consequences. | any decision by Saudi to seek out nuclear weapons would be highly destabilizing. It would increase the incentives of other nations to pursue nuclear weapons three or more nuclear powers would be prone to miscalculation and escalation Multi- polar systems less stable creating incentives for an attack. emerging nuclear powers might not avoid nuclear exchange. new powers might “launch on warning” uncertainty would trigger a regional nuclear war | (Jan/Feb, Distinguished Fellow at the Center for Strategic and Budgetary Assessments & Former U.S. Undersecretary of Defense for Policy, Foreign Affairs, http://www.foreignaffairs.com/articles/67162/eric-s-edelman-andrew-f-krepinevich-jr-and-evan-braden-montgomer/the-dangers-of-a-nuclear-iran)
There is, however, at least one state that could receive significant outside support: Saudi Arabia. And if it did, proliferation could accelerate throughout the region. Iran and Saudi Arabia have long been geopolitical and ideological rivals. Riyadh would face tremendous pressure to respond in some form to a nuclear-armed Iran, not only to deter Iranian coercion and subversion but also to preserve its sense that Saudi Arabia is the leading nation in the Muslim world. The Saudi government is already pursuing a nuclear power capability, which could be the first step along a slow road to nuclear weapons development. And concerns persist that it might be able to accelerate its progress by exploiting its close ties to Pakistan. During the 1980s, in response to the use of missiles during the Iran-Iraq War and their growing proliferation throughout the region, Saudi Arabia acquired several dozen css-2 intermediate-range ballistic missiles from China. The Pakistani government reportedly brokered the deal, and it may have also offered to sell Saudi Arabia nuclear warheads for the css-2s, which are not accurate enough to deliver conventional warheads effectively. There are still rumors that Riyadh and Islamabad have had discussions involving nuclear weapons, nuclear technology, or security guarantees. This “Islamabad option” could develop in one of several different ways. Pakistan could sell operational nuclear weapons and delivery systems to Saudi Arabia, or it could provide the Saudis with the infrastructure, material, and technical support they need to produce nuclear weapons themselves within a matter of years, as opposed to a decade or longer. Not only has Pakistan provided such support in the past, but it is currently building two more heavy-water reactors for plutonium production and a second chemical reprocessing facility to extract plutonium from spent nuclear fuel. In other words, it might accumulate more fissile material than it needs to maintain even a substantially expanded arsenal of its own. Alternatively, Pakistan might offer an extended deterrent guarantee to Saudi Arabia and deploy nuclear weapons, delivery systems, and troops on Saudi territory, a practice that the United States has employed for decades with its allies. This arrangement could be particularly appealing to both Saudi Arabia and Pakistan. It would allow the Saudis to argue that they are not violating the NPT since they would not be acquiring their own nuclear weapons. And an extended deterrent from Pakistan might be preferable to one from the United States because stationing foreign Muslim forces on Saudi territory would not trigger the kind of popular opposition that would accompany the deployment of U.S. troops. Pakistan, for its part, would gain financial benefits and international clout by deploying nuclear weapons in Saudi Arabia, as well as strategic depth against its chief rival, India. The Islamabad option raises a host of difficult issues, perhaps the most worrisome being how India would respond. Would it target Pakistan’s weapons in Saudi Arabia with its own conventional or nuclear weapons? How would this expanded nuclear competition influence stability during a crisis in either the Middle East or South Asia? Regardless of India’s reaction, any decision by the Saudi government to seek out nuclear weapons, by whatever means, would be highly destabilizing. It would increase the incentives of other nations in the Middle East to pursue nuclear weapons of their own. And it could increase their ability to do so by eroding the remaining barriers to nuclear proliferation: each additional state that acquires nuclear weapons weakens the nonproliferation regime, even if its particular method of acquisition only circumvents, rather than violates, the NPT. Were Saudi Arabia to acquire nuclear weapons, the Middle East would count three nuclear-armed states, and perhaps more before long. It is unclear how such an n-player competition would unfold because most analyses of nuclear deterrence are based on the U.S.- Soviet rivalry during the Cold War. It seems likely, however, that the interaction among three or more nuclear-armed powers would be more prone to miscalculation and escalation than a bipolar competition. During the Cold War, the United States and the Soviet Union only needed to concern themselves with an attack from the other. Multi- polar systems are generally considered to be less stable than bipolar systems because coalitions can shift quickly, upsetting the balance of power and creating incentives for an attack. More important, emerging nuclear powers in the Middle East might not take the costly steps necessary to preserve regional stability and avoid a nuclear exchange. For nuclear-armed states, the bedrock of deterrence is the knowledge that each side has a secure second-strike capability, so that no state can launch an attack with the expectation that it can wipe out its opponents’ forces and avoid a devastating retaliation. However, emerging nuclear powers might not invest in expensive but survivable capabilities such as hardened missile silos or submarine- based nuclear forces. Given this likely vulnerability, the close proximity of states in the Middle East, and the very short flight times of ballistic missiles in the region, any new nuclear powers might be compelled to “launch on warning” of an attack or even, during a crisis, to use their nuclear forces preemptively. Their governments might also delegate launch authority to lower-level commanders, heightening the possibility of miscalculation and escalation. Moreover, if early warning systems were not integrated into robust command-and-control systems, the risk of an unauthorized or accidental launch would increase further still. And without sophisticated early warning systems, a nuclear attack might be unattributable or attributed incorrectly. That is, assuming that the leadership of a targeted state survived a first strike, it might not be able to accurately determine which nation was responsible. And this uncertainty, when combined with the pressure to respond quickly, would create a significant risk that it would retaliate against the wrong party, potentially triggering a regional nuclear war. Most existing nuclear powers have taken steps to protect their nuclear weapons from unauthorized use: from closely screening key personnel to developing technical safety measures, such as permissive action links, which require special codes before the weapons can be armed. Yet there is no guarantee that emerging nuclear powers would be willing or able to implement these measures, creating a significant risk that their governments might lose control over the weapons or nuclear material and that nonstate actors could gain access to these items. Some states might seek to mitigate threats to their nuclear arsenals; for instance, they might hide their weapons. In that case, however, a single intelligence compromise could leave their weapons vulnerable to attack or theft. Meanwhile, states outside the Middle East could also be a source of instability. Throughout the Cold War, the United States and the Soviet Union were engaged in a nuclear arms race that other nations were essentially powerless to influence. In a multipolar nuclear Middle East, other nuclear powers and states with advanced military technology could influence—for good or ill—the military competition within the region by selling or transferring technologies that most local actors lack today: solid-fuel rocket motors, enhanced missile-guidance systems, war- head miniaturization technology, early warning systems, air and missile defenses. Such transfers could stabilize a fragile nuclear balance if the emerging nuclear powers acquired more survivable arsenals as a result. But they could also be highly destabilizing. If, for example, an outside power sought to curry favor with a potential client state or gain influence with a prospective ally, it might share with that state the technology it needed to enhance the accuracy of its missiles and thereby increase its ability to launch a disarming first strike against any adversary. The ability of existing nuclear powers and other technically advanced military states to shape the emerging nuclear competition in the Middle East could lead to a new Great Game, with unpredictable consequences. | 8,675 | <h4><strong>Saudi prolif goes nuclear</h4><p>Edelman ‘11</p><p><u></strong>(Jan/Feb, Distinguished Fellow at the Center for Strategic and Budgetary Assessments & Former U.S. Undersecretary of Defense for Policy, Foreign Affairs, http://www.foreignaffairs.com/articles/67162/eric-s-edelman-andrew-f-krepinevich-jr-and-evan-braden-montgomer/the-dangers-of-a-nuclear-iran)</p><p></u>There is, however, at least one state that could receive significant outside support: Saudi Arabia. And if it did, proliferation could accelerate throughout the region. Iran and Saudi Arabia have long been geopolitical and ideological rivals. Riyadh would face tremendous pressure to respond in some form to a nuclear-armed Iran, not only to deter Iranian coercion and subversion but also to preserve its sense that Saudi Arabia is the leading nation in the Muslim world. <u>The Saudi government is already pursuing a nuclear power capability, which could be the first step along a slow road to nuclear weapons development.</u> And concerns persist that it might be able to accelerate its progress by exploiting its close ties to Pakistan. During the 1980s, in response to the use of missiles during the Iran-Iraq War and their growing proliferation throughout the region, Saudi Arabia acquired several dozen css-2 intermediate-range ballistic missiles from China. The Pakistani government reportedly brokered the deal, and it may have also offered to sell Saudi Arabia nuclear warheads for the css-2s, which are not accurate enough to deliver conventional warheads effectively. <u>There are still rumors that Riyadh and Islamabad have had discussions involving nuclear weapons</u>, nuclear technology, or security guarantees. This “Islamabad option” could develop in one of several different ways. <u>Pakistan could sell operational nuclear weapons and delivery systems to Saudi Arabia, or it could provide the Saudis with the infrastructure</u>, material, and technical support they need <u>to produce nuclear weapons themselves within a matter of</u> years, as opposed to a decade or longer. Not only has Pakistan provided such support in the past, but it is currently building two more heavy-water reactors for plutonium production and a second chemical reprocessing facility to extract plutonium from spent nuclear fuel. In other words, it might accumulate more fissile material than it needs to maintain even a substantially expanded arsenal of its own. Alternatively, Pakistan might offer an extended deterrent guarantee to Saudi Arabia and deploy nuclear weapons, delivery systems, and troops on Saudi territory, a practice that the United States has employed for decades with its allies. This arrangement could be particularly appealing to both Saudi Arabia and Pakistan. It would allow the Saudis to argue that they are not violating the NPT since they would not be acquiring their own nuclear weapons. And an extended deterrent from Pakistan might be preferable to one from the United States because stationing foreign Muslim forces on Saudi territory would not trigger the kind of popular opposition that would accompany the deployment of U.S. troops. Pakistan, for its part, would gain financial benefits and international clout by deploying nuclear weapons in Saudi Arabia, as well as strategic depth against its chief rival, India. <u>The Islamabad option raises a host of difficult issues, perhaps the most worrisome being how India would respond. Would it target Pakistan’s weapons in Saudi Arabia with its own conventional or nuclear weapons?</u> How would this expanded nuclear competition influence stability during a crisis in either the Middle East or South Asia? Regardless of India’s reaction, <u><mark>any decision by</mark> the <mark>Saudi</mark> government <mark>to seek out nuclear weapons</mark>, by whatever means, <mark>would be highly destabilizing. It would increase the incentives of other nations</mark> in the Middle East <mark>to pursue nuclear weapons</mark> of their own. And it could increase their ability to do so by eroding the remaining barriers to nuclear proliferation: each additional state that acquires nuclear weapons weakens the nonproliferation regime, even if its particular method of acquisition only circumvents, rather than violates, the NPT. Were Saudi Arabia to acquire nuclear weapons, the Middle East would count three nuclear-armed states, and perhaps more before long.</u> It is unclear how such an n-player competition would unfold because most analyses of nuclear deterrence are based on the U.S.- Soviet rivalry during the Cold War. It seems likely, however, that <u>the interaction among <mark>three or more nuclear</mark>-armed <mark>powers would be</mark> more <mark>prone to miscalculation and escalation</u></mark> than a bipolar competition. During the Cold War, the United States and the Soviet Union only needed to concern themselves with an attack from the other. <u><mark>Multi- polar systems</mark> are generally considered to be <mark>less stable</mark> than bipolar systems because coalitions can shift quickly, upsetting the balance of power and <mark>creating incentives for an attack.</mark> More important, <mark>emerging nuclear powers</mark> in the Middle East <mark>might not</mark> take the costly steps necessary to preserve regional stability and <mark>avoid</mark> a <mark>nuclear exchange.</mark> </u>For nuclear-armed states, the bedrock of deterrence is the knowledge that each side has a secure second-strike capability, so that no state can launch an attack with the expectation that it can wipe out its opponents’ forces and avoid a devastating retaliation. However, <u>emerging nuclear powers might not invest in expensive but survivable capabilities such as hardened missile silos or submarine- based nuclear forces. Given this likely vulnerability, the close proximity of states in the Middle East, and the very short flight times of ballistic missiles in the region, any <mark>new</mark> nuclear <mark>powers might</mark> be compelled to <mark>“launch on warning”</mark> of an attack </u>or even, during a crisis, to use their nuclear forces preemptively. Their governments might also delegate launch authority to lower-level commanders, heightening the possibility of miscalculation and escalation. Moreover, if early warning systems were not integrated into robust command-and-control systems, the risk of an unauthorized or accidental launch would increase further still. And without sophisticated early warning systems<u>, a nuclear attack might be unattributable or attributed incorrectly</u>. That is, assuming that the leadership of a targeted state survived a first strike, it might not be able to accurately determine which nation was responsible. And <u>this <mark>uncertainty</mark>, when combined with the pressure to respond quickly, <mark>would</mark> create a significant risk that it would retaliate against the wrong party, potentially <mark>trigger</mark>ing <strong><mark>a regional nuclear war</strong></mark>. </u>Most existing nuclear powers have taken steps to protect their nuclear weapons from unauthorized use: from closely screening key personnel to developing technical safety measures, such as permissive action links, which require special codes before the weapons can be armed. Yet <u>there is no guarantee that emerging nuclear powers would be willing or able to implement these measures, creating a significant risk that their governments might lose control over the weapons or nuclear material and that nonstate actors could gain access to these items</u>. Some states might seek to mitigate threats to their nuclear arsenals; for instance, they might hide their weapons. In that case, however, a single intelligence compromise could leave their weapons vulnerable to attack or theft. Meanwhile, states outside the Middle East could also be a source of instability. Throughout the Cold War, the United States and the Soviet Union were engaged in a nuclear arms race that other nations were essentially powerless to influence. In a multipolar nuclear Middle East, other nuclear powers and states with advanced military technology could influence—for good or ill—the military competition within the region by selling or transferring technologies that most local actors lack today: solid-fuel rocket motors, enhanced missile-guidance systems, war- head miniaturization technology, early warning systems, air and missile defenses. Such transfers could stabilize a fragile nuclear balance if the emerging nuclear powers acquired more survivable arsenals as a result. But they could also be highly destabilizing. If, for example, an outside power sought to curry favor with a potential client state or gain influence with a prospective ally, it might share with that state the technology it needed to enhance the accuracy of its missiles and thereby increase its ability to launch a disarming first strike against any adversary. <u>The ability of existing nuclear powers and other technically advanced military states to shape the emerging nuclear competition in the Middle East could lead to a new Great Game, with unpredictable consequences.</p></u> | 1NR | 2020 | Top | 10,927 | 720 | 99,707 | ./documents/ndtceda18/Georgetown/BePi/Georgetown-Bernstein-Piliero-Neg-Navy-Round6.docx | 603,731 | N | Navy | 6 | Michigan PP | Jackie Chen | 1AC Tariffs (New FDI advantage)
1NC T Restrictions - ESR CP - Advantage CP - 2020 DA - Foreign Affairs DA - EU Trade Flex DA - FDI Bad and Trade Authority DA on case
2NC EU Trade Flex DA - ESR CP
1NR 2020 DA
2NR ESR CP - 2020 DA | ndtceda18/Georgetown/BePi/Georgetown-Bernstein-Piliero-Neg-Navy-Round6.docx | null | 51,339 | BePi | Georgetown BePi | null | Da..... | Be..... | Ra..... | Pi..... | 19,183 | Georgetown | Georgetown | null | null | 1,008 | ndtceda18 | NDT/CEDA 2018-19 | 2,018 | cx | college | 2 |
1,983,819 | Econ decline causes war | Mann 14 | Mann 14 (Eric Mann is a special agent with a United States federal agency, with significant domestic and international counterintelligence and counter-terrorism experience. Worked as a special assistant for a U.S. Senator and served as a presidential appointee for the U.S. Congress. He is currently responsible for an internal security and vulnerability assessment program. Bachelors @ University of South Carolina, Graduate degree in Homeland Security @ Georgetown. “AUSTERITY, ECONOMIC DECLINE, AND FINANCIAL WEAPONS OF WAR: A NEW PARADIGM FOR GLOBAL SECURITY,” May 2014, https://jscholarship.library.jhu.edu/bitstream/handle/1774.2/37262/MANN-THESIS-2014.pdf) | economic considerations within states can figure prominently into the calculus for future conflicts security issues with economic or financial underpinnings will transcend classical determinants of war and conflict, and change the manner by which rival states engage in hostile acts toward one another security concerns emanating from economic uncertainty and the inherent vulnerabilities within global financial markets will present new challenges for national security, and provide developing states new asymmetric options for balancing against stronger states. The security areas are likely to mature into global security threats in the immediate future the overlapping security issues associated with economic decline and reduced military spending by the United States will affect allied confidence in America’s security guarantees this outcome could cause regional instability or realignments of strategic partnerships in the Asia-pacific region with ramifications for U.S. national security Rival states and non-state groups may also become emboldened to challenge America’s status The potential risks associated with stolen or loose WMD resulting from poor security, can also pose a threat to U.S. national security financial constraints affect weapons security making weapons vulnerable to theft, and how financial factors can influence WMD proliferation inherent vulnerabilities within the global financial markets will provide terrorists’ organizations and other non-state groups with opportunities to disrupt global finance and perhaps weaken America’s status | econ can figure into calculus for future conflict economic challenges are global security threats economic decline by the U S will affect allied confidence cause regional instability Rival states may challenge America’s status risks associated with stolen WMD can pose a threat financial constraints making weapons vulnerable to theft | The conclusions reached in this thesis demonstrate how economic considerations within states can figure prominently into the calculus for future conflicts. The findings also suggest that security issues with economic or financial underpinnings will transcend classical determinants of war and conflict, and change the manner by which rival states engage in hostile acts toward one another. The research shows that security concerns emanating from economic uncertainty and the inherent vulnerabilities within global financial markets will present new challenges for national security, and provide developing states new asymmetric options for balancing against stronger states. The security areas, identified in the proceeding chapters, are likely to mature into global security threats in the immediate future. As the case study on South Korea suggest, the overlapping security issues associated with economic decline and reduced military spending by the United States will affect allied confidence in America’s security guarantees. The study shows that this outcome could cause regional instability or realignments of strategic partnerships in the Asia-pacific region with ramifications for U.S. national security. Rival states and non-state groups may also become emboldened to challenge America’s status in the unipolar international system. The potential risks associated with stolen or loose WMD, resulting from poor security, can also pose a threat to U.S. national security. The case study on Pakistan, Syria and North Korea show how financial constraints affect weapons security making weapons vulnerable to theft, and how financial factors can influence WMD proliferation by contributing to the motivating factors behind a trusted insider’s decision to sell weapons technology. The inherent vulnerabilities within the global financial markets will provide terrorists’ organizations and other non-state groups, who object to the current international system or distribution of power, with opportunities to disrupt global finance and perhaps weaken America’s status. A more ominous threat originates from states intent on increasing diversification of foreign currency holdings, establishing alternatives to the dollar for international trade, or engaging financial warfare against the United States. | 2,306 | <h4>Econ decline causes war</h4><p><strong>Mann 14</strong> (Eric Mann is a special agent with a United States federal agency, with significant domestic and international counterintelligence and counter-terrorism experience. Worked as a special assistant for a U.S. Senator and served as a presidential appointee for the U.S. Congress. He is currently responsible for an internal security and vulnerability assessment program. Bachelors @ University of South Carolina, Graduate degree in Homeland Security @ Georgetown. “AUSTERITY, ECONOMIC DECLINE, AND FINANCIAL WEAPONS OF WAR: A NEW PARADIGM FOR GLOBAL SECURITY,” May 2014, https://jscholarship.library.jhu.edu/bitstream/handle/1774.2/37262/MANN-THESIS-2014.pdf)</p><p>The conclusions reached in this thesis demonstrate how <u><mark>econ</mark>omic considerations within states <mark>can figure <strong></mark>prominently <mark>into</mark> the <mark>calculus for future conflict</mark>s</u></strong>. The findings also suggest that <u>security issues with economic or financial underpinnings will transcend classical determinants of war and conflict, and change the manner by which rival states engage in hostile acts toward one another</u>. The research shows that <u>security concerns emanating from <mark>economic </mark>uncertainty and the inherent vulnerabilities within global financial markets will present new <mark>challenges</mark> for national security, and provide developing states new asymmetric options for balancing against stronger states.</u> <u>The security areas</u>, identified in the proceeding chapters, <u><mark>are </mark>likely to mature into <strong><mark>global security threats</strong> </mark>in the immediate future</u>. As the case study on South Korea suggest, <u>the overlapping security issues associated with <mark>economic decline</mark> and reduced military spending <mark>by the U</mark>nited <mark>S</mark>tates <mark>will <strong>affect allied confidence</mark> in America’s security guarantees</u></strong>. The study shows that <u>this outcome could <mark>cause <strong>regional</mark> <mark>instability</strong></mark> or realignments of strategic partnerships in the Asia-pacific region with ramifications for U.S. national security</u>. <u><mark>Rival states</mark> and non-state groups <mark>may</mark> also become <strong>emboldened to <mark>challenge America’s status</u></strong></mark> in the unipolar international system. <u>The potential <mark>risks associated with <strong>stolen</mark> or loose <mark>WMD</u></strong></mark>, <u>resulting from poor security, <mark>can</mark> also <mark>pose a threat</mark> to U.S. national security</u>. The case study on Pakistan, Syria and North Korea show how <u><mark>financial constraints </mark>affect weapons security <mark>making weapons vulnerable to theft</mark>, and how financial factors can influence WMD proliferation</u> by contributing to the motivating factors behind a trusted insider’s decision to sell weapons technology. The <u>inherent vulnerabilities within the global financial markets will provide terrorists’ organizations and other non-state groups</u>, who object to the current international system or distribution of power, <u>with opportunities to disrupt global finance and perhaps weaken America’s status</u>. A more ominous threat originates from states intent on increasing diversification of foreign currency holdings, establishing alternatives to the dollar for international trade, or engaging financial warfare against the United States.</p> | Off case | 5 | null | 1,375 | 1,161 | 58,485 | ./documents/hspolicy20/NilesWest/ShKo/Niles%20West-Shehzad-Koeberl-Neg-Dowling-Round1.docx | 736,219 | N | Dowling | 1 | Glenbrook North KL | Eleni, Orfanos | 1ac- cfaa
1nc- states fed stimulus k t
2nc- k and case
1nr- fed da
2nr- k and case | hspolicy20/NilesWest/ShKo/Niles%20West-Shehzad-Koeberl-Neg-Dowling-Round1.docx | null | 62,758 | ShKo | Niles West ShKo | null | Hi..... | Sh..... | Mi..... | Ko..... | 21,737 | NilesWest | Niles West | IL | null | 1,019 | hspolicy20 | HS Policy 2020-21 | 2,020 | cx | hs | 2 |
4,604,343 | First, Dutch disease – foreign funds cause local inflation that devastates export sectors | Martin, 17 - | Martin, 17 - Professor of Agricultural and Resource Economics at the University of California-Davis (Philip, Merchants of Labor: Recruiters and International Labor Migration, Oxford University Press, p. 124-126)//RCU | remittances
have contributed little to economic growth in remittance-receiving economies the most persuasive evidence is the lack of a single example of a remittances success story
the dramatic increase in global remittances and remittance flows may reflect better measurement rather than more money flowing to developing countries outmigration and remittances can keep entrenched elites in power and slow overall economic growth if the migration escape valve reduces pressure on governments to make the policy changes necessary for faster growth
if remittances raise the value of the currencies of migrant-sending countries, exports can fall, displacing workers in export-oriented sectors and choking off their growth. This is an example of Dutch disease Many migrants are from countries with small export sectors, and the remittances that benefit migrant families may simultaneously hurt other families whose jobs depend on exporting manufacturing and agricultural goods that become more expensive as remittances drive up the value of the local currency
A shrinking export sector can mean less tax revenue and more demand for government services | remittances
have contributed little to economic growth the most persuasive evidence is the lack of a single example of a success story
remittances raise the value of the currencies of sending countries, exports fall, displacing workers in export sectors and choking growth. This is an example of Dutch disease Many migrants are from countries with small export sectors, and the remittances that benefit migrant families may hurt other families whose jobs depend on exporting
A shrinking export sector can mean less tax revenue and more demand for government services | Remittances can improve the lives of families receiving them, but may not speed the development of migrant-sending countries. An International Monetary Fund (IMF) paper concluded that remittances
have contributed little to economic growth in remittance-receiving economies... the most persuasive evidence in support of this finding is the lack of a single example of a remittances success story: a country in which remittances-led growth contributed significantly to its development... no nation can credibly claim that remittances have funded or catalyzed significant economic development. (Barajas et al., 2009)
There are several reasons for this pessimism about remittances transforming economies from poor to rich. The first is simple: the dramatic increase in global remittances and remittance flows may reflect better measurement rather than more money flowing to developing countries. Second, outmigration and remittances can keep entrenched elites in power and slow overall economic growth if the migration escape valve reduces pressure on governments to make the policy changes necessary for faster growth. The vice-president of Moldova, the poorest country in Eastern Europe, was quoted in 2004 as saying that if young and ambitious Moldovans could not migrate to Russia and Eastern Europe to work, they may protest at home and force a then-communist dominated government to change its policies. Talani (2014) makes a similar point about vicious circles in North Africa, where outmigration of the most able who cannot get ahead at home allows corrupt elites to remain in power and block the fundamental reforms necessary for sustainable growth.
Remittances can also be a two-edged sword in narrower economic terms. Countries such as Moldova that send workers abroad need to develop other export industries to keep workers at home in the future. However, if remittances raise the value of the currencies of migrant-sending countries, exports can fall, displacing workers in export-oriented sectors and choking off their growth. This is an example of Dutch disease: the rising value of the Dutch guilder after natural gas was discovered in the North Sea in the 1950s shrank the manufacturing sector and eliminated factory jobs. Many migrants are from countries with small export sectors, and the remittances that benefit migrant families may simultaneously hurt other families whose jobs depend on exporting manufacturing and agricultural goods that become more expensive as remittances drive up the value of the local currency (Acosta et al., 2009; Atoyan etal., 2016: 21).
A shrinking export sector and a higher share of the young and elderly among residents who depend on government programs can mean less tax revenue and more demand for government services. Governments must finance services for the elderly and children, and if they do so by raising taxes on ever fewer workers and their employers because many prime-aged workers are abroad, the economy's ability to produce goods and services competitively is reduced.
When a developing country produces workers for richer countries, the result can be a virtuous circle in which sending workers abroad in one period leads to stay-at-home development later, or a vicious circle in which villages turn into nurseries for children and nursing homes for the elderly that depend on external lifelines. There are examples of both virtuous and vicious circles between migration and development, suggesting skepticism when confronting assertions that migration speeds or slows development. | 3,545 | <h4>First, Dutch disease<strong> – foreign funds cause local inflation that devastates export sectors</h4><p>Martin, 17 - </strong>Professor of Agricultural and Resource Economics at the University of California-Davis (Philip, Merchants of Labor: Recruiters and International Labor Migration, Oxford University Press, p. 124-126)//RCU</p><p>Remittances can improve the lives of families receiving them, but may not speed the development of migrant-sending countries. An International Monetary Fund (IMF) paper concluded that <u><mark>remittances</p><p>have contributed little to economic growth</mark> in remittance-receiving economies</u>... <u><mark>the most persuasive evidence</u></mark> in support of this finding <u><mark>is the lack of a single example of a</mark> remittances <mark>success story</u></mark>: a country in which remittances-led growth contributed significantly to its development... no nation can credibly claim that remittances have funded or catalyzed significant economic development. (Barajas et al., 2009)</p><p>There are several reasons for this pessimism about remittances transforming economies from poor to rich. The first is simple: <u>the dramatic increase in global remittances and remittance flows may reflect better measurement rather than more money flowing to developing countries</u>. Second, <u>outmigration and remittances can keep entrenched elites in power and slow overall economic growth if the migration escape valve reduces pressure on governments to make the policy changes necessary for faster growth</u>. The vice-president of Moldova, the poorest country in Eastern Europe, was quoted in 2004 as saying that if young and ambitious Moldovans could not migrate to Russia and Eastern Europe to work, they may protest at home and force a then-communist dominated government to change its policies. Talani (2014) makes a similar point about vicious circles in North Africa, where outmigration of the most able who cannot get ahead at home allows corrupt elites to remain in power and block the fundamental reforms necessary for sustainable growth.</p><p>Remittances can also be a two-edged sword in narrower economic terms. Countries such as Moldova that send workers abroad need to develop other export industries to keep workers at home in the future. However, <u>if <mark>remittances raise the value of the currencies of</mark> migrant-<mark>sending countries, exports</mark> can <mark>fall, displacing workers in export</mark>-oriented <mark>sectors and choking</mark> off their <mark>growth. This is an example of Dutch disease</u></mark>: the rising value of the Dutch guilder after natural gas was discovered in the North Sea in the 1950s shrank the manufacturing sector and eliminated factory jobs. <u><mark>Many migrants are from countries with small export sectors, and the remittances that benefit migrant families may</mark> simultaneously <mark>hurt other families whose jobs depend on exporting</mark> manufacturing and agricultural goods that become more expensive as remittances drive up the value of the local currency</u> (Acosta et al., 2009; Atoyan etal., 2016: 21).</p><p><u><mark>A shrinking export sector</u></mark> and a higher share of the young and elderly among residents who depend on government programs <u><mark>can mean less tax revenue and more demand for government services</u></mark>. Governments must finance services for the elderly and children, and if they do so by raising taxes on ever fewer workers and their employers because many prime-aged workers are abroad, the economy's ability to produce goods and services competitively is reduced.</p><p>When a developing country produces workers for richer countries, the result can be a virtuous circle in which sending workers abroad in one period leads to stay-at-home development later, or a vicious circle in which villages turn into nurseries for children and nursing homes for the elderly that depend on external lifelines. There are examples of both virtuous and vicious circles between migration and development, suggesting skepticism when confronting assertions that migration speeds or slows development.</p> | Case | OFF | 1NC – Turn - Remittances | 61,589 | 112 | 152,646 | ./documents/hsld22/StAgnesAcademy/ElHu/StAgnesAcademy-ElHu-Neg-Strake-Jesuit-Round-5.docx | 956,411 | N | Strake Jesuit | 5 | Dulles TV | Dixon | 1AC Economy Crime
1NC Populism DA Cap K Case
1AR Same
2NR Populism DA Case
2AR same | hsld22/StAgnesAcademy/ElHu/StAgnesAcademy-ElHu-Neg-Strake-Jesuit-Round-5.docx | 2022-12-18 06:12:59 | 79,345 | ElHu | St Agnes Academy ElHu | null | El..... | Hu..... | null | null | 26,587 | StAgnesAcademy | St Agnes Academy | TX | 8,005 | 2,003 | hsld22 | HS LD 2022-23 | 2,022 | ld | hs | 1 |
3,957,122 | Negating an obligation requires proving a prohibition – means permissibility affirms because negating is prohibiting the aff action. | Timmons 02, [Mark Timmons. “Moral Theory: An Introduction.” Pg. 8. 2002.] Recut SJCP//JG | Timmons 02, [Mark Timmons. “Moral Theory: An Introduction.” Pg. 8. 2002.] Recut SJCP//JG | When the term is used broadly, right action is the opposite of wrong action: an action is right, in the broad sense of the term, when it is not wrong to say of someone that what she did was right conveys morally in the clear alright not wrong. Since actions that are not wrong include the categories of both the obligatory and the optional, talk of right action (in the broad sense) covers both of these categories. | right action is opposite of wrong to say did right conveys morally alright not wrong not wrong include obligatory and optional right action covers both | When the term is used broadly, right action is the opposite of wrong action: an action is right, in the broad sense of the term, when it is not wrong. For instance, to say of someone that what she did was right conveys the idea that her act was morally in the clear---that it was alright for her to do, that what she did was not wrong. Since actions that are not wrong include the categories of both the obligatory and the optional, talk of right action (in the broad sense) covers both of these categories. | 507 | <h4>Negating an obligation requires proving a prohibition – means permissibility affirms because negating is prohibiting the aff action.</h4><p><strong>Timmons 02, <u>[Mark Timmons. “Moral Theory: An Introduction.” Pg. 8. 2002.] Recut SJCP//JG</p><p>When the term is used broadly, <mark>right action is</mark> the <mark>opposite of wrong</mark> action: an action is right, in the broad sense of the term, when it is not wrong</u></strong>. For instance, <u><strong><mark>to say</mark> of someone that what she <mark>did</mark> was <mark>right</mark> <mark>conveys</u></strong></mark> the idea that her act was <u><strong><mark>morally</mark> in the clear</u></strong>---that it was <u><strong><mark>alright</u></strong></mark> for her to do, that what she did was <u><strong><mark>not wrong</mark>. Since actions that are <mark>not wrong include</mark> the categories of both the <mark>obligatory and</mark> the <mark>optional</mark>, talk of <mark>right action</mark> (in the broad sense) <mark>covers both</mark> of these categories.</p></u></strong> | null | UV | Adv 2: Virtue | 384,488 | 129 | 133,283 | ./documents/hsld20/Lexington/Th/Lexington-The-Aff-Blake-Round1.docx | 865,190 | A | John Edie Holiday Debates Hosted by the Blake School | 1 | Torrey Pines JS | Rachel Overstreet | AC - Virtue Ethics
NC - Set Col Spikes bad Case
1AR - All
2N - Spikes bad Set col
2AR - Case K | hsld20/Lexington/Th/Lexington-The-Aff-Blake-Round1.docx | null | 73,325 | AnTh | Lexington AnTh | null | An..... | Th..... | null | null | 24,591 | Lexington | Lexington | MA | null | 1,028 | hsld20 | HS LD 2020-21 | 2,020 | ld | hs | 1 |
2,457,487 | Orbital debris prevents the formation of the African Space Agency. | Ngcofe et al. ’16 | L.Ngcofe, Chief Directorate: National Geo-Spatial Information, Department of Land Reform, South Africa, et al. K. Gottschalk, Department of Political Studies, University of the Western Cape, Cape Town S.Madlanga, 3 National Research Foundation: Hartebeesthoek Radio Astronomy Observatory ’16, “THE SPACE RUSH - THE COST OF BEING A LATE STARTER FROM AN AFRICAN PERSPECTIVE,”African Association of Remote Sensing of the Environment, http://www.africanremotesensing.org/page-1524987/4136883 | The costs of being a late starter in space include the exponentially accumulating space debris
The current discussions in international forums about mitigating the creation of new space debris, has not yet gone to the next stage to discuss financial liability for collisions caused by such debris.
Access to development of space technology has historically been a key determinant of a country’s wealth, power, influence, status and prestige there are recent strides documented in literature showing Africa’s interest and participation in space exploration
The current major threat is the risk pertaining to space debris relative to the cost of launching satellites in space.
The vulnerability of space asserts interference and disruption held by the USA security space community, that space is a contested domain. Whoever seizes space has a powerful advantage both for social and economic enhancemen The development of micro satellite technology and multiple constellations is now making space technology more affordable for developing countries to utilise the space environment debate about the African Space Agency, which will cater for participation in space activities for Africa’s needs, is gaining momentum. there would be no major risk for space endeavours from current operational satellites only if it were not for space debris.
Space debris can, lead to collisions and loss of important satellites, which has tremendous cost effects for Africa’s participation in space activities. Losing a satellite in-orbit due to space debris is no longer hypothetical, but rather a harsh reality and is likely to increase with years to come | discussion has not yet gone to discuss financial liability for collisions caused by debris
there are recent strides in Africa’s interest in space exploration
The major threat is the risk pertaining to space debris relative to the cost of launching satellites in space
development of micro sat tech is making space tech more affordable for developing countries debate about the African Space Agency is gaining momentum there would be no major risk for space endeavours only if it were not for space debris
Space debris can lead to loss of important satellites, which has tremendous cost effects for Africa’s participation in space | Abstract
The costs of Africa being a late starter in space include the exponentially accumulating space debris. This threat to space assets is worse in low earth orbit (LEO), where it has already destroyed an Irridium operational US comsat.
The current discussions in international forums about mitigating the creation of new space debris, has not yet gone to the next stage to discuss financial liability for collisions caused by such debris. Late starters in space need to table the responsibility of the historic space powers to seek ways to remove their cumulative debris from orbit, and finance this.
Introduction
The ability to observe the Earth from space has enhanced accurate-up-to-date environmental monitoring, thus overcoming some of the environmental challenges experienced by humankind. Investment in space activities has endless, long term, benefits including diplomatic relations; technological advancement through collaboration with other countries; improving overall economic activities in the global arena, which in turn vastly contributes towards addressing social ills. Acknowledging this Chung et al., (2010) argues that where ground based systems are limited in frequency, continuity and coverage of important ecosystems, satellites can provide essential earth observation data on a continuous basis and over a range of scales, from local, regional, to global. Access to and the development of space technology has historically been a key determinant of a country’s wealth, power, influence, status and prestige. However, space exploration has been an issue of marginal political interest in Africa, thus leading the continent to be the late starter in space matters. Sharpe (2010) shows Africa as the least active continent with regards to space exploration activities. Aganaba-Jeanty (2013) cites a lack of consistent funding as the greatest barrier of the African space technology development. He argues that according to 2009 to 2012 the countries within Africa represent the lowest spending countries in space exploration when compared to developed and developing countries. Africa as a late starter in space might be seen through Abiodun (2012) words of wisdom starting that “the quality and character of a man’s perceptions as well as his subsequent responses are determined in part by limitations imposed by or opportunities available in his environment. If he is to manifest any real growth and reach his higher potentials, his creativity would need nourishment from his environment”. Currently there are recent strides documented in literature showing Africa’s growing interest and participation in space exploration (Ngcofe et al., 2013; Abiodun, 2012; Wood & Wiegel, 2012; Gottschalk, 2010; Martinez, 2008; Mostert, 2008). It is of this view that this paper attempts to examine the impact of being a late starter on space exploration, particularly looking at the issue of space debris and its potential impact on Africa as a developing space fearing nation.
Space debris
The current major threat of space exploration is the risk pertaining to space debris relative to the cost of launching satellites in space. The need to justify expenditure on space-related endeavours competes with other pressing expenditure needs such as provision of food, clean drinking water, housing, electricity, roads infrastructure and other commercial development. Space debris also known as orbital debris, or space junk, or space waste, is the collection of man-made objects that have exceeded its service life and broken down while in orbit around the earth (Interagency Report on Orbital Debris 2005; UN, 1999; Sénéchal, 2007; Colliot, 2002; Glassman, 2009; Griffiths, 2010). These include everything from spent rocket stages, old satellites, and fragments from disintegration erosion and collision. Space debris has vastly increased since the beginning of space travel in 1957 thus leading to orbit congestion (Colliot, 2012; Figure 2). According to NASA (2013), there are 500 000 pieces of debris tracked in orbit on Earth.
Collision at orbital velocity can be extremely dangerous to functioning satellites and space manned missions. Sénéchal (2007) argues that at orbital velocity of more than 28000 km/h, an object as small as 1 cm in diameter has enough kinetic energy to produce significant impact damage, to partially or completely destruct an operational satellite. While an object of 1mm size can cause surface pitting and erosion, with larger objects of about 10 cm totally destroying operational satellites, and may even kill space explorers. According to the Kessler Syndrome space debris model, as the number of debris object increases, collisions become more likely to occur thus creating yet more debris (Griffiths, 2010; Colliot, 2012; Durrieu & Nelson, 2013). This is an immense concern, which threatens safety of future space explorations. Though space is a large environment, satellites are actually concentrated in a few orbits that are currently optimal, namely:
Low Earth Orbit (LEO) – this is the altitude from 160 km to 2000 km above the earth’s surface. LEO is largely used for earth monitoring, military surveillance, and communication satellites, especially around 350 km.
Medium Earth Orbit (MEO) – this is an area from 2000 km to 35 000 km and is mainly used by navigation satellites such as global position system (GPS) networks at around 20 000 km.
Geostationary Orbit (GEO) – this is the belt at 36 000 km and is optimal for communication satellites. However, Griffiths (2010) argues that it is more expensive to launch satellites to this orbit. Hence, many communication satellites are placed at LEO.
High Earth Orbit (HEO) – This is the area above 36 000 km, and used almost only by satellites researching the magnetosphere or other solar-terrestrial physics.
LEO is regarded as the major used space orbit environment and therefore has a larger record of space debris than any other orbit. There has been four accidental collision events up-to-date (Durrieu and Nelson 2003), with a recent collision incident occurring in 2009 where a United States communication satellite collided with a defunct Russian satellite (Glassman, 2009; Griffiths, 2010; Smitham, 2010). These satellites collided at a speed of over 40 000 km/h, causing complete destruction of both satellites. Thus resulting in around 1400 recorded debris objects (Glassman, 2009; Griffiths, 2010; Smitham, 2010). The available computer models based on observation of debris used to predict future growth of the debris population and probability of collision with satellites under different assumptions reveal that in the next 40 years, collisions with objects larger than 10 cm in LEO are expected to occur on average every 5 years (Griffiths, 2010). This statistics coincide with Sénéchal (2007); Williamson (2003); Liou and Johnson (1996) who argued that in LEO the spatial density of objects is above critical point and the continuation of debris in this orbit may render it inaccessible in the future.
Space availability
The vulnerability of space asserts interference and disruption, led to the view, held by the USA security space community, that space is a contested domain. Whoever seizes space has a powerful advantage both for social and economic enhancement together with military applications (Sadeh, 2009). Space asserts provide a persistent view of the earth and offer ability of real or near real time global collection and dissemination of crucial information. Although, recently, there have been vast strides by Africa within the space arena, the continent still lags behind in space matters. Out of 53 countries in Africa, only four countries (Algeria, Egypt, Nigeria and South Africa) have successfully participated in space activities, through the development of their own space agencies which led to launching of their own satellites in space. The development of micro satellite technology and multiple constellations is now making space technology more affordable for developing countries to utilise the space environment (Durrieu & Nelson, 2013). Thus debate about the African Space Agency, which will cater for participation in space activities for Africa’s needs, is gaining momentum. Currently, Africa has an inspiring mission to the moon (http://africa2moon.developspacesa.org). With the vast interest in space activities by the African continent, one wonders, is there still space in space? Rex (1998) on his paper seeking to answer ‘will space run out of space’. He argues that there would be no major risk for space endeavours from current operational satellites only if it were not for space debris. The issue of space availability in space has been, and is still a major area of concern, more especially for Africa. Since the initial space exploration, the United Nations Committee on the Peaceful Uses of Outer Space (UNCOPOUS) was established in 1959 in order to safeguard the use of space and promote space sustainability. This resulted in five UN treaties on Outer Space (http://www.oosa.unvienna.org/oosa/COPUOS/copuos.html) namely:
Outer Space Treaty (1967) - This treaty promotes the international cooperation in the exploration and use of space, however, prohibits the usage of space for any nuclear weapons and / or any kind of weapons of mass destruction. It clearly emphasises that no state can claim sovereignty of or occupy outer space, the moon or any other Celestial Body. This treaty further deals with liability and states responsibility as to inform the UN secretary general and the international scientific community of the nature, conduct, location and results of their activities in outer space.
Rescue Agreement Treaty (1968) - This agreement deals with the rescue of astronauts, the return of astronauts and the return of objects launched into outer space. This agreement has a legal framework for emergency assistance of astronauts and the notification of launching of any space objects which has to return to earth and express who should be responsible for all the cost incurred for such a particular mission.
Liability Convention (1972) - This convention is a pact of international liability for damage caused by space objects. It imposes an international and absolute liability on a launching state, or states as well as on those states who are members of inter-governmental organisations, for any damage caused by their objects. Launching state is defined as the state which launches or procures the launching of a space object or from whose territory or facility a space object is launched, irrespective of the success or not of the launch. Damage includes the loss of life, personal injury or any other impairment or health or loss of damage to property of state or of persons, natural or juridical or property of international, intergovernmental organisations. This also applies to any damage caused by a space object on the surface of the earth or to an aircraft flight.
Registration Convention Treaty (1974) - The treaty obliges states to register all space objects in a register, which is maintained by the UN secretary general since 1962.
Moon Treaty (1979) - The treaty declares that the moon is a global common for all humankind and is not subject to national appropriation and occupation. It further stresses that no private ownership is allowed but all state parties have the right to exploration and use of the moon. In practice, this treaty has no force, because none of the space powers who engage in lunar exploration have ratified it: USA, Russia, China and India.
Although, these treaties exist there has been non-compliance by those leading space faring countries. Since the 1960s, the United States and Russia have conducted dozens of anti-satellite (ASAT) test missions in space, which resulted in most of orbital debris experienced even today (Weeden, 2013). Most recently China has performed an ASAT mission against its aging FY-1C weather satellite at 855 km altitude on the 11/01/2007. It launched a missile, which destroyed the satellite, resulting in 3000 pieces of debris larger than 10 cm in size (Glassman, 2009; Weeden, 2013). This event was further followed by the United States ASAT in 21/02/2008, firing a missile that destroyed one of its military satellites at around 250 km altitude. The US ascertained that the satellite was uncontrollably descending into the atmosphere with nearly fully fuelled tank of toxic hydrazine. Furthermore, its altitude was low enough to ensure swift re-entry of all the resulting space debris, and so, harmless to the space environment. The US delegate fully briefed the UN COPUOS unlike the Chinese. The outcome by the US in destroying its satellite is applaudable. However, ignorance has been shown by the former President George W. Bush when asked what would the people say about the mission? He said “I don’t care what people will say. We’re doing it for the right reason, and it’s transparent” (Oberg, 2008). These clearly are signs of bullying with regard to space matters by space powers with advanced space technologies.
Conclusion
The act of destroying a satellite can damage the space environment by creating dangerous amounts of space debris. Space debris can, therefore, lead to collisions and loss of important satellites, which has tremendous cost effects for Africa’s participation in space activities. Losing a satellite in-orbit due to space debris is no longer hypothetical, but rather a harsh reality and is likely to increase with years to come (Smitham, 2010). Grego (2014) argues that deliberate space debris creation might result in conflict between space fearing nations with unpredictable and dangerous consequences. Such consequences might trigger an arms race which would further divert the economic and political resources from other pressing issues like food security, climate change, health issues, etc. The need to sustain benefits of space for present and future generations and other countries that have not explored space as yet is vital if we are to obtain continuous benefits from space activities. Glassman (2009) suggests that a number of activities and commitments need to be revitalised. Current space best practice, also termed rules of the road, seek to minimize causing new space debris, through careful revision of both design and operational protocols:
· Separation of satellites from their carrier rocket should no longer result in loose bolts and other metal pieces flying off;
· satellites should have some propulsion capability to initiate collision avoidance manoeuvres;
· at the end of their service life, satellites, especially those in geosynchronous orbit (GSO), should be manoeuvred into a “graveyard orbit” at a different altitude;
· and valves should open to discharge any remaining propellant, to prevent overheating and explosive disruptions. | 14,867 | <h4>Orbital debris prevents the formation of the African Space Agency.</h4><p>L.<strong>Ngcofe</strong>, Chief Directorate: National Geo-Spatial Information, Department of Land Reform, South Africa, <strong>et al.</strong> K. Gottschalk, Department of Political Studies, University of the Western Cape, Cape Town S.Madlanga, 3 National Research Foundation: Hartebeesthoek Radio Astronomy Observatory <strong>’16</strong>, “THE SPACE RUSH - THE COST OF BEING A LATE STARTER FROM AN AFRICAN PERSPECTIVE,”African Association of Remote Sensing of the Environment, http://www.africanremotesensing.org/page-1524987/4136883</p><p>Abstract </p><p><u>The costs of</u> Africa <u>being a late starter in space include the exponentially accumulating space debris</u>. This threat to space assets is worse in low earth orbit (LEO), where it has already destroyed an Irridium operational US comsat.</p><p><u>The current <mark>discussion</mark>s in international forums about mitigating the creation of new space debris, <mark>has not yet gone to </mark>the next stage to <strong><mark>discuss financial liability for collisions caused by</mark> such <mark>debris</strong></mark>.</u> Late starters in space need to table the responsibility of the historic space powers to seek ways to remove their cumulative debris from orbit, and finance this.</p><p>Introduction</p><p>The ability to observe the Earth from space has enhanced accurate-up-to-date environmental monitoring, thus overcoming some of the environmental challenges experienced by humankind. Investment in space activities has endless, long term, benefits including diplomatic relations; technological advancement through collaboration with other countries; improving overall economic activities in the global arena, which in turn vastly contributes towards addressing social ills. Acknowledging this Chung et al., (2010) argues that where ground based systems are limited in frequency, continuity and coverage of important ecosystems, satellites can provide essential earth observation data on a continuous basis and over a range of scales, from local, regional, to global. <u>Access to</u> and the <u>development of space technology has historically been a key determinant of a country’s <strong>wealth</strong>, <strong>power</strong>, <strong>influence</strong>, status and <strong>prestige</u></strong>. However, space exploration has been an issue of marginal political interest in Africa, thus leading the continent to be the late starter in space matters. Sharpe (2010) shows Africa as the least active continent with regards to space exploration activities. Aganaba-Jeanty (2013) cites a lack of consistent funding as the greatest barrier of the African space technology development. He argues that according to 2009 to 2012 the countries within Africa represent the lowest spending countries in space exploration when compared to developed and developing countries. Africa as a late starter in space might be seen through Abiodun (2012) words of wisdom starting that “the quality and character of a man’s perceptions as well as his subsequent responses are determined in part by limitations imposed by or opportunities available in his environment. If he is to manifest any real growth and reach his higher potentials, his creativity would need nourishment from his environment”. Currently <u><mark>there are recent strides</mark> documented <mark>in</mark> literature showing <mark>Africa’s </u></mark>growing<u> <mark>interest</mark> and participation <mark>in space exploration</u></mark> (Ngcofe et al., 2013; Abiodun, 2012; Wood & Wiegel, 2012; Gottschalk, 2010; Martinez, 2008; Mostert, 2008). It is of this view that this paper attempts to examine the impact of being a late starter on space exploration, particularly looking at the issue of space debris and its potential impact on Africa as a developing space fearing nation. </p><p>Space debris</p><p><u><mark>The </mark>current <mark>major threat</u></mark> of space exploration <u><mark>is the risk pertaining to <strong>space debris relative to the cost of launching satellites</strong> in space</mark>.</u> The need to justify expenditure on space-related endeavours competes with other pressing expenditure needs such as provision of food, clean drinking water, housing, electricity, roads infrastructure and other commercial development. Space debris also known as orbital debris, or space junk, or space waste, is the collection of man-made objects that have exceeded its service life and broken down while in orbit around the earth (Interagency Report on Orbital Debris 2005; UN, 1999; Sénéchal, 2007; Colliot, 2002; Glassman, 2009; Griffiths, 2010). These include everything from spent rocket stages, old satellites, and fragments from disintegration erosion and collision. Space debris has vastly increased since the beginning of space travel in 1957 thus leading to orbit congestion (Colliot, 2012; Figure 2). According to NASA (2013), there are 500 000 pieces of debris tracked in orbit on Earth.</p><p>Collision at orbital velocity can be extremely dangerous to functioning satellites and space manned missions. Sénéchal (2007) argues that at orbital velocity of more than 28000 km/h, an object as small as 1 cm in diameter has enough kinetic energy to produce significant impact damage, to partially or completely destruct an operational satellite. While an object of 1mm size can cause surface pitting and erosion, with larger objects of about 10 cm totally destroying operational satellites, and may even kill space explorers. According to the Kessler Syndrome space debris model, as the number of debris object increases, collisions become more likely to occur thus creating yet more debris (Griffiths, 2010; Colliot, 2012; Durrieu & Nelson, 2013). This is an immense concern, which threatens safety of future space explorations. Though space is a large environment, satellites are actually concentrated in a few orbits that are currently optimal, namely:</p><p>Low Earth Orbit (LEO) – this is the altitude from 160 km to 2000 km above the earth’s surface. LEO is largely used for earth monitoring, military surveillance, and communication satellites, especially around 350 km.</p><p>Medium Earth Orbit (MEO) – this is an area from 2000 km to 35 000 km and is mainly used by navigation satellites such as global position system (GPS) networks at around 20 000 km.</p><p>Geostationary Orbit (GEO) – this is the belt at 36 000 km and is optimal for communication satellites. However, Griffiths (2010) argues that it is more expensive to launch satellites to this orbit. Hence, many communication satellites are placed at LEO.</p><p>High Earth Orbit (HEO) – This is the area above 36 000 km, and used almost only by satellites researching the magnetosphere or other solar-terrestrial physics.</p><p>LEO is regarded as the major used space orbit environment and therefore has a larger record of space debris than any other orbit. There has been four accidental collision events up-to-date (Durrieu and Nelson 2003), with a recent collision incident occurring in 2009 where a United States communication satellite collided with a defunct Russian satellite (Glassman, 2009; Griffiths, 2010; Smitham, 2010). These satellites collided at a speed of over 40 000 km/h, causing complete destruction of both satellites. Thus resulting in around 1400 recorded debris objects (Glassman, 2009; Griffiths, 2010; Smitham, 2010). The available computer models based on observation of debris used to predict future growth of the debris population and probability of collision with satellites under different assumptions reveal that in the next 40 years, collisions with objects larger than 10 cm in LEO are expected to occur on average every 5 years (Griffiths, 2010). This statistics coincide with Sénéchal (2007); Williamson (2003); Liou and Johnson (1996) who argued that in LEO the spatial density of objects is above critical point and the continuation of debris in this orbit may render it inaccessible in the future.</p><p>Space availability</p><p><u>The vulnerability of space asserts interference and disruption</u>, led to the view, <u>held by the USA security space community, that space is a contested domain.</u> <u>Whoever seizes space has a powerful advantage both for social and economic enhancemen</u>t together with military applications (Sadeh, 2009). Space asserts provide a persistent view of the earth and offer ability of real or near real time global collection and dissemination of crucial information. Although, recently, there have been vast strides by Africa within the space arena, the continent still lags behind in space matters. Out of 53 countries in Africa, only four countries (Algeria, Egypt, Nigeria and South Africa) have successfully participated in space activities, through the development of their own space agencies which led to launching of their own satellites in space. <u>The <mark>development of <strong>micro sat</strong></mark>ellite <mark>tech</mark>nology and multiple constellations <mark>is</mark> now <mark>making space tech</mark>nology <mark>more affordable for developing countries</mark> to utilise the space environment</u> (Durrieu & Nelson, 2013). Thus <u><mark>debate about the <strong>African Space Agency</strong></mark>, which will cater for participation in space activities for Africa’s needs, <mark>is gaining</mark> <mark>momentum</mark>.</u> Currently, Africa has an inspiring mission to the moon (http://africa2moon.developspacesa.org). With the vast interest in space activities by the African continent, one wonders, is there still space in space? Rex (1998) on his paper seeking to answer ‘will space run out of space’. He argues that <u><mark>there would be no major risk for space endeavours </mark>from current operational satellites <strong><mark>only if it were not for space debris</strong></mark>.</u> The issue of space availability in space has been, and is still a major area of concern, more especially for Africa. Since the initial space exploration, the United Nations Committee on the Peaceful Uses of Outer Space (UNCOPOUS) was established in 1959 in order to safeguard the use of space and promote space sustainability. This resulted in five UN treaties on Outer Space (http://www.oosa.unvienna.org/oosa/COPUOS/copuos.html) namely:</p><p>Outer Space Treaty (1967) - This treaty promotes the international cooperation in the exploration and use of space, however, prohibits the usage of space for any nuclear weapons and / or any kind of weapons of mass destruction. It clearly emphasises that no state can claim sovereignty of or occupy outer space, the moon or any other Celestial Body. This treaty further deals with liability and states responsibility as to inform the UN secretary general and the international scientific community of the nature, conduct, location and results of their activities in outer space.</p><p>Rescue Agreement Treaty (1968) - This agreement deals with the rescue of astronauts, the return of astronauts and the return of objects launched into outer space. This agreement has a legal framework for emergency assistance of astronauts and the notification of launching of any space objects which has to return to earth and express who should be responsible for all the cost incurred for such a particular mission.</p><p>Liability Convention (1972) - This convention is a pact of international liability for damage caused by space objects. It imposes an international and absolute liability on a launching state, or states as well as on those states who are members of inter-governmental organisations, for any damage caused by their objects. Launching state is defined as the state which launches or procures the launching of a space object or from whose territory or facility a space object is launched, irrespective of the success or not of the launch. Damage includes the loss of life, personal injury or any other impairment or health or loss of damage to property of state or of persons, natural or juridical or property of international, intergovernmental organisations. This also applies to any damage caused by a space object on the surface of the earth or to an aircraft flight.</p><p>Registration Convention Treaty (1974) - The treaty obliges states to register all space objects in a register, which is maintained by the UN secretary general since 1962.</p><p>Moon Treaty (1979) - The treaty declares that the moon is a global common for all humankind and is not subject to national appropriation and occupation. It further stresses that no private ownership is allowed but all state parties have the right to exploration and use of the moon. In practice, this treaty has no force, because none of the space powers who engage in lunar exploration have ratified it: USA, Russia, China and India.</p><p>Although, these treaties exist there has been non-compliance by those leading space faring countries. Since the 1960s, the United States and Russia have conducted dozens of anti-satellite (ASAT) test missions in space, which resulted in most of orbital debris experienced even today (Weeden, 2013). Most recently China has performed an ASAT mission against its aging FY-1C weather satellite at 855 km altitude on the 11/01/2007. It launched a missile, which destroyed the satellite, resulting in 3000 pieces of debris larger than 10 cm in size (Glassman, 2009; Weeden, 2013). This event was further followed by the United States ASAT in 21/02/2008, firing a missile that destroyed one of its military satellites at around 250 km altitude. The US ascertained that the satellite was uncontrollably descending into the atmosphere with nearly fully fuelled tank of toxic hydrazine. Furthermore, its altitude was low enough to ensure swift re-entry of all the resulting space debris, and so, harmless to the space environment. The US delegate fully briefed the UN COPUOS unlike the Chinese. The outcome by the US in destroying its satellite is applaudable. However, ignorance has been shown by the former President George W. Bush when asked what would the people say about the mission? He said “I don’t care what people will say. We’re doing it for the right reason, and it’s transparent” (Oberg, 2008). These clearly are signs of bullying with regard to space matters by space powers with advanced space technologies. </p><p>Conclusion</p><p>The act of destroying a satellite can damage the space environment by creating dangerous amounts of space debris. <u><mark>Space debris can</mark>,</u> therefore, <u><mark>lead to </mark>collisions and <mark>loss of important satellites, which has tremendous cost effects for Africa’s participation in space </mark>activities. Losing a satellite in-orbit due to space debris is no longer hypothetical, but rather a harsh reality and is likely to increase with years to come</u> (Smitham, 2010). Grego (2014) argues that deliberate space debris creation might result in conflict between space fearing nations with unpredictable and dangerous consequences. Such consequences might trigger an arms race which would further divert the economic and political resources from other pressing issues like food security, climate change, health issues, etc. The need to sustain benefits of space for present and future generations and other countries that have not explored space as yet is vital if we are to obtain continuous benefits from space activities. Glassman (2009) suggests that a number of activities and commitments need to be revitalised. Current space best practice, also termed rules of the road, seek to minimize causing new space debris, through careful revision of both design and operational protocols:</p><p>· Separation of satellites from their carrier rocket should no longer result in loose bolts and other metal pieces flying off;</p><p>· satellites should have some propulsion capability to initiate collision avoidance manoeuvres;</p><p>· at the end of their service life, satellites, especially those in geosynchronous orbit (GSO), should be manoeuvred into a “graveyard orbit” at a different altitude;</p><p>· and valves should open to discharge any remaining propellant, to prevent overheating and explosive disruptions.</p> | null | 1AC | 1AC – African Space Agency | 342,895 | 106 | 80,046 | ./documents/ndtceda19/Dartmouth/HeHe/Dartmouth-He-He-Aff-Navy-Round4.docx | 610,741 | A | Navy | 4 | Texas SW | Matt Harkins | 1ac - share liability (debris africa)
1nc - cosmo liberalism K tech K
2nr - liberalism K | ndtceda19/Dartmouth/HeHe/Dartmouth-He-He-Aff-Navy-Round4.docx | null | 51,756 | HeHe | Dartmouth HeHe | null | So..... | He..... | Er..... | He..... | 19,246 | Dartmouth | Dartmouth | null | null | 1,009 | ndtceda19 | NDT/CEDA 2019-20 | 2,019 | cx | college | 2 |
2,793,743 | Challenges to US primacy are coming now – defense industry R&D and production are critical to maintain our edge. | Marks 19, | Michael Marks 19, former Senior Policy Advisor to the Under Secretary for Security Assistance, Science and Technology at the U.S. Department of State., 10-10-2019, "Strengthen Us Industry To Counter National Security Challenges," American Military News, https://americanmilitarynews.com/2019/10/strengthen-us-industry-to-counter-national-security-challenges/ | While U.S. defense budgets have recently been on the rise, it is likely that we will see a spending decline in the coming years as competition for non-defense federal budget dollars increases and deficits grow. The United States, therefore, must take action to ensure that we maintain our technological edge against our adversaries by empowering the private sector to provide cost-effective innovation for America’s defense. Since the end of the Second World War the U.S. has relied on qualitative superiority over its potential adversaries, specially those like the Soviet Union/Russia and China, who enjoyed comparative quantitative advantages. These qualitative advantages were vital to maintaining global stability and helped enable our nation to become the preeminent global economy but they have been eroded over the last few decades. There can be no doubt that Russia and China are determined to challenge America’s qualitative advantage. From the rebirth of Russian military power under Vladimir Putin to the ever-growing Chinese military prowess across the board, their efforts show no sign of slowing down. One of the most frightening examples of Russia’s resurgence is its development of a hypersonic missile that could be ready for combat as early as 2020 To accompany these developments came the emergence in 2017 of Russia as the world’s second-largest arms producer, ready and able to support nations hostile to US interests. Technology development and innovation figure prominently in all of China’s national planning goals, with plans to make the country the global leader in science and innovation and the preeminent technological and manufacturing power by 2049 The country now has the second-largest national defense budget behind the U.S. and wants to be Asia’s preeminent military power. Beijing is developing next-generation fighter jets, ICBMs and shorter-range ballistic missiles, as well as advanced naval vessels. The People’s Liberation Army has reached a critical point of confidence and now feel they can match competitors like the United States in combat This has implications for the security of Taiwan, Japan, other US allies in the region as well as to America itself To make matters worse, there are a growing number of experts that see China developing asymmetric technologies, combined with conventional and nuclear systems that could create an existential threat to the U.S. pacific based assets. It is in the wake of these growing threats to our national security American industry will likely be expected to shoulder an even larger responsibility concerning investment in defense-related R&D. America’s R&D advantage, crucial to maintaining military superiority, is increasingly at risk. As China and Russia continue to challenge America’s military dominance and pressures on the defense budget continue to mount, the federal government will likely turn more and more to contractors and commercial companies to develop next-generation defense capabilities. Strengthening U.S. industry, therefore, will be critical to countering our national security challenges. | qualitative superiority over adversaries vital to global stability have been eroded Russia and China are determined to challenge America From the rebirth of Russian military power under Putin to Chinese military prowess One of the most frightening examples of Russia’s resurgence is its hypersonic missile Tech figure prominently This has implications for the security of US allies as well as America itself asymmetric tech could create an existential threat America’s R&D advantage, crucial to maintaining military superiority, is at risk. the government will turn more to commercial companies to develop next-gen defense capabilities. Strengthening U.S. industry will counter challenges | While U.S. defense budgets have recently been on the rise, it is likely that we will see a spending decline in the coming years as competition for non-defense federal budget dollars increases and deficits grow. The United States, therefore, must take action to ensure that we maintain our technological edge against our adversaries by empowering the private sector to provide cost-effective innovation for America’s defense. Since the end of the Second World War the U.S. has relied on qualitative superiority over its potential adversaries, especially those like the Soviet Union/Russia and China, who enjoyed comparative quantitative advantages. These qualitative advantages were vital to maintaining global stability and helped enable our nation to become the preeminent global economy, but they have been eroded over the last few decades. In 1960, the U.S. share of global research and development (R&D) spending stood at 69%. U.S. defense-related R&D alone accounted for 36% of total global expenditures. Soon thereafter other nations recognized the need to increase their R&D expenditures and build their own defense industrial bases to compete with the United States. From 2000-2016, China’s share of global R&D rose from 4.9% to 25.1% while the U.S. share of global R&D dropped to 28%. U.S. defense-related R&D meanwhile now makes up a mere 4% of global R&D spending. There can be no doubt that Russia and China are determined to challenge America’s qualitative advantage. From the rebirth of Russian military power under Vladimir Putin to the ever-growing Chinese military prowess across the board, their efforts show no sign of slowing down. Russia has been and continues to undergo a major modernization of its armed forces. For example, they are in the midst of a ten-year program to build hundreds of new nuclear missiles and have set a goal of modernizing 70% of the Russian Ground Force’s equipment by 2020. One of the most frightening examples of Russia’s resurgence is its development of a hypersonic missile that could be ready for combat as early as 2020. Worryingly, the US is currently unable to defend against this type of missile. To accompany these developments came the emergence in 2017 of Russia as the world’s second-largest arms producer, ready and able to support nations hostile to US interests. China, on the other hand, used to be a country that only manufactured cheap products and knockoffs, but that is no longer true. Technology development and innovation figure prominently in all of China’s national planning goals, with plans to make the country the global leader in science and innovation and the preeminent technological and manufacturing power by 2049, the 100th anniversary of the Chinese communist revolution. This, of course, has huge implications for China’s military capability. The country now has the second-largest national defense budget behind the U.S. and wants to be Asia’s preeminent military power. Beijing is developing next-generation fighter jets, ICBMs and shorter-range ballistic missiles, as well as advanced naval vessels. The People’s Liberation Army has reached a critical point of confidence and now feel they can match competitors like the United States in combat. This has implications for the security of Taiwan, Japan, other US allies in the region as well as to America itself. To make matters worse, there are a growing number of experts that see China developing asymmetric technologies, combined with conventional and nuclear systems that could create an existential threat to the U.S. pacific based assets. It is in the wake of these growing threats to our national security American industry will likely be expected to shoulder an even larger responsibility concerning investment in defense-related R&D. One of the ways we can empower companies to make these additional investments and lead next-generation defense innovation is to allow commonsense mergers between important defense and aerospace companies. Horizontal consolidation eliminates the redundancy of enormous fixed costs, leading to savings passed down to customers. Mergers can also create economies of scale and existing synergies that help the combined company realize access to larger numbers of engineers and innovators, while keeping costs low and improving the timeline for taking a product from concept to development. A recent example of how this can work is the proposed Raytheon and United Technologies merger. The two parties project that the new combined company will employ more than 60,000 engineers, hold over 38,000 patents and invest approximately $8 billion per year in research and development. This will allow the development of new, critical technologies more quickly and efficiently than either company could on its own. Such private sector investments in innovation will be critical in the face of the growing challenges to American military dominance. America’s R&D advantage, crucial to maintaining military superiority, is increasingly at risk. As China and Russia continue to challenge America’s military dominance and pressures on the defense budget continue to mount, the federal government will likely turn more and more to contractors and commercial companies to develop next-generation defense capabilities. Strengthening U.S. industry, therefore, will be critical to countering our national security challenges. | 5,385 | <h4>Challenges to US primacy are coming now – defense industry R&D and production are critical to maintain our edge. </h4><p>Michael <strong>Marks 19,<u></strong> former Senior Policy Advisor to the Under Secretary for Security Assistance, Science and Technology at the U.S. Department of State., 10-10-2019, "Strengthen Us Industry To Counter National Security Challenges," American Military News, https://americanmilitarynews.com/2019/10/strengthen-us-industry-to-counter-national-security-challenges/</p><p>While U.S. defense budgets have recently been on the rise, it is likely that we will see a spending decline in the coming years as competition for non-defense federal budget dollars increases and deficits grow. The United States, therefore, must take action to ensure that we maintain our technological edge against our adversaries by empowering the private sector to provide cost-effective innovation for America’s defense. Since the end of the Second World War <strong>the U.S. has relied on <mark>qualitative superiority</u></strong> <u>over</mark> its potential <mark>adversaries</mark>, </u>e<u>specially those like the Soviet Union/Russia and China, who enjoyed comparative quantitative advantages.</u> <u><strong>These qualitative advantages were <mark>vital to</mark> maintaining <mark>global stability</mark> and helped enable our nation to become the preeminent global economy</u></strong>, <u>but they <mark>have been eroded</mark> over the last few decades. </u>In 1960, the U.S. share of global research and development (R&D) spending stood at 69%. U.S. defense-related R&D alone accounted for 36% of total global expenditures. Soon thereafter other nations recognized the need to increase their R&D expenditures and build their own defense industrial bases to compete with the United States. From 2000-2016, China’s share of global R&D rose from 4.9% to 25.1% while the U.S. share of global R&D dropped to 28%. U.S. defense-related R&D meanwhile now makes up a mere 4% of global R&D spending. <u>There can be no doubt that <mark>Russia and China are determined to challenge America</mark>’s qualitative advantage. <mark>From the rebirth of Russian military power under</mark> Vladimir <mark>Putin to</mark> the ever-growing <mark>Chinese military prowess </mark>across the board, their efforts show no sign of slowing down. </u>Russia has been and continues to undergo a major modernization of its armed forces. For example, they are in the midst of a ten-year program to build hundreds of new nuclear missiles and have set a goal of modernizing 70% of the Russian Ground Force’s equipment by 2020. <u><mark>One of the most frightening examples of Russia’s resurgence is its</mark> development of a <mark>hypersonic missile</mark> that could be ready for combat as early as 2020</u>. Worryingly, the US is currently unable to defend against this type of missile. <u>To accompany these developments came the emergence in 2017 of Russia as the world’s second-largest arms producer, ready and able to support nations hostile to US interests. </u>China, on the other hand, used to be a country that only manufactured cheap products and knockoffs, but that is no longer true. <u><mark>Tech</mark>nology development and innovation <mark>figure prominently</mark> in all of China’s national planning goals, with plans to make the country the global leader in science and innovation and the preeminent technological and manufacturing power by 2049</u>, the 100th anniversary of the Chinese communist revolution. This, of course, has huge implications for China’s military capability. <u>The country now has the second-largest national defense budget behind the U.S. and wants to be Asia’s preeminent military power. Beijing is developing next-generation fighter jets, ICBMs and shorter-range ballistic missiles, as well as advanced naval vessels. The People’s Liberation Army has reached a critical point of confidence and now feel they can match competitors like the United States in combat</u>. <u><strong><mark>This has implications for the security of</mark> Taiwan, Japan, other <mark>US allies</mark> in the region <mark>as well as</mark> to <mark>America itself</u></strong></mark>. <u>To make matters worse, there are a growing number of experts that see China developing <mark>asymmetric tech</mark>nologies, combined with conventional and nuclear systems <strong>that <mark>could create an existential threat</mark> to the U.S. pacific based assets. </strong>It is in the wake of these growing threats to our national security American industry will likely be expected to shoulder an even larger responsibility concerning investment in defense-related R&D. </u>One of the ways we can empower companies to make these additional investments and lead next-generation defense innovation is to allow commonsense mergers between important defense and aerospace companies. Horizontal consolidation eliminates the redundancy of enormous fixed costs, leading to savings passed down to customers. Mergers can also create economies of scale and existing synergies that help the combined company realize access to larger numbers of engineers and innovators, while keeping costs low and improving the timeline for taking a product from concept to development. A recent example of how this can work is the proposed Raytheon and United Technologies merger. The two parties project that the new combined company will employ more than 60,000 engineers, hold over 38,000 patents and invest approximately $8 billion per year in research and development. This will allow the development of new, critical technologies more quickly and efficiently than either company could on its own. Such private sector investments in innovation will be critical in the face of the growing challenges to American military dominance. <u><mark>America’s R&D advantage, crucial to maintaining military superiority, is</mark> increasingly <mark>at risk.</mark> As China and Russia continue to challenge America’s military dominance and pressures on the defense budget continue to mount, <strong><mark>the</mark> federal <mark>government will</mark> likely <mark>turn more</mark> and more <mark>to</mark> contractors and <mark>commercial companies to develop next-gen</mark>eration <mark>defense capabilities</strong>. Strengthening U.S. industry</mark>, therefore, <mark>will</mark> be critical to <mark>counter</mark>ing our national security <mark>challenges</mark>.</p></u> | 1NC – Round 5 | null | 1NC – DA | 7,811 | 131 | 88,508 | ./documents/hspolicy19/RowlandHall/AmGu/Rowland%20Hall-Amiel-Gushin-Neg-Damus-Round5.docx | 720,090 | N | Damus | 5 | OES TW | Victor Li | 1AC - Japan
2NR - Proliferation Bad | hspolicy19/RowlandHall/AmGu/Rowland%20Hall-Amiel-Gushin-Neg-Damus-Round5.docx | null | 61,455 | AmGu | Rowland Hall AmGu | null | Be..... | Am..... | Ad..... | Gu..... | 21,405 | RowlandHall | Rowland Hall | UT | null | 1,018 | hspolicy19 | HS Policy 2019-20 | 2,019 | cx | hs | 2 |
2,638,741 | Prolif causes extinction and turns case | Chanlett-Avery 9 | Chanlett-Avery 9 [Emma Chanlett-Avery is a CRS Asian Affairs Specialist, “Japan’s Nuclear Future: Policy Debate, Prospects, and U.S. Interests,” Congressional Research Service, http://www.fas.org/sgp/crs/nuke/RL34487.pdf] | Any reconsideration of Japan’s policy of nuclear weapons abstention would have significant implications for Japan’s withdrawal from the NPT) could damage the most durable international non-prolif regime Japan could set off a nuclear arms race with China South Korea Taiwan and India and Pakistan may feel compelled to further strengthen their own nuclear weapons capability the move could indicate Tokyo’s lack of trust in the American commitment to defend Japan An erosion in the U.S.-Japan alliance could upset the geopolitical balance in East Asia, a shift that could indicate a further strengthening of China’s position These ramifications would be deeply destabilizing | reconsideration would have significant implications Japan could set off nuclear arms race with China, So Ko Taiwan India, Pakistan compelled to strengthen capability could indicate lack of trust in American commitment upset the balance in East Asia ramifications would be deeply destabilizing | Any reconsideration of Japan’s policy of nuclear weapons abstention would have significant implications for U.S. policy in East Asia. Globally, Japan’s withdrawal from the Nuclear NonProliferation Treaty (NPT) could damage the most durable international non-proliferation regime. Regionally, Japan “going nuclear” could set off a nuclear arms race with China, South Korea, and Taiwan and, in turn, India, and Pakistan may feel compelled to further strengthen their own nuclear weapons capability. Bilaterally, assuming that Japan made the decision without U.S. support, the move could indicate Tokyo’s lack of trust in the American commitment to defend Japan. An erosion in the U.S.-Japan alliance could upset the geopolitical balance in East Asia, a shift that could indicate a further strengthening of China’s position as an emerging hegemonic power. These ramifications would likely be deeply destabilizing for the security of the Asia Pacific region and beyond. | 965 | <h4>Prolif<strong> causes extinction and turns case </h4><p>Chanlett-Avery 9 </strong>[Emma Chanlett-Avery is a CRS Asian Affairs Specialist, “Japan’s Nuclear Future: Policy Debate, Prospects, and U.S. Interests,” Congressional Research Service, http://www.fas.org/sgp/crs/nuke/RL34487.pdf]</p><p><u><strong>Any <mark>reconsideration</u></strong></mark> <u>of Japan’s policy of nuclear weapons</u> <u>abstention <mark>would have significant implications</mark> for</u> U.S. policy in East Asia. Globally, <u>Japan’s withdrawal from the</u> Nuclear NonProliferation Treaty (<u>NPT) <strong>could damage</u></strong> <u>the most durable international</u> <u>non-prolif</u>eration <u>regime</u>. Regionally, <u><mark>Japan</u></mark> “going nuclear” <u><mark>could set off </mark>a <mark>nuclear arms race with <strong>China</u></strong>, <u><strong>So</mark>uth <mark>Ko</mark>rea</u></strong>, and <u><strong><mark>Taiwan </mark>and</u></strong>, in turn, <u><strong><mark>India</u></strong>, <u><strong></mark>and <mark>Pakistan</u></strong></mark> <u>may feel <strong><mark>compelled to </mark>further <mark>strengthen</strong> </mark>their own nuclear weapons <mark>capability</u></mark>. Bilaterally, assuming that Japan made the decision without U.S. support, <u>the</u> <u>move <mark>could indicate</mark> <strong>Tokyo’s <mark>lack of trust</strong> in </mark>the <mark>American commitment <strong></mark>to defend Japan</u></strong>. <u>An erosion in the U.S.-Japan alliance could <mark>upset <strong>the</mark> geopolitical <mark>balance in East Asia</mark>,</u></strong> <u>a shift that could indicate a <strong>further strengthening of China’s position</u></strong> as an emerging hegemonic power. <u>These <mark>ramifications would</u></mark> likely <u><mark>be <strong>deeply destabilizing</u></strong></mark> for the security of the Asia Pacific region and beyond. </p> | 1NC | 1NC | null | 92,962 | 160 | 83,787 | ./documents/ndtceda19/UNLV/BoBr/UNLV-Boelkens-Bradley-Neg-ADA-Round3.docx | 615,585 | N | ADA | 3 | Wyoming Bertagnolli-Pierce | Alaina Walberg | 1AC - China ASAT Ban
1NC - Commercial Space DA unilateral cp new start cp assurances v2 eu cp
2NC - answering international fiat commercial space da case
1NR - assurances v2
2NR - assurances case | ndtceda19/UNLV/BoBr/UNLV-Boelkens-Bradley-Neg-ADA-Round3.docx | null | 52,104 | BoBr | UNLV BoBr | null | Br..... | Bo..... | Jo..... | Br..... | 19,289 | UNLV | UNLV | null | null | 1,009 | ndtceda19 | NDT/CEDA 2019-20 | 2,019 | cx | college | 2 |
2,731,206 | Military doesn’t matter | Mueller 16 | John Mueller 16, Woody Hayes Senior Research Scientist, Mershon Center for International Security Studies; Adjunct Professor, Department of Political Science, Ohio State University, 6/5/16, “Embracing Threatlessness: US Military Spending, Newt Gingrich, and the Costa Rica Option,” http://politicalscience.osu.edu/faculty/jmueller/CNArestraintCato16.pdf | The U S seems free from threats that require a great deal of military preparedness conflict like World War II is extremely unlikely Some envision threat in China’s prosperity armed conflict would be overwhelmingly—costly Chinese leaders realize this. Russia’s assertiveness does not suggest that the game has been changed. It might make sense to maintain a containment capacity against rogue states the military requirements for the task are limited. Humanitarian intervention with military force is unlikely Concern about nuclear proliferation is overwrought Europe face no threats of a military nature Taiwan/China remains a remote concern Israel’s primary problems derive from the actions of sub-state groups military relevance of the terrorism “threat” has been substantially exaggerated | The U S seems free from threats that require military preparedness conflict would be overwhelmingly costly Chinese leaders realize this. Russia’s assertiveness does not suggest the game has changed against rogue states the military requirements are limited. Concern about prolif is overwrought military relevance of terrorism has been exaggerated | The United States seems to be substantially free from threats that require a great deal of military preparedness. To begin with, it really seems time to consider the consequences of the fact that a conflict like World War II is extremely unlikely to recur. Spending a lot of money for an eventuality—or fantasy—of ever-receding likelihood is highly questionable. Some envision threat in China’s rapidly-increasing prosperity. But, although its oft-stated desire to incorporate (or re-incorporate) Taiwan into its territory should be watched, armed conflict would be extremely—even overwhelmingly—costly to the country. And Chinese leaders, already rattled by internal difficulties, seem to realize this. Russia’s recent assertiveness bears watching, but it does not suggest that the game has been crucially changed. It might make sense to maintain a containment and deterrent capacity against rogue states in formal or informal coalition with other concerned countries. However, the military requirements for the task are limited. Humanitarian intervention with military force is unlikely due to a low tolerance for casualties in such ventures, an increasing aversion to the costs of nation-building, and the lack of political gain from successful ventures. Concern about nuclear proliferation is overwrought: long experience suggests that when countries obtain the weapons, they “use” them only to stoke their national ego and to deter real or imagined threats. Europe seems to face no notable threats of a military nature, the Taiwan/China issue remains a fairly remote concern, and Israel’s primary problems derive from the actions of sub-state groups. The military relevance of the terrorism “threat” has been substantially exaggerated, and it mainly calls for policing and intelligence work and perhaps for occasional focused strikes by small units. | 1,854 | <h4>Military doesn’t matter</h4><p>John <strong>Mueller 16</strong>, Woody Hayes Senior Research Scientist, Mershon Center for International Security Studies; Adjunct Professor, Department of Political Science, Ohio State University, 6/5/16, “Embracing Threatlessness: US Military Spending, Newt Gingrich, and the Costa Rica Option,” http://politicalscience.osu.edu/faculty/jmueller/CNArestraintCato16.pdf</p><p><u><mark>The <strong>U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates <u><mark>seems</u></mark> to be substantially <u><strong><mark>free from threats that require</mark> a great deal of <mark>military preparedness</u></strong></mark>. To begin with, it really seems time to consider the consequences of the fact that a <u>conflict like World War II is extremely unlikely</u> to recur. Spending a lot of money for an eventuality—or fantasy—of ever-receding likelihood is highly questionable. <u>Some envision threat in China’s</u> rapidly-increasing <u>prosperity</u>. But, although its oft-stated desire to incorporate (or re-incorporate) Taiwan into its territory should be watched, <u>armed <mark>conflict would be</u></mark> extremely—even <u><mark>overwhelmingly</mark>—<mark>costly</u></mark> to the country. And <u><strong><mark>Chinese leaders</u></strong></mark>, already rattled by internal difficulties, seem to <u><strong><mark>realize this</strong>. Russia’s</u></mark> recent <u><mark>assertiveness</u></mark> bears watching, but it <u><mark>does not suggest</mark> that <mark>the game has</mark> been</u> crucially <u><mark>changed</mark>. It might make sense to maintain a containment</u> and deterrent <u>capacity <mark>against rogue states</u></mark> in formal or informal coalition with other concerned countries. However, <u><strong><mark>the military requirements</mark> for the task <mark>are limited</strong>.</mark> Humanitarian intervention with military force is unlikely</u> due to a low tolerance for casualties in such ventures, an increasing aversion to the costs of nation-building, and the lack of political gain from successful ventures. <u><mark>Concern about</mark> nuclear <mark>prolif</mark>eration <mark>is overwrought</u></mark>: long experience suggests that when countries obtain the weapons, they “use” them only to stoke their national ego and to deter real or imagined threats. <u>Europe</u> seems to <u>face no</u> notable <u>threats of a military nature</u>, the <u>Taiwan/China</u> issue <u>remains a</u> fairly <u>remote concern</u>, and <u>Israel’s primary problems derive from the actions of sub-state groups</u>. The <u><mark>military relevance of</mark> the <mark>terrorism</mark> “threat” <mark>has been</mark> substantially <mark>exaggerated</u></mark>, and it mainly calls for policing and intelligence work and perhaps for occasional focused strikes by small units.</p> | 2AC | DIB DA | Escalate | 36,175 | 120 | 86,542 | ./documents/hspolicy19/KentDenver/TsCa/Kent%20Denver-Tsuei-Capoot-Aff-Copper%20Classic-Round5.docx | 713,945 | A | Copper Classic | 5 | Rowland Hall CT | Christina Phillips | 1AC- Yemen
1NC- Negotiations CP Suspend CP DIB DA Russia Fill in DA Saudi Prolif DA
2NR- Russia Fill in DA
2AR- Condo | hspolicy19/KentDenver/TsCa/Kent%20Denver-Tsuei-Capoot-Aff-Copper%20Classic-Round5.docx | null | 60,870 | TsCa | Kent Denver TsCa | null | Ma..... | Ts..... | Co..... | Ca..... | 21,262 | KentDenver | Kent Denver | CO | null | 1,018 | hspolicy19 | HS Policy 2019-20 | 2,019 | cx | hs | 2 |
4,183,818 | Resolved is in the present tense, not future | AHD ‘3 | AHD ‘3 | something that is resolved | something that is resolved | [The American Heritage Dictionary at Dictionary.com]
Full Definition of RESOLVED¶ 1¶ : fixity of purpose : resoluteness¶ 2¶ : something that is resolved¶ 3¶ : a legal or official determination; especially : a formal resolution | 226 | <h4><strong>Resolved is in the present tense, not future </h4><p>AHD ‘3</p><p></strong>[The American Heritage Dictionary at Dictionary.com]</p><p>Full Definition of RESOLVED¶ 1¶ : fixity of purpose : resoluteness¶ 2¶ : <u><mark>something that is resolved</u></mark>¶ 3¶ : a legal or official determination; especially : a formal resolution</p> | Block | Consult India | Assurance – 1NC | 79,073 | 114 | 143,804 | ./documents/hspolicy22/LiberalArtsAndScienceAcademy/ChHu/LiberalArtsAndScienceAcademy-ChHu-Neg-Greenhill-Finals.docx | 927,244 | N | Greenhill | Finals | Peninsula QY | KJ Reese, Sam Shore, Chris Fry | 1AC - NEW Baltics
1NC - T A5 - Tetlock CP - Consult India CP - DoS CP - Congress CP - DCAs CP - Ban NATO CP - Hungary PIC - NATO Bad
2NC - Consult India - DoS CP
1NR - Congress CP - New Affs Bad
2NR - New Affs Bad - DoS CP | hspolicy22/LiberalArtsAndScienceAcademy/ChHu/LiberalArtsAndScienceAcademy-ChHu-Neg-Greenhill-Finals.docx | 2022-09-20 17:10:44 | 79,342 | ChHu | Liberal Arts And Science Academy ChHu | null | Sa..... | Ch..... | Al..... | Hu..... | 26,584 | LiberalArtsAndScienceAcademy | Liberal Arts And Science Academy | TX | null | 2,002 | hspolicy22 | HS Policy 2022-23 | 2,022 | cx | hs | 2 |
1,928,332 | Investigatory power prevents nuclear, biological, and chemical terror attacks – financial crime is the only avenue to acquisition. | Kassenova, 20 | Kassenova, 20 [Togzhan, nonresident fellow in the Nuclear Policy Program at the Carnegie Endowment, 3-4-2020, “The Exploitation of the Global Financial Systems for Weapons of Mass Destruction (WMD) Proliferation”, https://carnegieendowment.org/2020/03/04/exploitation-of-global-financial-systems-for-weapons-of-mass-destruction-wmd-proliferation-pub-81221, don & pacc] | nuclear, biological, and chemical weapons risk WMD proliferation Several groups, such as Al Qaeda and ISIS, demonstrated interest in acquiring a WMD capability Stealing or buying a ready-made weapon is a next to impossible feat The main path to a WMD is to procure components, material, and technology and then build a weapon Because most goods usable in a WMD program are dual-use in nature they are available on the international commercial market. The goal of proliferators is to acquire goods that can contribute to WMD programs without being caught Proliferators defy export controls and sanctions Those buying WMD-related goods can be directly connected to proliferator states Proliferators have perfected methods that help them stay under the radar Proliferators use formal financial institutions to pay for procurement of WMD-related goods to fundraise, launder and move money associated with proliferation Financial institutions struggle with identifying and stopping transactions related to procurement, fundraising, and movement of money for illicit WMD programs due to limits in technical expertise, it is unlikely that financial institutions on their own will ever be in a confident and comfortable position to analyze if goods are sensitive Proliferators make extensive use of shell companies and get away with hiding behind non-transparent corporate structures Similar to money launderers, proliferators favor formal financial systems because the goods they procure mostly come from legitimate manufacturers. As with money launderers, proliferators rely on shell and front companies to avoid detection the money trail is linear – the money is generated to purchase goods transactions related to WMD procurement look like legitimate commercial activity it is also worth approaching various kinds of illicit financing holistically We know that proliferators and agents working on behalf of proliferating states engage in other types of financial crime. The most notorious case is North Korea, which exploits the global financial system to fundraise money launder funds, and pay for its WMD program a Chinese middleman Karl Lee for years supplied Iran with missile-related components financial system not only in support of his procurement and trade efforts but also to launder proceeds from such sales Even if a financial institution cannot be sure that they are dealing with a proliferation-related case, it is important that they flag/stop a transaction that appears suspicious to them. In some cases, proliferation financing was uncovered by a financial institution because of suspicious indicators related to money laundering Increasing the capacity to deal with one type of financial crime automatically increases the overall capacity to detect other types of illicit financing | – nuc bio and chem weapons risk prolif Stealing or buying is impossible The path is to procure components and then build Because program are dual-use they are available on the market Proliferators use financial institutions to pay for procurement to fund launder and move money Proliferators use shell companies and hiding behind corporate structures proliferators engage in other financial crime financing was uncovered because of suspicious money laundering Increasing the capacity to deal with one crime automatically increases the overall capacity to detect other types | WMD PROLIFERATION AS A SECURITY RISK1 Weapons of mass destruction – nuclear, biological, and chemical weapons - present a persistent risk to the U.S. and international security. If a 10-kiloton nuclear bomb, like the one tested by North Korea in 2013, is dropped in Washington, DC, a fireball of almost 500 feet in radius will cover the city.2 The radiation will reach such high levels within a half a mile radius that 50-90% percent of people could die without medical help – some of them within hours. When it comes to preventing WMD proliferation, we need to be conscious of both state and non-state actors. North Korea continues to procure sensitive goods for its nuclear and missile program in defiance of sanctions. Iran is procuring missile-related goods. Agents working on behalf of Syria have sought chemical goods on the commercial market. Several groups, such as Al Qaeda and ISIS, demonstrated interest in acquiring a WMD capability. We do not have a full picture of who might be interested in obtaining a WMD capability in the future. 2. How Proliferation Networks Operate Stealing or buying a ready-made weapon is a next to impossible feat. The main path to a WMD is to procure components, material, and technology and then build a weapon. Because most goods usable in a WMD program are dual-use in nature, with indispensable civilian purposes, they are available on the international commercial market. The international community attempts to minimize the risk that trade in dual-use and military goods entails. The international export control regimes and national export control systems are designed to regulate trade in sensitive items by requiring traders to obtain licenses. Additionally, the international and unilateral sanctions regimes target known proliferators. The goal of proliferators and their agents is to acquire goods that can contribute to WMD programs without being caught. Proliferators and their networks continue to defy both export controls and sanctions. Proliferation networks come in all sizes and shapes. They can be small or large, loose, or more organized. Those buying WMD-related goods can be directly connected to proliferator states, or they can do it purely for profit by inserting themselves into the illicit market to make money. Proliferators have perfected methods that help them stay under the radar.3 One of the standard techniques they use is to buy goods that are slightly below the controlled threshold. This means that unless exporting companies are incredibly vigilant,4 they would not apply for an export license and subject transaction to government scrutiny. However, these slightly inferior goods can still be used for nefarious purposes. There is another method proliferators use to avoid government oversight and licensing—they pretend they are ordering goods for a domestic company. In such cases, supplier companies do not have to apply for licenses. To avoid export controls and sanctions, proliferators lie about the end-use and end-user and hide behind front and shell companies all the time. They never declare that they are buying components for North Korea’s nuclear program, Iran’s missile program, or Syria’s chemical arsenal. For example, they can tell a supplying company they need goods for scientific research or other peaceful purposes. In 2006, an Iranian company ordered sensitive bioresearch equipment from Norway purportedly for a scientific laboratory. On closer look, an attentive Norwegian supplier determined that the equipment Iranians sought was technically superior to what would be necessary for a civilian lab and that it did not fit the physical layout of the laboratory.5 Increasingly, shipping companies and vessels are used prominently in sanction evasion. For example, Iran and North Korea falsify documents, reflag vessels, and switch off automatic identification systems to avoid being discovered in the process of illicit transfers of goods.6 Supplier companies that provide goods to proliferators can be complicit or not complicit. Larger companies have resources to implement strong internal compliance programs that help them detect any suspicious orders. But some companies, especially smaller ones, do not have resources to invest in compliance and remain negligent. In some cases, supplier companies or individuals within know precisely what they are doing. They do it either because of ideology (to support a sanctioned state) or for profit. In one notorious case, a U.S.-based company MKS Instruments sent pressure transducers to its subsidiary in China after duly applying for a U.S. export license, thinking that the goods would be used in China. The co-opted employee of the MKS Instruments’ subsidiary ordered transducers from an unsuspecting parent company and pretended they would be used by Chinese companies but planned all along to ship those goods to Iran.7 Pressure transducers can be used in uranium enrichment centrifuges, making possible the production of fissile material that can also be used in a nuclear weapon. Proliferators prefer to buy good quality goods – mostly from the U.S., European, and Asian suppliers. This means that in most cases, they have to pay for those goods through the formal financial system, making financial institutions part of their proliferation schemes. 3. CHALLENGES AND OPPORTUNITIES FOR FINANCIAL INSTITUTIONS Proliferators use formal financial institutions for two main purposes: (1) to pay for procurement of WMD-related goods; (2) to fundraise, launder and move money associated with proliferation activity (for example, this can apply to money that ends up paying for the WMD activity or to profit generated as a result of supplying proliferator states). Challenges Financial institutions struggle with identifying and stopping transactions related to procurement, fundraising, and movement of money for illicit WMD programs. Below is the list of key challenges: Lack of information and capacity to identify financial transactions related to procurement Financial institutions see limited or no information on goods for which payments are made. The information can be incomplete or even misleading. For example, in one case involving the purchase of chemical equipment from the United States that ended up in Syria, the wire description simply said: “laboratory spare parts.”8 As discussed above, proliferators often order goods just below controlled threshold, which means that there is a movement of goods that do not appear on export control lists but can still contribute to WMD programs. There is a big question mark as to whether information that financial institutions receive (through SWIFT or trade finance documentation) is sufficient to check against lists of controlled goods. Transactions happening under open accounts are especially vulnerable since it is not clear what each individual transaction involves. In general, due to limits in technical expertise, it is unlikely that financial institutions on their own will ever be in a confident and comfortable position to analyze if goods are sensitive. Lack of information on end-use and end-user In addition to limited information on the goods involved, financial institutions are constrained by a lack of information on end-use and end-users. Even in trade finance transactions, in which financial institutions receive more information on the parties involved, limitations apply. For example, not all parties can be captured from accompanying documentation, either because their signatures are illegible or because they are not key parties to the transactions. Limitations of the list-scanning approach to risk management One of the main tools employed by the financial institutions is scanning against lists of sanctioned and/or suspicious entities and individuals. While indispensable, this method has its limitations. First, such scanning returns a high number of false positives (up to 85%), which means that considerable time and effort is spent on clearing those false alarms. Second, concealment and deceit techniques of sanctioned/designated entities and individuals mean that list-scanning does not catch them. They use front and shell companies and the names of associates or family members. Third, the lists contain names of known proliferators and are not useful for preventing new (or newly disguised) proliferators from accessing the financial system. Beneficial ownership of entities Another vulnerability lies in the uneven implementation of beneficiary ownership controls internationally. European Union countries require collection of data and transparency when it comes to who owns companies and trusts. Some other major countries, including the United States, are lagging behind.9 In 2018, FinCEN issued a Customer Due Diligence (CDD) Rule, which applies to covered financial institutions and requires them to identify and verify the identity of beneficial owners of legal entities at the time of account opening and defined points after that.10 While useful, this rule has limited application. The United States is among the countries that do not require the disclosure of beneficial ownership information at the time of company formation. Proliferators make extensive use of shell companies and get away with hiding behind non-transparent corporate structures. Correspondent banking One of the main vulnerabilities to U.S. institutions comes from correspondent accounts as a result of weak controls in foreign jurisdictions and insufficient information on customers behind transactions originating in respondent banks. WMD proliferation financing networks exploit correspondent banking to move funds through U.S. correspondent accounts.11 Absence of proliferation financing risk assessment and dedicated proliferation financing component in “Know-Your-Customer” (KYC) and transaction monitoring procedures beyond sanctions compliance Preventing proliferation financing requires more than compliance with sanctions since sanctions do not address potential proliferators. For that purpose, national and institutional proliferation financing risk assessments, as well as the integration of proliferation financing components into KYC and transaction procedures, are critical. The United States was among the first to conduct a national proliferation financing risk assessment.12 However, proliferation financing risk assessments at the level of financial institutions are neither a norm nor a requirement. Similarly, KYC and transaction monitoring procedures at financial institutions normally do not include a proliferation financing component that could help identify specific risks that a particular institution faces. Vulnerabilities in the cyber and crypto domain North Korea is a poster child for how vulnerabilities in the cyber and crypto domain can be exploited to generate funds for illicit purposes, including for a WMD program. North Korea’s intelligence agency —Reconnaissance General Bureau—leads and coordinates cyberattacks to force the transfer of funds from financial institutions and cryptocurrency exchanges. For example, in 2018, the Reconnaissance General Lab group forced the transfer of $10 million from Banco de Chile mainly to accounts in Hong Kong.13 North Korea targets not only brick-and-mortar financial institutions but cryptocurrency exchanges as well. In 2018, in one attack on a cryptocurrency exchange, North Korean hackers stole close to $250 million in cryptocurrency.14 North Korean agents launder cryptocurrency (mined, stolen, and received through ransomware) via a complex web of online transactions.15 Opportunities Financial institutions can be critical in the fight against illicit activity related to weapons of mass destruction. Noting limitations in the capacity required to identify proliferation-relevant goods, the financial institutions should focus on a better understanding of customers and patterns in transactions, rather than on trying to understand the technical characteristics of goods. Such an approach will also be helpful in uncovering transactions that are not directly relevant to procurement (i.e., payment for goods) but that can still contribute to proliferation (i.e., fundraising, moving, and laundering funds associated with proliferation activity). Incorporating a proliferation financing component into KYC and transaction monitoring procedures can significantly increase the chances of uncovering “red flags.” Below are some recommendations for KYC procedures: Including information on the line of business in customer profiles and denoting whether business and/or activities involve dual-use and/or military goods. More detailed information on the type of business and/or activities can be requested from customers as part of service suitability for higher-risk/vulnerable products like trade finance or wires. Using data from a broader array of lists in addition to U.S. legally binding lists for scanning. For example, foreign countries, international and nonprofit organizations, and commercial vendors develop lists of parties suspected in proliferation for export control compliance purposes. Better scrutiny of phone numbers and addresses. It is not uncommon for front and shell companies to share managers, addresses, and phone numbers. Similarly, there are specific steps that can be integrated into transaction monitoring, including but not limited to: Greater automatic scrutiny of transactions involving accounts of the individuals and entities identified as sensitive (these can include individuals that could be associated with sanctioned activities; businesses that trade in dual-use and/or military goods; businesses commonly implicated in proliferation financing-related activities - shipping companies, trading houses, exchange houses, etc.) Scanning transactions against a broader array of lists. Incorporating scanning against foreign governments’ proliferation-relevant lists can prove especially useful when providing trade finance services. Adopting technical solutions to monitoring trade finance transactions that are more sophisticated and efficient than a manual review of trade documents. This can involve, for example, adopting blockchain-based trade finance platforms or harvesting unstructured data (wire data, transaction memos, suspicious activity reports (SARs), negatives news, etc.). Incorporation of tailored geographical factors into transaction monitoring such as specific cities and regions that are known to host agents working on behalf of proliferating states. For example, the U.S. “National Proliferation Financing Risk Assessment (NPFRA)” notes that many front companies working on behalf of North Korea are based in the Dalian, Dangdong, Jinzhou, and Shenyang municipalities in the Liaoning province as well as Hong Kong.16 Filing SARs on any transactions that do not make sense, as these might help uncover proliferation networks. Inserting a provision in trade finance service contracts to allow an institution to exist a transaction or a relationship without a penalty if the customer does not identify transactions involving sensitive goods or if there are other concerns about a transaction. 4. SIMILARITIES AND DIFFERENCES WITH MONEY LAUNDERING AND TERRORIST FINANCING Patterns of proliferation financing have both similarities and differences with other types of financial crime, such as money laundering and terrorist financing. Similar to money launderers, proliferators favor formal financial systems because the goods they procure mostly come from legitimate manufacturers. As with money launderers, proliferators rely on shell and front companies to avoid detection. Similar to terrorist financing and unlike money laundering, proliferation financing does not usually involve strikingly large amounts. In another similarity with terrorist financing and unlike money laundering, the money trail is linear – the money is generated to purchase goods.17 There are two main differences between proliferation financing, on the one hand, and money laundering and terrorist financing. First, transactions related to WMD procurement look like legitimate commercial activity. Second, in addition to individuals, entities, and transactions, there is an emphasis on goods (on which financial institutions do not have expertise). It is necessary to employ proliferation-specific tools to minimize proliferation financing due to the above-mentioned differences in typologies, but it is also worth approaching various kinds of illicit financing holistically. We know, for example, that proliferators and agents working on behalf of proliferating states engage in other types of financial crime. The most notorious case is North Korea, which exploits the global financial system to fundraise money from various licit and illicit activities, move and launder funds, and pay for its WMD program.18 In another example involving an individual, a Chinese middleman Karl Lee for years supplied (and likely continues to supply) Iran with missile-related components. He has used the global financial system not only in support of his procurement and trade efforts but also to launder proceeds from such sales.19 Even if a financial institution cannot be sure that they are dealing with a proliferation-related case, it is important that they flag/stop a transaction that appears suspicious to them. In some cases, proliferation financing was uncovered by a financial institution because of suspicious indicators related to money laundering.20 Increasing the capacity to deal with one type of financial crime automatically increases the overall capacity to detect other types of illicit financing. | 17,653 | <h4>Investigatory power prevents nuclear, biological, and chemical terror attacks – financial crime is the only avenue to acquisition.</h4><p><strong>Kassenova, 20</strong> [Togzhan, nonresident fellow in the Nuclear Policy Program at the Carnegie Endowment, 3-4-2020, “The Exploitation of the Global Financial Systems for Weapons of Mass Destruction (WMD) Proliferation”, https://carnegieendowment.org/2020/03/04/exploitation-of-global-financial-systems-for-weapons-of-mass-destruction-wmd-proliferation-pub-81221, don & pacc]</p><p>WMD PROLIFERATION AS A SECURITY RISK1 Weapons of mass destruction <mark>– <u><strong>nuc</strong></mark>lear, <strong><mark>bio</strong></mark>logical, <mark>and <strong>chem</strong></mark>ical <mark>weapons</u></mark> - present a persistent <u><mark>risk</u></mark> to the U.S. and international security. If a 10-kiloton nuclear bomb, like the one tested by North Korea in 2013, is dropped in Washington, DC, a fireball of almost 500 feet in radius will cover the city.2 The radiation will reach such high levels within a half a mile radius that 50-90% percent of people could die without medical help – some of them within hours. When it comes to preventing <u><strong>WMD <mark>prolif</mark>eration</u></strong>, we need to be conscious of both state and non-state actors. North Korea continues to procure sensitive goods for its nuclear and missile program in defiance of sanctions. Iran is procuring missile-related goods. Agents working on behalf of Syria have sought chemical goods on the commercial market. <u><strong>Several groups</strong>, such as Al Qaeda and ISIS, <strong>demonstrated interest</strong> in acquiring a WMD capability</u>. We do not have a full picture of who might be interested in obtaining a WMD capability in the future. 2. How Proliferation Networks Operate <u><strong><mark>Stealing or buying</strong></mark> a ready-made weapon <mark>is</mark> a next to <mark>impossible</mark> feat</u>. <u><mark>The</mark> main <mark>path</mark> to a WMD <mark>is to procure components</mark>, material, and technology <mark>and then build</mark> a weapon</u>. <u><mark>Because</mark> most goods usable in a WMD <mark>program are <strong>dual-use</strong></mark> in nature</u>, with indispensable civilian purposes, <u><mark>they are available on <strong>the </mark>international commercial <mark>market</strong></mark>.</u> The international community attempts to minimize the risk that trade in dual-use and military goods entails. The international export control regimes and national export control systems are designed to regulate trade in sensitive items by requiring traders to obtain licenses. Additionally, the international and unilateral sanctions regimes target known proliferators. <u>The goal of proliferators</u> and their agents <u>is to acquire goods that can contribute to WMD programs without being caught</u>. <u>Proliferators</u> and their networks continue to <u>defy</u> both <u>export controls and sanctions</u>.<u><strong> </u></strong>Proliferation networks come in all sizes and shapes. They can be small or large, loose, or more organized. <u>Those buying WMD-related goods can be directly connected to proliferator states</u>, or they can do it purely for profit by inserting themselves into the illicit market to make money. <u>Proliferators have <strong>perfected</strong> methods that help them stay under the radar</u>.3 One of the standard techniques they use is to buy goods that are slightly below the controlled threshold. This means that unless exporting companies are incredibly vigilant,4 they would not apply for an export license and subject transaction to government scrutiny. However, these slightly inferior goods can still be used for nefarious purposes. There is another method proliferators use to avoid government oversight and licensing—they pretend they are ordering goods for a domestic company. In such cases, supplier companies do not have to apply for licenses. To avoid export controls and sanctions, proliferators lie about the end-use and end-user and hide behind front and shell companies all the time. They never declare that they are buying components for North Korea’s nuclear program, Iran’s missile program, or Syria’s chemical arsenal. For example, they can tell a supplying company they need goods for scientific research or other peaceful purposes. In 2006, an Iranian company ordered sensitive bioresearch equipment from Norway purportedly for a scientific laboratory. On closer look, an attentive Norwegian supplier determined that the equipment Iranians sought was technically superior to what would be necessary for a civilian lab and that it did not fit the physical layout of the laboratory.5 Increasingly, shipping companies and vessels are used prominently in sanction evasion. For example, Iran and North Korea falsify documents, reflag vessels, and switch off automatic identification systems to avoid being discovered in the process of illicit transfers of goods.6 Supplier companies that provide goods to proliferators can be complicit or not complicit. Larger companies have resources to implement strong internal compliance programs that help them detect any suspicious orders. But some companies, especially smaller ones, do not have resources to invest in compliance and remain negligent. In some cases, supplier companies or individuals within know precisely what they are doing. They do it either because of ideology (to support a sanctioned state) or for profit. In one notorious case, a U.S.-based company MKS Instruments sent pressure transducers to its subsidiary in China after duly applying for a U.S. export license, thinking that the goods would be used in China. The co-opted employee of the MKS Instruments’ subsidiary ordered transducers from an unsuspecting parent company and pretended they would be used by Chinese companies but planned all along to ship those goods to Iran.7 Pressure transducers can be used in uranium enrichment centrifuges, making possible the production of fissile material that can also be used in a nuclear weapon. Proliferators prefer to buy good quality goods – mostly from the U.S., European, and Asian suppliers. This means that in most cases, they have to pay for those goods through the formal financial system, making financial institutions part of their proliferation schemes. 3. CHALLENGES AND OPPORTUNITIES FOR FINANCIAL INSTITUTIONS <u><mark>Proliferators use</mark> formal <mark>financial institutions</mark> </u>for two main purposes: (1) <u><mark>to pay for procurement</mark> of WMD-related goods</u>; (2) <u><strong><mark>to fund</mark>raise, <mark>launder and move money</strong></mark> associated with proliferation</u> activity (for example, this can apply to money that ends up paying for the WMD activity or to profit generated as a result of supplying proliferator states). Challenges <u>Financial institutions <strong>struggle</strong> with identifying and stopping transactions related to procurement, fundraising, and movement of money for illicit WMD programs</u>. Below is the list of key challenges: Lack of information and capacity to identify financial transactions related to procurement Financial institutions see limited or no information on goods for which payments are made. The information can be incomplete or even misleading. For example, in one case involving the purchase of chemical equipment from the United States that ended up in Syria, the wire description simply said: “laboratory spare parts.”8 As discussed above, proliferators often order goods just below controlled threshold, which means that there is a movement of goods that do not appear on export control lists but can still contribute to WMD programs. There is a big question mark as to whether information that financial institutions receive (through SWIFT or trade finance documentation) is sufficient to check against lists of controlled goods. Transactions happening under open accounts are especially vulnerable since it is not clear what each individual transaction involves. In general, <u>due to <strong>limits in technical expertise</strong>, it is unlikely that financial institutions <strong>on their own</strong> will ever be in a confident and comfortable position to analyze if goods are sensitive</u>. Lack of information on end-use and end-user In addition to limited information on the goods involved, financial institutions are constrained by a lack of information on end-use and end-users. Even in trade finance transactions, in which financial institutions receive more information on the parties involved, limitations apply. For example, not all parties can be captured from accompanying documentation, either because their signatures are illegible or because they are not key parties to the transactions. Limitations of the list-scanning approach to risk management One of the main tools employed by the financial institutions is scanning against lists of sanctioned and/or suspicious entities and individuals. While indispensable, this method has its limitations. First, such scanning returns a high number of false positives (up to 85%), which means that considerable time and effort is spent on clearing those false alarms. Second, concealment and deceit techniques of sanctioned/designated entities and individuals mean that list-scanning does not catch them. They use front and shell companies and the names of associates or family members. Third, the lists contain names of known proliferators and are not useful for preventing new (or newly disguised) proliferators from accessing the financial system. Beneficial ownership of entities Another vulnerability lies in the uneven implementation of beneficiary ownership controls internationally. European Union countries require collection of data and transparency when it comes to who owns companies and trusts. Some other major countries, including the United States, are lagging behind.9 In 2018, FinCEN issued a Customer Due Diligence (CDD) Rule, which applies to covered financial institutions and requires them to identify and verify the identity of beneficial owners of legal entities at the time of account opening and defined points after that.10 While useful, this rule has limited application. The United States is among the countries that do not require the disclosure of beneficial ownership information at the time of company formation. <u><mark>Proliferators</mark> make <strong>extensive <mark>use</strong></mark> of <mark>shell companies and</mark> get away with <strong><mark>hiding behind</strong></mark> non-transparent <strong><mark>corporate structures</u></strong></mark>. Correspondent banking One of the main vulnerabilities to U.S. institutions comes from correspondent accounts as a result of weak controls in foreign jurisdictions and insufficient information on customers behind transactions originating in respondent banks. WMD proliferation financing networks exploit correspondent banking to move funds through U.S. correspondent accounts.11 Absence of proliferation financing risk assessment and dedicated proliferation financing component in “Know-Your-Customer” (KYC) and transaction monitoring procedures beyond sanctions compliance Preventing proliferation financing requires more than compliance with sanctions since sanctions do not address potential proliferators. For that purpose, national and institutional proliferation financing risk assessments, as well as the integration of proliferation financing components into KYC and transaction procedures, are critical. The United States was among the first to conduct a national proliferation financing risk assessment.12 However, proliferation financing risk assessments at the level of financial institutions are neither a norm nor a requirement. Similarly, KYC and transaction monitoring procedures at financial institutions normally do not include a proliferation financing component that could help identify specific risks that a particular institution faces. Vulnerabilities in the cyber and crypto domain North Korea is a poster child for how vulnerabilities in the cyber and crypto domain can be exploited to generate funds for illicit purposes, including for a WMD program. North Korea’s intelligence agency —Reconnaissance General Bureau—leads and coordinates cyberattacks to force the transfer of funds from financial institutions and cryptocurrency exchanges. For example, in 2018, the Reconnaissance General Lab group forced the transfer of $10 million from Banco de Chile mainly to accounts in Hong Kong.13 North Korea targets not only brick-and-mortar financial institutions but cryptocurrency exchanges as well. In 2018, in one attack on a cryptocurrency exchange, North Korean hackers stole close to $250 million in cryptocurrency.14 North Korean agents launder cryptocurrency (mined, stolen, and received through ransomware) via a complex web of online transactions.15 Opportunities Financial institutions can be critical in the fight against illicit activity related to weapons of mass destruction. Noting limitations in the capacity required to identify proliferation-relevant goods, the financial institutions should focus on a better understanding of customers and patterns in transactions, rather than on trying to understand the technical characteristics of goods. Such an approach will also be helpful in uncovering transactions that are not directly relevant to procurement (i.e., payment for goods) but that can still contribute to proliferation (i.e., fundraising, moving, and laundering funds associated with proliferation activity). Incorporating a proliferation financing component into KYC and transaction monitoring procedures can significantly increase the chances of uncovering “red flags.” Below are some recommendations for KYC procedures: Including information on the line of business in customer profiles and denoting whether business and/or activities involve dual-use and/or military goods. More detailed information on the type of business and/or activities can be requested from customers as part of service suitability for higher-risk/vulnerable products like trade finance or wires. Using data from a broader array of lists in addition to U.S. legally binding lists for scanning. For example, foreign countries, international and nonprofit organizations, and commercial vendors develop lists of parties suspected in proliferation for export control compliance purposes. Better scrutiny of phone numbers and addresses. It is not uncommon for front and shell companies to share managers, addresses, and phone numbers. Similarly, there are specific steps that can be integrated into transaction monitoring, including but not limited to: Greater automatic scrutiny of transactions involving accounts of the individuals and entities identified as sensitive (these can include individuals that could be associated with sanctioned activities; businesses that trade in dual-use and/or military goods; businesses commonly implicated in proliferation financing-related activities - shipping companies, trading houses, exchange houses, etc.) Scanning transactions against a broader array of lists. Incorporating scanning against foreign governments’ proliferation-relevant lists can prove especially useful when providing trade finance services. Adopting technical solutions to monitoring trade finance transactions that are more sophisticated and efficient than a manual review of trade documents. This can involve, for example, adopting blockchain-based trade finance platforms or harvesting unstructured data (wire data, transaction memos, suspicious activity reports (SARs), negatives news, etc.). Incorporation of tailored geographical factors into transaction monitoring such as specific cities and regions that are known to host agents working on behalf of proliferating states. For example, the U.S. “National Proliferation Financing Risk Assessment (NPFRA)” notes that many front companies working on behalf of North Korea are based in the Dalian, Dangdong, Jinzhou, and Shenyang municipalities in the Liaoning province as well as Hong Kong.16 Filing SARs on any transactions that do not make sense, as these might help uncover proliferation networks. Inserting a provision in trade finance service contracts to allow an institution to exist a transaction or a relationship without a penalty if the customer does not identify transactions involving sensitive goods or if there are other concerns about a transaction. 4. SIMILARITIES AND DIFFERENCES WITH MONEY LAUNDERING AND TERRORIST FINANCING Patterns of proliferation financing have both similarities and differences with other types of financial crime, such as money laundering and terrorist financing. <u>Similar to money launderers, proliferators favor <strong>formal financial systems</strong> because the <strong>goods</strong> they procure mostly come from <strong>legitimate manufacturers</strong>. As with money launderers, proliferators rely on <strong>shell and front companies</strong> to avoid detection</u>. Similar to terrorist financing and unlike money laundering, proliferation financing does not usually involve strikingly large amounts. In another similarity with terrorist financing and unlike money laundering, <u>the money trail is linear – the money is generated to purchase goods</u>.17 There are two main differences between proliferation financing, on the one hand, and money laundering and terrorist financing. First, <u>transactions related to WMD procurement look like <strong>legitimate commercial activity</u></strong>. Second, in addition to individuals, entities, and transactions, there is an emphasis on goods (on which financial institutions do not have expertise). It is necessary to employ proliferation-specific tools to minimize proliferation financing due to the above-mentioned differences in typologies, but <u>it is also worth approaching various kinds of illicit financing <strong>holistically</u></strong>. <u>We know</u>, for example, <u>that <mark>proliferators</mark> and agents working on behalf of proliferating states <mark>engage in other</mark> types of <mark>financial crime</mark>. The most notorious case is <strong>North Korea</strong>, which exploits the global financial system to fundraise money</u> from various licit and illicit activities, move and <u>launder funds, and pay for its WMD program</u>.18 In another example involving an individual, <u>a Chinese middleman <strong>Karl Lee</strong> for years supplied</u> (and likely continues to supply) <u>Iran with missile-related components</u>. He has used the global <u>financial system not only in support of his procurement and trade efforts but also to launder proceeds from such sales</u>.19 <u><strong>Even if</strong> a financial institution cannot be sure that they are dealing with a proliferation-related case, it is important that they flag/stop a transaction that appears suspicious to them. In some cases, <strong>proliferation <mark>financing</strong> was uncovered</mark> by a financial institution <mark>because of suspicious</mark> indicators related to <mark>money laundering</u></mark>.20 <u><mark>Increasing the capacity to deal with one</mark> type of financial <mark>crime <strong>automatically increases</strong> the <strong>overall capacity</strong> to detect <strong>other types</mark> of illicit financing</u></strong>.</p> | aff card doc – pc r4 | 1ac | 1ac – adv – financial crimes | 5,414 | 163 | 56,950 | ./documents/hspolicy20/MaineEast/PiPi/Maine%20East-Piekut-Piekut-Aff-Pinecrest-Round4.docx | 733,793 | A | Pinecrest | 4 | Glenbrook South WK | Margaret Strong | 1ac - secret service v2
1nc - t cjr t policing reform k security cp executive pic cjr da doj da stimulus ct dhs
2nr - t policing | hspolicy20/MaineEast/PiPi/Maine%20East-Piekut-Piekut-Aff-Pinecrest-Round4.docx | null | 62,621 | PiPi | Maine East PiPi | null | Be..... | Pi..... | Ni..... | Pi..... | 21,704 | MaineEast | Maine East | IL | null | 1,019 | hspolicy20 | HS Policy 2020-21 | 2,020 | cx | hs | 2 |
2,382,453 | [3] Compulsory voting is key to avoiding freeriding. Put away coercion turns – goods produced from voting are public goods so it’s not subject to reciprocal constraints | Ripstein 9 | Ripstein 9 [Arthur Ripstein “Force and Freedom”, Harvard University Press 2009] // SJ AME | Violation of a public space consists in failing to contribute cooperation is mandatory on the preconditions of sustaining a condition of equal private freedom . In the context of mandatory social cooperation, if you do your part but others do not do theirs, they have treated you as a mere means, because you have contributed to the achievement of their purposes. You set out to do your part; rather than doing theirs, they took advantage of your efforts. No parallel principle applies to private cooperation The priority of private ordering cannot apply in cases of mandatory cooperation. You can be held to what you agreed to because you did not have to agree to it. Where cooperation is mandatory, agreement on terms is not even possible that there is only one type of mandatory cooperation: you are under an unconditional obligation to enter and remain in a rightful condition, mandatory cooperation cannot treat terms of interaction as reciprocal because they are voluntary. the “free rider” wrongs his fellow citizens by taking advantage of their efforts. Thefree rider may claim that he would rather do without the rightful condition . That claim is beside the point, because the obligation to enter a rightful condition is unconditional, does not depend upon any particular person’s subjective assessment Focusing on the example of roads provides a useful reminder that many other examples in which citizens can be required to bear burdens for the sake of benefits that they may not enjoy directly it is the task of the state to provide public goods,” such as public health . if the goods are produced, everyone benefits Instead of analyzing national defense in terms of benefits and burdens They are required to sustain a rightful condition. People can be compelled to contribute to genuine national self-defense quite apart from whether they personally stand to benefit from it. people can be compelled to contribute, not because they have accepted a benefit of national defense, but rather because it is the defense of their nation as their system of laws. | . In mandatory cooperation, if you do your part but others do not , they have treated you as a means, private ordering cannot apply in mandatory cooperation You can be held to what you agreed to because you did not have to agree the “free rider” wrongs citizens by taking advantage of their efforts. The may claim that he would rather without the rightful condition That claim is beside the point, because the obligation to enter is unconditional does not depend upon subjective assessment public goods,” such as if the goods are produced, everyone benefits Instead of analyzing in terms of benefits and burdens They are required to sustain a rightful condition. People can be compelled contribute apart from whether they personally benefit people can be compelled to contribute, not because they have accepted a benefit but rather because it is the defense of their nation as their system of laws. | Violation of a public space consists in failing to do your part, by failing to contribute, either positively to sustaining it, or negatively by taking up part of it for private purposes. The basic terms of public provision are dictated by the fact that it is mandatory. We have seen that the Kantian answer to the question of when cooperation is mandatory focuses on the preconditions of sustaining a condition of equal private freedom, in which no person is subject to the choice of another. Roads are a central example of this, and everyone can be compelled to contribute to them. A further question asks: on what terms can a free person be compelled to contribute to those social projects to which he or she can be compelled to contribute? The Kantian answer to this second question demands reciprocity: in sustaining a condition of private freedom, we are all in it together. The Kantian answer to the first question does not yet tell us what the relevant principle of contribution is. Kant’s political philosophy has additional resources, however, that generate a principle of contribution. As we saw in Chapter 2, Kant identifies a basic “internal” duty of rightful honor, expressed by the saying “Do not make yourself a mere means for others but be at the same time an end for them.” This obligation follows Public Right II: Roads to Freedom l 257 from the innate right of humanity that each of us has in his or her own person, and guarantees that you can have no more specific obligation that presupposes that you can be bound to act exclusively for the purposes of another. In the context of mandatory social cooperation, if you do your part but others do not do theirs, they have treated you as a mere means, because you have contributed to the achievement of their purposes. You set out to do your part; rather than doing theirs, they took advantage of your efforts. No parallel principle applies to private cooperation: whether, and on what terms, you confer a benefit on another person is entirely up to you. If things turn out differently than you had expected, and you bear a disproportionate burden, you have no claim against your contracting partner. It was up to you to protect yourself. Your responsibility, and the consequent lack of a cause of action, reflect the right of every selfdetermining being to voluntarily enter into binding arrangements with others on whatever terms he or she sees fit. Kant remarks that to require us to limit our contractual arrangements in light of some extrinsic conception of fairness would be to treat us like children, because we are free persons, each of us entitled to set and pursue our own purposes.29 The role of voluntariness is explicit in cases in which people negotiate terms, but it is no less important in cases in which a buyer simply accepts a seller’s offer, and in cases in which someone accepts something he or she knows to be valuable without asking about the price. If you order the special in a restaurant without asking its price, you have to pay for it. As Kant puts it, in voluntary private transactions, equity is “a mute divinity that cannot be heard.” The priority of private ordering cannot apply in cases of mandatory cooperation. Negotiations toward mutual agreement can only take place against the background of the entitlement of either of the parties to decline to cooperate at all. You can be held to what you agreed to because you did not have to agree to it. If you had no choice—if someone makes you an offer you can’t refuse—you cannot be held to its terms. Where cooperation is mandatory, agreement on terms is not even possible. As we have seen, Kant argues that there is only one type of mandatory cooperation: you are under an enforceable and unconditional obligation to enter and remain in a rightful condition, and to provide for its conditions; as such, you cannot attach terms to doing what you can already be forced to do. The only respect in which everyone can be thought to have set the specific terms is by having their representatives participate in the making of public law. Important though this is, it is not a sort of second-best approximation of private bargaining toward agreed terms. You have no entitlement to refuse to enter a rightful condition if you do not think the terms favorable enough, and neither does your representative. The most the representative can do is exercise judgment about how to achieve and sustain a rightful condition. To do so may sometimes require a weighing of interests and compromises, but that is not enough to turn it into a large-scale version of a private contract, not even a crude approximation of one. So mandatory cooperation cannot treat terms of interaction as reciprocal because they are voluntary. Instead, there is a more direct requirement of reciprocity: everyone must do his or her own part; the person who fails to do so violates reciprocity by taking advantage of the cooperative efforts of others, like the one who fails to keep up his end of a contract. From this perspective, the “free rider” wrongs his fellow citizens by taking advantage of their efforts. Thefree rider may claim—and it may even be true— that he would rather do without the rightful condition and go it alone. That claim is beside the point, because the obligation to enter a rightful condition is unconditional, that is, it does not depend upon any particular person’s subjective assessment of the benefits it will yield. Others are entitled to treat the creating and sustaining of a rightful condition as one of the free rider’s purposes, quite apart from what he may have to say about it. Thus they can rightly complain that they are being required to work for the purposes of another, or that they are being used by the free rider, and they can make this claim even if the free rider’s failure to contribute costs them nothing. The mandatory character of such cooperation generates a presumption in favor of an equal division of its burdens. Kant suggests that legislation that “goes against the law of equality in assigning the burdens of the state in matters of taxation, recruiting and so forth”30 is defective. Citizens are entitled to petition against such laws, because equal division is the basic case of mandatory cooperation. If everyone must do his or her part in jointly providing public spaces, those parts will be equal unless there are positive grounds for differentiation. The requirement that contribution in cases of mandatory cooperation be reciprocal is diffuse and open-ended. What exactly it requires in a particular case will often be unclear, even after some public decision has been made about how to measure the relevant burdens. This is not a problem for a principle of public law, however, because explicit legislation is required in order to determine the respective obligations of citizens to contribute. Any requirement of reciprocity will also need to be systematic, in exactly the same way that the system of public rights of way must be understood as systematic. It may be beyond the legitimate power of a public authority either to make traffic rules or to have a tax regime that distributes burdens in a grossly inequitable way, but it is plainly within its power to place specific burdens in ways that turn out to confer burdens and benefits unequally in particular cases. Focusing on the example of roads provides a useful reminder that many other examples in which citizens can be required to bear burdens for the sake of benefits that they may not enjoy directly need not be understood in terms of some more general calculus of benefits and burdens. In particular, it is often said to be the task of the state to provide what economists describe as “public goods,” such as public health and national defense. These are often characterized in terms of two features: if the goods are produced, everyone benefits, and it is difficult or impossible to exclude those who refuse to contribute from enjoying the bene fits. These features lead to positive externalities, that is, those who partic ipate confer benefits on those who do not. A rational agent considering whether to participate would conclude that she would do just as well taking advantage of the efforts of others. As a result of these problems of collective action, in particular free riding, these goods are not produced in adequate amounts by private actors in the market. Thus the state is said to have a role in their production. I do not mean to question the standard analysis of these goods in terms of collective action by rational agents on its own terms. The difficulty is with grounding mandatory cooperation or public provision in terms of benefits, burdens, or externalities. We saw already in our discussion of private right that externalities as such generate no issues of right; I do not need to pay you for the customers that come into my restaurant because of your nearby hotel, or the bees that pollinate my flowers because of your garden. The mere fact that problems of collective action may lead to an undersupply of a certain good, relative to people’s willingness to pay for it, does not underwrite mandatory contribution. The mere fact that a group of people are not able to coordinate to guarantee the production or preservation of something that they value does not entitle them to use the coercive apparatus of the state to compel others to join them in their efforts at producing it. Religious conformity or modest dress may be diffi cult to maintain without state support, but neither the difficulties posed by temptation nor the collective action problems that result underwrite state action.31 Instead of analyzing public health or national defense in terms of benefits and burdens, it is better to assimilate them to the example of roads. They are required to sustain a rightful condition. People can be compelled to contribute to genuine national self-defense quite apart from whether they personally stand to benefit from it. Perhaps some people would see their lives change little if their state were conquered by a hostile neighbor, as Kant’s life changed little during the Russian capture of Königsberg.32 Such people can be compelled to contribute, not because they have accepted a benefit of national defense, but rather because it is the defense of their nation, understood juridically, that is, as their system of laws. Another familiar public power, public health, has a similar structure. The state’s mandate to protect public health follows from its mandate to see to its own preservation. Thus the citizens can be compelled to pay taxes to support public health, and a particular citizen can be compelled to pay even if he or she has the financial wherewithal to take private precautions against plagues and epidemics, or is so elderly that public health measures will add little to his or her expected life span. | 10,896 | <h4>[3] Compulsory voting is key to avoiding freeriding. Put away coercion turns – goods produced from voting are public goods so it’s not subject to reciprocal constraints</h4><p><strong>Ripstein 9</strong> [Arthur Ripstein “Force and Freedom”, Harvard University Press 2009] // SJ AME</p><p><u><strong>Violation of a<mark> </mark>public space consists in</u></strong> failing to do your part, by <u><strong>failing to contribute</u></strong>, either positively to sustaining it, or negatively by taking up part of it for private purposes. The basic terms of public provision are dictated by the fact that it is mandatory. We have seen that the Kantian answer to the question of when <u><strong>cooperation is mandatory</u></strong> focuses <u><strong>on the preconditions of sustaining a condition of equal private freedom</u></strong>, in which no person is subject to the choice of another. Roads are a central example of this, and everyone can be compelled to contribute to them. A further question asks: on what terms can a free person be compelled to contribute to those social projects to which he or she can be compelled to contribute? The Kantian answer to this second question demands reciprocity: in sustaining a condition of private freedom, we are all in it together. The Kantian answer to the first question does not yet tell us what the relevant principle of contribution is. Kant’s political philosophy has additional resources, however, that generate a principle of contribution. As we saw in Chapter 2, Kant identifies a basic “internal” duty of rightful honor, expressed by the saying “Do not make yourself a mere means for others but be at the same time an end for them.” This obligation follows Public Right II: Roads to Freedom l 257 from the innate right of humanity that each of us has in his or her own person, and guarantees that you can have no more specific obligation that presupposes that you can be bound to act exclusively for the purposes of another<u><strong><mark>. In </mark>the context of<mark> mandatory</mark> social <mark>cooperation, if you do your part but others do not</mark> do theirs<mark>, they have treated you as a</mark> mere <mark>means,</mark> because you have contributed to the achievement of their purposes. You set out to do your part; rather than doing theirs, they took advantage of your efforts. No parallel principle applies to private cooperation</u></strong>: whether, and on what terms, you confer a benefit on another person is entirely up to you. If things turn out differently than you had expected, and you bear a disproportionate burden, you have no claim against your contracting partner. It was up to you to protect yourself. Your responsibility, and the consequent lack of a cause of action, reflect the right of every selfdetermining being to voluntarily enter into binding arrangements with others on whatever terms he or she sees fit. Kant remarks that to require us to limit our contractual arrangements in light of some extrinsic conception of fairness would be to treat us like children, because we are free persons, each of us entitled to set and pursue our own purposes.29 The role of voluntariness is explicit in cases in which people negotiate terms, but it is no less important in cases in which a buyer simply accepts a seller’s offer, and in cases in which someone accepts something he or she knows to be valuable without asking about the price. If you order the special in a restaurant without asking its price, you have to pay for it. As Kant puts it, in voluntary private transactions, equity is “a mute divinity that cannot be heard.” <u><strong>The priority of <mark>private ordering cannot apply in </mark>cases of <mark>mandatory cooperation</mark>. </u></strong>Negotiations toward mutual agreement can only take place against the background of the entitlement of either of the parties to decline to cooperate at all. <u><strong><mark>You can be held to what you agreed to because you did not have to agree</mark> to it. </u></strong>If you had no choice—if someone makes you an offer you can’t refuse—you cannot be held to its terms. <u><strong>Where cooperation is mandatory, agreement on terms is not even possible</u></strong>. As we have seen, Kant argues <u><strong>that there is only one type of mandatory cooperation: you are under an</u></strong> enforceable and <u><strong>unconditional obligation to enter and remain in a rightful condition,</u></strong> and to provide for its conditions; as such, you cannot attach terms to doing what you can already be forced to do. The only respect in which everyone can be thought to have set the specific terms is by having their representatives participate in the making of public law. Important though this is, it is not a sort of second-best approximation of private bargaining toward agreed terms. You have no entitlement to refuse to enter a rightful condition if you do not think the terms favorable enough, and neither does your representative. The most the representative can do is exercise judgment about how to achieve and sustain a rightful condition. To do so may sometimes require a weighing of interests and compromises, but that is not enough to turn it into a large-scale version of a private contract, not even a crude approximation of one. So <u><strong>mandatory cooperation cannot treat terms of interaction as reciprocal because they are voluntary.</u></strong> Instead, there is a more direct requirement of reciprocity: everyone must do his or her own part; the person who fails to do so violates reciprocity by taking advantage of the cooperative efforts of others, like the one who fails to keep up his end of a contract. From this perspective, <u><strong><mark>the “free rider” wrongs </mark>his fellow <mark>citizens by taking advantage of their efforts. The</mark>free rider <mark>may claim</u></strong></mark>—and it may even be true— <u><strong><mark>that he would rather </mark>do <mark>without the rightful condition</mark> </u></strong>and go it alone<u><strong>. <mark>That claim is beside the point, because the obligation to enter</mark> a rightful condition <mark>is unconditional</mark>,</u></strong> that is, it <u><strong><mark>does not depend upon</mark> any particular person’s <mark>subjective assessment</mark> </u></strong>of the benefits it will yield. Others are entitled to treat the creating and sustaining of a rightful condition as one of the free rider’s purposes, quite apart from what he may have to say about it. Thus they can rightly complain that they are being required to work for the purposes of another, or that they are being used by the free rider, and they can make this claim even if the free rider’s failure to contribute costs them nothing. The mandatory character of such cooperation generates a presumption in favor of an equal division of its burdens. Kant suggests that legislation that “goes against the law of equality in assigning the burdens of the state in matters of taxation, recruiting and so forth”30 is defective. Citizens are entitled to petition against such laws, because equal division is the basic case of mandatory cooperation. If everyone must do his or her part in jointly providing public spaces, those parts will be equal unless there are positive grounds for differentiation. The requirement that contribution in cases of mandatory cooperation be reciprocal is diffuse and open-ended. What exactly it requires in a particular case will often be unclear, even after some public decision has been made about how to measure the relevant burdens. This is not a problem for a principle of public law, however, because explicit legislation is required in order to determine the respective obligations of citizens to contribute. Any requirement of reciprocity will also need to be systematic, in exactly the same way that the system of public rights of way must be understood as systematic. It may be beyond the legitimate power of a public authority either to make traffic rules or to have a tax regime that distributes burdens in a grossly inequitable way, but it is plainly within its power to place specific burdens in ways that turn out to confer burdens and benefits unequally in particular cases. <u><strong>Focusing on the example of roads provides a useful reminder that many other examples in which citizens can be required to bear burdens for the sake of benefits that they may not enjoy directly</u></strong> need not be understood in terms of some more general calculus of benefits and burdens. In particular, <u><strong>it is</u></strong> often said to be <u><strong>the task of the state to provide</u></strong> what economists describe as “<u><strong><mark>public goods,” such as</mark> public health</u></strong> and national defense<u><strong>.</u></strong> These are often characterized in terms of two features: <u><strong><mark>if the goods are produced, everyone benefits</u></strong></mark>, and it is difficult or impossible to exclude those who refuse to contribute from enjoying the bene fits. These features lead to positive externalities, that is, those who partic ipate confer benefits on those who do not. A rational agent considering whether to participate would conclude that she would do just as well taking advantage of the efforts of others. As a result of these problems of collective action, in particular free riding, these goods are not produced in adequate amounts by private actors in the market. Thus the state is said to have a role in their production. I do not mean to question the standard analysis of these goods in terms of collective action by rational agents on its own terms. The difficulty is with grounding mandatory cooperation or public provision in terms of benefits, burdens, or externalities. We saw already in our discussion of private right that externalities as such generate no issues of right; I do not need to pay you for the customers that come into my restaurant because of your nearby hotel, or the bees that pollinate my flowers because of your garden. The mere fact that problems of collective action may lead to an undersupply of a certain good, relative to people’s willingness to pay for it, does not underwrite mandatory contribution. The mere fact that a group of people are not able to coordinate to guarantee the production or preservation of something that they value does not entitle them to use the coercive apparatus of the state to compel others to join them in their efforts at producing it. Religious conformity or modest dress may be diffi cult to maintain without state support, but neither the difficulties posed by temptation nor the collective action problems that result underwrite state action.31 <u><strong><mark>Instead of analyzing</mark> </u></strong>public health or <u><strong>national defense</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>in terms of benefits and burdens</u></strong></mark>, it is better to assimilate them to the example of roads. <u><strong><mark>They</u></strong></mark> <u><strong><mark>are required to sustain a rightful condition. People can be compelled</mark> to <mark>contribute</mark> to genuine national self-defense quite <mark>apart from whether they personally</mark> stand to <mark>benefit</mark> from it.</u></strong> Perhaps some people would see their lives change little if their state were conquered by a hostile neighbor, as Kant’s life changed little during the Russian capture of Königsberg.32 Such <u><strong><mark>people can be compelled to contribute, not because they have accepted a benefit</mark> of national defense, <mark>but rather because it</mark> <mark>is the defense of their nation</u></strong></mark>, understood juridically, that is, <u><strong><mark>as their system of laws.</u></strong></mark> Another familiar public power, public health, has a similar structure. The state’s mandate to protect public health follows from its mandate to see to its own preservation. Thus the citizens can be compelled to pay taxes to support public health, and a particular citizen can be compelled to pay even if he or she has the financial wherewithal to take private precautions against plagues and epidemics, or is so elderly that public health measures will add little to his or her expected life span.</p> | 1AC R3 | null | Offense | 360,959 | 188 | 76,101 | ./documents/hsld20/StrakeJesuit/Ge/Strake%20Jesuit-Georges-Aff-Loyola-Round3.docx | 874,159 | A | Loyola | 3 | San Mateo Independent YR | Tarun Ratnasabapathy | 1AC - Korsgaard
1NC - Util Climate DA AC
1AR - ACC or AFC Must Have Counter-Advocacy Text Must Defend CP DA
2NR - ACC or AFC Must Have Counter-Advocacy Text Must Defend CP DA
2AR - Must Have Counter-Advocacy Text | hsld20/StrakeJesuit/Ge/Strake%20Jesuit-Georges-Aff-Loyola-Round3.docx | null | 73,798 | JoGe | Strake Jesuit JoGe | null | Jo..... | Ge..... | null | null | 24,736 | StrakeJesuit | Strake Jesuit | TX | null | 1,028 | hsld20 | HS LD 2020-21 | 2,020 | ld | hs | 1 |
4,182,996 | 4. CAP GOOD - Capitalism key to space colonization---extinction. | Kovic '19 | Kovic '19 [Marko; March 2019; co-founder president of the Zurich Institute of Public Affairs Research; "The future of energy," https://osf.io/preprints/socarxiv/aswz9/download] | Ideally mitigation of climate risks will coincide with and contribute to the development of improved or even entirely novel sources of energy that will increase the long-term chances of humankind’s survival by means of space colonization This is not an unrealistic expectation given that the mitigation of climate risks consists of replacing fossil fuels with other, less harmful sources of energy some climate change mitigation strategies might actually harm the long-term prospects of humankind
it is possible that dominant climate change mitigation will actively exclude any form of nuclear energy from the repertoire of climate-friendly energy sources. Existing and experimental fission reactors could play a significant role in replacing carbon-heavy energy sources If such a scenario came to be, our attempts at colonizing space would almost certainly fail There are currently no alternatives to fission and fusion, and it is highly improbable that Solar power alone could suffice for sustaining extraterrestrial habitats
there is some probability that climate change mitigation strategies will change the social order towards a degrowth philosophy. Degrowth is a vague socio-economic concept and social movement that calls for a contraction of the global and national economies by means of lower production and consumption rates and more profound changes to the “capitalist” system of economic production degrowth would almost certainly be a highly effective measure for mitigating climate change the amount of greenhouse gases that are being emitted would accordingly drastically sink. From the long-term perspective of humankind’s survival, degrowth is problematic First, there is a risk that the general contraction of economic activity would also slow or eliminate progress in the domain of energy which would, reduce the probability of successful space colonization due to an absence of suitable energy sources Second, and more fundamental: If degrowth were to become a dominant societal paradigm it is uncertain whether the long-term survival of humankind by means of space colonization would be regarded a desirable goal In a literal sense, establishing extraterrestrial colonies would mean growth the size of the total human population would grow,
In a more philosophical sense, degrowth might even be antithetical to space colonization Even though both degrowth and space colonization have a similar moral goal increasing wellbeing the ends to that goal are very different. Within degrowth the goal is, not to “live beyond our means”: We should strive for “ecological balance”, and such a state should increase the average wellbeing But the frame of reference is the status quo; Earth and humankind as we know it today. Space colonization, operates with a much larger frame of reference All the future generations of humans who could enjoy wellbeing if we succeed in colonizing space and who will categorically be denied that wellbeing if we fail to colonize space The goal of space colonization as a moral project is not to live beyond our means, but to actively redefine and expand what our means are through scientific and technological progress | space colonization is realistic some climate strategies harm long-term prospects
it is possible mitigation will exclude nuclear energy attempts at colonizing space would fail
there is probability strategies will change towards degrowth From long-term perspective of survival, degrowth is problematic contraction of economic activity would slow or eliminate progress in energy, which would reduce probability of space colonization If degrowth were a dominant paradigm, it is uncertain whether space colonization would be desirable establishing colonies would mean growth
degrowth might be antithetical to colonization the goal is not to “live beyond our means” the frame of reference is the status quo humankind today. Space colonization operates with a larger frame All future generations denied wellbeing if we fail to colonize | Ideally, the mitigation of climate risks will coincide with and contribute to the development of improved or even entirely novel sources of energy that will increase the long-term chances of humankind’s survival by means of space colonization. This is not an unrealistic expectation, given that the mitigation of climate risks consists, to a large degree, of replacing fossil fuels with other, less harmful sources of energy. However, some climate change mitigation strategies might actually harm the long-term prospects of humankind.
First, it is possible that dominant climate change mitigation strategies will actively exclude any form of nuclear energy from the repertoire of climate-friendly energy sources. Existing and experimental (molten salt) fission reactors could play a significant role in replacing carbon-heavy energy sources, but pro-environmental attitudes often overlap with anti-nuclear sentiments [65]. As a result, and in combination with other problems such as large-scale market failures of existing fission reactors (one of the reasons being that generating electricity from fossil fuels is cheaper) [66], nuclear fission does not currently have significant standing as a “cleantech” contribution to climate change mitigation. From a long-term perspective, an unfavorable view of nuclear energy in the context of climate change might mean that technological progress in the areas of nuclear fission and fusion might come to a halt (for example, due to explicit bans or implicit disincentives). If such a scenario came to be, our attempts at colonizing space would almost certainly fail: There are currently no alternatives to fission and fusion, and it is highly improbable that Solar power alone could suffice for sustaining extraterrestrial habitats.
Second, there is some probability that climate change mitigation strategies will change the social order towards a degrowth philosophy. Degrowth is a vague socio-economic concept and social movement that, in general, calls for a contraction of the global and national economies by means of lower production and consumption rates, and, to some degree, to more profound changes to the “capitalist” system of economic production [67]. Degrowth or degrowth-like approaches are being actively considered as climate risk mitigation strategies [68, 69], and degrowth would almost certainly be a highly effective measure for mitigating climate change. After all, if we were to drastically reduce or even completely eliminate the (industrial) sources of greenhouse gases, the amount of greenhouse gases that are being emitted would accordingly drastically sink. From the long-term perspective of humankind’s survival, degrowth is problematic in at least two ways. First, there is a risk that the general contraction of economic activity would also slow or eliminate progress in the domain of energy, which would, in turn, reduce the probability of successful space colonization due to an absence of suitable energy sources. Second, and more fundamental: If degrowth were to become a dominant societal paradigm, it is uncertain whether the long-term survival of humankind by means of space colonization would be regarded a desirable goal. In a literal sense, establishing extraterrestrial colonies would mean growth; the size of the total human population would grow, and the area of space-time that humans occupy would grow.
In a more philosophical sense, degrowth might even be antithetical to space colonization. Even though both degrowth and space colonization have a similar moral goal – increasing wellbeing – , the ends to that goal are very different. Within degrowth philosophy, the goal is, metaphorically speaking, not to “live beyond our means”: We should strive for “ecological balance”, and such a state should increase the average wellbeing. But the frame of reference is the status quo; Earth and humankind as we know it today. Space colonization, on the other hand, operates with a much larger frame of reference: All the future generations of humans (and other sentient beings) who could enjoy wellbeing if we succeed in colonizing space – and who will categorically be denied that wellbeing if we fail to colonize space [70]. The goal of space colonization as a moral project is not to live beyond our means, but to actively redefine and expand what our means are through scientific and technological progress. | 4,399 | <h4>4. <u>CAP GOOD</u> - Capitalism key to <u>space colonization</u>---extinction. </h4><p><strong>Kovic '19 </strong>[Marko; March 2019; co-founder president of the Zurich Institute of Public Affairs Research; "The future of energy," https://osf.io/preprints/socarxiv/aswz9/download] </p><p><u>Ideally</u>, the <u>mitigation of climate risks will</u> <u><strong>coincide</u></strong> <u>with and</u> <u><strong>contribute</u></strong> <u>to the development of improved or even entirely novel <strong>sources of energy</u></strong> <u>that will increase the <strong>long-term chances of humankind’s survival</u></strong> <u>by means of</u> <u><strong><mark>space colonization</u></strong></mark>. <u>This <mark>is</mark> <strong>not an un<mark>realistic</mark> expectation</u></strong>, <u>given that the mitigation of climate risks consists</u>, to a large degree, <u>of replacing fossil fuels with other, less harmful sources of energy</u>. However, <u><mark>some climate</mark> change mitigation <mark>strategies</mark> might actually</u> <u><strong><mark>harm</mark> the <mark>long-term prospects</mark> of humankind</u></strong>.</p><p>First, <u><mark>it is possible</mark> that dominant climate change <mark>mitigation</u></mark> strategies <u><mark>will</mark> actively <strong><mark>exclude</strong></mark> any form of</u> <u><strong><mark>nuclear energy</u></strong></mark> <u>from the repertoire of climate-friendly energy sources. Existing and experimental</u> (molten salt) <u>fission reactors could play a significant role in replacing carbon-heavy energy sources</u>, but pro-environmental attitudes often overlap with anti-nuclear sentiments [65]. As a result, and in combination with other problems such as large-scale market failures of existing fission reactors (one of the reasons being that generating electricity from fossil fuels is cheaper) [66], nuclear fission does not currently have significant standing as a “cleantech” contribution to climate change mitigation. From a long-term perspective, an unfavorable view of nuclear energy in the context of climate change might mean that technological progress in the areas of nuclear fission and fusion might come to a halt (for example, due to explicit bans or implicit disincentives). <u>If such a scenario came to be, our <mark>attempts at <strong>colonizing space</strong> would</mark> almost</u> <u><strong>certainly <mark>fail</u></strong></mark>: <u>There are currently no alternatives to <strong>fission</strong> and <strong>fusion</strong>, and it is</u> <u><strong>highly improbable</u></strong> <u>that Solar power alone could suffice for sustaining <strong>extraterrestrial habitats</u></strong>.</p><p>Second, <u><mark>there is</mark> some <mark>probability</mark> that climate change mitigation <mark>strategies will <strong>change</mark> the social order</u></strong> <u><mark>towards</mark> a</u> <u><strong><mark>degrowth</u></strong></mark> <u>philosophy. Degrowth is a vague socio-economic concept and social movement that</u>, in general, <u>calls for a</u> <u><strong>contraction</u></strong> <u>of the global and national economies by means of</u> <u><strong>lower production</u></strong> <u>and</u> <u><strong>consumption rates</u></strong>, <u>and</u>, to some degree, to <u>more <strong>profound changes</u></strong> <u>to the “capitalist” system of</u> <u><strong>economic production</u></strong> [67]. Degrowth or degrowth-like approaches are being actively considered as climate risk mitigation strategies [68, 69], and <u>degrowth would almost certainly be a highly effective measure for mitigating climate change</u>. After all, if we were to drastically reduce or even completely eliminate the (industrial) sources of greenhouse gases, <u>the amount of greenhouse gases that are being emitted would accordingly drastically sink. <mark>From</mark> the <strong><mark>long-term perspective</u></strong> <u>of</mark> <strong>humankind’s <mark>survival</strong>, degrowth is <strong>problematic</u></strong></mark> in at least two ways. <u>First, there is a risk that the general <mark>contraction of economic activity would</mark> also <mark>slow or</u> <u><strong>eliminate progress</u></strong> <u>in</mark> the domain of</u> <u><strong><mark>energy</u></strong>, <u>which would</mark>,</u> in turn, <u><mark>reduce</mark> the <mark>probability of</mark> <strong>successful <mark>space colonization</u></strong></mark> <u>due to an absence of <strong>suitable energy sources</u></strong>. <u>Second, and more fundamental: <mark>If degrowth were</mark> to become <mark>a</u> <u><strong>dominant</mark> societal <mark>paradigm</u></strong>, <u>it is <strong>uncertain</strong> whether</mark> the long-term survival of humankind by means of <strong><mark>space colonization</u></strong> <u>would be</mark> regarded a <strong><mark>desirable</mark> goal</u></strong>. <u>In a literal sense, <mark>establishing</mark> <strong>extraterrestrial <mark>colonies would mean growth</u></strong></mark>; <u>the size of the total human population would grow,</u> and the area of space-time that humans occupy would grow.</p><p><u>In a more philosophical sense, <mark>degrowth might</mark> even<mark> be</u> <u><strong>antithetical to </mark>space <mark>colonization</u></strong></mark>. <u>Even though both degrowth and space colonization have a similar moral goal</u> – <u>increasing wellbeing</u> – , <u>the ends to that goal are very different. Within degrowth</u> philosophy, <u><mark>the goal is</mark>,</u> metaphorically speaking, <u><mark>not to “live beyond our means”</mark>: We should strive for “ecological balance”, and such a state should increase the</u> <u><strong>average wellbeing</u></strong>. <u>But <mark>the frame of reference is the status quo</mark>; Earth and <mark>humankind</mark> as we know it <strong><mark>today</strong>. Space colonization</mark>,</u> on the other hand, <u><mark>operates with a</mark> much</u> <u><strong><mark>larger frame</strong></mark> of reference</u>: <u><strong><mark>All</mark> the <mark>future generations</mark> of humans</u></strong> (and other sentient beings) <u>who could enjoy wellbeing if we succeed in colonizing space</u> – <u>and who will categorically be <strong><mark>denied</mark> that <mark>wellbeing</u></strong> <u>if we fail to colonize</mark> space</u> [70]. <u>The goal of space colonization as a <strong>moral project</u></strong> <u>is not to live beyond our means, but to actively <strong>redefine</strong> and</u> <u><strong>expand</u></strong> <u>what our means are through scientific and <strong>technological progress</u></strong>.</p> | 2AC | null | 2AC – AT: Cap K – Policy Short | 2,251 | 251 | 143,778 | ./documents/hspolicy22/GlenbrookSouth/ArKw/GlenbrookSouth-ArKw-Aff-03---University-of-Michigan-Round-5.docx | 943,418 | A | 03 - University of Michigan | 5 | Interlake MT | Brandon Kelley | 1AC - Space Assets
1NC - Ukraine Deal CP, Cap K, NDAA Politics DA
2NC - Cap K
1NR - Ukraine Deal CP
2NR - Cap K | hspolicy22/GlenbrookSouth/ArKw/GlenbrookSouth-ArKw-Aff-03---University-of-Michigan-Round-5.docx | 2022-11-19 12:14:54 | 80,327 | ArKw | Glenbrook South ArKw | Contact info
Ana Arzoumanidis - 1A/2N - [email protected]
Sarah Kwon - 2A/1N - [email protected] | An..... | Ar..... | Sa..... | Kw..... | 26,718 | GlenbrookSouth | Glenbrook South | IL | null | 2,002 | hspolicy22 | HS Policy 2022-23 | 2,022 | cx | hs | 2 |
1,210,662 | AND spills-over to Sino-India war. | Klare 20, | Michael T. Klare 20, Five Colleges Professor of Peace and World Security Studies at Hampshire College, Ph.D. from the Graduate School of the Union Institute, BA and MA from Columbia University, Member of the Board of Director at the Arms Control Association, Defense Correspondent for The Nation; “Climate Change, Water Scarcity, and the Potential for Interstate Conflict in South Asia”; Journal of Strategic Security; 2020; Vol. 13, No. 4, p 112-114//SJ | China, India, and the Brahmaputra River
potential for interstate conflict–even nuclear conflict–over shared water supplies arises in major river at Brahmaputra, which originates in China and traverses much of northeastern India it flows in southwesterly direction towards confluence with the Ganges and thence exit into the Bay of Bengal. For Chinese Brahmaputra is an important engine of hydroelectric power For the Indians, it is a valuable source of irrigation water agriculture-dependent regions Leaders of both countries have made little effort to reach a mutual understanding regarding its future development
Beijing insists was once part of the kingdom of Tibet, and belongs to China; New Delhi claims it is a legitimate part of India Arunachal Pradesh remains continuing source of friction in Sino-Indian relations and spark for violent conflict
Another potential source of friction between China and India arises from Chinese plans (or rumors of such plans) to divert water from the upper Brahmaputra and funnel it via a series of tunnels and canals to northeastern China, where existing supplies are hugely inadequate.33 While dismissed by many Chinese experts as overly ambitious and costly, the notion of diverting water from the Brahmaputra has generated considerable anxiety in India, where experts fear that the resulting decline in water flow into the Indian section of the river would threaten agricultural productivity. Given the centrality of farming in the Indian economy and political system, any Chinese move to proceed with such a diversion project could lead to increased tension between the two countries.
Given Brahmaputra’s critical importance to agriculture and economic activity in both countries significant longterm decline in its flow would be highly disruptive causing widespread hardship and social unrest.
Chinese leadership desperate to provide additional supply to China’s water-starved northeast more inclined to proceed with water diversion projects Coming at time of equivalent water scarcity in India certain to trigger a harsh Indian response pushing China and India towards an adversarial rather than competitive relationship Border clashes related to control of rivers are not out of the question
once fighting breaks out impossible to predict succeeding chain of events, and any outcome is conceivable minor skirmish might not be a cause for alarm in United States, but larger war between those two countries undoubtedly would be. Both are armed with nuclear weapons, Washington views India as strategic counterweight to China crushing defeat of India would be viewed as potential threat to American national interests and precipitate U.S. military intervention mere possibility of combat has made this scenario a matter of deep concern for security analysts | China, India,
potential for nuclear conflict arises Brahmaputra important engine of hydroelectric power Indians it is valuable source of irrigation
Arunachal Pradesh remains source of friction and spark for violent conflict
leadership desperate to provide additional supply inclined with water diversion projects pushing China and India towards adversarial
impossible to predict succeeding chain of events larger war between countries armed with nuc s defeat of India viewed as potential threat to American national interests precipitate U.S. military intervention | China, India, and the Brahmaputra River
The potential for interstate conflict–even nuclear conflict–over shared water supplies arises in the case of another major river at risk from climate change: The Brahmaputra, which originates in China and traverses much of northeastern India before merging with the Ganges in Bangladesh and emptying into the Bay of Bengal. The fifth-largest river in the world by volume of water flow, the Brahmaputra starts on the northern slopes of the Himalayas and flows easterly across the southern Tibetan plateau (where it is known as the Yarlung Tsangpo) before making a nearly 180-degree turn and crossing into the Indian state of Arunachal Pradesh; from there, it flows in a southwesterly direction towards its confluence with the Ganges and thence its exit into the Bay of Bengal. For the Chinese, the Brahmaputra is an important engine of hydroelectric power; they have already installed one dam on the river, at Zangmu, and have announced plans for at least three more. For the Indians, it is a valuable source of irrigation water, especially in agriculture-dependent regions of the northeast. Leaders of both countries are fully aware of their counterparts’ interests and concerns over the river but have made little effort to reach a mutual understanding–let alone any formal agreements–regarding its future development.31
Several factors make the future status of the Brahmaputra a matter of deep concern to security analysts. To begin with, the river enters India through the state of Arunachal Pradesh, an area of northeastern India abutting Tibet that is claimed by both countries. Beijing insists that this region was once part of the kingdom of Tibet, and so belongs to China; New Delhi claims it is a legitimate part of India under a 1914 treaty between Tibet and Great Britain. The two sides fought a war here in 1962, with India suffering significant battlefield setbacks but China agreeing to restore the status quo ante. The countries have not been able to resolve the ownership dispute in subsequent years, despite intermittent negotiations, and both continue to maintain substantial military forces in the region. To this day, discord over Arunachal Pradesh remains a continuing source of friction in Sino-Indian relations and a potential spark for violent conflict.32
Another potential source of friction between China and India arises from Chinese plans (or rumors of such plans) to divert water from the upper Brahmaputra and funnel it via a series of tunnels and canals to northeastern China, where existing supplies are hugely inadequate.33 While dismissed by many Chinese experts as overly ambitious and costly, the notion of diverting water from the Brahmaputra has generated considerable anxiety in India, where experts fear that the resulting decline in water flow into the Indian section of the river would threaten agricultural productivity. Given the centrality of farming in the Indian economy and political system, any Chinese move to proceed with such a diversion project could lead to increased tension between the two countries.
Few analysts believe that a Sino-Indian conflict over the Brahmaputra is likely in the years immediately ahead. Both countries have strong motives for maintaining friendly–if not necessarily, warm–relations between them, and water issues have not yet dominated the bilateral agenda. This, however, is where global warming enters the picture. The Brahmaputra, like the Indus, draws much of its flow during dry seasons from the melting of Himalayan glaciers–and these, as has already been noted, are melting as a result of climate change, and could eventually disappear. For both China and India, the melting of the Himalayan glaciers will have momentous consequences. Given the Brahmaputra’s critical importance to agriculture and economic activity in both countries, any significant longterm decline in its flow would be highly disruptive, causing widespread hardship and social unrest.
Under these more stressful conditions, the Chinese leadership, desperate to provide additional supply to China’s water-starved northeast, might be more inclined to proceed with water diversion projects on the Brahmaputra and other shared river systems.36 Coming at a time of equivalent water scarcity in India, such an effort is almost certain to trigger a harsh Indian response. “The most salient climate-related point of conflict [between China and India] could be China’s move to divert the upstream waters of rivers originating in the Himalayan watershed,” the NIC warned in a special report on climate change and India. “If China was determined to move forward with such a scheme, it could become a major element in pushing China and India towards an adversarial rather than simply a competitive relationship. Border clashes related to control of the rivers are not out of the question.”
Any conflict between China and India over the waters of the Brahmaputra, should one occur, is most likely to remain a localized affair, without provoking a full-scale mobilization of forces on both sides. During the 1962 war over Arunachal Pradesh, Chinese army troops engaged their Indian counterparts in disputed areas along the border, but neither side escalated to large-scale combat. However, once fighting breaks out, it is impossible to predict the succeeding chain of events, and any outcome is conceivable. A minor skirmish along the Indo-Chinese border might not be a cause for alarm in the United States, but a larger war between those two countries undoubtedly would be. Both are armed with nuclear weapons, and Washington views India as a strategic counterweight to China.38 A crushing defeat of India would be viewed as a potential threat to American national interests and might conceivably precipitate U.S. military intervention. Where that might lead is anyone’s guess, but the mere possibility of such combat has made this scenario a matter of deep concern for security analysts in Washington.39 | 5,991 | <h4>AND spills-over to <u>Sino-India</u> war.</h4><p>Michael T. <strong>Klare 20,<u></strong> Five Colleges Professor of Peace and World Security Studies at Hampshire College, Ph.D. from the Graduate School of the Union Institute, BA and MA from Columbia University, Member of the Board of Director at the Arms Control Association, Defense Correspondent for The Nation; “Climate Change, Water Scarcity, and the Potential for Interstate Conflict in South Asia”; Journal of Strategic Security; 2020; Vol. 13, No. 4, p 112-114//SJ</p><p><strong><mark>China, India</strong>,</mark> and the Brahmaputra River</p><p></u>The <u><mark>potential for</mark> interstate conflict–even <strong><mark>nuclear conflict</strong></mark>–over shared water supplies <strong><mark>arises</strong></mark> in</u> the case of another <u>major river at</u> risk from climate change: The <u>Brahmaputra, which originates in China and traverses much of northeastern India</u> before merging with the Ganges in Bangladesh and emptying into the Bay of Bengal. The fifth-largest river in the world by volume of water flow, the Brahmaputra starts on the northern slopes of the Himalayas and flows easterly across the southern Tibetan plateau (where it is known as the Yarlung Tsangpo) before making a nearly 180-degree turn and crossing into the Indian state of Arunachal Pradesh; from there, <u>it flows in</u> a <u>southwesterly direction towards</u> its <u>confluence with the Ganges and thence</u> its <u>exit into the Bay of Bengal. For</u> the <u><strong>Chinese</u></strong>, the <u><mark>Brahmaputra</mark> is an <strong><mark>important</strong></mark> <mark>engine of</mark> <strong><mark>hydroelectric power</u></strong></mark>; they have already installed one dam on the river, at Zangmu, and have announced plans for at least three more. <u>For the <mark>Indians</mark>, <mark>it is</mark> a <mark>valuable source of irrigation</mark> water</u>, especially in <u>agriculture-dependent regions</u> of the northeast. <u>Leaders of both countries</u> are fully aware of their counterparts’ interests and concerns over the river but <u>have made <strong>little effort</strong> to reach a <strong>mutual understanding</u></strong>–let alone any formal agreements–<u>regarding its future <strong>development</u></strong>.31</p><p>Several factors make the future status of the Brahmaputra a matter of deep concern to security analysts. To begin with, the river enters India through the state of Arunachal Pradesh, an area of northeastern India abutting Tibet that is claimed by both countries. <u>Beijing insists</u> that this region <u>was once part of</u> <u>the kingdom of Tibet, and</u> so <u>belongs to China; New Delhi claims it is a legitimate part of India</u> under a 1914 treaty between Tibet and Great Britain. The two sides fought a war here in 1962, with India suffering significant battlefield setbacks but China agreeing to restore the status quo ante. The countries have not been able to resolve the ownership dispute in subsequent years, despite intermittent negotiations, and both continue to maintain substantial military forces in the region. To this day, discord over <u><mark>Arunachal Pradesh</mark> <mark>remains</u></mark> a <u>continuing <strong><mark>source</strong></mark> <mark>of</mark> <strong><mark>friction</strong></mark> in Sino-Indian relations <mark>and</u></mark> a potential <u><strong><mark>spark</strong></mark> <mark>for</mark> <strong><mark>violent conflict</u></strong></mark>.32</p><p><u>Another potential source of friction between China and India arises from Chinese plans (or rumors of such plans) to divert water from the upper Brahmaputra and funnel it via a series of tunnels and canals to northeastern China, where existing supplies are hugely inadequate.33 While dismissed by many Chinese experts as overly ambitious and costly, the notion of diverting water from the Brahmaputra has generated considerable anxiety in India, where experts fear that the resulting decline in water flow into the Indian section of the river would threaten agricultural productivity. Given the centrality of farming in the Indian economy and political system, any Chinese move to proceed with such a diversion project could lead to increased tension between the two countries.</p><p></u>Few analysts believe that a Sino-Indian conflict over the Brahmaputra is likely in the years immediately ahead. Both countries have strong motives for maintaining friendly–if not necessarily, warm–relations between them, and water issues have not yet dominated the bilateral agenda. This, however, is where global warming enters the picture. The Brahmaputra, like the Indus, draws much of its flow during dry seasons from the melting of Himalayan glaciers–and these, as has already been noted, are melting as a result of climate change, and could eventually disappear. For both China and India, the melting of the Himalayan glaciers will have momentous consequences. <u>Given</u> the <u>Brahmaputra’s critical importance to agriculture and <strong>economic activity</strong> in both countries</u>, any <u>significant <strong>longterm decline</strong> in its flow would be highly <strong>disruptive</u></strong>, <u>causing <strong>widespread hardship</strong> and <strong>social unrest</strong>.</p><p></u>Under these more stressful conditions, the <u>Chinese <strong><mark>leadership</u></strong></mark>, <u><strong><mark>desperate</strong></mark> <mark>to provide</mark> <strong><mark>additional supply</strong></mark> to China’s water-starved northeast</u>, might be <u>more <strong><mark>inclined</strong></mark> to proceed <mark>with</mark> <strong><mark>water diversion</strong></mark> <mark>projects</u></mark> on the Brahmaputra and other shared river systems.36 <u>Coming at</u> a <u>time of equivalent <strong>water scarcity</strong> in <strong>India</u></strong>, such an effort is almost <u>certain to <strong>trigger</strong> a <strong>harsh Indian response</u></strong>. “The most salient climate-related point of conflict [between China and India] could be China’s move to divert the upstream waters of rivers originating in the Himalayan watershed,” the NIC warned in a special report on climate change and India. “If China was determined to move forward with such a scheme, it could become a major element in <u><strong><mark>pushing</strong></mark> <mark>China and India towards</mark> an <strong><mark>adversarial</strong></mark> rather than</u> simply a <u>competitive <strong>relationship</u></strong>. <u><strong>Border clashes</strong> related to control of</u> the <u>rivers are <strong>not out</strong> of the <strong>question</u></strong>.”</p><p>Any conflict between China and India over the waters of the Brahmaputra, should one occur, is most likely to remain a localized affair, without provoking a full-scale mobilization of forces on both sides. During the 1962 war over Arunachal Pradesh, Chinese army troops engaged their Indian counterparts in disputed areas along the border, but neither side escalated to large-scale combat. However, <u>once fighting breaks out</u>, it is <u><strong><mark>impossible</strong></mark> <mark>to</mark> <strong><mark>predict</u></strong></mark> the <u><mark>succeeding chain of events</mark>, and any outcome is conceivable</u>. A <u>minor skirmish </u>along the Indo-Chinese border <u>might not be a cause for alarm in</u> the <u>United States, but</u> a <u><strong><mark>larger war</strong></mark> <mark>between</mark> those two <mark>countries</mark> <strong>undoubtedly</strong> would be. Both are <mark>armed with</mark> <strong><mark>nuc</mark>lear weapon<mark>s</strong></mark>,</u> and <u><strong>Washington</strong> views India as</u> a <u><strong>strategic counterweight</strong> to China</u>.38 A <u>crushing <strong><mark>defeat of India</strong></mark> would be <mark>viewed as</u></mark> a <u><strong><mark>potential threat</strong></mark> <mark>to American</mark> <strong><mark>national</strong></mark> <mark>interests</mark> and</u> might conceivably <u><mark>precipitate</mark> <strong><mark>U.S. military intervention</u></strong></mark>. Where that might lead is anyone’s guess, but the <u>mere <strong>possibility</strong> of</u> such <u>combat has made this <strong>scenario</strong> a matter of <strong>deep concern</strong> for security analysts</u> in Washington.39</p> | 1AC---Mamaroneck r1---Stuyvesant VP | 1AC---PTD---Mamaroneck | 1AC---ADV---India---Mamaroneck | 25,096 | 717 | 29,803 | ./documents/hspolicy21/NilesNorth/GaBi/Niles%20North-Gabay-Bisevac-Aff-Mamaroneck-Round1.docx | 752,301 | A | Mamaroneck | 1 | Stuyvesant VP | Amanda Flashner | 1AC PTD
1NC States Fism BBB T - Regs
Block All
2NR States Fism | hspolicy21/NilesNorth/GaBi/Niles%20North-Gabay-Bisevac-Aff-Mamaroneck-Round1.docx | null | 64,153 | GaBi | Niles North GaBi | null | Ar..... | Ga..... | Ha..... | Bi..... | 22,068 | NilesNorth | Niles North | IL | null | 1,020 | hspolicy21 | HS Policy 2021-22 | 2,021 | cx | hs | 2 |
4,720,316 | Abled subjectivity is tied up in a two-tiered affective response that explains disabled life – primary pity which reflects disability upon the ego threatening its ability status, which invokes secondary pity to overcorrect for the shattered-ego necessitating disabled death – thus, the role of the ballot is to vote for the debater that best deconstructs ableism. | Mollow 15 | Mollow 15 The Disability Drive by Anna Mollow A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in English in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Professor Kent Puckett, Chair Professor Celeste G. Langan Professor Melinda Y. Chen Spring 2015 //ACCS JM | pity involves a complex affective reaction to the suffering of someone else. Primary pity entails a response to the image of another person succumbing to what I have termed the “tragedy of disability.” Primary pity arises primary pity could be described as a vicarious experience of the tragedy of disability. primary pity entails a mixing up of self and other such that the ego, in becoming permeable to pain that may properly belong to “someone else,” Primary pity is that intense pain-pleasure complex that is provoked by the image of a suffering other who This affective response can feel unbearable Primary pity is difficult to bear because it involves a drive toward disability which menaces the ego’s investments in health, pleasure, and control because to contemplate another person’s suffering is to question, “Could this happen to me?” Secondary pity attempts to heal primary pity’s self-rupturing effects by converting primary pity into a feeling that is bearable. both an attempt to get back to that ego-shattering state of painfully pleasurable primary pity, and at the same time to defend against that threat to the ego by aggrandizing oneself at someone else’s expense. nondisabled people could never endure such suffering. secondary pity encompasses our culture’s most clichéd reactions to disability: charity, tears, and calls for a cure. these affects enlarge the ego of the pitier or the narcissist at the expense of someone else. we feel primary pity and then, almost before we can blink, deny that we feel or have felt it. who wants to admit that one gets pleasure from the sight of another person’s suffering | pity involves a reaction to the “tragedy of disability.” Primary pity is unbearable to contemplate another person’s suffering is to question, “Could this happen to me?” Secondary pity attempts to heal the ego at someone else’s expense and calls for a cure. we feel primary pity and then deny that we have felt it. | Much as the differentiation between the inseparable processes of primary and secondary narcissism rests on a distinction between building up and breaking down the ego, a similar heuristic distinction gives structure to my concepts of primary and secondary pity. To be clear, pity and narcissism are not the same thing: if narcissism can be understood as love of the self, pity involves a complex affective reaction to the suffering of someone else. Primary pity entails a response to the image of another person succumbing to what I have termed the “tragedy of disability.”121 Primary pity arises when one witnesses a fall of the self, a collapse of the ego; such falling is at once painful and pleasurable to observe. In other words, primary pity could be described as a vicarious experience of the tragedy of disability. A great deal of the pain and pleasure of primary pity center on questions about what, or who, this fallen self is. When most people think about pity, we refer to an affect in which, to adopt Edelman’s phrase, we purport to “feel for the other.” But as with primary narcissism, in which the self has not yet been constituted, and therefore cannot be said to enter into intersubjective relations with an “other,” primary pity entails a mixing up of self and other such that the ego, in becoming permeable to pain that may properly belong to “someone else,” is profoundly threatened in its integrity. Primary pity is that intense pain-pleasure complex that is provoked by the image of a suffering other who, it seems momentarily, both is and is not one’s self. This affective response can feel unbearable, as seen in Siebers’s formulation: one “cannot bear to look...but also cannot bear not to look.” Primary pity is difficult to bear because it involves a drive toward disability (one cannot bear not to look), which menaces the ego’s investments in health, pleasure, and control—because to contemplate another person’s suffering is to confront the question, “Could this happen to me?” Such a prospect, although frightening, may also be compelling; in this way, primary pity replicates the self-rupturing aspects of sexuality. Indeed, the unbearability of primary pity reflects its coextensiveness with sexuality. Sex, or the Unbearable, a book coauthored by Edelman and by Lauren Berlant, argues that sex “unleashes unbearable contradictions that we nonetheless struggle to bear” (back cover). This claim accords with Freud’s account of sexuality as a “pleasurable” “unpleasure” that the ego can never fully master or control (Three 49,75). As Leo Bersani puts it in his reading of Freud, “the pleasurable unpleasurable tension of sexual enjoyment occurs when the body’s ‘normal’ range of sensation is exceeded, and when the organization of the self is momentarily disturbed”; thus, “sexuality would be that which is intolerable to the structured self” (Freudian 38). Primary pity is also intolerable to the structured self, because it entails a fascination with the fantasy of a self in a state of disintegration or disablement. Secondary pity is something else, although it cannot wholly be differentiated from primary pity. Secondary pity attempts to heal primary pity’s self-rupturing effects by converting primary pity into a feeling that is bearable. As with secondary narcissism, secondary pity involves both an attempt to get back to that ego-shattering state of painfully pleasurable primary pity, and at the same time to defend against that threat to the ego by aggrandizing oneself at someone else’s expense. Secondary pity refers to all those ego-bolstering behaviors that most people think of when they talk about pity. Disabled people are all too familiar with these behaviors: the saccharin sympathy, the telethon rituals of “conspicuous contribution,” the insistence that “they” (i.e., nondisabled people) could never endure such suffering. More commonly known in our culture simply as “pity,” secondary pity encompasses our culture’s most clichéd reactions to disability: charity, tears, and calls for a cure. Correlatives of these commonplace manifestations of secondary pity are the obligatory claims that disabled people’s suffering is “inspiring.” Indeed, the speed with which conventional cultural representations of disability segue from overt expressions of pity to celebrations of “the triumph of the human spirit” highlights the ways in which secondary pity, as a defense against primary pity’s incursions, reinforces the ego’s fantasy of sovereignty. Secondary pity, in other words, can be seen as a variation of secondary narcissism: these affects enlarge the ego of the pitier or the narcissist at the expense of someone else. But primary pity is not the same as either primary narcissism, secondary narcissism, or secondary pity. Unlike primary narcissism, a feeling that emerges out of a relation to the world in which notions of “self” and “other” do not obtain, primary pity does depend upon the constructs of self and other, although these constructions are unstable and are continually threatening to come undone. Primary pity can thus be envisioned as a threshold category occupying a liminal position between the total denial of the other that is inherent to primary narcissism and the rigid structure of (superior) self and (inferior) other that constitutes secondary narcissism and secondary pity. My concept of primary versus secondary pity also differs from Freud’s primary- secondary narcissism distinction at the level of genealogy. Like Freud’s account of primary and secondary narcissisms, my model of primary and secondary pities involves a temporal transition; but whereas Freud imagines the movement from primary to secondary narcissism as a passage from an earlier to a later stage of an individual’s development, the temporal shift from primary to secondary pity happens much more quickly than this. It happens in an instant: that moment in which we feel primary pity and then, almost before we can blink, deny that we feel or have felt it. The denial is understandable: who wants to admit that one gets pleasure from the sight of another person’s suffering—or, to make matters worse, that this pleasure derives in part from the specter of disability’s transferability, the possibility that this suffering could be—and, fantasmatically, perhaps already is—an image of one’s own self undone? | 6,363 | <h4>Abled subjectivity is tied up in a two-tiered affective response that explains disabled life – primary pity which reflects disability upon the ego threatening its ability status, which invokes secondary pity to overcorrect for the shattered-ego necessitating disabled death – thus, the role of the ballot is to vote for the debater that best deconstructs ableism.</h4><p><strong>Mollow 15</strong> The Disability Drive by Anna Mollow A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in English in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Professor Kent Puckett, Chair Professor Celeste G. Langan Professor Melinda Y. Chen Spring 2015 //ACCS JM</p><p>Much as the differentiation between the inseparable processes of primary and secondary narcissism rests on a distinction between building up and breaking down the ego, a similar heuristic distinction gives structure to my concepts of primary and secondary pity. To be clear, pity and narcissism are not the same thing: if narcissism can be understood as love of the self, <u><strong><mark>pity involves a</strong></mark> complex affective <strong><mark>reaction to the</mark> suffering of someone else.</u></strong> <u>Primary pity entails a response to the image of another person <strong>succumbing to</strong> what I have termed <strong>the <mark>“tragedy of disability.”</u></strong></mark>121 <u><strong>Primary pity arises</u></strong> when one witnesses a fall of the self, a collapse of the ego; such falling is at once painful and pleasurable to observe. In other words, <u>primary pity could be described <strong>as a vicarious experience of the tragedy of disability.</u></strong> A great deal of the pain and pleasure of primary pity center on questions about what, or who, this fallen self is. When most people think about pity, we refer to an affect in which, to adopt Edelman’s phrase, we purport to “feel for the other.” But as with primary narcissism, in which the self has not yet been constituted, and therefore cannot be said to enter into intersubjective relations with an “other,” <u><strong>primary pity entails a mixing up of self and other such that the ego</strong>, in becoming permeable to pain that<strong> may</strong> properly <strong>belong to “someone else,”</u></strong> is profoundly threatened in its integrity. <u><strong><mark>Primary pity is</mark> that</strong> <strong>intense pain</strong>-pleasure complex <strong>that</strong> is <strong>provoked by the</strong> image of a <strong>suffering other</strong> who</u>, it seems momentarily, both is and is not one’s self. <u><strong>This affective response can feel <mark>unbearable</u></strong></mark>, as seen in Siebers’s formulation: one “cannot bear to look...but also cannot bear not to look.” <u>Primary pity is difficult to bear because it involves a drive toward disability</u> (one cannot bear not to look), <u>which menaces the ego’s investments in health, pleasure, and control</u>—<u><strong>because <mark>to contemplate another person’s suffering is to</u></strong></mark> confront the <u><strong><mark>question, “Could this happen to me?”</u></strong></mark> Such a prospect, although frightening, may also be compelling; in this way, primary pity replicates the self-rupturing aspects of sexuality. Indeed, the unbearability of primary pity reflects its coextensiveness with sexuality. Sex, or the Unbearable, a book coauthored by Edelman and by Lauren Berlant, argues that sex “unleashes unbearable contradictions that we nonetheless struggle to bear” (back cover). This claim accords with Freud’s account of sexuality as a “pleasurable” “unpleasure” that the ego can never fully master or control (Three 49,75). As Leo Bersani puts it in his reading of Freud, “the pleasurable unpleasurable tension of sexual enjoyment occurs when the body’s ‘normal’ range of sensation is exceeded, and when the organization of the self is momentarily disturbed”; thus, “sexuality would be that which is intolerable to the structured self” (Freudian 38). Primary pity is also intolerable to the structured self, because it entails a fascination with the fantasy of a self in a state of disintegration or disablement. Secondary pity is something else, although it cannot wholly be differentiated from primary pity. <u><strong><mark>Secondary pity attempts to heal</mark> primary pity’s self-rupturing</strong> effects <strong>by</strong> <strong>converting primary pity into a feeling that is bearable.</u></strong> As with secondary narcissism, secondary pity involves <u>both <strong>an attempt</strong> to get back to that ego-shattering state of painfully pleasurable primary pity, and at the same time <strong>to defend</strong> against that threat to <strong><mark>the ego</mark> by aggrandizing</strong> oneself <strong><mark>at someone else’s expense</mark>.</u></strong> Secondary pity refers to all those ego-bolstering behaviors that most people think of when they talk about pity. Disabled people are all too familiar with these behaviors: the saccharin sympathy, the telethon rituals of “conspicuous contribution,” the insistence that “they” (i.e., <u><strong>nondisabled people</u></strong>) <u><strong>could never endure such suffering.</u></strong> More commonly known in our culture simply as “pity,” <u><strong>secondary pity</strong> encompasses our culture’s most clichéd reactions to disability: charity, tears, <strong><mark>and calls for a cure.</u></strong></mark> Correlatives of these commonplace manifestations of secondary pity are the obligatory claims that disabled people’s suffering is “inspiring.” Indeed, the speed with which conventional cultural representations of disability segue from overt expressions of pity to celebrations of “the triumph of the human spirit” highlights the ways in which secondary pity, as a defense against primary pity’s incursions, reinforces the ego’s fantasy of sovereignty. Secondary pity, in other words, can be seen as a variation of secondary narcissism: <u><strong>these affects enlarge the ego of the pitier</strong> or the narcissist <strong>at the expense of someone else.</u></strong> But primary pity is not the same as either primary narcissism, secondary narcissism, or secondary pity. Unlike primary narcissism, a feeling that emerges out of a relation to the world in which notions of “self” and “other” do not obtain, primary pity does depend upon the constructs of self and other, although these constructions are unstable and are continually threatening to come undone. Primary pity can thus be envisioned as a threshold category occupying a liminal position between the total denial of the other that is inherent to primary narcissism and the rigid structure of (superior) self and (inferior) other that constitutes secondary narcissism and secondary pity. My concept of primary versus secondary pity also differs from Freud’s primary- secondary narcissism distinction at the level of genealogy. Like Freud’s account of primary and secondary narcissisms, my model of primary and secondary pities involves a temporal transition; but whereas Freud imagines the movement from primary to secondary narcissism as a passage from an earlier to a later stage of an individual’s development, the temporal shift from primary to secondary pity happens much more quickly than this. It happens in an instant: that moment in which <u><strong><mark>we feel primary pity and then</strong></mark>, almost before we can blink,</u> <u><strong><mark>deny that we</mark> feel or <mark>have felt it.</u></strong></mark> The denial is understandable: <u>who wants to admit that one gets pleasure from the sight of another person’s suffering</u>—or, to make matters worse, that this pleasure derives in part from the specter of disability’s transferability, the possibility that this suffering could be—and, fantasmatically, perhaps already is—an image of one’s own self undone?</p> | 1NC vs Southlake Carroll TY | 1NC | 4 | 325,333 | 517 | 164,590 | ./documents/hsld22/King/ChPa/King-ChPa-Neg-Colleyville-Heritage-Winter-Invitational-Round-2.docx | 970,996 | N | Colleyville Heritage Winter Invitational | 2 | Southlake Carroll TY | Misra, Parth | 1AC - Schengenlargement
1NC - Freiman-Hidalgo T, CSA, Skeppy v3, Disability v9, ICJ v4, Case
1AR - All
2NR - CSA, Case
2AR - Case, CSA | hsld22/King/ChPa/King-ChPa-Neg-Colleyville-Heritage-Winter-Invitational-Round-2.docx | 2023-02-04 03:19:26 | 79,340 | ChPa | King ChPa | Hey y'all I'm Chan! (they/them) or (he/him)
Contact Info
Email: [email protected]
Messanger: https://www.facebook.com/chanh.park.167/
Please ask for consent to spread!
And please give content warnings about discussions of ableist and anti-asian violence | Ch..... | Pa..... | null | null | 26,583 | King | King | FL | null | 2,003 | hsld22 | HS LD 2022-23 | 2,022 | ld | hs | 1 |
514,611 | The risk of existential disease is .01% | Noy 22 | Dr. Ilan Noy 22, Chair in the Economics of Disasters and Climate Change at the Victoria University of Wellington, PhD from the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Dr. Tomáš Uher, PhD, Professor at Masaryk University, “Four New Horsemen of an Apocalypse? Solar Flares, Super-volcanoes, Pandemics, and Artificial Intelligence”, Economics of Disasters and Climate Change, 1/15/2022, SpringerLink | A naturally occurring pandemic that would threaten human extinction is a very small probability event
In terms of the probability of naturally occurring pandemics, a survey of participants of the Global Catastrophic Risk Conference shows that the median estimate for a probability of a natural pandemic killing more than 1 billion people before the year 2100 was surveyed to be 5%, and the probability of such pandemic to cause human extinction was 0.05%. Ord uses a slightly broader definition of existential risk, which apart from human extinction also includes a permanent reduction of human potential. He estimates the probability of an existential risk stemming from a natural pandemic in the next 100 years to be 0.01% | A pandemic that threaten extinction is a very small probability
a survey of the G C R Conference shows the median estimate for killing 1 billion to be 5% Ord estimates probability of existential risk from a pandemic in the next 100 years to be 0.01% | High-Mortality Pandemics
A naturally occurring pandemic (i.e., not from an engineered pathogen) that would threaten human extinction is a very small probability event. However, historical accounts point to several instances where disease spread played an important role in causing very significant decline of specific populations. For example, the introduction of novel diseases to the Native American population during the European colonization of the Americas had deadly consequences. It is difficult to distinguish the effects of the diseases that came with the Europeans from the war and conflict they also brought with them. Nevertheless, during the first hundred years of the colonization period, the American population may have been reduced by as much as 90% (Ord 2020).
Moreover, two major pandemic events, the Justinian Plague in the sixth century and the Black Death in the fourteenth century appear to have been severe enough to cause a significant population decline of tens of percent in the populations they affected. Both events are believed to have been caused by plague, an infectious disease caused by the bacteria Yersinia Pestis (Christakos et al. 2005; Allen 1979). While there is a certain degree of uncertainty involved in studying these events’ societal impacts, historical accounts in combination with modern scientific methods provide us with some valuable insights into the effects they may have had on the societies of the time.
With respect to the possibility of a future catastrophic global pandemic, it appears that this risk is increasing significantly along with the advances in the field of synthetic biology and the rising possibility of an accidental or intentional release of an engineered pathogen. While some of the scientific efforts in the field of synthetic biology are directed towards increasing our understanding and our ability to prevent future catastrophic epidemic threats, the risk stemming from these activities is non-trivial, and may outweigh their benefits.
The Justinian Plague
The Justinian Plague severely affected the people of Europe and East Asia, though estimates of its overall mortality vary. Focusing exclusively on the first wave of the pandemic (AD 541–544), Muehlhauser (2017) suggests the pandemic was associated with a 20% mortality in the Byzantine empire. This estimate is based on the mortality rate estimated for the empire’s capital, Constantinople, by Stathakopoulos (2007) to produce a death toll of roughly 5.6 million. For a longer time span, AD 541 to 600, which included subsequent waves of the plague, scholars estimate a higher mortality rate of 33–50% (Allen 1979; Meier 2016).
The demographic changes associated with this high mortality led to a significant disruption of economic activity in the Byzantine empire (Gârdan 2020). A decline in the labour force caused a decline in agricultural production which led to food shortages and famine (Meier 2016). Trade also collapsed. Decreased tax revenues caused by the population decline initiated a major fiscal contraction and consequently a military crisis for the empire (Sarris 2002; Meier 2016). In the longer run, however, the massive reduction of the labour force appears to have had a positive economic effect for the surviving laborers, as the increased marginal value of labour caused a rise in real wages and per capita incomes. These beneficial effects for the survivors were also observed after the Black Death (Pamuk and Shatzmiller 2014; Findlay and Lundahl 2017).
The mortality and the disruption of activity the plague caused in the Byzantine empire also led to further direct and indirect cultural and religious consequences. Meier (2016) particularly highlights the plague’s indirect effect of an increase in liturgification (a process of religious permeation and internalization throughout society as defined by Meier 2020), the rise of the Marian cult, and the sacralization of the emperor.
The direct and indirect effects of the plague also appear to have had far-reaching and long-term political repercussions. The societal disruptions caused by the plague are believed to have significantly weakened the position of the Byzantine empire and arguably led to the decline of the Sasanian empire (Sabbatani et al. 2012). Interestingly, the pandemic indirectly favoured the nomadic Arab tribes who were less vulnerable to the contagion while traveling through desert and semi-desert environments during the initial expansion of Islam (Sabbatani et al. 2012).
Of note is the absence of a scientific consensus on the severity of the Justinian Plague’s impacts. For example, Mordechai and Eisenberg (2019) and Mordechai et al. (2019) argue against the maximalist interpretation of the historical evidence described above. They suggest that the estimated mortality rate of the plague is exaggerated, and that the pandemic was not a primary cause of the transformational demographic, political and economic changes in the Mediterranean region between the sixth and eighth century. Recently, White and Mordechai (2020) highlighted the high likelihood of the plague having different impacts in the urban areas of the Mediterranean outside of Constantinople.
The Black Death
The Black Death which ravaged Europe, North Africa, and parts of Asia in the middle of the fourteenth century is considered the deadliest pandemic in human history and potentially the most severe global catastrophe to have ever struck mankind. With respect to its mortality, Ord (2020) argues that the best estimate of its global mortality rate is 5–14% of the global population, largely based on Muehlhauser (2017).
The plague created a large demographic shock in the affected regions. It reduced the European population by approximately 30–50% during the 6 years of its initial outbreak (Ord 2020). It took approximately two centuries for the population levels to recover (Livi-Bacci 2017; Jedwab et al. 2019b). As the mortality rates appear to have been the highest among the working-age population, the effects on the labour force were acute (Pamuk 2007).
The plague's mortality, morbidity and the associated societal disruption led to a major decline in economic output both in Europe (Pamuk 2007) and the Middle East (Dols 2019). In Europe, however, this decline in economic output was smaller than the decline in population; output per capita began to increase within a few years of the initial outbreak (Pamuk 2007).
The large demographic shock caused by the plague led to a shift in the relative price of labour which, similarly to the Justinian Plague, had a positive impact on wages. With a reduced labour force, real wages and per capita incomes in many European countries increased and were sustained at higher levels for several centuries (Voigtländer and Voth 2013a; Jedwab et al. 2020; Pamuk and Shatzmiller 2014). Scott and Duncan (2001) point out that real wages approximately doubled in most countries of Europe in the century following the plague.
An additional insight into the long-run relationship between the Black Death’s mortality and per capita incomes in Europe is offered by Voigtländer and Voth (2013a). Using a Malthusian model, they suggest that over time, the rise in income caused by the plague’s mortality led to an increase in urbanization and trade. Furthermore, the increased tax burden (per capita), combined with the contemporary political climate, increased the frequency of wars. Consequently, higher urbanization and trade led to an increase in disease spread which along with a more frequent war occurrence caused a long-term increase in mortality and a further positive effect on per capita incomes. In this way, the Black Death appears to have created a long-lasting environment of high-mortality and high-income specifically in Western Europe, functioning as an important contributing factor to its economic growth in the next centuries (Alfani 2020). However, while in Western Europe incomes remained elevated over the next centuries, in Southern Europe they began to decline as the Southern European population started recovering after AD 1500 (Jedwab et al. 2020).
Apart from the positive effects on wages, the increased marginal value of labour combined with other factors had further economic and social implications. A decreased relative value of land and the lack of workforce to use it effectively caused land prices and land rents to decrease (Jedwab et al. 2020; Pamuk 2007). A decreased marginal value of capital assets in general led to a lapse in the enforcement of property rights (Haddock and Kiesling 2002). Interest rates and real rates of return on assets also decreased (Pamuk 2007; Jedwab et al. 2020; Pamuk and Shatzmiller 2014; Jordà et al. 2021; Clark 2016).
Higher wages in combination with a relative abundance of land increased people’s access to land/home ownership, likely reducing social inequality (Alfani 2020). On the other end of the income distribution, decreased incomes for landowners led to an overall decrease in income inequality (Jedwab et al. 2020; Alfani and Murphy 2017).
With respect to the effects on agriculture, the structure of agricultural output moved away from cereals to other crops following the plague. Furthermore, the workforce shortages and the incentives to increase the labour supply are believed to have caused a shift from male-labour intensive arable farming towards pastoral farming, consequently raising the demand for female labour (Voigtländer and Voth 2013b). However, while the Black Death appears to have caused certain structural agricultural changes, Clark (2016) finds no effect of the plague on agricultural productivity in the long run.
In terms of other social consequences, the evidence suggests that the plague's mortality reduced labour coercion, particularly throughout Western Europe (Jedwab et al. 2020; Haddock and Kiesling 2002; Gingerich and Vogler 2021). The increased bargaining power of labour caused by the plague’s demographic shock contributed to and accelerated the decline in serfdom and development of a free labour regime. Gingerich and Voler (2021) further argue that these effects may have had long-lasting political implications and that a decline of repressive labour practices (such as serfdom) permitted the development of more inclusive political institutions. They find that the regions with the highest mortality were more likely to develop participatory political institutions and more equitable land ownership systems. They find that centuries later, In Germany, the populations in these high-mortality regions were less likely to vote for Hitler’s National Socialist (Nazi) Party in the 1930 and 1932 elections in Germany.
However, the positive effects on the emergence of freer labour did not take place in Eastern Europe, where serfdom was sustained and even intensified. Robinson and Torvik (2011) attempt to explain this asymmetry arguing that these differential outcomes may have been caused by the varying power and quality of institutions. The authors suggest that opportunities generated by the increased bargaining power of labour, in an environment of weak institutions, were less likely to lead to a positive effect than in the case of regions with stronger institutions (with more robust rule-of-law or less corrupt or predatory practices).
Apart from causing a negative demographic shock to the affected populations, the Black Death appears to have caused further indirect demographic changes, particularly in Western Europe. The increased employment opportunities for females caused by worker shortages and a higher female labour demand led to a decline in fertility rates and an increased age of marriage (Voigtländer and Voth 2013b). This demographic transition to a population characterized by lower birth rates likely helped to preserve the high levels of per capita incomes and contributed to further economic development of certain parts of Europe, enabling it to escape the “Malthusian trap” in the following centuries (Pamuk 2007). Siuda and Sunde (2021) confirm the pandemic’s effect on the accelerated demographic transition empirically, as they find that greater pandemic mortality was associated with an earlier onset of the demographic transition across the various regions of Germany.
Unfortunately, the Black Death also led to an increase in the persecution of Jews (Finley and Koyama 2018; Jedwab et al. 2019a). Interestingly, Jedwab et al. (2019a) were able to estimate that in the case of regions with the highest mortality rates, the probability of persecution decreased if the Jewish minority was believed to benefit the local economy.
It is important to highlight that the long-term repercussions of the Black Death were highly asymmetrical. While in Western Europe the pandemic appears to have led to some long-term dynamic shifts associated with increased wages, decreased inequality and a decrease in labour coercion, this was not the case for other regions. A decrease in wages was observed for example in Spain (Alfani 2020) and Egypt. In Spain, the plague's demographic impact on an already scarce population caused a long-lasting negative disruption to the local trade-oriented economy. The workforce disruption in Egypt led to a collapse of the labour-intensive irrigation system for growing crops in the Nile valley, with consequent disastrous effects on the rural economy (Alfani 2020). Borsch (2005) argues that the economic decline in Egypt caused by the Black Death “put an end to the power in the heartland of the Arab world” (p. 114) and to the impressive scientific and technological developments that came out of this region.
A consensus for an explanation of the Black Death’s varied impacts across regions, and their determinants, does not appear to exist. However, several researchers attempt to provide partial insights. For example, Alfani (2020) considers the differential outcomes to be broadly dependent upon the initial conditions in each region. More specifically, both Robinson and Torvik (2011) and Pamuk (2007) propose that the asymmetry of impacts can largely be explained by the differences in the institutional environments of the affected societies.
It is argued that the Black Death defined the threshold between the medieval and the modern ages, similarly to the way the Justinian Plague did for antiquity and the Middle Ages (Horden 2021). Furthermore, the differential long-term outcomes of the Black Death likely provided a significant contribution to the so-called “Great Divergence” between Europe and the rest of the world and the “Little Divergence” between North-western and Southern and Eastern Europe (Jedwab et al. 2020; Pamuk 2007).
From this perspective, it would seem rational to conclude that apart from causing substantial and long-term demographic, economic, political, and cultural changes, both the Justinian Plague and the Black Death likely significantly altered the course of human history.
Considering the above, it is not unreasonable to expect that a pandemic of a similar magnitude to these past catastrophes would do the same in the present day. However, what societal impacts a pandemic of similar or higher mortality would inflict in the twenty-first century has not really been the subject of any study, as far as we were able to identify. A possibility exists, given the newly developed capacity of humanity to create new pathogens, that the outcomes of a future catastrophic pandemic will be even more adverse than those of the Justinian Plague and the Black Death.
Probability
In terms of the probability of naturally occurring pandemics, an informal survey of participants of the Global Catastrophic Risk Conference in Oxford in 2008 shows that the median estimate for a probability of a natural pandemic killing more than 1 billion people before the year 2100 was surveyed to be 5%, and the probability of such pandemic to cause human extinction was 0.05%. Ord (2020) uses a slightly broader definition of existential risk, which apart from human extinction also includes a permanent reduction of human potential. He estimates the probability of an existential risk stemming from a natural pandemic in the next 100 years to be 0.01%. | 16,210 | <h4>The risk of existential disease is .01%</h4><p>Dr. Ilan <strong>Noy 22</strong>, Chair in the Economics of Disasters and Climate Change at the Victoria University of Wellington, PhD from the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Dr. Tomáš Uher, PhD, Professor at Masaryk University, “Four New Horsemen of an Apocalypse? Solar Flares, Super-volcanoes, Pandemics, and Artificial Intelligence”, Economics of Disasters and Climate Change, 1/15/2022, SpringerLink</p><p>High-Mortality Pandemics</p><p><u><mark>A</mark> naturally occurring <mark>pandemic</u></mark> (i.e., not from an engineered pathogen) <u><mark>that</mark> would <mark>threaten</mark> human <mark>extinction is a <strong>very small</strong> probability</mark> event</u>. However, historical accounts point to several instances where disease spread played an important role in causing very significant decline of specific populations. For example, the introduction of novel diseases to the Native American population during the European colonization of the Americas had deadly consequences. It is difficult to distinguish the effects of the diseases that came with the Europeans from the war and conflict they also brought with them. Nevertheless, during the first hundred years of the colonization period, the American population may have been reduced by as much as 90% (Ord 2020).</p><p>Moreover, two major pandemic events, the Justinian Plague in the sixth century and the Black Death in the fourteenth century appear to have been severe enough to cause a significant population decline of tens of percent in the populations they affected. Both events are believed to have been caused by plague, an infectious disease caused by the bacteria Yersinia Pestis (Christakos et al. 2005; Allen 1979). While there is a certain degree of uncertainty involved in studying these events’ societal impacts, historical accounts in combination with modern scientific methods provide us with some valuable insights into the effects they may have had on the societies of the time.</p><p>With respect to the possibility of a future catastrophic global pandemic, it appears that this risk is increasing significantly along with the advances in the field of synthetic biology and the rising possibility of an accidental or intentional release of an engineered pathogen. While some of the scientific efforts in the field of synthetic biology are directed towards increasing our understanding and our ability to prevent future catastrophic epidemic threats, the risk stemming from these activities is non-trivial, and may outweigh their benefits.</p><p>The Justinian Plague</p><p>The Justinian Plague severely affected the people of Europe and East Asia, though estimates of its overall mortality vary. Focusing exclusively on the first wave of the pandemic (AD 541–544), Muehlhauser (2017) suggests the pandemic was associated with a 20% mortality in the Byzantine empire. This estimate is based on the mortality rate estimated for the empire’s capital, Constantinople, by Stathakopoulos (2007) to produce a death toll of roughly 5.6 million. For a longer time span, AD 541 to 600, which included subsequent waves of the plague, scholars estimate a higher mortality rate of 33–50% (Allen 1979; Meier 2016).</p><p>The demographic changes associated with this high mortality led to a significant disruption of economic activity in the Byzantine empire (Gârdan 2020). A decline in the labour force caused a decline in agricultural production which led to food shortages and famine (Meier 2016). Trade also collapsed. Decreased tax revenues caused by the population decline initiated a major fiscal contraction and consequently a military crisis for the empire (Sarris 2002; Meier 2016). In the longer run, however, the massive reduction of the labour force appears to have had a positive economic effect for the surviving laborers, as the increased marginal value of labour caused a rise in real wages and per capita incomes. These beneficial effects for the survivors were also observed after the Black Death (Pamuk and Shatzmiller 2014; Findlay and Lundahl 2017).</p><p>The mortality and the disruption of activity the plague caused in the Byzantine empire also led to further direct and indirect cultural and religious consequences. Meier (2016) particularly highlights the plague’s indirect effect of an increase in liturgification (a process of religious permeation and internalization throughout society as defined by Meier 2020), the rise of the Marian cult, and the sacralization of the emperor.</p><p>The direct and indirect effects of the plague also appear to have had far-reaching and long-term political repercussions. The societal disruptions caused by the plague are believed to have significantly weakened the position of the Byzantine empire and arguably led to the decline of the Sasanian empire (Sabbatani et al. 2012). Interestingly, the pandemic indirectly favoured the nomadic Arab tribes who were less vulnerable to the contagion while traveling through desert and semi-desert environments during the initial expansion of Islam (Sabbatani et al. 2012).</p><p>Of note is the absence of a scientific consensus on the severity of the Justinian Plague’s impacts. For example, Mordechai and Eisenberg (2019) and Mordechai et al. (2019) argue against the maximalist interpretation of the historical evidence described above. They suggest that the estimated mortality rate of the plague is exaggerated, and that the pandemic was not a primary cause of the transformational demographic, political and economic changes in the Mediterranean region between the sixth and eighth century. Recently, White and Mordechai (2020) highlighted the high likelihood of the plague having different impacts in the urban areas of the Mediterranean outside of Constantinople.</p><p>The Black Death</p><p>The Black Death which ravaged Europe, North Africa, and parts of Asia in the middle of the fourteenth century is considered the deadliest pandemic in human history and potentially the most severe global catastrophe to have ever struck mankind. With respect to its mortality, Ord (2020) argues that the best estimate of its global mortality rate is 5–14% of the global population, largely based on Muehlhauser (2017).</p><p>The plague created a large demographic shock in the affected regions. It reduced the European population by approximately 30–50% during the 6 years of its initial outbreak (Ord 2020). It took approximately two centuries for the population levels to recover (Livi-Bacci 2017; Jedwab et al. 2019b). As the mortality rates appear to have been the highest among the working-age population, the effects on the labour force were acute (Pamuk 2007).</p><p>The plague's mortality, morbidity and the associated societal disruption led to a major decline in economic output both in Europe (Pamuk 2007) and the Middle East (Dols 2019). In Europe, however, this decline in economic output was smaller than the decline in population; output per capita began to increase within a few years of the initial outbreak (Pamuk 2007).</p><p>The large demographic shock caused by the plague led to a shift in the relative price of labour which, similarly to the Justinian Plague, had a positive impact on wages. With a reduced labour force, real wages and per capita incomes in many European countries increased and were sustained at higher levels for several centuries (Voigtländer and Voth 2013a; Jedwab et al. 2020; Pamuk and Shatzmiller 2014). Scott and Duncan (2001) point out that real wages approximately doubled in most countries of Europe in the century following the plague.</p><p>An additional insight into the long-run relationship between the Black Death’s mortality and per capita incomes in Europe is offered by Voigtländer and Voth (2013a). Using a Malthusian model, they suggest that over time, the rise in income caused by the plague’s mortality led to an increase in urbanization and trade. Furthermore, the increased tax burden (per capita), combined with the contemporary political climate, increased the frequency of wars. Consequently, higher urbanization and trade led to an increase in disease spread which along with a more frequent war occurrence caused a long-term increase in mortality and a further positive effect on per capita incomes. In this way, the Black Death appears to have created a long-lasting environment of high-mortality and high-income specifically in Western Europe, functioning as an important contributing factor to its economic growth in the next centuries (Alfani 2020). However, while in Western Europe incomes remained elevated over the next centuries, in Southern Europe they began to decline as the Southern European population started recovering after AD 1500 (Jedwab et al. 2020).</p><p>Apart from the positive effects on wages, the increased marginal value of labour combined with other factors had further economic and social implications. A decreased relative value of land and the lack of workforce to use it effectively caused land prices and land rents to decrease (Jedwab et al. 2020; Pamuk 2007). A decreased marginal value of capital assets in general led to a lapse in the enforcement of property rights (Haddock and Kiesling 2002). Interest rates and real rates of return on assets also decreased (Pamuk 2007; Jedwab et al. 2020; Pamuk and Shatzmiller 2014; Jordà et al. 2021; Clark 2016).</p><p>Higher wages in combination with a relative abundance of land increased people’s access to land/home ownership, likely reducing social inequality (Alfani 2020). On the other end of the income distribution, decreased incomes for landowners led to an overall decrease in income inequality (Jedwab et al. 2020; Alfani and Murphy 2017).</p><p>With respect to the effects on agriculture, the structure of agricultural output moved away from cereals to other crops following the plague. Furthermore, the workforce shortages and the incentives to increase the labour supply are believed to have caused a shift from male-labour intensive arable farming towards pastoral farming, consequently raising the demand for female labour (Voigtländer and Voth 2013b). However, while the Black Death appears to have caused certain structural agricultural changes, Clark (2016) finds no effect of the plague on agricultural productivity in the long run.</p><p>In terms of other social consequences, the evidence suggests that the plague's mortality reduced labour coercion, particularly throughout Western Europe (Jedwab et al. 2020; Haddock and Kiesling 2002; Gingerich and Vogler 2021). The increased bargaining power of labour caused by the plague’s demographic shock contributed to and accelerated the decline in serfdom and development of a free labour regime. Gingerich and Voler (2021) further argue that these effects may have had long-lasting political implications and that a decline of repressive labour practices (such as serfdom) permitted the development of more inclusive political institutions. They find that the regions with the highest mortality were more likely to develop participatory political institutions and more equitable land ownership systems. They find that centuries later, In Germany, the populations in these high-mortality regions were less likely to vote for Hitler’s National Socialist (Nazi) Party in the 1930 and 1932 elections in Germany.</p><p>However, the positive effects on the emergence of freer labour did not take place in Eastern Europe, where serfdom was sustained and even intensified. Robinson and Torvik (2011) attempt to explain this asymmetry arguing that these differential outcomes may have been caused by the varying power and quality of institutions. The authors suggest that opportunities generated by the increased bargaining power of labour, in an environment of weak institutions, were less likely to lead to a positive effect than in the case of regions with stronger institutions (with more robust rule-of-law or less corrupt or predatory practices).</p><p>Apart from causing a negative demographic shock to the affected populations, the Black Death appears to have caused further indirect demographic changes, particularly in Western Europe. The increased employment opportunities for females caused by worker shortages and a higher female labour demand led to a decline in fertility rates and an increased age of marriage (Voigtländer and Voth 2013b). This demographic transition to a population characterized by lower birth rates likely helped to preserve the high levels of per capita incomes and contributed to further economic development of certain parts of Europe, enabling it to escape the “Malthusian trap” in the following centuries (Pamuk 2007). Siuda and Sunde (2021) confirm the pandemic’s effect on the accelerated demographic transition empirically, as they find that greater pandemic mortality was associated with an earlier onset of the demographic transition across the various regions of Germany.</p><p>Unfortunately, the Black Death also led to an increase in the persecution of Jews (Finley and Koyama 2018; Jedwab et al. 2019a). Interestingly, Jedwab et al. (2019a) were able to estimate that in the case of regions with the highest mortality rates, the probability of persecution decreased if the Jewish minority was believed to benefit the local economy.</p><p>It is important to highlight that the long-term repercussions of the Black Death were highly asymmetrical. While in Western Europe the pandemic appears to have led to some long-term dynamic shifts associated with increased wages, decreased inequality and a decrease in labour coercion, this was not the case for other regions. A decrease in wages was observed for example in Spain (Alfani 2020) and Egypt. In Spain, the plague's demographic impact on an already scarce population caused a long-lasting negative disruption to the local trade-oriented economy. The workforce disruption in Egypt led to a collapse of the labour-intensive irrigation system for growing crops in the Nile valley, with consequent disastrous effects on the rural economy (Alfani 2020). Borsch (2005) argues that the economic decline in Egypt caused by the Black Death “put an end to the power in the heartland of the Arab world” (p. 114) and to the impressive scientific and technological developments that came out of this region.</p><p>A consensus for an explanation of the Black Death’s varied impacts across regions, and their determinants, does not appear to exist. However, several researchers attempt to provide partial insights. For example, Alfani (2020) considers the differential outcomes to be broadly dependent upon the initial conditions in each region. More specifically, both Robinson and Torvik (2011) and Pamuk (2007) propose that the asymmetry of impacts can largely be explained by the differences in the institutional environments of the affected societies.</p><p>It is argued that the Black Death defined the threshold between the medieval and the modern ages, similarly to the way the Justinian Plague did for antiquity and the Middle Ages (Horden 2021). Furthermore, the differential long-term outcomes of the Black Death likely provided a significant contribution to the so-called “Great Divergence” between Europe and the rest of the world and the “Little Divergence” between North-western and Southern and Eastern Europe (Jedwab et al. 2020; Pamuk 2007).</p><p>From this perspective, it would seem rational to conclude that apart from causing substantial and long-term demographic, economic, political, and cultural changes, both the Justinian Plague and the Black Death likely significantly altered the course of human history.</p><p>Considering the above, it is not unreasonable to expect that a pandemic of a similar magnitude to these past catastrophes would do the same in the present day. However, what societal impacts a pandemic of similar or higher mortality would inflict in the twenty-first century has not really been the subject of any study, as far as we were able to identify. A possibility exists, given the newly developed capacity of humanity to create new pathogens, that the outcomes of a future catastrophic pandemic will be even more adverse than those of the Justinian Plague and the Black Death.</p><p>Probability</p><p><u>In terms of the probability of naturally occurring pandemics, <strong><mark>a</u></strong></mark>n informal <u><mark>survey of</mark> participants of <mark>the <strong>G</strong></mark>lobal <strong><mark>C</strong></mark>atastrophic <strong><mark>R</strong></mark>isk <mark>Conference</u></mark> in Oxford in 2008 <u><mark>shows</mark> that <mark>the median estimate for</mark> a probability of a natural pandemic <mark>killing</mark> more than <mark>1 billion</mark> people before the year 2100 was surveyed <mark>to be <strong>5%</strong></mark>, and the probability of such pandemic to cause human extinction was <strong>0.05%</strong>. <mark>Ord</u></mark> (2020) <u>uses a slightly broader definition of existential risk, which apart from human extinction also includes a permanent reduction of human potential. He <mark>estimates</mark> the <strong><mark>probability</strong> of</mark> an <strong><mark>existential</strong> risk</mark> stemming <mark>from a</mark> natural <mark>pandemic in the <strong>next 100 years</strong> to be <strong>0.01%</u></strong></mark>.</p> | 1NC---Round 2---UK | Investment ADV | Investment ADV---1NC | 11,614 | 139 | 6,784 | ./documents/ndtceda22/Kentucky/DiGa/Kentucky-DiGa-Neg-JW-Patterson-Debates-hosted-by-UK-Round-2.docx | 931,451 | N | JW Patterson Debates hosted by UK | 2 | Wichita State HP | Alex McVey | 1AC: AI Inventorship
1NC: T Vest In, T Vest, Digital Capitalism K, Human in the Loop CP, Rights Creep DA, Spillover Turn, Trade Secrets Turn, Floodgates Turn, Case
2NC: Digital Capitalism K, Floodgates Turn, Spillover Turn, Case
1NR: T Vest In
2NR: T Vest In | ndtceda22/Kentucky/DiGa/Kentucky-DiGa-Neg-JW-Patterson-Debates-hosted-by-UK-Round-2.docx | 2022-10-01 18:43:29 | 80,086 | DiGa | Kentucky DiGa | null | Jo..... | Di..... | Ar..... | Ga..... | 26,892 | Kentucky | Kentucky | KY | null | 2,001 | ndtceda22 | NDT/CEDA College 2022-23 | 2,022 | cx | college | 2 |
511,766 | Embryonic personhood collapses bio-medical innovation. Impact is uncurable disease spread. | Piergentili 21 | Piergentili 21, Institute of Molecular Biology and Pathology, Italian National Research Council (Roberto, et al, “CRISPR-Cas and Its Wide-Ranging Applications: From Human Genome Editing to Environmental Implications, Technical Limitations, Hazards and Bioethical Issues,” Cells, 10.5) | If embryos are to be ascribed personhood status, then they are entitled to have their inalienable rights upheld experiments using CRISPR to edit embryos occurred in 2015 if embryos are deemed to have the right to legal safeguards such concerns are likely to significantly inform the debate human gene therapy research is not illegal Nonetheless the issue of whether scientists should seek to edit human embryos to prevent genetic diseases is controversial embryos cannot grant informed consent the time at which a human life embryo or fetus is deemed human has far-reaching ramifications that encompass the crucial realm of health care If human embryos are to be deemed personhood status major implications ensue constraining research on human embryos could put a damper on scientific progress and stymie the development of therapies that could defeat currently untreatable diseases | If embryos are ascribed personhood they are entitled to inalienable rights using CRISPR to edit embryos inform the debate human gene therapy research is not illegal Nonetheless the issue is controversial embryos cannot grant informed consent the time at which a embryo or fetus is human has far-reaching ramifications that encompass health care If human embryos are deemed personhood status major implications ensue constraining research on human embryos could put a damper on scientific progress and stymie development of therapies that could defeat currently untreatable diseases | If embryos are to be ascribed personhood status, then they are entitled to have their inalienable human rights upheld. If, on the other hand, they are deemed as something in between, i.e., less than human beings but more than mere pools of cells, what moral rights should they have acknowledged, if any? Certainly, some point out that the first experiments using CRISPR to edit human embryos occurred in 2015, and since then, only few teams around the world have focused on the process and its potential [85], but recent studies have highlighted an underappreciated risk of CRISPR–Cas9 editing: if embryos are deemed to have the right to at least some degree of legal safeguards, such safety concerns are likely to significantly inform the ongoing debate on the matter. In light of such major unsolved controversies, some have called for an international moratorium on all embryo editing [88,89], and some countries, including Canada, already have policies that ban human-embryo gene editing, irrespective of whether or not the edited embryo would be meant for implantation [90]. In the United States and Britain, on the other hand, an intermediate regulatory approach has been chosen. The US Food and Drug Administration views any use of CRISPR/Cas9 gene editing in humans as gene therapy, regulated by the FDA’s Center for Biologics Evaluation and Research (CBER). Clinical studies of gene therapy in human beings therefore require the submission of an investigational new drug application (IND) before they can be legally initiated in the United States. In addition, marketing gene therapy products calls for the submission and approval of a biologics license application (BLA). As a result of such requirements and restrictions, operating a private lab, with private funds, and conducting nonclinical, human gene therapy research is not illegal. Nonetheless, marketing such therapeutic options in the US would require FDA approval in terms of clinical studies and marketing. As far as it could be determined, no instances exist of a germline gene therapy product in the US; only somatic cell gene therapy products have been granted approval; currently, federal law prevents the FDA from reviewing or approving any application involving manipulated human embryos [91]. Again, it is necessary to draw a clear distinction between embryo editing for research purposes and the implantation of such edited embryos, which is ethically far more contentious. In the United Kingdom, for instance, the use of genome editing in embryos for the purpose of implantation is banned, albeit gene editing on discarded IVF embryos is lawful, provided that such embryos are destroyed immediately afterwards. In vitro culture of human embryos beyond 14 days after onset of embryo creation, i.e., after the appearance of the primitive streak, is prohibited: such a ban is enshrined in the Human Fertilisation and Embryology (HFE) Acts of 1990 and 2008 [92]. In Italy, specific provisions in law 40/2004 recognize the embryo as having rights from the moment of fertilization [93]. The law prohibits the use of embryos for any research unless it is specifically aimed towards improving the therapeutic and medical condition of the embryo itself [94,95]. Critics have pointed out the apparent paradox behind such a restriction, considering that in vivo embryos can be terminated up to 24 weeks through voluntary termination of pregnancy [96]. Some may in fact find it confusing that embryo research is required to stop so much earlier, particularly in light of the fact that it is arguably more ethically sustainable to use abandoned supernumerary embryos for research purposes that could benefit humanity, than to just dispose of them. While abortion ethics is beyond the scope of this review, it is worth pointing out that in these two scenarios, different fundamental goals are in play: legal termination of pregnancy stems from the need to uphold the right of women to have a choice and be in control of their body, whereas in vitro embryo research does not entail that issue. As for embryo experimentation, such intermediate regulatory approaches bear witness to the current uncertainty as to how strictly such techniques ought to be regulated, for the purpose of striking a balance between upholding bioethics precepts and fostering scientific progress for the common good. Nonetheless, nations with more lax, ambiguous or nonspecific regulatory frameworks governing new biomedical technologies may result in a worrisome “maverick” scientific environment in which untested techniques are made available. That has been found to be the case with mitochondrial replacement therapy (MRT), a form of nuclear transfer used as a germline therapy and believed to prevent the transmission of mitochondrial diseases and increase the likelihood of success in pregnancies [97]. Although MRT is banned in many countries due to its still dubious safety, clinics in Spain, Albania, Russia, Ukraine, and Israel have been found to offer the procedure [98]. That said, and irrespective of how individual countries decide to govern such techniques, the issue of whether scientists should seek to edit human embryos to prevent genetic diseases is controversial in itself, because the genomic change which it creates is permanent and may be passed down for generations. Even if embryo experimentation should be deemed justified, by virtue of its potential benefit to the embryo itself and others, embryos obviously cannot grant informed consent, but are still liable to experience life-altering consequences which can extend throughout their lifetimes and affect future generations as well. Besides, as mentioned earlier on, the enforcement and practice of both ethical precepts and legal provisions are inextricably linked to a set of notions that are hardly carved in stone and universally acknowledged. Hence, the time at which a human life (whether embryo or fetus) is deemed a fully-fledged human being has far-reaching ramifications that encompass the crucial realms of health care, law- and policy making and the inalienable right of individual autonomy of all humans [99]. There are no easy answers in our ever more culturally and ethically diverse societies: one-size-fits-all approaches seem doomed to fail, yet finding common ground is vital. If human embryos are to be deemed human beings with full personhood status, major implications ensue. That is the perspective espoused by Catholic doctrine, best exemplified by the late Pope John Paul II, who in 1995 famously stated that “the mere probability that a human person is involved would suffice to justify an absolutely clear prohibition of any intervention aimed at killing a human embryo” [100]. That approach does not differentiate between embryos edited for research purposes and edited embryos to be implanted. Conversely, prominent philosophers such as Kant, Locke and Fletcher have laid out criteria for identifying personhood closely tied to self-awareness, the capability to relate to others, self-control, rationality, and the use of memory, among others [101,102,103,104]. On the other hand, all such complexities and apparently irreconcilable views notwithstanding, there is no denying that banning or constraining research on human embryos could put a damper on scientific progress and stymie the development of therapies that could defeat currently untreatable diseases. Would that not be a moral and ethical imperative outweighing previously reported concerns? Again, no easy answers. | 7,528 | <h4>Embryonic personhood collapses <u>bio-medical innovation</u>. Impact is <u>uncurable</u> disease spread. </h4><p><strong>Piergentili 21</strong>, Institute of Molecular Biology and Pathology, Italian National Research Council (Roberto, et al, “CRISPR-Cas and Its Wide-Ranging Applications: From Human Genome Editing to Environmental Implications, Technical Limitations, Hazards and Bioethical Issues,” Cells, 10.5)</p><p><u><mark>If embryos are</mark> to be <strong><mark>ascribed personhood</mark> status</strong>, then <mark>they are entitled to</mark> have their</u> <u><strong><mark>inalienable</u></strong></mark> human <u><mark>rights</mark> upheld</u>. If, on the other hand, they are deemed as something in between, i.e., less than human beings but more than mere pools of cells, what moral rights should they have acknowledged, if any? Certainly, some point out that the first <u>experiments <mark>using CRISPR to edit</u></mark> human <u><mark>embryos</mark> occurred in 2015</u>, and since then, only few teams around the world have focused on the process and its potential [85], but recent studies have highlighted an underappreciated risk of CRISPR–Cas9 editing: <u>if embryos are deemed to have the right to</u> at least some degree of <u>legal</u> <u>safeguards</u>, <u>such</u> safety <u>concerns are likely to significantly <mark>inform the</u></mark> ongoing <u><mark>debate</u></mark> on the matter. In light of such major unsolved controversies, some have called for an international moratorium on all embryo editing [88,89], and some countries, including Canada, already have policies that ban human-embryo gene editing, irrespective of whether or not the edited embryo would be meant for implantation [90]. In the United States and Britain, on the other hand, an intermediate regulatory approach has been chosen. The US Food and Drug Administration views any use of CRISPR/Cas9 gene editing in humans as gene therapy, regulated by the FDA’s Center for Biologics Evaluation and Research (CBER). Clinical studies of gene therapy in human beings therefore require the submission of an investigational new drug application (IND) before they can be legally initiated in the United States. In addition, marketing gene therapy products calls for the submission and approval of a biologics license application (BLA). As a result of such requirements and restrictions, operating a private lab, with private funds, and conducting nonclinical, <u><mark>human gene therapy research is not illegal</u></mark>. <u><strong><mark>Nonetheless</u></strong></mark>, marketing such therapeutic options in the US would require FDA approval in terms of clinical studies and marketing. As far as it could be determined, no instances exist of a germline gene therapy product in the US; only somatic cell gene therapy products have been granted approval; currently, federal law prevents the FDA from reviewing or approving any application involving manipulated human embryos [91]. Again, it is necessary to draw a clear distinction between embryo editing for research purposes and the implantation of such edited embryos, which is ethically far more contentious. In the United Kingdom, for instance, the use of genome editing in embryos for the purpose of implantation is banned, albeit gene editing on discarded IVF embryos is lawful, provided that such embryos are destroyed immediately afterwards. In vitro culture of human embryos beyond 14 days after onset of embryo creation, i.e., after the appearance of the primitive streak, is prohibited: such a ban is enshrined in the Human Fertilisation and Embryology (HFE) Acts of 1990 and 2008 [92]. In Italy, specific provisions in law 40/2004 recognize the embryo as having rights from the moment of fertilization [93]. The law prohibits the use of embryos for any research unless it is specifically aimed towards improving the therapeutic and medical condition of the embryo itself [94,95]. Critics have pointed out the apparent paradox behind such a restriction, considering that in vivo embryos can be terminated up to 24 weeks through voluntary termination of pregnancy [96]. Some may in fact find it confusing that embryo research is required to stop so much earlier, particularly in light of the fact that it is arguably more ethically sustainable to use abandoned supernumerary embryos for research purposes that could benefit humanity, than to just dispose of them. While abortion ethics is beyond the scope of this review, it is worth pointing out that in these two scenarios, different fundamental goals are in play: legal termination of pregnancy stems from the need to uphold the right of women to have a choice and be in control of their body, whereas in vitro embryo research does not entail that issue. As for embryo experimentation, such intermediate regulatory approaches bear witness to the current uncertainty as to how strictly such techniques ought to be regulated, for the purpose of striking a balance between upholding bioethics precepts and fostering scientific progress for the common good. Nonetheless, nations with more lax, ambiguous or nonspecific regulatory frameworks governing new biomedical technologies may result in a worrisome “maverick” scientific environment in which untested techniques are made available. That has been found to be the case with mitochondrial replacement therapy (MRT), a form of nuclear transfer used as a germline therapy and believed to prevent the transmission of mitochondrial diseases and increase the likelihood of success in pregnancies [97]. Although MRT is banned in many countries due to its still dubious safety, clinics in Spain, Albania, Russia, Ukraine, and Israel have been found to offer the procedure [98]. That said, and irrespective of how individual countries decide to govern such techniques, <u><mark>the issue</mark> of whether scientists should seek to edit human embryos to prevent genetic diseases <mark>is <strong>controversial</u></strong></mark> in itself, because the genomic change which it creates is permanent and may be passed down for generations. Even if embryo experimentation should be deemed justified, by virtue of its potential benefit to the embryo itself and others, <u><strong><mark>embryos</u></strong></mark> obviously <u><strong><mark>cannot</mark> <mark>grant informed consent</u></strong></mark>, but are still liable to experience life-altering consequences which can extend throughout their lifetimes and affect future generations as well. Besides, as mentioned earlier on, the enforcement and practice of both ethical precepts and legal provisions are inextricably linked to a set of notions that are hardly carved in stone and universally acknowledged. Hence, <u><mark>the time at which a</mark> human life</u> (whether <u><strong><mark>embryo or fetus</u></strong></mark>) <u><mark>is</mark> deemed</u> a fully-fledged <u><strong><mark>human</u></strong></mark> being <u><mark>has <strong>far-reaching ramifications</strong> that encompass</mark> the crucial realm</u>s<u> of <strong><mark>health care</u></strong></mark>, law- and policy making and the inalienable right of individual autonomy of all humans [99]. There are no easy answers in our ever more culturally and ethically diverse societies: one-size-fits-all approaches seem doomed to fail, yet finding common ground is vital. <u><mark>If human embryos are</mark> to be <mark>deemed</mark> </u>human beings with full <u><strong><mark>personhood</u></strong></mark> <u><strong><mark>status</u></strong></mark>, <u><strong><mark>major implications ensue</u></strong></mark>. That is the perspective espoused by Catholic doctrine, best exemplified by the late Pope John Paul II, who in 1995 famously stated that “the mere probability that a human person is involved would suffice to justify an absolutely clear prohibition of any intervention aimed at killing a human embryo” [100]. That approach does not differentiate between embryos edited for research purposes and edited embryos to be implanted. Conversely, prominent philosophers such as Kant, Locke and Fletcher have laid out criteria for identifying personhood closely tied to self-awareness, the capability to relate to others, self-control, rationality, and the use of memory, among others [101,102,103,104]. On the other hand, all such complexities and apparently irreconcilable views notwithstanding, there is no denying that banning or <u><mark>constraining</u> <u>research</mark> <mark>on human embryos could put a <strong>damper on scientific progress</strong> and <strong>stymie</mark> the <mark>development of therapies</strong> that could defeat currently <strong>untreatable diseases</u></strong></mark>. Would that not be a moral and ethical imperative outweighing previously reported concerns? Again, no easy answers.</p> | 1NC---Northwestern---Round 1 | 1 | 1NC---DA | 72,183 | 220 | 6,710 | ./documents/ndtceda22/Kansas/PaMa/Kansas-PaMa-Neg-Owen-L-Coon-Memorial-Tournament-at-Northwestern-Round-1.docx | 925,315 | N | Owen L Coon Memorial Tournament at Northwestern | 1 | Dartmouth SV | Spencer Roetlin | 1AC
AI Civil Duties
1NC
Fetal Personhood DA
Colonialism K
Filibuster CP
Advantage CP
T-Vest
Developing Economies DA
T-Article III
Trade Bad
Block
Extinction K
Advantage CP
Fetal Personhood DA
T-Vest
2NR
Advantage CP
Fetal Personhood DA | ndtceda22/Kansas/PaMa/Kansas-PaMa-Neg-Owen-L-Coon-Memorial-Tournament-at-Northwestern-Round-1.docx | 2022-09-17 18:54:00 | 81,275 | PaMa | Kansas PaMa | Ji..... | Pa..... | Jo..... | Ma..... | 26,531 | Kansas | Kansas | null | null | 2,001 | ndtceda22 | NDT/CEDA College 2022-23 | 2,022 | cx | college | 2 |
|
4,074,641 | 1] Rural communities – plan solves disproportionate impacts on rural populations | Hirschfield 21 | Hirschfield 21 [Jared M. Hirschfield graduated in 2020 with a Bachelors degree in Biology and Political Science from Northeastern University in Boston, MA., Single-Payer Reform and Rural Health in the United States: Lessons from Our Northern Neighbor, 2021,Inquiries Journal,http://www.inquiriesjournal.com/articles/1889/single-payer-reform-and-rural-health-in-the-united-states-lessons-from-our-northern-neighbor, 8-16-2022 amrita] | The challenges of rural health were thrust into the mainstream Canadian health policy debate Referencing urban-rural disparities in life expectancy, infant mortality, and all-cause mortality rates, the Romanow Report found that “geography is, in fact, a determinant of health” Currently there is no coherent national approach for addressing issues specific to rural communities practically all movement in rural health policy has taken place at the provincial level. Rural-specific medical training has also been used to promote rural practice. The persistence of rural physician supply shortages, despite these policies, has frustrated rural stakeholders, some of whom feel that incentive programs have not addressed the “root causes” of the problem and have contributed to a self-perpetuating cycle of “band-aid” solutions While decentralized management theoretically helps to tailor the delivery and organization of services to the needs of each district, without an explicit focus on rural health and depending on the composition of the catchment areas/populations, even localized bodies risk overlooking the concerns of rural residents The ability of telehealth and other virtual care services to connect rural and remote Canadians with health care providers is cited by many rural stakeholders as key to the future of rural health care in Canada. the past two decades, telehealth has expanded rapidly, with the number of annual telehealth consultations nationwide predicted to reach more than one million in coming years the number of annual telehealth visits increased more than eightfold between 2008 and 2014. With telehealth utilization higher and therapeutic areas of care more diverse in northern Ontario than in southern parts of the province, this increase has been particularly consequential for the health of rural and remote communities Unlike in the United States, telehealth is widely covered in Canada. Rural and remote residents are able to access these services at no extra cost All provinces have designated telehealth billing codes, and some even pay additional fees to providers for delivering services through technology | urban-rural disparities in life expectancy and mortality geography is a determinant of health no coherent approach for addressing rural health physician supply shortages, despite policies frustrated stakeholders programs have not addressed root causes without an explicit focus on rural health even localized bodies risk overlooking telehealth connect rural with providers key to future of rural health telehealth expanded rapidly more than eightfold utilization higher and therapeutic areas more diverse increase consequential for rural communities telehealth is widely covered Rural residents access at no cost | Canadian Rural Health Policy The challenges of rural health were thrust into the mainstream Canadian health policy debate in December 2002 with the release of the final report of the Commission on the Future of Health Care in Canada, commonly known as the Romanow Report. Referencing urban-rural disparities in life expectancy, infant mortality, and all-cause mortality rates, the Romanow Report found that “geography is, in fact, a determinant of health” (Commission on the Future of Health Care in Canada 2002: 159). Concluding its section on rural health, the report declared: “Currently there is no coherent national approach for addressing issues specific to rural communities” (Commission on the Future of Health Care in Canada 2002: 159). The absence of a “coherent national approach” persists to date. Due to the division of governmental authority in Canada, practically all movement in rural health policy has taken place at the provincial level. In attempting to reduce the health penalty afflicting rural Canadians, provinces have concentrated their efforts on policies concerning physician distribution, hospital availability and accessibility, rural health services organization and planning, and telehealth coverage. Albeit modest, some pan-Canadian action on rural health issues has accompanied provincial efforts, particularly in recent years. Physician Distribution Policies aimed at ameliorating urban-rural disparities in health workforce supply have focused on financial incentives for recruitment of physicians and allied health professionals. In 1997, a landmark case out of the Supreme Court of British Columbia (Waldman v. The Medical Services Commission of British Columbia, et al.) barred provinces from reducing reimbursement rates for physicians who settled in well-served areas, meaning health officials were “denied the sticks and left with the carrots in their physician supply strategies” (Fierlbeck 2011: 133). Since then, all provinces have offered programs to incentivize, with differing degrees of generosity, physicians to relocate to rural and remote communities. Rural-specific medical training has also been used to promote rural practice. In 2005, Ontario established a rural-centric medical school, the Northern Ontario School of Medicine, focused on recruiting “rural-born” students and training the next generation of rural physicians. The persistence of rural physician supply shortages, despite these policies, has frustrated rural stakeholders, some of whom feel that incentive programs have not addressed the “root causes” of the problem and have contributed to a self-perpetuating cycle of “band-aid” solutions (Grzybowski and Kornelsen 2013: 11). Hospital Policy With 22% of Canadians (roughly 7 million residents) living more than a one-hour drive from a Level I or Level II trauma center, rural hospital policy is very much an ongoing priority. The Canadian constitution delegates the establishment and maintenance of hospitals to the respective provincial governments. While provinces have dealt with hospital issues in different ways, the accessibility principle of the Canada Health Act has generally been interpreted to mean financial—not geographic—accessibility, suggesting that rural Canadians do not have a right to immediate access to health services, but rather access “where and as available” (Fleet et al. 2013: 191; Rechel et al. 2016). The ambiguity of this interpretation has sparked debate over the medically and financially optimal locations of rural hospitals. Some provinces, particularly in times of economic decline or stagnation, have opted to close, repurpose, or merge rural hospitals—or have at least threatened to do so. In the 1990s, facing rising health care spending, federal cutbacks to Medicare, and a severe budget deficit, Saskatchewan turned its cost-cutting sights on rural hospitals. During this period, 52 rural hospitals in the province were “closed,” 23 of which continued to receive funding to operate as long-term care facilities, and 29 of which were offered one-time funding to convert to primary care centers (James 1999). Although less than a handful of hospitals closed permanently, the public response was vociferous, with many Saskatchewanians viewing rural hospital closures as “death certificate[s]” for affected communities (1030). In Ontario, the Health Services Restructuring Commission (HSRC) of 1996-2000 studied the province’s rural hospitals and made recommendations for reform. Approaching rural, northern, and remote hospitals differently than large, urban hospitals, the Commission released a rural health care framework that centered on the creation of Rural and Northern Health Care Networks, each composed of multiple hospitals offering varying levels of acute care (OMHLTC 1998; Sinclair, Rochon, and Leatt 2005: 1). Sixteen of these networks were designed by the Commission, but the prospect of political backlash in rural ridings prompted the government to stop short of mandating their establishment (108–9). The rural and northern components of the HSRC, while more aspirational than material, set the stage for Ontario’s subsequent experimentation with rural integrated care models. Health Services Planning As suggested by the saga of Ontario’s HSRC, innovation in the organization of health services has been central to Canada’s rural health care strategy. In many provinces, this innovation has taken the form of regionalization or districting. While decentralized management theoretically helps to tailor the delivery and organization of services to the needs of each district, without an explicit focus on rural health and depending on the composition of the catchment areas/populations, even localized bodies risk overlooking the concerns of rural residents. For instance, out of the 12 Local Health Integration Networks (LHINs) in southern Ontario, only one developed a rural-specific strategy (Whaley 2020). Ontario has experimented with rural-specific health models on a provincial level, however. In 2016, the Ontario Ministry of Health and Long-Term Care (OMHLTC) announced an investment of 2.5 million CAD in the creation of Rural Health Hubs at five health care centers around the province (Office of the Premier 2016). Rural Health Hubs integrated inpatient, outpatient, mental/behavioral, and long-term health care under a single funding envelope, in addition to contracting with “peripheral” health services (e.g., public health, ambulance services) and partnering with community organizations for the provision of social services, recreation, and education (Multi-Sector Rural Health Hub Advisory Committee 2015). Despite being well-received by the Ontario Hospital Association, the pilot program never expanded beyond the initial five Hubs. The election of a new Conservative provincial government in 2018 resulted in the creation of a new initiative, Ontario Health Teams, which replaced both the LHINs and Rural Health Hubs and raised concerns about the trajectory of rural health reform in the province. With many final design details, such as the budgeting methodology and the size of the catchment areas/populations, still to be determined, it is unclear how Ontario Health Teams will improve rural health care in the province, if at all. Telehealth The ability of telehealth and other virtual care services to connect rural and remote Canadians with health care providers is cited by many rural stakeholders as key to the future of rural health care in Canada. Over the past two decades, telehealth has expanded rapidly, with the number of annual telehealth consultations nationwide predicted to reach more than one million in coming years (Nasser and Chen 2014). In Ontario, the number of annual telehealth visits increased more than eightfold between 2008 and 2014. With telehealth utilization higher and therapeutic areas of care more diverse in northern Ontario than in southern parts of the province, this increase has been particularly consequential for the health of rural and remote communities (O’Gorman, Hogenbirk, and Warry 2016). Unlike in the United States, telehealth is widely covered in Canada. Rural and remote residents are able to access these services at no extra cost through their provincial insurance plans. All provinces have designated telehealth billing codes, and some even pay additional fees to providers for delivering services through technology (Waddell, Scallan, and Wilson 2018). | 8,458 | <h4><u><strong>1] Rural communities – plan solves disproportionate impacts on rural populations</h4><p>Hirschfield 21 </u></strong>[Jared M. Hirschfield graduated in 2020 with a Bachelors degree in Biology and Political Science from Northeastern University in Boston, MA., Single-Payer Reform and Rural Health in the United States: Lessons from Our Northern Neighbor, 2021,Inquiries Journal,http://www.inquiriesjournal.com/articles/1889/single-payer-reform-and-rural-health-in-the-united-states-lessons-from-our-northern-neighbor, 8-16-2022 amrita]</p><p>Canadian Rural Health Policy <u>The challenges of rural health were thrust into the mainstream Canadian health policy debate </u>in December 2002 with the release of the final report of the Commission on the Future of Health Care in Canada, commonly known as the Romanow Report. <u><strong>Referencing <mark>urban-rural disparities in life expectancy</mark>, infant mortality, <mark>and </mark>all-cause <mark>mortality </mark>rates, the Romanow Report found that “<mark>geography is</mark>, in fact, <mark>a determinant of health</mark>”</strong> </u>(Commission on the Future of Health Care in Canada 2002: 159). Concluding its section on rural health, the report declared: “<u>Currently there is <mark>no coherent </mark>national <mark>approach for addressing</mark> issues specific to rural communities</u>” (Commission on the Future of Health Care in Canada 2002: 159). The absence of a “coherent national approach” persists to date. Due to the division of governmental authority in Canada, <u>practically all movement in <mark>rural health</mark> policy has taken place at the provincial level.</u> In attempting to reduce the health penalty afflicting rural Canadians, provinces have concentrated their efforts on policies concerning physician distribution, hospital availability and accessibility, rural health services organization and planning, and telehealth coverage. Albeit modest, some pan-Canadian action on rural health issues has accompanied provincial efforts, particularly in recent years. Physician Distribution Policies aimed at ameliorating urban-rural disparities in health workforce supply have focused on financial incentives for recruitment of physicians and allied health professionals. In 1997, a landmark case out of the Supreme Court of British Columbia (Waldman v. The Medical Services Commission of British Columbia, et al.) barred provinces from reducing reimbursement rates for physicians who settled in well-served areas, meaning health officials were “denied the sticks and left with the carrots in their physician supply strategies” (Fierlbeck 2011: 133). Since then, all provinces have offered programs to incentivize, with differing degrees of generosity, physicians to relocate to rural and remote communities. <u>Rural-specific medical training has also been used to promote rural practice.</u> In 2005, Ontario established a rural-centric medical school, the Northern Ontario School of Medicine, focused on recruiting “rural-born” students and training the next generation of rural physicians. <u><strong>The persistence of rural <mark>physician supply shortages, despite</mark> these <mark>policies</mark>, has <mark>frustrated </mark>rural <mark>stakeholders</mark>, some of whom feel that incentive <mark>programs have not addressed</mark> the “<mark>root causes</mark>”</strong> of the problem and have contributed to a self-perpetuating cycle of “band-aid” solutions</u> (Grzybowski and Kornelsen 2013: 11). Hospital Policy With 22% of Canadians (roughly 7 million residents) living more than a one-hour drive from a Level I or Level II trauma center, rural hospital policy is very much an ongoing priority. The Canadian constitution delegates the establishment and maintenance of hospitals to the respective provincial governments. While provinces have dealt with hospital issues in different ways, the accessibility principle of the Canada Health Act has generally been interpreted to mean financial—not geographic—accessibility, suggesting that rural Canadians do not have a right to immediate access to health services, but rather access “where and as available” (Fleet et al. 2013: 191; Rechel et al. 2016). The ambiguity of this interpretation has sparked debate over the medically and financially optimal locations of rural hospitals. Some provinces, particularly in times of economic decline or stagnation, have opted to close, repurpose, or merge rural hospitals—or have at least threatened to do so. In the 1990s, facing rising health care spending, federal cutbacks to Medicare, and a severe budget deficit, Saskatchewan turned its cost-cutting sights on rural hospitals. During this period, 52 rural hospitals in the province were “closed,” 23 of which continued to receive funding to operate as long-term care facilities, and 29 of which were offered one-time funding to convert to primary care centers (James 1999). Although less than a handful of hospitals closed permanently, the public response was vociferous, with many Saskatchewanians viewing rural hospital closures as “death certificate[s]” for affected communities (1030). In Ontario, the Health Services Restructuring Commission (HSRC) of 1996-2000 studied the province’s rural hospitals and made recommendations for reform. Approaching rural, northern, and remote hospitals differently than large, urban hospitals, the Commission released a rural health care framework that centered on the creation of Rural and Northern Health Care Networks, each composed of multiple hospitals offering varying levels of acute care (OMHLTC 1998; Sinclair, Rochon, and Leatt 2005: 1). Sixteen of these networks were designed by the Commission, but the prospect of political backlash in rural ridings prompted the government to stop short of mandating their establishment (108–9). The rural and northern components of the HSRC, while more aspirational than material, set the stage for Ontario’s subsequent experimentation with rural integrated care models. Health Services Planning As suggested by the saga of Ontario’s HSRC, innovation in the organization of health services has been central to Canada’s rural health care strategy. In many provinces, this innovation has taken the form of regionalization or districting. <u>While <strong>decentralized management theoretically helps to tailor the delivery and organization of services to the needs of each district</strong>, <mark>without an explicit focus on rural health </mark>and depending on the composition of the catchment areas/populations, <mark>even localized bodies risk overlooking </mark>the concerns of rural residents</u>. For instance, out of the 12 Local Health Integration Networks (LHINs) in southern Ontario, only one developed a rural-specific strategy (Whaley 2020). Ontario has experimented with rural-specific health models on a provincial level, however. In 2016, the Ontario Ministry of Health and Long-Term Care (OMHLTC) announced an investment of 2.5 million CAD in the creation of Rural Health Hubs at five health care centers around the province (Office of the Premier 2016). Rural Health Hubs integrated inpatient, outpatient, mental/behavioral, and long-term health care under a single funding envelope, in addition to contracting with “peripheral” health services (e.g., public health, ambulance services) and partnering with community organizations for the provision of social services, recreation, and education (Multi-Sector Rural Health Hub Advisory Committee 2015). Despite being well-received by the Ontario Hospital Association, the pilot program never expanded beyond the initial five Hubs. The election of a new Conservative provincial government in 2018 resulted in the creation of a new initiative, Ontario Health Teams, which replaced both the LHINs and Rural Health Hubs and raised concerns about the trajectory of rural health reform in the province. With many final design details, such as the budgeting methodology and the size of the catchment areas/populations, still to be determined, it is unclear how Ontario Health Teams will improve rural health care in the province, if at all. Telehealth <u><strong>The ability of <mark>telehealth </mark>and other virtual care services to <mark>connect rural </mark>and remote Canadians <mark>with </mark>health care <mark>providers </mark>is cited by many rural stakeholders as <mark>key to </mark>the <mark>future of rural health </mark>care in Canada</strong>.</u> Over <u>the past two decades, <strong><mark>telehealth </mark>has <mark>expanded rapidly</mark>, with the number of annual telehealth consultations nationwide predicted to reach more than one million in coming years</u> </strong>(Nasser and Chen 2014). In Ontario, <u>the number of annual telehealth <strong>visits increased <mark>more than eightfold</mark> </strong>between 2008 and 2014. With telehealth <mark>utilization higher and therapeutic areas</mark> of care <mark>more diverse</mark> in northern Ontario than in southern parts of the province, <strong>this <mark>increase </mark>has been particularly <mark>consequential for </mark>the health of <mark>rural </mark>and remote <mark>communities</u></strong> </mark>(O’Gorman, Hogenbirk, and Warry 2016<strong>). <u>Unlike in the United States, <mark>telehealth is widely covered </mark>in Canada. <mark>Rural </mark>and remote <mark>residents </mark>are able to <mark>access </mark>these services <mark>at no</mark> extra <mark>cost</strong></mark> </u>through their provincial insurance plans. <u><strong>All provinces have designated telehealth billing codes, and some even pay additional fees </strong>to providers for delivering services through technology</u> (Waddell, Scallan, and Wilson 2018).</p> | 1AC | null | Adv - Pandemics | 328,367 | 97 | 139,554 | ./documents/hsld22/Saratoga/ArGa/Saratoga-ArGa-Aff-Loyola-Invitational-Round-3.docx | 921,112 | A | Loyola Invitational | 3 | Harvard-Westlake WL | Lukas Rhoades | 1ac - telehealth v2
nc - public option, econ da, t cant spec
1ar - all, condo, process cp
2nr - t
2ar - condo, t | hsld22/Saratoga/ArGa/Saratoga-ArGa-Aff-Loyola-Invitational-Round-3.docx | 2022-09-03 15:50:04 | 79,917 | ArGa | Saratoga ArGa | null | Ar..... | Ga..... | null | null | 26,838 | Saratoga | Saratoga | CA | 47,857 | 2,003 | hsld22 | HS LD 2022-23 | 2,022 | ld | hs | 1 |
4,386,304 | Market integration bolsters ASEAN integration and centrality – EU model can help facilitate it. | Intal 19 | Intal 19 Jr, Ponciano, and Mari Pangestu. "5. Skills Mobility and Development in ASEAN." (2019). (Professor of Economics and De La Selle University)//Elmer | The angst felt by the middle class as they face income and wage stagnation and job and social disruptions have fallen mainly on the role of foreign competition and foreign labour and public perceptions have not given due recognition to the disruptive effects of technological change and the inadequate catch-up in skills development of the labour force. The Association of Southeast Asian Nations (ASEAN) aspires and should continue to aspire in the foreseeable future towards a freer rather than free regional market for skilled labour or a free regional market for all labour This is in recognition of the political and social sensitivities associated with cross-border movement of people and labour amongst independent nation states (notwithstanding the rapid rise of crossborder tourism and student exchanges), and the particular huge diversities amongst the ten ASEAN member countries in geographic and demographic sizes, levels of economic development and wage incomes, and in socio-cultural-linguistic-religious characteristics of the population and labour force. it is necessary to have an ASEAN framework to regularise and facilitate movements to minimise the large numbers of irregular migrant workers found in many ASEAN countries and a code to protect the wellbeing of all regular and irregular, skilled, and unskilled foreign workers. By 2040, ASEAN should strive for an integrated skilled-labour market characterised by an enhanced circulation of skills within the region, and enabled by a mutual recognition of educational qualifications, professional licenses, and work experience; a minimal list of restricted or prohibited occupations for ASEAN foreign workers; preferential recruitment of ASEAN nationals where labour market tests are deemed necessary; and use of digital technology to disseminate labour market information in every ASEAN country. In an integrated ASEAN labour market for skills, the private sector should be able to hire skilled workers from any other ASEAN country with minimal regulatory barriers, and skilled workers in ASEAN should be able to choose to work in any ASEAN country ASEAN would require accelerated skill development in every ASEAN country so as to be internationally competitive, and economically and socially inclusive and cohesive Countries achieve the skills objective, not by working alone, but by cooperation and integration within the ASEAN Framework and the ASEAN Plus Frameworks. Skills mobility cum development is a positive sum game for both receiving and sending countries in an expanded pool of human resources with multi-national and deeper skill sets for every ASEAN country Skills mobility essential to ASEAN region’s rapid economic growth and industrial upgrading. It will require tapping skills and talent from everywhere in the ASEAN region and beyond Fostering a freer intra-regional flow of skills will provide a competitive edge to the ASEAN region A freer movement of skilled workers is also necessary for deepening ASEAN services integration. As the region becomes richer, its consumers will demand a variety of cross-border services Skills mobility is also crucial for achieving the ASEAN objective of inclusiveness and having a cohesive ASEAN community. Abilities and talents can be found throughout the ASEAN region. At the same time, opportunities to utilise these skills to their maximum potential are unevenly distributed across countries and geographic locations due to differences in level and rate of development and in economic structure. Skills mobility can make ASEAN a region where a person’s place of birth does not constrain his/her economic opportunities No single ASEAN economy can efficiently rely on domestic production of all the required skills. Current practices in ASEAN contain obstacles on the hiring of foreign skilled professionals by the private sector and their ban in the public sector (with the notable exception of Singapore) These include both formal and informal restrictions, including constitutional and legal restrictions and labour market tests, onerous and time-consuming procedures and various upfront payments The EU has broader integration objectives and guarantees the four fundamental freedoms on movement of goods, services, capital, and workers. Citizens of any EU country and their families have the right to live in any other EU country for up to 3 months; after which they must be working, enrolled in full-time education, or able to demonstrate financial independence permitted to work freely in the job and country of their choosing The EU has also implemented various policies to facilitate the movement of workers of any skill level These include mutual recognition of common forms of documentation and relative streamlining of entry processes There is a need to emphasise the benefits of working in another ASEAN country, which include closeness to home and cultural similarities; diversity of work, linguistic, and cultural experiences, which can enhance soft skills; and the facilitation of ASEAN-community building. It is necessary to minimise visa procedures and labour market access restrictions so ASEAN professionals can access better employment and income opportunities in the region. ASEAN migration should also entail less financial and time costs of labour mobility and family disruptions | ASEAN should continue towards freer regional market for labour it is necessary to have framework to regularise and facilitate movements to minimise irregular migrant workers strive for integrated market enhanced circulation of skills within the region and mutual recognition of qualifications licenses and work experience able to hire workers from any other ASEAN country with minimal regulatory barriers and workers able to choose to work in any ASEAN country require development in every ASEAN country to be internationally competitive Countries achieve integration within the ASEAN Framework an expanded pool of human resources for every ASEAN country Skills mobility essential to ASEAN region’s rapid economic growth Fostering intra-regional flow will provide competitive edge crucial for achieving inclusiveness and having a cohesive ASEAN community. opportunities to utilise skills to maximum potential are unevenly distributed Current practices in ASEAN contain obstacles on foreign professionals constitutional and legal restrictions onerous time-consuming procedures and various upfront payments EU integration guarantees freedoms on movemen of workers permitted to work freely in country of their choosing mutual recognition of common forms of documentation benefits of working in another ASEAN country facilitation of community building It is necessary to minimise visa procedures and labour market access restrictions so ASEAN professionals can access better employment and opportunities in the region. | Introduction: ASEAN Vision 2040 and the Role of Skills Mobility and Development The North American Free Trade Agreement (NAFTA) break-up, Brexit in the European Union (EU), and the anti-globalisation wave are in part due to insufficient attention by policymakers and analysts for the distributional aspects of globalisation and regional economic integration. The angst felt by the middle class as they face income and wage stagnation and job and social disruptions have fallen mainly on the role of foreign competition and foreign labour and public perceptions have not given due recognition to the disruptive effects of technological change and the inadequate catch-up in skills development of the labour force. The Association of Southeast Asian Nations (ASEAN) aspires and should continue to aspire in the foreseeable future towards a freer rather than free regional market for skilled labour or a free regional market for all labour. This is in recognition of the political and social sensitivities associated with cross-border movement of people and labour amongst independent nation states (notwithstanding the rapid rise of crossborder tourism and student exchanges), and the particular huge diversities amongst the ten ASEAN member countries in geographic and demographic sizes, levels of economic development and wage incomes, and in socio-cultural-linguistic-religious characteristics of the population and labour force. While not recommending the free or freer movement of the less-skilled and unskilled-labour across the region, it is necessary to have an ASEAN framework to regularise and facilitate such movements to minimise the large numbers of irregular migrant workers found in many ASEAN countries and a code to protect the wellbeing of all regular and irregular, skilled, and unskilled foreign workers. By 2040, ASEAN should strive for an integrated skilled-labour market characterised by an enhanced circulation of skills within the region, and enabled by a mutual recognition of educational qualifications, professional licenses, and work experience; a minimal list of restricted or prohibited occupations for ASEAN foreign workers; preferential recruitment of ASEAN nationals where labour market tests are deemed necessary; and use of digital technology to disseminate labour market information in every ASEAN country. In an integrated ASEAN labour market for skills, the private sector should be able to hire skilled workers from any other ASEAN country with minimal regulatory barriers, and skilled workers in ASEAN should be able to choose to work in any ASEAN country. Also by 2040, the ASEAN region would have further embraced the service and knowledge economy and the digital age. ASEAN would require accelerated skill development in every ASEAN country so as to be internationally competitive, and economically and socially inclusive and cohesive. Countries can achieve the skills objective, not by working alone, but by cooperation and integration within the ASEAN Framework and the ASEAN Plus Frameworks. Skills mobility cum development is a positive sum game for both receiving and sending countries in the ASEAN integration project. It results in an expanded pool of human resources with multi-national and deeper skill sets for every ASEAN country. II. Why Skills Mobility and Skills Development are Important Current demographic, economic, and technological trends mean that the economies of ASEAN Member States (AMS) by 2040 will reach highand upper middle-income status, and have a growing labour force that is increasingly skilled (with declining working-age population in ageing societies offset by the youthful populations in other ASEAN countries). They will have achieved technological advances, particularly the digital revolution, e-commerce and industry 4.0, and demand an increasingly skilled labour force, including skills that are currently scarce across ASEAN (or even non-existent). 1. Skills mobility is essential to the ASEAN region’s continuing rapid economic growth and industrial upgrading. It will require tapping skills and talent from everywhere in the ASEAN region and beyond. Fostering a freer intra-regional flow of skills will provide a competitive edge to the ASEAN region. 2. A freer movement of skilled workers is also necessary for deepening ASEAN services integration. As the region becomes richer, its consumers will demand a variety of cross-border services. Each AMS has unique services that can be demanded elsewhere in ASEAN. For example, ASEAN consumers may want to eat in restaurants run by Thai chefs, and access online education provided by Malaysian education sites and fintech services by Singapore financial institutions. With skills mobility, supplying these services becomes realisable and costeffective. 3. Skills mobility is also crucial for achieving the ASEAN objective of inclusiveness and having a cohesive ASEAN community. Abilities and talents can be found throughout the ASEAN region. At the same time, opportunities to utilise these skills to their maximum potential are unevenly distributed across countries and geographic locations due to differences in level and rate of development and in economic structure. Skills mobility can make ASEAN a region where a person’s place of birth does not constrain his/her economic opportunities. 4. Skills mobility is closely associated with production of skills for the regional, global, and future labour market. It is well known that employees of multinational corporations (MNCs), with work experience and socio-cultural-linguistic and management skills sets honed by international and regional postings are widely sought after by corporations (both big and small) seeking to venture or expand into new regional and international markets. A growing ASEAN labour force needs to be better educated and trained for the ongoing technological revolution and globalisation. No single ASEAN economy can efficiently rely on domestic production of all the required skills. As in the case of goods production, in the production of human capital there also exist comparative advantages and scale economies. There are large benefits to be gained by cooperating in the production of human capital and expanding the talent pool beyond national borders. 5. Looking towards 2040, ASEAN must consider the implications of the digital age for labour employment and mobility. E-commerce and other e-services can be provided across borders without physical movement of providers, resulting in ‘virtual migration’. This would include telemedicine, business process outsourcing and call centres, online education and fintech services. These service providers can work in their home base without migrating. The increasing demand for virtual migrants would help to offset some of the concerns of receiving and sending countries and migrant workers themselves regarding physical labour mobility. However, ASEAN would need a framework governing the virtual employment of foreign workers. III. Skills Mobility in ASEAN – Existing Measures and Challenges The importance of skills mobility is articulated in numerous ASEAN agreements and vision documents. The ASEAN Framework Agreement on Services (AFAS) and the ASEAN Economic Community (AEC) Blueprint indicate that labour mobility is considered an important part of the ASEAN integration project. In the Declaration of ASEAN Concord II in 2003, AMS are committed to ‘facilitate movement of business persons, skilled labour, and talents’ for deeper economic integration. The AEC Blueprint in 2007 reflected this commitment by specifying key areas of collaboration amongst AMS, including the facilitation of working visas and the harmonisation and standardisation of qualifications, including Mutual Recognition Arrangements for professionals (MRAs). The ASEAN Agreement on the Movement of Natural Persons (AMNP) was signed in 2012 to enhance the flow of natural persons engaging in trade in goods, services, and investment. In 2014, ASEAN Economic Ministers endorsed the ASEAN Qualification Reference Framework (AQRF) to complement the MRAs by providing guidelines for comparing qualifications across member states, with voluntary referencing. The AEC Blueprint 2025 reaffirms that facilitating the movement of skilled labour and business visitors is a key element of a ‘highly integrated and cohesive ASEAN economy’ (AEC Blueprint, 2025). Current practices in ASEAN contain obstacles on the hiring of foreign skilled professionals by the private sector and their ban in the public sector (with the notable exception of Singapore) These include both formal and informal restrictions, including constitutional and legal restrictions and labour market tests, onerous and time-consuming procedures and various upfront payments. It would be helpful for employers and foreign workers if these restrictions are liberalised and made transparent and the procedures simplified. While the AEC Blueprint focuses on enhancing the flow of skilled and professionals, they account for less than 10% of intra-regional labour flows, with Singapore the leading destination. The majority of intraregional migrants are middle- and low-skilled and irregular, and are commonly found in construction, agriculture, and domestic work. There is no AEC coverage on them. ASEAN’s major receiving countries are Malaysia, Thailand, and Singapore. Malaysia and Thailand host millions of irregular workers from neighbouring ASEAN countries. The ASEAN Declaration on the Protection and Promotion of the Rights of Migrant Workers, known as the Cebu declaration, makes commitments to protect migrant workers, but this is non-binding. ASEAN has reaffirmed this by signing the ASEAN Consensus on the Protection and Promotion of the Rights of Migrant Workers, but the commitments remain voluntary (ASEAN Secretariat 2017). An assessment of the progress made by ASEAN in regional skilled labour mobility (Testaverde et al., 2017) concluded that, notwithstanding the commitments and framework agreements that regional leaders place on this issue, the slowness of actual implementation highlights the difficult political and regulatory landscape. The ASEAN agreements cover skilled workers and professionals, but there are several gaps in its provisions. They facilitate the issuance of visas and employment passes, and work to harmonise and standardise qualifications. However, most foreign skilled professionals are intra-corporate transferees, AFAS and AMNP do not cover individual professionals and skilled workers, and MRAs cover only a small segment of ASEAN professionals. AMS have signed MRAs in six areas: engineering, nursing, architecture, medicine, dentistry, and tourism and framework agreements in surveying and accountancy. Conclusion and implementation of MRAs for professionals have been a long and arduous process, in part due to ‘occupational protectionism’. There are genuine cross-country differences in what a professional must know to practice, and automatic recognition of foreign qualifications and work experience is rare. Partial recognition is usually possible with compensatory measures to bridge differences in training and quality standards and work experience, but this can be difficult and highly sensitive. The implementation of MRAs is timeconsuming, technically demanding, and sometimes politically difficult as a wide range of stakeholders are responsible for different aspects of the recognition process. It requires support from the public and professional associations, which in turn rests on perceptions of benefits and threats pose by foreign professionals. More importantly, MRAs do not guarantee labour market access, which is still subject to national laws, regulations, and measures. The challenges to ASEAN skills mobility have been categorised by Papademetriou et al. (2015) as follows: (i) Issues related to the recognition of credentials. (ii) Restrictions on hiring foreign workers in certain occupations and industries, and on employment visas. (iii) Perceived costly barriers due to cultural, language, and socioeconomic differences. It is necessary to overcome each of these challenges to achieve full skills mobility. The second challenge and part of the first challenge can be achieved by reforming the laws and regulations and following through on commitments such as expanding MRAs on skills. However, a continuing challenge will require a positive change in perceptions and behaviours of individuals and businesses surrounding labour mobility within ASEAN, which would in turn influence people’s economic decisions to move. Without a serious effort to enhance ASEAN skills mobility, the region may lose its talent to other parts of the world. ASEAN’s major sending countries are Indonesia, Myanmar, the Philippines, and Viet Nam, with major destinations in the Middle East, Europe, North America, and Australia–New Zealand rather than in ASEAN. It is important to note the reasons behind the extra-ASEAN preference and strategise to make ASEAN an attractive destination region of choice for skilled migrants. Rising job opportunities and wage levels, an increasingly open society that accepts foreigners, and an increasingly better living environment can make the ASEAN region an increasingly attractive destination. IV. Benefits and Costs to Sending and Receiving Countries and Migrant Workers Since labour market liberalisation is a politically sensitive issue, it is necessary to evaluate the benefits and costs to ASEAN countries and workers. A. For Receiving Countries and Citizen Workers Affected Benefits include (i) relaxing domestic shortages of general and specific skills; (ii) upgrading and developing specific sectors of the economy (e.g., educational, medical, and information technology services); (iii) attracting foreign direct investment (FDI) and foreign MNCs by relaxing rules on intra-corporate transferees and business visitors; (iv) relaxing skill shortages faced particularly by small and medium-sized enterprises (SMEs) as compared to large and foreign enterprises; (iv) encouraging the development of private enterprise and entrepreneurship. Concerns include (i) at the national level, countries and communities may be concerned about overcrowding and upward price pressures from increased demand for public spaces, housing, education, health and recreational facilities, and the displacement of local SMEs and professionals by FDI and foreign professionals; (ii) at the individual level, citizen workers may be concerned about job displacement and retrenchment, competitive pressure from foreign workers and dimmer prospects of job promotion. (iii) communities and individuals often cannot make the distinction between job displacement due to technological change and due to the entry of foreign firms and foreign workers. Receiving countries could provide educational and training opportunities for foreign students to work after graduation; minimise discrimination against the foreign workforce in various areas of public policy; ensure the fair treatment of workers by employers; and provide better labour market information on areas with skills shortages. Ultimately, ASEAN should aspire to be a region characterised by the circulation of skills, with each country both receiving and sending skilled professionals in line with its economic structure. B. For Sending Countries and Workers Seeking Foreign Employment Benefits include (i) reduced socio-political pressures from a large pool of educated unemployed and underemployed persons; (ii) inward remittances contribute to improved household incomes, and the balance of payments; (iii) mobility of labour (as well as tourism) improves knowledge, understanding, and appreciation of ASEAN neighbours and is an excellent way of building an ASEAN Community. Concerns include: (i) brain drain, although this can be offset by eventual returnees (and their skills, experience, and financial assets) and growing role of virtual migration; (ii) concern over lack of protection of their rights and welfare of nationals working abroad; (iii) for individuals, migration for work is largely an economic decision made by balancing the costs and benefits of seeking work abroad. Benefits include opportunities for a better income and career advancement, to travel and gain work experience in a different environment, and in some cases the opportunity to migrate permanently. Costs include financial, social, and psychological costs such as adapting to a foreign environment, family disruptions, and the difficulty of re-integrating upon return. Sending countries could improve educational standards, curricula, and the linguistic skills of potential migrant workers; seek recognition and accreditation of their degrees and diplomas; improve knowledge and understanding of the cultures and social norms of other ASEAN countries; improve the provision of information about the labour market in destination countries; facilitate exit procedures and minimise exit costs of obtaining passport, visas, transportation, and accreditation; and troubleshoot problems and attend to the needs of its nationals abroad through its embassies and labour attaches V. Lessons from the North American Free Trade Agreement and the European Union NAFTA and the EU have very different models of managing labour mobility and its interplay with trade liberalisation, corresponding to each bloc’s economic and policy objectives. Their provisions offer useful lessons for the ASEAN labour mobility objective. A. NAFTA now defunct and replaced by the US, Canada, Mexico Agreement (USCMA) NAFTA focused on trade integration, with relatively narrow provisions for skilled labour mobility. The NAFTA Treaty established a new migration category in the US available exclusively to workers from Mexico and Canada pursuing jobs in 70 highly skilled occupations (e.g. accountants, architects, computer systems analysts, economists, engineers, hotel managers, etc.). The lack of a quota and an easier application process made the NAFTA Treaty visa more attractive than the US global H1-1B visa. However, NAFTA did not include specific provisions to facilitate the movement of low-skilled labour. The US and Canada offered limited avenues for the legal temporary employment of foreign low-skilled workers. Applicants from Canada and Mexico with college degrees and job offers in the US were eligible to apply and there was no numerical quota. Employment was for 3 years, and the visa was renewable indefinitely. Migrants could bring their dependents. Canadian applicants could apply on entry to the US with only proof of a job offer and proof of education; there was no requirement for a labour market test in which employers certify that US workers were unavailable to fill positions. On the other hand, Mexican applicants must apply for the visa in Mexico and the employer must go undergo a labour market test. B. The EU The EU has broader integration objectives and guarantees the four fundamental freedoms on movement of goods, services, capital, and workers. Citizens of any EU country and their families have the right to live in any other EU country for up to 3 months; after which they must be working, enrolled in full-time education, or able to demonstrate financial independence. After 5 years of residence, they earn the right to permanent residence. Citizens of any EU country are also generally permitted to work freely in the job and country of their choosing. The EU has also implemented various policies to facilitate the movement of workers of any skill level. These include mutual recognition of common forms of documentation and relative streamlining of entry processes; and the portability across the EU of various social rights and entitlements, including access to health care, social welfare, and pensions. In actuality, migration flows have generally been rather subdued despite the accession of Central and Eastern Europe countries, possibly due to various other barriers. Also, EU member countries may restrict access to their labour markets for public sector jobs and ‘in an emergency’ with approval from the European Commission; and may impose temporary mobility restrictions on citizens of new EU members. Besides direct policy, many supportive programmes facilitate movement within the EU. The Erasmus Programme began in 1987 as a student exchange programme for Europeans, while the parallel Erasmus Mundus Programme is oriented towards non-Europeans. Erasmus Plus (2014–2020), which succeeded Erasmus, incorporates all EU schemes for education, training youth, and sport. It provides grants to give students and teachers or trainers a unique opportunity to participate in different European countries. Previously, these opportunities were restricted to applicants who had completed at least 1 year of study at the tertiary level, but are now also available to secondary school students. Participants study at least 3 months or do an internship for a period of at least 2 months and up to 1 academic year in another European country. The period spent abroad is recognised by their university when they return. Students do not pay extra tuition fees to the host institution and can apply for an Erasmus grant through the home institution to help cover the additional expenses of living abroad. Millions of European students in thousands of higher education institutions participate in Erasmus across 37 European countries. The main benefit of the programme is that it fosters learning and understanding of the host country, as both a time for learning and a chance to socialise and bond with other European students. Similarly, the Bologna Process is based on an intergovernmental agreement with membership extended beyond the EU. The 1999 Bologna Declaration committed 29 European governments to pursue complementary higher education reforms and establish a European Higher Education Area of compatible national systems. Participation and cooperation are voluntary. Bilateral agreements between countries and institutions oblige signatories to recognise each other’s degrees, moving from strict convergence in time spent on qualifications towards a competency-based system. National reforms have made university qualifications more easily comparable across Europe. Country scorecards (reports, conferences, communiqués, and policy declarations) are closely monitored at the European-level and structured around a series of biennial ministerial meetings. The European Commission has played an active role in this process. The EU Credit Transfer and Accumulation System (ECTS), first piloted within the Erasmus networks, has become the European standard. The European Commission also provides financial incentives for higher education cooperation and reform projects in line with the Bologna objectives, as well as funding national Bologna Promoters, and informational activities. It also promoted joint degrees and the bachelor/master structure through its Erasmus Mundus programme and other pilot studies. Likewise, the European Qualifications Framework (EQF) aims to relate different national qualifications systems to a common European reference framework. Individuals and employers use the EQF to understand and compare more easily the qualification levels of different countries and education and training systems. This means that there is no need for individuals to repeat this learning when migrating. The core of the EQF comprises eight reference levels (1–8) describing what a learner knows, understands, and is able to do (‘learning outcomes’). Levels of national qualifications are placed at one of the central reference levels. This makes it much easier to compare national qualifications. ECTS credits are a standard means of comparing the ‘volume of learning based on the defined learning outcomes and their associated workload’ for higher education across the EU and collaborating European countries (European Commission, 2017: 10). ECTS credits are used to facilitate transfer and progression throughout the EU. VI. The Role of ASEAN in Regional Skills Mobility and Development 1. Emphasise the welfare gains from ASEAN skilled labour mobility The economic benefits of cross-border labour mobility are numerous. For destination countries, positive impacts include better employment opportunities and higher wages for workers; however, low-skilled workers could have negative impacts in rigid labour markets. For sending countries, out-migration boost wages for those remaining behind, migrant workers benefit from higher wages received, and their households benefit from remittances. Overall, there are economic benefits from improved economic growth and from remittances. The negative effects of ‘brain drain’ in sending countries are offset by ‘brain circulation’ and eventual returnees. The EU and NAFTA experiences indicate that intra-regional skills mobility remains limited even in the absence of legal and policy barriers. The same may hold true in the ASEAN region. Additionally, when skills migration takes place, a preference for non-ASEAN destinations may emerge, linked to permanent migration to North America, Western Europe, Australia, and New Zealand. There is a need to emphasise the benefits of working in another ASEAN country, which include closeness to home and cultural similarities; diversity of work, linguistic, and cultural experiences, which can enhance soft skills; and the facilitation of ASEAN-community building. Familiarity with other ASEAN countries can be enhanced by intra-ASEAN student and staff exchanges and tourism. For employers, businesses, and professional groups, more exchanges and cooperation promote business activities and intra-ASEAN FDI and services, leading to the employment and re-deployment of staff who are ASEAN nationals. 2. Incentives to attract ASEAN foreign professionals and skills as well as safeguarding the interests of citizen workers The key advantages of ASEAN destinations include closeness to home and less pronounced sociocultural diversities relative to destinations in North America, Europe, Australia, and New Zealand. It is necessary to minimise visa procedures and labour market access restrictions so that ASEAN professionals can access better employment and income opportunities in the region. ASEAN migration should also entail less financial and time costs of labour mobility and family disruptions. ASEAN can also provide a centralised database of job market information. To attract foreign skills and talents, policy and practice should provide a welcoming environment, including availability and competitive cost of housing, transport and education, competitive taxation rates, portable social security plans, ease of sending remittances overseas, and a safe and unpolluted living and working environment. For skills and talent seeking eventual migration and permanent settlement, availability of permanent residence schemes is an important attraction. Governments are elected by citizens, hence concerns over foreign competition should be addressed in parallel to the welcome mat for foreigners, and that the foreign presence should not undermine social cohesion. In all countries, employment of nationals has priority over employment of foreigners but such ‘protectionism’ should not lead to shortages of skilled personnel that ultimately prevent the country from achieving its economic growth and upgrading potential and fail to enhance the wellbeing of its citizenry. Policy and practice would have to ensure that citizen workers have developed technical, social and linguistic skill sets that enable them to compete effectively with foreigners within their country or abroad. Policy and practice would also have to ensure that citizen workers are not discriminated in the recruitment, employment and promotion processes of private sector employers. . Accelerate the ASEAN-wide accreditation system for universities and training institutions The process of comparing and recognising academic and training credentials within a country is complex enough but the issue becomes even more problematic and sensitive across the 10 diverse ASEAN countries. To hire a foreign skilled worker or professional from another ASEAN country, the prospective employer must assess the merits of the paper qualification and work experience. For top-end jobs, employers can resort to expensive head-hunting recruitment agencies. But for lower-level jobs, an ASEAN-wide accreditation of education and training institutions would be a tremendous help to employers in their assessment of suitable candidates for employment and promotion. 4. Providing an equal opportunity for developing relevant skillsets An individual born anywhere in ASEAN needs to be given equal opportunity to develop skill sets that are in demand in the region. At the national level, this means a comprehensive education and training system available to all. Financing and finding the teachers put tremendous strain on low-income countries and policymakers will need to prioritise and seek foreign assistance (in ASEAN, amongst ASEAN dialogue partners, international and regional institutions). It is essential that the education and training process results in the production of marketable skill-sets, embodying some quality-standard and relevance to the present economic structure of the country as well as its future evolution. While expanding the enrolment and scope of tertiary institutions, all ASEAN countries would need to improve the quality dimension of its institutions so that they can eventually compete with the best in the world. In this respect, the Singapore experience may offer some useful lessons for some ASEAN countries. Singapore’s school system has been producing students that achieve high Programme for International Student Assessment (PISA) test scores run by the Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development (OECD) and Singapore’s leading universities are ranked by various international ranking agencies as amongst the best in Asia. Also, Singapore’s education and training system is being revamped to prepare students for the technological requirements of future jobs. Singapore has achieved this level of educational excellence through continuous effort in developing Singapore’s human resources, learning from the best institutions and examples the world has to offer, entering into partnerships with worldrenowned institutions, and recruiting from the world’s best from the advanced industrial countries, China and India to teach and research in its universities, research institutes, and training centres. The Singapore education and training system is currently being revamped to meet the future job requirements brought on by technological changes. At the ASEAN regional level, this offers tremendous opportunity for cooperation and integration in a win-win framework. ASEAN countries that are more educationally advanced, with educational and training institutions of international standing and repute, could build physical campuses in other ASEAN countries and also offer online education (currently undertaken in the ASEAN region mainly by non-ASEAN universities and colleges). 5. Develop strong regional consciousness through travel and study experiences Migration and interest in migration often begin when individuals are studying abroad, and many ASEAN students who study overseas remain abroad for work experience and opportunities. There is more limited student movement amongst ASEAN countries, in part due to a dearth of scholarships and financial assistance schemes, and a lower profile of ASEAN tertiary educational institutions. Therefore, ASEAN should encourage student exchange through the ASEAN University Network (AUN), and Singapore’s ASEAN scholarships, amongst others. This can be achieved by improving the global rankings of ASEAN universities and training institutes. 6. Manage a gradual approach towards ASEAN labour mobility and integration Given the diversity of the AMS, ASEAN should adopt a more gradual approach towards an integrated ASEAN skilled labour market. Ideally, a regional framework based on binding bilateral agreements would be preferable, perhaps within a subset of AMS. Such an ‘ASEAN minus X’ approach would provide some flexibility. However, a voluntary regional approach may be appropriate to accommodate the diverse sensitivities in ASEAN. A more inclusive and equitable ASEAN and AEC could emphasise regional and bilateral cooperation instead of binding integration agreements. AMS have different priorities and face different socioeconomic realities. However, when political leaders and policymakers formulate and implement national visions, plans, and policies, they should also consider impacts on other ASEAN countries and, whenever and wherever possible, adopt positive-sum, not zero-sum, strategies. The ASEAN body need to take a leadership role in driving the discussion around mobility. However, countries at the top end of economic development (Malaysia, Singapore, and Thailand) could also play a more pro-active role in driving skills mobility and development. VII. Concluding Summary Due to demographic, economic, social, and technological changes in the ASEAN region and globally, ASEAN needs to move forward with skills mobility to build competitive and knowledge-driven economies. This will help maintain a united ASEAN and will contribute towards ASEAN centrality. A single ASEAN market for skills and talent will require free movement for various occupations and non-discriminatory treatment for foreign workers in national legislations and policies, employment practices, employment remuneration and benefits, and common quality assurance and qualifications recognition. A single ASEAN market for skills and talents by 2040 pre-supposes the establishment of a single market for goods and services in ASEAN. A single market for goods appears more likely than a single market for services as services delivery requires Mode 3 (right of establishment) and Mode 4 (temporary movement of natural persons). Mode 4 covers contractual service suppliers (self-employed independent service suppliers and employees of foreign service suppliers), intra-corporate transferees and persons directly recruited by the foreign affiliate, and service sellers or persons responsible for setting up a commercial presence. While intra-corporate transferees are well taken care of with the liberalisation of FDI, liberalising Mode 4 would take care of other service suppliers as well. Service-market integration will complement the skilled labour-market integration. The digital age makes possible virtual migration with an important impact on ASEAN skilled labour mobility. Many more services are being delivered online with short visits by service suppliers, and do not require the physical movement of service suppliers. This would remove some of the concerns over overcrowding or sociocultural disruptions by an influx of in-migrants (although the same is felt about large influxes of tourists) and concerns over brain drain caused by large outflows of the skilled. The economic importance of labour market integration cannot be overstated. Yet, it is necessary not to integrate hastily and acknowledge political and social concerns. First, a liberalised skills market, coupled with a strong push towards upskilling of the domestic labour force, can be an effective strategy for achieving rapid growth without leaving anyone behind. Second, given the vast differences amongst ASEAN countries in geographic and population sizes and in levels of economic development and wage incomes, free movement of all labour is politically unrealistic. Third, many ASEAN countries are still engaged in post-independence nation building and are struggling with managing plural societies and may not welcome more cultural, religious, and linguistic diversity. Some are looking outward beyond ASEAN. Some are internally divided and prioritise national cohesion over regional cohesion. There are also growing concerns related to security and terrorism prompting stricter immigration controls. A concerted effort is needed to instil a sense of common destiny amongst ASEAN countries. Moving forward, AMS could agree on an ASEAN-wide framework for governing the movement of skilled workers, with provisions for bilateral (preferably binding) agreements between AMS to operationalise the framework. Such bilateral agreements could be gradually expanded to cover ASEAN as a whole so that the region can achieve meaningful skills mobility. | 36,600 | <h4><strong>Market integration <u>bolsters</u> ASEAN <u>integration</u> and <u>centrality</u> – EU model can help facilitate it. </h4><p>Intal 19</strong> Jr, Ponciano, and Mari Pangestu. "5. Skills Mobility and Development in ASEAN." (2019). (Professor of Economics and De La Selle University)//Elmer </p><p>Introduction: ASEAN Vision 2040 and the Role of Skills Mobility and Development The North American Free Trade Agreement (NAFTA) break-up, Brexit in the European Union (EU), and the anti-globalisation wave are in part due to insufficient attention by policymakers and analysts for the distributional aspects of globalisation and regional economic integration. <u>The angst felt by the middle class as they face income and wage stagnation and job and social disruptions have fallen mainly on the role of foreign competition and foreign labour and public perceptions have not given due recognition to the disruptive effects of technological change and the inadequate catch-up in skills development of the labour force.</u> <u>The Association of Southeast Asian Nations (<strong><mark>ASEAN</strong></mark>) aspires and <strong><mark>should continue</strong> </mark>to aspire in the foreseeable future <strong><mark>towards</strong> </mark>a <strong><mark>freer</strong> </mark>rather than free <strong><mark>regional market for</strong> </mark>skilled <strong><mark>labour</strong> </mark>or a free regional market for all labour</u>. <u>This is in recognition of the political and social sensitivities associated with cross-border movement of people and labour amongst independent nation states (notwithstanding the rapid rise of crossborder tourism and student exchanges), and the particular huge diversities amongst the ten ASEAN member countries in geographic and demographic sizes, levels of economic development and wage incomes, and in socio-cultural-linguistic-religious characteristics of the population and labour force.</u> While not recommending the free or freer movement of the less-skilled and unskilled-labour across the region, <u><strong><mark>it is necessary</u></strong> <u><strong>to have</u></strong> <u></mark>an ASEAN</u> <u><strong><mark>framework to regularise and facilitate</u></strong> </mark>such <u><strong><mark>movements</u></strong> <u><strong>to minimise </strong></mark>the large numbers of</u> <u><strong><mark>irregular migrant workers</u></strong></mark> <u>found in many ASEAN countries and a code to protect the wellbeing of all regular and irregular, skilled, and unskilled foreign workers. By 2040, ASEAN should <strong><mark>strive for</strong> </mark>an <strong><mark>integrated</strong> </mark>skilled-labour <strong><mark>market</strong> </mark>characterised by an <strong><mark>enhanced circulation of skills within the region</strong></mark>, <strong><mark>and</strong> </mark>enabled by a <strong><mark>mutual recognition of</strong> </mark>educational <strong><mark>qualifications</strong></mark>, professional <strong><mark>licenses</strong></mark>, <strong><mark>and work experience</strong></mark>; a minimal list of restricted or prohibited occupations for ASEAN foreign workers; preferential recruitment of ASEAN nationals where labour market tests are deemed necessary; and use of digital technology to disseminate labour market information in every ASEAN country.</u> <u>In an integrated ASEAN labour market for skills, the private sector should be <strong><mark>able to hire</strong> </mark>skilled <strong><mark>workers</strong> <strong>from any other ASEAN country</strong> <strong>with minimal regulatory barriers</strong></mark>,</u> <u><strong><mark>and</u></strong> <u></mark>skilled</u> <u><strong><mark>workers</u></strong> <u></mark>in ASEAN should be</u> <u><strong><mark>able to choose to work in any ASEAN country</u></strong></mark>. Also by 2040, the ASEAN region would have further embraced the service and knowledge economy and the digital age. <u>ASEAN would <strong><mark>require</strong> </mark>accelerated skill <strong><mark>development in every ASEAN country</strong> </mark>so as <strong><mark>to be</strong> <strong>internationally competitive</strong></mark>, and economically and socially inclusive and cohesive</u>. <u><strong><mark>Countries</u></strong> </mark>can <u><strong><mark>achieve</u></strong> <u></mark>the skills objective, not by working alone, but by cooperation and</u> <u><strong><mark>integration</u></strong> <u><strong>within the ASEAN</u></strong> <u><strong>Framework</u></strong> <u></mark>and the ASEAN Plus Frameworks. Skills mobility cum development is a positive sum game for both receiving and sending countries in</u> the ASEAN integration project. It results in <u><strong><mark>an expanded pool</u></strong> <u><strong>of human resources</u></strong> <u></mark>with multi-national and deeper skill sets</u> <u><strong><mark>for every ASEAN country</u></strong></mark>. II. Why Skills Mobility and Skills Development are Important Current demographic, economic, and technological trends mean that the economies of ASEAN Member States (AMS) by 2040 will reach highand upper middle-income status, and have a growing labour force that is increasingly skilled (with declining working-age population in ageing societies offset by the youthful populations in other ASEAN countries). They will have achieved technological advances, particularly the digital revolution, e-commerce and industry 4.0, and demand an increasingly skilled labour force, including skills that are currently scarce across ASEAN (or even non-existent). 1. <u><strong><mark>Skills mobility</u></strong> </mark>is <u><strong><mark>essential</u></strong> <u><strong>to</u></strong> </mark>the <u><strong><mark>ASEAN region’s</u></strong> </mark>continuing <u><strong><mark>rapid economic growth</u></strong> <u></mark>and industrial upgrading. It will require tapping skills and talent from everywhere in the ASEAN region and beyond</u>. <u><strong><mark>Fostering</strong> </mark>a freer <strong><mark>intra-regional flow</strong> </mark>of skills <strong><mark>will provide</strong> </mark>a <strong><mark>competitive edge</strong></mark> to the ASEAN region</u>. 2. <u>A freer movement of skilled workers is also necessary for deepening ASEAN services integration. As the region becomes richer, its consumers will demand a variety of cross-border services</u>. Each AMS has unique services that can be demanded elsewhere in ASEAN. For example, ASEAN consumers may want to eat in restaurants run by Thai chefs, and access online education provided by Malaysian education sites and fintech services by Singapore financial institutions. With skills mobility, supplying these services becomes realisable and costeffective. 3. <u>Skills mobility is also <strong><mark>crucial for achieving</strong> </mark>the ASEAN objective of <strong><mark>inclusiveness</strong> <strong>and having a cohesive ASEAN community. </strong></mark>Abilities and talents can be found throughout the ASEAN region. At the same time, <strong><mark>opportunities to utilise</strong> </mark>these <strong><mark>skills</strong> <strong>to</strong> </mark>their <strong><mark>maximum potential are unevenly distributed</strong> </mark>across countries and geographic locations due to differences in level and rate of development and in economic structure. Skills mobility can make ASEAN a region where a person’s place of birth does not constrain his/her economic opportunities</u>. 4. Skills mobility is closely associated with production of skills for the regional, global, and future labour market. It is well known that employees of multinational corporations (MNCs), with work experience and socio-cultural-linguistic and management skills sets honed by international and regional postings are widely sought after by corporations (both big and small) seeking to venture or expand into new regional and international markets. A growing ASEAN labour force needs to be better educated and trained for the ongoing technological revolution and globalisation. <u>No single ASEAN economy can efficiently rely on domestic production of all the required skills.</u> As in the case of goods production, in the production of human capital there also exist comparative advantages and scale economies. There are large benefits to be gained by cooperating in the production of human capital and expanding the talent pool beyond national borders. 5. Looking towards 2040, ASEAN must consider the implications of the digital age for labour employment and mobility. E-commerce and other e-services can be provided across borders without physical movement of providers, resulting in ‘virtual migration’. This would include telemedicine, business process outsourcing and call centres, online education and fintech services. These service providers can work in their home base without migrating. The increasing demand for virtual migrants would help to offset some of the concerns of receiving and sending countries and migrant workers themselves regarding physical labour mobility. However, ASEAN would need a framework governing the virtual employment of foreign workers. III. Skills Mobility in ASEAN – Existing Measures and Challenges The importance of skills mobility is articulated in numerous ASEAN agreements and vision documents. The ASEAN Framework Agreement on Services (AFAS) and the ASEAN Economic Community (AEC) Blueprint indicate that labour mobility is considered an important part of the ASEAN integration project. In the Declaration of ASEAN Concord II in 2003, AMS are committed to ‘facilitate movement of business persons, skilled labour, and talents’ for deeper economic integration. The AEC Blueprint in 2007 reflected this commitment by specifying key areas of collaboration amongst AMS, including the facilitation of working visas and the harmonisation and standardisation of qualifications, including Mutual Recognition Arrangements for professionals (MRAs). The ASEAN Agreement on the Movement of Natural Persons (AMNP) was signed in 2012 to enhance the flow of natural persons engaging in trade in goods, services, and investment. In 2014, ASEAN Economic Ministers endorsed the ASEAN Qualification Reference Framework (AQRF) to complement the MRAs by providing guidelines for comparing qualifications across member states, with voluntary referencing. The AEC Blueprint 2025 reaffirms that facilitating the movement of skilled labour and business visitors is a key element of a ‘highly integrated and cohesive ASEAN economy’ (AEC Blueprint, 2025). <u><strong><mark>Current practices in ASEAN</strong> <strong>contain obstacles on</strong> </mark>the hiring of <strong><mark>foreign</strong> </mark>skilled <strong><mark>professionals</strong> </mark>by the private sector and their ban in the public sector (with the notable exception of Singapore) These include both formal and informal restrictions, including <strong><mark>constitutional and legal restrictions</strong> </mark>and labour market tests, <strong><mark>onerous</strong> </mark>and <strong><mark>time-consuming procedures</strong> <strong>and various upfront payments</u></strong></mark>. It would be helpful for employers and foreign workers if these restrictions are liberalised and made transparent and the procedures simplified. While the AEC Blueprint focuses on enhancing the flow of skilled and professionals, they account for less than 10% of intra-regional labour flows, with Singapore the leading destination. The majority of intraregional migrants are middle- and low-skilled and irregular, and are commonly found in construction, agriculture, and domestic work. There is no AEC coverage on them. ASEAN’s major receiving countries are Malaysia, Thailand, and Singapore. Malaysia and Thailand host millions of irregular workers from neighbouring ASEAN countries. The ASEAN Declaration on the Protection and Promotion of the Rights of Migrant Workers, known as the Cebu declaration, makes commitments to protect migrant workers, but this is non-binding. ASEAN has reaffirmed this by signing the ASEAN Consensus on the Protection and Promotion of the Rights of Migrant Workers, but the commitments remain voluntary (ASEAN Secretariat 2017). An assessment of the progress made by ASEAN in regional skilled labour mobility (Testaverde et al., 2017) concluded that, notwithstanding the commitments and framework agreements that regional leaders place on this issue, the slowness of actual implementation highlights the difficult political and regulatory landscape. The ASEAN agreements cover skilled workers and professionals, but there are several gaps in its provisions. They facilitate the issuance of visas and employment passes, and work to harmonise and standardise qualifications. However, most foreign skilled professionals are intra-corporate transferees, AFAS and AMNP do not cover individual professionals and skilled workers, and MRAs cover only a small segment of ASEAN professionals. AMS have signed MRAs in six areas: engineering, nursing, architecture, medicine, dentistry, and tourism and framework agreements in surveying and accountancy. Conclusion and implementation of MRAs for professionals have been a long and arduous process, in part due to ‘occupational protectionism’. There are genuine cross-country differences in what a professional must know to practice, and automatic recognition of foreign qualifications and work experience is rare. Partial recognition is usually possible with compensatory measures to bridge differences in training and quality standards and work experience, but this can be difficult and highly sensitive. The implementation of MRAs is timeconsuming, technically demanding, and sometimes politically difficult as a wide range of stakeholders are responsible for different aspects of the recognition process. It requires support from the public and professional associations, which in turn rests on perceptions of benefits and threats pose by foreign professionals. More importantly, MRAs do not guarantee labour market access, which is still subject to national laws, regulations, and measures. The challenges to ASEAN skills mobility have been categorised by Papademetriou et al. (2015) as follows: (i) Issues related to the recognition of credentials. (ii) Restrictions on hiring foreign workers in certain occupations and industries, and on employment visas. (iii) Perceived costly barriers due to cultural, language, and socioeconomic differences. It is necessary to overcome each of these challenges to achieve full skills mobility. The second challenge and part of the first challenge can be achieved by reforming the laws and regulations and following through on commitments such as expanding MRAs on skills. However, a continuing challenge will require a positive change in perceptions and behaviours of individuals and businesses surrounding labour mobility within ASEAN, which would in turn influence people’s economic decisions to move. Without a serious effort to enhance ASEAN skills mobility, the region may lose its talent to other parts of the world. ASEAN’s major sending countries are Indonesia, Myanmar, the Philippines, and Viet Nam, with major destinations in the Middle East, Europe, North America, and Australia–New Zealand rather than in ASEAN. It is important to note the reasons behind the extra-ASEAN preference and strategise to make ASEAN an attractive destination region of choice for skilled migrants. Rising job opportunities and wage levels, an increasingly open society that accepts foreigners, and an increasingly better living environment can make the ASEAN region an increasingly attractive destination. IV. Benefits and Costs to Sending and Receiving Countries and Migrant Workers Since labour market liberalisation is a politically sensitive issue, it is necessary to evaluate the benefits and costs to ASEAN countries and workers. A. For Receiving Countries and Citizen Workers Affected Benefits include (i) relaxing domestic shortages of general and specific skills; (ii) upgrading and developing specific sectors of the economy (e.g., educational, medical, and information technology services); (iii) attracting foreign direct investment (FDI) and foreign MNCs by relaxing rules on intra-corporate transferees and business visitors; (iv) relaxing skill shortages faced particularly by small and medium-sized enterprises (SMEs) as compared to large and foreign enterprises; (iv) encouraging the development of private enterprise and entrepreneurship. Concerns include (i) at the national level, countries and communities may be concerned about overcrowding and upward price pressures from increased demand for public spaces, housing, education, health and recreational facilities, and the displacement of local SMEs and professionals by FDI and foreign professionals; (ii) at the individual level, citizen workers may be concerned about job displacement and retrenchment, competitive pressure from foreign workers and dimmer prospects of job promotion. (iii) communities and individuals often cannot make the distinction between job displacement due to technological change and due to the entry of foreign firms and foreign workers. Receiving countries could provide educational and training opportunities for foreign students to work after graduation; minimise discrimination against the foreign workforce in various areas of public policy; ensure the fair treatment of workers by employers; and provide better labour market information on areas with skills shortages. Ultimately, ASEAN should aspire to be a region characterised by the circulation of skills, with each country both receiving and sending skilled professionals in line with its economic structure. B. For Sending Countries and Workers Seeking Foreign Employment Benefits include (i) reduced socio-political pressures from a large pool of educated unemployed and underemployed persons; (ii) inward remittances contribute to improved household incomes, and the balance of payments; (iii) mobility of labour (as well as tourism) improves knowledge, understanding, and appreciation of ASEAN neighbours and is an excellent way of building an ASEAN Community. Concerns include: (i) brain drain, although this can be offset by eventual returnees (and their skills, experience, and financial assets) and growing role of virtual migration; (ii) concern over lack of protection of their rights and welfare of nationals working abroad; (iii) for individuals, migration for work is largely an economic decision made by balancing the costs and benefits of seeking work abroad. Benefits include opportunities for a better income and career advancement, to travel and gain work experience in a different environment, and in some cases the opportunity to migrate permanently. Costs include financial, social, and psychological costs such as adapting to a foreign environment, family disruptions, and the difficulty of re-integrating upon return. Sending countries could improve educational standards, curricula, and the linguistic skills of potential migrant workers; seek recognition and accreditation of their degrees and diplomas; improve knowledge and understanding of the cultures and social norms of other ASEAN countries; improve the provision of information about the labour market in destination countries; facilitate exit procedures and minimise exit costs of obtaining passport, visas, transportation, and accreditation; and troubleshoot problems and attend to the needs of its nationals abroad through its embassies and labour attaches V. Lessons from the North American Free Trade Agreement and the European Union NAFTA and the EU have very different models of managing labour mobility and its interplay with trade liberalisation, corresponding to each bloc’s economic and policy objectives. Their provisions offer useful lessons for the ASEAN labour mobility objective. A. NAFTA now defunct and replaced by the US, Canada, Mexico Agreement (USCMA) NAFTA focused on trade integration, with relatively narrow provisions for skilled labour mobility. The NAFTA Treaty established a new migration category in the US available exclusively to workers from Mexico and Canada pursuing jobs in 70 highly skilled occupations (e.g. accountants, architects, computer systems analysts, economists, engineers, hotel managers, etc.). The lack of a quota and an easier application process made the NAFTA Treaty visa more attractive than the US global H1-1B visa. However, NAFTA did not include specific provisions to facilitate the movement of low-skilled labour. The US and Canada offered limited avenues for the legal temporary employment of foreign low-skilled workers. Applicants from Canada and Mexico with college degrees and job offers in the US were eligible to apply and there was no numerical quota. Employment was for 3 years, and the visa was renewable indefinitely. Migrants could bring their dependents. Canadian applicants could apply on entry to the US with only proof of a job offer and proof of education; there was no requirement for a labour market test in which employers certify that US workers were unavailable to fill positions. On the other hand, Mexican applicants must apply for the visa in Mexico and the employer must go undergo a labour market test. B. The EU <u>The <strong><mark>EU</strong> </mark>has broader <strong><mark>integration</strong> </mark>objectives and <strong><mark>guarantees</strong> </mark>the four fundamental <strong><mark>freedoms</strong> <strong>on movemen</strong></mark>t <strong><mark>of</strong> </mark>goods, services, capital, and <strong><mark>workers</strong></mark>. Citizens of any EU country and their families have the right to live in any other EU country for up to 3 months; after which they must be working, enrolled in full-time education, or able to demonstrate financial independence</u>. After 5 years of residence, they earn the right to permanent residence. Citizens of any EU country are also generally <u><strong><mark>permitted to work freely in </strong></mark>the job and</u> <u><strong><mark>country of their choosing</u></strong></mark>. <u>The EU has also implemented various policies to facilitate the movement of workers of any skill level</u>. <u>These include <strong><mark>mutual recognition of common forms of documentation</u></strong></mark> <u>and relative streamlining of entry processes</u>; and the portability across the EU of various social rights and entitlements, including access to health care, social welfare, and pensions. In actuality, migration flows have generally been rather subdued despite the accession of Central and Eastern Europe countries, possibly due to various other barriers. Also, EU member countries may restrict access to their labour markets for public sector jobs and ‘in an emergency’ with approval from the European Commission; and may impose temporary mobility restrictions on citizens of new EU members. Besides direct policy, many supportive programmes facilitate movement within the EU. The Erasmus Programme began in 1987 as a student exchange programme for Europeans, while the parallel Erasmus Mundus Programme is oriented towards non-Europeans. Erasmus Plus (2014–2020), which succeeded Erasmus, incorporates all EU schemes for education, training youth, and sport. It provides grants to give students and teachers or trainers a unique opportunity to participate in different European countries. Previously, these opportunities were restricted to applicants who had completed at least 1 year of study at the tertiary level, but are now also available to secondary school students. Participants study at least 3 months or do an internship for a period of at least 2 months and up to 1 academic year in another European country. The period spent abroad is recognised by their university when they return. Students do not pay extra tuition fees to the host institution and can apply for an Erasmus grant through the home institution to help cover the additional expenses of living abroad. Millions of European students in thousands of higher education institutions participate in Erasmus across 37 European countries. The main benefit of the programme is that it fosters learning and understanding of the host country, as both a time for learning and a chance to socialise and bond with other European students. Similarly, the Bologna Process is based on an intergovernmental agreement with membership extended beyond the EU. The 1999 Bologna Declaration committed 29 European governments to pursue complementary higher education reforms and establish a European Higher Education Area of compatible national systems. Participation and cooperation are voluntary. Bilateral agreements between countries and institutions oblige signatories to recognise each other’s degrees, moving from strict convergence in time spent on qualifications towards a competency-based system. National reforms have made university qualifications more easily comparable across Europe. Country scorecards (reports, conferences, communiqués, and policy declarations) are closely monitored at the European-level and structured around a series of biennial ministerial meetings. The European Commission has played an active role in this process. The EU Credit Transfer and Accumulation System (ECTS), first piloted within the Erasmus networks, has become the European standard. The European Commission also provides financial incentives for higher education cooperation and reform projects in line with the Bologna objectives, as well as funding national Bologna Promoters, and informational activities. It also promoted joint degrees and the bachelor/master structure through its Erasmus Mundus programme and other pilot studies. Likewise, the European Qualifications Framework (EQF) aims to relate different national qualifications systems to a common European reference framework. Individuals and employers use the EQF to understand and compare more easily the qualification levels of different countries and education and training systems. This means that there is no need for individuals to repeat this learning when migrating. The core of the EQF comprises eight reference levels (1–8) describing what a learner knows, understands, and is able to do (‘learning outcomes’). Levels of national qualifications are placed at one of the central reference levels. This makes it much easier to compare national qualifications. ECTS credits are a standard means of comparing the ‘volume of learning based on the defined learning outcomes and their associated workload’ for higher education across the EU and collaborating European countries (European Commission, 2017: 10). ECTS credits are used to facilitate transfer and progression throughout the EU. VI. The Role of ASEAN in Regional Skills Mobility and Development 1. Emphasise the welfare gains from ASEAN skilled labour mobility The economic benefits of cross-border labour mobility are numerous. For destination countries, positive impacts include better employment opportunities and higher wages for workers; however, low-skilled workers could have negative impacts in rigid labour markets. For sending countries, out-migration boost wages for those remaining behind, migrant workers benefit from higher wages received, and their households benefit from remittances. Overall, there are economic benefits from improved economic growth and from remittances. The negative effects of ‘brain drain’ in sending countries are offset by ‘brain circulation’ and eventual returnees. The EU and NAFTA experiences indicate that intra-regional skills mobility remains limited even in the absence of legal and policy barriers. The same may hold true in the ASEAN region. Additionally, when skills migration takes place, a preference for non-ASEAN destinations may emerge, linked to permanent migration to North America, Western Europe, Australia, and New Zealand. <u>There is a need to emphasise the <strong><mark>benefits of working in another ASEAN country</strong></mark>, which include closeness to home and cultural similarities; diversity of work, linguistic, and cultural experiences, which can enhance soft skills; and the <strong><mark>facilitation</strong> <strong>of</strong> </mark>ASEAN-<strong><mark>community building</strong></mark>.</u> Familiarity with other ASEAN countries can be enhanced by intra-ASEAN student and staff exchanges and tourism. For employers, businesses, and professional groups, more exchanges and cooperation promote business activities and intra-ASEAN FDI and services, leading to the employment and re-deployment of staff who are ASEAN nationals. 2. Incentives to attract ASEAN foreign professionals and skills as well as safeguarding the interests of citizen workers The key advantages of ASEAN destinations include closeness to home and less pronounced sociocultural diversities relative to destinations in North America, Europe, Australia, and New Zealand. <u><strong><mark>It is necessary to minimise visa procedures and labour market access restrictions</u></strong> <u><strong>so</u></strong> </mark>that <u><strong><mark>ASEAN professionals can access better employment and</u></strong> <u></mark>income</u> <u><strong><mark>opportunities in the region.</u></strong> <u></mark>ASEAN migration should also entail less financial and time costs of labour mobility and family disruptions</u>. ASEAN can also provide a centralised database of job market information. To attract foreign skills and talents, policy and practice should provide a welcoming environment, including availability and competitive cost of housing, transport and education, competitive taxation rates, portable social security plans, ease of sending remittances overseas, and a safe and unpolluted living and working environment. For skills and talent seeking eventual migration and permanent settlement, availability of permanent residence schemes is an important attraction. Governments are elected by citizens, hence concerns over foreign competition should be addressed in parallel to the welcome mat for foreigners, and that the foreign presence should not undermine social cohesion. In all countries, employment of nationals has priority over employment of foreigners but such ‘protectionism’ should not lead to shortages of skilled personnel that ultimately prevent the country from achieving its economic growth and upgrading potential and fail to enhance the wellbeing of its citizenry. Policy and practice would have to ensure that citizen workers have developed technical, social and linguistic skill sets that enable them to compete effectively with foreigners within their country or abroad. Policy and practice would also have to ensure that citizen workers are not discriminated in the recruitment, employment and promotion processes of private sector employers. . Accelerate the ASEAN-wide accreditation system for universities and training institutions The process of comparing and recognising academic and training credentials within a country is complex enough but the issue becomes even more problematic and sensitive across the 10 diverse ASEAN countries. To hire a foreign skilled worker or professional from another ASEAN country, the prospective employer must assess the merits of the paper qualification and work experience. For top-end jobs, employers can resort to expensive head-hunting recruitment agencies. But for lower-level jobs, an ASEAN-wide accreditation of education and training institutions would be a tremendous help to employers in their assessment of suitable candidates for employment and promotion. 4. Providing an equal opportunity for developing relevant skillsets An individual born anywhere in ASEAN needs to be given equal opportunity to develop skill sets that are in demand in the region. At the national level, this means a comprehensive education and training system available to all. Financing and finding the teachers put tremendous strain on low-income countries and policymakers will need to prioritise and seek foreign assistance (in ASEAN, amongst ASEAN dialogue partners, international and regional institutions). It is essential that the education and training process results in the production of marketable skill-sets, embodying some quality-standard and relevance to the present economic structure of the country as well as its future evolution. While expanding the enrolment and scope of tertiary institutions, all ASEAN countries would need to improve the quality dimension of its institutions so that they can eventually compete with the best in the world. In this respect, the Singapore experience may offer some useful lessons for some ASEAN countries. Singapore’s school system has been producing students that achieve high Programme for International Student Assessment (PISA) test scores run by the Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development (OECD) and Singapore’s leading universities are ranked by various international ranking agencies as amongst the best in Asia. Also, Singapore’s education and training system is being revamped to prepare students for the technological requirements of future jobs. Singapore has achieved this level of educational excellence through continuous effort in developing Singapore’s human resources, learning from the best institutions and examples the world has to offer, entering into partnerships with worldrenowned institutions, and recruiting from the world’s best from the advanced industrial countries, China and India to teach and research in its universities, research institutes, and training centres. The Singapore education and training system is currently being revamped to meet the future job requirements brought on by technological changes. At the ASEAN regional level, this offers tremendous opportunity for cooperation and integration in a win-win framework. ASEAN countries that are more educationally advanced, with educational and training institutions of international standing and repute, could build physical campuses in other ASEAN countries and also offer online education (currently undertaken in the ASEAN region mainly by non-ASEAN universities and colleges). 5. Develop strong regional consciousness through travel and study experiences Migration and interest in migration often begin when individuals are studying abroad, and many ASEAN students who study overseas remain abroad for work experience and opportunities. There is more limited student movement amongst ASEAN countries, in part due to a dearth of scholarships and financial assistance schemes, and a lower profile of ASEAN tertiary educational institutions. Therefore, ASEAN should encourage student exchange through the ASEAN University Network (AUN), and Singapore’s ASEAN scholarships, amongst others. This can be achieved by improving the global rankings of ASEAN universities and training institutes. 6. Manage a gradual approach towards ASEAN labour mobility and integration Given the diversity of the AMS, ASEAN should adopt a more gradual approach towards an integrated ASEAN skilled labour market. Ideally, a regional framework based on binding bilateral agreements would be preferable, perhaps within a subset of AMS. Such an ‘ASEAN minus X’ approach would provide some flexibility. However, a voluntary regional approach may be appropriate to accommodate the diverse sensitivities in ASEAN. A more inclusive and equitable ASEAN and AEC could emphasise regional and bilateral cooperation instead of binding integration agreements. AMS have different priorities and face different socioeconomic realities. However, when political leaders and policymakers formulate and implement national visions, plans, and policies, they should also consider impacts on other ASEAN countries and, whenever and wherever possible, adopt positive-sum, not zero-sum, strategies. The ASEAN body need to take a leadership role in driving the discussion around mobility. However, countries at the top end of economic development (Malaysia, Singapore, and Thailand) could also play a more pro-active role in driving skills mobility and development. VII. Concluding Summary Due to demographic, economic, social, and technological changes in the ASEAN region and globally, ASEAN needs to move forward with skills mobility to build competitive and knowledge-driven economies. This will help maintain a united ASEAN and will contribute towards ASEAN centrality. A single ASEAN market for skills and talent will require free movement for various occupations and non-discriminatory treatment for foreign workers in national legislations and policies, employment practices, employment remuneration and benefits, and common quality assurance and qualifications recognition. A single ASEAN market for skills and talents by 2040 pre-supposes the establishment of a single market for goods and services in ASEAN. A single market for goods appears more likely than a single market for services as services delivery requires Mode 3 (right of establishment) and Mode 4 (temporary movement of natural persons). Mode 4 covers contractual service suppliers (self-employed independent service suppliers and employees of foreign service suppliers), intra-corporate transferees and persons directly recruited by the foreign affiliate, and service sellers or persons responsible for setting up a commercial presence. While intra-corporate transferees are well taken care of with the liberalisation of FDI, liberalising Mode 4 would take care of other service suppliers as well. Service-market integration will complement the skilled labour-market integration. The digital age makes possible virtual migration with an important impact on ASEAN skilled labour mobility. Many more services are being delivered online with short visits by service suppliers, and do not require the physical movement of service suppliers. This would remove some of the concerns over overcrowding or sociocultural disruptions by an influx of in-migrants (although the same is felt about large influxes of tourists) and concerns over brain drain caused by large outflows of the skilled. The economic importance of labour market integration cannot be overstated. Yet, it is necessary not to integrate hastily and acknowledge political and social concerns. First, a liberalised skills market, coupled with a strong push towards upskilling of the domestic labour force, can be an effective strategy for achieving rapid growth without leaving anyone behind. Second, given the vast differences amongst ASEAN countries in geographic and population sizes and in levels of economic development and wage incomes, free movement of all labour is politically unrealistic. Third, many ASEAN countries are still engaged in post-independence nation building and are struggling with managing plural societies and may not welcome more cultural, religious, and linguistic diversity. Some are looking outward beyond ASEAN. Some are internally divided and prioritise national cohesion over regional cohesion. There are also growing concerns related to security and terrorism prompting stricter immigration controls. A concerted effort is needed to instil<strong> a sense of common destiny amongst ASEAN countries. Moving forward, AMS could agree on an ASEAN-wide framework for governing the movement of skilled workers, with provisions for bilateral (preferably binding) agreements between AMS to operationalise the framework. Such bilateral agreements could be gradually expanded to cover ASEAN as a whole so that the region can achieve meaningful skills mobility.</p></strong> | null | null | 1AC—Advantage 1 | 1,714,689 | 126 | 164,540 | ./documents/hsld22/Jasper/RyCh/Jasper-RyCh-Aff-04---Flower-Mound-TFA-NIETOC-Scholarship-Swing-Semis.docx | 972,606 | A | 04 - Flower Mound TFA NIETOC Scholarship Swing | Semis | Byron Nelson PM | Brandon Molina, Blake Ochoa, Patrick Tapia | 1AC - ASEAN
1NC - T - Nebel, Cap K, Case
1AR - All
2NR - All
2AR - All
Molina, Ochoa, and Tapia* vote Neg | hsld22/Jasper/RyCh/Jasper-RyCh-Aff-04---Flower-Mound-TFA-NIETOC-Scholarship-Swing-Semis.docx | 2023-05-10 15:25:49 | 83,295 | RyCh | Jasper RyCh | Hey! I’m Ryan (He/him/his)
214-799-3619
[email protected]
Jasper 24' | Ry..... | Ch..... | null | null | 27,615 | Jasper | Jasper | TX | null | 2,003 | hsld22 | HS LD 2022-23 | 2,022 | ld | hs | 1 |
4,749,645 | A Chinese shift to consumption-led growth solves the worst impacts of climate change and moves the country to carbon neutrality. | Rhee et al. 22 | Rhee et al. 22, [Chang Yong Rhee is director of the Asia and Pacific Department, Helge Berger is the China mission chief and assistant director in the Asia and Pacific Department, Wenjie Chen is a senior economist in the Asia and Pacific Department], “China’s Shift to Consumption-Led Growth Can Aid Green Goals,” IMF News, (1-27-2022), https://www.imf.org/en/News/Articles/2022/01/27/cf-china-shift-to-consumption-led-growth-can-aid-green-goals //PrK | growth is losing momentum while remaining overly dependent on support from investment and exports. This imperils the transition to sustained high-quality growth that’s balanced, inclusive and green
rebalancing toward a more consumption-based model will boost growth prospects in the short term and deliver high-quality expansion in the long run. Importantly, it will also help bring the country closer to achieving its climate goal of carbon neutrality before 2060
More immediate economic headwinds include slowing real estate investment and rapid withdrawal of fiscal support. What’s more, new outbreaks of more transmissible virus variants are prompting more lockdowns, weighing on the crucial recovery of private consumption.
stagnant domestic productivity growth, which has leveled off in the past 10 years just as China’s workforce stopped expanding.
The country will benefit in the long run from a strategy that strengthens consumption in a more lasting way a shift to a more consumption-based growth model will also get China closer to its climate goals
At the same time, re-energizing economic reforms stalled by the pandemic would boost productivity and reverse faltering market dynamism by empowering private enterprises. This means letting private firms compete more with state-owned companies and continuing to open domestic markets.
supporting the domestic economy while also improving prospects for the world avoiding the worst effects of climate change.
Further investment-driven growth would accelerate due to the high carbon-intensity of investment, including from construction—make it much harder for China to meet its climate goals
successfully rebalancing toward consumption will aid China’s climate aims by shifting away from carbon-intensive industrial sectors
rebalancing towards more consumption-led growth will decrease the energy intensity of China’s GDP and thus, lessen the country’s energy demand rebalancing alone can help cut carbon emissions by about 15 percent over the next three decades climate policies combined with greener investment—which is more productive and growth-friendly than traditional spending—will help steer demand away from emissions-intensive uses and support greener development. | investment and exports imperil transition to growth that’s green
rebalancing will boost prospects closer to achieving carbon neutrality
domestic growth has leveled off
consumption-based growth will
avoid the worst effects of climate change
investment accelerate carbon-intensity including construction
rebalancing shift away from industrial sectors
decrease energy intensity of China’s GDP and lessen energy demand cut carbon emissions 15 percent | China rebounded strongly from the pandemic, but growth is losing momentum while remaining overly dependent on support from investment and exports. This imperils the nation’s long-sought transition to sustained high-quality growth that’s balanced, inclusive and green.
While China’s many challenges have no easy answer, the key message of the IMF’s annual Article IV review of the economy is that rebalancing toward a more consumption-based model will boost growth prospects in the short term and deliver high-quality expansion in the long run. Importantly, it will also help bring the country closer to achieving its climate goal of carbon neutrality before 2060.
More immediate economic headwinds include slowing real estate investment and rapid withdrawal of fiscal support. What’s more, new outbreaks of more transmissible virus variants are prompting more lockdowns, weighing on the crucial recovery of private consumption.
While exports have boosted growth during the pandemic, these global tailwinds are poised to unwind eventually, leaving the world’s second-largest economy to contend with serious challenges. One of these is stagnant domestic productivity growth, which has leveled off in the past 10 years just as China’s workforce stopped expanding.
Economic challenges
Obstacles also include waning benefits from traditional infrastructure spending and technological decoupling, the reduced flow of international trade in high-tech goods and services. Importantly, a slowdown in trade and cross-border investment is bound to be quite costly economically and can affect global growth, recent IMF staff research shows.
And China’s quest for carbon neutrality is another challenge to tackle.
So, what are policymakers to do? The country will benefit in the long run from a strategy that strengthens consumption in a more lasting way while also supporting greater productivity. And a shift to a more consumption-based growth model will also get China closer to its climate goals.
In the near term, fiscal policy should be more neutral and steer spending away from infrastructure and toward income support to vulnerable people to boost lagging private consumption. And an improved social protection system would offer people more security, reduce precautionary savings, and better promote consumption in the future.
Fostering competition
At the same time, re-energizing economic reforms stalled by the pandemic would boost productivity and reverse faltering market dynamism by empowering private enterprises. This means letting private firms compete more with state-owned companies and continuing to open domestic markets.
Rebalancing China’s growth promises a double benefit, supporting the domestic economy while also improving prospects for the world avoiding the worst effects of climate change.
Further investment-driven growth would not only accelerate the decline in investment returns but also, —due to the high carbon-intensity of investment, including from construction—make it much harder for China to meet its climate goals.
Conversely, successfully rebalancing toward consumption will aid China’s climate aims by shifting activity to relatively untapped services industries and away from carbon-intensive industrial sectors.
Of course, there will be tradeoffs between achieving climate goals and growth. While those cannot be fully eliminated, rebalancing towards more consumption-led growth will decrease the energy intensity of China’s GDP and thus, lessen the country’s energy demand and ease the pressure for energy security. In fact, rebalancing alone can help cut carbon emissions by about 15 percent over the next three decades, as IMF staff simulations show. At the same time, climate policies combined with greener investment—which is more productive and growth-friendly than traditional spending—will help steer demand away from emissions-intensive uses and support greener development.
Together, policies centered around economic rebalancing would ensure that sustained high-quality growth is achievable and more durable. This would not only benefit China, but also the world. | 4,107 | <h4><strong>A Chinese shift to consumption-led growth solves the worst impacts of climate change and moves the country to carbon neutrality.</h4><p>Rhee et al. 22</strong>, [Chang Yong Rhee is director of the Asia and Pacific Department, Helge Berger is the China mission chief and assistant director in the Asia and Pacific Department, Wenjie Chen is a senior economist in the Asia and Pacific Department], “<u>China’s <mark>Shift to Consumption-Led Growth Can Aid Green Goals</u></mark>,” IMF News, (1-27-2022), https://www.imf.org/en/News/Articles/2022/01/27/cf-china-shift-to-consumption-led-growth-can-aid-green-goals //PrK</p><p>China rebounded strongly from the pandemic, but <u>growth is losing momentum while remaining overly dependent on support from <mark>investment and exports</mark>. This <mark>imperil</mark>s the</u> nation’s long-sought <u><mark>transition to</mark> sustained high-quality <mark>growth that’s</mark> balanced, inclusive and <mark>green</u></mark>.</p><p>While China’s many challenges have no easy answer, the key message of the IMF’s annual Article IV review of the economy is that <u><mark>rebalancing</mark> toward a more consumption-based model <mark>will boost</mark> growth <mark>prospects</mark> in the short term and deliver high-quality expansion in the long run. Importantly, it will also help bring the country <mark>closer to achieving</mark> its climate goal of <mark>carbon neutrality </mark>before 2060</u>.</p><p><u>More immediate economic headwinds include slowing real estate investment and rapid withdrawal of fiscal support. What’s more, new outbreaks of more transmissible virus variants are prompting more lockdowns, weighing on the crucial recovery of private consumption.</p><p></u>While exports have boosted growth during the pandemic, these global tailwinds are poised to unwind eventually, leaving the world’s second-largest economy to contend with serious challenges. One of these is <u>stagnant <mark>domestic</mark> productivity <mark>growth</mark>, which <mark>has leveled off</mark> in the past 10 years just as China’s workforce stopped expanding.</p><p></u>Economic challenges</p><p>Obstacles also include waning benefits from traditional infrastructure spending and technological decoupling, the reduced flow of international trade in high-tech goods and services. Importantly, a slowdown in trade and cross-border investment is bound to be quite costly economically and can affect global growth, recent IMF staff research shows.</p><p>And China’s quest for carbon neutrality is another challenge to tackle.</p><p>So, what are policymakers to do? <u>The country will benefit in the long run from a strategy that strengthens consumption in a more lasting way</u> while also supporting greater productivity. And <u>a shift to a more <mark>consumption-based growth</mark> model <mark>will</mark> also get China closer to its climate goals</u>.</p><p>In the near term, fiscal policy should be more neutral and steer spending away from infrastructure and toward income support to vulnerable people to boost lagging private consumption. And an improved social protection system would offer people more security, reduce precautionary savings, and better promote consumption in the future.</p><p>Fostering competition</p><p><u>At the same time, re-energizing economic reforms stalled by the pandemic would boost productivity and reverse faltering market dynamism by empowering private enterprises. This means letting private firms compete more with state-owned companies and continuing to open domestic markets.</p><p></u>Rebalancing China’s growth promises a double benefit, <u>supporting the domestic economy while also improving prospects for the world <mark>avoid</mark>ing <mark>the worst effects of climate change</mark>.</p><p>Further <mark>investment</mark>-driven growth would</u> not only <u><mark>accelerate</u></mark> the decline in investment returns but also, —<u>due to the high <mark>carbon-intensity</mark> of investment, <mark>including </mark>from <mark>construction</mark>—make it much harder for China to meet its climate goals</u>.</p><p>Conversely, <u>successfully <mark>rebalancing</mark> toward consumption will aid China’s climate aims by <mark>shift</mark>ing</u> activity to relatively untapped services industries and <u><mark>away from</mark> carbon-intensive <mark>industrial sectors</u></mark>.</p><p>Of course, there will be tradeoffs between achieving climate goals and growth. While those cannot be fully eliminated, <u>rebalancing towards more consumption-led growth will <mark>decrease</mark> the <mark>energy intensity of China’s GDP and</mark> thus, <mark>lessen</mark> the country’s <mark>energy demand</u></mark> and ease the pressure for energy security. In fact, <u>rebalancing alone can help <mark>cut carbon emissions</mark> by about <mark>15 percent</mark> over the next three decades</u>, as IMF staff simulations show. At the same time, <u>climate policies combined with greener investment—which is more productive and growth-friendly than traditional spending—will help steer demand away from emissions-intensive uses and support greener development.</p><p></u><strong>Together, policies centered around economic rebalancing would ensure that sustained high-quality growth is achievable and more durable. This would not only benefit China, but also the world.</p></strong> | 1AC | Advantage -- Economy | Scenario 2 is Warming | 1,702,412 | 116 | 166,422 | ./documents/hsld22/MontaVista/AaAg/MontaVista-AaAg-Aff-TOC-Digital-Speech-and-Debate-Series-2-Round-1.docx | 983,064 | A | TOC Digital Speech and Debate Series 2 | 1 | Sehome AM | Haritha Kumar | 1AC - Hukou
1NC - Terror DA, Populism DA, Case
1AR - All
2NR - All
2AR - All | hsld22/MontaVista/AaAg/MontaVista-AaAg-Aff-TOC-Digital-Speech-and-Debate-Series-2-Round-1.docx | 2023-02-25 00:29:07 | 80,362 | AaAg | Monta Vista AaAg | Hi! I'm Aarnav. My pronouns are he/him. Here is my contact information:
Email: [email protected]
Phone number: 650-518-8763
For disclosure, please use my email. If I don't respond (because tech issues happen, especially at in-person tournaments), definitely send me a message.
If it's anything out of round, any method of contact is fine. | Aa..... | Ag..... | null | null | 26,996 | MontaVista | Monta Vista | CA | null | 2,003 | hsld22 | HS LD 2022-23 | 2,022 | ld | hs | 1 |
3,525,694 | Establishing a policy requires enacting new laws | Schultz 5 | David Schultz 5, professor in the Hamline University Department of Political Science, 2005, Encyclopedia of the Supreme Court, p. 8-9 | The Constitution established three branches legislative, judicial, and executive Government agencies were necessary from the birth of the nation to carry out functions of the government and conduct the day-to-day business and duties of government Congress have the power to establish policy, but do they have the time to enforce each of those laws and policies? No. the other two branches were established to deal with broad and major issues facing the nation, not the minutiae of day-today government function there was a need for administrative agencies | The Constitution established three branches agencies were necessary to carry out functions of government Congress have the power to establish policy the other branches were established to deal with broad issues not minutiae of government | The Constitution established three branches of government, the legislative, judicial, and executive. It does refer to other elements of government but does not specifically define what those elements should be. Government agencies, however, were necessary from the birth of the nation to carry out functions of the government and conduct the day-to-day business and duties of government. Congress may have the power to make law and establish policy, but do they have the time to enforce each of those laws and policies? No. And the other two branches of government are similarly situated. They were established to deal with broad and major issues facing the nation, not the minutiae of day-today government function. And because there was a need for administrative agencies there also became a need for administrative law to regulate those agencies. | 849 | <h4>Establishing a policy requires enacting new laws</h4><p>David <strong>Schultz 5</strong>, professor in the Hamline University Department of Political Science, 2005, Encyclopedia of the Supreme Court, p. 8-9</p><p><u><mark>The Constitution established three branches</u></mark> of government, the <u>legislative, judicial, and executive</u>. It does refer to other elements of government but does not specifically define what those elements should be. <u>Government <mark>agencies</u></mark>, however, <u><mark>were necessary</mark> from the birth of the nation <mark>to carry out functions of</mark> the <mark>government</mark> and conduct the day-to-day business and duties of government</u>. <u><strong><mark>Congress</u></strong></mark> may <u><mark>have the power to</u></mark> make law and <u><strong><mark>establish policy</strong></mark>, but do they have the time to enforce each of those laws and policies? No.</u> And <u><mark>the other</mark> two <mark>branches</u></mark> of government are similarly situated. They <u><mark>were established to deal with broad</mark> and major <mark>issues</mark> facing the nation, <mark>not</mark> the <mark>minutiae of</mark> day-today <mark>government</mark> function</u>. And because <u>there was a need for <strong>administrative agencies</u></strong> there also became a need for administrative law to regulate those agencies.</p> | null | null | 1NC | 403,501 | 107 | 116,845 | ./documents/ndtceda17/Northwestern/JaWe/Northwestern-Jankovsky-Weideman-Neg-GSU-Round2.docx | 599,680 | N | GSU | 2 | Wayne State HR | Sean Ridley | 1AC Queernes
1NC T K Case
Block2NR TCase | ndtceda17/Northwestern/JaWe/Northwestern-Jankovsky-Weideman-Neg-GSU-Round2.docx | null | 51,029 | JaWe | Northwestern JaWe | null | Ga..... | Ja..... | Jo..... | We..... | 19,135 | Northwestern | Northwestern | null | null | 1,007 | ndtceda17 | NDT/CEDA 2017-18 | 2,017 | cx | college | 2 |
3,665,590 | Even massive economic decline has zero chance of war | Jervis 11 | Jervis 11 (Robert Jervis, Professor in the Department of Political Science and School of International and Public Affairs at Columbia University, December 2011, “Force in Our Times,” Survival, Vol. 25, No. 4, p. 403-425) | a worsening of current economic difficulties, could produce greater nationalism, undermine democracy and bring back old-fashioned beggar-my-neighbor economic policies While these dangers are real it is hard to believe that the conflicts could be great enough to lead members of the community to contemplate fighting each other. It is not so much that economic interdependence could not be reversed Rather it is that even if the more extreme versions of free trade and economic liberalism become discredited it is hard to see how leaders and mass opinion would come to believe that their countries could prosper by impoverishing or attacking others While a pessimist could note that this argument does not appear as outlandish as it did before the financial crisis an optimist could reply (correctly that the very fact that we have seen such a sharp economic down-turn without anyone suggesting that force is the solution shows that even if bad times bring about greater economic conflict, it will not make war thinkable | it is hard to believe conflicts could be great enough to lead the community to fighting each other even if the more extreme versions of trade and liberalism become discredited, it is hard to see how leaders and mass opinion would believe their countries could prosper by attacking others we have seen a sharp economic down-turn without anyone suggesting force shows bad times will not make war thinkable | Even if war is still seen as evil, the security community could be dissolved if severe conflicts of interest were to arise. Could the more peaceful world generate new interests that would bring the members of the community into sharp disputes? 45 A zero-sum sense of status would be one example, perhaps linked to a steep rise in nationalism. More likely would be a worsening of the current economic difficulties, which could itself produce greater nationalism, undermine democracy and bring back old-fashioned beggar-my-neighbor economic policies. While these dangers are real, it is hard to believe that the conflicts could be great enough to lead the members of the community to contemplate fighting each other. It is not so much that economic interdependence has proceeded to the point where it could not be reversed – states that were more internally interdependent than anything seen internationally have fought bloody civil wars. Rather it is that even if the more extreme versions of free trade and economic liberalism become discredited, it is hard to see how without building on a preexisting high level of political conflict leaders and mass opinion would come to believe that their countries could prosper by impoverishing or even attacking others. Is it possible that problems will not only become severe, but that people will entertain the thought that they have to be solved by war? While a pessimist could note that this argument does not appear as outlandish as it did before the financial crisis, an optimist could reply (correctly, in my view) that the very fact that we have seen such a sharp economic down-turn without anyone suggesting that force of arms is the solution shows that even if bad times bring about greater economic conflict, it will not make war thinkable. | 1,792 | <h4>Even <u>massive</u> economic decline has <u>zero</u> chance of war </h4><p><strong>Jervis 11</strong> (Robert Jervis, Professor in the Department of Political Science and School of International and Public Affairs at Columbia University, December 2011, “Force in Our Times,” Survival, Vol. 25, No. 4, p. 403-425)</p><p>Even if war is still seen as evil, the security community could be dissolved if severe conflicts of interest were to arise. Could the more peaceful world generate new interests that would bring the members of the community into sharp disputes? 45 A zero-sum sense of status would be one example, perhaps linked to a steep rise in nationalism. More likely would be <u><strong>a worsening of</u></strong> the <u><strong>current economic difficulties,</u></strong> which <u><strong>could</u></strong> itself <u><strong>produce greater nationalism, undermine democracy and bring back old-fashioned beggar-my-neighbor economic policies</u></strong>. <u><strong>While these dangers are real</u></strong>, <u><strong><mark>it is hard to believe</mark> that the <mark>conflicts could be great enough</u></strong> <u><strong>to lead</u></strong></mark> the <u><strong>members of <mark>the community to</mark> contemplate <mark>fighting each other</mark>. It is not so much that economic interdependence</u></strong> has proceeded to the point where it <u><strong>could not be reversed</u></strong> – states that were more internally interdependent than anything seen internationally have fought bloody civil wars. <u><strong>Rather it is that</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>even if the more extreme versions of</mark> free <mark>trade and</mark> economic <mark>liberalism become discredited</u></strong>, <u><strong>it is</u></strong> <u><strong>hard to see how</u></strong></mark> without building on a preexisting high level of political conflict <u><strong><mark>leaders and mass opinion would</mark> come to <mark>believe</mark> that <mark>their countries could prosper by</mark> impoverishing or</u></strong> even <u><strong><mark>attacking others</u></strong></mark>. Is it possible that problems will not only become severe, but that people will entertain the thought that they have to be solved by war? <u><strong>While a pessimist could note that this argument does not appear as outlandish as it did before the financial crisis</u></strong>, <u><strong>an optimist could reply (correctly</u></strong>, in my view) <u><strong>that the very fact that <mark>we have seen</u></strong> <u><strong></mark>such <mark>a sharp economic down-turn</u></strong> <u><strong>without</u></strong> <u><strong>anyone</u></strong> <u><strong>suggesting</mark> that <mark>force</u></strong></mark> of arms <u><strong>is the solution</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>shows</mark> that</u></strong> <u><strong>even if <mark>bad times </mark>bring about greater economic conflict,</u></strong> <u><strong>it <mark>will not make war thinkable</u></strong></mark>.</p> | 1NR | Clean Tech | No econ decline | 3,773 | 705 | 122,475 | ./documents/ndtceda16/Georgia/MaHi/Georgia-Mahajan-Hines-Neg-Samford-Round1.docx | 588,646 | N | Samford | 1 | Vanderbilt KM | Dan Bagwell | 1AC - Carbon Tax (Warming Clean Tech Leadership)
1NC -
Nietzsche
SwitchgrassTrade CP
Shale Turn
Case Defense
2NC - K
1NR - Shale TurnCase Defense
2NR - K | ndtceda16/Georgia/MaHi/Georgia-Mahajan-Hines-Neg-Samford-Round1.docx | null | 50,262 | MaHi | Georgia MaHi | null | Sa..... | Ma..... | Th..... | Hi..... | 19,028 | Georgia | Georgia | null | null | 1,006 | ndtceda16 | NDT/CEDA 2016-17 | 2,016 | cx | college | 2 |
3,683,771 | The alternative is a structural socialist analysis to strategically organize emancipation through a mass socialist movement---only total buy-in can deconstruct the totalizing nature of capital---identitarian politics fractures movements and fails to spur social or institutional change | Dudzic and Reed 15 | Dudzic and Reed 15 – national organizer of the labor party; PhD, professor of political science at the University of Pennsylvania.
(Mark and Adolph, “THE CRISIS OF LABOUR AND THE LEFT IN THE UNITED STATES”, November 2015, Socialist Register) | Any serious discussion of the prospects for rebuilding a left must start from the understanding that the left in the US suffered a strategic defeat, and that capital has reorganized and emerged from the 2008 economic crisis even stronger This does not mean that those who embrace a transformative vision must abandon all hope. Rather, the priorities, activities and resources of those who would rebuild a real left must be informed by this strategic sensibility. Building or rebuilding an effective left presence will be quite likely a decades-long process. We must start by excising the impulse – quite understandable for a political movement devoid of any real agency – toward utopian dreaming and wishful thinking. The spark will not ignite the prairie fire. Nor will the Ark float on its own account no matter how carefully we construct it. Recognizing the left’s political irrelevance can be emancipating as it reduces the sense of urgency to try to mobilize around every one of neoliberalism’s daily outrages That should provide space for serious strategic discussion of how to begin to build a mass socialist movement based in the working class and the creation of new institutions capable of mobilizing cross-class solidarity the US left could benefit from a nonsectarian, organized force with a coherent strategic vision and programme The absence of a disciplined, unified and sophisticated group of cadre is a major source of the left’s incoherence, and helps explain why moments of spontaneous political upsurge have had an episodic impact and remain unconnected to similar moments in the past Such organization cannot be created in a vacuum It can only emerge in tandem with a growing working-class movement. failing reflects the cultural and ideological triumph of neoliberalism and the identitarian ideologies and programmes that serve as its left wing. building socialism is exclusively a project of cadre development Broad movement-building requires mobilizing around an agenda of substantively anti-capitalist reforms that directly and militantly assert the priority of social needs over market forces, bourgeois property rights and managerial prerogative in the workplace and production process Struggles to preserve and expand public institutions and to decommoditize basic human needs like housing, transportation, healthcare and education could begin to address the immediate challenge, which is to create a new popular constituency for a revitalized movement, instead of reorganizing or re-mobilizing an already existing but totally marginalized left This approach correctly identifies the urgent need to preserve the remnants of the current labour movement as an institutional base upon which to build a future revitalized movement. it also correctly points out the haplessness of willy-nilly organizing schemes that do little to build power for working people while exposing their best leaders in unorganized workplaces to massive employer retaliation without any ability to defend them a strategy of waiting for workers to say they have had enough ultimately relies on magical thinking the ‘fortress’ strategy will do little to reduce inequality Instead, they place their hopes in ‘strategic alliances with willing employers’; in unions developing value-added services to complement human resource departments; and in leveraging union and public-sector pension funds to rebuild union density any revitalization movement would need to be built from a base that is far broader than the current institutional labour movement A revitalized labour movement will have to embrace new organizational forms and some of the models emerging from new labour organizing show significant potential Much of it seems also, more or less openly, to fold class analysis into identitarian discourses that both substitute moralizing for political critique and fit comfortably within the NGO model some associated with this category have begun to evolve into substantial, self-conscious worker-run organizations Some argue that these campaigns and projects have the capacity to coalesce into geographically based class-conscious organizations and have called for the building of worker assemblies to give voice to this new movement Attempts to establish these structures on the ground have been premature and could actually inhibit the kind of broad, class-based organizing that inspires this movement in much the same way that many Labor Party chapters became captured by an ‘activistist’ mentality that focused more on preaching to the converted than building a constituency, while driving away real working-class voices who represented something more than themselves. New models are most successful when they can leverage existing organization and power to build outwards into new organization Recent experiences organizing healthcare and homecare workers, hotel and casino workers and building services employees are fruitful examples of smart and strategic organizing that have leveraged existing union relationships and political opportunities to build power for working people organizing campaigns focus on the chokepoints of global capitalism and build on existing union power on the docks and other shipping centres as having the potential to develop a particularly powerful form of a strategic union presence in economic sectors at the very core of contemporary capitalism. | priorities and resources must be informed by strategic sensibility We must excis the impulse for a political movement devoid of real agency The spark will not ignite the prairie fire Recognizing the left’s political irrelevance can be emancipating to provide space for to build a mass socialist movement and creation of new institutions mobilizing cross-class solidarity absence of a disciplined, unified cadre is a source of the left’s incoherence and explain why spontaneous upsurge have had episodic impact failing reflects triumph of neoliberalism and identitarian ideologies Broad movement-building requires mobilizing around substantively anti-capitalist reforms that militantly assert the priority of social needs Struggles to preserve and expand public institutions like housing transportation healthcare and education could create a popular constituency for a revitalized movement willy-nilly organizing schemes do little to build power for working people while relies on magical thinking the ‘fortress’ strategy will do little to reduce inequality it seems to fold class analysis into identitarian discourses that substitute moralizing for political critique campaigns have the capacity to coalesce into class-conscious organizations Attempts to establish these structures could inhibit class-based organizing that captured by an ‘activistist’ mentality that focused more on preaching than building a constituency, while driving away real working-class voices models are most successful when they can leverage existing organization to build outwards strategic organizing that have leveraged political opportunities to build power for working people focus on the chokepoints of global capitalism and develop powerful presence at the core of contemporary capitalism.35 | Any serious discussion of the prospects for rebuilding a left must start from the understanding that the left in the US, as in the rest of the capitalist world, suffered a strategic defeat, and that capital has reorganized and emerged from the 2008 economic crisis even stronger.24 While the extreme financialization of capital is likely to increase the frequency and intensity of episodic crises, this crisis once again confirms that there is no necessary correlation between crisis and revitalization of the left. In fact, notwithstanding glimmers of hope like SYRIZA in Greece and strong showings by anti-austerity parties in the spring 2014 European elections, the history of the post-2008 crisis politics in Europe would indicate that the more intense the crisis, the more deeply reactionary the response. This does not mean that those who embrace a transformative vision must abandon all hope. Rather, the priorities, activities and resources of those who would rebuild a real left must be informed by this strategic sensibility. Building or rebuilding an effective left presence will be quite likely a decades-long process. This means that we are not well served by clambering after the Next Big Thing. We must start by excising the impulse – quite understandable for a political movement devoid of any real agency – toward utopian dreaming and wishful thinking. The spark will not ignite the prairie fire. Nor will the Ark float on its own account no matter how carefully we construct it. Recognizing the left’s political irrelevance can be emancipating, as it reduces the sense of urgency to try to mobilize around every one of neoliberalism’s daily outrages. That should provide space for serious strategic discussion of how to begin to build a mass socialist movement based in the working class and the creation of new institutions capable of mobilizing cross-class solidarity, as Sam Gindin has articulated in a particularly clear and compelling way.25 Certainly, the US left could benefit from a nonsectarian, organized force with a coherent strategic vision and programme. The absence of a disciplined, unified and sophisticated group of cadre is a major source of the left’s incoherence, and helps explain why moments of spontaneous political upsurge have had, at best, an episodic impact and remain unconnected to similar moments in the past – even those in which the same activists have participated. Such organization, however, cannot be created in a vacuum. It can only emerge in tandem with a growing working-class movement. We fear that in the specific context of US history and practice, the socialist project is too narrow a platform from which to launch a broad and far ranging left revitalization. Socialist practice in the US has become the domain of sectarian groups that drive away working-class support, and socialist consciousness has not embedded itself in any significant sections of the working class or a left capable of exercising social power. That failing reflects the cultural and ideological triumph of neoliberalism and the identitarian ideologies and programmes that serve as its left wing. In this environment, building socialism is exclusively a project of cadre development, albeit one that cannot hope to succeed apart from broader movement-building. Broad movement-building requires mobilizing around an agenda of substantively anti-capitalist reforms that directly and militantly assert the priority of social needs over market forces, bourgeois property rights and managerial prerogative in the workplace and production process. Struggles to preserve and expand public institutions and to decommoditize basic human needs like housing, transportation, healthcare and education could begin to address the immediate challenge, which is to create a new popular constituency for a revitalized movement, instead of reorganizing or re-mobilizing an already existing but totally marginalized left.26 Some question whether the current US labour movement is too narrow a platform on which to rebuild a left. In a widely circulated article, ‘Fortress Unionism’, Rich Yeselson correctly highlights the atrophy of the labour movement and shows how its decline began with the passage of the TaftHartley Act in 1947. He contends that labour’s ‘current institutional expression cannot, via a creative conceptual breakthrough (“tactics or broader strategy”), engender a vast growth in union strength comparable to its former peak. In short, “organized labor” can no longer create a space for workers to join their organizations by the millions’.27 In grim statistical detail, Jake Rosenfeld’s What Unions No Longer Do gives fuel to this thesis. He points out that despite decades of exemplary, heroic and pioneering organizing by Justice for Janitors in the immigrant community, ‘Today only one in seven Hispanic janitors in the United States belongs to a union, down from one in five back in 1988, when Justice for Janitors began’.28 Yeselson calls for a ‘fortress unionism’ that would ‘defend the remaining high-density regions, sectors and companies’ and then ‘Wait for the workers to say they have had enough. When they demand in vast numbers collective solutions to their problems, seize upon that energy and institutionalize it.’29 This approach correctly identifies the urgent need to preserve the remnants of the current labour movement as an institutional base upon which to build a future revitalized movement. And it also correctly points out the haplessness of willy-nilly organizing schemes that do little to build power for working people while exposing their best leaders in unorganized workplaces to massive employer retaliation without any ability to defend them. But a strategy of waiting for workers to say they have had enough ultimately relies on magical thinking not unlike that of isolated Japanese soldiers scattered on island outposts at the end of the Second World War waiting for reinforcements from a defeated empire. Many of Yeselson’s critics, however, are equally quixotic. Bruce Raynor and Andy Stern, two of the most cynical practitioners of a unionism that disempowers workers and is based on a model of global class collaboration, point out that the ‘fortress’ strategy will do little to reduce inequality. Instead, they place their hopes in ‘strategic alliances with willing employers’; in unions developing value-added services to complement human resource departments; and in leveraging union and public-sector pension funds to rebuild union density.30 This strategy would liquidate the very concept of an independent labour movement. Given its decimation and marginalization, any revitalization movement would need to be built from a base that is far broader than the current institutional labour movement. A revitalized labour movement will have to embrace new organizational forms and some of the models emerging from new labour organizing show significant potential. Some are driven by necessity as the legal status of many immigrants and of workers in industries such as trucking, taxi driving and residential construction make organizing under current labour law virtually illegal. Much of this new organizing is being done by Worker Centers with heavy foundation funding and has the character of social work along the settlement house model of the early twentieth century. Much of it seems also, more or less openly, to fold class analysis into identitarian discourses that both substitute moralizing for political critique and fit comfortably within the NGO model. Such impulses, as well as the popularity of neologism, underlie arguments that current conditions have generated a new social formation, a ‘precariat’ that lies outside the traditional capitalist class structure.31 But some associated with this category have begun to evolve into substantial, self-conscious worker-run organizations. The Taxi Workers Alliance grew from a small New York City advocacy group to become a national organization (whose members are classified as ‘independent contractors’ and thus ineligible for union representation under US labour law) and was recently admitted to the AFL-CIO.32 In Vermont and elsewhere, strategic Workers Centers have built organic alliances with the labour movement and gone on to lead significant campaigns for healthcare for all, paid sick days and economic justice through the mobilization of a working-class constituency.33 Some argue that these campaigns and projects have the capacity to coalesce into geographically based class-conscious organizations and have called for the building of worker assemblies to give voice to this new movement.34 Such an effort would require a level of ideological sophistication and institutional independence that does not currently exist. Attempts to establish these structures on the ground have been premature and could actually inhibit the kind of broad, class-based organizing that inspires this movement in much the same way that many Labor Party chapters became captured by an ‘activistist’ mentality that focused more on preaching to the converted than building a constituency, while driving away real working-class voices who represented something more than themselves. New models are most successful when they can leverage existing organization and power to build outwards into new organization. Recent experiences organizing healthcare and homecare workers, hotel and casino workers and building services employees are fruitful examples of smart and strategic organizing that have leveraged existing union relationships and/ or political opportunities to build power for working people. We also look to the logistics organizing campaigns – which focus on the chokepoints of global capitalism and build on existing union power on the docks and other shipping centres – as having the potential to develop a particularly powerful form of a strategic union presence in economic sectors at the very core of contemporary capitalism.35 | 9,972 | <h4>The alternative is a <u>structural socialist analysis</u> to <u>strategically</u> organize emancipation through a mass socialist movement---only total buy-in can deconstruct the <u>totalizing</u> nature of capital---identitarian politics fractures movements and fails to spur social or institutional change</h4><p><strong>Dudzic and Reed 15</strong> – national organizer of the labor party; PhD, professor of political science at the University of Pennsylvania.</p><p><u>(Mark and Adolph, “THE CRISIS OF LABOUR AND THE LEFT IN THE UNITED STATES”, November 2015, Socialist Register)</p><p>Any serious discussion of the prospects for rebuilding a left must start from the understanding that the left in the US</u>, as in the rest of the capitalist world, <u>suffered a strategic defeat, and that capital has reorganized and emerged from the 2008 economic crisis even stronger</u>.24 While the extreme financialization of capital is likely to increase the frequency and intensity of episodic crises, this crisis once again confirms that there is no necessary correlation between crisis and revitalization of the left. In fact, notwithstanding glimmers of hope like SYRIZA in Greece and strong showings by anti-austerity parties in the spring 2014 European elections, the history of the post-2008 crisis politics in Europe would indicate that the more intense the crisis, the more deeply reactionary the response. <u>This does not mean that those who embrace a transformative vision must abandon all hope. Rather, the <mark>priorities</mark>, activities <mark>and resources</mark> of those who would rebuild a real left <mark>must be informed by </mark>this <strong><mark>strategic sensibility</strong></mark>. Building or rebuilding an effective left presence will be quite likely a decades-long process.</u> This means that we are not well served by clambering after the Next Big Thing. <u><mark>We must</mark> start by <strong><mark>excis</mark>ing <mark>the impulse</strong></mark> – quite understandable <mark>for a political movement <strong>devoid of</mark> any <mark>real agency</strong></mark> – <strong>toward utopian dreaming and wishful thinking</strong>.</u> <u><strong><mark>The spark will not ignite the prairie fire</mark>.</u></strong> <u>Nor will the Ark float on its own account no matter how carefully we construct it. <mark>Recognizing the left’s political irrelevance can be <strong>emancipating</u></strong></mark>, <u>as it reduces the sense of urgency <mark>to</mark> try to mobilize around every one of neoliberalism’s daily outrages</u>. <u>That should <mark>provide space for</mark> serious strategic discussion of how to begin <mark>to <strong>build a mass socialist movement</strong></mark> based in the working class <mark>and</mark> the <mark>creation of new institutions</mark> capable of <mark>mobilizing cross-class solidarity</u></mark>, as Sam Gindin has articulated in a particularly clear and compelling way.25 Certainly, <u>the US left could benefit from a nonsectarian, organized force with a <strong>coherent strategic vision and programme</u></strong>. <u>The <mark>absence of a disciplined, unified</mark> and sophisticated group of <mark>cadre is a</mark> major <mark>source of the left’s incoherence</mark>, <mark>and</mark> helps <mark>explain why</mark> moments of <mark>spontaneous </mark>political <mark>upsurge have had</u></mark>, at best, <u>an <strong><mark>episodic impact</strong></mark> and remain unconnected to similar moments in the past</u> – even those in which the same activists have participated. <u>Such organization</u>, however,<u> cannot be created in a vacuum</u>. <u>It can only emerge in tandem with a growing working-class movement. </u>We fear that in the specific context of US history and practice, the socialist project is too narrow a platform from which to launch a broad and far ranging left revitalization. Socialist practice in the US has become the domain of sectarian groups that drive away working-class support, and socialist consciousness has not embedded itself in any significant sections of the working class or a left capable of exercising social power. That<u> <mark>failing reflects</mark> the cultural and ideological <mark>triumph of</mark> <mark>neoliberalism and</mark> the <mark>identitarian ideologies</mark> and programmes that serve as its left wing.</u> In this environment, <u>building socialism is exclusively a project of cadre development</u>, albeit one that cannot hope to succeed apart from broader movement-building. <u><mark>Broad movement-building requires <strong>mobilizing around</mark> an agenda of <mark>substantively anti-capitalist reforms</u></strong> <u>that</mark> directly and <mark>militantly assert the priority of social needs</mark> over market forces, bourgeois property rights and managerial prerogative in the workplace and production process</u>. <u><mark>Struggles to preserve and expand public institutions</mark> and to decommoditize basic human needs <mark>like</mark> <strong><mark>housing</strong></mark>, <strong><mark>transportation</strong></mark>, <strong><mark>healthcare</strong></mark> <mark>and</mark> <strong><mark>education</strong></mark> <mark>could</mark> begin to address the immediate challenge, which is to <mark>create a</mark> new <mark>popular constituency for a revitalized movement</mark>, instead of reorganizing or re-mobilizing an already existing but <strong>totally marginalized left</u></strong>.26 Some question whether the current US labour movement is too narrow a platform on which to rebuild a left. In a widely circulated article, ‘Fortress Unionism’, Rich Yeselson correctly highlights the atrophy of the labour movement and shows how its decline began with the passage of the TaftHartley Act in 1947. He contends that labour’s ‘current institutional expression cannot, via a creative conceptual breakthrough (“tactics or broader strategy”), engender a vast growth in union strength comparable to its former peak. In short, “organized labor” can no longer create a space for workers to join their organizations by the millions’.27 In grim statistical detail, Jake Rosenfeld’s What Unions No Longer Do gives fuel to this thesis. He points out that despite decades of exemplary, heroic and pioneering organizing by Justice for Janitors in the immigrant community, ‘Today only one in seven Hispanic janitors in the United States belongs to a union, down from one in five back in 1988, when Justice for Janitors began’.28 Yeselson calls for a ‘fortress unionism’ that would ‘defend the remaining high-density regions, sectors and companies’ and then ‘Wait for the workers to say they have had enough. When they demand in vast numbers collective solutions to their problems, seize upon that energy and institutionalize it.’29 <u>This approach correctly identifies the urgent need to preserve the remnants of the current labour movement as an institutional base upon which to build a future revitalized movement.</u> And <u>it also correctly points out the <strong>haplessness of <mark>willy-nilly organizing schemes</strong></mark> that <mark>do little to build power for working people while</mark> exposing their best leaders in unorganized workplaces to massive employer retaliation without any ability to defend them</u>. But <u>a strategy of waiting for workers to say they have had enough ultimately <mark>relies on <strong>magical thinking</u></strong></mark> not unlike that of isolated Japanese soldiers scattered on island outposts at the end of the Second World War waiting for reinforcements from a defeated empire. Many of Yeselson’s critics, however, are equally quixotic. Bruce Raynor and Andy Stern, two of the most cynical practitioners of a unionism that disempowers workers and is based on a model of global class collaboration, point out that <u><strong><mark>the ‘fortress’ strategy will do little to reduce inequality</u></strong></mark>. <u>Instead, they place their hopes in ‘strategic alliances with willing employers’; in unions developing value-added services to complement human resource departments; and in leveraging union and public-sector pension funds to rebuild union density</u>.30 This strategy would liquidate the very concept of an independent labour movement. Given its decimation and marginalization, <u>any revitalization movement would need to be built from a base that is far broader than the current institutional labour movement</u>. <u>A revitalized labour movement will have to embrace new organizational forms and some of the models emerging from new labour organizing show <strong>significant potential</u></strong>. Some are driven by necessity as the legal status of many immigrants and of workers in industries such as trucking, taxi driving and residential construction make organizing under current labour law virtually illegal. Much of this new organizing is being done by Worker Centers with heavy foundation funding and has the character of social work along the settlement house model of the early twentieth century. <u>Much of <mark>it seems</mark> also, more or less openly, <mark>to fold class analysis into identitarian discourses that</mark> both <mark>substitute moralizing for political critique</mark> and fit comfortably within the NGO model</u>. Such impulses, as well as the popularity of neologism, underlie arguments that current conditions have generated a new social formation, a ‘precariat’ that lies outside the traditional capitalist class structure.31 But <u>some associated with this category have begun to evolve into substantial, self-conscious worker-run organizations</u>. The Taxi Workers Alliance grew from a small New York City advocacy group to become a national organization (whose members are classified as ‘independent contractors’ and thus ineligible for union representation under US labour law) and was recently admitted to the AFL-CIO.32 In Vermont and elsewhere, strategic Workers Centers have built organic alliances with the labour movement and gone on to lead significant campaigns for healthcare for all, paid sick days and economic justice through the mobilization of a working-class constituency.33 <u>Some argue that these <mark>campaigns</mark> and projects <mark>have the capacity to <strong>coalesce into</mark> geographically based <mark>class-conscious organizations</strong></mark> and have called for the building of worker assemblies to give voice to this new movement</u>.34 Such an effort would require a level of ideological sophistication and institutional independence that does not currently exist. <u><mark>Attempts to establish these structures</mark> on the ground have been premature and <mark>could</mark> actually <strong><mark>inhibit </mark>the kind of broad, <mark>class-based organizing</strong> that</mark> inspires this movement in much the same way that many Labor Party chapters became <strong><mark>captured by an ‘activistist’ mentality that focused more on preaching</strong></mark> to the converted <mark>than building a constituency, while driving away real working-class voices</mark> who represented something more than themselves. New <mark>models are most successful when they can <strong>leverage existing organization</strong></mark> and power <mark>to build outwards</mark> into new organization</u>. <u>Recent experiences organizing healthcare and homecare workers, hotel and casino workers and building services employees are fruitful examples of smart and <mark>strategic organizing that have leveraged</mark> existing union relationships and</u>/ or <u><strong><mark>political opportunities to build power for working people</u></strong></mark>. We also look to the logistics <u>organizing campaigns</u> – which <u><mark>focus on the <strong>chokepoints of global capitalism </strong>and</mark> build on existing union power on the docks and other shipping centres</u> – <u>as having the potential to <mark>develop</mark> a particularly <mark>powerful</mark> form of a strategic union <mark>presence</mark> in economic sectors <strong><mark>at the</mark> very <mark>core of contemporary capitalism</strong>.</u>35</p></mark> | null | null | K | 51,714 | 314 | 123,440 | ./documents/ndtceda16/Kansas/LiWe/Kansas-Lipka-Wefald-Neg-WSU-Round6.docx | 590,154 | N | WSU | 6 | Central Oklahoma Colen-Moore | montee | 1AC - Wynter
1NC - T USFG Oil DA Cap K
2NR - T USFG | ndtceda16/Kansas/LiWe/Kansas-Lipka-Wefald-Neg-WSU-Round6.docx | null | 50,356 | LiWe | Kansas LiWe | null | Ka..... | Li..... | Pe..... | We..... | 19,039 | Kansas | Kansas | null | null | 1,006 | ndtceda16 | NDT/CEDA 2016-17 | 2,016 | cx | college | 2 |
3,812,577 | Food shortages cause global wars | Brown, 9 | Brown, 9 (Lester R, - founder of the Worldwatch Institute and the Earth Policy Institute “Can Food Shortages Bring Down Civilization?” Scientific American, May) | The biggest threat to global stability is the potential for food crises to cause government collapse. Those crises are brought on by ever worsening environmental degradation
the idea that civilization could disintegrate seems preposterous. The combined effects of those trends and the political tensions they generate point to the breakdown of governments and societies. Yet I, too, have resisted the idea that food shortages could bring down not only individual governments but also our global civilization.
Our continuing failure to deal with the environmental declines that are undermining the world food economy--most important, falling water tables, eroding soils and rising temperatures-- such a collapse is possible. As demand for food rises faster than supplies are growing, the resulting food-price inflation puts severe stress on the governments of countries already teetering on the edge of chaos. if the food situation continues to deteriorate, entire nations will break down at an ever increasing rate. In the 20th century the main threat to international security was superpower conflict; today it is failing states. Failing states are of international concern because they are a source of terrorists, drugs, weapons and refugees, threatening political stability everywhere. Our global civilization depends on a functioning network of politically healthy nation-states If the system for controlling infectious diseases breaks down, humanity will be in trouble. Once states fail their fall will threaten the stability of global civilization itself. | The biggest threat to global stability is food crises cause government collapse
those trends and political tensions point to the breakdown of governments and societies
such a collapse is possible. if the food situation continues to deteriorate, entire nations will break down the main threat to international security was superpower conflict; today it is failing states Failing states are a source of terrorists, drugs, weapons and refugees, threatening political stability everywhere If the system for controlling diseases-- breaks down, humanity will be in trouble. Once states fai their fall will threaten the stability of global civilization | The biggest threat to global stability is the potential for food crises in poor countries to cause government collapse. Those crises are brought on by ever worsening environmental degradation
One of the toughest things for people to do is to anticipate sudden change. Typically we project the future by extrapolating from trends in the past. Much of the time this approach works well. But sometimes it fails spectacularly, and people are simply blindsided by events such as today's economic crisis.
For most of us, the idea that civilization itself could disintegrate probably seems preposterous. Who would not find it hard to think seriously about such a complete departure from what we expect of ordinary life? What evidence could make us heed a warning so dire--and how would we go about responding to it? We are so inured to a long list of highly unlikely catastrophes that we are virtually programmed to dismiss them all with a wave of the hand: Sure, our civilization might devolve into chaos--and Earth might collide with an asteroid, too! For many years I have studied global agricultural, population, environmental and economic trends and their interactions. The combined effects of those trends and the political tensions they generate point to the breakdown of governments and societies. Yet I, too, have resisted the idea that food shortages could bring down not only individual governments but also our global civilization.
I can no longer ignore that risk. Our continuing failure to deal with the environmental declines that are undermining the world food economy--most important, falling water tables, eroding soils and rising temperatures--forces me to conclude that such a collapse is possible. The Problem of Failed States Even a cursory look at the vital signs of our current world order lends unwelcome support to my conclusion. And those of us in the environmental field are well into our third decade of charting trends of environmental decline without seeing any significant effort to reverse a single one. In six of the past nine years world grain production has fallen short of consumption, forcing a steady drawdown in stocks. When the 2008 harvest began, world carryover stocks of grain (the amount in the bin when the new harvest begins) were at 62 days of consumption, a near record low. In response, world grain prices in the spring and summer of last year climbed to the highest level ever. As demand for food rises faster than supplies are growing, the resulting food-price inflation puts severe stress on the governments of countries already teetering on the edge of chaos. Unable to buy grain or grow their own, hungry people take to the streets. Indeed, even before the steep climb in grain prices in 2008, the number of failing states was expanding [see sidebar at left]. Many of their problem's stem from a failure to slow the growth of their populations. But if the food situation continues to deteriorate, entire nations will break down at an ever increasing rate. We have entered a new era in geopolitics. In the 20th century the main threat to international security was superpower conflict; today it is failing states. It is not the concentration of power but its absence that puts us at risk. States fail when national governments can no longer provide personal security, food security and basic social services such as education and health care. They often lose control of part or all of their territory. When governments lose their monopoly on power, law and order begin to disintegrate. After a point, countries can become so dangerous that food relief workers are no longer safe and their programs are halted; in Somalia and Afghanistan, deteriorating conditions have already put such programs in jeopardy. Failing states are of international concern because they are a source of terrorists, drugs, weapons and refugees, threatening political stability everywhere. Somalia, number one on the 2008 list of failing states, has become a base for piracy. Iraq, number five, is a hotbed for terrorist training. Afghanistan, number seven, is the world's leading supplier of heroin. Following the massive genocide of 1994 in Rwanda, refugees from that troubled state, thousands of armed soldiers among them, helped to destabilize neighboring Democratic Republic of the Congo (number six). Our global civilization depends on a functioning network of politically healthy nation-states to control the spread of infectious disease, to manage the international monetary system, to control international terrorism and to reach scores of other common goals. If the system for controlling infectious diseases--such as polio, SARS or avian flu--breaks down, humanity will be in trouble. Once states fail, no one assumes responsibility for their debt to outside lenders. If enough states disintegrate, their fall will threaten the stability of global civilization itself. | 4,903 | <h4><strong>Food shortages cause global wars</h4><p>Brown, 9 <u></strong>(Lester R, - founder of the Worldwatch Institute and the Earth Policy Institute “Can Food Shortages Bring Down Civilization?” Scientific American, May)</p><p><mark>The biggest threat to global stability</mark> <mark>is </mark>the potential for<mark> food crises</u></mark> in poor countries <u>to <mark>cause government collapse</mark>.</u> <u>Those crises are brought on by ever worsening environmental degradation</p><p></u>One of the toughest things for people to do is to anticipate sudden change. Typically we project the future by extrapolating from trends in the past. Much of the time this approach works well. But sometimes it fails spectacularly, and people are simply blindsided by events such as today's economic crisis.</p><p>For most of us, <u>the idea that civilization</u> itself <u>could disintegrate</u> probably <u>seems preposterous.</u> Who would not find it hard to think seriously about such a complete departure from what we expect of ordinary life? What evidence could make us heed a warning so dire--and how would we go about responding to it? We are so inured to a long list of highly unlikely catastrophes that we are virtually programmed to dismiss them all with a wave of the hand: Sure, our civilization might devolve into chaos--and Earth might collide with an asteroid, too! For many years I have studied global agricultural, population, environmental and economic trends and their interactions. <u>The combined effects of <mark>those trends and</mark> the <mark>political tensions</mark> they generate <mark>point to the breakdown of governments and societies</mark>. Yet I, too, have resisted the idea that food shortages could bring down not only individual governments but also our global civilization.</p><p></u>I can no longer ignore that risk. <u>Our continuing failure to deal with the environmental declines that are undermining the world food economy--most important, falling water tables, eroding soils and rising temperatures--</u>forces me to conclude that <u><mark>such a collapse is possible.</mark> </u>The Problem of Failed States Even a cursory look at the vital signs of our current world order lends unwelcome support to my conclusion. And those of us in the environmental field are well into our third decade of charting trends of environmental decline without seeing any significant effort to reverse a single one. In six of the past nine years world grain production has fallen short of consumption, forcing a steady drawdown in stocks. When the 2008 harvest began, world carryover stocks of grain (the amount in the bin when the new harvest begins) were at 62 days of consumption, a near record low. In response, world grain prices in the spring and summer of last year climbed to the highest level ever.<u> As demand for food rises faster than supplies are growing, the resulting food-price inflation puts severe stress on the governments of countries already teetering on the edge of chaos.</u> Unable to buy grain or grow their own, hungry people take to the streets. Indeed, even before the steep climb in grain prices in 2008, the number of failing states was expanding [see sidebar at left]. Many of their problem's stem from a failure to slow the growth of their populations. But <u><mark>if the food situation continues to deteriorate, entire nations will break down </mark>at an ever increasing rate.</u> We have entered a new era in geopolitics. <u>In the 20th century<mark> the main threat to international security was superpower conflict; today it is failing states</mark>.</u> It is not the concentration of power but its absence that puts us at risk.<u> </u>States fail when national governments can no longer provide personal security, food security and basic social services such as education and health care. They often lose control of part or all of their territory. When governments lose their monopoly on power, law and order begin to disintegrate. After a point, countries can become so dangerous that food relief workers are no longer safe and their programs are halted; in Somalia and Afghanistan, deteriorating conditions have already put such programs in jeopardy.<u> <mark>Failing states </mark>are of international concern because they<mark> are a source of terrorists, drugs, weapons and refugees, threatening political stability everywhere</mark>.</u> Somalia, number one on the 2008 list of failing states, has become a base for piracy. Iraq, number five, is a hotbed for terrorist training. Afghanistan, number seven, is the world's leading supplier of heroin. Following the massive genocide of 1994 in Rwanda, refugees from that troubled state, thousands of armed soldiers among them, helped to destabilize neighboring Democratic Republic of the Congo (number six).<u> Our global civilization depends on a functioning network of politically healthy nation-states</u> to control the spread of infectious disease, to manage the international monetary system, to control international terrorism and to reach scores of other common goals. <u><mark>If the system for controlling </mark>infectious<mark> diseases</u>--</mark>such as polio, SARS or avian flu--<u><mark>breaks down, humanity will be in trouble. Once states fai</mark>l</u>, no one assumes responsibility for their debt to outside lenders. If enough states disintegrate, <u><mark>their fall will threaten the stability of global civilization</mark> itself.</p></u> | 1nc | 3 | null | 21,964 | 191 | 126,799 | ./documents/hspolicy16/MontgomeryBellAcademy/BaHa/Montgomery%20Bell%20Academy-Barton-Habermann-Neg-Michigan-Round3.docx | 663,028 | N | Michigan | 3 | USN KW | Alex Kong | 1ac-mes steel
1nc-t uncondo t bonds qpq nationalism da congress elections da
2nr-t bonds qpq | hspolicy16/MontgomeryBellAcademy/BaHa/Montgomery%20Bell%20Academy-Barton-Habermann-Neg-Michigan-Round3.docx | null | 56,194 | BaHa | Montgomery Bell Academy BaHa | null | Ad..... | Ba..... | Ju..... | Ha..... | 20,211 | MontgomeryBellAcademy | Montgomery Bell Academy | null | null | 1,015 | hspolicy16 | HS Policy 2016-17 | 2,016 | cx | hs | 2 |
1,117,813 | Biod loss is not an existential threat | Kareiva & Carranza 18 .2018.01.001. | Peter Kareiva & Valerie Carranza 18. Institute of the Environment and Sustainability, University of California, Los Angeles. 01/2018. “Existential Risk Due to Ecosystem Collapse: Nature Strikes Back.” Futures. CrossRef, doi:10.1016/j.futures.2018.01.001. | The question is whether any thresholds could also portend existential risks the answer is not clear One boundary often mentioned as a concern for the fate of global civilization is biodiversity There is little evidence that annual loss is a threshold—and it is hard to imagine any data that would allow one to identify where the threshold was A better question is whether one can imagine any scenario by which the loss of too many species leads to the collapse of societies and environmental disasters While there are data that relate local reductions to altered ecosystem function, these results do not point to substantial existential risks The data are small-scale experiments in which plant productivity, or nutrient retention is reduced as species number declines locally or are local observations of increased variability in fisheries yield when stock diversity is lost Those are not existential risks To make the link even more tenuous, there is little evidence that biodiversity is even declining at local scales Total biodiversity may be in decline, but local and regional biodiversity is often staying the same because species from elsewhere replace local losses albeit homogenizing the world in the process Although the majority of conservation scientists are likely to flinch at this conclusion, there is growing skepticism regarding the strength of evidence linking trends in biodiversity loss to an existential risk for humans Obviously if all biodiversity disappeared civilization would end—but no one is forecasting the loss of all species the loss of 90% could also be apocalyptic, but no one is predicting that degree of biodiversity loss either Tragic, but plausible is the possibility our planet suffering a loss of as many as half of its species. If global biodiversity were halved, but at the same time locally the number of species stayed relatively stable, what would be the mechanism for an end-of-civilization or even end of human prosperity scenario? Extinctions and biodiversity loss are ethical and spiritual losses, but not an existential risk. ozone depletion thanks to the Montreal Protocol is being reversed Disruptions of the nitrogen cycle and phosphorous have also been proposed as representing potential planetary boundaries There are compelling data linking excesses in these nutrients to environmental damage However, these impacts are local At the same time that there is too much N loading in the US, there is a need for more N in Africa as a way of increasing agricultural yields While the disruption of nitrogen and phosphorous cycles clearly perturb local ecosystems end-of-the-world scenarios seem far-fetched Another hypothesized planetary boundary entails the conversion of natural habitats to agricultural land The mechanism by which too much agricultural land could cause a crisis is unclear unless it is because conversion causes so much biodiversity loss that is species extinctions that are the proximate cause of an eco-catastrophe chemical pollution have been suggested as planetary boundaries as well. In the case of these pollution boundaries, there are well-documented mechanisms by which surpassing some concentration of a pollutant inflicts severe human health hazards. There is abundant evidence linking chemical and aerosol pollution to higher mortality and lower reproductive success in humans, which in turn could cause a major die-off. It is appropriate then that when Hollywood envisions an unlivable world, it often invokes a story of humans poisoning themselves. That said, it is doubtful that we will poison ourselves towards extinction as nations develop and increase their wealth, they tend to clean up their air and water and reduce environmental pollution In addition, as economies become more circular environmental damage due to waste products is likely to decline. The key point is that the pollutants associated with the planetary boundaries are so widely recognized and the consequences of local toxic events are so immediate that it is reasonable to expect national governments to act before we suffer a planetary ecocatastrophe. | existential risks often mention biodiversity There is little ev While local reductions alter ecosystem these do not point to existential risks data are small-scale there is little ev that diversity is even declining at local scales Total diversity decline, but local diversity is staying the same because species from elsewhere replace local losses If diversity were halved, but local species stayed stable, what would be the mech for end-of-civilization pollution is Hollywood as nations increase wealth, they clean up pollution as economies become circular waste products decline the consequences are so immediate, that governments act before catastrophe | The interesting question is whether any of the planetary thresholds other than CO2 could also portend existential risks. Here the answer is not clear. One boundary often mentioned as a concern for the fate of global civilization is biodiversity (Ehrlich & Ehrlich, 2012), with the proposed safety threshold being a loss of greater than .001% per year (Rockström et al., 2009). There is little evidence that this particular .001% annual loss is a threshold—and it is hard to imagine any data that would allow one to identify where the threshold was (Brook et al., 2013; Lenton & Williams, 2013). A better question is whether one can imagine any scenario by which the loss of too many species leads to the collapse of societies and environmental disasters, even though one cannot know the absolute number of extinctions that would be required to create this dystopia. While there are data that relate local reductions in species richness to altered ecosystem function, these results do not point to substantial existential risks. The data are small-scale experiments in which plant productivity, or nutrient retention is reduced as species number declines locally (Vellend, 2017), or are local observations of increased variability in fisheries yield when stock diversity is lost (Schindler et al., 2010). Those are not existential risks. To make the link even more tenuous, there is little evidence that biodiversity is even declining at local scales (Vellend et al 2017; Vellend et al., 2013). Total planetary biodiversity may be in decline, but local and regional biodiversity is often staying the same because species from elsewhere replace local losses, albeit homogenizing the world in the process. Although the majority of conservation scientists are likely to flinch at this conclusion, there is growing skepticism regarding the strength of evidence linking trends in biodiversity loss to an existential risk for humans (Maier, 2012; Vellend, 2014). Obviously if all biodiversity disappeared civilization would end—but no one is forecasting the loss of all species. It seems plausible that the loss of 90% of the world’s species could also be apocalyptic, but not one is predicting that degree of biodiversity loss either. Tragic, but plausible is the possibility our planet suffering a loss of as many as half of its species. If global biodiversity were halved, but at the same time locally the number of species stayed relatively stable, what would be the mechanism for an end-of-civilization or even end of human prosperity scenario? Extinctions and biodiversity loss are ethical and spiritual losses, but perhaps not an existential risk. What about the remaining eight planetary boundaries? Stratospheric ozone depletion is one—but thanks to the Montreal Protocol ozone depletion is being reversed (Hand, 2016). Disruptions of the nitrogen cycle and of the phosphorous cycle have also been proposed as representing potential planetary boundaries (one boundary for nitrogen and one boundary for phosphorous). There are compelling data linking excesses in these nutrients to environmental damage. For example, over-application of fertilizer in Midwestern USA has led to dead zones in the Gulf of Mexico. Similarly, excessive nitrogen has polluted groundwater in California to such an extent that it is unsuitable for drinking and some rural communities are forced to drink bottled water. However, these impacts are local. At the same time that there is too much N loading in the US, there is a need for more N in Africa as a way of increasing agricultural yields (Mueller et al., 2012). While the disruption of nitrogen and phosphorous cycles clearly perturb local ecosystems, end-of-the-world scenarios seem a bit far-fetched. Another hypothesized planetary boundary entails the conversion of natural habitats to agricultural land. The mechanism by which too much agricultural land could cause a crisis is unclear—unless it is because land conversion causes so much biodiversity loss that is species extinctions that are the proximate cause of an eco-catastrophe. Excessive chemical pollution and excessive atmospheric aerosol loading have each been suggested as planetary boundaries as well. In the case of these pollution boundaries, there are well-documented mechanisms by which surpassing some concentration of a pollutant inflicts severe human health hazards. There is abundant evidence linking chemical and aerosol pollution to higher mortality and lower reproductive success in humans, which in turn could cause a major die-off. It is perhaps appropriate then that when Hollywood envisions an unlivable world, it often invokes a story of humans poisoning themselves. That said, it is doubtful that we will poison ourselves towards extinction. Data show that as nations develop and increase their wealth, they tend to clean up their air and water and reduce environmental pollution (Flörke et al., 2013; Hao & Wang, 2005). In addition, as economies become more circular (see Mathews & Tan, 2016), environmental damage due to waste products is likely to decline. The key point is that the pollutants associated with the planetary boundaries are so widely recognized, and the consequences of local toxic events are so immediate, that it is reasonable to expect national governments to act before we suffer a planetary ecocatastrophe. | 5,346 | <h4>Biod loss is not an existential threat</h4><p>Peter <strong>Kareiva &</strong> Valerie <strong>Carranza 18</strong>. Institute of the Environment and Sustainability, University of California, Los Angeles. 01/2018. “Existential Risk Due to Ecosystem Collapse: Nature Strikes Back.” Futures. CrossRef, doi:10.1016/j.futures<u><strong>.2018.01.001.</p><p></strong>The</u> interesting <u>question is whether any</u> of the planetary <u>thresholds</u> other than CO2 <u>could</u> <u><strong>also portend <mark>existential risks</u></strong></mark>. Here <u>the answer is <strong>not clear</u></strong>. <u>One boundary <mark>often mention</mark>ed as a concern for the fate of global civilization is <strong><mark>biodiversity</u></strong></mark> (Ehrlich & Ehrlich, 2012), with the proposed safety threshold being a loss of greater than .001% per year (Rockström et al., 2009). <u><mark>There is <strong>little ev</mark>idence</u></strong> <u>that</u> this particular .001% <u>annual loss is a threshold—and it is <strong>hard to imagine any data</strong> that would allow one to identify where the threshold was</u> (Brook et al., 2013; Lenton & Williams, 2013). <u>A better question is whether one can imagine <strong>any scenario</u></strong> <u>by which the loss of too many species leads to the collapse of societies and environmental disasters</u>, even though one cannot know the absolute number of extinctions that would be required to create this dystopia. <u><mark>While</mark> there are data that relate <strong><mark>local reductions</u></strong></mark> in species richness <u>to <mark>alter</mark>ed <mark>ecosystem</mark> function, <mark>these</mark> results <strong><mark>do not point to</mark> substantial <mark>existential risks</u></strong></mark>. <u>The <mark>data are <strong>small-scale</mark> experiments</u></strong> <u>in which plant productivity, or nutrient retention is reduced as species number declines locally</u> (Vellend, 2017), <u>or are <strong>local observations</strong> of increased variability in fisheries yield when stock diversity is lost</u> (Schindler et al., 2010). <u><strong>Those are not existential risks</u></strong>. <u>To make the link even more tenuous, <mark>there is little ev</mark>idence <mark>that</mark> bio<mark>diversity is <strong>even declining at local scales</strong></mark> </u>(Vellend et al 2017; Vellend et al., 2013). <u><strong><mark>Total</u></strong></mark> planetary <u>bio<mark>diversity</mark> may be in <mark>decline, but local</mark> and regional bio<mark>diversity is</mark> <strong>often <mark>staying the same</u></strong> <u>because species from elsewhere <strong>replace local losses</u></strong></mark>, <u>albeit homogenizing the world in the process</u>. <u>Although the majority of conservation scientists are likely to flinch at this conclusion, there is <strong>growing skepticism</strong> regarding the strength of evidence linking trends in biodiversity loss to an existential risk for humans</u> (Maier, 2012; Vellend, 2014). <u>Obviously if <strong>all biodiversity</strong> disappeared civilization would end—but <strong>no one is forecasting the loss of all species</u></strong>. It seems plausible that <u>the loss of <strong>90%</u></strong> of the world’s species <u>could also be apocalyptic, but no</u>t <u>one is predicting that degree of biodiversity loss either</u>. <u>Tragic, but <strong>plausible</strong> is the possibility our planet suffering a loss of as many as <strong>half</strong> of its species. <mark>If</mark> global bio<mark>diversity were halved, but</mark> at the same time <mark>local</mark>ly the number of <mark>species stayed</mark> relatively <mark>stable, <strong>what would be the mech</mark>anism <mark>for</mark> an <mark>end-of-civilization</mark> or even end of human prosperity scenario?</u></strong> <u>Extinctions and biodiversity loss are ethical and spiritual losses, but</u> perhaps <u><strong>not an existential risk. </u></strong>What about the remaining eight planetary boundaries? Stratospheric <u><strong>ozone depletion</u></strong> is one—but <u>thanks to the Montreal Protocol</u> ozone depletion <u>is being <strong>reversed</u></strong> (Hand, 2016). <u>Disruptions of the <strong>nitrogen cycle</u></strong> <u>and</u> of the <u><strong>phosphorous</u></strong> cycle <u>have also been proposed as representing potential planetary boundaries</u> (one boundary for nitrogen and one boundary for phosphorous). <u>There are compelling data linking excesses in these nutrients to environmental damage</u>. For example, over-application of fertilizer in Midwestern USA has led to dead zones in the Gulf of Mexico. Similarly, excessive nitrogen has polluted groundwater in California to such an extent that it is unsuitable for drinking and some rural communities are forced to drink bottled water. <u>However, these impacts are <strong>local</u></strong>. <u>At the same time that there is <strong>too much</strong> N loading in the US, there is a need for <strong>more N in Africa</u></strong> <u>as a way of increasing agricultural yields</u> (Mueller et al., 2012). <u>While the disruption of nitrogen and phosphorous cycles clearly perturb <strong>local ecosystems</u></strong>, <u><strong>end-of-the-world scenarios</u></strong> <u>seem</u> a bit <u><strong>far-fetched</u></strong>. <u>Another hypothesized planetary boundary entails the conversion of natural habitats to <strong>agricultural land</u></strong>. <u>The mechanism by which too much agricultural land could cause a crisis is <strong>unclear</u></strong>—<u>unless it is because</u> land <u>conversion causes so much biodiversity loss that is species extinctions that are the proximate cause of an eco-catastrophe</u>. Excessive <u><strong>chemical <mark>pollution</u></strong></mark> and excessive atmospheric aerosol loading <u>have</u> each <u>been suggested as planetary boundaries as well. In the case of these pollution boundaries, there are well-documented mechanisms by which surpassing some concentration of a pollutant inflicts <strong>severe human health hazards</strong>.</u> <u>There is abundant evidence linking chemical and aerosol pollution to higher <strong>mortality</strong> and lower reproductive success in humans, which in turn could cause a major die-off. It <mark>is</u></mark> perhaps <u>appropriate then that when <strong><mark>Hollywood</u></strong></mark> <u>envisions an unlivable world, it often invokes a story of humans poisoning themselves. That said, it is <strong>doubtful that we will poison ourselves towards extinction</u></strong>. Data show that <u><mark>as nations</mark> develop and <mark>increase</mark> their <mark>wealth, they</mark> tend to <strong><mark>clean up</mark> their air and water and reduce environmental <mark>pollution</u></strong></mark> (Flörke et al., 2013; Hao & Wang, 2005). <u>In addition, <mark>as economies become</mark> more <strong><mark>circular</u></strong></mark> (see Mathews & Tan, 2016), <u>environmental damage due to <mark>waste products</mark> is likely to <mark>decline</mark>. The key point is that the pollutants associated with the planetary boundaries are <strong>so widely recognized</u></strong>, <u>and <mark>the consequences</mark> of local toxic events <mark>are so <strong>immediate</u></strong>, <u>that</mark> it is <strong>reasonable to expect national <mark>governments</mark> to <mark>act before</mark> we suffer a planetary eco<mark>catastrophe</mark>.</p></u></strong> | null | Environment | null | 1,651,128 | 1,331 | 26,792 | ./documents/hspolicy21/Greenhill/MaMe/Greenhill-Madhavanur-Mettu-Neg-UT-Doubles.docx | 747,313 | N | UT | Doubles | Mount Pleasant CO | Rosie Valdez, Eric Melin, Bennett Dobcik | 1AC Line 5
1NC Court Legitamacy DA Michigan State CP Set Col T protect
2NR T-Protect | hspolicy21/Greenhill/MaMe/Greenhill-Madhavanur-Mettu-Neg-UT-Doubles.docx | null | 63,757 | MaMe | Greenhill MaMe | null | Sh..... | Ma..... | Te..... | Me..... | 21,980 | Greenhill | Greenhill | TX | null | 1,020 | hspolicy21 | HS Policy 2021-22 | 2,021 | cx | hs | 2 |
3,032,214 | Independently, economic crisis results in diversionary wars of aggression—robust statistical proof | Howell 13 | Patrick Howell 13. Graduate Student, International Affairs, University of Georgia; BA, International Studies, Emory. “Economic Crises and the Initiation of Militarized Disputes.” Thesis. https://getd.libs.uga.edu/pdfs/howell_patrick_d_201305_ma.pdf. | The findings are clear: economic crises are an important trigger for shifts in a state’s rate of dispute initiation using a large sample of states over a period of 185 years, this conclusion can be taken as generalizable to the entire population of states in the international system the findings here also support the methodological rationale for using economic crises as explicit, observable events, instead of as trends in other variables
diversionary war exists in both quantitative tests and in more fine-toothed examinations of actual cases the observed effect is driven by individual decision-makers themselves
Smith hypothesizes strategic avoidance in the study of the U S If strategic avoidance is occurring, it actually increases the strength of aspects of the diversionary war literature in that other states are actually behaving according to expectations of diversionary actions
The final implication of the findings to be discussed here is the role of institutions institutional controls that were included in the estimation demonstrated null effects on the overall rate of militarized dispute initiation. some find that the diversionary effects exist in democratic settings while others find that diversionary effects occur in autocratic settings
One method of reconciling the conflicting conclusions of whether democratic or autocratic leaders are more likely to engage in diversionary behavior is in direct tests comparing the two regime types Splitting the sample has the effect of interacting regime type with all independent variables, giving regime specific effects not only for economic crises, but also all control variables.1
the effect of economic crises is significant in both institutional settings all democracies and autocracies possess similar incentives for increasing crisis initiation following economic crises so any variation across institutions was only averaged out The similarity in the main independent variable of economic crises, furthers the assertion that the effect of economic crises increasing dispute initiation can be viewed as a general behavior of all states in the international system.
Conclusions
there can be said to be a robust, positive relationship between the occurrence of economic crises and the rate of dispute initiation by states This effect is especially strong and demonstrable when time ordering is preserved by examining how crises in the previous year affect states in their current year The nearly 20 percentage point increase in dispute initiation across the range of the lagged economic crisis variable also represents a substantial impact, especially considering the rare event nature of militarized disputes to begin with
there is good evidence to support the use of acute economic crises over those variables based on the slowershifting trends of GDP or public opinion measurements. Economic crises act as an explicit trigger that can mark a leader’s shift into a losses frame and engage in riskier behavior consistent with both prospect theory and diversionary war hypotheses | economic crises are an important trigger for dispute initiation using a large sample over 185 years, this conclusion can be generalizable
diversionary war exists in quantitative tests and fine-toothed examinations of cases
increases the strength of diversionary war lit states are behaving according to expectations of diversionary actions
institutional controls demonstrated null effects on dispute initiation
the effect is significant all democracies and autocracies possess similar incentives
a robust, positive relationship between economic crises and dispute initiation is especially strong when time ordering is preserved The 20 point increase in dispute initiation represents a substantial impact considering the rare nature of militarized disputes
crises act as an explicit trigger that mark a leader’s shift into a losses frame and engage in riskier behavior | The findings are clear: economic crises are an important trigger for shifts in a state’s rate of dispute initiation. By using a large sample of states over a period of 185 years, this conclusion then can also be taken as generalizable to the entire population of states in the international system. In addition to providing support for issue crossover and the influence economic troubles can play on foreign policy decisions, the findings here also support the methodological rationale for using economic crises as explicit, observable events, instead of as trends in other variables (e.g. GDP growth). Of course, this is not to say that all work on this topic is final. There exist a number of areas where this research agenda can be improved upon and/or extended to in order to provide a more holistic account of where and how economic crises exactly apply political pressure on leaders.
First, the study of diversionary war exists in both quantitative tests and in more fine-toothed examinations of actual cases (Levy and Vakili 1992; Fravel 2010). Exploring the internal processes within states in such a fashion can also produce a deeper understanding of the exact causal mechanisms through which prospect theory operates. Aggregation and levels of analysis become a basic concern with applying prospect theory outside of the laboratory and to states and governments. After all, “prospect theory is developed as a theory of individual decision making, the question is whether it is applicable to collective decision making” (Vis 2011, 337). Here a unitary actor assumption is made from the outset, but it is also possible that the observed effect is driven instead by individual decision-makers themselves (for example, Fuhrmann and Early 2008, who keep the level of analysis only on President Bush). A deeper case study of a few select cases with an eye towards process might reveal whether the increase in conflict initiation is due to a single policy entrepreneur or leader, or if it is the result of collective behavior (as perhaps even aides, legislators, and bureaucrats seek to compensate for the detrimental effects that accompany an economic crisis separately or in concert).
Examination of specific cases might also provide a more accurate picture for policymakers of the strategy that can accompany an economic crisis and inducement of diversionary tendencies in another state. Smith (Smith 1998) hypothesizes diversionary actions as a strategic game, and finds that potential target states should then adopt a policy of strategic avoidance – disengaging from any scenario that might make them a target from a diversionary conflict initiated by an opposing state in dire straits. This question of strategic avoidance occurs most often in the study of the United States (Fordham 2005; Meernik 2005), with evidence that other states avoid and/or initiate fewer disputes with the United States when the American economy is performing poorly. The empirical test here using a proportionbased dependent variable might already be capturing some degree of a strategic avoidance effect, in that some of the variation in the proportion of initiation could be because the rate of other states initiating disputes on the crisis-stricken state is decreasing. If strategic avoidance is occurring, it actually increases the strength of aspects of the diversionary war literature (in that other states are actually behaving according to expectations of diversionary actions), but much more work and nuance would be needed to separate where then the logic in strategic avoiders is originating.
The final implication of the findings to be discussed here is the role of institutions in this analysis. As stated above, the institutional controls that were included in the estimation demonstrated null effects on the overall rate of militarized dispute initiation. This finding is interesting considering the enshrined role that institutions and regime types tend to play within scholarly work on diversionary war. Similar to the mixed results of GDP indicators, mixed and contradictory results can be found throughout the body of work on diversionary war: some find that the diversionary effects exist mainly in democratic settings (Gelpi 1997; Davies 2002; Brul´e and Williams 2009), while others find that diversionary effects occur in autocratic settings (Miller 1999; Lai and Slater 2005; Pickering and Kisangani 2010).
One method of reconciling the conflicting conclusions of whether democratic or autocratic leaders are more likely to engage in diversionary behavior is in direct tests comparing the two regime types. Typically, these comparisons have either found the two regime types differ in the targets that are selected by each (Bueno De Mesquita and Siverson 1995), or have found some fault with the way that the regime types themselves are defined, due to differing incentives for differing subtypes of regimes (Pickering and Kisangani 2005). In order to examine the difference between democracies and autocracies, I split the sample from Model 2 into either of the regime types, using a score of 6 in the Polity2 measure as a cut-point. Splitting the sample has the effect of interacting regime type with all independent variables, giving regime specific effects not only for economic crises, but also all control variables.1
The results of this regime split can be found in Table 2. As can be seen here, the effect of economic crises is positive and significant in both institutional settings. Comparing the coefficients for economic crisis in Table 2 with those of the original Model 2, the likely explanation for why the institutional variables in the original model did not have an impact on crisis initiation is because all democracies and autocracies possess relatively similar incentives for increasing crisis initiation following economic crises, so any variation across institutions was only averaged out. However, the results presented in Table 2 also provide support for a difference existing in the process of how diversionary conflict might occur in either regime type, due to the differences in control variable significance. This lends some credence to the separation of democracies and autocracies for study of diversionary war, but provides no evidence that the effect should only exist in one or the other. The similarity in the main independent variable of economic crises, though, furthers the assertion that the effect of economic crises increasing dispute initiation can be viewed as a general behavior of all states in the international system.
Conclusions
Altogether, there can be said to be a robust, positive relationship between the occurrence of economic crises and the rate of dispute initiation by states. This effect is especially strong and demonstrable when time ordering is preserved by examining how crises in the previous year affect states in their current year. These findings can also be said to have a relatively high degree of substantive import as well. As Figure 1 showed, the occurrence of each subsequent economic crisis increases the chances of a state initiating disputes by almost 3%. The nearly 20 percentage point increase in dispute initiation across the range of the lagged economic crisis variable also represents a substantial impact, especially considering the rare event nature of militarized disputes to begin with.
This generalizable finding can have far-reaching impact to both the study of diversionary war in academia, as well as directly for policymakers. In academe settings, there is good evidence to support the use of acute economic crises over those variables based on the slowershifting trends of GDP or public opinion measurements. Economic crises act as an explicit trigger that can mark a leader’s shift into a losses frame and engage in riskier behavior consistent with both prospect theory and diversionary war hypotheses. Meanwhile, applying this observed effect to the real world would seem to indicate that if a state goes through an economic crisis, other states should have increased wariness in their dealings with the crisis-stricken state and/or be more prepared for the possibility of a new dispute emerging in the wake of such an event. | 8,230 | <h4>Independently, economic crisis results in diversionary wars of aggression—robust statistical proof</h4><p>Patrick <strong>Howell 13</strong>. Graduate Student, International Affairs, University of Georgia; BA, International Studies, Emory. “Economic Crises and the Initiation of Militarized Disputes.” Thesis. https://getd.libs.uga.edu/pdfs/howell_patrick_d_201305_ma.pdf. </p><p><u>The findings are clear:</u> <u><mark>economic crises are an important trigger for</mark> shifts in a state’s rate of <mark>dispute initiation</u></mark>. By <u><mark>using a <strong>large sample</strong></mark> of states <mark>over</mark> a period of <mark>185 years, this conclusion</u></mark> then <u><mark>can</u></mark> also <u><mark>be</mark> taken as <strong><mark>generalizable</mark> to the entire population of states</strong> in the international system</u>. In addition to providing support for issue crossover and the influence economic troubles can play on foreign policy decisions, <u>the findings here also support the methodological rationale for using economic crises as explicit, <strong>observable events</strong>, <strong>instead of as trends in other variables</strong> </u>(e.g. GDP growth). Of course, this is not to say that all work on this topic is final. There exist a number of areas where this research agenda can be improved upon and/or extended to in order to provide a more holistic account of where and how economic crises exactly apply political pressure on leaders.</p><p>First, the study of <u><mark>diversionary war exists in</mark> both <strong><mark>quantitative tests</strong> and</mark> in more <strong><mark>fine-toothed examinations</strong> of</mark> actual <mark>cases</u></mark> (Levy and Vakili 1992; Fravel 2010). Exploring the internal processes within states in such a fashion can also produce a deeper understanding of the exact causal mechanisms through which prospect theory operates. Aggregation and levels of analysis become a basic concern with applying prospect theory outside of the laboratory and to states and governments. After all, “prospect theory is developed as a theory of individual decision making, the question is whether it is applicable to collective decision making” (Vis 2011, 337). Here a unitary actor assumption is made from the outset, but it is also possible that <u>the observed effect is driven </u>instead<u> by individual decision-makers themselves</u> (for example, Fuhrmann and Early 2008, who keep the level of analysis only on President Bush). A deeper case study of a few select cases with an eye towards process might reveal whether the increase in conflict initiation is due to a single policy entrepreneur or leader, or if it is the result of collective behavior (as perhaps even aides, legislators, and bureaucrats seek to compensate for the detrimental effects that accompany an economic crisis separately or in concert).</p><p>Examination of specific cases might also provide a more accurate picture for policymakers of the strategy that can accompany an economic crisis and inducement of diversionary tendencies in another state. <u>Smith</u> (Smith 1998) <u>hypothesizes</u> diversionary actions as a strategic game, and finds that potential target states should then adopt a policy of <u>strategic avoidance</u> – disengaging from any scenario that might make them a target from a diversionary conflict initiated by an opposing state in dire straits. This question of strategic avoidance occurs most often <u>in the study of the</u> <u><strong>U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates (Fordham 2005; Meernik 2005), with evidence that other states avoid and/or initiate fewer disputes with the United States when the American economy is performing poorly. The empirical test here using a proportionbased dependent variable might already be capturing some degree of a strategic avoidance effect, in that some of the variation in the proportion of initiation could be because the rate of other states initiating disputes on the crisis-stricken state is decreasing. <u>If strategic avoidance is occurring, it actually <strong><mark>increases the strength of</strong></mark> aspects of the <strong><mark>diversionary war lit</strong></mark>erature</u> (<u>in that other <mark>states are</mark> actually <mark>behaving according to <strong>expectations of diversionary actions</u></strong></mark>), but much more work and nuance would be needed to separate where then the logic in strategic avoiders is originating.</p><p><u>The final implication of the findings to be discussed here is the role of institutions</u> in this analysis. As stated above, the <u><mark>institutional controls</mark> that were included in the estimation <strong><mark>demonstrated null effects</strong> on</mark> the overall rate of militarized <mark>dispute initiation</mark>.</u> This finding is interesting considering the enshrined role that institutions and regime types tend to play within scholarly work on diversionary war. Similar to the mixed results of GDP indicators, mixed and contradictory results can be found throughout the body of work on diversionary war: <u>some find that the diversionary effects exist </u>mainly <u>in democratic settings</u> (Gelpi 1997; Davies 2002; Brul´e and Williams 2009), <u>while others find that diversionary effects occur in autocratic settings</u> (Miller 1999; Lai and Slater 2005; Pickering and Kisangani 2010).</p><p><u>One method of reconciling the conflicting conclusions of whether democratic or autocratic leaders are more likely to engage in diversionary behavior is</u> <u>in direct tests comparing</u> <u>the two regime types</u>. Typically, these comparisons have either found the two regime types differ in the targets that are selected by each (Bueno De Mesquita and Siverson 1995), or have found some fault with the way that the regime types themselves are defined, due to differing incentives for differing subtypes of regimes (Pickering and Kisangani 2005). In order to examine the difference between democracies and autocracies, I split the sample from Model 2 into either of the regime types, using a score of 6 in the Polity2 measure as a cut-point. <u>Splitting the sample has the effect of interacting regime type with all independent variables, giving regime specific effects not only for economic crises, but also all control variables.1</p><p></u>The results of this regime split can be found in Table 2. As can be seen here, <u><mark>the effect</mark> of economic crises <mark>is</u></mark> positive and <u><strong><mark>significant</mark> in both institutional settings</u></strong>. Comparing the coefficients for economic crisis in Table 2 with those of the original Model 2, the likely explanation for why the institutional variables in the original model did not have an impact on crisis initiation is because <u><mark>all <strong>democracies and autocracies</strong> possess</u></mark> relatively <u><strong><mark>similar incentives</strong></mark> for increasing crisis initiation following</u> <u>economic crises</u>, <u>so any variation across institutions was only averaged out</u>. However, the results presented in Table 2 also provide support for a difference existing in the process of how diversionary conflict might occur in either regime type, due to the differences in control variable significance. This lends some credence to the separation of democracies and autocracies for study of diversionary war, but provides no evidence that the effect should only exist in one or the other. <u>The similarity in the <strong>main independent variable</strong> of economic crises,</u> though, <u>furthers the assertion that the effect of economic crises increasing dispute initiation can be viewed as a general behavior of all states in the international system.</p><p><strong>Conclusions</p><p></u></strong>Altogether, <u>there can be said to be <mark>a <strong>robust, positive relationship</strong> between</mark> the occurrence of <mark>economic crises and</mark> the rate of <mark>dispute initiation</mark> by states</u>. <u>This effect <mark>is <strong>especially strong</strong></mark> and demonstrable <mark>when <strong>time ordering is preserved</strong></mark> by examining how crises in the previous year affect states in their current year</u>. These findings can also be said to have a relatively high degree of substantive import as well. As Figure 1 showed, the occurrence of each subsequent economic crisis increases the chances of a state initiating disputes by almost 3%. <u><mark>The</mark> nearly <mark>20</mark> percentage <mark>point increase in dispute initiation</mark> across the range of the lagged economic crisis variable also <mark>represents a <strong>substantial impact</strong></mark>, especially <strong><mark>considering the rare</mark> event <mark>nature of militarized disputes</mark> to begin with</u></strong>.</p><p>This generalizable finding can have far-reaching impact to both the study of diversionary war in academia, as well as directly for policymakers. In academe settings, <u>there is good evidence to support the use of acute economic crises over those variables based on the slowershifting trends of GDP or public opinion measurements. Economic <mark>crises act as an</mark> <strong><mark>explicit trigger</strong> that</mark> can <mark>mark a leader’s shift into a losses frame and <strong>engage in riskier behavior</strong></mark> consistent with both prospect theory and diversionary war hypotheses</u>. Meanwhile, applying this observed effect to the real world would seem to indicate that if a state goes through an economic crisis, other states should have increased wariness in their dealings with the crisis-stricken state and/or be more prepared for the possibility of a new dispute emerging in the wake of such an event.</p> | 1ac | Contention 1: Economy | null | 42,259 | 245 | 99,356 | ./documents/ndtceda18/Emory/JaAl/Emory-Jablonski-Allums-Aff-Wake-Round3.docx | 602,951 | A | Wake | 3 | Navy BR | Victoria Yonter | 1ac auer
2nr extra t | ndtceda18/Emory/JaAl/Emory-Jablonski-Allums-Aff-Wake-Round3.docx | null | 51,289 | JaAl | Emory JaAl | null | Be..... | Ja..... | Ka..... | Al..... | 19,176 | Emory | Emory | null | null | 1,008 | ndtceda18 | NDT/CEDA 2018-19 | 2,018 | cx | college | 2 |
3,051,255 | NPT breakdown triggers a widespread nuclear cascade and makes prolif fast | Coe and Vaynman 15 (Andrew J. Coe, Assistant Professor at the School of International Relations of the University of Southern California (USC) and an adjunct member of the research staff of the Institute for Defense Analyses, and Jane Vaynman, Associate Director of the Institute for Security and Conflict Studies and Research Instructor at the Elliott School of International Affairs, Ph.D. in Government from Harvard University, co-founder of the Nuclear Studies Research Initiative, Stanton Nuclear Security Fellow at the Council on Foreign Relations, held positions with the Bureau of Arms Control, Verification, and Compliance at the U.S. Department of State and at the Carnegie Endowment for International Peace, B.A. in International Relations from Stanford University with honors in security studies from the Center for International Security and Cooperation, University of Chicago Press on behalf of the Southern Political Science Association Volume 77 Number 4, October 2015. “Collusion and the Nuclear Nonproliferation Regime.” http://www.jstor.org/stable/pdf/10.1086/682080.pdf?acceptTC=true) | Coe and Vaynman 15 (Andrew J. Coe, Assistant Professor at the School of International Relations of the University of Southern California (USC) and an adjunct member of the research staff of the Institute for Defense Analyses, and Jane Vaynman, Associate Director of the Institute for Security and Conflict Studies and Research Instructor at the Elliott School of International Affairs, Ph.D. in Government from Harvard University, co-founder of the Nuclear Studies Research Initiative, Stanton Nuclear Security Fellow at the Council on Foreign Relations, held positions with the Bureau of Arms Control, Verification, and Compliance at the U.S. Department of State and at the Carnegie Endowment for International Peace, B.A. in International Relations from Stanford University with honors in security studies from the Center for International Security and Cooperation, University of Chicago Press on behalf of the Southern Political Science Association Volume 77 Number 4, October 2015. “Collusion and the Nuclear Nonproliferation Regime.” http://www.jstor.org/stable/pdf/10.1086/682080.pdf?acceptTC=true) | the breakdown if any state gets nuclear weapons and the superpowers will not collude to prevent any other state from following then all states that do not have nuclear weapons will seek them immediately In effect, if proliferation gets started and is not stopped then it will snowball This nuclear domino theory is widely believed and there is now substantial evidence for it We look for a perfect Bayesian equilibrium in which no state seeks nuclear weapons If this equilibrium exists, it is enforced by superpower collusion to stop the spoilers each state is deterred from seeking nuclear weapons in one of two ways First states are deterred by the fact that their acquisition would lead to the breakdown of the nonproliferation regime leading other states to seek weapons For these states, the resultant widespread proliferation would be worse than abiding by the nonproliferation regime other states—the spoilers—have the opposite preference These states would actually prefer seeking nuclear weapons, even if all other states followed, to complying with the nonproliferation regime along with the other states the spoilers cannot be deterred from seeking weapons by the threat of the regime’s subsequent breakdown, since they actually prefer this outcome. Instead they are deterred by the prospect that, if they seek nuclear weapons and are detected, the superpowers will collude to stop them, so that the resources invested in a nuclear program will be lost Thus, this condition specifies that, for any spoiler, the expected cost of cheating on the regime outweighs the expected benefit. These spoilers are not just a theoretical possibility In a world without superpower enforcement of nonproliferation it is easy to imagine other spoilers In the absence of superpower enforcement, the spoiler states would seek nuclear weapons, and in response, other states would pursue nuclear weapons, and yet more states would acquire weapons in response to these, so that proliferation would eventually be widespread To make the regime—and the underlying grand bargain among the nonspoilers—viable, the spoilers must be coerced into nonproliferation, so that it is safe for the nonspoilers to abide by their bargain We use the following result to make explicit how the regime’s viability is affected by the parameters of our model The NPT decreases the willingness of spoilers to cheat and This lowers the super powers’ perceived costs of enforcing the regime (by decreasing FS1 F), because it enables the superpowers to confirm that only a few holdouts will have to be strong-armed into nonproliferation the NPT served as a device to coordinate all states on the nonproliferation equilibrium, rather than the widespread proliferation that otherwise result By leading nonspoilers to expect nonproliferation to be upheld, it encouraged them to abide by it and contribute to the superpowers’ efforts to enforce the regime, lowering the costs of enforcement Our theory of the nonproliferation regime offers observable implications EMPIRICAL TESTS We turn now to testing these observable implications of our theory. Hymans argues that the fundamental question for students of proliferation is why so few of the nuclear-capable states ended up acquiring nuclear weapons Our answer is that once superpowers realized nonproliferation was necessary to preserve their influence and set about colluding to enforce it many states chose not to realize their latent nuclear capacity most preferred nonproliferation to widespread proliferation and were confident enough that the superpowers would be able to curtail proliferation to voluntarily forgo weapons for themselves Moreover, we presented evidence, consistent with this answer that superpowers explicitly colluded to create the nonproliferation regime cajole worrisome states into joining and complying Within this regime, the NPT serves to ease detection of cheating by either these states or the superpowers, to identify potential spoilers, and finally to coordinate states’ expectations on widespread nonproliferation This strongly suggests that the nonproliferation regime substantially reduced proliferation relative to what would occur in its absence in The absence of the regime is an equilibrium in which states expect spoilers to get nuclear weapons and others to follow eventually resulting in widespread proliferation so that many non–spoiler states are unwilling to eschew nuclear weapons, which in turn makes the superpowers unwilling to stop them To conclude that the regime did not substantially reduce proliferation, one of two claims would have to be true: first, that breakdown would not occur in the absence of the regime: the numerous states that were initially—or might in response become—interested in nuclear weapons would prefer to abstain, even knowing that they would not be stopped and that proliferation would eventually be widespread; or, second, that in the absence of the NPT to coordinate states on nonproliferation, the superpowers would be able and willing to stop proliferation, even given that many states were seeking nuclear weapons and would thus have to be coerced. history of states’ nuclear decision making and of the superpowers’ attitudes toward proliferation presented here shows that neither claim is plausible Hymans and Solingen argue that the regime only appears successful because it prohibits things that few states want Our theory yields different interpretation of these findings that is consistent with the regime substantially reducing proliferation overall Hymans and Solingen depends on the belief that most other states are not seeking them and in other cases on the belief that pursuing weapons would bring international pressure—both beliefs that only exist because of the regime the regime makes a subsequent breakdown into widespread proliferation less likely inally, though Hymans (2012) is surely right that incompetence played an important role in the long timelines of later nuclear programs, the regime’s prevention of a broad market in nuclear weapons likely also contributed | if any state gets nuclear weapons then all states will seek them immediately proliferation will snowball This nuclear domino theory is widely believed and there is substantial ev for it In the absence of enforcement, spoiler states would seek nuclear weapons, and prolif would be widespread The NPT decreases the willingness of spoilers to cheat and lead nonspoilers to abide by the regime states were confident that superpowers would curtail prolif to voluntarily forgo weapons This strongly suggests that the regime substantially reduced prolif relative to what would occur in its absence in The absence of the regime | All players discount the future by d > 0, and all payoffs are common knowledge. Let St N be the set of states that have nuclear weapons at the end of period t. The per-period payoff of each state j∈S is vj(St N). We assume that, for any j ∈S, T ⊂S, and k ≠ j, vj(T) ≥ vj(T ∪ fkg): for any given state, the spread of nuclear weapons to other states is (weakly) bad. We also make the following “breakdown” assumption: if any state gets nuclear weapons, and the superpowers will not collude to prevent any other state from following, then all states that do not have nuclear weapons will seek them immediately, and SN p S will be the unique equilibrium outcome. In effect, if proliferation gets started and is not stopped, then it will snowball.6 This nuclear domino theory was, and is, widely believed, at least among US policy makers, and there is now substantial evidence for it (Miller 2014a). The per-period payoffs of the superpowers are vUS p p(St N) 1 a i(St N) 2 lUS(St N) and vSU p 2p(St N) 1 a½ 2i(St N) 2 lSU(St N). These represent the two different effects that proliferation can have on the superpowers’ interests, termed inter-alliance effects and intra-alliance effects, with the relative importance of the latter given by a. First, proliferation may alter the balance of power between the superpowers’ alliances, represented by p(·). Because nuclear-armed clients would be stronger, the spread of weapons to a superpower’s clients might strengthen its side relative to the other superpower’s. The change in sign of p(·) between the superpowers reflects the fact that what strengthens one side’s relative power must weaken the other’s. We assume that, for any T ⊂S and j ∉ T, p(T ∪ fjg) ≥ p(T) if j∈SUS, and p(T ∪fjg) ≤ p(T) if j ∈SSU. In other words, the spread of nuclear weapons to one superpower’s ally (weakly) shifts the inter-alliance balance of power in that superpower’s favor.7 The second effect of proliferation is to alter the balance of power within each superpower’s alliance, represented by the bracketed terms in the superpowers’ payoffs. A client that got nuclear weapons would no longer need to rely so heavily on its superpower patron, as its nuclear arms would partially substitute for a patron’s protection. Thus, a nucleararmed client might be more assertive of its interests within the alliance or seek more autonomy from it. On the one hand, the patron’s loss of influence over a newly nucleararmed client would be good for the other superpower, who would face a less cohesive opposing alliance and possibly find common interests with the erstwhile client. This is represented by i(·), which can be thought of as the total US influence over all states with respect to issues where US and Soviet interests are directly opposed. The sign of i(·) changes between the superpowers because one’s loss of influence on such issues must be the other’s gain. We assume that, for any T ⊂S and j ∉ T, i(T ∪ fjg) ≤ i(T) if j ∈ SUS, and i(T ∪ fjg) ≥ i(T) if j ∈ SSU. That is, the spread of nuclear weapons to one superpower’s ally is (weakly) bad for that superpower and (weakly) good for the other, as the ally may now act less consistently with the interests of its patron superpower and more consistently with those of the other superpower.8 On the other hand, the patron’s loss of influence is not fully recouped by the other superpower, because newly nuclear-armed states achieve greater autonomy from both superpowers and so may pursue interests that neither superpower supports. Proliferation can thus shift influence, not just from one superpower to the other but from the superpowers to the other states. This is represented by the functions lUS(·) and lSU(·), which can be thought of as each superpower’s loss of influence over nuclear-armed states on issues where the superpowers’ interests are not opposed. For any T ⊂ S and j ∉ T, lUS(T∪fjg) ≥ lUS(T) and lSU(T∪fjg) ≥ lSU(T), so that these losses (weakly) grow as nuclear weapons spread. Power and influence, as we use the terms here, should be construed quite broadly. A state’s acquisition of nuclear weapons can affect a superpower’s interests in many ways: deterring the superpower from using military force against that state; reducing its ability to coerce that state; triggering regional instability that might entrap the superpower or require its mediation; undermining the superpower’s alliance structure by reducing the value of or need for its security guarantees; and absorbing strategic attention that a superpower might otherwise devote to other states; all in addition to the possibility of generating further proliferation (Kroenig 2009, 2010, 2014). Each of these can be understood in terms of p(·), i(·), and l· (·). As examples, the risk of entrapment increases l· , while the reduced ability to coerce a nuclear-armed Soviet client may decrease p (the Soviet alliance is more powerful) but increase i (the freed client may drift toward the United States). For convenience, we normalize p(∅), i(∅), lUS(∅), and lSU(∅) to zero. We also assume that p(S) pi(S) p 0 and lUS(S) plSU(S) p l(S): if proliferation goes from zero to universal, the many resulting gains and losses in power and competitive influence for each superpower will cancel out, and each will suffer the same total loss of noncompetitive influence. Finally, we assume that, for any T ⊂ S, (1 1 d) ∣i(T)∣ ≤ (d2 =1 2 d)l(S). That is, any momentary shift in influence between the superpowers due to some states getting nuclear weapons is no larger than the loss of influence that would result from permanent universal proliferation. Collusion and nonproliferation We look for a perfect Bayesian equilibrium in which no state seeks nuclear weapons.9 We require that no individual state have an incentive to deviate from nonproliferation, as is standard, but additionally that no coalition of states drawn from S and either superpower have an incentive to deviate together. A regime that managed to keep individual states in line but that could not prevent a concerted breakout by a group of “spoilers,” possibly aided by a superpower, would not last long. Let S1 be composed of every state j ∈ S such that vj(j) 1 d jvj(S) 1 (1 2 j)vj(j) 1 d2 1 2 d vj(S) ≥ 1 1 2 d vj(∅). As we will explain,10 S1 is the set of potential spoilers. Proposition 1. There is a universal nonproliferation equilibrium if and only if, for all j∈S1 , T ⊂S1 , and a∈ fUS, SUg: jd ≥ (1 2 j) (1 1 d)vj(j) 1 d2 1 2 d vj(S) 2 1 1 2 d vj(∅); (1) 1 1 2 d va(∅) 2 ∣T ∣c ≥ va(T) 1 d(1 2 t) ∣T∣ va(T) 1 d 1 2 (1 2 t) ∣T ∣ ½ va(S) 1 d2 1 2 d va(S). ð2Þ If this equilibrium exists, it is enforced by superpower collusion to stop the spoilers. Under this equilibrium, each state is deterred from seeking nuclear weapons in one of two ways. First, most states are deterred by the fact that their acquisition of nuclear arms would lead to the breakdown of the nonproliferation regime, leading other states to seek weapons. For these states, the resultant widespread proliferation would be worse than abiding by the nonproliferation regime, even if it meant giving up the chance to be the first, and temporarily the only, state to acquire nuclear weapons. However, other states—the spoilers—have the opposite preference. These states would actually prefer seeking nuclear weapons, even if all other states followed, to complying with the nonproliferation regime along with the other states. This preference is formalized in the condition defining S1 . The right side is the value of abiding by the regime, while the left side is the value of cheating on it: the spoiler enjoys sole possession of nuclear weapons temporarily, but eventually all other states get nuclear weapons as well. Obviously, the spoilers cannot be deterred from seeking weapons by the threat of the regime’s subsequent breakdown, since they actually prefer this outcome. Instead they are deterred by the prospect that, if they seek nuclear weapons and are detected, the superpowers will collude to stop them, so that the resources invested in a nuclear program will be lost. In condition (1) above, the left side is the expected cost of pursuing nuclear weapons (sacrificing the investment d if caught and stopped), while the right side is the expected benefit of going undetected and getting nuclear weapons, over and above the value received from abiding by the regime. Thus, this condition specifies that, for any spoiler, the expected cost of cheating on the regime outweighs the expected benefit. These spoilers are not just a theoretical possibility. India sought nuclear weapons despite surely knowing that Pakistan would follow and preferring that it not; it is hard to believe that North Korea would have been deterred from pursuing nuclear weapons if it thought that South Korea, or any other country, would get them in response. In a counterfactual world without superpower enforcement of nonproliferation, it is easy to imagine other spoilers. For instance, WestGermany, which had to contend with the massive conventional forces of theWarsaw Pact and the uncertain reliability of its US security guarantee, might have resorted to nuclear arms in spite of the likelihood that other European states would follow. For their part, the superpowers enforce nonproliferation because the cost of doing so is outweighed by the losses they will suffer from proliferation if they shirk. For each possible set of spoilers, and each superpower, condition (2) above requires that the superpower’s value of enforcing the regime at least equal its value of shirking, wherein the superpower allows the set of spoilers to get nuclear weapons but soon faces proliferation by the other states.11 This result synthesizes the grand bargain and cartel views of the nonproliferation regime and also exposes the flaws of each view when considered on its own. The grand bargain envisions a set of states that agree to eschew nuclear weapons so long as other states also do so. And, indeed, this is an apt description of the way the equilibrium looks from the point of view of the nonspoiler states. These states prefer nonproliferation to widespread proliferation, are willing to give up weapons themselves to support the former, and will renege only if other states cheat on the bargain. These states abide by the regime voluntarily rather than being coerced into compliance by the superpowers. However, this in itself is not enough to make the regime viable. In the absence of superpower enforcement, the spoiler states would seek nuclear weapons, and in response, other states would pursue nuclear weapons, and yet more states would acquire weapons in response to these, so that proliferation would eventually be widespread.12 The grand bargain is thus not robust to spoilers. To make the regime—and the underlying grand bargain among the nonspoilers—viable, the spoilers must be coerced into nonproliferation, so that it is safe for the nonspoilers to abide by their bargain. From the spoilers’ point of view, then, the nonproliferation equilibrium looks much more like the cartel: the superpowers collude to strong-arm these states into the regime. The flaw in the cartel view is that because this enforcement is expensive for the superpowers, it is only worth doing if, by coercing just a few states, the superpowers can make nonproliferation among a much wider set of states possible. Thus, the superpowers are willing to form a cartel only because many states do not need to be strongarmed into nonproliferation at all. In short, the cartel is needed to render the grand bargain robust to spoilers, and the grand bargain is needed to make the cartel affordable. The origins and roles of the NPT We first discuss the origins of the NPT in a shift in the superpowers’ perceptions of the effects of proliferation. We then explain how the NPT itself affects the underlying parameters that govern the viability of the nonproliferation regime. This in turn leads to the observable implications of our theory that are tested in the subsequent section. We use the following result to make explicit how the regime’s viability is affected by the parameters of our model. Proposition 2. The nonproliferation equilibrium only exists if a, j are high enough and c is low enough, and it is more likely to exist if t is higher and FS1 F is lower. Recall that a governs the importance of the intra-alliance effects (a superpower loses influence over a nuclear-armed client) relative to the inter-alliance effects (a superpower’s side gets stronger with nuclear-armed clients) of proliferation. In the limiting case where a p 0, there are no intra alliance effects and proliferation simply increases one side’s power and decreases the other’s by the same amount, so that proliferation is zero-sum. Then, for any set of states that get nuclear weapons, one superpower will be left at least equally well off by this proliferation. This superpower will be unwilling to pay the costs of enforcing nonproliferation against these states, and anticipating this, the other superpower will not try either, since enforcement would fail without the first superpower’s help. So, if proliferation is zero-sum, neither superpower will ever enforce nonproliferation in equilibrium. As a rises from zero, proliferation has increasingly strong intra-alliance effects. Because one superpower’s loss of influence over a nuclear-armed client is not fully recouped by the other, proliferation becomes increasingly negative-sum. Now, if nuclear weapons spread far enough, both superpowers could be left worse off because of their net loss of influence. Once a is high enough, the anticipated joint loss of influence from proliferation will outweigh the costs of stopping it and the superpowers will become willing to institute a nonproliferation regime. Essentially, a controls the size of the net benefits to the superpowers from nonproliferation. The superpowers’ perceived value of a changed over the course of the early Cold War, explaining why the regime was not instantiated until the late 1960s. In principle, the superpowers could have pushed the NPT forward as early as the 1950s, once both had nuclear weapons and established alliances and thus something potentially to lose from further proliferation. However, until well into the 1960s, each superpower instead saw substantial advantages to be gained from selective proliferation to certain of their clients. The United States perceived nuclear cooperation and weapons-sharing with its European allies to be a valuable counter to the USSR’s superior conventional forces, and these initiatives were prioritized over nonproliferation. As late as the mid-1960s, the US interest in sharing weapons with West Germany in the form of the multi-lateral force (MLF), adamantly opposed by the Soviets, was an important obstacle to creating the regime (Brands 2007). High-level US officials also privately advocated the consideration of giving weapons to India and Japan, reasoning that this would help to balance the threat from nuclear-armed China.13 For its part, the USSR greatly facilitated China’s development of the bomb in the 1950s, providing expertise and materials and even building a model weapon intended for China to copy (Timerbaev 1999). In short, both superpowers focused on the inter-alliance effects as opposed to the intra-alliance effects of proliferation, suggesting that they perceived the importance of the latter (i.e., a) to be low. The experience of dealing with newly nuclear—and newly obstreperous—allies led the superpowers to reassess the intraalliance effects of proliferation, raising their perceived value of a. The estrangement of China from the USSR allowed the United States to play one against the other, while the ructions France generated in NATO were surely to the USSR’s liking. However, after ending its alliance with the USSR, China proselytized for a more radical version of communist ideology that neither superpower favored, while France sought to preserve control over its remaining colonies against both superpowers’ desires for colonial independence. In the United States, elites increasingly recognized that nonproliferation was needed to limit the superpowers’ joint loss of influence. High-level deliberations after China’s nuclear test led to the United States dropping its support for the MLF in favor of establishing a nonproliferation regime (Brands 2007). A similar evolution of views took place in the Soviet Union (Potter 1985). With both superpowers weighing the intraalliance effects of proliferation more heavily, both became more willing to pay the costs of enforcement under a nonproliferation regime, and so the NPT was agreed. Thus, the increase in a explains the origins of the NPT. The NPT contributes to the viability of the incipient nonproliferation regime in four ways. First, the inspections that nonnuclear signatories are required to accept increase the chance that a covert nuclear weapons program will be detected and subsequently stopped (raising j). This decreases the willingness of spoilers to try to cheat under the regime and thus also renders enforcement cheaper for the superpowers. Second, the same inspections also make it easier to catch a superpower surreptitiously helping a state with its program or simply allowing it to proceed (increasing t). This increases the willingness of each superpower to enforce nonproliferation, secure in the knowledge that the other superpower is doing its part and thus that their efforts will be effective, and it decreases the temptation to enable favored states to get nuclear weapons. Third, the willingness of non–nuclear states to sign the NPT, and thus voluntarily subject themselves to better monitoring, reveals that most states are not spoilers.14 This lowers the super powers’ perceived costs of enforcing the regime (by decreasing FS1 F), because it enables the superpowers to confirm that only a few holdouts will have to be strong-armed into nonproliferation. And, finally, the NPT served as a device to coordinate all states on the nonproliferation equilibrium, rather than the widespread proliferation that might otherwise result. By leading nonspoilers to expect nonproliferation to be upheld, it encouraged them to abide by it and contribute to the superpowers’ efforts to enforce the regime, lowering the costs of enforcement (c). Our theory of the nonproliferation regime, and the origins and roles of the NPT within it, offers at least three observable implications. First, our model assumes that collusion between the superpowers is central to the regime’s establishment and enforcement, so the first implication is that this collusion should have taken place during negotiations over the regime and in reactions to states’ noncompliance with the regime. H1. The superpowers will collude with one another on nonproliferation concerns and press one another to comply with their side of the collusion terms. Second, the theory implies that the superpowers should pressure the other states into joining the NPT. If a state refused to join, it would increase the difficulty of catching it pursuing nuclear weapons covertly, undermine the willingness of other states to join and comply with the treaty, and thereby increase the superpowers’ costs of enforcing the regime. Since each superpower ought to have more leverage over its own clients than other states, we expect that each would be held responsible for policing its own clients, while the other superpower would be expected not to interfere in or obstruct this policing. We also expect the superpowers to apply this pressure only when it is actually perceived as necessary to induce a state to join the NPT and only when it is perceived to have some chance of success. H2. Each superpower will pressure other states, especially its own clients, to join the NPT, focusing its efforts on cases where pressures are likely to be both necessary and effective, and neither superpower will undermine the other’s efforts. Third, the superpowers should collude to stop any state that is revealed to be (potentially) pursuing nuclear weapons, as doing otherwise could lead to the breakdown of the regime. Here again, we expect that each superpower would be most involved in the policing of its own clients, while the other superpower would be expected not to aid the erstwhile client. H3. Each superpower will apply pressure to prevent other states, especially its own clients, from moving toward acquiring nuclear weapons. Neither superpower will offer assistance to a state suspected to be pursuing a nuclear weapons program. EMPIRICAL TESTS We turn now to testing these observable implications of our theory. Looking at archival and secondary sources, we evaluate the history of nonproliferation-related interactions between the superpowers, superpower responses to those states that hesitated to join the NPT, and, finally, superpower responses to suspicions of nuclear weapons programs in various states. We also demonstrate that neither the grand bargain nor the cartel theory can account for the evidence on its own. Extensive documentation of our sources, the set of cases we employ, and our coding of data are available in the appendix. Hypothesis 1: Superpowers collude over nonproliferation While we do not expect collusion to be explicit in all cases, a total absence of observable collusion would call our theory into question. We examined declassified documentation of private meetings between the superpowers to assess whether collusion occurred, focusing on episodes particularly relevant to nonproliferation, that is, the NPT negotiations and instances when states came under suspicion of pursuing nuclear weapons. We found ample evidence that when the superpowers discussed proliferation issues, they did so in collusive terms. The United States and the Soviet Union had numerous disputes in negotiating the NPT, and the process was at times seriously stalled due to their disagreements (Brands 2007). However, when it came to dealing with other states, their discussions became remarkably cooperative. First, the superpowers sought to coordinate their mutual efforts to corral states into the treaty. In joint meetings in 1967 and 1968, high-level US and Soviet officials discussed concerns over which states would join and measures the superpowers were taking to promote signature of the treaty. They reported on prospects for signature among their respective allies, Japan and Latin American countries, in the case of the United States, and Romania and some African countries, in the case of the Soviet Union. After the NPT was opened for signature, senior US and Soviet officials exchanged explicit assessments of whether Japan, Brazil, Argentina, and India would sign, and they expressed hopes that the other superpower would use its leverage to cajole the holdouts.15 The United States and the USSR also worked together to control the process of the treaty negotiations; drafts of the treaty were prepared privately by the superpowers before being presented to other states (Swango 2014). Finally, the superpowers often presented a united front to the rest of the international community, and this evidence of their collusion was noticed by other states. For example, Soviet and US delegations regularly coordinated their strategies on nonproliferation discussions at the UN General Assembly (Quester 1981, 228). While the superpowers attempted to keep their cooperation private, numerous states, including US and Soviet allies, decried the treaty’s discriminatory nature, referring not to the official discrimination between nuclear haves and have-nots but to the US-Soviet hegemony they saw the regime as entrenching. We also found instances of explicit US-Soviet collusion in responding to suspicious nuclear activity by another state. In surveying cases where a state was suspected of pursuing a nuclear weapons program, we find that such states were most often pressured by their patron superpower, without comment or interference by the other superpower. In this respect, collusion is implicit in the other superpower’s acquiescence to the patron’s pressure. However, there are at least two cases—North Korea and South Africa—where collusion was explicit in requests from one superpower to the other to police the state in question. In the mid-1980s, US satellites detected the construction of a nuclear reactor at Yongbyon. US officials approached the Soviet Union, highlighting its obligations under the NPT and calling into question its provision of nuclear technology assistance to North Korea. The USSR responded positively, and during the next visit to Moscow of North Korean KWP Secretary Kang Song San, the USSR pushed for North Korea to sign the NPT, offering to provide new nuclear energy reactors if it did (Mazarr 1995, 40–41). The episode shows the United States pressing the USSR to act on the obligation implicit in the superpowers’ collusion and the USSR willing to comply and even offer incentives. It suggests that the DPRK proliferation issue was not one of opposition between the two superpowers but rather cooperation. We observe a similar incident in the case of South Africa but with the roles reversed. In July 1977, a Soviet reconnaissance satellite detected a site for a possible South African nuclear test. The USSR passed the information to the United States, with a personal request from Secretary Brezhnev to President Carter for assistance in stopping the test (Richelson 2007, 278). Several days later Carter replied to Brezhnev that the US assessment was in agreement. Collusion in pressuring South Africa continued during the following months, and declassified memos refer to ongoing “quiet cooperation” on the issue.16 This cooperation was kept private. Publicly, Soviet newspapers alleged that the United States was helping South Africa with a nuclear program. However, declassified documents reveal a recognition on the United States’ side that the USSR was likely using the South Africa issue to divert attention from international criticism of the superpowers failing to curb the growth of their own arsenals.17 This connection between private and public approaches suggests that the superpowers had a considerable understanding of each others’ real interests in preventing proliferation. Our findings reinforce the conclusions of the most recent historiography of the NPT, which has documented the superpowers’ discussions of mutual interests in maintaining dominant positions within their alliances, their support for the NPT over allied opposition, and their attempts to control the drafting of the treaty itself (Brands 2006, 2007; Gavin 2004, 2010; Popp 2014; Swango 2014). Our points on the superpowers’ coordination of efforts to get treaty signatures and cooperation in dealing with suspected nuclear weapons programs in South Africa and North Korea contribute important new examples to the increasingly strong body of evidence on collusion between the superpowers over nonproliferation. Hypothesis 2: Superpowers pressure states to join the NPT The superpowers have a clear interest in other states joining the NPT, as this signals their commitment to eschew nuclear weapons and eases the monitoring of that commitment. Our theory also implies that the number of states the superpowers need to pressure to join should be relatively small; most states should join the treaty voluntarily. To evaluate this hypothesis, we assess how the superpowers acted toward those states they judged as technologically capable of, and potentially interested in, seeking nuclear weapons. Such states would pose the greatest threats to the nonproliferation regime, since states that lacked either capability or interest would be unlikely to acquire nuclear weapons even if they stayed out of the treaty. Because our theory posits that the superpowers are the main enforcers of nonproliferation, our selection of cases relies on the superpowers’ own contemporary assessments of which states were worrisome. We intentionally do not use present-day assessments of states’ historical nuclear interest and capability. Such assessments would pose an unfair test for the theory because the superpowers were, at the time, simply unaware of what would later be revealed about certain states’ nuclear programs and thus would not be predicted to do anything about these programs. For the United States’ side, we use a series of intelligence estimates from 1957 to 1974 that assess states’ technological capability for, and, after 1960, interest in, developing nuclear weapons. Unfortunately, the analogous documents are not available from the Soviet side. The documents we do have indicate that the United States saw the Eastern bloc states as under the tight control of the USSR, which would not allow them to develop nuclear weapons.18 From the Soviet side, certain Eastern European states were likely considered nuclear-capable, and the USSR would probably have added North Korea to the list, as the state had received Soviet nuclear assistance in the 1950s and 1960s (Szalontai and Radchenko 2006). We also use other declassified documents, containing superpower assessments of states’ positions on the NPT, to evaluate whether the superpowers were uncertain or suspicious of a given state’s intent toward nuclear weapons. As long as some doubt remains, we expect the superpowers to explicitly pressure the state to join the treaty. However, if a state expresses a resolute position against the treaty and it becomes apparent to the superpower that no feasible measures would alter its position, then it would be reasonable for the superpower to reassess whether any available pressure is worth exerting. Additionally, if a state delays joining the NPT but the superpowers are confident that this is driven by something other than an interest in nuclear weapons, then we do not expect the superpowers to apply pressure. We then assess superpower behavior toward each state. In some cases, the superpowers took no action; in others, their actions involved only informational meetings and diplomatic discussions with the state in question; and in still others, the superpowers resorted to stronger pressures, such as explicit threats or offers of benefits in exchange for joining the treaty. In the results presented in table 1, a coding of“yes” indicates that the observed superpower behavior is consistent with our theory’s expectations. A coding of “partial” means that the limited historical record is supportive for the theory, but additional information would be needed for a more confident assessment. A coding of “mixed” implies that we found mixed support for the theory: the superpowers pursued the expected action, but they did so either to a lesser extent or inconsistently. Finally, a “no” coding indicates evidence of superpower behavior opposed to our expectations, such as assisting a state in avoiding NPT signature or failing to pay attention to a possible nuclear state’s rejection of the NPT. To summarize, we see that a number of states assessed to be nuclear-capable did not join the NPT completely voluntarily. Rather, when voluntary participation did not appear forthcoming, these states were pressured, largely as expected though not always successfully, by the superpowers. By contrast, but also as expected, the superpowers paid little attention to clear joiners. We also observe some interesting changes in the level of pressure applied in cases where doubts regarding signature are introduced or dispelled. South Korea, for example, was an early supporter of the NPT, and there is initially little action by the United States to persuade it to sign the treaty. However, when South Korea was identified as having nuclear capabilities and delayed ratifying the treaty in the early 1970s, the United States applied pressure to encourage speedier ratification. In the case of Israel, pressure and incentives were attempted until it became clear to key negotiators that Israel had already developed a nuclear device, so that no available means of pressure would be effective. In no case did we find any evidence of one superpower undermining the other’s efforts to pressure a state into joining. Finally, we note that the evidence does not support either the grand bargain or the cartel theory alone. If the grand bargain theory were correct, then all states should be better off with the NPT and all should join voluntarily given that they expect others to do so. This was clearly not the case, and for a number of states, the superpowers had to go to considerable lengths to ensure their participation. Additionally, the fact that this pressure was at times ineffective suggests that some states had very strong incentives to stay out of the treaty, even as most others joined. If, instead, the cartel view is correct, then all states would have to be pressured to join the treaty and all would do so with a desire to cheat. However, the evidence shows that numerous nuclear-capable states, even those that had previously considered weapons programs, joined the regime with little or no pressure from the superpowers. Hypothesis 3: Superpowers pressure states not to proliferate As in the previous hypothesis, if a state is suspected of making a move toward nuclear weapons, its patron superpower ought to have the most leverage over it, and so we expect its patron to be the one to apply pressure while the other superpower refrains from assisting the aspirant. With nonaligned states, we expect that either or both superpowers would apply pressure and neither should assist the errant state in any way. To test this, we considered all cases where a state became suspected of pursuing a nuclear weapons program, and we evaluated the superpowers’ response. Our findings are presented in table 2. In each case, we assess what the superpowers perceived about a state’s activity and how they responded. A coding of “yes” indicates that the superpower acted as our theory predicts, taking steps to restrain a client’s progress toward nuclear weapons or its access to dual-use nuclear technology needed to make progress in the future. As before, a coding of “mixed” means that the superpowers sought to restrain the proliferant but that it did so either to a lesser extent or inconsistently. “Partial” implies that the limited historical record is supportive for the theory but that additional information would be needed to reach a confident assessment. Finally, a “no” coding indicates that the superpower did not behave as our theory predicts, instead aiding a client state with a nuclear weapons program or turning a blind eye to apparent attempts to proliferate. We find general support for hypothesis 3, with a few mixed cases. In the majority of cases, the superpower patron of each nuclear aspirant intervened with threats or incentives to prevent the nuclear program from progressing, so that the “policing” element of superpower relations with nuclear aspirants is clear. Examples of policing actions by the superpowers included direct instructions to stop the suspicious activity, threats to withdraw some military or economic support, restrictions on suppliers and access to technology, and highlevel diplomatic pressure. By contrast, we find no cases where the opposing superpower provided assistance, reassurance, or any support for the fledgling nuclear state. To investigate this point, we surveyed a wide range of primary and secondary sources for evidence that such assistance occurred, and we also looked for any accusations that might have been made by one superpower against the other for such a transgression. Although it is difficult to prove that neither superpower sought to lure away the opponent’s ally by offering nuclear support, we have not located any evidence of such behavior in all the cases surveyed. Neither the grand bargain nor the cartel theory fit this evidence. The nuclear weapons states were widely perceived as reneging on their end of the grand bargain. No significant disarmament on the part of any of the nuclear-weapons states occurred until the very end of the Cold War. Moreover, there is no evidence that NPT membership increased a state’s chance of receiving nuclear energy assistance (Fuhrmann 2009b). Despite this, hardly any of the non–nuclear weapons states cheated on the regime; those few that did were not motivated by the need to punish the nuclear-weapons states for not disarming, and these were stopped from getting nuclear weapons not by the prospect that others would follow but by the intervention of the superpowers. None of these three facts is consistent with the grand bargain theory. While the superpowers’ enforcement of nonproliferation is consistent with the cartel view, the small number of cases in which such enforcement was needed is not. Most states showed no interest in bucking the nonproliferation regime and abided by it voluntarily, without pressure from the superpowers. IMPLICATIONS We conclude by discussing the implications of our study for the broader literature on nuclear proliferation. Hymans (2010) argues that the fundamental question for students of proliferation is why so few of the nuclear-capable states ended up acquiring nuclear weapons: some six nuclearweapons states out of more than 40 estimated to be nuclearcapable by 1970. Our answer is that once the superpowers realized nonproliferation was necessary to preserve their influence and set about colluding to enforce it, many states chose not to realize their latent nuclear capacity. A few of these states refrained because they were deterred by the punishment the superpowers would impose if they were caught seeking nuclear weapons. But most did so because they preferred nonproliferation to widespread proliferation, and they were confident enough that the superpowers would be able to curtail proliferation to voluntarily forgo weapons for themselves. These latter states’ willing compliance with nonproliferation made the regime’s enforcement affordable for the superpowers. Moreover, we presented evidence, consistent with this answer, that the superpowers explicitly colluded to create the nonproliferation regime and to cajole the few worrisome states into joining and complying with it. Within this regime, the NPT serves to ease detection of cheating by either these states or the superpowers, to identify potential spoilers, and finally to coordinate states’ expectations on widespread nonproliferation. This strongly suggests that the nonproliferation regime, and the treaty that coordinated states onto behaving in accordance with it, substantially reduced proliferation, relative to what would have occurred in its absence. To explain this, we need to specify exactly what is meant by “the regime” and “its absence,” since the latter is the appropriate counterfactual for assessing the regime’s overall effect. In our theory, the regime is an equilibrium in which the superpowers are able and willing to enforce nonproliferation because of the voluntary compliance of non–spoiler states, whose support is driven by the expectation that others will either not seek weapons or be stopped from getting them. The absence of the regime is an equilibrium in which states expect spoilers to get nuclear weapons and others to follow, eventually resulting in widespread proliferation, so that many non–spoiler states are unwilling to eschew nuclear weapons, which in turn makes the superpowers unwilling to stop them. The NPT coordinates the movement of all states from the latter equilibrium to the former. To conclude that the regime did not substantially reduce proliferation, one of two claims would have to be true: first, that breakdown would not occur in the absence of the regime: the numerous states that were initially—or might in response become—interested in nuclear weapons would prefer to abstain, even knowing that they would not be stopped and that proliferation would eventually be widespread; or, second, that in the absence of the NPT to coordinate states on nonproliferation, the superpowers would be able and willing to stop proliferation, even given that many states were seeking nuclear weapons and would thus have to be coerced. The history of states’ nuclear decision making and of the superpowers’ attitudes toward proliferation presented here shows that neither claim is plausible. By contrast, the most recent previous research concludes that the regime has had little effect on proliferation (Sagan 2011). Although several studies find that NPT membership is associated with a reduced risk of seeking or getting nuclear weapons (Fuhrmann 2009a, 2012; Jo and Gartzke 2007; Kroenig 2010), some have suggested it may only be that NPT members are mostly those states that do not want nuclear weapons anyway, so that the treaty does not constrain states so much as screen them (Fuhrmann 2012; Jo and Gartzke 2007).19 Similarly, Hymans (2006) and Solingen (2007) argue that the regime only appears successful because it prohibits things that few states want. Fuhrmann (2009b, 2012) shows that NPT membership has little effect on the provision of peaceful nuclear assistance, and that, having received such assistance, NPT membership has little effect on a state’s subsequent pursuit of nuclear weapons. Jo and Gartzke (2007) find that the adoption of the NPT (measured by the proportion of states that are members) is not associated with a reduction in the initiation of weapons programs, and Kroenig (2010) finds that the establishment of the NPT does not itself affect the provision of sensitive nuclear assistance. Finally, Hymans (2012) argues that it is managerial incompetence due to domestic politics, rather than the nonproliferation regime, that explains why states seeking nuclear weapons after the regime’s creation have been less likely to succeed and have taken much longer to get them when they do. Our theory yields a different interpretation of these findings that is consistent with the regime substantially reducing proliferation overall. Even if NPT membership serves only to screen voluntary compliers, the wide joining of the NPT may still have a large effect by reinforcing the superpowers’ belief that enforcement will be affordable and thus that the regime is viable. States that comply may simply not want nuclear weapons, as Hymans (2006) and Solingen (2007) find, but this likely depends in many cases on the belief that most other states are not seeking them and in other cases on the belief that pursuing weapons would bring international pressure—both beliefs that only exist because of the regime. The fact that the receipt of peaceful nuclear assistance and its link to nuclear weapons programs are unaffected by whether a state is an NPT member, as Fuhrmann (2009b, 2012) shows, is also explicable within our framework. The existence of the regime makes peaceful nuclear assistance less dangerous, regardless of whether the recipient is an NPT member, because even if an occasional state receiving assistance ends up getting nuclear weapons, the regime makes a subsequent breakdown into widespread proliferation less likely. Similarly, the regime makes the rare provision of weapons-relevant nuclear assistance more tempting to some potential suppliers, who can be assured that any resulting proliferation will be isolated. So it is not surprising that the establishment of the regime is not associated with a reduction in such assistance, as Kroenig (2010) found. Finally, though Hymans (2012) is surely right that incompetence played an important role in the long timelines of later nuclear programs, the regime’s prevention of a broad market in nuclear weapons likely also contributed. We close with the hope that scholars of the politics of nuclear weapons will find this study helpful in developing new avenues for research and interpreting new findings. Our theory and evidence provide an overarching picture of the constellation of states’ interests in and expectations about nuclear weapons that gave rise to the nonproliferation regime. This theory is built upon, but also clarifies and integrates, previous research on particular elements of this constellation. It should thus form a solid foundation for further research, including theorizing about the evolution of the nonproliferation regime since the Cold War’s end, evaluating present-day fears about a “nuclear tipping point,” and explaining the occurrence of and responses to the challenges to the regime posed by North Korea, Iran, and others. | 44,596 | <h4>NPT breakdown triggers a <u>widespread</u><strong> nuclear cascade and makes prolif fast </h4><p>Coe and Vaynman 15 (Andrew J. Coe, Assistant Professor at the School of International Relations of the University of Southern California (USC) and an adjunct member of the research staff of the Institute for Defense Analyses, and Jane Vaynman, Associate Director of the Institute for Security and Conflict Studies and Research Instructor at the Elliott School of International Affairs, Ph.D. in Government from Harvard University, co-founder of the Nuclear Studies Research Initiative, Stanton Nuclear Security Fellow at the Council on Foreign Relations, held positions with the Bureau of Arms Control, Verification, and Compliance at the U.S. Department of State and at the Carnegie Endowment for International Peace, B.A. in International Relations from Stanford University with honors in security studies from the Center for International Security and Cooperation, University of Chicago Press on behalf of the Southern Political Science Association Volume 77 Number 4, October 2015. “Collusion and the Nuclear Nonproliferation Regime.” http://www.jstor.org/stable/pdf/10.1086/682080.pdf?acceptTC=true)</p><p></strong>All players discount the future by d > 0, and all payoffs are common knowledge. Let St N be the set of states that have nuclear weapons at the end of period t. The per-period payoff of each state j∈S is vj(St N). We assume that, for any j ∈S, T ⊂S, and k ≠ j, vj(T) ≥ vj(T ∪ fkg): for any given state, the spread of nuclear weapons to other states is (weakly) bad. We also make <u>the</u> following “<u><strong>breakdown</u></strong>” assumption: <u><mark>if <strong>any state gets nuclear weapons</u></strong></mark>, <u>and the superpowers will not collude to prevent any other state from following</u>, <u><mark>then</u></mark> <u><strong><mark>all states </mark>that do not have nuclear weapons <mark>will seek them immediately</u></strong></mark>, and SN p S will be the unique equilibrium outcome. <u>In effect, if <mark>proliferation</u> <u></mark>gets started and <strong>is not stopped</u></strong>, <u><strong>then it <mark>will snowball</u></strong></mark>.6 <u><mark>This <strong>nuclear domino theory</u></strong></mark> was, and <u><mark>is</u></mark>, <u><strong><mark>widely believed</u></strong></mark>, at least among US policy makers, <u><mark>and there is</u></mark> <u><strong>now <mark>substantial ev</mark>idence<mark> for it</u></strong></mark> (Miller 2014a). The per-period payoffs of the superpowers are vUS p p(St N) 1 a i(St N) 2 lUS(St N) and vSU p 2p(St N) 1 a½ 2i(St N) 2 lSU(St N). These represent the two different effects that proliferation can have on the superpowers’ interests, termed inter-alliance effects and intra-alliance effects, with the relative importance of the latter given by a. First, proliferation may alter the balance of power between the superpowers’ alliances, represented by p(·). Because nuclear-armed clients would be stronger, the spread of weapons to a superpower’s clients might strengthen its side relative to the other superpower’s. The change in sign of p(·) between the superpowers reflects the fact that what strengthens one side’s relative power must weaken the other’s. We assume that, for any T ⊂S and j ∉ T, p(T ∪ fjg) ≥ p(T) if j∈SUS, and p(T ∪fjg) ≤ p(T) if j ∈SSU. In other words, the spread of nuclear weapons to one superpower’s ally (weakly) shifts the inter-alliance balance of power in that superpower’s favor.7 The second effect of proliferation is to alter the balance of power within each superpower’s alliance, represented by the bracketed terms in the superpowers’ payoffs. A client that got nuclear weapons would no longer need to rely so heavily on its superpower patron, as its nuclear arms would partially substitute for a patron’s protection. Thus, a nucleararmed client might be more assertive of its interests within the alliance or seek more autonomy from it. On the one hand, the patron’s loss of influence over a newly nucleararmed client would be good for the other superpower, who would face a less cohesive opposing alliance and possibly find common interests with the erstwhile client. This is represented by i(·), which can be thought of as the total US influence over all states with respect to issues where US and Soviet interests are directly opposed. The sign of i(·) changes between the superpowers because one’s loss of influence on such issues must be the other’s gain. We assume that, for any T ⊂S and j ∉ T, i(T ∪ fjg) ≤ i(T) if j ∈ SUS, and i(T ∪ fjg) ≥ i(T) if j ∈ SSU. That is, the spread of nuclear weapons to one superpower’s ally is (weakly) bad for that superpower and (weakly) good for the other, as the ally may now act less consistently with the interests of its patron superpower and more consistently with those of the other superpower.8 On the other hand, the patron’s loss of influence is not fully recouped by the other superpower, because newly nuclear-armed states achieve greater autonomy from both superpowers and so may pursue interests that neither superpower supports. Proliferation can thus shift influence, not just from one superpower to the other but from the superpowers to the other states. This is represented by the functions lUS(·) and lSU(·), which can be thought of as each superpower’s loss of influence over nuclear-armed states on issues where the superpowers’ interests are not opposed. For any T ⊂ S and j ∉ T, lUS(T∪fjg) ≥ lUS(T) and lSU(T∪fjg) ≥ lSU(T), so that these losses (weakly) grow as nuclear weapons spread. Power and influence, as we use the terms here, should be construed quite broadly. A state’s acquisition of nuclear weapons can affect a superpower’s interests in many ways: deterring the superpower from using military force against that state; reducing its ability to coerce that state; triggering regional instability that might entrap the superpower or require its mediation; undermining the superpower’s alliance structure by reducing the value of or need for its security guarantees; and absorbing strategic attention that a superpower might otherwise devote to other states; all in addition to the possibility of generating further proliferation (Kroenig 2009, 2010, 2014). Each of these can be understood in terms of p(·), i(·), and l· (·). As examples, the risk of entrapment increases l· , while the reduced ability to coerce a nuclear-armed Soviet client may decrease p (the Soviet alliance is more powerful) but increase i (the freed client may drift toward the United States). For convenience, we normalize p(∅), i(∅), lUS(∅), and lSU(∅) to zero. We also assume that p(S) pi(S) p 0 and lUS(S) plSU(S) p l(S): if proliferation goes from zero to universal, the many resulting gains and losses in power and competitive influence for each superpower will cancel out, and each will suffer the same total loss of noncompetitive influence. Finally, we assume that, for any T ⊂ S, (1 1 d) ∣i(T)∣ ≤ (d2 =1 2 d)l(S). That is, any momentary shift in influence between the superpowers due to some states getting nuclear weapons is no larger than the loss of influence that would result from permanent universal proliferation. Collusion and nonproliferation <u>We look for a <strong>perfect Bayesian equilibrium</u></strong> <u>in which <strong>no state</strong> seeks nuclear weapons</u>.9 We require that no individual state have an incentive to deviate from nonproliferation, as is standard, but additionally that no coalition of states drawn from S and either superpower have an incentive to deviate together. A regime that managed to keep individual states in line but that could not prevent a concerted breakout by a group of “spoilers,” possibly aided by a superpower, would not last long. Let S1 be composed of every state j ∈ S such that vj(j) 1 d jvj(S) 1 (1 2 j)vj(j) 1 d2 1 2 d vj(S) ≥ 1 1 2 d vj(∅). As we will explain,10 S1 is the set of potential spoilers. Proposition 1. There is a universal nonproliferation equilibrium if and only if, for all j∈S1 , T ⊂S1 , and a∈ fUS, SUg: jd ≥ (1 2 j) (1 1 d)vj(j) 1 d2 1 2 d vj(S) 2 1 1 2 d vj(∅); (1) 1 1 2 d va(∅) 2 ∣T ∣c ≥ va(T) 1 d(1 2 t) ∣T∣ va(T) 1 d 1 2 (1 2 t) ∣T ∣ ½ va(S) 1 d2 1 2 d va(S). ð2Þ <u>If this equilibrium <strong>exists</strong>, it is <strong>enforced by superpower</strong> collusion to stop the spoilers</u>. Under this equilibrium, <u><strong>each state</u></strong> <u>is deterred from seeking nuclear weapons in <strong>one of two ways</u></strong>. <u>First</u>, most <u><strong>states</u></strong> <u>are deterred by the fact that their acquisition</u> of nuclear arms <u>would lead to the</u> <u><strong>breakdown of the nonproliferation regime</u></strong>, <u>leading other states to seek weapons</u>. <u>For these states, the resultant widespread proliferation would be worse than abiding by the nonproliferation regime</u>, even if it meant giving up the chance to be the first, and temporarily the only, state to acquire nuclear weapons. However, <u><strong>other states—the spoilers—have the opposite preference</u></strong>. <u>These states would actually prefer seeking nuclear weapons, even if all other states followed, to complying with the nonproliferation regime along with the other states</u>. This preference is formalized in the condition defining S1 . The right side is the value of abiding by the regime, while the left side is the value of cheating on it: the spoiler enjoys sole possession of nuclear weapons temporarily, but eventually all other states get nuclear weapons as well. Obviously, <u>the spoilers cannot be deterred from seeking weapons by the threat of the regime’s subsequent breakdown, since they actually prefer this outcome. <strong>Instead</strong> they are deterred by the prospect that, if they seek nuclear weapons and are detected, the superpowers will collude to stop them, so that the resources invested in a nuclear program will be lost</u>. In condition (1) above, the left side is the expected cost of pursuing nuclear weapons (sacrificing the investment d if caught and stopped), while the right side is the expected benefit of going undetected and getting nuclear weapons, over and above the value received from abiding by the regime. <u>Thus, this condition specifies that, for any spoiler, the expected cost of cheating on the regime outweighs the expected benefit. These spoilers are not just a theoretical possibility</u>. India sought nuclear weapons despite surely knowing that Pakistan would follow and preferring that it not; it is hard to believe that North Korea would have been deterred from pursuing nuclear weapons if it thought that South Korea, or any other country, would get them in response. <u>In a</u> counterfactual <u>world</u> <u><strong>without superpower enforcement of nonproliferation</u></strong>, <u>it is <strong>easy to imagine other spoilers</u></strong>. For instance, WestGermany, which had to contend with the massive conventional forces of theWarsaw Pact and the uncertain reliability of its US security guarantee, might have resorted to nuclear arms in spite of the likelihood that other European states would follow. For their part, the superpowers enforce nonproliferation because the cost of doing so is outweighed by the losses they will suffer from proliferation if they shirk. For each possible set of spoilers, and each superpower, condition (2) above requires that the superpower’s value of enforcing the regime at least equal its value of shirking, wherein the superpower allows the set of spoilers to get nuclear weapons but soon faces proliferation by the other states.11 This result synthesizes the grand bargain and cartel views of the nonproliferation regime and also exposes the flaws of each view when considered on its own. The grand bargain envisions a set of states that agree to eschew nuclear weapons so long as other states also do so. And, indeed, this is an apt description of the way the equilibrium looks from the point of view of the nonspoiler states. These states prefer nonproliferation to widespread proliferation, are willing to give up weapons themselves to support the former, and will renege only if other states cheat on the bargain. These states abide by the regime voluntarily rather than being coerced into compliance by the superpowers. However, this in itself is not enough to make the regime viable. <u><mark>In the <strong>absence of </mark>superpower <mark>enforcement</strong>,</mark> the <strong><mark>spoiler states</strong> would seek nuclear weapons, and</mark> in response, other states would pursue nuclear weapons, and <strong>yet more states</strong> would acquire weapons in response to these, so that <strong><mark>prolif</mark>eration</strong><mark> would </mark>eventually <mark>be</mark> <strong><mark>widespread</u></strong></mark>.12 The grand bargain is thus not robust to spoilers. <u>To make the regime—and the underlying grand bargain among the nonspoilers—viable, the spoilers must be coerced into nonproliferation, so that it is safe for the nonspoilers to abide by their bargain</u>. From the spoilers’ point of view, then, the nonproliferation equilibrium looks much more like the cartel: the superpowers collude to strong-arm these states into the regime. The flaw in the cartel view is that because this enforcement is expensive for the superpowers, it is only worth doing if, by coercing just a few states, the superpowers can make nonproliferation among a much wider set of states possible. Thus, the superpowers are willing to form a cartel only because many states do not need to be strongarmed into nonproliferation at all. In short, the cartel is needed to render the grand bargain robust to spoilers, and the grand bargain is needed to make the cartel affordable. The origins and roles of the NPT We first discuss the origins of the NPT in a shift in the superpowers’ perceptions of the effects of proliferation. We then explain how the NPT itself affects the underlying parameters that govern the viability of the nonproliferation regime. This in turn leads to the observable implications of our theory that are tested in the subsequent section. <u>We use the following result to make explicit how the regime’s viability is affected by the parameters of our model</u>. Proposition 2. The nonproliferation equilibrium only exists if a, j are high enough and c is low enough, and it is more likely to exist if t is higher and FS1 F is lower. Recall that a governs the importance of the intra-alliance effects (a superpower loses influence over a nuclear-armed client) relative to the inter-alliance effects (a superpower’s side gets stronger with nuclear-armed clients) of proliferation. In the limiting case where a p 0, there are no intra alliance effects and proliferation simply increases one side’s power and decreases the other’s by the same amount, so that proliferation is zero-sum. Then, for any set of states that get nuclear weapons, one superpower will be left at least equally well off by this proliferation. This superpower will be unwilling to pay the costs of enforcing nonproliferation against these states, and anticipating this, the other superpower will not try either, since enforcement would fail without the first superpower’s help. So, if proliferation is zero-sum, neither superpower will ever enforce nonproliferation in equilibrium. As a rises from zero, proliferation has increasingly strong intra-alliance effects. Because one superpower’s loss of influence over a nuclear-armed client is not fully recouped by the other, proliferation becomes increasingly negative-sum. Now, if nuclear weapons spread far enough, both superpowers could be left worse off because of their net loss of influence. Once a is high enough, the anticipated joint loss of influence from proliferation will outweigh the costs of stopping it and the superpowers will become willing to institute a nonproliferation regime. Essentially, a controls the size of the net benefits to the superpowers from nonproliferation. The superpowers’ perceived value of a changed over the course of the early Cold War, explaining why the regime was not instantiated until the late 1960s. In principle, the superpowers could have pushed the NPT forward as early as the 1950s, once both had nuclear weapons and established alliances and thus something potentially to lose from further proliferation. However, until well into the 1960s, each superpower instead saw substantial advantages to be gained from selective proliferation to certain of their clients. The United States perceived nuclear cooperation and weapons-sharing with its European allies to be a valuable counter to the USSR’s superior conventional forces, and these initiatives were prioritized over nonproliferation. As late as the mid-1960s, the US interest in sharing weapons with West Germany in the form of the multi-lateral force (MLF), adamantly opposed by the Soviets, was an important obstacle to creating the regime (Brands 2007). High-level US officials also privately advocated the consideration of giving weapons to India and Japan, reasoning that this would help to balance the threat from nuclear-armed China.13 For its part, the USSR greatly facilitated China’s development of the bomb in the 1950s, providing expertise and materials and even building a model weapon intended for China to copy (Timerbaev 1999). In short, both superpowers focused on the inter-alliance effects as opposed to the intra-alliance effects of proliferation, suggesting that they perceived the importance of the latter (i.e., a) to be low. The experience of dealing with newly nuclear—and newly obstreperous—allies led the superpowers to reassess the intraalliance effects of proliferation, raising their perceived value of a. The estrangement of China from the USSR allowed the United States to play one against the other, while the ructions France generated in NATO were surely to the USSR’s liking. However, after ending its alliance with the USSR, China proselytized for a more radical version of communist ideology that neither superpower favored, while France sought to preserve control over its remaining colonies against both superpowers’ desires for colonial independence. In the United States, elites increasingly recognized that nonproliferation was needed to limit the superpowers’ joint loss of influence. High-level deliberations after China’s nuclear test led to the United States dropping its support for the MLF in favor of establishing a nonproliferation regime (Brands 2007). A similar evolution of views took place in the Soviet Union (Potter 1985). With both superpowers weighing the intraalliance effects of proliferation more heavily, both became more willing to pay the costs of enforcement under a nonproliferation regime, and so the NPT was agreed. Thus, the increase in a explains the origins of the NPT. <u><mark>The <strong>NPT</u></strong></mark> contributes to the viability of the incipient nonproliferation regime in four ways. First, the inspections that nonnuclear signatories are required to accept increase the chance that a covert nuclear weapons program will be detected and subsequently stopped (raising j). This <u><strong><mark>decreases the willingness of spoilers</strong> to</u></mark> try to <u><mark>cheat</u></mark> under the regime <u><mark>and</u></mark> thus also renders enforcement cheaper for the superpowers. Second, the same inspections also make it easier to catch a superpower surreptitiously helping a state with its program or simply allowing it to proceed (increasing t). This increases the willingness of each superpower to enforce nonproliferation, secure in the knowledge that the other superpower is doing its part and thus that their efforts will be effective, and it decreases the temptation to enable favored states to get nuclear weapons. Third, the willingness of non–nuclear states to sign the NPT, and thus voluntarily subject themselves to better monitoring, reveals that most states are not spoilers.14 <u>This <strong>lowers</strong> the super powers’ perceived costs of enforcing the regime (by decreasing FS1 F), because it enables the superpowers to confirm that only a few holdouts will have to be strong-armed into nonproliferation</u>. And, finally, <u><strong>the NPT</strong> served as a device to coordinate all states on the <strong>nonproliferation equilibrium</strong>, rather than the <strong>widespread proliferation</strong> that </u>might<u> <strong>otherwise result</u></strong>. <u>By <mark>lead</mark>ing <strong><mark>nonspoilers</strong></mark> <mark>to </mark>expect nonproliferation to be <strong>upheld</strong>, it encouraged them to <strong><mark>abide by </mark>it</strong> and <strong>contribute</strong> to the superpowers’ efforts to <strong>enforce <mark>the regime</strong></mark>, lowering the costs of enforcement</u> (c). <u>Our theory</u> <u>of the nonproliferation regime</u>, and the origins and roles of the NPT within it, <u>offers</u> at least three <u><strong>observable implications</u></strong>. First, our model assumes that collusion between the superpowers is central to the regime’s establishment and enforcement, so the first implication is that this collusion should have taken place during negotiations over the regime and in reactions to states’ noncompliance with the regime. H1. The superpowers will collude with one another on nonproliferation concerns and press one another to comply with their side of the collusion terms. Second, the theory implies that the superpowers should pressure the other states into joining the NPT. If a state refused to join, it would increase the difficulty of catching it pursuing nuclear weapons covertly, undermine the willingness of other states to join and comply with the treaty, and thereby increase the superpowers’ costs of enforcing the regime. Since each superpower ought to have more leverage over its own clients than other states, we expect that each would be held responsible for policing its own clients, while the other superpower would be expected not to interfere in or obstruct this policing. We also expect the superpowers to apply this pressure only when it is actually perceived as necessary to induce a state to join the NPT and only when it is perceived to have some chance of success. H2. Each superpower will pressure other states, especially its own clients, to join the NPT, focusing its efforts on cases where pressures are likely to be both necessary and effective, and neither superpower will undermine the other’s efforts. Third, the superpowers should collude to stop any state that is revealed to be (potentially) pursuing nuclear weapons, as doing otherwise could lead to the breakdown of the regime. Here again, we expect that each superpower would be most involved in the policing of its own clients, while the other superpower would be expected not to aid the erstwhile client. H3. Each superpower will apply pressure to prevent other states, especially its own clients, from moving toward acquiring nuclear weapons. Neither superpower will offer assistance to a state suspected to be pursuing a nuclear weapons program. <u><strong>EMPIRICAL TESTS </strong>We turn now to testing these observable implications of our theory.</u> Looking at archival and secondary sources, we evaluate the history of nonproliferation-related interactions between the superpowers, superpower responses to those states that hesitated to join the NPT, and, finally, superpower responses to suspicions of nuclear weapons programs in various states. We also demonstrate that neither the grand bargain nor the cartel theory can account for the evidence on its own. Extensive documentation of our sources, the set of cases we employ, and our coding of data are available in the appendix. Hypothesis 1: Superpowers collude over nonproliferation While we do not expect collusion to be explicit in all cases, a total absence of observable collusion would call our theory into question. We examined declassified documentation of private meetings between the superpowers to assess whether collusion occurred, focusing on episodes particularly relevant to nonproliferation, that is, the NPT negotiations and instances when states came under suspicion of pursuing nuclear weapons. We found ample evidence that when the superpowers discussed proliferation issues, they did so in collusive terms. The United States and the Soviet Union had numerous disputes in negotiating the NPT, and the process was at times seriously stalled due to their disagreements (Brands 2007). However, when it came to dealing with other states, their discussions became remarkably cooperative. First, the superpowers sought to coordinate their mutual efforts to corral states into the treaty. In joint meetings in 1967 and 1968, high-level US and Soviet officials discussed concerns over which states would join and measures the superpowers were taking to promote signature of the treaty. They reported on prospects for signature among their respective allies, Japan and Latin American countries, in the case of the United States, and Romania and some African countries, in the case of the Soviet Union. After the NPT was opened for signature, senior US and Soviet officials exchanged explicit assessments of whether Japan, Brazil, Argentina, and India would sign, and they expressed hopes that the other superpower would use its leverage to cajole the holdouts.15 The United States and the USSR also worked together to control the process of the treaty negotiations; drafts of the treaty were prepared privately by the superpowers before being presented to other states (Swango 2014). Finally, the superpowers often presented a united front to the rest of the international community, and this evidence of their collusion was noticed by other states. For example, Soviet and US delegations regularly coordinated their strategies on nonproliferation discussions at the UN General Assembly (Quester 1981, 228). While the superpowers attempted to keep their cooperation private, numerous states, including US and Soviet allies, decried the treaty’s discriminatory nature, referring not to the official discrimination between nuclear haves and have-nots but to the US-Soviet hegemony they saw the regime as entrenching. We also found instances of explicit US-Soviet collusion in responding to suspicious nuclear activity by another state. In surveying cases where a state was suspected of pursuing a nuclear weapons program, we find that such states were most often pressured by their patron superpower, without comment or interference by the other superpower. In this respect, collusion is implicit in the other superpower’s acquiescence to the patron’s pressure. However, there are at least two cases—North Korea and South Africa—where collusion was explicit in requests from one superpower to the other to police the state in question. In the mid-1980s, US satellites detected the construction of a nuclear reactor at Yongbyon. US officials approached the Soviet Union, highlighting its obligations under the NPT and calling into question its provision of nuclear technology assistance to North Korea. The USSR responded positively, and during the next visit to Moscow of North Korean KWP Secretary Kang Song San, the USSR pushed for North Korea to sign the NPT, offering to provide new nuclear energy reactors if it did (Mazarr 1995, 40–41). The episode shows the United States pressing the USSR to act on the obligation implicit in the superpowers’ collusion and the USSR willing to comply and even offer incentives. It suggests that the DPRK proliferation issue was not one of opposition between the two superpowers but rather cooperation. We observe a similar incident in the case of South Africa but with the roles reversed. In July 1977, a Soviet reconnaissance satellite detected a site for a possible South African nuclear test. The USSR passed the information to the United States, with a personal request from Secretary Brezhnev to President Carter for assistance in stopping the test (Richelson 2007, 278). Several days later Carter replied to Brezhnev that the US assessment was in agreement. Collusion in pressuring South Africa continued during the following months, and declassified memos refer to ongoing “quiet cooperation” on the issue.16 This cooperation was kept private. Publicly, Soviet newspapers alleged that the United States was helping South Africa with a nuclear program. However, declassified documents reveal a recognition on the United States’ side that the USSR was likely using the South Africa issue to divert attention from international criticism of the superpowers failing to curb the growth of their own arsenals.17 This connection between private and public approaches suggests that the superpowers had a considerable understanding of each others’ real interests in preventing proliferation. Our findings reinforce the conclusions of the most recent historiography of the NPT, which has documented the superpowers’ discussions of mutual interests in maintaining dominant positions within their alliances, their support for the NPT over allied opposition, and their attempts to control the drafting of the treaty itself (Brands 2006, 2007; Gavin 2004, 2010; Popp 2014; Swango 2014). Our points on the superpowers’ coordination of efforts to get treaty signatures and cooperation in dealing with suspected nuclear weapons programs in South Africa and North Korea contribute important new examples to the increasingly strong body of evidence on collusion between the superpowers over nonproliferation. Hypothesis 2: Superpowers pressure states to join the NPT The superpowers have a clear interest in other states joining the NPT, as this signals their commitment to eschew nuclear weapons and eases the monitoring of that commitment. Our theory also implies that the number of states the superpowers need to pressure to join should be relatively small; most states should join the treaty voluntarily. To evaluate this hypothesis, we assess how the superpowers acted toward those states they judged as technologically capable of, and potentially interested in, seeking nuclear weapons. Such states would pose the greatest threats to the nonproliferation regime, since states that lacked either capability or interest would be unlikely to acquire nuclear weapons even if they stayed out of the treaty. Because our theory posits that the superpowers are the main enforcers of nonproliferation, our selection of cases relies on the superpowers’ own contemporary assessments of which states were worrisome. We intentionally do not use present-day assessments of states’ historical nuclear interest and capability. Such assessments would pose an unfair test for the theory because the superpowers were, at the time, simply unaware of what would later be revealed about certain states’ nuclear programs and thus would not be predicted to do anything about these programs. For the United States’ side, we use a series of intelligence estimates from 1957 to 1974 that assess states’ technological capability for, and, after 1960, interest in, developing nuclear weapons. Unfortunately, the analogous documents are not available from the Soviet side. The documents we do have indicate that the United States saw the Eastern bloc states as under the tight control of the USSR, which would not allow them to develop nuclear weapons.18 From the Soviet side, certain Eastern European states were likely considered nuclear-capable, and the USSR would probably have added North Korea to the list, as the state had received Soviet nuclear assistance in the 1950s and 1960s (Szalontai and Radchenko 2006). We also use other declassified documents, containing superpower assessments of states’ positions on the NPT, to evaluate whether the superpowers were uncertain or suspicious of a given state’s intent toward nuclear weapons. As long as some doubt remains, we expect the superpowers to explicitly pressure the state to join the treaty. However, if a state expresses a resolute position against the treaty and it becomes apparent to the superpower that no feasible measures would alter its position, then it would be reasonable for the superpower to reassess whether any available pressure is worth exerting. Additionally, if a state delays joining the NPT but the superpowers are confident that this is driven by something other than an interest in nuclear weapons, then we do not expect the superpowers to apply pressure. We then assess superpower behavior toward each state. In some cases, the superpowers took no action; in others, their actions involved only informational meetings and diplomatic discussions with the state in question; and in still others, the superpowers resorted to stronger pressures, such as explicit threats or offers of benefits in exchange for joining the treaty. In the results presented in table 1, a coding of“yes” indicates that the observed superpower behavior is consistent with our theory’s expectations. A coding of “partial” means that the limited historical record is supportive for the theory, but additional information would be needed for a more confident assessment. A coding of “mixed” implies that we found mixed support for the theory: the superpowers pursued the expected action, but they did so either to a lesser extent or inconsistently. Finally, a “no” coding indicates evidence of superpower behavior opposed to our expectations, such as assisting a state in avoiding NPT signature or failing to pay attention to a possible nuclear state’s rejection of the NPT. To summarize, we see that a number of states assessed to be nuclear-capable did not join the NPT completely voluntarily. Rather, when voluntary participation did not appear forthcoming, these states were pressured, largely as expected though not always successfully, by the superpowers. By contrast, but also as expected, the superpowers paid little attention to clear joiners. We also observe some interesting changes in the level of pressure applied in cases where doubts regarding signature are introduced or dispelled. South Korea, for example, was an early supporter of the NPT, and there is initially little action by the United States to persuade it to sign the treaty. However, when South Korea was identified as having nuclear capabilities and delayed ratifying the treaty in the early 1970s, the United States applied pressure to encourage speedier ratification. In the case of Israel, pressure and incentives were attempted until it became clear to key negotiators that Israel had already developed a nuclear device, so that no available means of pressure would be effective. In no case did we find any evidence of one superpower undermining the other’s efforts to pressure a state into joining. Finally, we note that the evidence does not support either the grand bargain or the cartel theory alone. If the grand bargain theory were correct, then all states should be better off with the NPT and all should join voluntarily given that they expect others to do so. This was clearly not the case, and for a number of states, the superpowers had to go to considerable lengths to ensure their participation. Additionally, the fact that this pressure was at times ineffective suggests that some states had very strong incentives to stay out of the treaty, even as most others joined. If, instead, the cartel view is correct, then all states would have to be pressured to join the treaty and all would do so with a desire to cheat. However, the evidence shows that numerous nuclear-capable states, even those that had previously considered weapons programs, joined the regime with little or no pressure from the superpowers. Hypothesis 3: Superpowers pressure states not to proliferate As in the previous hypothesis, if a state is suspected of making a move toward nuclear weapons, its patron superpower ought to have the most leverage over it, and so we expect its patron to be the one to apply pressure while the other superpower refrains from assisting the aspirant. With nonaligned states, we expect that either or both superpowers would apply pressure and neither should assist the errant state in any way. To test this, we considered all cases where a state became suspected of pursuing a nuclear weapons program, and we evaluated the superpowers’ response. Our findings are presented in table 2. In each case, we assess what the superpowers perceived about a state’s activity and how they responded. A coding of “yes” indicates that the superpower acted as our theory predicts, taking steps to restrain a client’s progress toward nuclear weapons or its access to dual-use nuclear technology needed to make progress in the future. As before, a coding of “mixed” means that the superpowers sought to restrain the proliferant but that it did so either to a lesser extent or inconsistently. “Partial” implies that the limited historical record is supportive for the theory but that additional information would be needed to reach a confident assessment. Finally, a “no” coding indicates that the superpower did not behave as our theory predicts, instead aiding a client state with a nuclear weapons program or turning a blind eye to apparent attempts to proliferate. We find general support for hypothesis 3, with a few mixed cases. In the majority of cases, the superpower patron of each nuclear aspirant intervened with threats or incentives to prevent the nuclear program from progressing, so that the “policing” element of superpower relations with nuclear aspirants is clear. Examples of policing actions by the superpowers included direct instructions to stop the suspicious activity, threats to withdraw some military or economic support, restrictions on suppliers and access to technology, and highlevel diplomatic pressure. By contrast, we find no cases where the opposing superpower provided assistance, reassurance, or any support for the fledgling nuclear state. To investigate this point, we surveyed a wide range of primary and secondary sources for evidence that such assistance occurred, and we also looked for any accusations that might have been made by one superpower against the other for such a transgression. Although it is difficult to prove that neither superpower sought to lure away the opponent’s ally by offering nuclear support, we have not located any evidence of such behavior in all the cases surveyed. Neither the grand bargain nor the cartel theory fit this evidence. The nuclear weapons states were widely perceived as reneging on their end of the grand bargain. No significant disarmament on the part of any of the nuclear-weapons states occurred until the very end of the Cold War. Moreover, there is no evidence that NPT membership increased a state’s chance of receiving nuclear energy assistance (Fuhrmann 2009b). Despite this, hardly any of the non–nuclear weapons states cheated on the regime; those few that did were not motivated by the need to punish the nuclear-weapons states for not disarming, and these were stopped from getting nuclear weapons not by the prospect that others would follow but by the intervention of the superpowers. None of these three facts is consistent with the grand bargain theory. While the superpowers’ enforcement of nonproliferation is consistent with the cartel view, the small number of cases in which such enforcement was needed is not. Most states showed no interest in bucking the nonproliferation regime and abided by it voluntarily, without pressure from the superpowers. IMPLICATIONS We conclude by discussing the implications of our study for the broader literature on nuclear proliferation. <u><strong>Hymans</u></strong> (2010) <u><strong>argues</strong> that the fundamental question for students of proliferation is why so few of the <strong>nuclear-capable <mark>states</strong> </mark>ended up acquiring nuclear weapons</u>: some six nuclearweapons states out of more than 40 estimated to be nuclearcapable by 1970. <u><strong>Our answer</u></strong> <u>is that once</u> the <u>superpowers</u> <u>realized</u> <u><strong>nonproliferation</u></strong> <u>was necessary to preserve their influence and</u> <u>set about colluding to enforce it</u>, <u><strong>many states chose not to realize their latent nuclear capacity</u></strong>. A few of these states refrained because they were deterred by the punishment the superpowers would impose if they were caught seeking nuclear weapons. But <u>most</u> did so because they <u><strong>preferred nonproliferation to widespread proliferation</u></strong>, <u>and</u> they <u><mark>were</u></mark> <u><strong><mark>confident </mark>enough</u></strong> <u><mark>that </mark>the</u> <u><mark>superpowers would </mark>be <strong>able to <mark>curtail prolif</mark>eration</u></strong> <u><mark>to <strong>voluntarily forgo weapons </mark>for themselves</u></strong>. These latter states’ willing compliance with nonproliferation made the regime’s enforcement affordable for the superpowers. <u>Moreover, we presented <strong>evidence</strong>, consistent with this answer</u>, <u>that</u> the <u>superpowers</u> <u><strong>explicitly colluded</u></strong> <u>to create the <strong>nonproliferation regime</u></strong> and to <u><strong>cajole</u></strong> the few <u><strong>worrisome states</u></strong> <u>into joining and complying</u> with it. <u>Within this regime, the <strong>NPT</strong> serves to ease <strong>detect</strong>ion of cheating by either these states or the superpowers, to identify potential spoilers, and finally to <strong>coordinate states’ expectations</strong> on widespread nonproliferation</u>. <u><strong><mark>This strongly suggests</u></strong> <u>that the <strong></mark>nonproliferation <mark>regime</u></strong></mark>, and the treaty that coordinated states onto behaving in accordance with it, <u><strong><mark>substantially reduced prolif</mark>eration</u></strong>, <u><mark>relative to <strong>what would</u></strong></mark> have <u><mark>occur</u></mark>red <u><mark>in its <strong>absence</u></strong></mark>. To explain this, we need to specify exactly what is meant by “the regime” and “its absence,” since the latter is the appropriate counterfactual for assessing the regime’s overall effect. In our theory, the regime is an equilibrium <u><mark>in</u></mark> which the superpowers are able and willing to enforce nonproliferation because of the voluntary compliance of non–spoiler states, whose support is driven by the expectation that others will either not seek weapons or be stopped from getting them. <u><strong><mark>The</mark> <mark>absence of the regime</u></strong></mark> <u>is an equilibrium in which states</u> <u><strong>expect spoilers</u></strong> <u>to get nuclear weapons</u> <u>and others to follow</u>, <u><strong>eventually resulting in widespread proliferation</u></strong>, <u>so that many non–spoiler states are unwilling to eschew nuclear weapons, which in turn makes the superpowers unwilling to stop them</u>. The NPT coordinates the movement of all states from the latter equilibrium to the former. <u>To <strong>conclude</strong> that the regime did not <strong>substantially reduce proliferation</strong>, one of two <strong>claims</strong> would have to be true: first, that breakdown would <strong>not occur</strong> in the <strong>absence of the regime</strong>: the numerous states that were initially—or might in response become—<strong>interested</strong> in nuclear weapons would prefer to <strong>abstain</strong>, even knowing that they would <strong>not be stopped</strong> and that proliferation would eventually be <strong>widespread</strong>; or, second, that in the <strong>absence of the NPT</strong> to coordinate states on nonproliferation, the <strong>superpowers</strong> would be able and willing to <strong>stop proliferation</strong>, even given that many states were seeking nuclear weapons and would thus have to be coerced.</u> The <u><strong>history</u></strong> <u>of states’ nuclear decision making and of the superpowers’ attitudes toward proliferation presented here</u> <u>shows that</u> <u><strong>neither claim is plausible</u></strong>. By contrast, the most recent previous research concludes that the regime has had little effect on proliferation (Sagan 2011). Although several studies find that NPT membership is associated with a reduced risk of seeking or getting nuclear weapons (Fuhrmann 2009a, 2012; Jo and Gartzke 2007; Kroenig 2010), some have suggested it may only be that NPT members are mostly those states that do not want nuclear weapons anyway, so that the treaty does not constrain states so much as screen them (Fuhrmann 2012; Jo and Gartzke 2007).19 Similarly, <u><strong>Hymans</u></strong> (2006) <u>and</u> <u><strong>Solingen</u></strong> (2007) <u>argue that the regime <strong>only appears successful</u></strong> <u>because it <strong>prohibits</strong> things that few states want</u>. Fuhrmann (2009b, 2012) shows that NPT membership has little effect on the provision of peaceful nuclear assistance, and that, having received such assistance, NPT membership has little effect on a state’s subsequent pursuit of nuclear weapons. Jo and Gartzke (2007) find that the adoption of the NPT (measured by the proportion of states that are members) is not associated with a reduction in the initiation of weapons programs, and Kroenig (2010) finds that the establishment of the NPT does not itself affect the provision of sensitive nuclear assistance. Finally, Hymans (2012) argues that it is managerial incompetence due to domestic politics, rather than the nonproliferation regime, that explains why states seeking nuclear weapons after the regime’s creation have been less likely to succeed and have taken much longer to get them when they do. <u><strong>Our theory</strong> yields</u> a<u><strong> different interpretation of these findings</strong> that is consistent with the regime <strong>substantially reducing proliferation</strong> overall</u>. Even if NPT membership serves only to screen voluntary compliers, the wide joining of the NPT may still have a large effect by reinforcing the superpowers’ belief that enforcement will be affordable and thus that the regime is viable. States that comply may simply not want nuclear weapons, as <u><strong>Hymans</u></strong> (2006) <u>and</u> <u><strong>Solingen</u></strong> (2007) find, but this likely <u>depends</u> in many cases <u>on the belief that <strong>most other states</u></strong> <u>are not seeking them</u> <u>and in other cases on the belief that pursuing weapons would bring <strong>international pressure</strong>—both</u> <u>beliefs that <strong>only exist because of the regime</u></strong>. The fact that the receipt of peaceful nuclear assistance and its link to nuclear weapons programs are unaffected by whether a state is an NPT member, as Fuhrmann (2009b, 2012) shows, is also explicable within our framework. The existence of the regime makes peaceful nuclear assistance less dangerous, regardless of whether the recipient is an NPT member, because even if an occasional state receiving assistance ends up getting nuclear weapons, <u>the regime makes a subsequent <strong>breakdown into widespread proliferation less likely</u></strong>. Similarly, the regime makes the rare provision of weapons-relevant nuclear assistance more tempting to some potential suppliers, who can be assured that any resulting proliferation will be isolated. So it is not surprising that the establishment of the regime is not associated with a reduction in such assistance, as Kroenig (2010) found. F<u>inally, though Hymans (2012) is surely right that incompetence played an important role in the long timelines of later nuclear programs, the regime’s prevention of a broad market in nuclear weapons likely also contributed</u>. We close with the hope that scholars of the politics of nuclear weapons will find this study helpful in developing new avenues for research and interpreting new findings. Our theory and evidence provide an overarching picture of the constellation of states’ interests in and expectations about nuclear weapons that gave rise to the nonproliferation regime. This theory is built upon, but also clarifies and integrates, previous research on particular elements of this constellation. It should thus form a solid foundation for further research, including theorizing about the evolution of the nonproliferation regime since the Cold War’s end, evaluating present-day fears about a “nuclear tipping point,” and explaining the occurrence of and responses to the challenges to the regime posed by North Korea, Iran, and others.</p> | 1AC | null | 1AC ― NPT Credibility | 774,132 | 236 | 99,785 | ./documents/ndtceda18/Georgia/HoHa/Georgia-Hoover-Haskins-Aff-ADA-Round5.docx | 603,990 | A | ADA | 5 | Trinity DK | Jeff Buntin | 1AC - NWFZs (NPT and Africa)
1NC - T-First Strike T-Statutory T-Threats ESR CP 2020 DA Prolif K NPT Latency Turn African Development Turn Cobalt Mining Turn
2NR - Prolif K | ndtceda18/Georgia/HoHa/Georgia-Hoover-Haskins-Aff-ADA-Round5.docx | null | 51,343 | HoHa | Georgia HoHa | null | Al..... | Ho..... | Tr..... | Ha..... | 19,184 | Georgia | Georgia | null | null | 1,008 | ndtceda18 | NDT/CEDA 2018-19 | 2,018 | cx | college | 2 |
2,803,155 | The state is inevitable --- denouncing us as “liberal reformism” ignores that even if we don’t engage the state, it will engage us --- any method which is mutually exclusive with ours devolves politics into a dogmatic void that the right is all too willing to fill | Choat 16 | Choat 16 PhD in Political Science at Queen Mary University of London, member of the Political Studies Association, Senior Lecturer in the School of Economics, Politics, and History (Simon, “Marxism and anarchism in an age of neoliberal crisis,” http://eprints.kingston.ac.uk/32233/1/Choat-S-3223-AAM.pdf, dml) | some anarchists have rejected any engagement with the state – whether it be voting, demanding legal rights or protections, forming political parties, or attempting the revolutionary seizure of government – on the basis that such engagement can only end up replicating the oppressive hierarchies that they are fighting: either it will lead to new forms of dictatorship and bureaucracy or reformism and merely reinforce existing structures and relations of power. If Marxists support engagement with the state and even the formation of political parties it is not because they think that centralised hierarchies are desirable or inevitable, but because they begin from a different understanding of politics the anarchist abstention from state politics denies us the most effective means of political action: we disempower ourselves rather than the state when we refuse to engage with it. Making demands on the state does not necessarily entail an endorsement of the state, any more than the demands that are made by employees during a strike are an endorsement of the employer or of the system of wage-labour abstention from state politics is not a genuine option: whether we like it or not, we are all already involved in state politics, because we are all always already submitted to state power, control, and oppression. Anarchists are concerned that participation in conventional politics will lead to reformism. But this concern is itself ultimately premised on a tacit acceptance of the liberal-parliamentary understanding of politics: to claim that we can safely repudiate state politics simply by refusing ever to enter a polling booth is to assume that ‘the state’ stops at the door of Parliament simply in going about our daily lives we are all therefore implicated in state politics. Given our necessary involvement within politics, the question is not whether we engage with it, but how we do so the recommendation of disengagement from the state risks a politics of withdrawal and isolation the willingness to engage in state politics is preferable Given the strength of neoliberalism since the crisis that it created, there is a strong case for a certain pragmatism in our response prefigurative politics dogmatically dictates an a priori exclusion of certain forms of political action political strategies must be decided according to particular conditions and within a certain context the active defence of state services and institutions should be seen not as a reformist compromise with the existing order but as safeguarding the gains of class struggle against capitalist processes of accumulation by dispossession. The anti-state politics of anarchism may have made sense during eras in which the state could plausibly be presented as the main threat to freedom it has far less purchase in an era in which neoliberalism, as both the official ideology and a form of everyday common sense, is anti-statist. the attack on state power too easily echoes the rhetoric of neoliberalism itself When government actors themselves are explicitly endorsing the retreat of the state, then attacks on state power have limited efficacy either as a tactical call to arms or as a convincing analysis of our present conjuncture | anarchists rejected any engagement with the state such engagement end up replicating oppressive hierarchies abstention from state politics denies us the most effective means of action: we disempower ourselves Making demands on the state does not entail an endorsement of the state we are all implicated in state politics the question is not whether we engage , but how we do so there is a strong case for pragmatism defence of state services should be seen not as reformist compromise but safeguarding gains of struggle , the attack on state power echoes the rhetoric of neoliberalism | The anarchist critique of Marxist organisational forms is unconvincing, then, because it does not acknowledge the diversity of Marxist approaches and it tends towards a theoreticism that sees a linear, causal, and continuous line from theory to practice. Nonetheless, there are significant differences of strategy between anarchism and Marxism: it is just that these are less to do with organisation as such, and are much more broadly to do with differing attitudes toward politics and the state. Although some (though by no means all) anarchists have supported formal political organisations, with rules, membership criteria, and even internal discipline (Schmidt and van der Walt 2009: 247-263), they have traditionally rejected any engagement with the state – whether it be voting, demanding legal rights or protections, forming political parties, or attempting the revolutionary seizure of government – on the basis that such engagement can only end up replicating the oppressive hierarchies that they are fighting: either it will lead to new forms of dictatorship and bureaucracy (such as developed in the Soviet Union); or it will lead to parliamentary reformism and hence merely reinforce existing structures and relations of power. If Marxists support (qualified) engagement with the state and even the formation of political parties, however, it is not because they think that centralised hierarchies are desirable or inevitable, but because they begin from a different understanding of politics. They argue that the anarchist abstention from state politics denies us the most effective means of political action: we disempower ourselves rather than the state when we refuse to engage with it. Making demands on the state does not necessarily entail an endorsement of the state, any more than the demands that are made by employees during a strike are an endorsement of the employer or of the system of wage-labour (Marx 1988). Anarchists themselves have at least implicitly recognised the efficacy of political engagement by occasionally supporting the policies of certain governments and even participating in elections (Engels 1988; Franks 2012: 216). More than this, abstention from state politics is not a genuine option: whether we like it or not, we are all already involved in state politics, because we are all always already submitted to state power, control, and oppression. Anarchists are concerned that participation in conventional politics will lead to parliamentary reformism. But this concern is itself ultimately premised on a tacit acceptance of the liberal-parliamentary understanding of politics: to claim that we can safely repudiate state politics simply by refusing ever to enter a polling booth is to assume that ‘the state’ stops at the door of Parliament. Marxists, in contrast, have argued that the state apparatus includes educational institutions, the media, churches, the family, and so on (e.g. Althusser 1971): simply in going about our daily lives we are all therefore implicated in state politics. Given our necessary involvement within politics, the question is not whether we engage with it, but how we do so; even libertarian Marxists like Holloway argue that engagement with the state is inevitable (Holloway 2005: 40). In contrast, the anarchist recommendation of disengagement from the state risks a politics of withdrawal and isolation. There are two related reasons why under our current conditions in particular the Marxist willingness to engage in state politics is preferable to an anarchist position. The first is the dominance of neoliberalism today. Given the strength of neoliberalism since the crisis that it created, there is a strong case for a certain pragmatism in our response. A danger of the prefigurative politics favoured by anarchists is that it dogmatically dictates an a priori exclusion of certain forms of political action. For Marxists, on the other hand, political strategies must be decided according to particular conditions and within a certain context. In a context in which private companies are increasingly undertaking tasks previously performed by the state, the active defence of state services and institutions can be viewed as a radical position to adopt: defending welfare provision, public pensions, universal healthcare, and free higher education should be seen not as a reformist compromise with the existing order but as safeguarding the gains of class struggle against capitalist processes of accumulation by dispossession. This leads to the second reason for doubting the refusal of state politics as a viable tactic under current conditions, which concerns the specific role of the state under neoliberalism. The anti-state politics of anarchism may have made sense during eras in which the state could plausibly be presented as the main threat to freedom and equality: during the period of nation-building and imperialistic expansion in the mid- to late-19th century, of the rise of fascism in the early-20th century, or even of the development of welfare capitalism after WWII. But it has far less purchase in an era in which neoliberalism, as both the official ideology and a form of everyday common sense, is anti-statist. Put simply, the attack on state power too easily echoes the rhetoric of neoliberalism itself (Taylor 2013: 735). When government actors themselves are explicitly endorsing the retreat of the state, then anarchist attacks on state power have limited efficacy either as a tactical call to arms or as a convincing analysis of our present conjuncture. In practice, of course, it is true that neoliberalism has not dissolved state power. But nor has the relation between state and capital remained the same under neoliberalism, such that our analyses, strategies, or rhetoric need not alter. The nature of this relationship between state and capital will be examined in the next section. | 5,904 | <h4><strong>The state is <u>inevitable</u> --- denouncing us as “liberal reformism” ignores that even if we don’t engage the state, it will engage us --- any method which is mutually exclusive with ours devolves politics into a dogmatic void that the right is all too willing to fill </h4><p>Choat 16</strong> PhD in Political Science at Queen Mary University of London, member of the Political Studies Association, Senior Lecturer in the School of Economics, Politics, and History (Simon, “Marxism and anarchism in an age of neoliberal crisis,” http://eprints.kingston.ac.uk/32233/1/Choat-S-3223-AAM.pdf, dml)</p><p>The anarchist critique of Marxist organisational forms is unconvincing, then, because it does not acknowledge the diversity of Marxist approaches and it tends towards a theoreticism that sees a linear, causal, and continuous line from theory to practice. Nonetheless, there are significant differences of strategy between anarchism and Marxism: it is just that these are less to do with organisation as such, and are much more broadly to do with differing attitudes toward politics and the state. Although <u>some</u> (though by no means all) <u><mark>anarchists</u></mark> have supported formal political organisations, with rules, membership criteria, and even internal discipline (Schmidt and van der Walt 2009: 247-263), they <u>have</u> traditionally <u><strong><mark>rejected any engagement with the state</strong></mark> – whether it be <strong>voting</strong>, <strong>demanding legal rights</strong> or protections, <strong>forming political parties</strong>, or attempting <strong>the revolutionary seizure of government</strong> – on the basis that <mark>such engagement</mark> <strong>can only <mark>end up replicating</mark> the <mark>oppressive hierarchies</strong></mark> that they are fighting: either it will lead to <strong>new forms of dictatorship</strong> and <strong>bureaucracy</u></strong> (such as developed in the Soviet Union); <u>or</u> it will lead to parliamentary <u><strong>reformism</strong> and</u> hence <u>merely <strong>reinforce existing structures</strong> and relations of power. If Marxists support</u> (qualified) <u>engagement with the state and even the formation of political parties</u>, however, <u>it is <strong>not</strong> because they think that centralised hierarchies are <strong>desirable</strong> or <strong>inevitable</strong>, but because they begin from a <strong>different understanding of politics</u></strong>. They argue that <u>the</u> <u>anarchist</u> <u><mark>abstention from state politics <strong>denies us the most effective means of</mark> political <mark>action</strong>: we <strong>disempower ourselves</mark> rather than the state</strong> when we refuse to engage with it. <mark>Making demands on the state <strong>does not</mark> necessarily <mark>entail an endorsement of the state</strong></mark>, any more than the demands that are made by employees during a strike are an endorsement of the employer or of the system of wage-labour</u> (Marx 1988). Anarchists themselves have at least implicitly recognised the efficacy of political engagement by occasionally supporting the policies of certain governments and even participating in elections (Engels 1988; Franks 2012: 216). More than this, <u>abstention from state politics is <strong>not a genuine option</strong>: <strong>whether we like it or not</strong>, we are all <strong>already involved in state politics</strong>, because we are all <strong>always already submitted to state power</strong>, <strong>control</strong>, and <strong>oppression</strong>. Anarchists are concerned that participation in conventional politics will lead to</u> parliamentary <u>reformism. But this concern is itself ultimately <strong>premised on a tacit acceptance of the liberal-parliamentary understanding of politics</strong>: to claim that we can safely repudiate state politics simply by refusing ever to enter a polling booth <strong>is to assume that ‘the state’ stops at the door of Parliament</u></strong>. Marxists, in contrast, have argued that the state apparatus includes educational institutions, the media, churches, the family, and so on (e.g. Althusser 1971): <u>simply in going about our daily lives <mark>we are <strong>all</mark> therefore <mark>implicated in state politics</strong></mark>. Given our necessary involvement within politics, <mark>the question is <strong>not whether we engage</mark> with it</strong><mark>, but <strong>how we do so</u></strong></mark>; even libertarian Marxists like Holloway argue that engagement with the state is inevitable (Holloway 2005: 40). In contrast, <u>the</u> anarchist <u>recommendation of disengagement from the state <strong>risks a politics of withdrawal</strong> and <strong>isolation</u></strong>. There are two related reasons why under our current conditions in particular <u>the</u> Marxist <u>willingness to engage in state politics is preferable</u> to an anarchist position. The first is the dominance of neoliberalism today. <u>Given the strength of neoliberalism since the crisis that it created, <mark>there is a <strong>strong case</strong> for</mark> a <strong>certain <mark>pragmatism</strong></mark> in our response</u>. A danger of the <u>prefigurative politics</u> favoured by anarchists is that it <u><strong>dogmatically dictates</strong> an <strong>a priori exclusion</strong> of certain forms of political action</u>. For Marxists, on the other hand, <u>political strategies must be decided <strong>according to particular conditions</strong> and <strong>within a certain context</u></strong>. In a context in which private companies are increasingly undertaking tasks previously performed by the state, <u>the active <mark>defence of state services</mark> and institutions</u> can be viewed as a radical position to adopt: defending welfare provision, public pensions, universal healthcare, and free higher education <u><mark>should be seen <strong>not as</mark> a <mark>reformist compromise</strong></mark> with the existing order <mark>but</mark> as <strong><mark>safeguarding</mark> the <mark>gains of</mark> class <mark>struggle</strong></mark> against capitalist processes of accumulation by dispossession. </u>This leads to the second reason for doubting the refusal of state politics as a viable tactic under current conditions, which concerns the specific role of the state under neoliberalism. <u>The anti-state politics of anarchism may have made sense during eras in which the state could plausibly be presented as the main threat to freedom</u> and equality: during the period of nation-building and imperialistic expansion in the mid- to late-19th century, of the rise of fascism in the early-20th century, or even of the development of welfare capitalism after WWII. But <u>it has <strong>far less purchase</strong> in an era in which neoliberalism, as both the official ideology and a form of everyday common sense, is anti-statist.</u> Put simply<mark>, <u>the attack on state power</mark> <strong>too easily <mark>echoes the rhetoric of neoliberalism</mark> itself</u></strong> (Taylor 2013: 735). <u>When government actors themselves are <strong>explicitly endorsing the retreat of the state</strong>, then</u> anarchist <u>attacks on state power have <strong>limited efficacy</strong> either as a tactical call to arms or as a convincing analysis of our present conjuncture</u>. In practice, of course, it is true that neoliberalism has not dissolved state power. But nor has the relation between state and capital remained the same under neoliberalism, such that our analyses, strategies, or rhetoric need not alter. The nature of this relationship between state and capital will be examined in the next section.</p> | Strath Haven RY – Round 2 - Mamaroneck | 1AC | 1AC – Advantage | 12,567 | 954 | 88,954 | ./documents/hspolicy19/StrathHaven/RuYu/Strath%20Haven-Ruan-Yu-Aff-Mamaroneck-Round2.docx | 721,212 | A | Mamaroneck | 2 | Newark TN | Janet Novak | 1AC - Japan v K
1NC - Biopolitics K
Neg Block - Biopolitics K
2NR - Biopolitics K | hspolicy19/StrathHaven/RuYu/Strath%20Haven-Ruan-Yu-Aff-Mamaroneck-Round2.docx | null | 61,570 | RuYu | Strath Haven RuYu | null | Ai..... | Ru..... | Ha..... | Yu..... | 21,440 | StrathHaven | Strath Haven | PA | null | 1,018 | hspolicy19 | HS Policy 2019-20 | 2,019 | cx | hs | 2 |
2,453,570 | Russia and China say yes. | Muñoz-Patchen ’18 | Chelsea, Muñoz-Patchen, Chicago Law J.D. Expected 2019, ’18, "Regulating the Space Commons: Treating Space Debris as Abandoned Property in Violation of the Outer Space Treaty," Chicago Journal of International Law: Vol. 19: No. 1, Article 7. | Academics have taken this idea and sought to apply it to space debris, which has similar fungibility and causation issues but their applications have been limited to a tort-like context liability and compensation should be apportioned “among spacefaring nations equal to the percentages of the total debris population for which the particular nation is responsible This mechanism frees the victim from having to prove causation by a specific nation, when that would be virtually impossible. there is fairly accurate information from the U.N mathematical models and other records of known collisions
states primarily responsible for existing debris are the U.S., Russia, and China these nations would be paying the highest cost proportional to their respective contributions to the problem these nations may welcome this remedy, because their space activity is threatened by the proliferation of space debris and they likely value continuing their extensive and advanced use of space. This solution solves the free rider problem and would compensate any nation or company that cleans up space such that any nation like the U.S., Russia, or China fearing the collapse of its space program and unwilling to bear all the cleanup costs itself would see this as an attractive solution. It is even possible that liable states like the U.S. and Russia will be eager to aid in debris identification add to other states’ liability.
nations or companies would be incentivized to begin cleanup operations, because they would know that others will not freeride on their costly efforts. they will have guaranteed compensation from those responsible. | . any nation like the U.S., Russia, or China fearing the collapse of its space program and unwilling to bear all the cleanup costs would see this as an attractive solution
nations or companies would be incentivized to begin cleanup operations, because they will have guaranteed compensation | Academics have taken this idea and sought to apply it to space debris, which has similar fungibility and causation issues, but their applications have been limited to a tort-like context.162 One author suggested that whenever a collision occurs due to an unidentifiable piece of debris and a functional space object, liability and compensation should be apportioned “among spacefaring nations equal to the percentages of the total debris population for which the particular nation is responsible.” 163 This mechanism frees the victim from having to prove causation by a specific nation, when that would be virtually impossible.164 There will be difficulties calculating the percentage with precision in such a system, but there is fairly accurate information from the U.N., including registry, sampling, mathematical models, and other records of known collisions and the resultant debris.165
Without strong buy-in, it may be challenging to get this rarely used domestic tort theory to apply in international space law, especially with the potential for disputes over the proper apportionment of market share.166 The states primarily responsible for existing debris are the U.S., Russia, and China – powerful countries unlikely to be pleased with this newfound expense. That said, though these nations would be paying the highest cost, this would be proportional to their respective contributions to the problem. Indeed, these nations may welcome this remedy, because their space activity is threatened by the proliferation of space debris and they likely value continuing their extensive and advanced use of space. This solution solves the free rider problem and would compensate any nation or company that cleans up space such that any nation (like the U.S., Russia, or China) fearing the collapse of its space program and unwilling to bear all the cleanup costs itself would see this as an attractive solution. It is even possible that liable states like the U.S. and Russia will be eager to aid in debris identification, so as to add to other states’ liability.167
This regulatory remedy would resolve the current tragedy of the commons. By assigning responsibility for the cost of cleanup, nations or companies would be incentivized to begin cleanup operations, because they would know that others will not freeride on their costly efforts. Instead, they will have guaranteed compensation from those responsible. Obtaining the funds is crucial, particularly since the high cost of deploying existing technology to destroy space debris has been a hindrance thus far.168 | 2,572 | <h4>Russia and China say yes. </h4><p>Chelsea, <u><strong>Muñoz-Patchen</u></strong>, Chicago Law J.D. Expected 2019, <u><strong>’18</u></strong>, "Regulating the Space Commons: Treating Space Debris as Abandoned Property in Violation of the Outer Space Treaty," Chicago Journal of International Law: Vol. 19: No. 1, Article 7.</p><p><u>Academics have taken this idea and sought to <strong>apply it to space debris</strong>, which has similar fungibility and causation issues</u>, <u>but their applications have been limited to a tort-like context</u>.162 One author suggested that whenever a collision occurs due to an unidentifiable piece of debris and a functional space object, <u>liability and compensation should be apportioned “among spacefaring nations equal to the percentages of the total debris population for which the particular nation is responsible</u>.” 163 <u>This mechanism frees the victim from having to prove causation by a specific nation, when that would be virtually impossible.</u>164 There will be difficulties calculating the percentage with precision in such a system, but <u>there is fairly accurate information from the U.N</u>., including registry, sampling, <u><strong>mathematical models</u></strong>, <u>and other records of known collisions</u> and the resultant debris.165</p><p>Without strong buy-in, it may be challenging to get this rarely used domestic tort theory to apply in international space law, especially with the potential for disputes over the proper apportionment of market share.166 The <u>states primarily responsible for existing debris are the U.S., Russia, and China</u> – powerful countries unlikely to be pleased with this newfound expense. That said, though <u>these nations would be paying the highest cost</u>, this would be <u>proportional to their respective contributions to the problem</u>. Indeed, <u>these nations may welcome this remedy, because their space activity is threatened by the proliferation of space debris and they likely value continuing their extensive and advanced use of space<mark>.</u></mark> <u>This solution solves the free rider problem and would compensate any nation or company that cleans up space such that <mark>any nation</mark> </u>(<u><mark>like the U.S., Russia, or China</u></mark>) <u><mark>fearing the <strong>collapse of its space program</strong> and <strong>unwilling to bear all the cleanup costs</strong></mark> itself <mark>would see this as an attractive solution</mark>. It is even possible that liable states like the U.S. and Russia will be eager to aid in debris identification</u>, so as to <u>add to other states’ liability.</u>167</p><p>This regulatory remedy would resolve the current tragedy of the commons. By assigning responsibility for the cost of cleanup, <u><mark>nations or companies would be incentivized to begin cleanup operations, because </mark>they would know that others will not freeride on their costly efforts. </u>Instead, <u><mark>they will have <strong>guaranteed compensation</strong></mark> from those responsible.</u> Obtaining the funds is crucial, particularly since the high cost of deploying existing technology to destroy space debris has been a hindrance thus far.168</p> | null | 1NC | 1NC: Liability CP | 342,069 | 130 | 79,969 | ./documents/ndtceda19/Dartmouth/EsTa/Dartmouth-Estrada-Tambe-Neg-Kentucky%20Round%20Robin-Round4.docx | 610,459 | N | Kentucky Round Robin | 4 | Kentucky EH | Klinger | 1AC - Lasers (New)
1NC - T Russia DA China CP Ban CP Liability CP Sharing DA EIA CP Industrial Ag Bad
2NC - T New Arms Control CP Industrial Ag Bad
1NR - EIA CP
2NR - T | ndtceda19/Dartmouth/EsTa/Dartmouth-Estrada-Tambe-Neg-Kentucky%20Round%20Robin-Round4.docx | null | 51,746 | EsTa | Dartmouth EsTa | null | Jo..... | Es..... | Ra..... | Ta..... | 19,246 | Dartmouth | Dartmouth | null | null | 1,009 | ndtceda19 | NDT/CEDA 2019-20 | 2,019 | cx | college | 2 |
2,498,265 | They cause global calamity and nuclear winter – comprehensive simulations | Baum ’19 | Baum ’19 - executive director of the Global Catastrophic Risk Institute, Ph.D in Geography
Seth Baum, “Risk-Risk Tradeoff Analysis of Nuclear Explosives for Asteroid Deflection,” SSRN Scholarly Paper (Rochester, NY: Social Science Research Network, May 31, 2019), https://papers.ssrn.com/abstract=3397559. | The most severe asteroid collisions and nuclear wars can cause global environmental effects The core mechanism is the transport of particulate matter into the stratosphere where it can spread worldwide and remain aloft for decades Large asteroid collisions create dust and large fireballs the fire heats the dust so that some portion of it rises into the stratosphere The largest collisions eject debris into space reentry heats up enough to spark global fires are a major impact in their own right and can send additional smoke into the stratosphere
the particulate matter blocks sunlight and destroys ozone The ozone loss increases the amount of ultraviolet radiation causing skin cancer and other harms he blocked sunlight causes abrupt cooling of Earth’s surface and in turn reduced precipitation cool, dry, and dark conditions reduce plant growth a hypothetical IndiaPakistan nuclear war scenario with 100 weapons find agriculture declines approximately 50% crop declines could threaten starvation for two billion people the 100 weapon scenario is not the largest potential scenario The largest asteroid collisions could even reduce sunlight below the minimum needed for vision the global environmental disruption from large collisions could cause one billion deaths or 25% of all humans
food shortages from severe global environmental disruption could lead to infectious disease outbreaks as public health conditions deteriorate Today’s complex global political-economic system already shows fragility to shocks an asteroid collision could be an extremely large shock The systemic consequences of a nuclear war would be further worsened by the likely loss of major world cities
It is possible for asteroid collisions to cause nuclear war An asteroid explosion could be misinterpreted as a nuclear attack, prompting nuclear attack that is believed to be retaliation. Chelyabinsk occurred near an important Russian military installation
Would the reaction be disciplined ? Or would the reaction be disorderly and destructive ? This leaves considerable uncertainty in the total human harm from an asteroid collision published estimates of the human consequences do not account for this uncertainty and are likely to be inaccurate.
Of particular importance which could vastly outnumber the present generation If an asteroid collision or nuclear war would cause human extinction, then there would be no future generations future generations would be permanently diminished. prudent risk management would aim for very low probabilities of permanent collapse
the severity of violent nuclear conflict could depend on more than just the effects of nuclear explosions, because the overall conflict scenario could include non-nuclear violence. it is possible for the nuclear explosions to constitute a relatively small portion of the total severity
it is necessary to discuss the risk of violent non-nuclear conflict
Nuclear deterrence theory does permit limited, small-scale violent conflicts between nuclear-armed countries conflicts would not involve nuclear weapons. nuclear deterrence may make small conflicts more likely known as the stability-instability paradox brings instability with respect to minor conflicts. Empirical support has been found by some research | asteroid collisions cause global environmental effects collisions create large fireballs collisions eject debris into space reentry spark global fires a major impact in their own right
ozone loss increases u v radiation blocked sunlight causes abrupt cooling and reduced precipitation conditions reduce plant growth crop declines threaten starvation for two billion people the scenario is not the largest largest collisions could reduce sunlight below the minimum needed for vision
food shortages lead to infectious disease outbreaks
An asteroid could be misinterpreted as a nuclear attack prompting retaliation
published estimates are likely to be inaccurate
there would be no future generations prudent risk management would aim for very low probabilities of permanent collapse
the conflict could include non-nuclear violence nuclear explosions constitute a relatively small portion of total severity | The most severe asteroid collisions and nuclear wars can cause global environmental effects. The core mechanism is the transport of particulate matter into the stratosphere, where it can spread worldwide and remain aloft for years or decades. Large asteroid collisions create large quantities of dust and large fireballs; the fire heats the dust so that some portion of it rises into the stratosphere. The largest collisions, such as the 10km Chicxulub impactor, can also eject debris from the collision site into space; upon reentry into the atmosphere, the debris heats up enough to spark global fires (Toon, Zahnle, Morrison, Turco, & Covey, 1997). The fires are a major impact in their own right and can send additional smoke into the stratosphere. For nuclear explosions, there is also a fireball and smoke, in this case from the burning of cities or other military targets.
While in the stratosphere, the particulate matter blocks sunlight and destroys ozone (Toon et al., 2007). The ozone loss increases the amount of ultraviolet radiation reaching the surface, causing skin cancer and other harms (Mills, Toon, Turco, Kinnison, & Garcia, 2008). The blocked sunlight causes abrupt cooling of Earth’s surface and in turn reduced precipitation due to a weakened hydrological cycle. The cool, dry, and dark conditions reduce plant growth. Recent studies use modern climate and crop models to examine the effects for a hypothetical IndiaPakistan nuclear war scenario with 100 weapons (50 per side) each of 15KT yield. The studies find agriculture declines in the range of approximately 2% to 50% depending on the crop and location.11 Another study compares the crop data to existing poverty and malnourishment and estimates that the crop declines could threaten starvation for two billion people (Helfand, 2013). However, the aforementioned studies do not account for new nuclear explosion fire simulations that find approximately five times less particulate matter reaching the stratosphere, and correspondingly weaker global environmental effects (Reisner et al., 2018). Note also that the 100 weapon scenario used in these studies is not the largest potential scenario. Larger nuclear wars and large asteroid collisions could cause greater harm. The largest asteroid collisions could even reduce sunlight below the minimum needed for vision (Toon et al., 1997). Asteroid risk analyses have proposed that the global environmental disruption from large collisions could cause one billion deaths (NRC, 2010) or the death of 25% of all humans (Chapman, 2004; Chapman & Morrison, 1994; Morrison, 1992), though these figures have not been rigorously justified (Baum, 2018a).
The harms from asteroid collisions and nuclear wars can also include important secondary effects. The food shortages from severe global environmental disruption could lead to infectious disease outbreaks as public health conditions deteriorate (Helfand, 2013). Law and order could be lost in at least some locations as people struggle for survival (Maher & Baum, 2013). Today’s complex global political-economic system already shows fragility to shocks such as the 2007- 2008 financial crisis (Centeno, Nag, Patterson, Shaver, & Windawi, 2015); an asteroid collision or nuclear war could be an extremely large shock. The systemic consequences of a nuclear war would be further worsened by the likely loss of major world cities that serve as important hubs in the global economy. Even a single detonation in nuclear terrorism would have ripple effects across the global political-economic system (similar to, but likely larger than, the response prompted by the terrorist attacks of 11 September 2001).
It is possible for asteroid collisions to cause nuclear war. An asteroid explosion could be misinterpreted as a nuclear attack, prompting nuclear attack that is believed to be retaliation. For example, the 2013 Chelyabinsk event occurred near an important Russian military installation, prompting concerns about the event’s interpretation (Harris et al., 2015).
The ultimate severity of an asteroid collision or violent nuclear conflict use would depend on how human society reacts. Would the reaction be disciplined and constructive: bury the dead, heal the sick, feed the hungry, and rebuild all that has fallen? Or would the reaction be disorderly and destructive: leave the rubble in place, fight for scarce resources, and descend into minimalist tribalism or worse? Prior studies have identified some key issues, including the viability of trade (Cantor, Henry, & Rayner, 1989) and the self-sufficiency of local communities (Maher & Baum, 2013). However, the issue has received little research attention and remains poorly understood. This leaves considerable uncertainty in the total human harm from an asteroid collision or nuclear weapons use. Previously published point estimates of the human consequences of asteroid collisions12 and nuclear wars (Helfand, 2013) do not account for this uncertainty and are likely to be inaccurate.
Of particular importance are the consequences for future generations, which could vastly outnumber the present generation. If an asteroid collision or nuclear war would cause human extinction, then there would be no future generations. Alternatively, if survivors fail to recover a large population and advanced technological civilization, then future generations would be permanently diminished. The largest long-term factor is whether future generations would colonize space and benefit from its astronomically large amount of resources (Tonn, 1999). However, it is not presently known which asteroid collisions or nuclear wars (if any) would cause the permanent collapse of human civilization and thus the loss of the large future benefits (Baum et al., 2019). Given the enormous stakes, prudent risk management would aim for very low probabilities of permanent collapse (Tonn, 2009).
It should be noted that the severity of violent nuclear conflict could depend on more than just the effects of nuclear explosions, because the overall conflict scenario could include non-nuclear violence. Indeed, it is possible for the nuclear explosions to constitute a relatively small portion of the total severity, as was the case in World War II.
4.4 Risk of Violent Non-Nuclear Conflict
Finally, it is necessary to discuss the risk of violent non-nuclear conflict. Only a small portion of violent non-nuclear conflicts are applicable, specifically the portion affected by nuclear weapons. More precisely, this section discusses non-nuclear conflicts involving one or more countries that possess nuclear weapons at some point during the lifetime of a nuclear deflection program.
Nuclear deterrence theory predicts that nuclear-armed adversaries will not initiate major wars against each other because both sides could be destroyed in a nuclear war. However, the theory does permit limited, small-scale violent conflicts between nuclear-armed countries. These conflicts likely would not involve nuclear weapons. Indeed, nuclear deterrence may even make small violent conflicts more likely, because the countries know that neither side wants to escalate the conflict into major war. This idea is known as the stability-instability paradox: nuclear deterrence brings stability with respect to major wars but instability with respect to minor conflicts. Empirical support for the stability-instability paradox has been found by some research (Rauchhaus, 2009),while other research has found no significant effect of the possession of nuclear weapons on the probability of conflicts of any scale (Bell & Miller, 2015; Gartzke & Jo, 2009).
If countries fully disarm their nuclear arsenals, such that they would never have nuclear weapons again, then there would be no nuclear deterrence to prevent the onset of major wars. A simple risk analysis could assume that the risk of major wars would be comparable to the risk prior to the development of nuclear weapons. The two twentieth century World Wars combined for around 100 million deaths in 50 years,13 suggesting an annualized risk of two million deaths. However, two World Wars do not make for a robust dataset. Indeed, the robustness of these two data points is called into question by historical analysis finding that both world wars might not have occurred in the reasonably plausible event that the 1914 assassination of Archduke Ferdinand had failed (Lebow, 2014). Similarly, another historical analysis finds that the U.S. and Soviet Union would probably not have waged major war against each other even in the absence of nuclear deterrence (Mueller, 1988). Furthermore, these past events are not necessarily applicable to the future conditions of a post-nuclear-disarmament world. To the best of the present author’s knowledge, no studies have analyzed the risk of major wars in a post-nucleardisarmament world. | 8,878 | <h4>They cause global calamity and nuclear winter – comprehensive simulations </h4><p><strong>Baum ’19 </strong>- executive director of the Global Catastrophic Risk Institute, Ph.D in Geography</p><p>Seth Baum, “Risk-Risk Tradeoff Analysis of Nuclear Explosives for Asteroid Deflection,” SSRN Scholarly Paper (Rochester, NY: Social Science Research Network, May 31, 2019), https://papers.ssrn.com/abstract=3397559.</p><p><u>The most severe <mark>asteroid collisions </mark>and nuclear wars can <mark>cause <strong>global environmental effects</u></strong></mark>. <u>The core mechanism is the transport of particulate matter into the stratosphere</u>, <u>where it can spread worldwide and</u> <u>remain aloft for</u> years or <u>decades</u>. <u>Large asteroid <mark>collisions create</u></mark> large quantities of <u>dust and <strong><mark>large fireballs</u></strong></mark>; <u>the fire heats the dust so that some portion of it rises into the stratosphere</u>. <u>The largest <mark>collisions</u></mark>, such as the 10km Chicxulub impactor, can also <u><mark>eject debris</u></mark> from the collision site <u><mark>into space</u></mark>; upon <u><mark>reentry</u></mark> into the atmosphere, the debris <u>heats up enough to <mark>spark <strong>global fires</u></strong></mark> (Toon, Zahnle, Morrison, Turco, & Covey, 1997). The fires <u>are <mark>a <strong>major impact in their own right</strong></mark> and can send additional smoke into the stratosphere</u>. For nuclear explosions, there is also a fireball and smoke, in this case from the burning of cities or other military targets.</p><p>While in the stratosphere, <u>the particulate matter blocks sunlight and destroys ozone</u> (Toon et al., 2007). <u>The <mark>ozone loss</mark> <mark>increases</mark> the amount of <mark>u</mark>ltra<mark>v</mark>iolet <mark>radiation</u></mark> reaching the surface, <u>causing skin cancer and other harms</u> (Mills, Toon, Turco, Kinnison, & Garcia, 2008). T<u>he <mark>blocked sunlight causes abrupt cooling</mark> of Earth’s surface <mark>and</mark> in turn <mark>reduced precipitation</u></mark> due to a weakened hydrological cycle. The <u>cool, dry, and dark <mark>conditions</mark> <mark>reduce plant growth</u></mark>. Recent studies use modern climate and crop models to examine the effects for <u>a hypothetical IndiaPakistan nuclear war scenario with 100 weapons</u> (50 per side) each of 15KT yield. The studies <u>find agriculture declines</u> in the range of <u>approximately</u> 2% to <u>50%</u> depending on the crop and location.11 Another study compares the crop data to existing poverty and malnourishment and estimates that the <u><mark>crop declines</mark> could <mark>threaten <strong>starvation for two billion people</u></strong></mark> (Helfand, 2013). However, the aforementioned studies do not account for new nuclear explosion fire simulations that find approximately five times less particulate matter reaching the stratosphere, and correspondingly weaker global environmental effects (Reisner et al., 2018). Note also that <u><mark>the</mark> 100 weapon <mark>scenario</u></mark> used in these studies <u><strong><mark>is not the largest</mark> potential scenario</u></strong>. Larger nuclear wars and large asteroid collisions could cause greater harm. <u>The <mark>largest</mark> asteroid <mark>collisions could</mark> even <mark>reduce <strong>sunlight below the minimum needed for vision</u></strong></mark> (Toon et al., 1997). Asteroid risk analyses have proposed that <u>the global environmental disruption from <strong>large collisions could cause one billion deaths</u></strong> (NRC, 2010) <u><strong>or</u></strong> the death of <u><strong>25% of all humans</u></strong> (Chapman, 2004; Chapman & Morrison, 1994; Morrison, 1992), though these figures have not been rigorously justified (Baum, 2018a).</p><p>The harms from asteroid collisions and nuclear wars can also include important secondary effects. The <u><strong><mark>food shortages</strong></mark> from severe global environmental disruption could <strong><mark>lead to infectious disease outbreaks</strong></mark> as public health conditions deteriorate</u> (Helfand, 2013). Law and order could be lost in at least some locations as people struggle for survival (Maher & Baum, 2013). <u>Today’s complex global political-economic system already shows fragility to shocks</u> such as the 2007- 2008 financial crisis (Centeno, Nag, Patterson, Shaver, & Windawi, 2015); <u><strong>an asteroid collision</u></strong> or nuclear war <u><strong>could be an extremely large shock</u></strong>. <u>The systemic consequences of a nuclear war would be further worsened by the likely loss of major world cities</u> that serve as important hubs in the global economy. Even a single detonation in nuclear terrorism would have ripple effects across the global political-economic system (similar to, but likely larger than, the response prompted by the terrorist attacks of 11 September 2001).</p><p><u><strong>It is possible for asteroid collisions to cause nuclear war</u></strong>. <u><mark>An</mark> <mark>asteroid</mark> explosion <mark>could be <strong>misinterpreted as a nuclear attack</mark>, <mark>prompting</mark> nuclear attack that is believed to be <mark>retaliation</mark>.</u></strong> For example, the 2013 <u>Chelyabinsk</u> event <u>occurred near an important Russian military installation</u>, prompting concerns about the event’s interpretation (Harris et al., 2015).</p><p>The ultimate severity of an asteroid collision or violent nuclear conflict use would depend on how human society reacts. <u>Would the reaction be disciplined</u> and constructive: bury the dead, heal the sick, feed the hungry, and rebuild all that has fallen<u>?</u> <u>Or would the reaction be disorderly and destructive</u>: leave the rubble in place, fight for scarce resources, and descend into minimalist tribalism or worse<u>?</u> Prior studies have identified some key issues, including the viability of trade (Cantor, Henry, & Rayner, 1989) and the self-sufficiency of local communities (Maher & Baum, 2013). However, the issue has received little research attention and remains poorly understood. <u>This leaves considerable uncertainty in the total human harm from an asteroid collision</u> or nuclear weapons use. Previously <u><strong><mark>published</u></strong></mark> point <u><strong><mark>estimates</strong></mark> of the human consequences</u> of asteroid collisions12 and nuclear wars (Helfand, 2013) <u>do not account for this uncertainty and <strong><mark>are likely to be inaccurate</strong></mark>.</p><p>Of particular importance</u> are the consequences for future generations, <u>which could vastly outnumber the present generation</u>. <u><strong>If an asteroid collision or nuclear war would cause human extinction, then <mark>there would be no future generations</u></strong></mark>. Alternatively, if survivors fail to recover a large population and advanced technological civilization, then <u>future generations would be permanently diminished.</u> The largest long-term factor is whether future generations would colonize space and benefit from its astronomically large amount of resources (Tonn, 1999). However, it is not presently known which asteroid collisions or nuclear wars (if any) would cause the permanent collapse of human civilization and thus the loss of the large future benefits (Baum et al., 2019). Given the enormous stakes, <u><strong><mark>prudent risk management would aim for very low probabilities of permanent collapse</mark> </u></strong>(Tonn, 2009).</p><p>It should be noted that <u>the severity of violent nuclear conflict could depend on more than just the effects of nuclear explosions, because <mark>the</mark> overall <mark>conflict</mark> scenario <mark>could <strong>include non-nuclear violence</strong></mark>. </u>Indeed, <u><strong>it is possible for the <mark>nuclear explosions</mark> to <mark>constitute a relatively small portion of </mark>the <mark>total severity</u></strong></mark>, as was the case in World War II.</p><p>4.4 Risk of Violent Non-Nuclear Conflict</p><p>Finally, <u>it is necessary to discuss the risk of violent non-nuclear conflict</u>. Only a small portion of violent non-nuclear conflicts are applicable, specifically the portion affected by nuclear weapons. More precisely, this section discusses non-nuclear conflicts involving one or more countries that possess nuclear weapons at some point during the lifetime of a nuclear deflection program.</p><p><u>Nuclear deterrence</u> theory predicts that nuclear-armed adversaries will not initiate major wars against each other because both sides could be destroyed in a nuclear war. However, the <u>theory <strong>does permit limited, small-scale violent conflicts</strong> between nuclear-armed countries</u>. These <u>conflicts</u> likely <u>would not involve nuclear weapons.</u> Indeed, <u>nuclear deterrence may</u> even <u>make</u> <u>small</u> violent <u>conflicts <strong>more likely</u></strong>, because the countries know that neither side wants to escalate the conflict into major war. This idea is <u>known as the stability-instability paradox</u>: nuclear deterrence <u>brings</u> stability with respect to major wars but <u>instability with respect to minor conflicts. Empirical support</u> for the stability-instability paradox <u>has been found by some research</u> (Rauchhaus, 2009),while other research has found no significant effect of the possession of nuclear weapons on the probability of conflicts of any scale (Bell & Miller, 2015; Gartzke & Jo, 2009).</p><p>If countries fully disarm their nuclear arsenals, such that they would never have nuclear weapons again, then there would be no nuclear deterrence to prevent the onset of major wars. A simple risk analysis could assume that the risk of major wars would be comparable to the risk prior to the development of nuclear weapons. The two twentieth century World Wars combined for around 100 million deaths in 50 years,13 suggesting an annualized risk of two million deaths. However, two World Wars do not make for a robust dataset. Indeed, the robustness of these two data points is called into question by historical analysis finding that both world wars might not have occurred in the reasonably plausible event that the 1914 assassination of Archduke Ferdinand had failed (Lebow, 2014). Similarly, another historical analysis finds that the U.S. and Soviet Union would probably not have waged major war against each other even in the absence of nuclear deterrence (Mueller, 1988). Furthermore, these past events are not necessarily applicable to the future conditions of a post-nuclear-disarmament world. To the best of the present author’s knowledge, no studies have analyzed the risk of major wars in a post-nucleardisarmament world.</p> | Asteroids 1AC | Asteroids Advantage | Plan | 336,137 | 283 | 80,896 | ./documents/ndtceda19/Georgetown/BePi/Georgetown-Bernstein-Piliero-Aff-Wake-Round8.docx | 611,456 | A | Wake | 8 | Louisville BY | Geoff Lundeen | 1AC Asteroids
1NC Black Rage K
2NR K | ndtceda19/Georgetown/BePi/Georgetown-Bernstein-Piliero-Aff-Wake-Round8.docx | null | 51,812 | BePi | Georgetown BePi | null | Da..... | Be..... | Ra..... | Pi..... | 19,253 | Georgetown | Georgetown | null | null | 1,009 | ndtceda19 | NDT/CEDA 2019-20 | 2,019 | cx | college | 2 |
1,037,254 | A cautious futurity is the only way to confront anti-queer violence. The alternative forecloses alternative futures and dooms queer folks with a desire for better to the status quo. | Manalansan ’15 | Manalansan ’15 Martin F. Manalansan IV - Associate Professor of all of the following at The University of Illinois: Gender and Women's Studies, Asian American Studies, Anthropology, Latin American and Caribbean Studies, LAS Global Studies, Center for East Asian and Pacific Studies, and Center for Global Studies. The author holds a Ph.D. in Social Anthropology from The University of Rochester and studied philosophy, Asian Studies and anthropology at the University of the Philippines. As part of claims about futurity, the author references lived excahnges with queer trans women of color. The author also references concurring professional exchanges with David L. Eng, Professor of English at the University of Pennsylvania; Gayatri Gopinath, who is an associate professor of Social and Cultural Analysis and director of Asian/Pacific/American Studies at New York University.; Roderick Ferguson, who is a professor of African American and Gender and Women's Studies in the African American Studies Department at the University of Illinois, Chicago; Chandan Reddy, who is an Associate Professor of Gender, Women & Sexuality Studies at the University of Washington; and the late José Esteban Muñoz, was an American academic in the fields of performance studies, visual culture, queer theory, cultural studies, and critical theory; “A Question from Bruno Latour” This article is part of the series Queer Futures. Fieldsights - Theorizing the Contemporary, Cultural Anthropology Online, July 21, 2015 - https://www.culanth.org/fieldsights/703-a-question-from-bruno-latour | However, there was a general sense that the issue of “no future” comes from a vantage point and a comfortable perch of privilege. As a scholar immersed in the plight of queers of color, futurity is not just a possibility but a necessity. To paraphrase queer-of-color critique colleagues we cannot not think of a future it is the very fuel of existence that animates energies feelings, and other bodily capacities. The promise of queer both as a stance and as a field of study is precisely in its hopeful dimensions. Queer is constituted by a yearning and a longing for something better than what is here right now It is a horizon that we are drawn to and which is not yet here. Consider the group of undocumented immigrant queers of color in New York City whose lives I have been following for years. they live in precarious conditions but they live moments that showcase fabulosity These moments provide some way for them to think of another day While this might be called naïve hopefulness thinking of a future that is an alternative to the present is a potent way to think beyond and against the status quo to plant the seed for transformation. In other words, there is a political potential to queer futurity. we need to complicate and unravel the negativity inherent in the “no future” stance and to be open to the various alternative ways futures can be imagined particularly by those in the margins. | However, there was a general sense that the issue of “no future” comes from a comfortable perch of privilege. As a scholar immersed in the plight of queers of color, futurity is not just a possibility but a necessity. we cannot not think of a future it is the very fuel of existence that animates energies The promise of queer is precisely in its hopeful dimensions. Consider undocumented immigrant queers of color they live in precarious conditions but they live moments that showcase fabulosity These moments provide some way for them to think of another day While this might be called naïve hopefulness thinking of a future that is an alternative to the present is a potent way to think beyond and against the status quo to plant the seed for transformation. we need to unravel the negativity inherent in the “no future” stance | My response to the question of “no future” comes from my encounters, engagements, and conversations with colleagues under the aegis of queer-of-color critique, scholars like David Eng, Gayatri Gopinath, Roderick Ferguson, Chandan Reddy, and the late José Esteban Muñoz, among others. We appreciate the renegade antireproductive stance of the “no future” camp, which states that we should not subscribe to a future that is entrenched in heteropatriarchal dreams of marriage and procreation. However, there was a general sense among us that the issue of “no future” comes from a vantage point and a comfortable perch of privilege. As a scholar invested and immersed in the plight of queers of color, futurity is not just a possibility but a necessity. To paraphrase my queer-of-color critique colleagues, we cannot not think of a future—it is the very fuel of existence, the pivot that animates and propels energies, performances, feelings, and other bodily capacities. The promise and peril of queer, both as a stance and as a field of study, is precisely in its anticipatory and hopeful dimensions. Queer is constituted by a yearning and a longing for something better than what is here right now. It is, as Muñoz would say, a horizon that we are drawn to and which is not yet here. Consider the group of undocumented immigrant queers of color in New York City whose lives I have been following for years. Dwelling in cramped domiciles and working in contingent jobs, there is very little to witness in their lives that suggests a kind of gay/lesbian triumphalism or the bright markers of the new normal. In fact, they live in precarious conditions but—a very important caveat—they live in moments that showcase fleeting gestures and images of fabulosity set amidst the squalor and mess of their lives. These moments, while fleeting, provide some way for them to think of another day, giving them a brief glimpse of a time and a place where there are sequined gowns, plush salons, and many sparkling things. While this might be called naïve hopefulness, thinking of a future that is an alternative to the present is a potent way to think beyond and against the status quo—to plant the seed for social transformation. In other words, there is a political potential to queer futurity. Or, to put it another way, we need to complicate and unravel the negativity inherent in the “no future” stance and to be open to the various alternative ways a future or futures can be imagined, particularly by those in the margins. Otherwise, we can all just pack our bags, go back home, put on some makeup, close the door, and hide under the bedcovers. | 2,637 | <h4>A cautious futurity is the only way to confront anti-queer violence. The alternative forecloses alternative futures and dooms queer folks with a desire for better to the status quo.</h4><p><strong>Manalansan ’15 </strong>Martin F. Manalansan IV - Associate Professor of all of the following at The University of Illinois: Gender and Women's Studies, Asian American Studies, Anthropology, Latin American and Caribbean Studies, LAS Global Studies, Center for East Asian and Pacific Studies, and Center for Global Studies. The author holds a Ph.D. in Social Anthropology from The University of Rochester and studied philosophy, Asian Studies and anthropology at the University of the Philippines. As part of claims about futurity, the author references lived excahnges with queer trans women of color. The author also references concurring professional exchanges with David L. Eng, Professor of English at the University of Pennsylvania; Gayatri Gopinath, who is an associate professor of Social and Cultural Analysis and director of Asian/Pacific/American Studies at New York University.; Roderick Ferguson, who is a professor of African American and Gender and Women's Studies in the African American Studies Department at the University of Illinois, Chicago; Chandan Reddy, who is an Associate Professor of Gender, Women & Sexuality Studies at the University of Washington; and the late José Esteban Muñoz, was an American academic in the fields of performance studies, visual culture, queer theory, cultural studies, and critical theory; “A Question from Bruno Latour” This article is part of the series Queer Futures. Fieldsights - Theorizing the Contemporary, Cultural Anthropology Online, July 21, 2015 - https://www.culanth.org/fieldsights/703-a-question-from-bruno-latour</p><p>My response to the question of “no future” comes from my encounters, engagements, and conversations with colleagues under the aegis of queer-of-color critique, scholars like David Eng, Gayatri Gopinath, Roderick Ferguson, Chandan Reddy, and the late José Esteban Muñoz, among others. We appreciate the renegade antireproductive stance of the “no future” camp, which states that we should not subscribe to a future that is entrenched in heteropatriarchal dreams of marriage and procreation. <u><strong><mark>However, there was a general sense</u></strong></mark> among us <u><strong><mark>that the issue of “no future” comes from a </mark>vantage point and a</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>comfortable perch of privilege.</u></strong></mark> <u><strong><mark>As a scholar</u></strong></mark> invested and <u><strong><mark>immersed in the plight of queers of color,</u></strong></mark> <u><strong><mark>futurity is not just a possibility but a necessity.</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>To paraphrase</u></strong> my <u><strong>queer-of-color critique colleagues</u></strong>, <u><strong><mark>we cannot not think of a future</u></strong></mark>—<u><strong><mark>it is the very fuel of existence</u></strong></mark>, the pivot <u><strong><mark>that animates</u></strong></mark> and propels <u><strong><mark>energies</u></strong></mark>, performances, <u><strong>feelings, and other bodily capacities. <mark>The promise</u></strong></mark> and peril <u><strong><mark>of queer</u></strong></mark>, <u><strong>both as a stance and as a field of study</u></strong>, <u><strong><mark>is precisely in its</u></strong></mark> anticipatory and <u><strong><mark>hopeful dimensions.</mark> Queer is constituted by a yearning and a longing for something better than what is here right now</u></strong>. <u><strong>It is</u></strong>, as Muñoz would say, <u><strong>a horizon that we are drawn to and which is not yet here.</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>Consider</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>the group of</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>undocumented immigrant queers of color</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>in New York City whose lives I have been following for years.</u></strong> Dwelling in cramped domiciles and working in contingent jobs, there is very little to witness in their lives that suggests a kind of gay/lesbian triumphalism or the bright markers of the new normal. In fact, <u><strong><mark>they live in precarious conditions but</u></strong></mark>—a very important caveat—<u><strong><mark>they live</u></strong></mark> in <u><strong><mark>moments that showcase</u></strong></mark> fleeting gestures and images of <u><strong><mark>fabulosity</u></strong></mark> set amidst the squalor and mess of their lives. <u><strong><mark>These moments</u></strong></mark>, while fleeting, <u><strong><mark>provide some way for them to think of another day</u></strong></mark>, giving them a brief glimpse of a time and a place where there are sequined gowns, plush salons, and many sparkling things. <u><strong><mark>While this might be called naïve hopefulness</u></strong></mark>, <u><strong><mark>thinking of a future that is an alternative to the present is a potent way to think beyond and against the status quo</u></strong></mark>—<u><strong><mark>to plant the seed for</mark> </u></strong>social<u><strong> <mark>transformation.</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>In other words, there is a political potential to queer futurity.</u></strong> Or, to put it another way, <u><strong><mark>we need to</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>complicate and</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>unravel the negativity inherent in the “no future” stance</mark> and to be open to the various alternative ways</u></strong> a future or <u><strong>futures can be imagined</u></strong>, <u><strong>particularly by those in the margins.</u></strong> Otherwise, we can all just pack our bags, go back home, put on some makeup, close the door, and hide under the bedcovers. </p> | null | Off | 2ac k proper f/l | 94,370 | 151 | 25,105 | ./documents/ndtceda21/WichitaState/PhHi/Wichita%20State-Phillips-Hinecker-Aff-Kentucky-Round5.docx | 628,005 | A | Kentucky | 5 | GMU IJ | Eric Morris | 1AC - patents
1NC - queerness and case
2NR - queerness | ndtceda21/WichitaState/PhHi/Wichita%20State-Phillips-Hinecker-Aff-Kentucky-Round5.docx | null | 52,950 | PhHi | Wichita State PhHi | null | Bo..... | Ph..... | Al..... | Hi..... | 19,433 | WichitaState | Wichita State | null | null | 1,011 | ndtceda21 | NDT/CEDA 2021-22 | 2,021 | cx | college | 2 |
1,116,149 | Nuclear war | Cribb 16 | Dr. Julian Cribb 16, Adjunct Professor of Science Communication at the University of Technology Sydney and Fellow of the Australian Academy of Technological Sciences and Engineering (ATSE), Principal of Julian Cribb & Associates, “Surviving the 21st Century: Humanity's Ten Great Challenges and How We Can Overcome Them”, p. 74-75 | ‘fish wars’) have erupted on numerous occasions These fights are almost always over the fundamentals of human survival and tend to originate as civil conflicts, which then spiral out of control to embroil neighbour states and even the superpowers
war is liable to increase in proportion to the scarcity of food The possibiity that some of these conflicts will involve the discharge of chemical, biological or nuclear weapons cannot be discounted so-called “limited nuclear war” in any part of the world can escalate to a full-scale nuclear exchange among the big nuclear powers.” nuclear war is possible | ‘fish wars’ erupt These originate as civil then spiral out of control to embroil superpowers
war increase in proportion to scarcity of food conflicts will involve bio or nuclear weapons limited war” in any part can escalate to full-scale nuclear exchange among big powers | In 1999 the Oslo Peace Research Institute issued a ground-breaking paper by Indra de Soysa and Nils Gleditsch which drew attention to the fact that, in the first decade of the post-Cold War era, most conflicts began with develop- ment failure and contests between the different players over those fundamen- tal resources for life: food, land and water. “The new internal wars, extremely bloody in terms of civilian casualties, reflect subsistence crises and are largely apolitical,” they said (De Soya and Gleditsch 1999). This represented a chal- lenge to the long-held academic view that scarcity is a product of war—rather than war a being product of scarcity. In fact, humans have always contested key resources vi et armis—and politics, religion, patriotism and ethnicity are just the way we tend to marshal ourselves into opposing groups around them. Peter Gleick’s work on water conflicts lends substance to the warnings of two UN chiefs, Boutros Boutros-Ghali and Ban Ki-Moon, of the increased danger of wars breaking out over this indispensable resource as scarcity takes hold. ‘Food wars’ (including so-called ‘fish wars’) have erupted on numerous occasions in Africa—where the Rwandan genocide and drawn-out bloody con- flicts in Darfur and the Horn of Africa are particular examples—but also in Central America and Asia (Messer et al. 1998). These fights are almost always over the fundamentals of human survival and tend to originate as civil conflicts, which then spiral out of control to embroil neighbour states and even the superpowers.
In the emerging era of resource instability, described in Chap. 3, the risk of war is liable to increase in proportion to the scarcity of essential resources, be they water, farm land, food itself, oil, gas or strategic minerals. The possibiity that some of these conflicts will involve the discharge of chemical, biological or nuclear weapons cannot be discounted. For example, in their Age of Consequences report, Kurt Campbell and colleagues at the US Center for Strategic and International Studies (CSIS) foreshadowed that with the famines and global disruption arising out of severe climate change (2.6 °C, in their sce- nario) “It is clear that even nuclear war cannot be excluded as a political consequence. Moreover, so-called “limited nuclear war” in any part of the world can escalate to a full-scale nuclear exchange among the big nuclear powers.” With catastrophic change of 5° or more, “The probability of conflict between two destabilized nuclear powers would seem high.” Furthermore “Armed conflict between nations over resources and even territory, such as the Nile and tributaries, is likely, and nuclear war is possible” (Campbell et al. 2007). | 2,716 | <h4>Nuclear war</h4><p>Dr. Julian <strong>Cribb 16</strong>, Adjunct Professor of Science Communication at the University of Technology Sydney and Fellow of the Australian Academy of Technological Sciences and Engineering (ATSE), Principal of Julian Cribb & Associates, “Surviving the 21st Century: Humanity's Ten Great Challenges and How We Can Overcome Them”, p. 74-75</p><p>In 1999 the Oslo Peace Research Institute issued a ground-breaking paper by Indra de Soysa and Nils Gleditsch which drew attention to the fact that, in the first decade of the post-Cold War era, most conflicts began with develop- ment failure and contests between the different players over those fundamen- tal resources for life: food, land and water. “The new internal wars, extremely bloody in terms of civilian casualties, reflect subsistence crises and are largely apolitical,” they said (De Soya and Gleditsch 1999). This represented a chal- lenge to the long-held academic view that scarcity is a product of war—rather than war a being product of scarcity. In fact, humans have always contested key resources vi et armis—and politics, religion, patriotism and ethnicity are just the way we tend to marshal ourselves into opposing groups around them. Peter Gleick’s work on water conflicts lends substance to the warnings of two UN chiefs, Boutros Boutros-Ghali and Ban Ki-Moon, of the increased danger of wars breaking out over this indispensable resource as scarcity takes hold. ‘Food wars’ (including so-called <u><strong><mark>‘fish wars’</strong></mark>) have <strong><mark>erupt</strong></mark>ed on numerous occasions</u> in Africa—where the Rwandan genocide and drawn-out bloody con- flicts in Darfur and the Horn of Africa are particular examples—but also in Central America and Asia (Messer et al. 1998). <u><mark>These</mark> fights are almost always over the fundamentals of human survival and tend to <mark>originate as <strong>civil</strong></mark> conflicts, which <mark>then <strong>spiral</strong> out of control to <strong>embroil</mark> neighbour states</strong> and even the <strong><mark>superpowers</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>In the emerging era of resource instability, described in Chap. 3, the risk of <u><mark>war</mark> is liable to <mark>increase in proportion to</mark> the <mark>scarcity of</u></mark> essential resources, be they water, farm land, <u><mark>food</u></mark> itself, oil, gas or strategic minerals. <u>The possibiity that some of these <mark>conflicts will involve</mark> the discharge of chemical, <strong><mark>bio</strong></mark>logical <mark>or <strong>nuclear weapons</strong></mark> cannot be discounted</u>. For example, in their Age of Consequences report, Kurt Campbell and colleagues at the US Center for Strategic and International Studies (CSIS) foreshadowed that with the famines and global disruption arising out of severe climate change (2.6 °C, in their sce- nario) “It is clear that even nuclear war cannot be excluded as a political consequence. Moreover, <u>so-called “<mark>limited</mark> nuclear <mark>war” in <strong>any part</strong></mark> of the world <mark>can <strong>escalate</strong> to</mark> a <strong><mark>full-scale nuclear exchange</strong> among</mark> the <strong><mark>big</mark> nuclear <mark>powers</strong></mark>.”</u> With catastrophic change of 5° or more, “The probability of conflict between two destabilized nuclear powers would seem high.” Furthermore “Armed conflict between nations over resources and even territory, such as the Nile and tributaries, is likely, and <u><strong>nuclear war</strong> is possible</u>” (Campbell et al. 2007).</p> | 1ac – waste management v1 | null | 1ac – waste | 7,109 | 124 | 26,666 | ./documents/hspolicy21/GlenbrookNorth/WaYi/Glenbrook%20North-Wallace-Yin-Aff-University%20of%20Michigan-Round3.docx | 746,675 | A | University of Michigan | 3 | MBA PC | Jordan Di | 1ac - waste management
1nc - federalism da states cp reverse guidance cp adv cp business confidence da t cessation
2nc - states cp adv cp reverse guidance cp
1nr - federalism da
2nr - reverse guidance cp | hspolicy21/GlenbrookNorth/WaYi/Glenbrook%20North-Wallace-Yin-Aff-University%20of%20Michigan-Round3.docx | null | 63,719 | WaYi | Glenbrook North WaYi | null | Pa..... | Wa..... | Fi..... | Yi..... | 21,975 | GlenbrookNorth | Glenbrook North | IL | null | 1,020 | hspolicy21 | HS Policy 2021-22 | 2,021 | cx | hs | 2 |
2,751,943 | C/I – Reduce means to diminish in size – it includes targeted reductions | Ingram, 88 | Ingram, 88 – law student (Cindi M. Ingram, Plaintiff's Right to Recover from Non-Settling Tortfeasor When Settlement with Joint Tortfeasor Exceeds the Jury Award, 53 Mo. L. Rev. (1988) Available at: http://scholarship.law.missouri.edu/mlr/vol53/iss2/8 | Consideration of the "plain meaning" of the words used is a basic principle of determining legislative intent The court discussed the "plain meaning" of reduce as meaning "to diminish in size, amount, extent or number to bring down a quantity | Consideration of the "plain meaning is a basic principle reduce mean "to diminish in size | In answering this question, the Hampton court turned to various principles for guidance. The court looked first to the "plain meaning" of the statute.6 " Interpretation of a statute involves ascertaining the legislative intent behind the enactment of the statute. Consideration of the "plain meaning" of the words used in the statute is a basic principle of statutory construction in determining legislative intent.6 7 The Hampton court discussed the "plain meaning" of the words "reduce" and "claim" in reaching its construction of the statute. The court referred to the dictionary definition of "reduce" as meaning "to diminish in size, amount, extent or number; to make small or to lower, bring down or to change the denomination of a quantity." 68 The court then judicially defined "claim" as "the amount of damages as determined by an impartial fact finder - the jury."' | 875 | <h4>C/I – Reduce means to diminish in size – it includes targeted reductions</h4><p><strong>Ingram, 88 </strong>– law student (Cindi M. Ingram, Plaintiff's Right to Recover from Non-Settling Tortfeasor When Settlement with Joint Tortfeasor Exceeds the Jury Award, 53 Mo. L. Rev. (1988) Available at: http://scholarship.law.missouri.edu/mlr/vol53/iss2/8</p><p>In answering this question, the Hampton court turned to various principles for guidance. The court looked first to the "plain meaning" of the statute.6 " Interpretation of a statute involves ascertaining the legislative intent behind the enactment of the statute. <u><mark>Consideration of the "plain meaning</mark>" of the words used</u> in the statute <u><mark>is a basic principle</mark> of</u> statutory construction in <u>determining legislative intent</u>.6 7 <u>The</u> Hampton <u>court discussed</u> <u>the "plain meaning" of </u>the words "<u><mark>reduce</u></mark>" and "claim" in reaching its construction of the statute. The court referred to the dictionary definition of "reduce" <u>as <mark>mean</mark>ing <mark>"to diminish in size</mark>, amount, extent or number</u>; <u>to</u> make small or to lower, <u>bring down</u> or to change the denomination of <u>a quantity</u>." 68 The court then judicially defined "claim" as "the amount of damages as determined by an impartial fact finder - the jury."'</p> | 2ac | T | null | 76,025 | 420 | 87,312 | ./documents/hspolicy19/MontgomeryBell/BaMe/Montgomery%20Bell-Barton-Meacham-Aff-Berkeley-Semis.docx | 717,195 | A | Berkeley | Semis | Jesuit HN | Rengarajan, Rice, Kochman | 1AC - Taiwan
2NR - Appeasement Turn | hspolicy19/MontgomeryBell/BaMe/Montgomery%20Bell-Barton-Meacham-Aff-Berkeley-Semis.docx | null | 61,133 | BaMe | Montgomery Bell BaMe | null | Ad..... | Ba..... | Sa..... | Me..... | 21,322 | MontgomeryBell | Montgomery Bell | TN | null | 1,018 | hspolicy19 | HS Policy 2019-20 | 2,019 | cx | hs | 2 |
2,702,368 | Dominant moral calculus always prioritizes future suffering in the face of ongoing structural violence. | Olson 2015 | Olson 2015 – prof of geography @ UNC Chapel Hill (Elizabeth, ‘Geography and Ethics I: Waiting and Urgency,’ Progress in Human Geography, vol. 39 no. 4, pp. 517-526) | the body is increasingly set at odds with large-scale future events of forecasted suffering large-scale threats of future suffering distort moral reasoning the urgent body must be bypassed because there are bigger scales to worry about Bodies that are currently suffering cannot be urgent, because they are excluded from the potential collectivity that could be suffering everywhere in some future time. the urgent body is increasingly obscured through technical planning The predominant characteristic is a ‘built-in bias for action’ The urgent body is at best an eventuality the urgent body becomes , a non sequitur within societies that will always be more urgent Waiting can demobilize radical reform, depoliticizing ‘the insurrectionary possibilities of the present by delaying the revolutionary imperative to a future moment that is forever drifting towards infinity’ Waiting can function as a spatial technology of the elite and powerful, mobilized not only for the purpose of governing individuals, but also to retain claims over moral urgency Insisting that a suffering body cannot wait, has the ethical effect of drawing it into consideration alongside the scope of large-scale futures Saving the world should require a debate about whose world is being saved, when, and at what cost – and this requires a debate about what really cannot wait 6), they may also serve as fertile ground for radical critique, a truly fierce urgency for now. | large-scale threats distort moral reasoning the urgent body must be bypassed because there are bigger scales Bodies currently suffering cannot be urgent, because they are excluded from collectivity that could be suffering Waiting can function as a technology of the elite mobilized for the purpose of governing individuals to retain claims over moral urgency Saving the world should require a debate about whose world is being saved, when, and at what cost – and this requires a debate about what cannot wait | Though toileting might be thought of as a special case of bodily urgency, geographic research suggests that the body is increasingly set at odds with larger scale ethical concerns, especially large-scale future events of forecasted suffering. Emergency planning is a particularly good example in which the large-scale threats of future suffering can distort moral reasoning. Žižek (2006) lightly develops this point in the context of the war on terror, where in the presence of fictitious and real ticking clocks and warning systems, the urgent body must be bypassed because there are bigger scales to worry about: What does this all-pervasive sense of urgency mean ethically? The pressure of events is so overbearing, the stakes are so high, that they necessitate a suspension of ordinary ethical concerns. After all, displaying moral qualms when the lives of millions are at stake plays into the hands of the enemy. (Žižek, 2006) In the presence of large-scale future emergency, the urgency to secure the state, the citizenry, the economy, or the climate creates new scales and new temporal orders of response (see Anderson, 2010; Baldwin, 2012; Dalby, 2013; Morrissey, 2012), many of which treat the urgent body as impulsive and thus requiring management. McDonald’s (2013) analysis of three interconnected discourses of ‘climate security’ illustrates how bodily urgency in climate change is also recast as a menacing impulse that might require exclusion from moral reckoning. The logics of climate security, especially those related to national security, ‘can encourage perverse political responses that not only fail to respond effectively to climate change but may present victims of it as a threat’ (McDonald, 2013: 49). Bodies that are currently suffering cannot be urgent, because they are excluded from the potential collectivity that could be suffering everywhere in some future time. Similar bypassing of existing bodily urgency is echoed in writing about violent securitization, such as drone warfare (Shaw and Akhter, 2012), and also in intimate scales like the street and the school, especially in relation to race (Mitchell, 2009; Young et al., 2014). As large-scale urgent concerns are institutionalized, the urgent body is increasingly obscured through technical planning and coordination (Anderson and Adey, 2012). The predominant characteristic of this institutionalization of large-scale emergency is a ‘built-in bias for action’ (Wuthnow, 2010: 212) that circumvents contingencies. The urgent body is at best an assumed eventuality, one that will likely require another state of waiting, such as triage (e.g. Greatbach et al., 2005). Amin (2013) cautions that in much of the West, governmental need to provide evidence of laissez-faire governing on the one hand, and assurance of strength in facing a threatening future on the other, produces ‘just-in-case preparedness’ (Amin, 2013: 151) of neoliberal risk management policies. In the US, ‘personal ingenuity’ is built into emergency response at the expense of the poor and vulnerable for whom ‘[t]he difference between abjection and bearable survival’ (Amin, 2013: 153) will not be determined by emergency planning, but in the material infrastructure of the city. In short, the urgencies of the body provide justifications for social exclusion of the most marginalized based on impulse and perceived threat, while large-scale future emergencies effectively absorb the deliberative power of urgency into the institutions of preparedness and risk avoidance. Žižek references Arendt’s (2006) analysis of the banality of evil to explain the current state of ethical reasoning under the war on terror, noting that people who perform morally reprehensible actions under the conditions of urgency assume a ‘tragic-ethic grandeur’ (Žižek, 2006) by sacrificing their own morality for the good of the state. But his analysis fails to note that bodies are today so rarely legitimate sites for claiming urgency. In the context of the assumed priority of the large-scale future emergency, the urgent body becomes literally nonsense, a non sequitur within societies, states and worlds that will always be more urgent. If the important ethical work of urgency has been to identify that which must not wait, then the capture of the power and persuasiveness of urgency by large-scale future emergencies has consequences for the kinds of normative arguments we can raise on behalf of urgent bodies. How, then, might waiting compare as a normative description and critique in our own urgent time? Waiting can be categorized according to its purpose or outcome (see Corbridge, 2004; Gray, 2011), but it also modifies the place of the individual in society and her importance. As Ramdas (2012: 834) writes, ‘waiting … produces hierarchies which segregate people and places into those which matter and those which do not’. The segregation of waiting might produce effects that counteract suffering, however, and Jeffery (2008: 957) explains that though the ‘politics of waiting’ can be repressive, it can also engender creative political engagement. In his research with educated unemployed Jat youth who spend days and years waiting for desired employment, Jeffery finds that ‘the temporal suffering and sense of ambivalence experienced by young men can generate cultural and political experiments that, in turn, have marked social and spatial effects’ (Jeffery, 2010: 186). Though this is not the same as claiming normative neutrality for waiting, it does suggest that waiting is more ethically ambivalent and open than urgency. In other contexts, however, our descriptions of waiting indicate a strong condemnation of its effects upon the subjects of study. Waiting can demobilize radical reform, depoliticizing ‘the insurrectionary possibilities of the present by delaying the revolutionary imperative to a future moment that is forever drifting towards infinity’ (Springer, 2014: 407). Yonucu’s (2011) analysis of the self-destructive activities of disrespected working-class youth in Istanbul suggests that this sense of infinite waiting can lead not only to depoliticization, but also to a disbelief in the possibility of a future self of any value. Waiting, like urgency, can undermine the possibility of self-care two-fold, first by making people wait for essential needs, and again by reinforcing that waiting is ‘[s]omething to be ashamed of because it may be noted or taken as evidence of indolence or low status, seen as a symptom of rejection or a signal to exclude’ (Bauman, 2004: 109). This is why Auyero (2012) suggests that waiting creates an ideal state subject, providing ‘temporal processes in and through which political subordination is produced’ (Auyero, 2012: loc. 90; see also Secor, 2007). Furthermore, Auyero notes, it is not only political subordination, but the subjective effect of waiting that secures domination, as citizens and non-citizens find themselves ‘waiting hopefully and then frustratedly for others to make decisions, and in effect surrendering to the authority of others’ (Auyero, 2012: loc. 123). Waiting can therefore function as a potentially important spatial technology of the elite and powerful, mobilized not only for the purpose of governing individuals, but also to retain claims over moral urgency. But there is growing resistance to the capture of claims of urgency by the elite, and it is important to note that even in cases where the material conditions of containment are currently impenetrable, arguments based on human value are at the forefront of reclaiming urgency for the body. In detention centers, clandestine prisons, state borders and refugee camps, geographers point to ongoing struggles against the ethical impossibility of bodily urgency and a rejection of states of waiting (see Conlon, 2011; Darling, 2009, 2011; Garmany, 2012; Mountz et al., 2013; Schuster, 2011). Ramakrishnan’s (2014) analysis of a Delhi resettlement colony and Shewly’s (2013) discussion of the enclave between India and Bangladesh describe people who refuse to give up their own status as legitimately urgent, even in the context of larger scale politics. Similarly, Tyler’s (2013) account of desperate female detainees stripping off their clothes to expose their humanness and suffering in the Yarl’s Wood Immigration Removal Centre in the UK suggests that demands for recognition are not just about politics, but also about the acknowledgement of humanness and the irrevocable possibility of being that which cannot wait. The continued existence of places like Yarl’s Wood and similar institutions in the USA nonetheless points to the challenge of exposing the urgent body as a moral priority when it is so easily hidden from view, and also reminds us that our research can help to explain the relationships between normative dimensions and the political and social conditions of struggle. In closing, geographic depictions of waiting do seem to evocatively describe otherwise obscured suffering (e.g. Bennett, 2011), but it is striking how rarely these descriptions also use the language of urgency. Given the discussion above, what might be accomplished – and risked – by incorporating urgency more overtly and deliberately into our discussions of waiting, surplus and abandoned bodies? Urgency can clarify the implicit but understated ethical consequences and normativity associated with waiting, and encourage explicit discussion about harmful suffering. Waiting can be productive or unproductive for radical praxis, but urgency compels and requires response. Geographers could be instrumental in reclaiming the ethical work of urgency in ways that leave it open for critique, clarifying common spatial misunderstandings and representations. There is good reason to be thoughtful in this process, since moral outrage towards inhumanity can itself obscure differentiated experiences of being human, dividing up ‘those for whom we feel urgent unreasoned concern and those whose lives and deaths simply do not touch us, or do not appear as lives at all’ (Butler, 2009: 50). But when the urgent body is rendered as only waiting, both materially and discursively, it is just as easily cast as impulsive, disgusting, animalistic (see also McKittrick, 2006). Feminist theory insists that the urgent body, whose encounters of violence are ‘usually framed as private, apolitical and mundane’ (Pain, 2014: 8), are as deeply political, public, and exceptional as other forms of violence (Phillips, 2008; Pratt, 2005). Insisting that a suffering body, now, is that which cannot wait, has the ethical effect of drawing it into consideration alongside the political, public and exceptional scope of large-scale futures. It may help us insist on the body, both as a single unit and a plurality, as a legitimate scale of normative priority and social care. In this report, I have explored old and new reflections on the ethical work of urgency and waiting. Geographic research suggests a contemporary popular bias towards the urgency of large-scale futures, institutionalized in ways that further obscure and discredit the urgencies of the body. This bias also justifies the production of new waiting places in our material landscape, places like the detention center and the waiting room. In some cases, waiting is normatively neutral, even providing opportunities for alternative politics. In others, the technologies of waiting serve to manage potentially problematic bodies, leading to suspended suffering and even to extermination (e.g. Wright, 2013). One of my aims has been to suggest that moral reasoning is important both because it exposes normative biases against subjugated people, and because it potentially provides routes toward struggle where claims to urgency seem to foreclose the possibilities of alleviation of suffering. Saving the world still should require a debate about whose world is being saved, when, and at what cost – and this requires a debate about what really cannot wait. My next report will extend some of these concerns by reviewing how feelings of urgency, as well as hope, fear, and other emotions, have played a role in geography and ethical reasoning. I conclude, however, by pulling together past and present. In 1972, Gilbert White asked why geographers were not engaging ‘the truly urgent questions’ (1972: 101) such as racial repression, decaying cities, economic inequality, and global environmental destruction. His question highlights just how much the discipline has changed, but it is also unnerving in its echoes of our contemporary problems. Since White’s writing, our moral reasoning has been stretched to consider the future body and the more-than-human, alongside the presently urgent body – topics and concerns that I have not taken up in this review but which will provide their own new possibilities for urgent concerns. My own hope presently is drawn from an acknowledgement that the temporal characteristics of contemporary capitalism can be interrupted in creative ways (Sharma, 2014), with the possibility of squaring the urgent body with our large-scale future concerns. Temporal alternatives already exist in ongoing and emerging revolutions and the disruption of claims of cycles and circular political processes (e.g. Lombard, 2013; Reyes, 2012). Though calls for urgency will certainly be used to obscure evasion of responsibility (e.g. Gilmore, 2008: 56, fn 6), they may also serve as fertile ground for radical critique, a truly fierce urgency for now. | 13,509 | <h4>Dominant moral calculus always prioritizes future suffering in the face of ongoing structural violence.</h4><p><strong>Olson 2015</strong> – prof of geography @ UNC Chapel Hill (Elizabeth, ‘Geography and Ethics I: Waiting and Urgency,’ Progress in Human Geography, vol. 39 no. 4, pp. 517-526)</p><p>Though toileting might be thought of as a special case of bodily urgency, geographic research suggests that <u>the body is increasingly set at odds with</u> larger scale ethical concerns, especially <u>large-scale future events of forecasted suffering</u>. Emergency planning is a particularly good example in which the <u><mark>large-scale threats </mark>of future suffering</u> can <u><mark>distort moral reasoning</u></mark>. Žižek (2006) lightly develops this point in the context of the war on terror, where in the presence of fictitious and real ticking clocks and warning systems, <u><mark>the urgent body must be bypassed because there are bigger scales </mark>to worry about</u>: What does this all-pervasive sense of urgency mean ethically? The pressure of events is so overbearing, the stakes are so high, that they necessitate a suspension of ordinary ethical concerns. After all, displaying moral qualms when the lives of millions are at stake plays into the hands of the enemy. (Žižek, 2006) In the presence of large-scale future emergency, the urgency to secure the state, the citizenry, the economy, or the climate creates new scales and new temporal orders of response (see Anderson, 2010; Baldwin, 2012; Dalby, 2013; Morrissey, 2012), many of which treat the urgent body as impulsive and thus requiring management. McDonald’s (2013) analysis of three interconnected discourses of ‘climate security’ illustrates how bodily urgency in climate change is also recast as a menacing impulse that might require exclusion from moral reckoning. The logics of climate security, especially those related to national security, ‘can encourage perverse political responses that not only fail to respond effectively to climate change but may present victims of it as a threat’ (McDonald, 2013: 49). <u><mark>Bodies </mark>that are <mark>currently suffering cannot be urgent, because they are excluded from </mark>the potential <mark>collectivity that could be suffering </mark>everywhere in some future time.</u> Similar bypassing of existing bodily urgency is echoed in writing about violent securitization, such as drone warfare (Shaw and Akhter, 2012), and also in intimate scales like the street and the school, especially in relation to race (Mitchell, 2009; Young et al., 2014). As large-scale urgent concerns are institutionalized, <u>the urgent body is increasingly obscured through technical planning</u> and coordination (Anderson and Adey, 2012). <u>The predominant characteristic</u> of this institutionalization of large-scale emergency <u>is a ‘built-in bias for action’</u> (Wuthnow, 2010: 212) that circumvents contingencies. <u>The urgent body is at best an</u> assumed <u>eventuality</u>, one that will likely require another state of waiting, such as triage (e.g. Greatbach et al., 2005). Amin (2013) cautions that in much of the West, governmental need to provide evidence of laissez-faire governing on the one hand, and assurance of strength in facing a threatening future on the other, produces ‘just-in-case preparedness’ (Amin, 2013: 151) of neoliberal risk management policies. In the US, ‘personal ingenuity’ is built into emergency response at the expense of the poor and vulnerable for whom ‘[t]he difference between abjection and bearable survival’ (Amin, 2013: 153) will not be determined by emergency planning, but in the material infrastructure of the city. In short, the urgencies of the body provide justifications for social exclusion of the most marginalized based on impulse and perceived threat, while large-scale future emergencies effectively absorb the deliberative power of urgency into the institutions of preparedness and risk avoidance. Žižek references Arendt’s (2006) analysis of the banality of evil to explain the current state of ethical reasoning under the war on terror, noting that people who perform morally reprehensible actions under the conditions of urgency assume a ‘tragic-ethic grandeur’ (Žižek, 2006) by sacrificing their own morality for the good of the state. But his analysis fails to note that bodies are today so rarely legitimate sites for claiming urgency. In the context of the assumed priority of the large-scale future emergency, <u>the urgent body becomes</u> literally nonsense<u>, a non sequitur within societies</u>, states and worlds <u>that will always be more urgent</u>. If the important ethical work of urgency has been to identify that which must not wait, then the capture of the power and persuasiveness of urgency by large-scale future emergencies has consequences for the kinds of normative arguments we can raise on behalf of urgent bodies. How, then, might waiting compare as a normative description and critique in our own urgent time? Waiting can be categorized according to its purpose or outcome (see Corbridge, 2004; Gray, 2011), but it also modifies the place of the individual in society and her importance. As Ramdas (2012: 834) writes, ‘waiting … produces hierarchies which segregate people and places into those which matter and those which do not’. The segregation of waiting might produce effects that counteract suffering, however, and Jeffery (2008: 957) explains that though the ‘politics of waiting’ can be repressive, it can also engender creative political engagement. In his research with educated unemployed Jat youth who spend days and years waiting for desired employment, Jeffery finds that ‘the temporal suffering and sense of ambivalence experienced by young men can generate cultural and political experiments that, in turn, have marked social and spatial effects’ (Jeffery, 2010: 186). Though this is not the same as claiming normative neutrality for waiting, it does suggest that waiting is more ethically ambivalent and open than urgency. In other contexts, however, our descriptions of waiting indicate a strong condemnation of its effects upon the subjects of study. <u>Waiting can demobilize radical reform, depoliticizing ‘the insurrectionary possibilities of the present by delaying the revolutionary imperative to a future moment that is forever drifting towards infinity’</u> (Springer, 2014: 407). Yonucu’s (2011) analysis of the self-destructive activities of disrespected working-class youth in Istanbul suggests that this sense of infinite waiting can lead not only to depoliticization, but also to a disbelief in the possibility of a future self of any value. Waiting, like urgency, can undermine the possibility of self-care two-fold, first by making people wait for essential needs, and again by reinforcing that waiting is ‘[s]omething to be ashamed of because it may be noted or taken as evidence of indolence or low status, seen as a symptom of rejection or a signal to exclude’ (Bauman, 2004: 109). This is why Auyero (2012) suggests that waiting creates an ideal state subject, providing ‘temporal processes in and through which political subordination is produced’ (Auyero, 2012: loc. 90; see also Secor, 2007). Furthermore, Auyero notes, it is not only political subordination, but the subjective effect of waiting that secures domination, as citizens and non-citizens find themselves ‘waiting hopefully and then frustratedly for others to make decisions, and in effect surrendering to the authority of others’ (Auyero, 2012: loc. 123). <u><mark>Waiting can</u></mark> therefore <u><mark>function as a</u></mark> potentially important <u>spatial <mark>technology of the elite </mark>and powerful, <mark>mobilized </mark>not only <mark>for the purpose of governing individuals</mark>, but also <mark>to retain claims over moral urgency</u></mark>. But there is growing resistance to the capture of claims of urgency by the elite, and it is important to note that even in cases where the material conditions of containment are currently impenetrable, arguments based on human value are at the forefront of reclaiming urgency for the body. In detention centers, clandestine prisons, state borders and refugee camps, geographers point to ongoing struggles against the ethical impossibility of bodily urgency and a rejection of states of waiting (see Conlon, 2011; Darling, 2009, 2011; Garmany, 2012; Mountz et al., 2013; Schuster, 2011). Ramakrishnan’s (2014) analysis of a Delhi resettlement colony and Shewly’s (2013) discussion of the enclave between India and Bangladesh describe people who refuse to give up their own status as legitimately urgent, even in the context of larger scale politics. Similarly, Tyler’s (2013) account of desperate female detainees stripping off their clothes to expose their humanness and suffering in the Yarl’s Wood Immigration Removal Centre in the UK suggests that demands for recognition are not just about politics, but also about the acknowledgement of humanness and the irrevocable possibility of being that which cannot wait. The continued existence of places like Yarl’s Wood and similar institutions in the USA nonetheless points to the challenge of exposing the urgent body as a moral priority when it is so easily hidden from view, and also reminds us that our research can help to explain the relationships between normative dimensions and the political and social conditions of struggle. In closing, geographic depictions of waiting do seem to evocatively describe otherwise obscured suffering (e.g. Bennett, 2011), but it is striking how rarely these descriptions also use the language of urgency. Given the discussion above, what might be accomplished – and risked – by incorporating urgency more overtly and deliberately into our discussions of waiting, surplus and abandoned bodies? Urgency can clarify the implicit but understated ethical consequences and normativity associated with waiting, and encourage explicit discussion about harmful suffering. Waiting can be productive or unproductive for radical praxis, but urgency compels and requires response. Geographers could be instrumental in reclaiming the ethical work of urgency in ways that leave it open for critique, clarifying common spatial misunderstandings and representations. There is good reason to be thoughtful in this process, since moral outrage towards inhumanity can itself obscure differentiated experiences of being human, dividing up ‘those for whom we feel urgent unreasoned concern and those whose lives and deaths simply do not touch us, or do not appear as lives at all’ (Butler, 2009: 50). But when the urgent body is rendered as only waiting, both materially and discursively, it is just as easily cast as impulsive, disgusting, animalistic (see also McKittrick, 2006). Feminist theory insists that the urgent body, whose encounters of violence are ‘usually framed as private, apolitical and mundane’ (Pain, 2014: 8), are as deeply political, public, and exceptional as other forms of violence (Phillips, 2008; Pratt, 2005). <u>Insisting that a suffering body</u>, now, is that which <u>cannot wait, has the ethical effect of drawing it into consideration alongside the</u> political, public and exceptional <u>scope of large-scale futures</u>. It may help us insist on the body, both as a single unit and a plurality, as a legitimate scale of normative priority and social care. In this report, I have explored old and new reflections on the ethical work of urgency and waiting. Geographic research suggests a contemporary popular bias towards the urgency of large-scale futures, institutionalized in ways that further obscure and discredit the urgencies of the body. This bias also justifies the production of new waiting places in our material landscape, places like the detention center and the waiting room. In some cases, waiting is normatively neutral, even providing opportunities for alternative politics. In others, the technologies of waiting serve to manage potentially problematic bodies, leading to suspended suffering and even to extermination (e.g. Wright, 2013). One of my aims has been to suggest that moral reasoning is important both because it exposes normative biases against subjugated people, and because it potentially provides routes toward struggle where claims to urgency seem to foreclose the possibilities of alleviation of suffering. <u><mark>Saving the world</u></mark> still <u><mark>should require a debate about whose world is being saved, when, and at what cost – and this requires a debate about what </mark>really <mark>cannot wait</u></mark>. My next report will extend some of these concerns by reviewing how feelings of urgency, as well as hope, fear, and other emotions, have played a role in geography and ethical reasoning. I conclude, however, by pulling together past and present. In 1972, Gilbert White asked why geographers were not engaging ‘the truly urgent questions’ (1972: 101) such as racial repression, decaying cities, economic inequality, and global environmental destruction. His question highlights just how much the discipline has changed, but it is also unnerving in its echoes of our contemporary problems. Since White’s writing, our moral reasoning has been stretched to consider the future body and the more-than-human, alongside the presently urgent body – topics and concerns that I have not taken up in this review but which will provide their own new possibilities for urgent concerns. My own hope presently is drawn from an acknowledgement that the temporal characteristics of contemporary capitalism can be interrupted in creative ways (Sharma, 2014), with the possibility of squaring the urgent body with our large-scale future concerns. Temporal alternatives already exist in ongoing and emerging revolutions and the disruption of claims of cycles and circular political processes (e.g. Lombard, 2013; Reyes, 2012). Though calls for urgency will certainly be used to obscure evasion of responsibility (e.g. Gilmore, 2008: 56, fn<u><strong> 6), they may also serve as fertile ground for radical critique, a truly fierce urgency for now.</p></u></strong> | 1AC v2.0 | null | 1AC Framing | 2,658 | 857 | 85,853 | ./documents/hspolicy19/Hawknatius/WeNa/Hawknatius-Wei-Navracruz-Aff-The%20Caroline%20Moore%20Solon%20Round%20Robin-Finals.docx | 711,906 | A | The Caroline Moore Solon Round Robin | Finals | St Ignawken | Yufan Li | 1AC Refugees
2NR Canada CP 2020 DA | hspolicy19/Hawknatius/WeNa/Hawknatius-Wei-Navracruz-Aff-The%20Caroline%20Moore%20Solon%20Round%20Robin-Finals.docx | null | 60,672 | WeNa | Hawknatius WeNa | null | Ja..... | We..... | Sa..... | Na..... | 21,218 | Hawknatius | Hawknatius | OH | null | 1,018 | hspolicy19 | HS Policy 2019-20 | 2,019 | cx | hs | 2 |
2,305,886 | 5] Unipolarity is sustainable and prevents great power war. Transition risks extinction | Beckley 18 | Michael Beckley 18. Professor of political science at Tufts. Unrivaled: Why America Will Remain the World’s Sole Superpower. Cornell University Press. 1-2. | in terms of wealth and military capabilities the pillars of global power the U S is in a league of its own the U S accounts for 25 percent of global wealth, 35 percent of world innovation, and 40 percent of global military spending to nearly 600 of the world’s 2,000 most profi table companies and 50 of the top 100 universities it is the only country that can fight major wars beyond its home region and strike targets anywhere on earth within an hour, with 587 bases scattered across 42 countries and a navy and air force stronger than that of the next ten nations combined Nothing has ever existed like this disparity of power; nothing The U S is the greatest superpower ever.”
the U S will remain the world’s sole superpower for many decades We are not living in a transitional post–Cold War era Instead, we are in the midst of what could be called the unipolar era
scholars have dismissed unipolarity as a fleeting “moment” that would soon be swept away by the rise of new powers reports advising to prepare multipolarity and the “rise of China” has been the most read-about news story people think China is overtaking the U S
the current lit suffers from two shortcomings that distort peoples’ perceptions of the balance of power
First, the lit mismeasures power Most studies size up countries using gross indicators of economic and military resources, such as GDP and military spending As a result, standard indicators exaggerate the wealth and military power of poor, populous countries like China and India these countries bear massive welfare and security burdens that drain their resources
measure power in net rather than gross terms it becomes clear that America’s economic and military lead over other countries is much larger than typically assumed trends are in its favor.
Second projections of U.S. power are based on flawed notions about why great powers rise and fall the lit assumes great powers have predictable life spans The Habsburg, French, and British empires all collapsed It is natural to assume the American empire is destined for the dustbin of history
the laws of history do not apply today The U S is not like other great powers it enjoys a unique set of geographic, demographic, and institutional advantages that translate into a commanding geopolitical position The U S scores highly across the board, whereas all of its potential rivals suffer from critical weaknesses The U S has the best prospects of any nation to amass wealth and military power in the decades ahead
no country is likely to acquire the means to challenge the U S for global primacy This is an extraordinary development, because the world has been plagued by great power rivalry for millennia hegemonic rivalries ended in catastrophic wars when the world was multipolar, Germany twice challenged Britain for European primacy The result was two world wars under bipolarity superpowers brought the world to the brink of nuclear Armageddon
Today, by contrast, unipolarity makes a comparable level of great power competition impossible and makes conflict highly unlikely | the U S is in a league of its own 25 percent of wealth, 35 of innovation, and 40 of military spending
people think China is overtaking
shortcomings distort perceptions
, the lit mismeasures power studies size up GDP and exaggerate power of poor, populous countries like China massive welfare and security burdens drain resources
measure power in net terms it becomes clear America’s lead is much larger
projections of power are based on flawed notions about why powers fall
laws of history do not apply The U S is not like other powers , it enjoys a unique set of geographic, demographic, and institutional advantages that translate into a commanding position all rivals suffer from critical weaknesses
hegemonic rivalries ended in catastrophic wars multipolar result was two world wars bipolarity brought the brink of nuclear Armageddon
unipolarity makes great power competition impossible and conflict highly unlikely | Yet in terms of wealth and military capabilities—the pillars of global power—the United States is in a league of its own. With only 5 percent of the world’s population, the United States accounts for 25 percent of global wealth, 35 percent of world innovation, and 40 percent of global military spending. 4 It is home to nearly 600 of the world’s 2,000 most profi table companies and 50 of the top 100 universities. 5 And it is the only country that can fight major wars beyond its home region and strike targets anywhere on earth within an hour, with 587 bases scattered across 42 countries and a navy and air force stronger than that of the next ten nations combined. 6 According to Yale historian Paul Kennedy, “Nothing has ever existed like this disparity of power; nothing.” The United States is, quite simply, “the greatest superpower ever.” 7
Why is the United States so dominant? And how long will this imbalance of power last? In the following pages, I argue that the United States will remain the world’s sole superpower for many decades, and probably throughout this century. We are not living in a transitional post–Cold War era. Instead, we are in the midst of what could be called the unipolar era—a period as profound as any epoch in modern history.
This conclusion challenges the conventional wisdom among pundits, policymakers, and the public. 8 Since the end of the Cold War, scholars have dismissed unipolarity as a fleeting “moment” that would soon be swept away by the rise of new powers. 9 Bookstores feature bestsellers such as The Post-American World and Easternization: Asia’s Rise and America’s Decline ; 10 the U.S. National Intelligence Council has issued multiple reports advising the president to prepare the country for multipolarity by 2030; 11 and the “rise of China” has been the most read-about news story of the twenty-fi rst century. 12 These writings, in turn, have shaped public opinion: polls show that most people in most countries think that China is overtaking the United States as the world’s leading power. 13
How can all of these people be wrong? I argue that the current literature suffers from two shortcomings that distort peoples’ perceptions of the balance of power.
First, the literature mismeasures power. Most studies size up countries using gross indicators of economic and military resources, such as gross domestic product (GDP) and military spending. 14 These indicators tally countries’ resources without deducting the costs countries pay to police, protect, and provide services for their people. As a result, standard indicators exaggerate the wealth and military power of poor, populous countries like China and India—these countries produce vast output and field large armies, but they also bear massive welfare and security burdens that drain their resources.
To account for these costs, I measure power in net rather than gross terms. In essence, I create a balance sheet for each country: assets go on one side of the ledger, liabilities go on the other, and net resources are calculated by subtracting the latter from the former. When this is done, it becomes clear that America’s economic and military lead over other countries is much larger than typically assumed—and the trends are mostly in its favor.
Second, many projections of U.S. power are based on flawed notions about why great powers rise and fall. Much of the literature assumes that great powers have predictable life spans and that the more powerful a country becomes the more it suffers from crippling ailments that doom it to decline. 15 The Habsburg, French, and British empires all collapsed. It is therefore natural to assume that the American empire is also destined for the dustbin of history.
I argue, however, that the laws of history do not apply today. The United States is not like other great powers. Rather, it enjoys a unique set of geographic, demographic, and institutional advantages that translate into a commanding geopolitical position. The United States does not rank first in all sources of national strength, but it scores highly across the board, whereas all of its potential rivals suffer from critical weaknesses. The United States thus has the best prospects of any nation to amass wealth and military power in the decades ahead.
For the foreseeable future, therefore, no country is likely to acquire the means to challenge the United States for global primacy. This is an extraordinary development, because the world has been plagued by great power rivalry for millennia. In the past five hundred years alone, there have been sixteen hegemonic rivalries between a ruling power and a rising power, and twelve of them ended in catastrophic wars. 16 In the first half of the twentieth century, for example, when the world was multipolar, Germany twice challenged Britain for European primacy. The result was two world wars. In the second half of the twentieth century, under bipolarity, the Soviet Union challenged the United States for global primacy. The result was the Cold War, a conflict in which the superpowers spent between 6 and 25 percent of their GDPs on defense every year, waged proxy wars that killed millions of people, and brought the world to the brink of nuclear Armageddon.
Today, by contrast, unipolarity makes a comparable level of great power competition impossible and thus makes a comparable level of conflict highly unlikely. 17 | 5,401 | <h4>5] Unipolarity is <u>sustainable</u> and prevents <u>great power war</u>. Transition risks <u>extinction</h4><p></u>Michael <strong>Beckley 18</strong>. Professor of political science at Tufts. Unrivaled: Why America Will Remain the World’s Sole Superpower. Cornell University Press. 1-2. </p><p>Yet <u>in terms of <strong>wealth</u></strong> <u>and <strong>military capabilities</u></strong>—<u>the <strong>pillars of global power</u></strong>—<u><mark>the</u> <u><strong>U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates <u><mark>is in a <strong>league of its own</u></strong></mark>. With only 5 percent of the world’s population, <u>the</u> <u><strong>U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates <u>accounts for <strong><mark>25 percent</strong> of</mark> global <mark>wealth, <strong>35</mark> percent</strong> <mark>of</mark> world <mark>innovation, and <strong>40</mark> percent</strong> <mark>of</mark> global <mark>military spending</u></mark>. 4 It is home <u>to nearly 600 of the world’s 2,000 most profi table companies and 50 of the top 100 universities</u>. 5 And <u>it is the <strong>only country</strong> that can <strong>fight major wars</strong> beyond its home region and <strong>strike targets anywhere on earth within an hour</strong>, with 587 <strong>bases</strong> scattered across 42 countries and a <strong>navy</strong> and <strong>air force</strong> <strong>stronger than that of the next ten nations combined</u></strong>. 6 According to Yale historian Paul Kennedy, “<u><strong>Nothing has ever existed like this disparity of power; nothing</u></strong>.” <u>The</u> <u><strong>U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates <u>is</u>, quite simply, “<u>the <strong>greatest superpower ever.”</u></strong> 7 </p><p>Why is the United States so dominant? And how long will this imbalance of power last? In the following pages, I argue that <u>the</u> <u><strong>U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates <u>will <strong>remain the world’s sole superpower for many decades</u></strong>, and probably throughout this century. <u>We are <strong>not living in a transitional post–Cold War era</u></strong>. <u><strong>Instead</strong>, we are in the midst of what could be called the <strong>unipolar era</u></strong>—a period as profound as any epoch in modern history. </p><p>This conclusion challenges the conventional wisdom among pundits, policymakers, and the public. 8 Since the end of the Cold War, <u>scholars have dismissed unipolarity as a fleeting “moment” that would soon be swept away by the rise of new powers</u>. 9 Bookstores feature bestsellers such as The Post-American World and Easternization: Asia’s Rise and America’s Decline ; 10 the U.S. National Intelligence Council has issued multiple <u>reports advising</u> the president <u>to prepare</u> the country for <u><strong>multipolarity</u></strong> by 2030; 11 <u>and the <strong>“rise of China”</u></strong> <u>has been the most read-about news story</u> of the twenty-fi rst century. 12 These writings, in turn, have shaped public opinion: polls show that most <u><mark>people</u></mark> in most countries <u><strong><mark>think</u></strong></mark> that <u><mark>China is overtaking </mark>the</u> <u><strong>U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates as the world’s leading power. 13 </p><p>How can all of these people be wrong? I argue that <u>the current <strong>lit</u></strong>erature <u>suffers from <strong>two <mark>shortcomings</strong></mark> that <mark>distort</mark> peoples’ <mark>perceptions </mark>of the balance of power</u>. </p><p><u>First<mark>, the <strong>lit</u></strong></mark>erature <u><strong><mark>mismeasures power</u></strong></mark>. <u>Most <mark>studies size up</mark> countries using gross indicators of economic and military resources, such as</u> gross domestic product (<u><mark>GDP</u></mark>) <u><mark>and</mark> military spending</u>. 14 These indicators tally countries’ resources without deducting the costs countries pay to police, protect, and provide services for their people. <u>As a result, standard indicators <strong><mark>exaggerate</strong></mark> the wealth and military <mark>power of poor, <strong>populous countries</strong> like China</mark> and India</u>—<u>these countries</u> produce vast output and field large armies, but they also <u><strong>bear <mark>massive welfare and security burdens</u></strong></mark> <u>that <strong><mark>drain</mark> their <mark>resources</u></strong></mark>. </p><p>To account for these costs, I <u><mark>measure</u> <u><strong>power in net</mark> rather than gross <mark>terms</u></strong></mark>. In essence, I create a balance sheet for each country: assets go on one side of the ledger, liabilities go on the other, and net resources are calculated by subtracting the latter from the former. When this is done, <u><mark>it becomes <strong>clear</strong></mark> that <mark>America’s</mark> economic and military <mark>lead</mark> over other countries <mark>is <strong>much larger</strong></mark> than typically assumed</u>—and the <u>trends are</u> mostly <u>in its favor<strong>. </p><p></strong>Second</u>, many <u><mark>projections of</mark> U.S. <mark>power are based on <strong>flawed notions</strong> about why</mark> great <mark>powers</mark> rise and <mark>fall</u></mark>. Much of <u>the</u> <u><strong>lit</u></strong>erature <u>assumes</u> that <u>great powers have predictable life spans</u> and that the more powerful a country becomes the more it suffers from crippling ailments that doom it to decline. 15 <u>The Habsburg, French, and British empires all collapsed</u>. <u>It is</u> therefore <u>natural to assume </u>that <u>the American empire is</u> also <u>destined for the dustbin of history</u>. </p><p>I argue, however, that <u><strong>the <mark>laws of history do not apply </mark>today</u></strong>. <u><mark>The</u></mark> <u><strong><mark>U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates <u><mark>is not like other </mark>great <mark>powers</u></mark>. Rather<mark>, <u>it enjoys a <strong>unique set</strong> of <strong>geographic</strong>, <strong>demographic</strong>, and <strong>institutional advantages</strong> that translate into a <strong>commanding</mark> geopolitical <mark>position</u></strong></mark>. <u>The</u> <u><strong>U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates does not rank first in all sources of national strength, but it <u>scores highly across the board, whereas <mark>all</mark> of its potential <mark>rivals <strong>suffer from critical weaknesses</u></strong></mark>. <u>The</u> <u><strong>U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates thus <u>has the best prospects of any nation to amass wealth and military power in the decades ahead</u>. </p><p>For the foreseeable future, therefore, <u><strong>no country</u></strong> <u>is likely to acquire the means to challenge the</u> <u><strong>U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates <u>for <strong>global primacy</u></strong>. <u>This is an <strong>extraordinary development</strong>, because the world has been plagued by great power rivalry for millennia</u>. In the past five hundred years alone, there have been sixteen <u><mark>hegemonic rivalries</u></mark> between a ruling power and a rising power, and twelve of them <u><mark>ended in <strong>catastrophic wars</u></strong></mark>. 16 In the first half of the twentieth century, for example, <u>when the world was <strong><mark>multipolar</strong></mark>, Germany <strong>twice challenged Britain</strong> for European primacy</u>. <u>The <mark>result was <strong>two world wars</u></strong></mark>. In the second half of the twentieth century, <u><strong>under <mark>bipolarity</u></strong></mark>, the Soviet Union challenged the United States for global primacy. The result was the Cold War, a conflict in which the <u>superpowers</u> spent between 6 and 25 percent of their GDPs on defense every year, waged proxy wars that killed millions of people, and <u><mark>brought </mark>the world to <mark>the <strong>brink of nuclear Armageddon</u></mark>. </p><p><u></strong>Today, by contrast, <mark>unipolarity makes</mark> a comparable level of <mark>great power competition <strong>impossible</u></strong> <u>and</u></mark> thus <u>makes</u> a comparable level of <u><mark>conflict <strong>highly unlikely</u></strong></mark>. 17 </p> | 1AC | 1AC | 1AC – Primacy | 20,919 | 225 | 72,686 | ./documents/hsld20/Peninsula/Ra/Peninsula-Ramireddy-Aff-NDCA-Doubles.docx | 870,311 | A | NDCA | Doubles | harker as | panel | 1ac china
1nc pla da nigeria cp t-plural
1ar all plus condo bad and repurpose cp bad
2nr t
2ar t | hsld20/Peninsula/Ra/Peninsula-Ramireddy-Aff-NDCA-Doubles.docx | null | 73,622 | AnRa | Peninsula AnRa | null | An..... | Ra..... | null | null | 24,672 | Peninsula | Peninsula | CA | null | 1,028 | hsld20 | HS LD 2020-21 | 2,020 | ld | hs | 1 |
1,941,922 | Congress key | Hayes 20 | Tara Hayes 20. Director of Human Welfare Policy at the American Action Forum, Master’s in Public Policy and Management from Carnegie Mellon University. “Recent Federal Proposals to Police Reform”. American Action Forum. Jun 18 2020. https://www.americanactionforum.org/insight/recent-federal-proposals-to-police-reform/. wms-hhb. | police reform policy changes sought would leverage the importance of the Community Oriented Policing Services (COPS) and Byrne policing grant funds provided by the DOJ by conditioning eligibility for such funds on compliance with the new policies outlined In 2020, the COPS program is providing state and local law enforcement agencies with $343 million $424 million was appropriated for Byrne grants.
The JUSTICE Act would incentivize bans on chokeholds by conditioning all funds provided through the COPS and Byrne grant programs on a state or locality imposing a ban because of how much agencies rely on these grant programs, it is expected that such a condition of funds would effectively result in bans across the country. | police reform, would leverage COPS) and Byrne grant funds conditioning eligibility for such funds on compliance with new policies the COPS program is $343 million $424 million was Byrne
because of how agencies rely on these programs a condition of funds would result in bans across the country. | House Democrats and Senate Republicans have each introduced their own pieces of legislation on police reform, and there is significant overlap between the bills. Both seek to improve police accountability, impose national operating standards to reduce the use of force, and mandate data collection to study and improve transparency. Many of the policy changes sought would leverage the importance of the Community Oriented Policing Services (COPS) and Byrne policing grant funds provided by the DOJ by conditioning eligibility for such funds on compliance with the new policies outlined. In 2020, the COPS program is providing state and local law enforcement agencies with $343 million. In 2019, $424 million was appropriated for Byrne grants.
H.R. 7120, the George Floyd Justice in Policing Act, was introduced by Rep. Karen Bass (D-CA) and is expected to be considered by the House next week. The JUSTICE Act, introduced by Senator Tim Scott (R-SC), is expected to be considered by the Senate next week.
Use of Force
Under H.R. 7120, the use of a chokehold would be a federal civil rights violation. To incentivize states to ban chokeholds and carotid holds—holds or maneuvers that disrupt, prevent, or hinder breathing or restrict blood or oxygen flow to the brain—funding under the COPS and Byrne grants programs would be restricted to states that have outlawed such holds or maneuvers. Further, an act would be considered to result in death if it is a substantial factor contributing to one’s death.
Under the PEACE Act provisions of H.R. 7120, federal law enforcement would be prohibited from using lethal force unless it is necessary (a change from the current “reasonable” standard) as a last resort to prevent imminent and serious bodily injury or death to the police officer or another person; it creates no substantial risk of injury to a third person; and reasonable alternatives have been exhausted. When feasible, a verbal warning must be issued in advance and must include a request to surrender. Federal law enforcement officers would also have a duty to intervene when another officer is using excessive force against a civilian and a training program must be developed to teach officers how to intervene.
H.R. 7120 would require the attorney general (AG) to issue guidance, in consultation with others from the community, on how to assess when force is necessary and how to ensure the use of the least amount of force that is necessary and appropriate. Officers would be required to take special training to learn how to deal with pregnant women; minors; the elderly; persons with mental, physical, and behavioral disabilities; people under the influence; people suffering from a serious medical condition; and people with limited English proficiency. An officer would not be able to use as a justifying defense that use of force was necessary if the officer’s gross negligence prior to the use of force contributed to its necessitation.
The JUSTICE Act would incentivize bans on chokeholds—defined as any physical maneuver that restricts an individual’s ability to breathe for the purposes of incapacitation—by conditioning all funds provided through the COPS and Byrne grant programs on a state or locality imposing a ban. Again, because of how much agencies rely on these grant programs, it is expected that such a condition of funds would effectively result in bans across the country. | 3,408 | <h4>Congress <u>key</h4><p></u>Tara <strong>Hayes 20</strong>. Director of Human Welfare Policy at the American Action Forum, Master’s in Public Policy and Management from Carnegie Mellon University. “Recent Federal Proposals to Police Reform”. American Action Forum. Jun 18 2020. https://www.americanactionforum.org/insight/recent-federal-proposals-to-police-reform/<u>. wms-hhb.</p><p></u>House Democrats and Senate Republicans have each introduced their own pieces of legislation on <u><mark>police reform</u>, </mark>and there is significant overlap between the bills. Both seek to improve police accountability, impose national operating standards to reduce the use of force, and mandate data collection to study and improve transparency. Many of the <u>policy changes sought <mark>would leverage </mark>the importance of the Community Oriented Policing Services (<strong><mark>COPS</strong>) and <strong>Byrne</strong> </mark>policing <mark>grant funds </mark>provided by the DOJ by <strong><mark>conditioning eligibility for such funds on compliance with </mark>the <mark>new policies </mark>outlined</u></strong>. <u>In 2020, <mark>the COPS program is </mark>providing state and local law enforcement agencies with <mark>$343 million</u></mark>. In 2019, <u><mark>$424 million was </mark>appropriated for <mark>Byrne </mark>grants.</p><p></u>H.R. 7120, the George Floyd Justice in Policing Act, was introduced by Rep. Karen Bass (D-CA) and is expected to be considered by the House next week. The JUSTICE Act, introduced by Senator Tim Scott (R-SC), is expected to be considered by the Senate next week.</p><p>Use of Force</p><p>Under H.R. 7120, the use of a chokehold would be a federal civil rights violation. To incentivize states to ban chokeholds and carotid holds—holds or maneuvers that disrupt, prevent, or hinder breathing or restrict blood or oxygen flow to the brain—funding under the COPS and Byrne grants programs would be restricted to states that have outlawed such holds or maneuvers. Further, an act would be considered to result in death if it is a substantial factor contributing to one’s death.</p><p>Under the PEACE Act provisions of H.R. 7120, federal law enforcement would be prohibited from using lethal force unless it is necessary (a change from the current “reasonable” standard) as a last resort to prevent imminent and serious bodily injury or death to the police officer or another person; it creates no substantial risk of injury to a third person; and reasonable alternatives have been exhausted. When feasible, a verbal warning must be issued in advance and must include a request to surrender. Federal law enforcement officers would also have a duty to intervene when another officer is using excessive force against a civilian and a training program must be developed to teach officers how to intervene.</p><p>H.R. 7120 would require the attorney general (AG) to issue guidance, in consultation with others from the community, on how to assess when force is necessary and how to ensure the use of the least amount of force that is necessary and appropriate. Officers would be required to take special training to learn how to deal with pregnant women; minors; the elderly; persons with mental, physical, and behavioral disabilities; people under the influence; people suffering from a serious medical condition; and people with limited English proficiency. An officer would not be able to use as a justifying defense that use of force was necessary if the officer’s gross negligence prior to the use of force contributed to its necessitation.</p><p><u>The JUSTICE Act would incentivize bans on chokeholds</u>—defined as any physical maneuver that restricts an individual’s ability to breathe for the purposes of incapacitation—<u>by conditioning all funds provided through the COPS and Byrne grant programs on a state or locality imposing a ban</u>. Again, <u><strong><mark>because of how </mark>much <mark>agencies rely on these </mark>grant <mark>programs</mark>, it is expected that such <mark>a condition of funds would </mark>effectively <mark>result in bans across the country.</p></u></strong></mark> | 2AC | null | null | 556,864 | 96 | 57,289 | ./documents/hspolicy20/Mamaroneck/MiRa/Mamaroneck-Miller-Rahman-Aff-Michigan-Round2.docx | 733,946 | A | Michigan | 2 | GBS LR | Rafael Pierry | 1AC - Forensics
2NR - Con Con MORE | hspolicy20/Mamaroneck/MiRa/Mamaroneck-Miller-Rahman-Aff-Michigan-Round2.docx | null | 62,629 | MiRa | Mamaroneck MiRa | null | Ja..... | Mi..... | Ra..... | Ra..... | 21,706 | Mamaroneck | Mamaroneck | NY | null | 1,019 | hspolicy20 | HS Policy 2020-21 | 2,020 | cx | hs | 2 |
2,309,313 | 6] Stats prove. | Rhamey et al. ’15 | Rhamey et al. ’15 (J. Patrick Rhamey, Jr.; Michael O. Slobodchikoff; Thomas J. Volgy; Associate Professor of International Studies and Political Science at the Virginia Military Institute, Ph.D. in Political Science from the University of Arizona, M.A. in Political Science from the University of Georgia, B.A. in International Studies and Political Science from Rhodes College; Associate Professor of Political Science at Troy University; Professor of Political Science at the University of Arizona; October 2015; “Order and disorder across geopolitical space: the effect of declining dominance on interstate conflict”; https://link.springer.com/article/10.1057/jird.2014.3; Journal of International Relations and Development, Vol. 18, Issue 4; accessed 11/24/18; TV) *MID = Militarized Interstate Disputes. Edited in brackets for reading clarity. | Findings for the three models are listed in Table 2. Each model offers results that support our theory of dominance vacuums and conflict onset. Regardless of the analysis or controls the influence of vacuums on MID onset is statistically significant Model 1 demonstrates that spaces are 3.6 times more likely to experience a MID than those where a single state's capabilities are unchallenged When the space includes a border, the vacuum is even more dramatic, with the probability of conflict onset at 25% Model 2 the dependent variable to major power MID onset within a geographic space Results confirm our expectations, with spaces in a dominance vacuum [is] 16.9 times more likely to experience major power conflicts than spaces where a single state's capabilities dominate with the probability rising rapidly as parity increases between the top two states In the absence of a vacuum major power conflict is entirely absent The effect of dominance vacuums is confirmed by Model 3 On the chessboard of international politics states are subject to the ordering influence by dominant powers Within vacuums, where no clear leader exists to structure politics, the formation of “shatterbelts” is likely as states are less restrained by dominant powers these vacuums present the most likely contexts for conflict our theory provides a compelling case where willingness measures are present, but conflict does not occur, including ongoing territorial disputes such as Japan and Russia’s Kuril Islands, Guatemala’s claims on Belize, or British and Spanish disagreement over Gibraltar. The framework for identifying conflict has numerous other applications our theory is based upon the stability of a clear hierarchy in international politics and instability resulting when hierarchical dominance is degraded the byproducts of instability should not be restricted to MIDs, but other forms of political violence The absence of a clearly defined hierarchy may increase the probability of civil war, separatist movements, terrorism, and enduring rivalries | the influence of vacuums is statistically significant a dominance vacuum [is] 16.9 times more likely to experience major conflicts with probability rising as parity increases between top states In the absence of a vacuum conflict is absent Within vacuums no clear leader exists states are less restrained these present the most likely contexts for conflict instability result when hierarchical dominance is degraded absence increase civil war terrorism, and rivalries | Findings for each of the three models are listed in Table 2. Each model offers results that appear to support our theory of dominance vacuums and conflict onset. Regardless of the unit of analysis or controls present in the testing of our hypothesis, the influence of vacuums on MID onset is substantively and statistically significant.22 Model 1, using ten degree by ten degree geographic spaces as the unit of analysis, demonstrates that geographic spaces in a space of complete dominance are 3.6 times more likely to experience a MID than those in a space where a single state's projected capabilities are unchallenged. The presence of a border within the geographic space is also statistically significant and increase the odds of MID onset by 9.2 times, underscoring the significant number of MIDs that are territorial disputes and demonstrating the particular potential for MID onset within dominance vacuums that contain borders [Table 2 About Here] Figure 4 illustrates the predicted probabilities of MID onset for these geographic spaces depending upon whether they include interstate borders and the strength of the dominance vacuum.23 When the space includes a border, the effect of a vacuum is even more dramatic, with the predicted probability of conflict onset in a dominance vacuum containing a border at 25%, and the degree of dominance vacuum present increasing the probability of conflict across the range of observations by 18%. [Figure 4 About Here] Model 2 repeats the analysis but restricts the dependent variable to joint major power MID onset within a geographic space, as a test of hypothesis 2. Results confirm our expectations, with geographic spaces in a complete dominance vacuum [is] 16.9 times more likely to experience joint major power conflicts than geographic spaces where a single state's projected capabilities dominate. Figure 5 illustrates the predicted probability of Joint Major Power MID onset for geographic spaces, with the probability rising rapidly as relative projected parity increases between the top two projecting dominant states, and at a greater rate if the space includes a border. In the absence of a dominance vacuum, joint major power conflict is almost entirely absent. [Figure 5 About Here] The effect of dominance vacuums on conflict is confirmed by the dyadic test in Model 3, testing Hypothesis 3 expectations regarding all contiguous dyads. Even when controlling for joint democracy, perhaps the most consistently powerful indicator of conflict behavior in the literature (Levy 1989), we find a strong substantive impact, with the existence of a dominance vacuum in the geopolitical space increasing the probability of experiencing a MID within a dyad by 18%, as illustrated in Figure 6. [Figure 6 About Here] Dominance Vacuums and Politics On the chessboard of international politics the dynamics of regions and the security of states are subject to the ordering influence by dominant powers. However, their influence is not constant across geographic space, as their relative capabilities deteriorate across distance. Within dominance vacuums, where no clear leader exists to structure international politics, the formation of “shatterbelts” is likely as other states are less restrained by dominant powers. As demonstrated by our findings and descriptive analysis, these vacuums present the most likely contexts of geopolitical spaces for conflict onset in the international system. We may expect, for instance, the clustering of conflicts in the Middle East and Africa to continue until a shift in the power hierarchy within these geographic spaces terminates the vacuum. By contrast, the implications for states moving out of vacuums may be observed in the rapid evolution of the preexisting European Economic Community into the more sophisticated and cooperative institutional structures of the European Union with the Maastricht Treaty following the end of the Cold War. While we provide an important component to explaining the opportunity for states to engage in conflict given the contextual salience of the systemic environment, willingness to engage in conflict remains a product of dyadic and domestic level indicators, ranging across historical, cultural, national, and ideological grievances, territory, and economic interests. Yet, our theory also provides a compelling case in those instances where these willingness measures are present, but conflict does not occur, including many ongoing territorial disputes such as Japan and Russia’s continued disagreement over the Kuril Islands, Guatemala’s territorial claims on Belize, or British and Spanish disagreement over Gibraltar. The framework for identifying probable conflict locations in this effort has the potential for numerous other applications. First, further exploration of the regional dynamics identified by Lemke (2002) is warranted. We examined only the projected capabilities of the most powerful states in a geographic space. Applying our analysis to regional subsystems nested within the dominant power reach used here to define vacuums may have important implications for regional politics, as well as the prospects for regional powers such as Brazil and India to achieve future major power status as they attempt to reconcile regional concerns and focus globally (Volgy et al. 2014). Consistent with the literature on regional politics over the past century, it is likely that the intersection of dominant power capabilities with regional power dynamics is an additional component influencing regional stability (e.g. Buzan and Waever 2003; Katzenstein 2005). In fact, an analysis of regions based in part on the extent to which those geopolitical spaces vary according to the extent of the existence of dominance vacuums may yield fruitful inter-regional comparisons regarding conflict processes. Second, our theory is based upon the stability of a clear hierarchy in international politics and the instability resulting when hierarchical dominance is degraded over geopolitical spaces. Logically, the byproducts of this instability should not simply be restricted to MIDs, but also other forms of political violence. For example, the decline of piracy in the South China Sea coincides with the rise of Chinese dominance in the geographic space in the early 1990s (Prins and Daxecker 2011) and domestic conflicts in Central and Eastern Africa likely reside within very consistent power vacuums. The absence of a clearly defined hierarchy over a geographic space may increase the probability of civil war, separatist movements, terrorism, and perhaps even the ending of enduring rivalries. Research relating such vacuums to the locations of extra and intra- state violence is a logical next step toward a better understanding of peace and conflict in the international system. | 6,825 | <h4>6] <u>Stats</u> prove.</h4><p><strong>Rhamey et al. ’15</strong> (J. Patrick Rhamey, Jr.; Michael O. Slobodchikoff; Thomas J. Volgy; Associate Professor of International Studies and Political Science at the Virginia Military Institute, Ph.D. in Political Science from the University of Arizona, M.A. in Political Science from the University of Georgia, B.A. in International Studies and Political Science from Rhodes College; Associate Professor of Political Science at Troy University; Professor of Political Science at the University of Arizona; October 2015; “Order and disorder across geopolitical space: the effect of declining dominance on interstate conflict”; https://link.springer.com/article/10.1057/jird.2014.3; Journal of International Relations and Development, Vol. 18, Issue 4; accessed 11/24/18; TV) *MID = Militarized Interstate Disputes. Edited in brackets for reading clarity. </p><p><u>Findings for</u> each of <u>the <strong>three models</strong> are listed in Table 2. Each model offers results that</u> appear to <u>support our theory of <strong>dominance vacuums</strong> and <strong>conflict</strong> onset. Regardless of the</u> unit of <u>analysis or controls</u> present in the testing of our hypothesis, <u><mark>the influence of vacuums</mark> on MID onset <mark>is</u></mark> substantively and <u><strong><mark>statistically significant</u></strong></mark>.22 <u>Model 1</u>, using ten degree by ten degree geographic spaces as the unit of analysis, <u>demonstrates that</u> geographic <u>spaces</u> in a space of complete dominance <u>are <strong>3.6 times more likely</strong> to experience a MID than those</u> in a space <u>where a <strong>single state's</u></strong> projected <u><strong>capabilities are unchallenged</u></strong>. The presence of a border within the geographic space is also statistically significant and increase the odds of MID onset by 9.2 times, underscoring the significant number of MIDs that are territorial disputes and demonstrating the particular potential for MID onset within dominance vacuums that contain borders [Table 2 About Here] Figure 4 illustrates the predicted probabilities of MID onset for these geographic spaces depending upon whether they include interstate borders and the strength of the dominance vacuum.23 <u>When the space includes a <strong>border</strong>, the </u>effect of a <u>vacuum is even more dramatic, with the </u>predicted <u>probability of conflict onset </u>in a dominance vacuum containing a border <u>at<strong> 25%</u></strong>, and the degree of dominance vacuum present increasing the probability of conflict across the range of observations by 18%. [Figure 4 About Here] <u>Model 2</u> repeats the analysis but restricts <u>the dependent variable to</u> joint <u>major power MID onset within a geographic space</u>, as a test of hypothesis 2. <u>Results confirm our expectations, with</u> geographic <u>spaces in <mark>a</u></mark> complete <u><mark>dominance vacuum [is] <strong>16.9 times more likely</strong> to experience</u></mark> joint <u><mark>major</mark> power <mark>conflicts</mark> than</u> geographic <u>spaces where a single state's</u> projected <u>capabilities dominate</u>. Figure 5 illustrates the predicted probability of Joint Major Power MID onset for geographic spaces, <u><mark>with</mark> the <mark>probability rising</mark> rapidly <strong><mark>as</u></strong></mark> relative projected <u><strong><mark>parity increases</strong> between</mark> the <mark>top</mark> two</u> projecting dominant <u><mark>states</u></mark>, and at a greater rate if the space includes a border. <u><mark>In the absence of a</u></mark> dominance <u><mark>vacuum</u></mark>, joint <u>major power <mark>conflict is</u></mark> almost <u><strong>entirely <mark>absent</u></strong></mark>. [Figure 5 About Here] <u>The effect of dominance vacuums</u> on conflict <u>is confirmed by</u> the dyadic test in <u>Model 3</u>, testing Hypothesis 3 expectations regarding all contiguous dyads. Even when controlling for joint democracy, perhaps the most consistently powerful indicator of conflict behavior in the literature (Levy 1989), we find a strong substantive impact, with the existence of a dominance vacuum in the geopolitical space increasing the probability of experiencing a MID within a dyad by 18%, as illustrated in Figure 6. [Figure 6 About Here] Dominance Vacuums and Politics <u>On the <strong>chessboard of international politics</u></strong> the dynamics of regions and the security of <u>states are subject to the <strong>ordering influence</strong> by dominant powers</u>. However, their influence is not constant across geographic space, as their relative capabilities deteriorate across distance. <u><mark>Within</u></mark> dominance <u><mark>vacuums</mark>, where <strong><mark>no clear leader exists</strong></mark> to structure</u> international <u>politics, the formation of “shatterbelts” is likely as</u> other <u><mark>states are <strong>less restrained</strong></mark> by dominant powers</u>. As demonstrated by our findings and descriptive analysis, <u><mark>these</mark> vacuums <mark>present the <strong>most likely contexts</u></strong></mark> of geopolitical spaces <u><mark>for conflict</u></mark> onset in the international system. We may expect, for instance, the clustering of conflicts in the Middle East and Africa to continue until a shift in the power hierarchy within these geographic spaces terminates the vacuum. By contrast, the implications for states moving out of vacuums may be observed in the rapid evolution of the preexisting European Economic Community into the more sophisticated and cooperative institutional structures of the European Union with the Maastricht Treaty following the end of the Cold War. While we provide an important component to explaining the opportunity for states to engage in conflict given the contextual salience of the systemic environment, willingness to engage in conflict remains a product of dyadic and domestic level indicators, ranging across historical, cultural, national, and ideological grievances, territory, and economic interests. Yet, <u>our theory</u> also <u>provides a compelling case</u> in those instances <u>where</u> these <u>willingness measures are present, but conflict does not occur, including</u> many <u><strong>ongoing territorial disputes</strong> such as Japan and Russia’s</u> continued disagreement over the <u>Kuril Islands, Guatemala’s</u> territorial <u>claims on Belize, or British and Spanish disagreement over Gibraltar. The framework for identifying</u> probable <u>conflict</u> locations in this effort <u>has</u> the potential for <u>numerous other applications</u>. First, further exploration of the regional dynamics identified by Lemke (2002) is warranted. We examined only the projected capabilities of the most powerful states in a geographic space. Applying our analysis to regional subsystems nested within the dominant power reach used here to define vacuums may have important implications for regional politics, as well as the prospects for regional powers such as Brazil and India to achieve future major power status as they attempt to reconcile regional concerns and focus globally (Volgy et al. 2014). Consistent with the literature on regional politics over the past century, it is likely that the intersection of dominant power capabilities with regional power dynamics is an additional component influencing regional stability (e.g. Buzan and Waever 2003; Katzenstein 2005). In fact, an analysis of regions based in part on the extent to which those geopolitical spaces vary according to the extent of the existence of dominance vacuums may yield fruitful inter-regional comparisons regarding conflict processes. Second, <u>our theory is based upon the <strong>stability of a clear hierarchy</strong> in international politics and</u> the <u><mark>instability result</mark>ing <mark>when <strong>hierarchical dominance</strong> is degraded</u></mark> over geopolitical spaces. Logically, <u>the byproducts of</u> this <u>instability should not</u> simply <u>be restricted to MIDs, but</u> also <u>other forms of political violence</u>. For example, the decline of piracy in the South China Sea coincides with the rise of Chinese dominance in the geographic space in the early 1990s (Prins and Daxecker 2011) and domestic conflicts in Central and Eastern Africa likely reside within very consistent power vacuums. <u>The <mark>absence</mark> of a clearly defined hierarchy</u> over a geographic space <u>may <mark>increase</mark> the probability of <strong><mark>civil war</strong></mark>, <strong>separatist movements</strong>, <strong><mark>terrorism</strong>, and</u></mark> perhaps even the ending of <u><strong>enduring <mark>rivalries</u></strong></mark>. Research relating such vacuums to the locations of extra and intra- state violence is a logical next step toward a better understanding of peace and conflict in the international system.</p> | 1AC - CS | 1AC – China | 1AC – Primacy | 63,869 | 136 | 72,849 | ./documents/hsld20/Peninsula/Si/Peninsula-Sims-Aff-Berkeley-Round1.docx | 870,746 | A | Berkeley | 1 | Modernbrain AW | Annabelle Long | 1AC -- China
1NC -- T Nebel
2NR -- T Nebel | hsld20/Peninsula/Si/Peninsula-Sims-Aff-Berkeley-Round1.docx | null | 73,633 | ChSi | Peninsula ChSi | null | Ch..... | Si..... | null | null | 24,672 | Peninsula | Peninsula | CA | null | 1,028 | hsld20 | HS LD 2020-21 | 2,020 | ld | hs | 1 |
1,563,844 | Democracies are not a monolithic system—even if some democracies are problematic, ones with more accountability and civic engagement are less likely to engage in regional warfare, have armed conflict, etc. | Cortright 13 | Cortright 13 [David Cortright, American Scholar and peace activist, director of policy studies at the Kroc Institute for international peace studies at the university of Notre Dame and Chair of the Board of the Fourth Freedom forum, “How State Capacity and Regime Type Influence the prospects for war and peace, https://oefresearch.org/sites/default/files/documents/publications/Cortright-Seyle-Wall-Paper.pdf ] JJ | A trend runs through nearly all of the empirical studies on the democratic peace effect. Fully mature democratic states with high threshold scores on indicators of voice and accountability have the lowest risk of war and armed conflict. The characteristics of democracy that are most strongly associated with the absence of armed conflict and violent repression are political representativeness and inclusiveness These are made possible by, civil liberties and human rights.
As democracies become more inclusive, their risk of armed conflict diminishes Discriminatory policies increase the risk of civil war, while guarantees of political freedom reduce that risk. The more participatory and open the political governance system the lower the chances of armed conflict and political violence. Peace is more likely when people are free to participate actively in choosing political decision makers and when diverse interests have effective political representation. Programs that foster citizen participation, inclusive institutions, accountability mechanisms, and greater public oversight bolster the conditions for peace.
Effective institutions prevent armed conflict when they provide security and civilian services, and when they are inclusive and representative Effective capacity and democratic governance go hand in hand and need to be combined to create the greatest peace effect.
governments are better able to prevent armed conflict if they have strong institutions and maintain effective control over their territory, and if they provide the full range of public goods, including essential social services. The findings also highlight the importance of fostering governance systems with greater citizen participation and oversight, more inclusive and accountable forms of representation, and guarantees of political freedom and human rights. These and other policy approaches help to reduce the risk of armed conflict and are part of the process through which good governance promotes peace. | A trend through all l studies Fully mature democratic states have the lowest risk of war
As democracies become more inclusive, armed conflict diminishes Discriminatory policies increase risk of civil war Programs that foster citizen participation, and greater p oversight bolster peace.
governments are better able to prevent armed conflict if they have strong institutions | A recurring trend runs through nearly all of the empirical studies on the democratic peace effect. Fully mature democratic states with high threshold scores on indicators of voice and accountability have the lowest risk of war and armed conflict. The characteristics of democracy that are most strongly associated with the absence of armed conflict and violent repression are political representativeness and inclusiveness. These are made possible by, and help to sustain, essential civil liberties and human rights.
Walter, Reynal-Querol, Joshi, Davenport, and other scholars come to similar conclusions on the irenic effect of inclusive and participatory forms of governance. Jeffrey Dixon confirms these findings in his synthesis of quantitative studies on the correlates of civil war. As democracies become more inclusive, their risk of armed conflict diminishes. Discriminatory policies increase the risk of civil war, while guarantees of political freedom reduce that risk.140 The more participatory and open the political governance system the lower the chances of armed conflict and political violence. Peace is more likely when people are free to participate actively in choosing political decision makers and when diverse interests have effective political representation. Programs that foster citizen participation, inclusive institutions, accountability mechanisms, and greater public oversight bolster the conditions for peace.
The two parts of this paper examine state capacity and democracy separately, but the irenic features of these separate dimensions overlap and reinforce one another. Effective institutions prevent armed conflict when they provide security and civilian services, and when they are inclusive and representative. A narrow focus on one dimension of governance—for example building strong institutions while ignoring the need for democratic accountability—could be counterproductive. Effective capacity and democratic governance go hand in hand and need to be combined to create the greatest peace effect.
Social science research confirms that governments are better able to prevent armed conflict if they have strong institutions and maintain effective control over their territory, and if they provide the full range of public goods, including essential social services. The findings also highlight the importance of fostering governance systems with greater citizen participation and oversight, more inclusive and accountable forms of representation, and guarantees of political freedom and human rights. These and other policy approaches help to reduce the risk of armed conflict and are part of the process through which good governance promotes peace. | 2,692 | <h4>Democracies are not a <u>monolithic system—</u>even if some democracies are problematic, ones with more accountability and civic engagement are less likely to engage in regional warfare, have armed conflict, etc. </h4><p><strong>Cortright 13</strong> [David Cortright, American Scholar and peace activist, director of policy studies at the Kroc Institute for international peace studies at the university of Notre Dame and Chair of the Board of the Fourth Freedom forum, “How State Capacity and Regime Type Influence the prospects for war and peace, https://oefresearch.org/sites/default/files/documents/publications/Cortright-Seyle-Wall-Paper.pdf ] JJ</p><p><u><strong><mark>A</mark> </u></strong>recurring <u><strong><mark>trend</strong></mark> runs <strong><mark>through</mark> </strong>nearly <strong><mark>all</strong></mark> of the <strong>empirica<mark>l studies</strong></mark> on the democratic peace effect. <strong><mark>Fully mature democratic states</strong></mark> with high threshold scores on indicators of voice and accountability <strong><mark>have the lowest risk of war </mark>and armed conflict.</u></strong> <u>The characteristics of democracy that are most strongly associated with the absence of armed conflict and violent repression are political representativeness and inclusiveness</u>. <u>These are made possible by,</u> and help to sustain, essential <u><strong>civil liberties and human rights.</p><p></u></strong> Walter, Reynal-Querol, Joshi, Davenport, and other scholars come to similar conclusions on the irenic effect of inclusive and participatory forms of governance. Jeffrey Dixon confirms these findings in his synthesis of quantitative studies on the correlates of civil war. <u><strong><mark>As democracies become more inclusive, </mark>their risk of <mark>armed conflict diminishes</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong><mark>Discriminatory policies increase</strong></mark> the <strong><mark>risk of civil war</strong></mark>, while guarantees of political freedom reduce that risk.</u>140 <u>The more participatory and open the political governance system the lower the chances of armed conflict and political violence. Peace is more likely when people are free to participate actively in choosing political decision makers and when diverse interests have effective political representation.</u> <u><strong><mark>Programs that foster citizen participation, </mark>inclusive institutions</strong>, accountability mechanisms, <strong><mark>and greater p</mark>ublic <mark>oversight bolster </mark>the conditions for <mark>peace.</strong></mark> </p><p></u>The two parts of this paper examine state capacity and democracy separately, but the irenic features of these separate dimensions overlap and reinforce one another. <u>Effective institutions prevent armed conflict when they provide security and civilian services, and when they are inclusive and representative</u>. A narrow focus on one dimension of governance—for example building strong institutions while ignoring the need for democratic accountability—could be counterproductive. <u>Effective capacity and democratic governance go hand in hand and need to be combined to create the greatest peace effect. </p><p></u>Social science research confirms that <u><strong><mark>governments are better able to prevent armed conflict if they have strong institutions</strong></mark> and maintain effective control over their territory, and if they provide the full range of public goods, including essential social services.</u> <u>The findings also highlight the importance of fostering governance systems with greater citizen participation and oversight, more inclusive and accountable forms of representation, and guarantees of political freedom and human rights. These and other policy approaches help to reduce the risk of armed conflict and are part of the process through which good governance promotes peace.</p></u> | Democracy Aff | null | Advantage – Democracy – Long | 687,777 | 103 | 45,045 | ./documents/hsld21/SouthlakeCarroll/Pi/Southlake%20Carroll-Pinjani-Aff-florida%20blue%20key%20round%20robin-Round3.docx | 899,265 | A | florida blue key round robin | 3 | lexington vm | abhilash datti, raunak dua | 1ac- democracy
1nc - skep nc tt split brain infinite regress aprioris 1ar theory heg interp - aff may not run cx checks (
1ar - all
2nr - skep nc aprioris
2ar - skep independent voter | hsld21/SouthlakeCarroll/Pi/Southlake%20Carroll-Pinjani-Aff-florida%20blue%20key%20round%20robin-Round3.docx | null | 75,341 | EnPi | Southlake Carroll EnPi | null | En..... | Pi..... | null | null | 25,168 | SouthlakeCarroll | Southlake Carroll | TX | null | 1,029 | hsld21 | HS LD 2021-22 | 2,021 | ld | hs | 1 |
1,545,940 | Overthinking paradox- the 1NC is a form of unnecessary overthinking that prevents decisions to be made so don’t evaluate it | Wikipedia | Wikipedia [Brackets Original. “Analysis Paralysis”. Wikipedia. No Date. https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Bonini%27s_paradox] | overanalyzing or overthinking a situation can cause forward motion or decision-making to become [frozen] "paralyzed", meaning that no solution or course of action is decided upon. A situation may be deemed too complicated and a decision is never made, due to the fear that a potentially larger problem may arise. A person may desire a perfect solution, but may fear making a decision that could result in error, while on the way to a better solution. | overanalyzing a situation cause decision-making to become [frozen] meaning that no solution or course of action is decided upon decision is never made, due to the fear that a potentially larger problem may arise. | Analysis paralysis (or paralysis by analysis) describes an individual or group process when overanalyzing or overthinking a situation can cause forward motion or decision-making to become [frozen] "paralyzed", meaning that no solution or course of action is decided upon. A situation may be deemed too complicated and a decision is never made, due to the fear that a potentially larger problem may arise. A person may desire a perfect solution, but may fear making a decision that could result in error, while on the way to a better solution. Equally, a person may hold that a superior solution is a short step away, and stall in its endless pursuit, with no concept of diminishing returns. On the opposite end of the time spectrum is the phrase extinct by instinct, which is making a fatal decision based on hasty judgment or a gut reaction. | 842 | <h4>Overthinking paradox- the 1NC is a form of unnecessary overthinking that prevents decisions to be made so don’t evaluate it</h4><p><strong>Wikipedia</strong> [Brackets Original. “Analysis Paralysis”. Wikipedia. No Date. https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Bonini%27s_paradox]</p><p>Analysis paralysis (or paralysis by analysis) describes an individual or group process when <u><mark>overanalyzing</mark> or overthinking <mark>a situation</mark> can <mark>cause</mark> forward motion or <mark>decision-making to become [frozen]</mark> "paralyzed", <mark>meaning that no solution or course of action is decided upon</mark>. A situation may be deemed too complicated and a <mark>decision is never made, due to the fear that a potentially larger problem may arise.</mark> A person may desire a perfect solution, but may fear making a decision that could result in error, while on the way to a better solution. </u>Equally, a person may hold that a superior solution is a short step away, and stall in its endless pursuit, with no concept of diminishing returns. On the opposite end of the time spectrum is the phrase extinct by instinct, which is making a fatal decision based on hasty judgment or a gut reaction.</p> | 1AC | null | 1AC – Framework | 327,084 | 95 | 44,285 | ./documents/hsld21/SanMateo/Ra/San%20Mateo-Rao-Aff-grapevine-Round2.docx | 897,846 | A | grapevine | 2 | strake jk | connor self | 1ac - agonism
1nc - must not read eval after ac psycho
1ar - new off case
2nr - psycho case
2ar - same | hsld21/SanMateo/Ra/San%20Mateo-Rao-Aff-grapevine-Round2.docx | null | 75,300 | YeRa | San Mateo YeRa | null | Ye..... | Ra..... | null | null | 25,154 | SanMateo | San Mateo | CA | null | 1,029 | hsld21 | HS LD 2021-22 | 2,021 | ld | hs | 1 |
606,376 | Debris triggers miscalculated war. | Dockrill 16 | Dockrill 16 [Peter; 2016; Award-winning science & technology journalist. “Space Junk Accidents Could Trigger Armed Conflict, Study Finds.” https://www.sciencealert.com/space-junk-accidents-could-trigger-armed-conflict-expert-warns] brett | The increasingly crowded space in Earth's low orbit could set the stage for an international armed conflict that accidents stemming from the steady rise in space junk floating around the planet could incite political rows and even war with nations potentially mistaking debris-caused incidents as the results of intentional aggressive acts by others. team suggests that space debris in the form of spent rocket parts and other fragments of hardware hurtling at high speed pose a "special political danger" that could dangerously escalate tensions between nations. destructive impacts caused by random space junk cannot easily be told apart from military attacks. The owner of the impacted and destroyed satellite can hardly quickly determine the real cause of the accident The risks of such an event occurring are compounded by the sheer volume of debris now orbiting Earth. Recent figures from NASA indicate that there are more than 500,000 pieces of space junk currently being tracked in orbit, travelling at speeds up to 28,160 km/h NASA estimates that there are millions of undetectable pieces of debris in orbit that are too small to be monitored. But even extremely small fragments such as these pose a threat – in fact, they're considered a greater risk than trackable debris, as their invisible status means spacecraft and satellites can't do anything to avoid them until it's too late. Even tiny paint flecks can damage a spacecraft when travelling at these velocities While we may have been lucky in the past, we can't rely on that to continue cites the repeated sudden failures of defence satellites in past decades that were never explained. The researchers attribute two possible causes: either unrecorded collisions with space junk, or aggressive actions from adversaries. "This is a politically dangerous dilemma | crowded space in low orbit set the stage for an international armed conflict accidents from space junk incite war with nations mistaking debris as intentional aggressive acts that could escalate tensions impacts cannot be told apart from military attacks. risks are compounded by the sheer volume of debris extremely small fragments pose greater risk as their invisible status means satellites can't avoid them we have been lucky we can't rely on that | The increasingly crowded space in Earth's low orbit could set the stage for an international armed conflict, says a new study. Researchers from the Russian Academy of Sciences warn that accidents stemming from the steady rise in space junk floating around the planet could incite political rows and even warfare, with nations potentially mistaking debris-caused incidents as the results of intentional aggressive acts by others. In a paper published in Acta Astronautica, the team suggests that space debris in the form of spent rocket parts and other fragments of hardware hurtling at high speed pose a "special political danger" that could dangerously escalate tensions between nations. According to the study, destructive impacts caused by random space junk cannot easily be told apart from military attacks. "The owner of the impacted and destroyed satellite can hardly quickly determine the real cause of the accident," the authors write. The risks of such an event occurring are compounded by the sheer volume of debris now orbiting Earth. Recent figures from NASA indicate that there are more than 500,000 pieces of space junk currently being tracked in orbit, travelling at speeds up to 28,160 km/h (17,500 mph). The majority of those objects are small – around the size of a marble – but some 20,000 of them are bigger than a softball. In addition to these 500,000 or so fragments – which are big enough for scientists to know about them – NASA estimates that there are millions of undetectable pieces of debris in orbit that are too small to be monitored. But even extremely small fragments such as these pose a threat – in fact, they're considered a greater risk than trackable debris, as their invisible status means spacecraft and satellites can't do anything to avoid them until it's too late. As NASA observed in 2013: "Even tiny paint flecks can damage a spacecraft when travelling at these velocities. In fact a number of space shuttle windows have been replaced because of damage caused by material that was analysed and shown to be paint flecks… With so much orbital debris, there have been surprisingly few disastrous collisions." While we may have been lucky in the past, we can't rely on that to continue. The study by the Russian team cites the repeated sudden failures of defence satellites in past decades that were never explained. The researchers attribute two possible causes: either unrecorded collisions with space junk, or aggressive actions from adversaries. "This is a politically dangerous dilemma," the authors write. | 2,552 | <h4>Debris triggers <u>miscalculated war</u>.</h4><p><strong>Dockrill 16</strong> [Peter; 2016; Award-winning science & technology journalist. “Space Junk Accidents Could Trigger Armed Conflict, Study Finds.” https://www.sciencealert.com/space-junk-accidents-could-trigger-armed-conflict-expert-warns] <u>brett</p><p>The increasingly <mark>crowded space in</mark> Earth's <mark>low orbit</mark> could <mark>set the stage for an <strong>international armed conflict</u></strong></mark>, says a new study. Researchers from the Russian Academy of Sciences warn <u>that <mark>accidents</mark> stemming <mark>from</mark> the steady rise in <mark>space junk</mark> floating around the planet could <mark>incite</mark> <strong>political rows</strong> and even <strong><mark>war</u></strong></mark>fare, <u><mark>with nations</mark> potentially <strong><mark>mistaking debris</strong></mark>-caused incidents <mark>as</mark> the results of <strong><mark>intentional aggressive acts</mark> </strong>by others. </u>In a paper published in Acta Astronautica, the <u>team suggests that space debris in the form of spent rocket parts and other fragments of hardware hurtling at high speed pose a "<strong>special political danger</strong>" <mark>that could</mark> <strong>dangerously <mark>escalate</strong></mark> <mark>tensions</mark> between nations. </u>According to the study, <u>destructive <mark>impacts</mark> caused by random space junk <mark>cannot</mark> easily <mark>be told apart from military attacks.</u></mark> "<u>The owner of the impacted and destroyed satellite can hardly quickly determine the real cause of the accident</u>," the authors write. <u>The <mark>risks</mark> of such an event occurring <mark>are compounded by the <strong>sheer volume</strong> of debris</mark> now orbiting Earth. Recent figures from NASA indicate that there are more than 500,000 pieces of space junk currently being tracked in orbit, travelling at speeds up to 28,160 km/h</u> (17,500 mph). The majority of those objects are small – around the size of a marble – but some 20,000 of them are bigger than a softball. In addition to these 500,000 or so fragments – which are big enough for scientists to know about them – <u>NASA estimates that there are millions of undetectable pieces of debris in orbit that are too small to be monitored. But even <mark>extremely small fragments</mark> such as these <mark>pose</mark> a threat – in fact, they're considered a <mark>greater risk </mark>than trackable debris, <mark>as their <strong>invisible status</strong> means</mark> spacecraft and <mark>satellites can't</mark> do anything to <mark>avoid them <strong></mark>until it's too late.</u></strong> As NASA observed in 2013:<u> </u>"<u>Even tiny paint flecks can damage a spacecraft when travelling at these velocities</u>. In fact a number of space shuttle windows have been replaced because of damage caused by material that was analysed and shown to be paint flecks… With so much orbital debris, there have been surprisingly few disastrous collisions." <u>While <mark>we</mark> may <mark>have been lucky</mark> in the past, <strong><mark>we can't rely on that</mark> to continue</u></strong>. The study by the Russian team <u>cites the repeated sudden failures of defence satellites in past decades that were never explained. The researchers attribute two possible causes: either unrecorded collisions with space junk, or aggressive actions from adversaries. "This is a <strong>politically dangerous dilemma</u>," the authors write.</p></strong> | Harvard R6 1AC---Debris // Constellations | null | null | 339,330 | 337 | 10,578 | ./documents/hsld21/CarnegieVanguard/Hu/Carnegie%20Vanguard-Huang-Aff-Harvard-Round6.docx | 884,614 | A | Harvard | 6 | Jupiter KG | Hever Arjon | 1ac - constellations v6
1nc - cap good space ex space col
1ar - all
2nr - case space ex space col
2ar - case space ex space col | hsld21/CarnegieVanguard/Hu/Carnegie%20Vanguard-Huang-Aff-Harvard-Round6.docx | null | 74,467 | LaHu | Carnegie Vanguard LaHu | null | La..... | Hu..... | null | null | 24,939 | CarnegieVanguard | Carnegie Vanguard | TX | null | 1,029 | hsld21 | HS LD 2021-22 | 2,021 | ld | hs | 1 |
1,121,625 | Attacks on critical infrastructure cause tit-for-tat escalation to nuke war. | Klare 19 | Klare 19 [Michael T. Klare, professor emeritus of peace and world security studies at Hampshire College, “Cyber Battles, Nuclear Outcomes? Dangerous New Pathways to Escalation,” Arms Control Association, November 2019, armscontrol.org/act/2019-11/features/cyber-battles-nuclear-outcomes-dangerous-new-pathways-escalation] | another pathway to escalation could arise from a cascading series of cyberstrikes and counterstrikes against vital national infrastructure rather than on military targets. All major powers, along with Iran and North Korea, have developed and deployed cyberweapons designed to disrupt and destroy key economic systems power grids, financial systems, and transportation network
economic attacks of this sort, if undertaken during a period of tension and crisis, could lead to an escalating series of tit-for-tat attacks against ever more vital elements of an adversary’s critical infrastructure eventually leading one side to initiate kinetic attacks on critical military targets risking the slippery slope to nuclear conflict a Russian cyberattack on the U.S. power grid could trigger U.S. attacks on energy and financial systems generating an impulse for even more devastating attacks lead to major conflict and possibly nuclear war.”14
As states’ reliance on cyberspace grows and cyberweapons become more powerful, the dangers of unintended or accidental escalation can only grow more severe. | escalation could arise from cascading cyberstrikes and counterstrikes against national infra Iran and No Ko developed and deployed cyberweapons to destroy economic systems
could lead to escalating tit-for-tat attacks against infra initiate kinetic attacks on military targets slippery slope to nuclear conflict generating an impulse for more devastating attacks to nuc war
dangers of unintended or accidental escalation grow | Yet another pathway to escalation could arise from a cascading series of cyberstrikes and counterstrikes against vital national infrastructure rather than on military targets. All major powers, along with Iran and North Korea, have developed and deployed cyberweapons designed to disrupt and destroy major elements of an adversary’s key economic systems, such as power grids, financial systems, and transportation networks. As noted, Russia has infiltrated the U.S. electrical grid, and it is widely believed that the United States has done the same in Russia.12 The Pentagon has also devised a plan known as “Nitro Zeus,” intended to immobilize the entire Iranian economy and so force it to capitulate to U.S. demands or, if that approach failed, to pave the way for a crippling air and missile attack.13
The danger here is that economic attacks of this sort, if undertaken during a period of tension and crisis, could lead to an escalating series of tit-for-tat attacks against ever more vital elements of an adversary’s critical infrastructure, producing widespread chaos and harm and eventually leading one side to initiate kinetic attacks on critical military targets, risking the slippery slope to nuclear conflict. For example, a Russian cyberattack on the U.S. power grid could trigger U.S. attacks on Russian energy and financial systems, causing widespread disorder in both countries and generating an impulse for even more devastating attacks. At some point, such attacks “could lead to major conflict and possibly nuclear war.”14
These are by no means the only pathways to escalation resulting from the offensive use of cyberweapons. Others include efforts by third parties, such as proxy states or terrorist organizations, to provoke a global nuclear crisis by causing early-warning systems to generate false readings (“spoofing”) of missile launches. Yet, they do provide a clear indication of the severity of the threat. As states’ reliance on cyberspace grows and cyberweapons become more powerful, the dangers of unintended or accidental escalation can only grow more severe. | 2,092 | <h4>Attacks on critical infrastructure cause <u>tit-for-tat escalation</u> to nuke war.</h4><p><strong>Klare 19</strong> [Michael T. Klare, professor emeritus of peace and world security studies at Hampshire College, “Cyber Battles, Nuclear Outcomes? Dangerous New Pathways to Escalation,” Arms Control Association, November 2019, armscontrol.org/act/2019-11/features/cyber-battles-nuclear-outcomes-dangerous-new-pathways-escalation]</p><p>Yet <u>another pathway to <mark>escalation could arise from</mark> a <mark>cascading</mark> series of <mark>cyberstrikes and counterstrikes against</mark> vital <mark>national infra</mark>structure rather than on military targets.</u> <u>All major powers, along with <mark>Iran and No</mark>rth <mark>Ko</mark>rea, have <mark>developed and deployed</mark> <mark>cyberweapons</mark> designed <mark>to</mark> disrupt and <mark>destroy</u></mark> major elements of an adversary’s <u>key <mark>economic systems</u></mark>, such as <u>power grids, financial systems, and transportation network</u>s. As noted, Russia has infiltrated the U.S. electrical grid, and it is widely believed that the United States has done the same in Russia.12 The Pentagon has also devised a plan known as “Nitro Zeus,” intended to immobilize the entire Iranian economy and so force it to capitulate to U.S. demands or, if that approach failed, to pave the way for a crippling air and missile attack.13 </p><p>The danger here is that <u>economic attacks of this sort, if undertaken during a period of tension and crisis, <mark>could lead to</mark> an <mark>escalating</mark> series of <mark>tit-for-tat attacks against</mark> ever more vital elements of an adversary’s critical <mark>infra</mark>structure</u>, producing widespread chaos and harm and <u>eventually leading one side to <mark>initiate kinetic attacks on</mark> critical <mark>military targets</u></mark>, <u><strong>risking the <mark>slippery slope to nuclear</mark> <mark>conflict</u></strong></mark>. For example, <u>a Russian cyberattack on the U.S. power grid</u> <u>could trigger U.S. attacks on</u> Russian <u>energy and financial systems</u>, causing widespread disorder in both countries and <u><mark>generating an impulse for</mark> even <mark>more devastating attacks</u></mark>. At some point, such attacks “could <u>lead <mark>to</mark> major conflict and possibly <strong><mark>nuc</mark>lear <mark>war</strong></mark>.”14 </p><p></u>These are by no means the only pathways to escalation resulting from the offensive use of cyberweapons. Others include efforts by third parties, such as proxy states or terrorist organizations, to provoke a global nuclear crisis by causing early-warning systems to generate false readings (“spoofing”) of missile launches. Yet, they do provide a clear indication of the severity of the threat. <u>As states’ reliance on cyberspace grows and cyberweapons become more powerful, the <mark>dangers of</mark> <mark>unintended or accidental escalation</mark> can only <mark>grow</mark> more severe.</p></u> | null | CP | 1NC – Privatization CP | 55 | 1,568 | 26,902 | ./documents/hspolicy21/Gunn/VaSh/Gunn-Valame-Shirts-Neg-03%20-%20Heart%20of%20Texas-Octas.docx | 747,472 | N | 03 - Heart of Texas | Octas | Kinkaid FZ | Panel | 1AC - Tribal WQS
1NC - T Substantial T Its T Cessation Infrastructure DA EPA DA States CP Privatization CP Set Col K
2NR - Infrastructure DA | hspolicy21/Gunn/VaSh/Gunn-Valame-Shirts-Neg-03%20-%20Heart%20of%20Texas-Octas.docx | null | 63,768 | VaSh | Gunn VaSh | null | Vi..... | Va..... | Ja..... | Sh..... | 21,983 | Gunn | Gunn | CA | null | 1,020 | hspolicy21 | HS Policy 2021-22 | 2,021 | cx | hs | 2 |
4,158,576 | Extinction | Thomas 20 . | Mike Thomas 20. Quoting AI experts including MIT Physics Professors, Senior Features Writer for BuiltIn. THE FUTURE OF ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE: 7 ways AI can change the world for better ... or worse, Updated: April 20, 2020, https://builtin.com/artificial-intelligence/artificial-intelligence-future | Klabjan puts little stock in extreme scenarios involving murderous cyborgs that turn the earth into a smoldering hellscape. He’s much more concerned with machines being fed faulty “incentives” by humans. As MIT physics professors and leading AI researcher put it in a 2018 TED Talk, “The real threat from AI isn’t malice, like in silly Hollywood movies, but competence — AI accomplishing goals that just aren’t aligned with ours the scenario where something wakes up and decides to take over the world that’s science fiction and not the way it’s going to play out.” But There are several major breakthroughs that have to occur, and could come very quickly Referencing the rapid transformational effect of nuclear fission he added, “It’s very, very hard to predict when these conceptual breakthroughs are going to happen But whenever they do he emphasized the importance of preparation. That means working to eliminate data bias, which has a corrupting effect on algorithms and is currently a fat fly in the AI ointment And it means having the humility to realize that just because we can doesn’t mean we should. AGI researchers expect AGI within decades, and if we just bumble into this unprepared, it will be the biggest mistake in human history It could enable brutal dictatorship with unprecedented inequality, surveillance, suffering and maybe even human extinction But if we steer carefully, we could end up in a fantastic future where everybody’s better off—the poor are richer, the rich are richer, everybody’s healthy and free | Klabjan concerned with machines being fed faulty “incentives” by humans MIT physics professors and leading AI researcher put it real threat from AI is competence emphasized importance of preparation. means working to eliminate data bias, which has corrupting effect on algorithms and fat fly in AI ointment expect AGI and if we bumble unprepared, it will be biggest mistake in human history enable brutal dictatorship with unprecedented inequality suffering and extinction if we steer carefully end up in fantastic future | Klabjan also puts little stock in extreme scenarios — the type involving, say, murderous cyborgs that turn the earth into a smoldering hellscape. He’s much more concerned with machines — war robots, for instance — being fed faulty “incentives” by nefarious humans. As MIT physics professors and leading AI researcher Max Tegmark put it in a 2018 TED Talk, “The real threat from AI isn’t malice, like in silly Hollywood movies, but competence — AI accomplishing goals that just aren’t aligned with ours.” That’s Laird’s take, too. “I definitely don’t see the scenario where something wakes up and decides it wants to take over the world,” he says. “I think that’s science fiction and not the way it’s going to play out.” What Laird worries most about isn’t evil AI, per se, but “evil humans using AI as a sort of false force multiplier” for things like bank robbery and credit card fraud, among many other crimes. And so, while he’s often frustrated with the pace of progress, AI’s slow burn may actually be a blessing. “Time to understand what we’re creating and how we’re going to incorporate it into society,” Laird says, “might be exactly what we need.” But no one knows for sure. “There are several major breakthroughs that have to occur, and those could come very quickly,” Russell said during his Westminster talk. Referencing the rapid transformational effect of nuclear fission (atom splitting) by British physicist Ernest Rutherford in 1917, he added, “It’s very, very hard to predict when these conceptual breakthroughs are going to happen.” But whenever they do, if they do, he emphasized the importance of preparation. That means starting or continuing discussions about the ethical use of A.G.I. and whether it should be regulated. That means working to eliminate data bias, which has a corrupting effect on algorithms and is currently a fat fly in the AI ointment. That means working to invent and augment security measures capable of keeping the technology in check. And it means having the humility to realize that just because we can doesn’t mean we should. “Our situation with technology is complicated, but the big picture is rather simple,” Tegmark said during his TED Talk. “Most AGI researchers expect AGI within decades, and if we just bumble into this unprepared, it will probably be the biggest mistake in human history. It could enable brutal global dictatorship with unprecedented inequality, surveillance, suffering and maybe even human extinction. But if we steer carefully, we could end up in a fantastic future where everybody’s better off—the poor are richer, the rich are richer, everybody’s healthy and free to live out their dreams.” | 2,668 | <h4>Extinction </h4><p>Mike<strong> Thomas 20</strong>. Quoting AI experts including MIT Physics Professors, Senior Features Writer for BuiltIn<strong>. </strong>THE FUTURE OF ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE: 7 ways AI can change the world for better ... or worse, Updated: April 20, 2020, https://builtin.com/artificial-intelligence/artificial-intelligence-future</p><p><u><mark>Klabjan</u></mark> also <u>puts <strong>little stock in extreme scenarios</u></strong> — the type <u>involving</u>, say, <u>murderous cyborgs that turn the earth into a smoldering hellscape. He’s <strong>much</strong> more <mark>concerned with machines</u></mark> — war robots, for instance — <u><mark>being <strong>fed faulty “incentives</strong>” by</u></mark> nefarious <u><mark>humans</mark>. As <mark>MIT physics professors and leading AI researcher</u></mark> Max Tegmark <u><mark>put it</mark> in a 2018 TED Talk, “The <strong><mark>real threat</strong> from AI is</mark>n’t <strong>malice</strong>, like in silly Hollywood movies, but <strong><mark>competence</strong></mark> — AI accomplishing goals that just aren’t aligned with ours</u>.” That’s Laird’s take, too. “I definitely don’t see <u>the scenario where something wakes up and decides</u> it wants <u>to take over the world</u>,” he says. “I think <u>that’s science fiction and not the way it’s going to play out.”</u> What Laird worries most about isn’t evil AI, per se, but “evil humans using AI as a sort of false force multiplier” for things like bank robbery and credit card fraud, among many other crimes. And so, while he’s often frustrated with the pace of progress, AI’s slow burn may actually be a blessing. “Time to understand what we’re creating and how we’re going to incorporate it into society,” Laird says, “might be exactly what we need.” <u>But</u> no one knows for sure. “<u>There are several major breakthroughs that have to occur, and</u> those <u>could come very quickly</u>,” Russell said during his Westminster talk. <u>Referencing the rapid transformational effect of nuclear fission</u> (atom splitting) by British physicist Ernest Rutherford in 1917, <u>he added, “It’s very, very hard to predict when these conceptual breakthroughs are going to happen</u>.” <u>But whenever they do</u>, if they do, <u>he <mark>emphasized</mark> the <mark>importance of preparation.</mark> </u>That means starting or continuing discussions about the ethical use of A.G.I. and whether it should be regulated. <u>That <mark>means working to <strong>eliminate data bias</strong>, which has</mark> a <strong><mark>corrupting effect on algorithms</strong> and</mark> is <strong>currently a <mark>fat fly in</mark> the <mark>AI ointment</u></strong></mark>. That means working to invent and augment security measures capable of keeping the technology in check. <u>And it means having the humility to realize that just because we can doesn’t mean we should. </u>“Our situation with technology is complicated, but the big picture is rather simple,” Tegmark said during his TED Talk. “Most <u>AGI researchers <mark>expect AGI</mark> within decades, <mark>and <strong>if we</mark> just <mark>bumble</mark> into this <mark>unprepared</strong>, it will</u></mark> probably <u><strong><mark>be</mark> the <mark>biggest mistake in human history</u></strong></mark>. <u>It could <mark>enable brutal</u></mark> global <u><mark>dictatorship with <strong>unprecedented inequality</strong></mark>, surveillance, <strong><mark>suffering</strong> and</mark> maybe <strong>even human <mark>extinction</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong>But <mark>if we steer carefully</strong></mark>, we could <mark>end up in</mark> a <strong><mark>fantastic future</u></strong></mark> <u>where <strong>everybody’s better off</strong>—the poor are richer, the rich are richer, <strong>everybody’s healthy and free</u></strong> to live out their dreams.”</p> | null | null | AT: Humans = Biased | 32,802 | 338 | 142,864 | ./documents/ndtceda22/Emory/GiKe/Emory-GiKe-Neg-georgetown-Round-8.docx | 959,245 | N | georgetown | 8 | dartmouth SV | perkins | 1AC - civil duties
1NC - civil duties pic, automation DA, politics DA, ai bad turn, t vest = all, court clog DA
2NC - civil duties pic
1NR - automation DA
2NR - civil duties pic | ndtceda22/Emory/GiKe/Emory-GiKe-Neg-georgetown-Round-8.docx | 2023-01-07 01:47:55 | 80,491 | GiKe | Emory GiKe | null | Eu..... | Gi..... | Gr..... | Ke..... | 27,030 | Emory | Emory | null | null | 2,001 | ndtceda22 | NDT/CEDA College 2022-23 | 2,022 | cx | college | 2 |
48,741 | The plan spills over to form a radically protective doctrine. All areas of ecosystems are intrinsically connected. Applying the public trust doctrine to every arc of the water cycle ensures every tangentially related impact is resolved. That solves imminent converging crisis, including warming — extinction. | Olson ’14 | Olson ’14 — James Olson, Founder and President of FLOW, Lecturer, University of Michigan Law School, and Michigan Department of Natural Resources LL.M., University of Michigan, J.D., Detroit College of Law, Michigan State University College of Law; (2014; “ARTICLE: ALL ABOARD: NAVIGATING THE COURSE FOR UNIVERSAL ADOPTION OF THE PUBLIC TRUST DOCTRINE”; University of Michigan Libraries, Nexis Uni; University of Vermont Journal of Environmental Law, Vol. 15; //LFS—JCM) | public trust principles are important for protecting the sustainable limits of water resources universal adoption of public trust principles could be applied with equal force to many of the threats to our earth's water, air, and ecosystems so vital to health a sustainable economy quality of life and wellbeing all of the waters of the earth through the hydrologic cycle the threats to the Great Lakes are part of the same natural processes and human behavior that threaten the planet everywhere to better address the threats connect the dots and look at all inputs and outputs impacts and effects of the entire water cycle the actions causing harm to the water cycle and ecosystem can all be considered at once there is a dynamic living snapshot of how human activities and natural processes interact in the air on the earth under the ground in wetlands creeks streams lakes and the oceans showing these interactions at every arc of the water cycle the public trust in water navigable or other has any basic value it is the outside limitation or umbrella on any actions by government or others that might effect protected public trust uses so vital to every person A good example is climate change and the impacts of dislocation or diversion of water
the evidence shows that climate change the effect of greenhouse gases on the atmosphere is impacting the water cycle by altering precipitation and causing water levels to drop it would violate the significant impairment standard of the public trust doctrine the dead zone in Lake Erie caused by increased warming and nutrient run-off and discharges that resulted in upended boating and shut down a large portion of the local fishery for the season fisheries and water resources are protected public trust resources
public trust law and principles could be used to address and remedy harm or seek equitable relief to force government to take affirmative actions consistent with its duty to protect these public trust uses and resources the public trust doctrine would be used to mitigate conduct that affects the hydrosphere the approach is no different than the courts extending the reach of the public trust doctrine to tributary streams or groundwater the approach is within the traditional scope of the doctrine because neither government or private persons could interfere with the public rights of navigation fishing or boating As the scope of public trust resources have been extended the remedies to protect them damages equitable remedies or enforcement are extended accordingly
trust cannot be abdicated or alienated If the public trust is applied to every arc of the water cycle that affects public trust waters the waters and these uses cannot be subordinated or harmed If they are then the human actions that contribute to or cause such harm are necessarily limited because of the overarching duty to protect the integrity of the waters for the beneficiaries of this and future generations
For these reasons a possible answer is the immediate adoption of a new narrative that view the systemic threats we face as part of the single connected hydrological whole a commons governed by public trust principles public trust is necessary to solve these threats that impact public trust resources Every arc of the water cycle flows through and effects and is affected by everything else the water cycle and the life cycle are one | universal trust could be applied to many threats to earth vital to health economy quality of life and wellbeing connect the dots of the water cycle harm can all be considered at once there is dynamic interactions at every arc public trust in water is the umbrella on any actions by government that might effect protected trust
climate change the effect of g h g s is impacting water it would violate the doctrine the dead zone caused by run-off water resources are protected trust
trust could force government to take affirmative actions to protect resources mitigate the hydrosphere neither government or private persons could interfere with public rights
If applied to water waters cannot be harmed If they are the actions that cause harm are limited for future generations
adopt a new narrative that view systemic threats we face as part of the connected hydro whole Every arc flows through everything else water and life are one | But public trust principles are not only important for protecting the sustainable limits of the Great Lakes and connected or tributary waters and water resources. The reasons described in this article calling for universal adoption of public trust principles for the Great Lakes under the framework of the IJC could be applied with equal force to many of the threats to our earth's water, air, and ecosystems so vital to health, a sustainable economy, quality of life and wellbeing. Just as the waters of the Great Lakes Basin [*189] are a single whole, so too are all of the waters of the earth through the hydrologic cycle or through what might characterized as the "hydrosphere." 282 The examples of the threats to the Great Lakes are part of the same natural processes and human behavior that threaten the planet everywhere. In order to better comprehend and address the threats simultaneously, scientists are beginning to connect the dots, and look at all inputs and outputs, impacts and effects of the entire water cycle in a given watershed. By doing this, the various actions causing harm or benefit to the water cycle and ecosystem can all be considered at once. As science begins to do this, there is a corresponding dynamic living snapshot of how human activities and natural processes interact in the air, on the earth, under the ground, in wetlands, creeks, streams, lakes, and the oceans--in effect showing these interactions at every arc of the water cycle or hydrosphere. If the public trust in water, particularly navigable or other waters and natural features recognized as such by law, has any basic value at all, it is the outside limitation or umbrella on any actions by government or others that might effect protected public trust uses so vital to every person, individually and as a member of the community. A good example is the relationship between climate change and the impacts of dislocation or diversion of water from the Great Lakes Basin demonstrated by the recent nearly unprecedented drops in water levels in Lake Michigan and Lake Huron.
As described in Section IV above, if the scientific evidence shows that climate change, that is, the effect of greenhouse gases on the atmosphere, is impacting the water cycle by altering precipitation patterns and causing water levels to drop, it would violate the no subordination or significant impairment standard of the public trust doctrine. Another example is the 3,000 square kilometer "dead zone" in Lake Erie that developed during the summer of 2011. 283 The dead zone was caused by increased warming and nutrient run-off and discharges that resulted in closed beaches, upended recreational boating and tourism, and shut down a large portion of the local fishery for the season. 284 Fishing, boating, swimming and recreation are [*190] protected uses, 285 and fisheries and water resources are protected public trust resources. 286
In both examples, public trust law and principles could be used to address and remedy harm or seek equitable relief against those causing the harm, or used to force government to take affirmative actions consistent with its duty to protect these public trust uses and resources. And in both instances, the public trust doctrine would be used to mitigate conduct that affects the hydrosphere through its direct affect on the hydrologic cycle. Theoretically, the approach is no different than the California Supreme Court or other courts extending the reach of the public trust doctrine to tributary streams or groundwater. 287 Moreover, the approach is within the traditional scope of the doctrine, because under the earliest cases neither government or private persons could interfere with the public rights of navigation, fishing, or boating. As the scope of public trust resources or public uses of these resources have been extended, the remedies to protect them--damages, equitable remedies, or enforcement of affirmative duties--are extended accordingly.
B. Toward a Public Trust in the Hydrologic Cycle
Water passes through the atmosphere as vapor, precipitates to earth as rain, snow, or something in between, runs over the surface and percolates into the ground, enters the roots of plants through uptake, transpires and evaporates back into the atmosphere, or percolates downward into underground moving lakes or pools or streams known as groundwater or aquifers. Water moves though saturated soil or rock, collects and rises forth as springs or seeps and forms wetlands, creeks, streams, ponds, lakes, and rivers and larger lakes, and runs to the sea, all the while evaporating back into the atmosphere, around and around in a cycle, everywhere in some form and at some rate of movement all at once. At every arc of the cycle, water gives back and absorbs--to and from plants, wildlife, human beings. Water gains and loses through the natural hydrological cycle that flows continuously. As recognized by the eminent 19th century jurist Thomas [*191] Cooley, "water is a moveable, wandering thing, and must of necessity continue common by the law of nature." 288
In the words of the U.S. Supreme Court in the Illinois Central case, nullifying a deed to part of Lake Michigan given by the State of Illinois to a private railroad company, "this trust cannot be abdicated or alienated." 289 It cannot be impaired, not the water, not the public purposes. The principles mean that the resource and its uses are to remain in public control, for the public good and purposes, and without substantial interference or impairment. If the public trust is applied to every arc of the water cycle that affects public trust waters, especially traditional navigable waters, the waters and these uses cannot be subordinated or harmed. If they are harmed or impaired, then the human actions that contribute to or cause such subordination or harm are necessarily limited because of the overarching duty to protect the integrity of the waters and uses for the beneficiaries of this and future generations. 290
For these reasons, a possible answer is the immediate adoption of a new narrative, with principles grounded in science, values, and policy, that view the systemic threats we face as part of the single connected hydrological whole, a commons governed by public trust principles. The public trust is necessary to solve these threats that directly impact traditional public trust resources like the Great Lakes and its tributary waters. The most obvious whole is not a construct of mind, but the one in which we live--the hydrosphere, basin, and watershed through which water flows, evaporates, transpires, is used, transferred, and is discharged in a continuous cycle. Every arc of the water cycle flows through and effects and is affected by everything else, reminiscent of what Jacques Cousteau once said, "We forget that the water cycle and the life cycle are one." 291 | 6,885 | <h4>The plan <u>spills over</u> to form a <u>radically protective doctrine</u>. All areas of ecosystems are intrinsically connected. Applying the public trust doctrine to every arc of the water cycle ensures every <u>tangentially related impact</u> is resolved. That solves imminent converging crisis, including warming — <u>extinction</u>.</h4><p><strong>Olson ’14</strong> — James Olson, Founder and President of FLOW, Lecturer, University of Michigan Law School, and Michigan Department of Natural Resources LL.M., University of Michigan, J.D., Detroit College of Law, Michigan State University College of Law; (2014; “ARTICLE: ALL ABOARD: NAVIGATING THE COURSE FOR UNIVERSAL ADOPTION OF THE PUBLIC TRUST DOCTRINE”; University of Michigan Libraries, Nexis Uni; University of Vermont Journal of Environmental Law, Vol. 15; //LFS—JCM)</p><p>But <u><strong>public trust</u></strong> <u>principles are</u> not only <u>important for <strong>protecting</u></strong> <u>the sustainable limits</u> <u>of</u> the Great Lakes and connected or tributary waters and <u><strong>water resources</u></strong>. The reasons described in this article calling for <u><mark>universal</mark> <strong>adoption</u></strong> <u>of public <mark>trust</u></mark> <u>principles</u> for the Great Lakes under the framework of the IJC <u><strong><mark>could be applied</u></strong></mark> <u>with equal force</u> <u><mark>to many</mark> of</u> <u>the <mark>threats to</mark> our</u> <u><mark>earth</mark>'s <strong>water, air, and ecosystems</u></strong> <u>so <mark>vital to</mark> <strong><mark>health</u></strong></mark>, <u>a <strong>sustainable <mark>economy</u></strong></mark>, <u><strong><mark>quality of life</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>and</mark> <strong><mark>wellbeing</u></strong></mark>. Just as the waters of the Great Lakes Basin [*189] are a single whole, so too are <u>all of the waters</u> <u>of the earth</u> <u>through the</u> <u>hydrologic cycle</u> or through what might characterized as the "hydrosphere." 282 The examples of <u>the threats</u> <u>to the</u> <u>Great Lakes</u> <u>are part of the</u> <u>same natural processes</u> <u>and human behavior</u> <u>that <strong>threaten the planet</strong> everywhere</u>. In order <u>to better</u> comprehend and <u>address the</u> <u>threats</u> simultaneously, scientists are beginning to <u><strong><mark>connect the dots</u></strong></mark>, <u>and look at all</u> <u>inputs and outputs</u>, <u>impacts and effects</u> <u><mark>of the</mark> entire</u> <u><mark>water cycle</u></mark> in a given watershed. By doing this, <u>the</u> various <u>actions causing <mark>harm</u></mark> or benefit <u>to the water</u> <u>cycle and ecosystem</u> <u><mark>can all be</mark> <mark>considered</u> <u>at once</u></mark>. As science begins to do this, <u><mark>there is</mark> a</u> corresponding <u><strong><mark>dynamic</mark> living snapshot</u></strong> <u>of how human</u> <u>activities and</u> <u>natural processes</u> <u>interact in the <strong>air</u></strong>, <u>on the <strong>earth</u></strong>, <u>under the <strong>ground</u></strong>, <u>in <strong>wetlands</u></strong>, <u><strong>creeks</u></strong>, <u><strong>streams</u></strong>, <u><strong>lakes</u></strong>, <u>and the <strong>oceans</u></strong>--in effect <u>showing</u> <u>these <mark>interactions</u></mark> <u><mark>at every arc</u></mark> <u>of the water cycle</u> or hydrosphere. If <u>the</u> <u><strong><mark>public trust in water</u></strong></mark>, particularly <u>navigable or other</u> waters and natural features recognized as such by law, <u>has any basic</u> <u>value</u> at all, <u>it <mark>is the</mark> <strong>outside limitation or <mark>umbrella</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>on any</mark> <mark>actions by</mark> <mark>government</u></mark> <u>or others <mark>that</u> <u>might</mark> <mark>effect</u></mark> <u><mark>protected</mark> public <mark>trust</u></mark> <u>uses so vital</u> <u>to every person</u>, individually and as a member of the community. <u>A good example</u> <u>is</u> the relationship between <u><strong>climate change</u></strong> <u>and the impacts</u> <u>of dislocation</u> <u>or <strong>diversion of water</u></strong> from the Great Lakes Basin demonstrated by the recent nearly unprecedented drops in water levels in Lake Michigan and Lake Huron.</p><p>As described in Section IV above, if <u>the</u> scientific <u>evidence shows that</u> <u><strong><mark>climate change</u></strong></mark>, that is, <u><mark>the effect of</u></mark> <u><strong><mark>g</mark>reen<mark>h</mark>ouse <mark>g</mark>ase<mark>s</u></strong></mark> <u>on the atmosphere</u>, <u><mark>is impacting</u></mark> <u>the <strong><mark>water</mark> cycle</u></strong> <u>by altering</u> <u>precipitation</u> patterns <u>and causing</u> <u>water levels to drop</u>, <u><mark>it would</mark> <mark>violate the</u></mark> no subordination or <u><strong>significant impairment</u></strong> <u>standard of the</u> <u>public trust <mark>doctrine</u></mark>. Another example is <u><mark>the</u></mark> 3,000 square kilometer "<u><strong><mark>dead zone</u></strong></mark>" <u>in Lake Erie</u> that developed during the summer of 2011. 283 The dead zone was <u><mark>caused by</mark> increased</u> <u><strong>warming</strong> and</u> <u>nutrient <strong><mark>run-off</u></strong></mark> <u>and discharges</u> <u>that resulted in</u> closed beaches, <u>upended</u> recreational <u>boating</u> and tourism, <u>and</u> <u><strong>shut down</strong> a</u> <u>large portion</u> <u>of the local <strong>fishery</u></strong> <u>for the season</u>. 284 Fishing, boating, swimming and recreation are [*190] protected uses, 285 and <u>fisheries and</u> <u><strong><mark>water resources</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>are protected</u></mark> <u><strong>public <mark>trust </mark>resources</u></strong>. 286</p><p>In both examples, <u>public <mark>trust</mark> law</u> <u>and principles</u> <u><mark>could</mark> be used</u> <u>to address</u> <u>and remedy harm</u> <u>or seek equitable relief</u> against those causing the harm, or used <u>to <mark>force government</u></mark> <u><mark>to take</u></mark> <u><strong><mark>affirmative actions</strong></mark> consistent</u> <u>with its duty</u> <u><mark>to protect</u></mark> <u>these <strong>public trust uses</strong> and <mark>resources</u></mark>. And in both instances, <u>the public trust</u> <u>doctrine would</u> <u>be used to</u> <u><mark>mitigate</mark> conduct</u> <u>that affects</u> <u><mark>the hydrosphere</u></mark> through its direct affect on the hydrologic cycle. Theoretically, <u>the approach is no</u> <u>different than the</u> California Supreme Court or other <u>courts extending</u> <u>the reach of the</u> <u><strong>public trust doctrine</u></strong> <u>to tributary streams</u> <u>or groundwater</u>. 287 Moreover, <u>the approach</u> <u>is within</u> <u>the traditional</u> <u><strong>scope of the doctrine</u></strong>, <u>because</u> under the earliest cases <u><strong><mark>neither government</mark> <mark>or private</mark> <mark>persons</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>could interfere</u></mark> <u><mark>with</mark> the</u> <u><mark>public rights</u></mark> <u>of navigation</u>, <u>fishing</u>, <u>or boating</u>. <u>As the scope</u> <u>of <strong>public trust resources</u></strong> or public uses of these resources <u>have been extended</u>, <u>the <strong>remedies</u></strong> <u>to protect them</u>--<u>damages</u>, <u>equitable remedies</u>, <u>or enforcement</u> of affirmative duties--<u>are <strong>extended</strong> accordingly</u>.</p><p>B. Toward a Public Trust in the Hydrologic Cycle</p><p>Water passes through the atmosphere as vapor, precipitates to earth as rain, snow, or something in between, runs over the surface and percolates into the ground, enters the roots of plants through uptake, transpires and evaporates back into the atmosphere, or percolates downward into underground moving lakes or pools or streams known as groundwater or aquifers. Water moves though saturated soil or rock, collects and rises forth as springs or seeps and forms wetlands, creeks, streams, ponds, lakes, and rivers and larger lakes, and runs to the sea, all the while evaporating back into the atmosphere, around and around in a cycle, everywhere in some form and at some rate of movement all at once. At every arc of the cycle, water gives back and absorbs--to and from plants, wildlife, human beings. Water gains and loses through the natural hydrological cycle that flows continuously. As recognized by the eminent 19th century jurist Thomas [*191] Cooley, "water is a moveable, wandering thing, and must of necessity continue common by the law of nature." 288</p><p>In the words of the U.S. Supreme Court in the Illinois Central case, nullifying a deed to part of Lake Michigan given by the State of Illinois to a private railroad company, "this <u>trust <strong>cannot be abdicated</strong> or alienated</u>." 289 It cannot be impaired, not the water, not the public purposes. The principles mean that the resource and its uses are to remain in public control, for the public good and purposes, and without substantial interference or impairment. <u><mark>If</mark> the <strong>public trust</u></strong> <u>is <mark>applied to</mark> <strong>every arc of the <mark>water</mark> cycle</u></strong> <u>that affects</u> <u>public trust waters</u>, especially traditional navigable waters, <u>the <mark>waters</u></mark> <u>and these uses</u> <u><mark>cannot be</mark> subordinated</u> <u>or</u> <u><mark>harmed</u></mark>. <u><mark>If they are</u></mark> harmed or impaired, <u>then <mark>the</mark> <strong>human <mark>actions</strong> that</mark> contribute</u> <u>to or <mark>cause</u></mark> <u>such</u> subordination or <u><mark>harm are</mark> necessarily <strong><mark>limited</u></strong></mark> <u>because of the</u> <u>overarching duty</u> <u>to protect the integrity</u> <u>of the waters</u> and uses <u><mark>for</mark> the beneficiaries</u> <u>of this and</u> <u><strong><mark>future generations</u></strong></mark>. 290</p><p><u>For these reasons</u>, <u>a possible answer is</u> <u>the <strong>immediate <mark>adopt</mark>ion</strong> of <mark>a</u> <u>new narrative</u></mark>, with principles grounded in science, values, and policy, <u><mark>that view</mark> the</u> <u><strong><mark>systemic threats</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>we face as</u></mark> <u><mark>part of the</u></mark> <u>single <mark>connected</mark> <strong><mark>hydro</mark>logical <mark>whole</u></strong></mark>, <u>a commons</u> <u>governed by</u> <u>public trust principles</u>. The <u>public trust</u> <u>is <strong>necessary to solve</strong> these</u> <u>threats that</u> directly <u>impact</u> traditional <u>public trust resources</u> like the Great Lakes and its tributary waters. The most obvious whole is not a construct of mind, but the one in which we live--the hydrosphere, basin, and watershed through which water flows, evaporates, transpires, is used, transferred, and is discharged in a continuous cycle. <u><strong><mark>Every arc</strong></mark> of the</u> <u>water cycle</u> <u><mark>flows through</u></mark> <u>and effects</u> <u>and is <strong>affected by <mark>everything else</u></strong></mark>, reminiscent of what Jacques Cousteau once said, "We forget that <u>the <mark>water</mark> cycle <mark>and</u></mark> <u>the <mark>life</mark> cycle <mark>are one</u></mark>." 291</p> | Aff – PTD – BFHPR | 1ac ptd | 1ac ptd adv | 33,687 | 129 | 850 | ./documents/openev/2021/UM7/PTD Aff - Michigan7 2021 BFHPR.docx | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null |
785,833 | Collapses heg—challengers abroad and allied prolif | Haddick 10 | Robert Haddick 10, Managing Editor of the Small Wars Journal, This Week at War: If Mexico Is at War, Does America Have to Win It?, Sept 10, http://www.foreignpolicy.com/articles/2010/09/10/this_week_at_war_if_mexico_is_at_war_does_america_have_to_win_it | Clinton said, "We face an increasing threat from a well-organized network, drug-trafficking threat that is, morphing into, what we would consider an insurgency The clashes over shipping routes and distribution power could just as well occur inside the United States Isolating Mexico's cartel insurgents from their enormous American revenue base a crucial step in a counterinsurgency campaign , a strengthening Mexican insurgency would very likely affect America's role in the rest of the world. An increasingly chaotic American side of the border, marked by bloody cartel wars and a breakdown in security, would likely cause many in the United States to question the importance of military and foreign policy ventures elsewhere in the world.¶ Should the southern border become a U.S. president's primary national security concern, nervous allies and opportunistic adversaries elsewhere in the world would no doubt adjust to a distracted and inward-looking America, with potentially disruptive arms races the result. | We face an increasing threat from trafficking that is morphing into an insurgency Isolating cartel insurgents from their enormous American revenue -- a crucial step a strengthening insurgency would affect America's role in the world. An increasingly chaotic border and a breakdown in security, would cause many to question the importance of foreign policy ventures elsewhere Should the southern border become a primary concern, nervous allies and opportunistic adversaries would adjust to a distracted and inward-looking America, with disruptive arms races the result | While answering a question on Mexico this week at the Council on Foreign Relations, U.S. Secretary of State Hillary Clinton said, "We face an increasing threat from a well-organized network, drug-trafficking threat that is, in some cases, morphing into, or making common cause with, what we would consider an insurgency." Mexico's foreign minister Patricia Espinosa was quick to dispute this characterization, arguing that Mexico's drug cartels have no political agenda. But as I have previously discussed, the cartels, evidenced by their attacks on both the government and the media, are gradually becoming political insurgents as a means of defending their turf.¶ I note that Clinton used the phrase "We [the United States] face an increasing threat ...," not "they [Mexico]." The cartels are transnational shipping businesses, with consumers in the United States as their dominant market. The clashes over shipping routes and distribution power -- which over the past four years have killed 28,000 and thoroughly corrupted Mexico's police and judiciary -- could just as well occur inside the United States. Indeed, growing anxiety that southern Arizona is in danger of becoming a "no-go zone" controlled by drug and human traffickers contributed to the passage of Arizona's controversial immigration enforcement statute earlier this year.¶ Both Clinton and Mexican officials have discussed Colombia's struggle against extreme drug violence and corruption, revealing concerns about how dreadful the situation in Mexico might yet become and also as a model for how to recover from disaster. Colombia's long climb from the abyss, aided by the U.S. government's Plan Colombia assistance, should certainly give hope to Mexico's counterinsurgents. But if the United States and Mexico are to achieve similar success, both will have to resolve political dilemmas that would prevent effective action. Clinton herself acknowledged as much when she remarked that Plan Colombia was "controversial ... there were problems and there were mistakes. But it worked."¶ Isolating Mexico's cartel insurgents from their enormous American revenue base -- a crucial step in a counterinsurgency campaign -- may require a much more severe border crackdown, an action that would be highly controversial in both the United States and Mexico. Plan Colombia was a success partly because of the long-term presence of U.S. Special Forces advisers, intelligence experts, and other military specialists inside Colombia, a presence which would not please most Mexicans. And Colombia's long counterattack against its insurgents resulted in actions that boiled the blood of many human rights observers.¶ Most significantly, a strengthening Mexican insurgency would very likely affect America's role in the rest of the world. An increasingly chaotic American side of the border, marked by bloody cartel wars, corrupted government and media, and a breakdown in security, would likely cause many in the United States to question the importance of military and foreign policy ventures elsewhere in the world.¶ Should the southern border become a U.S. president's primary national security concern, nervous allies and opportunistic adversaries elsewhere in the world would no doubt adjust to a distracted and inward-looking America, with potentially disruptive arms races the result. Secretary Clinton has looked south and now sees an insurgency. Let's hope that the United States can apply what it has recently learned about insurgencies to stop this one from getting out of control. | 3,546 | <h4>Collapses heg—challengers abroad and allied prolif</h4><p>Robert <strong>Haddick 10</strong>, Managing Editor of the Small Wars Journal, This Week at War: If Mexico Is at War, Does America Have to Win It?, Sept 10, http://www.foreignpolicy.com/articles/2010/09/10/this_week_at_war_if_mexico_is_at_war_does_america_have_to_win_it</p><p>While answering a question on Mexico this week at the Council on Foreign Relations, U.S. Secretary of State Hillary <u>Clinton said, "<mark>We face an increasing threat from</mark> a well-organized network, drug-<mark>trafficking</mark> threat <mark>that is</mark>,</u> in some cases, <u><mark>morphing into</mark>, </u>or making common cause with, <u>what we would consider <mark>an insurgency</u></mark>." Mexico's foreign minister Patricia Espinosa was quick to dispute this characterization, arguing that Mexico's drug cartels have no political agenda. But as I have previously discussed, the cartels, evidenced by their attacks on both the government and the media, are gradually becoming political insurgents as a means of defending their turf.¶ I note that Clinton used the phrase "We [the United States] face an increasing threat ...," not "they [Mexico]." The cartels are transnational shipping businesses, with consumers in the United States as their dominant market. <u>The clashes over shipping routes and distribution power</u> -- which over the past four years have killed 28,000 and thoroughly corrupted Mexico's police and judiciary -- <u>could just as well occur inside the United States</u>. Indeed, growing anxiety that southern Arizona is in danger of becoming a "no-go zone" controlled by drug and human traffickers contributed to the passage of Arizona's controversial immigration enforcement statute earlier this year.¶ Both Clinton and Mexican officials have discussed Colombia's struggle against extreme drug violence and corruption, revealing concerns about how dreadful the situation in Mexico might yet become and also as a model for how to recover from disaster. Colombia's long climb from the abyss, aided by the U.S. government's Plan Colombia assistance, should certainly give hope to Mexico's counterinsurgents. But if the United States and Mexico are to achieve similar success, both will have to resolve political dilemmas that would prevent effective action. Clinton herself acknowledged as much when she remarked that Plan Colombia was "controversial ... there were problems and there were mistakes. But it worked."¶ <u><mark>Isolating </mark>Mexico's <mark>cartel insurgents from their enormous American revenue </mark>base</u> <mark>-- <u><strong>a crucial step</mark> in a counterinsurgency campaign</u></strong> -- may require a much more severe border crackdown, an action that would be highly controversial in both the United States and Mexico. Plan Colombia was a success partly because of the long-term presence of U.S. Special Forces advisers, intelligence experts, and other military specialists inside Colombia, a presence which would not please most Mexicans. And Colombia's long counterattack against its insurgents resulted in actions that boiled the blood of many human rights observers.¶ Most significantly<u>, <mark>a strengthening </mark>Mexican <mark>insurgency would</mark> <strong>very likely <mark>affect America's role in the</mark> rest of the <mark>world.</u></strong> <u>An increasingly chaotic </mark>American side of the <mark>border</mark>, marked by bloody cartel wars</u>, corrupted government and media, <u><mark>and a breakdown in security, would</mark> likely <mark>cause many </mark>in the United States <mark>to question the importance of</mark> military and <mark>foreign policy ventures elsewhere</mark> in the world.¶ <mark>Should the southern border become a</mark> U.S. president's <mark>primary</mark> national security <mark>concern, <strong>nervous allies and opportunistic adversaries</mark> elsewhere in the world <mark>would</mark> no doubt <mark>adjust to a distracted and inward-looking America, with</mark> potentially <mark>disruptive arms races the result</mark>.</u></strong> Secretary Clinton has looked south and now sees an insurgency. Let's hope that the United States can apply what it has recently learned about insurgencies to stop this one from getting out of control.</p> | null | 1ac | Adv 2 | 41,370 | 368 | 18,377 | ./documents/ndtceda14/Michigan/PaAl/Michigan-Pappas-Allen-Aff-Wake-Round5.docx | 568,538 | A | Wake | 5 | Liberty Apthorp-Murray | Galloway | null | ndtceda14/Michigan/PaAl/Michigan-Pappas-Allen-Aff-Wake-Round5.docx | null | 48,712 | PaAl | Michigan PaAl | null | Al..... | Pa..... | El..... | Al..... | 18,792 | Michigan | Michigan | null | null | 1,004 | ndtceda14 | NDT/CEDA 2014-15 | 2,014 | cx | college | 2 |
809,738 | “Resolved” is legislative | Parcher 1 | Jeff Parcher 1, former debate coach at Georgetown, Feb 2001 http://www.ndtceda.com/archives/200102/0790.html | American Heritage Dictionary: Resolve Firmness of resolution A determination or decision The very nature of the word "resolution" makes it a question A course of action determined or decided on as by a legislature Further context: the word resolved is used to emphasis the fact that it's policy debate Resolved comes from the adoption of resolutions by legislative bodies. | American Heritage Dictionary: Resolve A determination or decision resolved is used to emphasis the fact that it's policy debate. Resolved comes from the adoption of resolutions by legislative bodies | Pardon me if I turn to a source besides Bill. American Heritage Dictionary: Resolve: 1. To make a firm decision about. 2. To decide or express by formal vote. 3. To separate something into constiutent parts See Syns at *analyze* (emphasis in orginal) 4. Find a solution to. See Syns at *Solve* (emphasis in original) 5. To dispel: resolve a doubt. - n 1. Firmness of purpose; resolution. 2. A determination or decision. (2) The very nature of the word "resolution" makes it a question. American Heritage: A course of action determined or decided on. A formal statement of a decision, as by a legislature. (3) The resolution is obviously a question. Any other conclusion is utterly inconceivable. Why? Context. The debate community empowers a topic committee to write a topic for ALTERNATE side debating. The committee is not a random group of people coming together to "reserve" themselves about some issue. There is context - they are empowered by a community to do something. In their deliberations, the topic community attempts to craft a resolution which can be ANSWERED in either direction. They focus on issues like ground and fairness because they know the resolution will serve as the basis for debate which will be resolved by determining the policy desirablility of that resolution. That's not only what they do, but it's what we REQUIRE them to do. We don't just send the topic committee somewhere to adopt their own group resolution. It's not the end point of a resolution adopted by a body - it's the preliminary wording of a resolution sent to others to be answered or decided upon. (4) Further context: the word resolved is used to emphasis the fact that it's policy debate. Resolved comes from the adoption of resolutions by legislative bodies. A resolution is either adopted or it is not. It's a question before a legislative body. Should this statement be adopted or not. (5) The very terms 'affirmative' and 'negative' support my view. One affirms a resolution. Affirmative and negative are the equivalents of 'yes' or 'no' - which, of course, are answers to a question. | 2,089 | <h4>“Resolved” is legislative </h4><p>Jeff <strong>Parcher 1</strong>, former debate coach at Georgetown, Feb 2001 http://www.ndtceda.com/archives/200102/0790.html</p><p>Pardon me if I turn to a source besides Bill. <u><mark>American Heritage Dictionary: Resolve</u></mark>: 1. To make a firm decision about. 2. To decide or express by formal vote. 3. To separate something into constiutent parts See Syns at *analyze* (emphasis in orginal) 4. Find a solution to. See Syns at *Solve* (emphasis in original) 5. To dispel: resolve a doubt. - n 1. <u>Firmness of </u>purpose; <u>resolution</u>. 2. <u><mark>A determination or decision</u></mark>. (2) <u>The very nature of the word "resolution" makes it a question</u>. American Heritage: <u>A course of action determined or decided on</u>. A formal statement of a decision, <u>as by a legislature</u>. (3) The resolution is obviously a question. Any other conclusion is utterly inconceivable. Why? Context. The debate community empowers a topic committee to write a topic for ALTERNATE side debating. The committee is not a random group of people coming together to "reserve" themselves about some issue. There is context - they are empowered by a community to do something. In their deliberations, the topic community attempts to craft a resolution which can be ANSWERED in either direction. They focus on issues like ground and fairness because they know the resolution will serve as the basis for debate which will be resolved by determining the policy desirablility of that resolution. That's not only what they do, but it's what we REQUIRE them to do. We don't just send the topic committee somewhere to adopt their own group resolution. It's not the end point of a resolution adopted by a body - it's the preliminary wording of a resolution sent to others to be answered or decided upon. (4) <u>Further context: the word <mark>resolved is used to emphasis the fact that it's policy debate</u>. <u>Resolved comes from the adoption of resolutions by <strong>legislative bodies</strong></mark>.</u> A resolution is either adopted or it is not. It's a question before a legislative body. Should this statement be adopted or not. (5) The very terms 'affirmative' and 'negative' support my view. One affirms a resolution. Affirmative and negative are the equivalents of 'yes' or 'no' - which, of course, are answers to a question. </p> | null | null | 1NC | 1,136 | 861 | 19,031 | ./documents/ndtceda14/Trinity/VaTo/Trinity-Vargas-Torres-Neg-Weberswing-Round2.docx | 570,341 | N | Weberswing | 2 | Kansas State Pena-Ramirez | Montee | 1AC - Decolonial Prositution
1NC - Framework Anthro K Bhambra (Case)
2NR - Anthro K | ndtceda14/Trinity/VaTo/Trinity-Vargas-Torres-Neg-Weberswing-Round2.docx | null | 48,842 | VaTo | Trinity VaTo | null | Cr..... | Va..... | Ro..... | To..... | 18,818 | Trinity | Trinity | null | null | 1,004 | ndtceda14 | NDT/CEDA 2014-15 | 2,014 | cx | college | 2 |
1,306,694 | Middle East wars cause extinction | Russell 9 | Russell 9
James A. Russell, Senior Lecturer, National Security Affairs, Naval Postgraduate School, ‘9 (Spring) “Strategic Stability Reconsidered: Prospects for Escalation and Nuclear War in the Middle East” IFRI, Proliferation Papers//, #26, __http://www.ifri.org/downloads/PP26_Russell_2009.pdf__ | Strategic stability is undermined by the presence of non-state actors that introduce unpredictability into relationships between the antagonists; incompatible assumptions about the structure of the deterrent relationship that makes the bargaining framework strategically unstable the lack of a communications framework to build trust and cooperation among framework participants escalation by any the parties could happen as a result of miscalculation or the pressures of wartime circumstance a conflict could quickly escalate in which the regional antagonists would consider the use nuclear weapons an unprecedented disaster for | stability is undermined by actors that introduce unpredictability incompatible assumptions about the deterrent relationship the lack of a framework to build trust escalation could happen as a result of miscalculation or the pressures a conflict could quickly escalate in which the regional antagonists would consider the use nuclear weapons an unprecedented disaster for | Strategic stability in the region is thus undermined by various factors: (1) asymmetric interests in the bargaining framework that can introduce unpredictable behavior from actors; (2) the presence of non-state actors that introduce unpredictability into relationships between the antagonists; (3) incompatible assumptions about the structure of the deterrent relationship that makes the bargaining framework strategically unstable; (4) perceptions by Israel and the United States that its window of opportunity for military action is closing, which could prompt a preventive attack; (5) the prospect that Iran’s response to pre-emptive attacks could involve unconventional weapons, which could prompt escalation by Israel and/or the United States; (6) the lack of a communications framework to build trust and cooperation among framework participants. These systemic weaknesses in the coercive bargaining framework all suggest that escalation by any the parties could happen either on purpose or as a result of miscalculation or the pressures of wartime circumstance. Given these factors, it is disturbingly easy to imagine scenarios under which a conflict could quickly escalate in which the regional antagonists would consider the use of chemical, biological, or nuclear weapons. It would be a mistake to believe the nuclear taboo can somehow magically keep nuclear weapons from being used in the context of an unstable strategic framework. Systemic asymmetries between actors in fact suggest a certain increase in the probability of war – a war in which escalation could happen quickly and from a variety of participants. Once such a war starts, events would likely develop a momentum all their own and decision-making would consequently be shaped in unpredictable ways. The international community must take this possibility seriously, and muster every tool at its disposal to prevent such an outcome, which would be an unprecedented disaster for the peoples of the region, with substantial risk for the entire world. | 2,022 | <h4><strong>Middle East wars cause extinction</h4><p>Russell 9</strong> </p><p>James A. Russell, Senior Lecturer, National Security Affairs, Naval Postgraduate School, ‘9 (Spring) “Strategic Stability Reconsidered: Prospects for Escalation and Nuclear War in the Middle East” IFRI, Proliferation Papers//, #26, <u>__http://www.ifri.org/downloads/PP26_Russell_2009.pdf__</p><p>Strategic <mark>stability</u></mark> in the region <u><mark>is</u></mark> thus <u><mark>undermined</mark> <mark>by</u></mark> various factors: (1) asymmetric interests in the bargaining framework that can introduce unpredictable behavior from actors; (2) <u>the presence of non-state <mark>actors that introduce unpredictability </mark>into relationships between the antagonists;</u> (3) <u><mark>incompatible assumptions about</mark> the structure of <mark>the deterrent relationship</mark> that makes the bargaining framework strategically unstable</u>; (4) perceptions by Israel and the United States that its window of opportunity for military action is closing, which could prompt a preventive attack; (5) the prospect that Iran’s response to pre-emptive attacks could involve unconventional weapons, which could prompt escalation by Israel and/or the United States; (6) <u><mark>the lack of a</mark> communications <mark>framework to build trust</mark> and cooperation among framework participants</u>. These systemic weaknesses in the coercive bargaining framework all suggest that <u><mark>escalation </mark>by any the parties <mark>could happen</mark> </u>either on purpose or <u><mark>as a result of miscalculation or the pressures </mark>of wartime circumstance</u>. Given these factors, it is disturbingly easy to imagine scenarios under which <u><mark>a conflict could <strong>quickly escalate</strong> in which the regional antagonists would consider the use</u></mark> of chemical, biological, or <u><strong><mark>nuclear weapons</u></strong></mark>. It would be a mistake to believe the nuclear taboo can somehow magically keep nuclear weapons from being used in the context of an unstable strategic framework. Systemic asymmetries between actors in fact suggest a certain increase in the probability of war – a war in which escalation could happen quickly and from a variety of participants. Once such a war starts, events would likely develop a momentum all their own and decision-making would consequently be shaped in unpredictable ways. The international community must take this possibility seriously, and muster every tool at its disposal to prevent such an outcome, which would be <u><mark>an <strong>unprecedented disaster</strong> for</u></mark> the peoples of the region, with substantial risk for the <strong>entire world.</p></strong> | 1AC | null | 1AC—ISIS | 54,072 | 393 | 33,325 | ./documents/ndtceda15/WakeForest/SiSh/Wake%20Forest-Sims-Shapiro-Aff-Liberty-Round4.docx | 585,827 | A | Liberty | 4 | JMU GT | Tom OGorman | 1NC - T - its T- reduce T significant Surge CP Saudi DA
2NR - T - significant | ndtceda15/WakeForest/SiSh/Wake%20Forest-Sims-Shapiro-Aff-Liberty-Round4.docx | null | 50,047 | SiSh | Wake Forest SiSh | null | Ca..... | Si..... | Ka..... | Sh..... | 18,998 | WakeForest | Wake Forest | null | null | 1,005 | ndtceda15 | NDT/CEDA 2015-16 | 2,015 | cx | college | 2 |
2,188,280 | 3. Disregarding foreseeable harm reifies structures of domination | McCluskey 12 | McCluskey 12 – JSD @ Columbia, Professor of Law @ SUNY-Buffalo | By similarly making structures of inequality appear beyond the reach of law the "unintended consequences" message helps update and reinforce the narrowing of protections against intentional racial harm. Justice is centrally a question of whose harms should count Power is centrally about being able to act without having to take harm to others into account This power to gain by harming others is strongest when it operates through structures that make disregarding that harm appear acceptable the unintended consequences" story helps affirm the resulting harm The unequal effects of policy are foreseeable and obvious, not accidental or surprising justice requires careful attention to both harmful intent and to complex harmful effects the concept of "unintended consequences" inverts justice by suggesting that the best way to care is to not care to make law more attentive Unintended consequences" arguments promote a simplistic moral message in the guise of sophisticated intellectual critique like Ayn Rand's overt philosophy of selfishness, that message promotes the theme that those who have power to ignore harmful effects on others need not-indeed should not-be induced by law to care about this harm Legal scholars and advocates who intend to put intellectual rigor and justice ahead of service to elites should reject stories of "unintended consequences" and instead scrutinize the power and laws that have so effectively achieved the intention of making devastating losses to so many of us seem natural, inevitable, and beneficial | By making structures of inequality appear beyond the law the "unintended consequences" message helps reinforce the narrowing of protections against intentional racial harm unequal effects of policy are foreseeable and obvious, not accidental justice requires attention to both intent and effects unintended consequences" inverts justice by suggesting that the best way to care is to not care to make law more attentive U c arguments promote simplistic moral message in the guise of sophisticated critique | (Martha, “How the "Unintended Consequences" Story Promotes Unjust Intent and Impact,” Berkeley La Raza, doi: dx.doi.org/doi:10.15779/Z381664)
By similarly making structures of inequality appear beyond the reach of law reform, the "unintended consequences" message helps update and reinforce the narrowing of protections against intentional racial harm. Justice is centrally a question of whose interests and whose harms should count, in what context and in what form and to whom. Power is centrally about being able to act without having to take harm to others into account. This power to gain by harming others is strongest when it operates through systems and structures that make disregarding that harm appear routine, rational, and beneficial or at least acceptable or perhaps inevitable. By portraying law's unequal harms as the "side effects" of systems and structures with unquestionable "main effects," the "unintended consequences" story helps affirm the resulting harm even as it seems to offer sympathy and technical assistance. In considering solutions to the financial market problems, the policy puzzle is not that struggling homeowners' interests are overwhelmingly complex or uncertain. Instead, the bigger problem is that overwhelmingly powerful interests and ideologies are actively resisting systemic changes that would make those interests count. The failure to criminally prosecute or otherwise severely penalize high-level financial industry fraud is not primarily the result of uncertainty about the harmful effects of that fraudulent behavior, but because the political and justice systems are skewed to protect the gains and unaccountability of wealthy executives despite the clear harms to hosts of others. The unequal effects of the prevailing policy response to the crisis are foreseeable and obvious, not accidental or surprising. It would not take advanced knowledge of economics to readily predict that modest-income homeowners would tend to be far worse off than bank executives by a policy approach that failed to provide substantial mortgage forgiveness and foreclosure protections for modest-income homeowners but instead provided massive subsidized credit and other protections for Wall Street. Many policy actions likely to alleviate the unequal harm of the crisis similarly are impeded not because consumer advocates, low-income homeowners, or racial justice advocates hesitate to risk major changes in existing systems, or are divided about the technical design of alternative programs or more effective mechanisms for enforcing laws against fraud and racial discrimination. Instead, the problem is that these voices pressing for effective change are often excluded, drowned out or distorted in Congress and in federal agencies such as the Treasury Department and the Federal Reserve, or in the media, in the mainstream economics profession, and to a large extent in legal scholarship about financial markets. More generally, those diverse voices from the bottom have been largely absent or marginalized in the dominant theoretical framework that constructs widespread and severe inequality as unforeseeable and largely inevitable, or even beneficial. Moreover, justice requires careful attention to both harmful intent and to complex harmful effects. But the concept of "unintended consequences" inverts justice by suggesting that the best way to care for those at the bottom is to not care to make law more attentive to the bottom. "Unintended consequences" arguments promote a simplistic moral message in the guise of sophisticated intellectual critique-the message that those who lack power should not seek it because the desire for more power is what hurts most. Further, like Ayn Rand's overt philosophy of selfishness, that message promotes the theme that those who have power to ignore their harmful effects on others need not-indeed should not-be induced by law to care about this harm, because this caring is what is harmful. One right-wing think tank has recently made this moral message more explicit with an economic values campaign suggesting that the intentional pursuit of economic equality is a problem of the immoral envy of those whose economic success proves they are more deserving.169 Legal scholars and advocates who intend to put intellectual rigor and justice ahead of service to financial elites should reject stories of "unintended consequences" and instead scrutinize the power and laws that have so effectively achieved the intention of making devastating losses to so many of us seem natural, inevitable, and beneficial. | 4,589 | <h4>3. Disregarding foreseeable harm reifies structures of domination</h4><p><strong>McCluskey 12</strong> – JSD @ Columbia, Professor of Law @ SUNY-Buffalo</p><p>(Martha, “How the "Unintended Consequences" Story Promotes Unjust Intent and Impact,” Berkeley La Raza, doi: dx.doi.org/doi:10.15779/Z381664)</p><p><u><strong><mark>By</mark> similarly <mark>making structures of inequality appear beyond the</mark> reach of <mark>law</u></strong></mark> reform, <u><strong><mark>the "unintended consequences" message helps</mark> update and <mark>reinforce the narrowing of protections against intentional racial harm</mark>. Justice is centrally a question of whose</u></strong> interests and whose <u><strong>harms should count</u></strong>, in what context and in what form and to whom. <u><strong>Power is centrally about being able to act without having to take harm to others into account</u></strong>. <u><strong>This power to gain by harming others is strongest when it operates through</u></strong> systems and <u><strong>structures that make disregarding that harm appear</u></strong> routine, rational, and beneficial or at least <u><strong>acceptable</u></strong> or perhaps inevitable. By portraying law's unequal harms as the "side effects" of systems and structures with unquestionable "main effects," <u><strong>the</u></strong> "<u><strong>unintended consequences" story helps affirm the resulting harm</u></strong> even as it seems to offer sympathy and technical assistance. In considering solutions to the financial market problems, the policy puzzle is not that struggling homeowners' interests are overwhelmingly complex or uncertain. Instead, the bigger problem is that overwhelmingly powerful interests and ideologies are actively resisting systemic changes that would make those interests count. The failure to criminally prosecute or otherwise severely penalize high-level financial industry fraud is not primarily the result of uncertainty about the harmful effects of that fraudulent behavior, but because the political and justice systems are skewed to protect the gains and unaccountability of wealthy executives despite the clear harms to hosts of others. <u><strong>The <mark>unequal effects of</u></strong></mark> the prevailing <u><strong><mark>policy</u></strong></mark> response to the crisis <u><strong><mark>are foreseeable and obvious, not accidental</mark> or surprising</u></strong>. It would not take advanced knowledge of economics to readily predict that modest-income homeowners would tend to be far worse off than bank executives by a policy approach that failed to provide substantial mortgage forgiveness and foreclosure protections for modest-income homeowners but instead provided massive subsidized credit and other protections for Wall Street. Many policy actions likely to alleviate the unequal harm of the crisis similarly are impeded not because consumer advocates, low-income homeowners, or racial justice advocates hesitate to risk major changes in existing systems, or are divided about the technical design of alternative programs or more effective mechanisms for enforcing laws against fraud and racial discrimination. Instead, the problem is that these voices pressing for effective change are often excluded, drowned out or distorted in Congress and in federal agencies such as the Treasury Department and the Federal Reserve, or in the media, in the mainstream economics profession, and to a large extent in legal scholarship about financial markets. More generally, those diverse voices from the bottom have been largely absent or marginalized in the dominant theoretical framework that constructs widespread and severe inequality as unforeseeable and largely inevitable, or even beneficial. Moreover, <u><strong><mark>justice requires</mark> careful <mark>attention to both</mark> harmful <mark>intent and</mark> to complex harmful <mark>effects</u></strong></mark>. But <u><strong>the concept of "<mark>unintended consequences" inverts justice by suggesting that the best way to care</u></strong></mark> for those at the bottom <u><strong><mark>is to not care to make law more attentive</u></strong></mark> to the bottom. "<u><strong><mark>U</mark>nintended <mark>c</mark>onsequences" <mark>arguments promote</mark> a <mark>simplistic moral message in the guise of sophisticated</mark> intellectual <mark>critique</u></strong></mark>-the message that those who lack power should not seek it because the desire for more power is what hurts most. Further, <u><strong>like Ayn Rand's overt philosophy of selfishness, that message promotes the theme that those who have power to ignore</u></strong> their <u><strong>harmful effects on others need not-indeed should not-be induced by law to care about this harm</u></strong>, because this caring is what is harmful. One right-wing think tank has recently made this moral message more explicit with an economic values campaign suggesting that the intentional pursuit of economic equality is a problem of the immoral envy of those whose economic success proves they are more deserving.169 <u><strong>Legal scholars and advocates who intend to put intellectual rigor and justice ahead of service to</u></strong> financial <u><strong>elites should reject stories of "unintended consequences" and instead scrutinize the power and laws that have so effectively achieved the intention of making devastating losses to so many of us seem natural, inevitable, and beneficial</u></strong>.</p> | 1NC | Framing | 1NC | 56,127 | 506 | 67,193 | ./documents/hsld20/HarvardWestlake/Zh1/Harvard%20Westlake-Zhang-Neg-Greenhill%20Fall%20Classic-Round3.docx | 861,613 | N | Greenhill Fall Classic | 3 | Dulles AS | Rex Evans | 1AC - Japan Pragmatism
1NC - T a Conscientious Objectors PIC v2 Util Case
1AR - Condo Bad Pics Bad All
2NR - T a
2AR - Condo Bad T a | hsld20/HarvardWestlake/Zh1/Harvard%20Westlake-Zhang-Neg-Greenhill%20Fall%20Classic-Round3.docx | null | 73,125 | GeZh | Harvard Westlake GeZh | null | Ge..... | Zh..... | null | null | 24,537 | HarvardWestlake | Harvard Westlake | CA | null | 1,028 | hsld20 | HS LD 2020-21 | 2,020 | ld | hs | 1 |
495,987 | B) Can’t solve the kritik | Jones ‘11 | Jones ‘11 (Owen, Masters at Oxford, named one of the Daily Telegraph's 'Top 100 Most Influential People on the Left' for 2011, author of "Chavs: The Demonization of the Working Class", The Independent, UK, "Owen Jones: Protest without politics will change nothing", 2011, www.independent.co.uk/opinion/commentators/owen-jones-protest-without-politics-will-change-nothing-2373612.html | anti-globalisation movement did lack a coherent alternative to the neo-liberal project. , the movement was easily swept away by , But a alternative to the global economic order remains, it seems, as distant as ever. , there doesn't even seem to be an alternative for the right to defeat the left has never recovered from being smothered out of existence | anti-globalisation movement did lack a coherent alternative to the neo-liberal project. , the movement was easily swept away a alternative to the global economic order remains, as distant as ever there doesn't even seem to be an alternative for the right to defeat. the left has never recovered from being smothered out of existence | My first experience of police kettling was aged 16. It was May Day 2001, and the anti-globalisation movement was at its peak. The turn-of-the-century anti-capitalist movement feels largely forgotten today, but it was a big deal at the time. To a left-wing teenager growing up in an age of unchallenged neo-liberal triumphalism, just to have "anti-capitalism" flash up in the headlines was thrilling. Thousands of apparently unstoppable protesters chased the world's rulers from IMF to World Bank summits – from Seattle to Prague to Genoa – and the authorities were rattled.¶ Today, as protesters in nearly a thousand cities across the world follow the example set by the Occupy Wall Street protests, it's worth pondering what happened to the anti-globalisation movement. Its activists did not lack passion or determination. But they did lack a coherent alternative to the neo-liberal project. With no clear political direction, the movement was easily swept away by the jingoism and turmoil that followed 9/11, just two months after Genoa.¶ Don't get me wrong: the Occupy movement is a glimmer of sanity amid today's economic madness. By descending on the West's financial epicentres, it reminds us of how a crisis caused by the banks (a sentence that needs to be repeated until it becomes a cliché) has been cynically transformed into a crisis of public spending. The founding statement of Occupy London puts it succinctly: "We refuse to pay for the banks' crisis." The Occupiers direct their fire at the top 1 per cent, and rightly so – as US billionaire Warren Buffett confessed: "There's class warfare, all right, but it's my class, the rich class, that's making war, and we're winning."¶ The Occupy movement has provoked fury from senior US Republicans such as Presidential contender Herman Cain who – predictably – labelled it "anti-American". They're right to be worried: those camping outside banks threaten to refocus attention on the real villains, and to act as a catalyst for wider dissent. But a coherent alternative to the tottering global economic order remains, it seems, as distant as ever. Neo-liberalism crashes around, half-dead, with no-one to administer the killer blow. There's always a presumption that a crisis of capitalism is good news for the left. Yet in the Great Depression, fascism consumed much of Europe. The economic crisis of the 1970s did lead to a resurgence of radicalism on both left and right. But, spearheaded by Thatcherism and Reaganism, the New Right definitively crushed its opposition in the 1980s.This time round, there doesn't even seem to be an alternative for the right to defeat. That's not the fault of the protesters. In truth, the left has never recovered from being virtually smothered out of existence. It was the victim of a perfect storm: the rise of the New Right; neo-liberal globalisation; and the repeated defeats suffered by the trade union movement. But, above all, it was the aftermath of the collapse of Communism that did for the left. As US neo-conservative Midge Decter triumphantly put it: "It's time to say: We've won. Goodbye." From the British Labour Party to the African National Congress, left-wing movements across the world hurtled to the right in an almost synchronised fashion. It was as though the left wing of the global political spectrum had been sliced off. That's why, although we live in an age of revolt, there remains no left to give it direction and purpose. | 3,452 | <h4>B) Can’t solve the kritik</h4><p><strong>Jones ‘11</strong> (Owen, Masters at Oxford, named one of the Daily Telegraph's 'Top 100 Most Influential People on the Left' for 2011, author of "Chavs: The Demonization of the Working Class", The Independent, UK, "Owen Jones: Protest without politics will change nothing", 2011, <u>www.independent.co.uk/opinion/commentators/owen-jones-protest-without-politics-will-change-nothing-2373612.html</p><p></u>My first experience of police kettling was aged 16. It was May Day 2001, and the anti-globalisation movement was at its peak. The turn-of-the-century anti-capitalist movement feels largely forgotten today, but it was a big deal at the time. To a left-wing teenager growing up in an age of unchallenged neo-liberal triumphalism, just to have "anti-capitalism" flash up in the headlines was thrilling. Thousands of apparently unstoppable protesters chased the world's rulers from IMF to World Bank summits – from Seattle to Prague to Genoa – and the authorities were rattled.¶ Today, as protesters in nearly a thousand cities across the world follow the example set by the Occupy Wall Street protests, it's worth pondering what happened to the<u><strong> <mark>anti-globalisation movement</u></strong></mark>. Its activists did not lack passion or determination. But they<u> <mark>did <strong>lack a coherent alternative to the neo-liberal project.</u></strong> </mark>With no clear political direction<u><mark>, <strong>the movement was easily swept away</strong></mark> by</u> the jingoism and turmoil that followed 9/11<u>,</u> just two months after Genoa.¶ Don't get me wrong: the Occupy movement is a glimmer of sanity amid today's economic madness. By descending on the West's financial epicentres, it reminds us of how a crisis caused by the banks (a sentence that needs to be repeated until it becomes a cliché) has been cynically transformed into a crisis of public spending. The founding statement of Occupy London puts it succinctly: "We refuse to pay for the banks' crisis." The Occupiers direct their fire at the top 1 per cent, and rightly so – as US billionaire Warren Buffett confessed: "There's class warfare, all right, but it's my class, the rich class, that's making war, and we're winning."¶ The Occupy movement has provoked fury from senior US Republicans such as Presidential contender Herman Cain who – predictably – labelled it "anti-American". They're right to be worried: those camping outside banks threaten to refocus attention on the real villains, and to act as a catalyst for wider dissent. <u>But <mark>a</mark> </u>coherent<u> <mark>alternative to the</mark> </u>tottering<u> <mark>global economic order remains,</mark> it seems, <strong><mark>as distant as ever</mark>.</strong> <strong> </u></strong>Neo-liberalism crashes around, half-dead, with no-one to administer the killer blow. There's always a presumption that a crisis of capitalism is good news for the left. Yet in the Great Depression, fascism consumed much of Europe. The economic crisis of the 1970s did lead to a resurgence of radicalism on both left and right. But, spearheaded by Thatcherism and Reaganism, the New Right definitively crushed its opposition in the 1980s.This time round<u>, <mark>there <strong>doesn't even seem to be an alternative for the right to defeat</u></strong>.</mark> That's not the fault of the protesters. In truth, <u><mark>the left has never recovered from being</mark> </u>virtually<u> <strong><mark>smothered out of existence</u></strong></mark>. It was the victim of a perfect storm: the rise of the New Right; neo-liberal globalisation; and the repeated defeats suffered by the trade union movement. But, above all, it was the aftermath of the collapse of Communism that did for the left. As US neo-conservative Midge Decter triumphantly put it: "It's time to say: We've won. Goodbye." From the British Labour Party to the African National Congress, left-wing movements across the world hurtled to the right in an almost synchronised fashion. It was as though the left wing of the global political spectrum had been sliced off. That's why, although we live in an age of revolt, there remains no left to give it direction and purpose.</p> | ***Affirmative Answers*** | ***2NC Answers To*** | 2AC Frontline | 300 | 258 | 6,414 | ./documents/openev/2013/SSDI/Neoliberalism Kritik - Samford 2013.docx | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null | null |
3,534,065 | No warming impact---their predictions are wrong and adaptation solves | Cass 17 | Oren Cass 17, senior fellow at the Manhattan Institute, Winter 2017, “How to Worry about Climate Change,” National Affairs, http://www.nationalaffairs.com/publications/detail/how-to-worry-about-climate-change | estimates for the expected environmental impacts of warming vary widely IPCC represents the gold standard for synthesizing scientific estimates, and crucially, its best guesses bear little resemblance to the a pocalyptic predictions often repeated by activists and politicians At the high end of the 3-to-4-degree range the impact on ecosystems will be no worse than that of the land-use changes to which human civilization already subjects the natural world
responsibility for translating disruptions into economic costs falls to Integrated Assessment Models While 4% is a large dollar amount, arriving at that impact over nearly 100 years implies imperceptibly small changes in economic growth
3.8 degrees Celsius of warming by 2100 costing 3.9% of GDP in that year this is the equivalent of slowing economic growth by less than one-tenth of one percentage point annually regardless of climate change, the world is more than six times wealthier than in 2015 The economy continues to grow, so that the climate-change-afflicted world of 2105 is already much wealthier than a world of 2100 facing no climate change
the economy of 2100 will likely be able to allocate those resources toward climate change while also allocating to every other facet of society far more resources than are available today
Corroborating these models IPCC concludes for most economic sectors, the impacts of changes in population, age structure technology regulation, and governance are projected to be large relative to the impacts of climate change
None of this means climate change would be impacts expected from climate change over the next hundred years look similar to those through which both civilization and our planet have successfully muddled over the past hundred and continue to struggle with today
These challenges are not existential threats or even ones that require analysis outside the standard policy process
If expected climate change represents the most likely outcome, extreme climate change represents the worst case feedback loops could hit a tripwire that collapses global ecosystems or some other prerequisite of modern civilization
extreme climate change has no guarantee or even likelihood of occurring scientific consensus on climate change does not extend to confidence in such scenarios
Consider the magnitude of the forecasted impact. Many worrying problems feature the credible prospect of killing a significant share of the human population or erasing modern civilization Not extreme climate change even considering higher temperature increases IPCC concludes
risks include impacts on unique and threatened systems, substantial species extinction compromising normal human activities
Obviously those effects would carry severe consequences for entire nations, and wreak havoc with the natural environment. But as a worst case, it pales in comparison to catastrophes that might kill a significant share of the human population or erase the basic physical and economic infrastructure of modern civilization
Serious efforts to quantify existential threats concur worst case climate change could "render the tropics substantially less habitable as compared to billions of deaths associated with other challenges. An Oxford study asked to estimate probability of global catastrophes leading to human extinction and did not even see fit to include climate change as an option
analysts place climate change among genuinely existential threats on the basis of its "fat tail arguing some unknowable but non-zero chance exists for an outcome with infinite cost. But this is true of all worrying problems Climate change cannot be distinguished from other worrying problems on that basis the argument begs the question: What characteristics of climate change make its tail relatively fatter or thinner?
weight accorded to forecasted effects depends greatly on the number of causal steps between the underlying phenomena and worst-case outcomes
Climate change has a very short chain to some impact But the connection from warmer temperatures to civilizational catastrophe is highly attenuated warming must cause crises across societies. Those must overwhelm coping capacity of the entire global community, which must trigger military conflict, which must in turn metastasize into...what? one can invent a scenario But the specifics quickly become hazy, and a worst case entirely outside of human experience difficult to articulate
all worrying problems have worst-case forecasts that look this way the burden of proof should lie on those declaring that climate change stands apart from other worrying problems to explain why
climate change is less worrying than most especially with respect to irreversibility Most worrying problems have worst-case scenarios that sweep the globe in a matter of months, days, or minutes. For climate change, damage unfolds over decades or centuries
climate change does allow for interventions even once well underway natural processes already exist for extracting carbon dioxide new technologies could accelerate those or create artificial ones
time permits adaptation losing 50% of existing agricultural capacity is daunting, over a 50-year period 1% of capacity needs to shift annually over the past 50 years, total agricultural output has tripled
Purveyors of catastrophic climate cases face a Catch-22 ever-more extreme scenarios typically requires ever-longer timescales. Even higher temperatures and risks of further dominos falling are threatened after "centuries." Confident forecasts of multi-meter sea-level rises are issued, to occur over multiple millennia if heightening the threat requires extending the timeframe further More time becomes available for adaptation, for economic progress and technological innovation that render the threat irrelevant, or for the model to fail | IPCC represents the gold standard its best guesses bear little resemblance to a pocalyptic predictions At the high end the impact will be no worse than land-use changes civilization already subjects
The economy continues to grow the climate afflicted world of 2105 is much wealthier than 2100 facing no climate change
impacts over the next hundred years look similar to those civilization and our planet successfully muddled
These are not existential
forecasted effects depend on the causal steps between phenomena and worst-case
one can invent a scenario specifics quickly become hazy
more extreme scenarios requires longer timescales further dominos are threatened after "centuries tech innovation render the threat irrelevant | Even focusing within that range, estimates for the expected environmental impacts of warming vary widely. The IPCC represents the gold standard for synthesizing scientific estimates, and, crucially, its best guesses bear little resemblance to the a pocalyptic predictions often repeated by activists and politicians. For instance, the IPCC estimates that sea levels have risen by half a foot over the past century and will rise by another two feet over the current century. At the high end of the 3-to-4-degree range, it reports the impact on ecosystems will be no worse than that of the land-use changes to which human civilization already subjects the natural world.
The responsibility for translating these and other disruptions into economic costs falls to Integrated Assessment Models (IAMs). To create its "Social Cost of Carbon," the Obama administration surveyed this economic literature and focused specifically on three models whose forecasts themselves vary widely, even starting from a common level of warming. For warming of 3 to 4 degrees Celsius by 2100, the middle of the three models estimates an annual cost of 1% to 3% of GDP. The low case estimates 0 to 1%. The high case estimates 2% to 4%. While 4% is a large dollar amount, arriving at that impact over nearly 100 years implies almost imperceptibly small changes in economic growth.
The specifics of this high-case model are informative: The Dynamic Integrated model of Climate and the Economy (known as the DICE model) developed by William Nordhaus at Yale University estimates 3.8 degrees Celsius of warming by 2100 costing an associated 3.9% of GDP in that year. But over time, this cost is the equivalent of slowing economic growth by less than one-tenth of one percentage point annually. By 2100, regardless of climate change, the world is more than six times wealthier than in 2015 under this model; global GDP is $500 trillion. The effect of climate change is to reduce that gain from a multiple of 6.7 to a multiple of 6.5. The economy also continues to grow, so that the climate-change-afflicted world of 2105 is already much wealthier than a world of 2100 facing no climate change at all.
Such estimates might seem counterintuitively low, especially given the rhetoric often employed. Part of the explanation lies in the almost incomprehensible economic progress that human civilization is capable of making over the course of a century. The annual cost identified by Nordhaus in 2100 is $20 trillion — massive by the standards of 2015, manageable by the standards of 2100. Further, that cost repeats every year even as the impacts are spread over many years. Thus, over the 2090 to 2110 time period, Nordhaus envisions the world spending a stunning $350 trillion to cope with climate change. One might despair over what else such resources might accomplish over that time period. But one must also recognize that the economy of 2100 will likely be able to allocate those resources toward climate change while also allocating to every other facet of society far more resources than are available today.
Corroborating these models, the IPCC concludes that "for most economic sectors, the impacts of drivers such as changes in population, age structure, income, technology, relative prices, lifestyle, regulation, and governance are projected to be large relative to the impacts of climate change." In other words, other worrying problems have a far greater capacity to influence progress.
None of this means the dislocations from climate change would be painless or the disruptions cheap. It is merely to observe that the impacts expected from climate change over the next hundred years look similar to those through which both civilization and our planet have successfully muddled over the past hundred and continue to struggle with today. Other worrying problems have their own anticipated but less-severe analogs, too. Whether a global pandemic strikes, epidemics will inevitably occur like the 2014 Ebola outbreak in West Africa that claimed more than 10,000 lives and cost the three countries at its center more than a tenth of their GDP. Whether artificial intelligence makes humans superfluous, self-driving vehicles could throw millions out of work in the years to come. Some countries will default on their debt; some business cycles will spawn deep global recessions.
These challenges are not existential threats or even ones that require analysis outside the standard policy process — that is, they are not really worrying problems at all.
EXTREME CASES
If expected climate change represents the most likely outcome, extreme climate change represents the worst case: Models could be underestimating the warming that emissions will cause; feedback loops could send a 3-degree increase suddenly careening higher; or even at the expected level the climate could hit a tripwire that collapses global ecosystems or ocean currents or ice sheets or some other prerequisite of modern civilization.
Any of these things may be true — as is the nature of genuinely forecasted challenges, they are mostly non-falsifiable. But while extreme climate change is a quintessentially worrying problem, it is also one that has no guarantee or even likelihood of occurring. Certainly, the "scientific consensus" or even the "scientific mainstream" on climate change does not extend to confidence in such scenarios.
To compare extreme climate change with other worrying problems, it is helpful to consider the dimensions that make a problem "worrying": that it is forecasted, irreversible, and pervasive. On all three, climate change appears less worrying than most.
Consider, first, the magnitude of the forecasted impact. Many worrying problems feature the credible prospect of killing a significant share of the human population or erasing modern civilization. Not extreme climate change. For instance, even considering higher temperature increases, the IPCC concludes that:
Global climate change risks are high to very high with global mean temperature increase of 4°C or more above preindustrial levels in all reasons for concern, and include severe and widespread impacts on unique and threatened systems, substantial species extinction, large risks to global and regional food security, and the combination of high temperature and humidity compromising normal human activities, including growing food or working outdoors in some areas for parts of the year.
Obviously, each of those effects would entail enormous economic costs, carry severe consequences for entire nations, and wreak havoc with the natural environment. But as a worst case, it nevertheless pales in comparison to catastrophes that might kill a significant share of the human population or erase the basic physical and economic infrastructure of modern civilization.
Serious efforts to quantify existential threats concur. A 2016 report by the Global Priorities Project at Oxford offered as its example of a worst case that climate change could "render most of the tropics substantially less habitable than at present," as compared to hundreds of millions or billions of deaths associated with other challenges. Another Oxford study from 2008 asked conference participants to estimate the probability of various global catastrophes leading to human extinction in the coming century, and did not even see fit to include climate change as an option, while respondents gave molecular nanotechnology, super-intelligent artificial intelligence, and an engineered pandemic each at least a 2% chance of erasing humanity by 2100.
Some analysts nonetheless place climate change among humanity's genuinely existential threats on the basis of its "fat tail," arguing that some unknowable but non-zero chance exists at the far-right end of the probability distribution for an outcome with essentially infinite cost. But this is true of all worrying problems — indeed, the characteristics of worrying problems might be viewed as those that generate such unknowable non-zero probabilities. Climate change cannot be distinguished from other worrying problems on that basis. Rather, the argument begs the question: What characteristics of climate change make its tail relatively fatter or thinner?
The weight accorded to a worrying problem's forecasted effects depends greatly on the number of causal steps between the underlying phenomena and worst-case outcomes. Where fewer steps are necessary, or where steps are relatively more likely to occur, the probability of the worst case arising should increase. For instance, whether an engineered pandemic devastates humanity depends on development of the necessary technology (highly likely), its use by a malicious actor (indeterminate), and its spread defying efforts at containment (indeterminate). Generally speaking, technological threats will have the shortest chains while sociological threats will have the longest ones.
Climate change would appear to sit somewhere in between. It has a very short chain to some impact — indeed, higher atmospheric concentrations of carbon dioxide are already having effects. But the connection from warmer temperatures to civilizational catastrophe is highly attenuated. The initial warming must cross thresholds that produce feedback loops. The ensuing warmth must produce environmental effects that cause unprecedented crises across societies. Those crises must in turn overwhelm the coping capacity of the entire global community, which must in turn produce wide-scale breakdowns in social order or trigger military conflict, which must in turn metastasize into...what? Certainly, one can invent a scenario. But the specifics quickly become hazy, and a worst case entirely outside of human experience difficult to articulate.
The intent of this analysis is not to dismiss the severity of worst-case climate scenarios or to suggest that "wide-scale breakdowns in social order" are acceptable. But all worrying problems have worst-case forecasts that look this way, all with indeterminate probabilities of occurring, which leaves only a few options: We could become overwhelmed with despair, emphasize whichever problems are most politically useful, or seek out qualitative and quantitative bases for analysis. Too much discussion of climate change adopts the first or second approach. Efforts at the third approach will inevitably be imprecise and imperfect, but the burden of proof should lie on those declaring that climate change stands apart from other worrying problems to explain why that is so. The suggestion here is not that the forecasted threat of climate change does not belong alongside other worrying problems, only that the nature of its forecast cannot be what separates it as uniquely worrying.
WORRYING IN SLOW MOTION
In the other ways climate change is a worrying problem, meanwhile, it is less worrying than most. This is especially true with respect to irreversibility. While President Obama has lamented that climate change is a "comparatively slow-moving emergency," the one thing worse is a fast-moving one. Most worrying problems have worst-case scenarios that sweep the globe in a matter of months, days, or even minutes. For climate change, the damage unfolds over decades or centuries. This has several implications.
First, while climate change is irreversible compared to the typical policy problem, it does allow for some potential interventions even once well underway. For instance, natural processes already exist for extracting carbon dioxide from the atmosphere, and new technologies could be developed that accelerate those processes or create artificial ones. Alternatively, humans could use so-called "geoengineering" to effect other changes in the climate system that might counteract an intensifying greenhouse effect. These approaches offer no guarantee or even likelihood of success; turning to geoengineering might be seen as a disaster in its own right. But they offer more cause for optimism than exists with many other worrying problems.
Second, time permits adaptation. While the prospect of losing 50% of existing agricultural capacity is daunting, over a 50-year period only 1% of capacity needs to shift annually. By comparison, over the past 50 years, total agricultural output has tripled. Similarly, the need for hundreds of millions of people to migrate over a century amounts to little out of the ordinary on an annual basis. There are, for instance, more than 200 million migrant workers within China, as well as another 200 million international migrants and at least 60 million refugees around the world right now. The United Nations estimates 2.5 billion people will migrate to cities in just the next 35 years. Further migration, or perhaps the gradual abandonment of some cities or even entire regions, would obviously be extraordinarily costly and disruptive in human, economic, and environmental terms. But the reason such adaptations are rarely mentioned in the context of other worrying problems is not that they would be unnecessary, but rather that, in those other cases, they would be either impossible or else futile.
Purveyors of creatively catastrophic climate cases also face a Catch-22: Developing ever-more extreme scenarios typically requires ever-longer timescales. Even higher temperatures and risks of further dominos falling are threatened — by 2300, or after "centuries." Confident forecasts of multi-meter sea-level rises are issued, to occur over multiple millennia. Harvard University's Martin Weitzman, the leading proponent of the case that climate change presents a uniquely "fat tail," falls into precisely this trap: The worst case he offers relies on continued temperature increases over multiple centuries. But if heightening the threat requires extending the timeframe further, it becomes diluted threefold: More time becomes available for adaptation, for economic progress and technological innovation that render the threat irrelevant, or for the model to fail. Any impact forecasted for 200, let alone 2,000, years into the future becomes almost inherently less cognizable than those already under study for 2100. | 14,129 | <h4>No warming impact---their predictions are wrong and adaptation solves</h4><p>Oren <strong>Cass 17</strong>, senior fellow at the Manhattan Institute, Winter 2017, “How to Worry about Climate Change,” National Affairs, http://www.nationalaffairs.com/publications/detail/how-to-worry-about-climate-change</p><p>Even focusing within that range, <u>estimates for the expected environmental impacts of warming vary widely</u>. The <u><mark>IPCC</u> <u>represents the <strong>gold standard</strong></mark> for synthesizing scientific estimates, and</u>, <u><strong>crucially, <mark>its best guesses bear little resemblance to</mark> the <mark>a pocalyptic predictions</mark> often repeated by activists and politicians</u></strong>. For instance, the IPCC estimates that sea levels have risen by half a foot over the past century and will rise by another two feet over the current century. <u><mark>At the <strong>high end</strong></mark> of the 3-to-4-degree range</u>, it reports <u><mark>the impact</mark> on ecosystems <mark>will be no worse than</mark> that of the <strong><mark>land-use changes</mark> to which human <mark>civilization already subjects</mark> the natural world</u></strong>.</p><p>The <u>responsibility for translating</u> these and other <u>disruptions into economic costs falls to Integrated Assessment Models</u> (IAMs). To create its "Social Cost of Carbon," the Obama administration surveyed this economic literature and focused specifically on three models whose forecasts themselves vary widely, even starting from a common level of warming. For warming of 3 to 4 degrees Celsius by 2100, the middle of the three models estimates an annual cost of 1% to 3% of GDP. The low case estimates 0 to 1%. The high case estimates 2% to 4%. <u>While 4% is a large dollar amount, arriving at that impact over nearly 100 years implies</u> almost <u><strong>imperceptibly small changes in economic growth</u></strong>.</p><p>The specifics of this high-case model are informative: The Dynamic Integrated model of Climate and the Economy (known as the DICE model) developed by William Nordhaus at Yale University estimates <u>3.8 degrees Celsius of warming by 2100 costing</u> an associated <u>3.9% of GDP in that year</u>. But over time, <u>this</u> cost <u>is the equivalent of slowing economic growth by less than one-tenth of one percentage point annually</u>. By 2100, <u>regardless of climate change, the world is more than six times wealthier than in 2015</u> under this model; global GDP is $500 trillion. The effect of climate change is to reduce that gain from a multiple of 6.7 to a multiple of 6.5. <u><mark>The economy</u></mark> also <u><mark>continues to grow</mark>, so that <mark>the climate</mark>-change-<mark>afflicted world of 2105 is</mark> already <mark>much wealthier than</mark> a world of <mark>2100 facing no climate change</u></mark> at all.</p><p>Such estimates might seem counterintuitively low, especially given the rhetoric often employed. Part of the explanation lies in the almost incomprehensible economic progress that human civilization is capable of making over the course of a century. The annual cost identified by Nordhaus in 2100 is $20 trillion — massive by the standards of 2015, manageable by the standards of 2100. Further, that cost repeats every year even as the impacts are spread over many years. Thus, over the 2090 to 2110 time period, Nordhaus envisions the world spending a stunning $350 trillion to cope with climate change. One might despair over what else such resources might accomplish over that time period. But one must also recognize that <u>the economy of 2100 will likely be able to allocate those resources toward climate change while also allocating to every other facet of society far more resources than are available today</u>.</p><p><u><strong>Corroborating these models</u></strong>, the <u>IPCC concludes</u> that "<u>for most economic sectors, the impacts of</u> drivers such as <u>changes in population, age structure</u>, income, <u>technology</u>, relative prices, lifestyle, <u>regulation, and governance are projected to be large relative to the impacts of climate change</u>." In other words, other worrying problems have a far greater capacity to influence progress.</p><p><u>None of this means</u> the dislocations from <u>climate change would be</u> painless or the disruptions cheap. It is merely to observe that the <u><mark>impacts</mark> expected from climate change <mark>over the next hundred years look <strong>similar to those</mark> through which both <mark>civilization and our planet</mark> have <mark>successfully muddled</strong></mark> over the past hundred and continue to struggle with today</u>. Other worrying problems have their own anticipated but less-severe analogs, too. Whether a global pandemic strikes, epidemics will inevitably occur like the 2014 Ebola outbreak in West Africa that claimed more than 10,000 lives and cost the three countries at its center more than a tenth of their GDP. Whether artificial intelligence makes humans superfluous, self-driving vehicles could throw millions out of work in the years to come. Some countries will default on their debt; some business cycles will spawn deep global recessions.</p><p><u><mark>These</mark> challenges <mark>are <strong>not existential</mark> threats</strong> or even ones that require analysis outside the standard policy process</u> — that is, they are not really worrying problems at all.</p><p>EXTREME CASES</p><p><u>If expected climate change represents the most likely outcome, extreme climate change represents the worst case</u>: Models could be underestimating the warming that emissions will cause; <u>feedback loops could</u> send a 3-degree increase suddenly careening higher; or even at the expected level the climate could <u>hit a tripwire that collapses global ecosystems</u> or ocean currents or ice sheets <u>or some other prerequisite of modern civilization</u>.</p><p>Any of these things may be true — as is the nature of genuinely forecasted challenges, they are mostly non-falsifiable. But while <u>extreme climate change</u> is a quintessentially worrying problem, it is also one that <u>has <strong>no guarantee or even likelihood of occurring</u></strong>. Certainly, the "<u>scientific consensus</u>" or even the "scientific mainstream" <u>on climate change <strong>does not extend to confidence in such scenarios</u></strong>.</p><p>To compare extreme climate change with other worrying problems, it is helpful to consider the dimensions that make a problem "worrying": that it is forecasted, irreversible, and pervasive. On all three, climate change appears less worrying than most.</p><p><u>Consider</u>, first, <u>the <strong>magnitude</strong> of the forecasted impact. Many worrying problems feature the credible prospect of killing a significant share of the human population or erasing modern civilization</u>. <u><strong>Not extreme climate change</u></strong>. For instance, <u>even considering higher temperature increases</u>, the <u>IPCC concludes</u> that:</p><p>Global climate change <u>risks</u> are high to very high with global mean temperature increase of 4°C or more above preindustrial levels in all reasons for concern, and <u>include</u> severe and widespread <u>impacts on unique and threatened systems, substantial species extinction</u>, large risks to global and regional food security, and the combination of high temperature and humidity <u>compromising normal human activities</u>, including growing food or working outdoors in some areas for parts of the year.</p><p><u>Obviously</u>, each of <u>those effects would</u> entail enormous economic costs, <u>carry severe consequences for entire nations, and wreak havoc with the natural environment. But as a worst case, it</u> nevertheless <u>pales in comparison to catastrophes that might kill a significant share of the human population or erase the basic physical and economic infrastructure of modern civilization</u>.</p><p><u><strong>Serious</strong> efforts to quantify existential threats <strong>concur</u></strong>. A 2016 report by the Global Priorities Project at Oxford offered as its example of a <u>worst case</u> that <u>climate change could "render</u> most of <u>the tropics substantially less habitable</u> than at present," <u>as compared to</u> hundreds of millions or <u><strong>billions of deaths associated with other challenges</strong>. An</u>other <u>Oxford study</u> from 2008 <u>asked</u> conference participants <u>to estimate</u> the <u>probability of</u> various <u>global catastrophes leading to <strong>human extinction</u></strong> in the coming century, <u>and <strong>did not even see fit to include climate change as an option</u></strong>, while respondents gave molecular nanotechnology, super-intelligent artificial intelligence, and an engineered pandemic each at least a 2% chance of erasing humanity by 2100.</p><p>Some <u>analysts</u> nonetheless <u>place climate change among</u> humanity's <u>genuinely existential threats on the basis of its "fat tail</u>," <u>arguing</u> that <u>some unknowable but non-zero chance exists</u> at the far-right end of the probability distribution <u>for an outcome with</u> essentially <u>infinite cost. But this is true of all worrying problems</u> — indeed, the characteristics of worrying problems might be viewed as those that generate such unknowable non-zero probabilities. <u>Climate change cannot be distinguished from other worrying problems on that basis</u>. Rather, <u>the argument begs the question: What characteristics of climate change make its tail relatively fatter or thinner?</p><p></u>The <u>weight accorded to</u> a worrying problem's <u><mark>forecasted effects <strong>depend</mark>s greatly <mark>on the</mark> number of <mark>causal steps between</mark> the underlying <mark>phenomena and worst-case</mark> outcomes</u></strong>. Where fewer steps are necessary, or where steps are relatively more likely to occur, the probability of the worst case arising should increase. For instance, whether an engineered pandemic devastates humanity depends on development of the necessary technology (highly likely), its use by a malicious actor (indeterminate), and its spread defying efforts at containment (indeterminate). Generally speaking, technological threats will have the shortest chains while sociological threats will have the longest ones.</p><p><u>Climate change</u> would appear to sit somewhere in between. It <u>has a very short chain to <strong>some</strong> impact</u> — indeed, higher atmospheric concentrations of carbon dioxide are already having effects. <u>But the connection from warmer temperatures to civilizational catastrophe is <strong>highly attenuated</u></strong>. The initial <u>warming must</u> cross thresholds that produce feedback loops. The ensuing warmth must produce environmental effects that <u>cause</u> unprecedented <u>crises across societies. Those</u> crises <u>must</u> in turn <u>overwhelm</u> the <u>coping capacity of the entire global community, which must</u> in turn produce wide-scale breakdowns in social order or <u>trigger military conflict, which must in turn metastasize into...what?</u> Certainly, <u><strong><mark>one can invent a scenario</u></strong></mark>. <u>But the <strong><mark>specifics quickly become hazy</strong></mark>, and a worst case entirely outside of human experience difficult to articulate</u>.</p><p>The intent of this analysis is not to dismiss the severity of worst-case climate scenarios or to suggest that "wide-scale breakdowns in social order" are acceptable. But <u><strong>all</strong> worrying problems have worst-case forecasts that look this way</u>, all with indeterminate probabilities of occurring, which leaves only a few options: We could become overwhelmed with despair, emphasize whichever problems are most politically useful, or seek out qualitative and quantitative bases for analysis. Too much discussion of climate change adopts the first or second approach. Efforts at the third approach will inevitably be imprecise and imperfect, but <u>the burden of proof should lie on those declaring that climate change stands apart from other worrying problems to explain why</u> that is so. The suggestion here is not that the forecasted threat of climate change does not belong alongside other worrying problems, only that the nature of its forecast cannot be what separates it as uniquely worrying.</p><p>WORRYING IN SLOW MOTION</p><p>In the other ways <u>climate change is</u> a worrying problem, meanwhile, it is <u>less worrying than most</u>. This is <u>especially</u> true <u>with respect to irreversibility</u>. While President Obama has lamented that climate change is a "comparatively slow-moving emergency," the one thing worse is a fast-moving one. <u>Most worrying problems have worst-case scenarios that sweep the globe in a matter of months, days, or </u>even <u>minutes. For climate change,</u> the <u>damage unfolds over decades or centuries</u>. This has several implications.</p><p>First, while <u>climate change</u> is irreversible compared to the typical policy problem, it <u>does allow for</u> some potential <u>interventions <strong>even once well underway</u></strong>. For instance, <u>natural processes already exist for extracting carbon dioxide</u> from the atmosphere, and <u>new technologies could</u> be developed that <u>accelerate those</u> processes <u>or create artificial ones</u>. Alternatively, humans could use so-called "geoengineering" to effect other changes in the climate system that might counteract an intensifying greenhouse effect. These approaches offer no guarantee or even likelihood of success; turning to geoengineering might be seen as a disaster in its own right. But they offer more cause for optimism than exists with many other worrying problems.</p><p>Second, <u><strong>time permits adaptation</u></strong>. While the prospect of <u>losing 50% of existing agricultural capacity is daunting, over a 50-year period</u> only <u>1% of capacity needs to shift annually</u>. By comparison, <u>over the past 50 years, <strong>total agricultural output has tripled</u></strong>. Similarly, the need for hundreds of millions of people to migrate over a century amounts to little out of the ordinary on an annual basis. There are, for instance, more than 200 million migrant workers within China, as well as another 200 million international migrants and at least 60 million refugees around the world right now. The United Nations estimates 2.5 billion people will migrate to cities in just the next 35 years. Further migration, or perhaps the gradual abandonment of some cities or even entire regions, would obviously be extraordinarily costly and disruptive in human, economic, and environmental terms. But the reason such adaptations are rarely mentioned in the context of other worrying problems is not that they would be unnecessary, but rather that, in those other cases, they would be either impossible or else futile.</p><p><u>Purveyors of</u> creatively <u>catastrophic climate cases</u> also <u>face a Catch-22</u>: Developing <u><strong>ever-<mark>more extreme scenarios</mark> typically <mark>requires</mark> ever-<mark>longer timescales</strong></mark>. Even higher temperatures and risks of <mark>further dominos</mark> falling <mark>are threatened</u></mark> — by 2300, or <u><strong><mark>after "centuries</strong></mark>." Confident forecasts of multi-meter sea-level rises are issued, to occur over multiple millennia</u>. Harvard University's Martin Weitzman, the leading proponent of the case that climate change presents a uniquely "fat tail," falls into precisely this trap: The worst case he offers relies on continued temperature increases over multiple centuries. But <u>if heightening the threat requires extending the timeframe further</u>, it becomes diluted threefold: <u><strong>More time becomes available for adaptation</strong>, for <strong>economic progress and <mark>tech</mark>nological <mark>innovation</strong></mark> that <mark>render</mark> <mark>the threat irrelevant</mark>, or for the <strong>model to fail</u></strong>. Any impact forecasted for 200, let alone 2,000, years into the future becomes almost inherently less cognizable than those already under study for 2100.</p> | 2AC | Base Bad | Warming Defense---1NC (Short) | 62,534 | 169 | 116,896 | ./documents/ndtceda17/Northwestern/LeYo/Northwestern-Levin-Young-Aff-Gonzaga-Round8.docx | 599,782 | A | Gonzaga | 8 | Kansas FM | Lepp | 1AC - ACA (Econ China)
1NC - Ban employer insurance Base Bad DA T-establish Subsidies CP Reshoring Bad Heg Bad
2NR - Heg Bad | ndtceda17/Northwestern/LeYo/Northwestern-Levin-Young-Aff-Gonzaga-Round8.docx | null | 51,032 | LeYo | Northwestern LeYo | null | Ja..... | Le..... | Me..... | Yo..... | 19,135 | Northwestern | Northwestern | null | null | 1,007 | ndtceda17 | NDT/CEDA 2017-18 | 2,017 | cx | college | 2 |
3,837,712 | The plan is key to getting China say to yes and simultaneously creates cyber integration to the Law of Armed Conflict | Harold et al 16 | Harold et al 16 – Libicki is an American scholar and Professor at the Frederick S. Pardee RAND Graduate School in Santa Monica, California, Harold is associate director of the RAND Center for Asia Pacific Policy, Cevallos is a political scientist at the RAND Corporation | )
The global salience of U.S.-China relations and the potential for quarrels over cyberspace play an increasingly disruptive role in the relationship make it desirable for the two countries to come to some terms over each other’s behavior in cyberspace In our interviews in China most did not appear to see any agreement with the U S plausible, likely, or necessary the September 2015 U.S.-China cybersecurity agreement may have caught our interlocutors as much by surprise as it appeared to catch most of the community that is watching U.S.-China relations it remains to be seen whether the agreement has effectively resolved the EMCE issue Our conclusion is that, if the U S is determined to adopt a negotiation-based approach that addresses the entire range of Chinese cyber espionage success is unlikely there is no guarantee that a strategy based solely on imposing costs on China for its conduct will have the desired effect This means that a continued effort to resolve differences and establish norms through dialogue and negotiation is highly desirable the possibility of achieving progress in cybersecurity negotiations means an agreement that would have the U S and China refrain from attacking each other Here, we found common ground Chinese reflect a willingness to agree to such a proposition Such an agreement would represent a valuable step forward in terms of mutual reassurance and consolidate norms that would affirm, clarify, or at least supplement the applicability of the international LOAC to cyberspace A logical codicil of any such agreement on avoiding targeting critical infrastructure also implied an agreement not to spy on such targets there is no reason for a foreign government to be collecting detailed information on a system’s construct it is impossible to distinguish between spying and an attack spying should be abjured by all sides we found grounds for agreement the current relative weakness of Chinese attribution capabilities suggests other’s prima facie evidence would not work a bilateral resolution mechanism, supplemented by U.S. efforts to help China improve its own attribution capabilities a three-part agreement—including a norm of not targeting or intruding into each side’s critical infrastructure—combined with an offer to help China improve its attribution capabilities in exchange for a deal to actually follow through on, investigate, and maybe even prosecute cyber intrusions come into existence it might change the nature of the two sides’ relations in cyberspace across an important swath of issues such a deal would represent a substantial improvement of the U.S.-China relationship in cyberspace Chinese and U.S. views of cybersecurity overlap on a few points the two sides will find it difficult to make progress if the two sides struggle to maintain progress in the September 2015 summit agreement the most promising area of norms lies in avoiding targeting or carrying out espionage on critical infrastructure This could be supported by efforts to create common standards of evidence, define how attribution is to be done, and prosecute those who commit such actions. | desirable for the two countries to come to terms over each other’s behavior in cyberspace , if the U S is determined to address the entire range of cyber success is unlikely a continued effort to resolve differences and establish norms through dialogue is highly desirable an agreement that would have the U S and China refrain from attacking each other. found common ground in terms of mutual reassurance consolidate norms that would affirm, clarify, or at least supplement the applicability of the international LOAC to cyberspace a bilateral resolution agreement not targeting infrastructure help China improve attribution would represent a substantial improvement of the U.S.-China relationship in cyberspace the two sides will find it difficult to make progress if the two sides struggle to maintain progress in the September agreement the most promising area lies in avoiding targeting or carrying out espionage on critical infrastructure | (Scott Warren, Martin C. Libicki, Astrid Stuth Cevallos, Getting to Yes with China in Cyberspace, Kindle, Chapter 5)
The global salience of U.S.-China relations and the potential for quarrels over cyberspace to play an increasingly disruptive role in the relationship make it desirable for the two countries to come to some terms over each other’s behavior in cyberspace. In the course of our interviews in China in May 2015, most of our interlocutors did not appear to see any agreement with the United States as plausible, likely, or even particularly necessary. While the United States appeared to see the two countries’ relationship in cyberspace as untenable, Chinese interviewees in contrast did not seem to see any urgent need to make changes. As a consequence, the September 2015 U.S.-China cybersecurity agreement may have caught our interlocutors as much by surprise as it appeared to catch most of the community that is watching U.S.-China relations (including the authors). As of mid-February 2016 it remains to be seen whether or not the agreement on cyberspace reached at the Xi-Obama summit has effectively resolved the EMCE issue.1 Our first conclusion is that, if the United States is determined to adopt a negotiation-based approach that addresses the entire range of Chinese cyber espionage, success is unlikely to take place any time soon, unless the costs to China of refusing to negotiate over the cyber issue can be increased (beyond simply the threat of a canceled or failed summit meeting). This could potentially be accomplished through linking this issue more directly to the broader health of the overall relationship through representations to China at the highest levels or to the use of other levers, such as the threat of economic sanctions or retaliation. However, there is no guarantee that a strategy based solely on imposing costs on China for its conduct, sponsorship, or willingness to condone cyber espionage will have the desired effect of reducing Chinese cyber espionage or creating norms on what targets are out of bounds for cyber espionage. This means that a continued effort to resolve differences and establish norms through dialogue and negotiation is highly desirable, even if such an approach may need to be backed up by the threat of cost imposition. Worryingly, as of May 2015, our Chinese interlocutors did not tend to see direct, bilateral talks with the United States on cybersecurity as a way to achieve much regarding specific norms or limitations on cyberspace activities. Instead, China’s approach to the issue of cybersecurity appears in many respects to be focused first and foremost on attempting to articulate and defend a set of values and proposals for the international governance of cyberspace that would redefine cybersecurity away from issues of concern to the United States, such as EMCE and applying the LOAC to cyberspace. In articulating its positions and submitting proposals on cybersecurity to the UN, China has argued for redefining cybersecurity with an eye toward such issues as cyber sovereignty and moving the management of the Internet out of the hands of the United States and the West and into a more China-friendly setting, such as the UN. Our team hoped that Chinese respondents and interlocutors would present suggestions for changes in U.S. behavior that might form a basis for a deal on important issues, such as EMCE or cyber espionage against critical infrastructure, but we found that there was little to no corresponding set of asks on the Chinese side. This may stem from the relative lack of expertise on a technically complex policy issue, combined with the understandable reluctance of respondents to speak ahead of official policy on a sensitive issue. The few suggestions we heard were either not as pressing to our interlocutors as U.S. concerns are to U.S. officials or would be unacceptable because they would require U.S. officials to make promises that contravened the U.S. Constitution (notably, the First Amendment). Thus, our second conclusion is that any deal with China to restrain EMCE in exchange for something that the United States might be able and willing to offer in the cyber domain is unlikely to be particularly wide ranging or robust unless it is linked to broader cooperation and conflict avoidance in the overall relationship. We next explored the possibility of achieving progress in cybersecurity negotiations by means of an agreement that would have both the United States and China refrain from attacking each other. Here, we found more common ground; our respondents, and Chinese writings more broadly, generally reflect a willingness to agree to such a proposition (although some of our respondents preferred a multilateral approach over a bilateral agreement). Such an agreement would potentially represent a valuable step forward in terms of mutual reassurance and could help consolidate norms that would affirm, clarify, or at least supplement the applicability of the international LOAC to cyberspace. Since China announced an agreement with Russia in May 2015 to refrain from carrying out cyberattacks on each other, there may be precedent to draw on in negotiations with China over such an issue.2 A logical codicil of any such agreement on avoiding targeting critical infrastructure was that an agreement not to attack also implied an agreement not to spy on such targets. If one is not planning to attack critical infrastructure, there is no reason for a foreign government to be collecting detailed information on a system’s construct and, hence, its vulnerabilities. Additionally, since it is difficult or even impossible to distinguish between evidence of spying on such systems and evidence of intrusions that are preparations for an attack, spying should be abjured by all sides. Here, too, we found some grounds for agreement, although less clear commitment, perhaps because the Chinese we spoke with declined to affirm that victims of cyber espionage could always plausibly and rightfully infer that intrusions constitute preparations for attack. The last proposition we put to our Chinese interlocutors—that the United States might consider sharing insights into attribution if China agreed to common evidentiary standards and credibly committed to prosecuting those found to have violated these—was the trickiest. Such an agreement would require some mutually approved method of determining when one or the other side had violated its part of the bargain in ways that would have the guilty party admit that it erred. As argued above, the current relative weakness of Chinese attribution capabilities, combined with the high levels of mutual strategic mistrust, suggests that having each side accept the other’s prima facie evidence would not work. This suggests that what may be needed for progress is the construction of a bilateral, multilateral, or international cyber-dispute resolution mechanism, supplemented perhaps by U.S. efforts to help China improve its own attribution capabilities. Such an agreement will not come easily; it carries with it political and potential policy risks and may also not gain China’s buy-in. In an environment as troubled by issues of mutual mistrust as the current U.S.-China relationship is, it would be challenging to muster enough U.S. political support for such a step. For their part, many of China’s actors are likely to be suspicious of any U.S. efforts to shape Chinese views of or capabilities in the cyber domain. Yet, such an approach may be an idea that is worth exploring further in Track Two dialogues and conducting further research on to more completely assess all of its practical, technological, and political implications, and to further flesh out where the main sources of opposition are likely to stem from and how they might be reduced. Were such a three-part agreement—including a norm of not targeting or intruding into each side’s critical infrastructure—combined with an offer to help China improve its attribution capabilities in exchange for a deal to actually follow through on, investigate, and maybe even prosecute cyber intrusions originating in China (or the United States) come into existence, it might change the nature of the two sides’ relations in cyberspace across an important swath of issues. To be sure, the two countries would still disagree strongly over such issues as freedom of access to information (United States) versus information control and cyber sovereignty (PRC), efficiency and effectiveness of the current international backbone architecture of the Internet (United States) versus cyber hegemony (PRC), whether both would still engage in cyber-enabled national security espionage, and differences over a host of other issues in cyberspace and beyond. But such a deal, if it could be credibly committed to and followed through on in practice, would represent a substantial improvement of the U.S.-China relationship in cyberspace, for which reason we argue it is worth consideration and additional research. In conclusion, Chinese and U.S. views of cybersecurity overlap only on a few points, and even where they do, the two sides will find it difficult to make progress on such issues as avoiding targeting of critical infrastructure if the two sides struggle to maintain the progress hinted at in the September 2015 summit agreement on cyberspace. With respect to reaching a broad, meaningful, and lasting agreement on norms about legitimate targets in cyberspace, much work remains to be done, and it is unclear that such a result will indeed be possible. Perhaps the most promising area where we might see some prospect of negotiating a set of norms in the years ahead lies in avoiding targeting or carrying out espionage on critical infrastructure. This could be supported by efforts to create common standards of evidence, define how attribution is to be done, and prosecute those who commit such actions. | 9,950 | <h4>The plan is key to getting China say to yes and simultaneously creates cyber integration to the Law of Armed Conflict</h4><p><strong>Harold et al 16</strong> – Libicki is an American scholar and Professor at the Frederick S. Pardee RAND Graduate School in Santa Monica, California, Harold is associate director of the RAND Center for Asia Pacific Policy, Cevallos is a political scientist at the RAND Corporation </p><p>(Scott Warren, Martin C. Libicki, Astrid Stuth Cevallos, Getting to Yes with China in Cyberspace, Kindle, Chapter 5<u>)</p><p>The global salience of U.S.-China relations and the potential for quarrels over cyberspace</u> to <u>play an increasingly disruptive role in the relationship <strong>make it <mark>desirable for the two countries to come to </mark>some <mark>terms over each other’s behavior in cyberspace</u></strong></mark>. <u>In</u> the course of <u>our interviews in China</u> in May 2015, <u>most</u> of our interlocutors <u>did not appear to see any agreement with the</u> <u><strong>U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates as <u>plausible, likely, or</u> even particularly <u>necessary</u>. While the United States appeared to see the two countries’ relationship in cyberspace as untenable, Chinese interviewees in contrast did not seem to see any urgent need to make changes. As a consequence, <u>the September 2015 U.S.-China cybersecurity agreement may have caught our interlocutors as much by surprise as it appeared to catch most of the community that is watching U.S.-China relations</u> (including the authors). As of mid-February 2016 <u>it remains to be seen whether</u> or not <u>the agreement</u> on cyberspace reached at the Xi-Obama summit <u>has effectively resolved the EMCE issue</u>.1 <u>Our</u> first <u>conclusion is that<mark>, if the</u> <u><strong>U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates <u><mark>is determined to </mark>adopt a negotiation-based approach</u> <u>that <mark>address</mark>es</u> <u><mark>the entire range of</mark> Chinese <mark>cyber</mark> espionage</u>, <u><strong><mark>success is unlikely</u></strong></mark> to take place any time soon, unless the costs to China of refusing to negotiate over the cyber issue can be increased (beyond simply the threat of a canceled or failed summit meeting). This could potentially be accomplished through linking this issue more directly to the broader health of the overall relationship through representations to China at the highest levels or to the use of other levers, such as the threat of economic sanctions or retaliation. However, <u>there is no guarantee that a strategy based solely on imposing costs on China for its conduct</u>, sponsorship, or willingness to condone cyber espionage <u>will have the desired effect</u> of reducing Chinese cyber espionage or creating norms on what targets are out of bounds for cyber espionage. <u><strong>This means that <mark>a continued effort to resolve differences and establish norms through dialogue </mark>and negotiation <mark>is highly desirable</u></strong></mark>, even if such an approach may need to be backed up by the threat of cost imposition. Worryingly, as of May 2015, our Chinese interlocutors did not tend to see direct, bilateral talks with the United States on cybersecurity as a way to achieve much regarding specific norms or limitations on cyberspace activities. Instead, China’s approach to the issue of cybersecurity appears in many respects to be focused first and foremost on attempting to articulate and defend a set of values and proposals for the international governance of cyberspace that would redefine cybersecurity away from issues of concern to the United States, such as EMCE and applying the LOAC to cyberspace. In articulating its positions and submitting proposals on cybersecurity to the UN, China has argued for redefining cybersecurity with an eye toward such issues as cyber sovereignty and moving the management of the Internet out of the hands of the United States and the West and into a more China-friendly setting, such as the UN. Our team hoped that Chinese respondents and interlocutors would present suggestions for changes in U.S. behavior that might form a basis for a deal on important issues, such as EMCE or cyber espionage against critical infrastructure, but we found that there was little to no corresponding set of asks on the Chinese side. This may stem from the relative lack of expertise on a technically complex policy issue, combined with the understandable reluctance of respondents to speak ahead of official policy on a sensitive issue. The few suggestions we heard were either not as pressing to our interlocutors as U.S. concerns are to U.S. officials or would be unacceptable because they would require U.S. officials to make promises that contravened the U.S. Constitution (notably, the First Amendment). Thus, our second conclusion is that any deal with China to restrain EMCE in exchange for something that the United States might be able and willing to offer in the cyber domain is unlikely to be particularly wide ranging or robust unless it is linked to broader cooperation and conflict avoidance in the overall relationship. We next explored <u>the possibility of achieving progress in cybersecurity negotiations</u> by <u>means</u> of <u><mark>an agreement that would have</u></mark> both <u><mark>the</u> <u><strong>U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates <u><mark>and China refrain from attacking each other</u>.</mark> <u>Here, <strong>we <mark>found</strong></mark> </u>more <u><strong><mark>common ground</u></strong></mark>; our respondents, and <u>Chinese</u> writings more broadly, generally <u><strong>reflect a willingness to agree to such a proposition</u></strong> (although some of our respondents preferred a multilateral approach over a bilateral agreement). <u>Such an agreement would</u> potentially <u>represent a valuable step forward <mark>in <strong>terms of mutual reassurance</u></strong></mark> <u>and</u> could help <u><strong><mark>consolidate norms that would affirm, clarify, or at least supplement the applicability of the international LOAC to cyberspace</u></strong></mark>. Since China announced an agreement with Russia in May 2015 to refrain from carrying out cyberattacks on each other, there may be precedent to draw on in negotiations with China over such an issue.2 <u>A logical codicil of any such agreement</u> <u>on avoiding targeting critical infrastructure</u> was that an agreement not to attack <u>also implied an agreement not to spy on such targets</u>. If one is not planning to attack critical infrastructure, <u>there is no reason for a foreign government to be collecting detailed information on a system’s construct</u> and, hence, its vulnerabilities. Additionally, since <u>it is </u>difficult or even <u>impossible to distinguish between</u> evidence of <u>spying</u> on such systems <u>and</u> evidence of intrusions that are preparations for <u>an attack</u>, <u>spying should be abjured by all sides</u>. Here, too, <u>we found</u> some <u>grounds for agreement</u>, although less clear commitment, perhaps because the Chinese we spoke with declined to affirm that victims of cyber espionage could always plausibly and rightfully infer that intrusions constitute preparations for attack. The last proposition we put to our Chinese interlocutors—that the United States might consider sharing insights into attribution if China agreed to common evidentiary standards and credibly committed to prosecuting those found to have violated these—was the trickiest. Such an agreement would require some mutually approved method of determining when one or the other side had violated its part of the bargain in ways that would have the guilty party admit that it erred. As argued above, <u>the current relative weakness of Chinese attribution capabilities</u>, combined with the high levels of mutual strategic mistrust, <u>suggests</u> that having each side accept the <u>other’s prima facie evidence would not work</u>. This suggests that what may be needed for progress is the construction of <u><mark>a bilateral</u></mark>, multilateral, or international cyber-dispute <u><mark>resolution </mark>mechanism, supplemented </u>perhaps <u><strong>by U.S. efforts to help China improve its own attribution capabilities</u></strong>. Such an agreement will not come easily; it carries with it political and potential policy risks and may also not gain China’s buy-in. In an environment as troubled by issues of mutual mistrust as the current U.S.-China relationship is, it would be challenging to muster enough U.S. political support for such a step. For their part, many of China’s actors are likely to be suspicious of any U.S. efforts to shape Chinese views of or capabilities in the cyber domain. Yet, such an approach may be an idea that is worth exploring further in Track Two dialogues and conducting further research on to more completely assess all of its practical, technological, and political implications, and to further flesh out where the main sources of opposition are likely to stem from and how they might be reduced. Were such <u>a three-part <mark>agreement</mark>—including a norm of <mark>not targeting</mark> or intruding into each side’s critical <mark>infrastructure</mark>—combined with an offer to <mark>help China improve </mark>its <mark>attribution </mark>capabilities in exchange for a deal to actually follow through on, investigate, and maybe even prosecute cyber intrusions</u> originating in China (or the United States) <u>come into existence</u>, <u><strong>it might change the nature of the two sides’ relations in cyberspace across an important swath of issues</u></strong>. To be sure, the two countries would still disagree strongly over such issues as freedom of access to information (United States) versus information control and cyber sovereignty (PRC), efficiency and effectiveness of the current international backbone architecture of the Internet (United States) versus cyber hegemony (PRC), whether both would still engage in cyber-enabled national security espionage, and differences over a host of other issues in cyberspace and beyond. But <u>such a deal</u>, if it could be credibly committed to and followed through on in practice, <u><strong><mark>would represent a substantial improvement of the U.S.-China relationship in cyberspace</u></strong></mark>, for which reason we argue it is worth consideration and additional research. In conclusion, <u>Chinese and U.S. views of cybersecurity overlap</u> only <u>on a few points</u>, and even where they do, <u><mark>the two sides will find it difficult to make progress</u></mark> on such issues as avoiding targeting of critical infrastructure <u><mark>if the two sides struggle</u> <u>to maintain</u></mark> the <u><mark>progress</u></mark> hinted at <u><mark>in the September</mark> 2015 summit <mark>agreement</u></mark> on cyberspace. With respect to reaching a broad, meaningful, and lasting agreement on norms about legitimate targets in cyberspace, much work remains to be done, and it is unclear that such a result will indeed be possible. Perhaps <u><mark>the most promising area</u></mark> where we might see some prospect of negotiating a set <u>of norms</u> in the years ahead <u><strong><mark>lies in avoiding targeting</u></strong> <u><strong>or carrying out espionage on critical infrastructure</u></strong></mark>. <u>This could be supported by efforts to create common standards of evidence, define how attribution is to be done, and prosecute those who commit such actions.</p></u> | 1AC DCI – Bell v1.0 Hui/Vering | 1AC – DCI | LOAC | 167,319 | 112 | 127,596 | ./documents/hspolicy16/ShawneeMissionWest/HuVe/Shawnee%20Mission%20West-Hui-Vering-Aff-DCI-Round2.docx | 667,026 | A | DCI | 2 | BVN RT | Peg Wefald | 1AC Cyber - Attribution and LOAC v1
1NC China war good T No QPQ New Affs Bad Russia DA Consult Russia CP Cap K
2NR China war good | hspolicy16/ShawneeMissionWest/HuVe/Shawnee%20Mission%20West-Hui-Vering-Aff-DCI-Round2.docx | null | 56,487 | HuVe | Shawnee Mission West HuVe | null | An..... | Hu..... | Ca..... | Ve..... | 20,285 | ShawneeMissionWest | Shawnee Mission West | null | null | 1,015 | hspolicy16 | HS Policy 2016-17 | 2,016 | cx | hs | 2 |
3,535,485 | We’d just respond to an attack by making the treatment free for everyone | Petersen 14 | Kimberly Ann Petersen 14, M.A. Candidate in Security Studies, Naval Post-Graduate School, September 2014, “The Affordable Care Act: a prescription for homeland security preparedness?,” https://calhoun.nps.edu/bitstream/handle/10945/43979/14Sep_Petersen_Kimberly.pdf?sequence=1 | a robust accessible health care system aids homeland security through prevention Vaccines are used to prevent bioattacks, or manage a successful attack. Homeland security experts considered smallpox a potential bioweapon, hence the stockpiling of the smallpox vaccine for vaccination and treatment to be successful in the event of an outbreak, the population will need access to providers
It is likely in the event of such a scenario as a smallpox attack, the U.S. government will set up emergency distribution centers, where all people will receive antibiotics, without regard for health insurance or payment, as in the C D C Smallpox Response Plan the smallpox vaccination program serves as a model for universal health care access | It is likely in the event the U.S will set up emergency distribution centers where all will receive antibiotics, without regard for insurance as in the C D C Smallpox Response Plan smallpox vaccination program serves as a model for universal access | Another way that a robust and accessible health care system aids homeland security is through prevention. Vaccines are one of the tools used to prevent bioattacks, or at least to manage a successful attack. Homeland security experts have long considered smallpox a potential bioweapon, hence the stockpiling of the smallpox vaccine since 9/11. Smallpox is an infectious disease caused by the virus variola major or variola minor. The more common and more virulent form, variola minor, has a mortality rate of about 30 percent.70 The disease was present throughout the world for tens of thousands of years, but was eradicated via a worldwide vaccination program prior to 1980. The smallpox virus only exists now in laboratory stockpiles.71 One of the concerns post-9/11 was the stockpiles would be pilfered and used to intentionally reintroduce the virus to humans. The U.S. currently has 300 million doses of smallpox vaccine in stockpiles around the U.S.—enough to vaccinate nearly the entire population. Recently, the U.S. government purchased enough of a new smallpox medication to treat two million people.72 However, for the vaccination process and the treatment process to be successful in the event of an outbreak, the population will need access to health care providers. The Department of Homeland Security’s fact sheet on what to do in the event of a bioterror directs us as follows: “People in the group or area that authorities have linked to exposure who have symptoms that match those described should seek emergency medical attention.”73
It is likely in the event of such a dramatic scenario as a smallpox attack, the U.S. government will set up emergency distribution centers, where all people will receive prophylaxis antibiotics, without regard for health insurance or payment, as outlined in the Center for Disease Control’s Smallpox Response Plan and Guidelines. 74 So perhaps the smallpox vaccination program serves as a model for universal health care access. | 1,981 | <h4>We’d just respond to an attack by making the treatment free for everyone </h4><p>Kimberly Ann <strong>Petersen 14</strong>, M.A. Candidate in Security Studies, Naval Post-Graduate School, September 2014, “The Affordable Care Act: a prescription for homeland security preparedness?,” https://calhoun.nps.edu/bitstream/handle/10945/43979/14Sep_Petersen_Kimberly.pdf?sequence=1</p><p>Another way that <u>a robust</u> and <u>accessible health care system aids homeland security</u> is <u>through prevention</u>. <u>Vaccines are</u> one of the tools <u>used to prevent bioattacks, or</u> at least to <u>manage a successful attack. Homeland security experts</u> have long <u>considered smallpox a potential bioweapon, hence the stockpiling of the smallpox vaccine</u> since 9/11. Smallpox is an infectious disease caused by the virus variola major or variola minor. The more common and more virulent form, variola minor, has a mortality rate of about 30 percent.70 The disease was present throughout the world for tens of thousands of years, but was eradicated via a worldwide vaccination program prior to 1980. The smallpox virus only exists now in laboratory stockpiles.71 One of the concerns post-9/11 was the stockpiles would be pilfered and used to intentionally reintroduce the virus to humans. The U.S. currently has 300 million doses of smallpox vaccine in stockpiles around the U.S.—enough to vaccinate nearly the entire population. Recently, the U.S. government purchased enough of a new smallpox medication to treat two million people.72 However, <u>for</u> the <u>vaccination</u> process <u>and</u> the <u>treatment</u> process <u>to be successful in the event of an outbreak, the population will need access to</u> health care <u>providers</u>. The Department of Homeland Security’s fact sheet on what to do in the event of a bioterror directs us as follows: “People in the group or area that authorities have linked to exposure who have symptoms that match those described should seek emergency medical attention.”73</p><p><u><mark>It is <strong>likely</strong> in the event</mark> of such a</u> dramatic <u>scenario as a smallpox attack, <mark>the U.S</mark>. government <mark>will set up <strong>emergency</mark> <mark>distribution centers</strong></mark>, <mark>where all</mark> people <mark>will receive</u></mark> prophylaxis <u><mark>antibiotics, <strong>without regard for</mark> health <mark>insurance</mark> or payment</strong>, <mark>as</u></mark> outlined <u><mark>in the <strong>C</u></strong></mark>enter for <u><strong><mark>D</u></strong></mark>isease <u><strong><mark>C</u></strong></mark>ontrol’s <u><mark>Smallpox Response Plan</u></mark> and Guidelines. 74 So perhaps <u>the <mark>smallpox vaccination</mark> <mark>program serves as a <strong>model for universal</mark> health care <mark>access</u></strong></mark>.</p> | ***1NC*** | Disease | Squo Solves---Free Treatment | 45,886 | 390 | 116,862 | ./documents/ndtceda17/Northwestern/JaWe/Northwestern-Jankovsky-Weideman-Neg-ADA-Round1.docx | 599,720 | N | ADA | 1 | MoState | Tom OGorman | 1AC Single Payer
2NR Econ da and innovation turn | ndtceda17/Northwestern/JaWe/Northwestern-Jankovsky-Weideman-Neg-ADA-Round1.docx | null | 51,029 | JaWe | Northwestern JaWe | null | Ga..... | Ja..... | Jo..... | We..... | 19,135 | Northwestern | Northwestern | null | null | 1,007 | ndtceda17 | NDT/CEDA 2017-18 | 2,017 | cx | college | 2 |
3,505,561 | Bargaining leverage significantly decreases costs relative to the percentage of GDP---robust studies establish causality between bargaining power and cost | Seidman 14 | Seidman 14 — Laurence Seidman, Professor of Economics at the University of Delaware, PhD in Economics from the University of California-Berkley, Prepared for National Tax Association Conference November 2013, Revised February 2014 for the Proceedings of the 106th Annual Conference, “Medicare for All: A Public Finance Analysis” National Tax Association, https://www.ntanet.org/wp-content/uploads/proceedings/2013/007-seidman-medicare-for-all.pdf | the U.S. has been an extreme outlier among high-income countries with respect to medical cost as a percent of GDP. the U.S. medical cost is 18% of GDP but no other country exceeds 12%. countries have used single-payer bargaining power to limit the rise in prices High price, not high quantity, is the main reason that U.S. medical expenditure is so high. That is the conclusion of an empirical study of OECD countries They analyze the split between price and quantity They conclude that prices, not quantities, are the drivers of cross-national differences in health spending, and that a major cause of the difference in prices is the difference in the bargaining power the highly fragmented buy side of is relatively weak by international standards. Medicare for All is the simplest way to achieve payer bargaining power over medical providers while at the a private insurance system. should be able to cut several percentage points off U.S. medical cost as a percent of GDP, thereby reducing the medical cost gap between the U.S. and other economically advanced countries. | the U.S. has been an outlier among countries with respect to medical cost countries have used bargaining power to limit the rise in prices an empirical study of OECD countries conclude prices, not quantities, are the drivers a major cause of the difference is the difference in the bargaining power the highly fragmented buy side is weak by international standards bargaining power should be able to cut several percentage points off U.S. medical cost as a percent of GDP reducing the cost gap between the U.S. and other countries | The Impact of Single-Payer Bargaining Power on Medical Cost as a Percent of GDP
For several decades the U.S. has been an extreme outlier among high-income countries with respect to medical cost as a percent of GDP. Today the U.S. medical cost is 18% of GDP but no other country exceeds 12%. For several decades, virtually all high-income countries have used single-payer bargaining power to limit the rise in prices of medical goods and services. Payer bargaining power has been used to limit prices set by hospitals and drug companies and fees set by doctors, and to set budgets—total spending caps—for hospitals, drugs, and doctors. Some countries have exercised payer bargaining power through a government national health service—for example, Britain; others, by having government be the single-payer of private medical providers—for example, Canada; and others, by having the government coordinate private insurers into a united bargaining unit, sometimes called an “all-payer” system--for example, Germany. But will this method lead to waiting lists and low quality? It depends on whether payer bargaining power is applied severely or moderately. Figure 1 shows that with 100% insurance, the patients’ demand curve would be a vertical line—no matter how high a price is charged by the medical provider (doctor, hospital, or drug company), patients’ demand is the same as it would be if the price charged were zero. With a normal supply curve S, at first glance it might seem that the market would move to point G and stay there. But once the market reaches point G, price continues to climb up D without limit unless insurers or government regulators stop it because with 100% insurance, patients no longer care about the price their own medical provider charges when they seek medical care and choose among medical providers, and providers know this. The unlimited price rise would occur even if patients must pay a fixed dollar copayment or modest deductible before the 100% insurance kicks in. As long as the dollar copayment or deductible doesn’t vary with the price the provider charges, a patient is not deterred from going to a medical provider no matter how much the provider raises the price charged to the patient’s insurer. Of course, the insurers paying the bills will try to resist the unlimited price rise under 100% insurance. When insurers receive bills from medical providers, they usually refuse to pay the providers’ prices. When the provider charges $500 for a particular service to an enrolled patient, the insurer announces that its “allowable” charge for that service is $200 and that’s all it will pay. The provider usually accepts the “allowable” charge of a large insurer with many enrollees. But the ability of an insurer to stop rising medical provider prices depends on its share of the market. Suppose one private insurer tries to set its allowable charge well below the provider’s price. The provider will tell that insurer that unless its allowable charge is substantially raised, the provider will not treat its enrollees. Enrollees will complain to their employers that they can’t use the providers they want unless the employer switches insurance companies. With other insurance companies available, employers will switch. To prevent the loss of enrollees, the insurer will have to raise its allowable charge substantially. Thus, with many competing private insurers, no single insurer will have sufficient bargaining power to significantly hold down allowable charges. High price, not high quantity, is the main reason that U.S. medical expenditure—which equals price times quantity—is so high. That is the conclusion of an empirical study of OECD countries by health economists Anderson, Reinhardt, Hussey, and Petrosyan (2003) in their article entitled, “It’s the Prices, Stupid: Why the United States Is So Different from Other Countries.” They analyze the split between price and quantity in 2000, presenting comparisons of different quantity measures including doctors, nurses, hospital beds, hospital admissions, and hospital days. In most of these, the quantity per capita in the U.S. was below the OECD median. They conclude that prices, not quantities, are the drivers of cross-national differences in health spending, and that a major cause of the difference in prices is the difference in the bargaining power of the payers of medical providers. They emphasize the difference between the U.S. and other OECD countries in the degree of bargaining power on the buyers’ side of markets for medical care, writing (p102): “Although the huge federal Medicare program and the federal-state Medicaid programs do possess some monopsony power, and large private insurers may enjoy some degree of bargaining power as well in some localities, the highly fragmented buy side of the U.S. health system is relatively weak by international standards. It is one factor, among others, that could explain the relatively high prices paid for health care and for health professionals in the United States. In comparison, the government-controlled health systems of Canada, Europe, and Japan allocate considerably more market power to the buy side.” Their findings can be interpreted using Figure 1. The U.S. is currently at a price well above point G because of widespread 100% patient insurance and the relatively weak bargaining power of multiple insurers. Replacing multiple private insurers with a single payer— Medicare for All—would enable the price to be brought down to G. If Medicare for All reduces price to G, but no further, there would be no waiting lists. Only if Medicare for All reduces the price below G would waiting lists be generated. As shown in the diagram, some countries—for example, Britain and to some extent Canada—have used payer bargaining power to reduce the price too far—below G—and generated waiting lists. But other countries--for example, Germany and France—have used payer bargaining power to reduce the price to G but not lower than G and have therefore avoided waiting lists. The U.S. is an affluent country with a preference for high spending on medical care. Medicare has always paid doctor and hospital prices that are high enough--point G in Figure 1- - to avoid waiting lists and to enable Medicare patients to obtain high quality medical care, technology, and pharmaceuticals. Medicare for All should have the same objective. The aim should be to keep prices from rising above G or falling below G; Medicare for All should aim for G. Any signs of waiting lists or low quality should be a signal that prices have been set below G and should therefore be raised in order to eliminate waiting lists and restore higher quality. Medicare for All is the simplest way to achieve payer bargaining power over medical providers while at the same time eliminating the other shortcomings of a private insurance system. Based on the experience of other countries, it should be able to cut several percentage points off U.S. medical cost as a percent of GDP, thereby reducing the medical cost gap between the U.S. and other economically advanced countries. | 7,117 | <h4>Bargaining leverage <u>significantly decreases</u> costs relative to the percentage of GDP---robust studies <u>establish causality</u> between bargaining power and cost</h4><p><strong>Seidman 14</strong> — Laurence Seidman, Professor of Economics at the University of Delaware, PhD in Economics from the University of California-Berkley, Prepared for National Tax Association Conference November 2013, Revised February 2014 for the Proceedings of the 106th Annual Conference, “Medicare for All: A Public Finance Analysis” National Tax Association, https://www.ntanet.org/wp-content/uploads/proceedings/2013/007-seidman-medicare-for-all.pdf</p><p>The Impact of Single-Payer Bargaining Power on Medical Cost as a Percent of GDP </p><p>For several decades <u><mark>the U.S. has been an</mark> <strong>extreme <mark>outlier</strong> among</mark> high-income <mark>countries with respect to medical cost</mark> as a percent of GDP.</u> Today <u>the U.S. medical cost is <strong>18% of GDP</strong> but no other country exceeds 12%.</u> For several decades, virtually all high-income <u><mark>countries have used</mark> <strong>single-payer <mark>bargaining power</strong> to limit the rise in prices</u></mark> of medical goods and services. Payer bargaining power has been used to limit prices set by hospitals and drug companies and fees set by doctors, and to set budgets—total spending caps—for hospitals, drugs, and doctors. Some countries have exercised payer bargaining power through a government national health service—for example, Britain; others, by having government be the single-payer of private medical providers—for example, Canada; and others, by having the government coordinate private insurers into a united bargaining unit, sometimes called an “all-payer” system--for example, Germany. But will this method lead to waiting lists and low quality? It depends on whether payer bargaining power is applied severely or moderately. Figure 1 shows that with 100% insurance, the patients’ demand curve would be a vertical line—no matter how high a price is charged by the medical provider (doctor, hospital, or drug company), patients’ demand is the same as it would be if the price charged were zero. With a normal supply curve S, at first glance it might seem that the market would move to point G and stay there. But once the market reaches point G, price continues to climb up D without limit unless insurers or government regulators stop it because with 100% insurance, patients no longer care about the price their own medical provider charges when they seek medical care and choose among medical providers, and providers know this. The unlimited price rise would occur even if patients must pay a fixed dollar copayment or modest deductible before the 100% insurance kicks in. As long as the dollar copayment or deductible doesn’t vary with the price the provider charges, a patient is not deterred from going to a medical provider no matter how much the provider raises the price charged to the patient’s insurer. Of course, the insurers paying the bills will try to resist the unlimited price rise under 100% insurance. When insurers receive bills from medical providers, they usually refuse to pay the providers’ prices. When the provider charges $500 for a particular service to an enrolled patient, the insurer announces that its “allowable” charge for that service is $200 and that’s all it will pay. The provider usually accepts the “allowable” charge of a large insurer with many enrollees. But the ability of an insurer to stop rising medical provider prices depends on its share of the market. Suppose one private insurer tries to set its allowable charge well below the provider’s price. The provider will tell that insurer that unless its allowable charge is substantially raised, the provider will not treat its enrollees. Enrollees will complain to their employers that they can’t use the providers they want unless the employer switches insurance companies. With other insurance companies available, employers will switch. To prevent the loss of enrollees, the insurer will have to raise its allowable charge substantially. Thus, with many competing private insurers, no single insurer will have sufficient bargaining power to significantly hold down allowable charges. <u><strong>High price, not high quantity</strong>, is the main reason that U.S. medical expenditure</u>—which equals price times quantity—<u>is so high. That is the conclusion of <mark>an <strong>empirical study of OECD countries</u></strong></mark> by health economists Anderson, Reinhardt, Hussey, and Petrosyan (2003) in their article entitled, “It’s the Prices, Stupid: Why the United States Is So Different from Other Countries.” <u>They analyze the split between <strong>price and quantity</u></strong> in 2000, presenting comparisons of different quantity measures including doctors, nurses, hospital beds, hospital admissions, and hospital days. In most of these, the quantity per capita in the U.S. was below the OECD median. <u>They <mark>conclude</mark> that <strong><mark>prices, not quantities</strong>, are the drivers </mark>of cross-national differences in health spending, and that <mark>a major cause of the <strong>difference</mark> in prices</strong> <mark>is the difference in the <strong>bargaining power</u></strong></mark> of the payers of medical providers. They emphasize the difference between the U.S. and other OECD countries in the degree of bargaining power on the buyers’ side of markets for medical care, writing (p102): “Although the huge federal Medicare program and the federal-state Medicaid programs do possess some monopsony power, and large private insurers may enjoy some degree of bargaining power as well in some localities, <u><mark>the <strong>highly fragmented</strong> buy side</mark> of</u> the U.S. health system <u><mark>is</mark> relatively <mark>weak by <strong>international standards</strong></mark>.</u> It is one factor, among others, that could explain the relatively high prices paid for health care and for health professionals in the United States. In comparison, the government-controlled health systems of Canada, Europe, and Japan allocate considerably more market power to the buy side.” Their findings can be interpreted using Figure 1. The U.S. is currently at a price well above point G because of widespread 100% patient insurance and the relatively weak bargaining power of multiple insurers. Replacing multiple private insurers with a single payer— Medicare for All—would enable the price to be brought down to G. If Medicare for All reduces price to G, but no further, there would be no waiting lists. Only if Medicare for All reduces the price below G would waiting lists be generated. As shown in the diagram, some countries—for example, Britain and to some extent Canada—have used payer bargaining power to reduce the price too far—below G—and generated waiting lists. But other countries--for example, Germany and France—have used payer bargaining power to reduce the price to G but not lower than G and have therefore avoided waiting lists. The U.S. is an affluent country with a preference for high spending on medical care. Medicare has always paid doctor and hospital prices that are high enough--point G in Figure 1- - to avoid waiting lists and to enable Medicare patients to obtain high quality medical care, technology, and pharmaceuticals. Medicare for All should have the same objective. The aim should be to keep prices from rising above G or falling below G; Medicare for All should aim for G. Any signs of waiting lists or low quality should be a signal that prices have been set below G and should therefore be raised in order to eliminate waiting lists and restore higher quality. <u>Medicare for All is the simplest way to achieve payer <strong><mark>bargaining power</strong></mark> over medical providers while at the</u> same time eliminating the other shortcomings of <u>a <strong>private insurance system</strong>.</u> Based on the experience of other countries, it <u><mark>should be able to cut <strong>several percentage points</strong> off U.S. medical cost as a percent of GDP</mark>, thereby <mark>reducing the <strong></mark>medical <mark>cost gap</strong> between the U.S. and other</mark> <strong>economically advanced <mark>countries</strong></mark>. </p></u> | null | 1AC Rd 1 UT | 2 | 1,435,220 | 112 | 116,410 | ./documents/ndtceda17/Minnesota/WaKo/Minnesota-Wang-Kostelny-Aff-Texas-Round1.docx | 599,078 | A | Texas | 1 | Liberty GK | Whitley | 1ac- sp with cost coverage job lock
1nc- spec Hagopian and Goldman cp econ da
2nc- cp and econ
1nr- spec
2nr- spec | ndtceda17/Minnesota/WaKo/Minnesota-Wang-Kostelny-Aff-Texas-Round1.docx | null | 50,983 | WaKo | Minnesota WaKo | null | Al..... | Wa..... | Co..... | Ko..... | 19,128 | Minnesota | Minnesota | null | null | 1,007 | ndtceda17 | NDT/CEDA 2017-18 | 2,017 | cx | college | 2 |
3,508,061 | Heg stops global nuclear war | Khalilzad 16 | Zalmay Khalilzad 16, former U.S. ambassador to the United Nations, counselor at the CSIS, 3/23/16, “4 Lessons about America's Role in the World,” http://nationalinterest.org/feature/4-lessons-about-americas-role-the-world-15574?page=show | the U S has a strong interest in precluding the emergence of another bipolar world or a world of many great powers Multipolarity led to two world wars and bipolarity resulted in a worldwide struggle with the risk of nuclear annihilation. To avoid a return such circumstances our objective must be to prevent a hostile power to dominate a “critical region,” which would pose a global challenge
Giving major powers the green light to establish spheres of influence would produce a multipolar world and risk war between the major powers
The U S can manage the rise and resurgence of great powers like China, Russia and Iran at an acceptable cost without ceding entire spheres of influence The U S should promote a balance of power in key regions while seeking opportunities to reconcile differences among major actors | the U S has a strong interest in precluding another bipolar world or many powers Multipolarity led to world wars bipolarity resulted in risk of nuclear annihilation. To avoid a return our objective must be to prevent a hostile power to dominate a “critical region
Giving major powers the green light would produce a multipolar world and risk war between major powers
The U S can manage the rise of great powers like China, Russia and Iran without ceding spheres of influence | Ultimately, however, we concluded that the United States has a strong interest in precluding the emergence of another bipolar world—as in the Cold War—or a world of many great powers, as existed before the two world wars. Multipolarity led to two world wars and bipolarity resulted in a protracted worldwide struggle with the risk of nuclear annihilation. To avoid a return such circumstances, Secretary of Defense Dick Cheney ultimately agreed that our objective must be to prevent a hostile power to dominate a “critical region,” which would give it the resources, industrial capabilities and population to pose a global challenge. This insight has guided U.S. defense policy throughout the post–Cold War era.
Giving major powers the green light to establish spheres of influence would produce a multipolar world and risk the return of war between the major powers. Without a stabilizing U.S. presence in the Persian Gulf and U.S. relationships with Jordan and the Gulf States, Iran could shut down oil shipments in its supposed sphere of influence. A similar scenario in fact played out during the 1987 “tanker war” of the Iran-Iraq war, which eventually escalated into a direct military conflict between the United States and Iran. Iran’s nuclear program makes these scenarios even more dangerous.
The United States can manage the rise and resurgence of great powers like China, Russia and Iran at an acceptable cost without ceding entire spheres of influence. The key is to focus on normalizing the geopolitics of the Middle East, Europe and the Asia-Pacific, which the United States can do by strengthening its transatlantic and transpacific alliances and adapting them to the new, dangerous circumstances on the horizon. The United States should promote a balance of power in key regions while seeking opportunities to reconcile differences among major actors. | 1,867 | <h4>Heg stops global nuclear war</h4><p>Zalmay <strong>Khalilzad 16</strong>, former U.S. ambassador to the United Nations, counselor at the CSIS, 3/23/16, “4 Lessons about America's Role in the World,” http://nationalinterest.org/feature/4-lessons-about-americas-role-the-world-15574?page=show </p><p>Ultimately, however, we concluded that <u><strong><mark>the U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates <u><strong><mark>has a strong interest in precluding</mark> the emergence of <mark>another bipolar world</u></strong></mark>—as in the Cold War—<u><strong><mark>or</mark> a world of <mark>many</mark> great <mark>powers</u></strong></mark>, as existed before the two world wars. <u><strong><mark>Multipolarity led to</mark> two <mark>world wars</mark> and <mark>bipolarity resulted in</mark> a</u></strong> protracted <u><strong>worldwide struggle with the <mark>risk of nuclear annihilation. To avoid a return</mark> such circumstances</u></strong>, Secretary of Defense Dick Cheney ultimately agreed that <u><strong><mark>our objective must be to prevent a hostile power to dominate a “critical region</mark>,” which would</u></strong> give it the resources, industrial capabilities and population to <u><strong>pose a global challenge</u></strong>. This insight has guided U.S. defense policy throughout the post–Cold War era. </p><p><u><strong><mark>Giving major powers the green light</mark> to establish spheres of influence <mark>would produce a multipolar world and risk</u></strong></mark> the return of <u><strong><mark>war between</mark> the <mark>major powers</u></strong></mark>. Without a stabilizing U.S. presence in the Persian Gulf and U.S. relationships with Jordan and the Gulf States, Iran could shut down oil shipments in its supposed sphere of influence. A similar scenario in fact played out during the 1987 “tanker war” of the Iran-Iraq war, which eventually escalated into a direct military conflict between the United States and Iran. Iran’s nuclear program makes these scenarios even more dangerous. </p><p><u><strong><mark>The U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates <u><strong><mark>can manage the rise</mark> and resurgence <mark>of great powers like China, Russia and Iran</mark> at an acceptable cost <mark>without ceding</mark> entire <mark>spheres of influence</u></strong></mark>. The key is to focus on normalizing the geopolitics of the Middle East, Europe and the Asia-Pacific, which the United States can do by strengthening its transatlantic and transpacific alliances and adapting them to the new, dangerous circumstances on the horizon. <u><strong>The U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates <u><strong>should promote a balance of power in key regions while seeking opportunities to reconcile differences among major actors</u></strong>.</p> | 2AC | Hegemony | 2AC – Heg Good | 9,761 | 120 | 116,548 | ./documents/ndtceda17/Northwestern/CaEs/Northwestern-Callahan-Esman-Aff-Dartmouth%20RR-Round5.docx | 599,550 | A | Dartmouth RR | 5 | Emory FG | Arnett | 1AC Implement New ACA Mandate Aff
1NC T Gov Insurance States CP Commerce Clause CP and DA Midterms Federalism Heg Bad
2NR Heg Bad | ndtceda17/Northwestern/CaEs/Northwestern-Callahan-Esman-Aff-Dartmouth%20RR-Round5.docx | null | 51,028 | CaEs | Northwestern CaEs | null | Ch..... | Ca..... | Pa..... | Es..... | 19,135 | Northwestern | Northwestern | null | null | 1,007 | ndtceda17 | NDT/CEDA 2017-18 | 2,017 | cx | college | 2 |
3,003,758 | Their Lissner ev doesn’t assume the cp, but it does say that Trump can’t deescalate other threats even without NFU – can’t solve | Lissner 17. Stanton Nuclear Security Fellow at the Council on Foreign Relations. 5-23-2017. "The Risk of Nuclear Catastrophe Under Trump." War on the Rocks. https://warontherocks.com/2017/05/the-risk-of-nuclear-catastrophe-under-trump/ | Rebecca Friedman Lissner 17. Stanton Nuclear Security Fellow at the Council on Foreign Relations. 5-23-2017. "The Risk of Nuclear Catastrophe Under Trump." War on the Rocks. https://warontherocks.com/2017/05/the-risk-of-nuclear-catastrophe-under-trump/ | as the world’s most powerful state the United States plays an important role in moderating —– or enhancing —– the likelihood of nuclear use. Trump’s comments during the campaign and transition prompted concern about his cavalier attitude toward, and lack of knowledge about, the world’s deadliest weapons more than 100 days into the Trump administration, there are early warning signs indicating the president’s policies could increase the risk of nuclear catastrophe this president is nothing if not unpredictable the president has the sole authority to launch nuclear weapons through the “nuclear triad” Trump’s impulsive temperament obsession with projecting strength and aversion to normative constraints may make him more prone to the Trump administration’s penchant for sending mixed signals increases the risk of misperception Trump is famously mercurial, abruptly changing positions on issues Rather than allowing the White House communications staff to clarify his positions Trump often contradicts them. when aides sought to soften Trump’s call for the United States to “strengthen and expand” its nuclear arsenal, Trump went on the record a second time to threaten an arms race senior national security aides frequently stake out divergent policy positions – with the president’s apparent encouragement — as exhibited by the slew of incompatible explanations for Syria The result is confusion surrounding whose statements represent administration policy —– a whiplash effect recently on display in the back-and-forth on North Korea. Though the president seems to believe unpredictability creates bargaining leverage, it also prevents the administration from credibly telegraphing its intentions. This dynamic privileges potentially escalatory military displays to demonstrate seriousness. If a crisis were to reach boiling point, the Trump administration would struggle to turn down the heat by credibly signaling restraint or limited aims a weaker adversary would have little choice but to engage in worst-case-scenario planning, and a threatening tweet could provoke a foreign leader to gamble on a first strike rather than risk U.S. preemption Trump’s slippery reputation could also hinder his ability to arbitrate international disputes involving nuclear powers —– for example, if war were to break out between India and Pakistan. | Trump’s comments prompt concern about his cavalier attitude the president has sole authority to launch nuc s Trump’s impulsive temperament and aversion to normative constraints may make him prone to sending mixed signals increases misperception Trump is mercurial Rather than allowing staff to clarify Trump contradicts them The result is confusion prevents credibly telegraphing intent If a crisis were to reach boiling Trump would struggle to credibly signal restraint a weak adversary would engage in worst-case-scenario planning a threatening tweet could provoke first strike Trump’s slippery reputation could also hinder his ability to arbitrate international disputes involving nuclear powers —– for example, if war were to break out between India and Pakistan. | Growing tension on the Korean Peninsula has returned the unimaginable terror of nuclear war to the American public consciousness. The danger is a global one: Nine states possess nearly 15,000 nuclear weapons and the detonation of even one of these weapons could cause humanitarian and economic catastrophe. Although the use of a nuclear weapon by a state or non-state actor is unlikely, it is not impossible, and the risk may be growing. Indeed, such a rare event can be evaluated in terms of a simple risk-assessment formula: probability multiplied by consequences. Given the enormous consequences of nuclear use, even small fluctuations in probability warrant attention. Some variation will arise from changes in the international environment, such as technological advances that make nuclear command and control systems more or less vulnerable to cyber-attack, or fluctuation in the level of tension between nuclear-armed rivals like India and Pakistan. But as the world’s most powerful state, with its own vast nuclear arsenal as well as a record of leadership in nonproliferation and nuclear security efforts, the United States plays an important role in moderating —– or enhancing —– the likelihood of nuclear use. President Donald Trump’s comments during the campaign and transition prompted widespread concern about his cavalier attitude toward, and lack of knowledge about, the world’s deadliest weapons. Since taking office, he has tempered his rhetoric somewhat —– but more than 100 days into the Trump administration, there are early warning signs indicating the president’s policies could increase the risk of nuclear catastrophe. Setting aside accidental launch or detonation, the most likely scenarios for the intentional or miscalculated use of a nuclear weapon are nuclear detonation by a state during crisis or wartime, and nuclear use by a non-state actor, such as a terrorist group. While this president is nothing if not unpredictable, it is both important and possible to sketch out how such a nuclear use might play out. The five risks described below are meant as a starting point for that discussion. Risk #1: Nuclear First-Use by the United States First, the president has the sole authority to launch nuclear weapons through the “nuclear triad” of land, sea, and air-launched systems. The horrific consequences, fear of retaliation, and extraordinary capabilities of U.S. conventional forces militate against nuclear use in all but the most extreme circumstances. Nonetheless, Trump’s impulsive temperament, obsession with projecting strength, and aversion to normative constraints may make him more prone to nuclear use than other recent presidents. Beyond these already-perceptible presidential proclivities, the Nuclear Posture Review —– which recently began under Pentagon leadership —– will elucidate the administration’s declaratory nuclear doctrine, providing the first concrete indication of scenarios in which the Trump administration would consider nuclear use. Risk #2: Inadvertent Nuclear Escalation Second, the Trump administration’s penchant for sending mixed signals increases the risk of misperception in the event of a crisis or war involving another nuclear state. Trump is famously mercurial, abruptly changing positions on issues ranging from NATO’s obsolescence to the desirability of nuclear proliferation. Rather than allowing the White House communications staff to clarify his positions, Trump often contradicts them. In December, for example, when aides sought to soften Trump’s call for the United States to “strengthen and expand” its nuclear arsenal, Trump went on the record a second time to threaten an arms race. Moreover, senior national security aides frequently stake out divergent policy positions – with the president’s apparent encouragement — as exhibited by the slew of incompatible explanations for Trump’s April decision to launch cruise missiles into Syria. The result is confusion surrounding whose statements represent administration policy —– a whiplash effect most recently on display in the back-and-forth on North Korea. Though the president seems to believe unpredictability creates bargaining leverage, it also prevents the administration from credibly telegraphing its intentions. This dynamic makes diplomacy difficult and privileges potentially escalatory military displays to demonstrate seriousness. If a crisis were to reach boiling point, the Trump administration would struggle to turn down the heat by credibly signaling restraint or limited aims. Moreover, amidst rising tensions, a weaker adversary would have little choice but to engage in worst-case-scenario planning, and a threatening tweet impulsively dispatched by the president could provoke a foreign leader to gamble on a first strike rather than risk U.S. preemption. Beyond contingencies that directly implicate the United States, Trump’s slippery reputation could also hinder his ability to arbitrate international disputes involving nuclear powers —– for example, if war were to break out between India and Pakistan. | 5,068 | <h4>Their Lissner ev doesn’t assume the cp, but it does say that Trump can’t deescalate <u>other threats</u> even without NFU – can’t solve</h4><p>Rebecca Friedman <strong>Lissner 17<u>. Stanton Nuclear Security Fellow at the Council on Foreign Relations. 5-23-2017. "The Risk of Nuclear Catastrophe Under Trump." War on the Rocks. https://warontherocks.com/2017/05/the-risk-of-nuclear-catastrophe-under-trump/</p><p></u></strong>Growing tension on the Korean Peninsula has returned the unimaginable terror of nuclear war to the American public consciousness. The danger is a global one: Nine states possess nearly 15,000 nuclear weapons and the detonation of even one of these weapons could cause humanitarian and economic catastrophe. Although the use of a nuclear weapon by a state or non-state actor is unlikely, it is not impossible, and the risk may be growing. Indeed, such a rare event can be evaluated in terms of a simple risk-assessment formula: probability multiplied by consequences. Given the enormous consequences of nuclear use, even small fluctuations in probability warrant attention. Some variation will arise from changes in the international environment, such as technological advances that make nuclear command and control systems more or less vulnerable to cyber-attack, or fluctuation in the level of tension between nuclear-armed rivals like India and Pakistan. But <u>as the world’s most powerful state</u>, with its own vast nuclear arsenal as well as a record of leadership in nonproliferation and nuclear security efforts, <u>the United States plays an important role in moderating —– or enhancing —– the <strong>likelihood of nuclear use. </u></strong>President Donald <u><mark>Trump’s comments</mark> during the campaign and transition <mark>prompt</mark>ed</u> widespread <u><strong><mark>concern</u></strong> <u>about his <strong>cavalier attitude</mark> toward</strong>, and <strong>lack of knowledge about</strong>, the world’s <strong>deadliest weapons</u></strong>. Since taking office, he has tempered his rhetoric somewhat —– but <u>more than 100 days into the Trump administration, there are early warning signs indicating the president’s <strong>policies</strong> could <strong>increase the risk</strong> of nuclear catastrophe</u>. Setting aside accidental launch or detonation, the most likely scenarios for the intentional or miscalculated use of a nuclear weapon are nuclear detonation by a state during crisis or wartime, and nuclear use by a non-state actor, such as a terrorist group. While <u>this president is</u> <u><strong>nothing if not unpredictable</u></strong>, it is both important and possible to sketch out how such a nuclear use might play out. The five risks described below are meant as a starting point for that discussion. Risk #1: Nuclear First-Use by the United States First, <u><mark>the president has</mark> the <strong><mark>sole authority to launch nuc</strong></mark>lear weapon<strong><mark>s</u></strong></mark> <u>through the “<strong>nuclear triad</strong>”</u> of land, sea, and air-launched systems. The horrific consequences, fear of retaliation, and extraordinary capabilities of U.S. conventional forces militate against nuclear use in all but the most extreme circumstances. Nonetheless, <u><mark>Trump’s</u> <u><strong>impulsive temperament</u></strong></mark>, <u>obsession with <strong>projecting strength</u></strong>, <u><mark>and</u> <u><strong>aversion to normative constraints</u></strong> <u>may make him</mark> <strong>more <mark>prone</strong></mark> <mark>to</u></mark> nuclear use than other recent presidents. Beyond these already-perceptible presidential proclivities, the Nuclear Posture Review —– which recently began under Pentagon leadership —– will elucidate the administration’s declaratory nuclear doctrine, providing the first concrete indication of scenarios in which the Trump administration would consider nuclear use. Risk #2: Inadvertent Nuclear Escalation Second, <u>the Trump administration’s penchant for <strong><mark>sending mixed signals</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>increases</mark> the risk of <strong><mark>misperception</u></strong></mark> in the event of a crisis or war involving another nuclear state. <u><mark>Trump is</mark> <strong>famously <mark>mercurial</strong></mark>, <strong>abruptly changing positions</u></strong> <u>on issues</u> ranging from NATO’s obsolescence to the desirability of nuclear proliferation. <u><mark>Rather than allowing</mark> the White House <strong>communications <mark>staff to clarify</mark> his positions</u></strong>, <u><mark>Trump</mark> often <strong><mark>contradicts</strong> them</mark>.</u> In December, for example, <u>when aides sought to soften Trump’s call for the United States to “strengthen and expand” its nuclear arsenal, Trump went on the record a second time to <strong>threaten an arms race</u></strong>. Moreover, <u>senior national security aides frequently stake out divergent policy positions – with the president’s apparent encouragement — as exhibited by the <strong>slew of incompatible explanations</u></strong> <u>for</u> Trump’s April decision to launch cruise missiles into <u><strong>Syria</u></strong>. <u><mark>The result is <strong>confusion</u></strong></mark> <u>surrounding whose statements represent administration <strong>policy</u></strong> <u>—– a <strong>whiplash effect</u></strong> most <u>recently on display in the back-and-forth on <strong>North Korea</strong>. Though the president seems to believe unpredictability creates bargaining leverage, it also <mark>prevents</mark> the administration from <strong><mark>credibly telegraphing</mark> its <mark>intent</strong></mark>ions. This dynamic</u> makes diplomacy difficult and <u>privileges potentially escalatory <strong>military displays</u></strong> <u>to demonstrate seriousness. <mark>If a crisis were to reach boiling</mark> point, the <mark>Trump</mark> administration <mark>would <strong>struggle to</mark> turn down the heat by <mark>credibly signal</strong></mark>ing <strong><mark>restraint</mark> or limited aims</u></strong>. Moreover, amidst rising tensions, <u><mark>a weak</mark>er <mark>adversary would</mark> have little choice but to <mark>engage in <strong>worst-case-scenario planning</strong></mark>, and <mark>a threatening <strong>tweet</u></strong></mark> impulsively dispatched by the president <u><mark>could <strong>provoke</mark> a foreign leader to gamble on a <mark>first strike</strong></mark> rather than <strong>risk U.S. preemption</u></strong>. Beyond contingencies that directly implicate the United States, <u><strong><mark>Trump’s slippery reputation could also hinder his ability to arbitrate international disputes involving nuclear powers —– for example, if war were to break out between India and Pakistan.</p></u></strong></mark> | 2NC | OLC | Recuttings | 796,447 | 123 | 98,732 | ./documents/ndtceda18/CalBerkeley/GrFl/Cal%20Berkeley-Gray-Fleming-Neg-GSU-Quarters.docx | 602,126 | N | GSU | Quarters | Kentucky BT | Kall Herndon Justice | 1NC - Midterms Prez Powers FAA OLC Hotlines CP
2NR - Midterms | ndtceda18/CalBerkeley/GrFl/Cal%20Berkeley-Gray-Fleming-Neg-GSU-Quarters.docx | null | 51,229 | GrFl | Cal Berkeley GrFl | null | Mi..... | Gr..... | Na..... | Fl..... | 19,169 | CalBerkeley | Cal Berkeley | null | null | 1,008 | ndtceda18 | NDT/CEDA 2018-19 | 2,018 | cx | college | 2 |
3,156,589 | Specifically, CPGS blunts adversaries’ ability to employ anti-access strategies---eliminating nuclear ICBMs is key to make it viable | Scheber 12 | Thomas Scheber 12, Vice President, National Institute for Public Policy, et al., June 2012, “Conventional Prompt Global Strike: A Fresh Perspective,” http://www.nipp.org/wp-content/uploads/2015/11/CPGS_REPORT-for-web.pdf | CPGS is intended to expand options available while reducing collateral damage In the past, the U S relied heavily on forward presence to to strike targets distant from U.S. shores complicating factors have emerged
expanding focus of adversaries on developing A2AD] capabilities degrades U.S. confidence in the ability to destroy critical targets in a timely manner by relying exclusively on the forward deployment of existing conventional weapons systems
current U.S. ability to strike quickly at targets half a world away is limited. Without costly prepositioning CPGS has been proposed to fill the gap in capabilities There appear to be multiple advantages to using long-range, prompt, conventional missiles including their precision guidance and targeting accuracy, positive command and control, and physical security. The biggest perceived disadvantage of current long-range ballistic missiles is these systems carry nuclear warheads STRATCOM) noted, “That’s not a good position We would like to have the capability to be able to go after a time-critical target in a very short amount of time with a conventional warhead | In the past, the U S relied on forward presence to strike targets complicating factors emerged
expanding focus of adversaries on A2AD degrades U.S. confidence in ability to destroy critical targets by relying on forward deployment
current U.S. ability to strike quickly is limited CPGS has been proposed to fill the gap advantages to long-range, prompt, conventional missiles precision guidance accuracy c and c The biggest perceived disad of current ballistic missiles is nuclear warheads STRATCOM) noted, “That’s not a good position | Militarily, development of a CPGS capability is intended to expand the range of options available to support the objectives of national military strategy while reducing the level of collateral damage that occurs through the exercise of military force. In the past, the United States has relied heavily—though not exclusively—on forward presence to extend deterrence and provide the ability to strike at targets distant from U.S. shores. While forward presence will continue to contribute to deterrence and the ability of the United States to defeat aggression abroad, two complicating factors have emerged in recent years:
• First, adversaries are becoming more adept at protecting those assets they consider most vital to their own security—including high-value targets like weapons of mass destruction (WMD)—from military attack, creating gaps in the ability of U.S. forces to strike promptly and effectively at such targets. Underground shelters, improved mobility, and other factors are placing a growing subset of targets beyond the reach of existing conventional military forces, potentially negating some of the traditional advantages of forward deployment.
• Second, the expanding focus of adversaries on developing their own antiaccess and area denial[A2AD] capabilities further degrades U.S. confidence in the ability to negate or destroy critical targets in a timely manner by relying exclusively on the forward deployment of existing conventional weapons systems.
Consequently, current U.S. ability to strike quickly at targets half a world away is limited. Without adequate, timely, and often costly prepositioning of sufficient military capabilities in a potential area of conflict that is capable of overcoming the challenges noted above, CPGS has been proposed to fill the gap in capabilities resulting from these trends. There appear to be multiple advantages to using long-range, prompt, conventional missiles in such a role, including their precision guidance and targeting accuracy, positive command and control, and physical security. The biggest perceived disadvantage of current long-range ballistic missiles is that these systems carry nuclear warheads. As General C. Robert Kehler, Commander of U.S. Strategic Command (USSTRATCOM) noted, “That’s not a good position to be in. We would like to have the capability to be able to go after a time-critical target in a very short amount of time with a conventional warhead.”6 | 2,445 | <h4>Specifically, CPGS blunts adversaries’ ability to employ anti-access strategies---eliminating <u>nuclear</u> ICBMs is key to make it <u>viable</u> </h4><p>Thomas <strong>Scheber 12</strong>, Vice President, National Institute for Public Policy, et al., June 2012, “Conventional Prompt Global Strike: A Fresh Perspective,” http://www.nipp.org/wp-content/uploads/2015/11/CPGS_REPORT-for-web.pdf</p><p>Militarily, development of a <u>CPGS</u> capability <u>is intended to expand</u> the range of <u>options available</u> to support the objectives of national military strategy <u>while reducing</u> the level of <u>collateral damage</u> that occurs through the exercise of military force. <u><strong><mark>In the past</strong>, the <strong>U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates has <u><mark>relied</mark> heavily</u>—though not exclusively—<u><mark>on forward presence</mark> to</u> extend deterrence and provide the ability <u><mark>to strike</u></mark> at <u><mark>targets</mark> distant from U.S. shores</u>. While forward presence will continue to contribute to deterrence and the ability of the United States to defeat aggression abroad, two <u><strong><mark>complicating factors</strong></mark> have <mark>emerged</u></mark> in recent years:</p><p>• First, adversaries are becoming more adept at protecting those assets they consider most vital to their own security—including high-value targets like weapons of mass destruction (WMD)—from military attack, creating gaps in the ability of U.S. forces to strike promptly and effectively at such targets. Underground shelters, improved mobility, and other factors are placing a growing subset of targets beyond the reach of existing conventional military forces, potentially negating some of the traditional advantages of forward deployment. </p><p>• Second, the <u><mark>expanding focus of adversaries on</mark> developing</u> their own antiaccess and area denial[<u><strong><mark>A2AD</mark>] capabilities</u></strong> further <u><mark>degrades U.S. confidence in</mark> the <mark>ability to</u></mark> negate or <u><mark>destroy critical targets</mark> in a timely manner <mark>by <strong>relying</mark> exclusively <mark>on</mark> the <mark>forward deployment</strong></mark> of existing conventional weapons systems</u>.</p><p>Consequently, <u><mark>current U.S. ability to strike quickly</mark> at targets half a world away <mark>is <strong>limited</strong></mark>. Without</u> adequate, timely, and often <u>costly prepositioning</u> of sufficient military capabilities in a potential area of conflict that is capable of overcoming the challenges noted above, <u><mark>CPGS has been proposed to fill the gap</mark> in capabilities</u> resulting from these trends. <u>There appear to be <strong>multiple <mark>advantages</strong> to</mark> using <mark>long-range, prompt, conventional missiles</u></mark> in such a role, <u>including their <mark>precision guidance</mark> and targeting <mark>accuracy</mark>, positive <strong><mark>c</strong></mark>ommand <mark>and <strong>c</strong></mark>ontrol, and physical security. <mark>The <strong>biggest perceived disad</mark>vantage</strong> <mark>of <strong>current</strong></mark> long-range <mark>ballistic missiles is</u></mark> that <u><strong>these systems carry <mark>nuclear warheads</u></strong></mark>. As General C. Robert Kehler, Commander of U.S. Strategic Command (US<u><mark>STRATCOM) noted, “<strong>That’s not a good position</u></strong></mark> to be in. <u>We would like to have the capability to be able to go after a time-critical target in a very short amount of time with a conventional warhead</u>.”6</p> | ***1AC*** | Send | 1AC | 373,893 | 100 | 102,526 | ./documents/ndtceda18/Northwestern/JaWe/Northwestern-Jankovsky-Weideman-Aff-Georgetown-Round2.docx | 607,435 | A | Georgetown | 2 | Michigan SV | Brandon Kelley | 1AC ICBMs
2NR Advantage cp and assurance da | ndtceda18/Northwestern/JaWe/Northwestern-Jankovsky-Weideman-Aff-Georgetown-Round2.docx | null | 51,521 | JaWe | Northwestern JaWe | null | Ga..... | Ja..... | Jo..... | We..... | 19,208 | Northwestern | Northwestern | null | null | 1,008 | ndtceda18 | NDT/CEDA 2018-19 | 2,018 | cx | college | 2 |
1,011,570 | Perm do both---refusal of queer critique to engage the state recreates neoliberal ideology by falsely staticizing the state as always violent---tactical engagement is better than pure rejection | Dhawan 15 | Nikita Dhawan 15, Professor of Political Science (Political Theory and Gender Studies) and Director of the Research Platform Gender Studies: "Identities – Discourses – Transformations" at the University of Innsbruck, Austria, Homonationalism and State-phobia: The Postcolonial Predicament of Queering Modernities, Academia.edu | state-phobia is deeply inscribed in liberal and neo-liberal ideas of civil society Puar In contrast they support civil society campaigns like pink-watching that increasingly deploy the strategy of surveillance for shaming states into good behavior. the rejection of all feminist- queer politics oriented towards the state as part of a biopolitical agenda is disingenuous state-phobic rhetoric.
Postcolonial-queer-feminists are caught in an ambivalent, double-bind vis-à-vis the state: On the one hand, the state has historically been the source of violence and repression And yet, queer strategies seek to instru- mentalize the state to promote sexual justice. Even as the state is known to perpetuate heteronormative ideologies, which are founding myths of nations, the hope is that the state can function as a site of redress Despite the problematic track-record with regard to sexual politics of all nation-states it is dangerous to disregard the immense political implications of state-phobic positions, increasingly popular in radical discourses
This is not a plea for statism; rather, one must be aware of the dangers of the replacement of state with non-state actors as motors of justice the recent anti-statist stance within postcolonial queer scholarship is alarming, as it ignores the importance of the state for those citizens who do not have access to transnational counterpublic spheres to address their grievances
Decolonization, whether in USA, Israel or India, cannot be achieved merely through a strategy of shaming the state. Rather it is imperative to enable vulnerable disenfranchised indi- viduals and groups to access the state Accordingly, instead of a for or against position vis-à-vis the state, the more challenging question is how to reconfigure the state, given that its institutions and policies are the mobile effect of a regime of multiple governmentalities the chal- lenge is how to pursue a non-statephobic queer politics that at the same time neither rationalizes the biopolitical state nor makes the queer bodies governable. In postcolonial contexts, the state is like a pharmakon both poison and medicine. Postcolonial queer politics must explore strategies of converting poison into counterpoison ).
the ambivalent function of the state must be addressed the inherent condradictions must be engaged with: Violence and justice, ideology and emancipation, law and discipline. If, the state has no stable essence, then it is marked by undecidability or doubleness. The sole focus on the negative aspects of the Pharmakon, namely the destructive and repressive traits, neutralizes and ignores the enabling and empowering aspects postcolonial-queer-feminist poli- tics must transform poison into remedy and formulate critique of the state beyond state-phobia. A challenging task, but anything else would be too risky! | state-phobia is inscribed in neo-liberal civil society
Even as the state perpetuate heteronormative ideologies, which are founding myths of nations, the state can function as a site of redress Despite the problematic track-record it is dangerous to disregard the political implications of state-phobic positions,
This is not a plea for statism;
Decolonization cannot be achieved merely through shaming the state instead of a for or against position the question is how to reconfigure the state, the chal- lenge is pursue a non-statephobic queer politics that neither rationalizes the biopolitical state nor makes queer bodies governable the state is like a pharmakon both poison and medicine queer politics must explore converting poison into counterpoison
the condradictions must be engaged with the state has no stable essence it is marked by undecidability The sole focus on the negative aspects neutralizes the enabling and empowering aspects | As Foucault himself warns state-phobia is deeply inscribed in liberal and neo-liberal ideas of civil society. The wickedness of the state is juxta- posed against the inherent goodness of civil society, so that the aim is the ‘whithering away of the state’. This anti-state-centric approach to political power, locates radical politics in extra-state space of innovation. This is why Puar and others reject pragmatic politics of same-sex marriage or anti-discrimination legislations. In contrast they support civil society campaigns like pink-watching that increasingly deploy the strategy of surveillance for shaming states into good behavior. Even as one critiques the harnessing of gender and sexuality by neo-liberal capitalism, the rejection of all feminist- queer politics oriented towards the state as part of a biopolitical agenda is disingenuous state-phobic rhetoric.
Postcolonial-queer-feminists are caught in an ambivalent, double-bind vis-à-vis the state: On the one hand, the state has historically been the source of violence and repression through the criminalization and pathologization of non-normative sexual practices. And yet, queer strategies seek to instru- mentalize the state to promote sexual justice. Even as the state is known to perpetuate heteronormative ideologies, which are founding myths of nations, the hope is that the state can function as a site of redress of gender and sexual inequality. Despite the problematic track-record with regard to sexual politics of all nation-states, whether European or non-European, it is dangerous to disregard the immense political implications of state-phobic positions, which are increasingly popular in radical discourses in the West.
As the recent re-criminalization of homosexuality in Uganda, India and Nigeria demonstrate, negotiations with state are indispensable and imperative for emancipatory queer politics in the global South. This is not a plea for statism; rather, one must be aware of the dangers of the replacement of state with non-state actors as motors of justice. Against this background, the recent anti-statist stance within postcolonial queer scholarship is alarming, as it ignores the importance of the state for those citizens who do not have access to transnational counterpublic spheres to address their grievances.
Decolonization, whether in USA, Israel or India, cannot be achieved merely through a strategy of shaming the state. Rather in the Gramscian- Spivakian sense, it is imperative to enable vulnerable disenfranchised indi- viduals and groups to access the state (Dhawan ). Accordingly, instead of a for or against position vis-à-vis the state, the more challenging question is how to reconfigure the state, given that its institutions and policies are the mobile effect of a regime of multiple governmentalities. Thus the chal- lenge is how to pursue a non-statephobic queer politics that at the same time neither rationalizes the biopolitical state project nor makes the queer bodies governable. In postcolonial contexts, the state is like a pharmakon , namely, both poison and medicine. Postcolonial queer politics must explore strategies of converting poison into counterpoison (Spivak : ).
Herein the ambivalent function of the state must be addressed. As Pharmakon, the inherent condradictions must be engaged with: Violence and justice, ideology and emancipation, law and discipline. If, following Foucault, the state has no stable essence, then it is marked by undecidability or doubleness. The sole focus on the negative aspects of the Pharmakon, namely the destructive and repressive traits, neutralizes and ignores the enabling and empowering aspects. Thus postcolonial-queer-feminist poli- tics must transform poison into remedy and formulate critique of the state beyond state-phobia. A challenging task, but anything else would be too risky! | 3,872 | <h4>Perm do both---refusal of queer critique to engage the state recreates neoliberal ideology by falsely staticizing the state as always violent---tactical engagement is better than pure rejection </h4><p>Nikita <strong>Dhawan 15</strong>, Professor of Political Science (Political Theory and Gender Studies) and Director of the Research Platform Gender Studies: "Identities – Discourses – Transformations" at the University of Innsbruck, Austria, Homonationalism and State-phobia: The Postcolonial Predicament of Queering Modernities, Academia.edu </p><p>As Foucault himself warns <u><mark>state-phobia is</mark> deeply <mark>inscribed in</mark> liberal and <mark>neo-liberal </mark>ideas of <mark>civil society</u></mark>. The wickedness of the state is juxta- posed against the inherent goodness of civil society, so that the aim is the ‘whithering away of the state’. This anti-state-centric approach to political power, locates radical politics in extra-state space of innovation. This is why <u>Puar</u> and others reject pragmatic politics of same-sex marriage or anti-discrimination legislations. <u>In contrast they support civil society campaigns like pink-watching that increasingly deploy the strategy of surveillance for shaming states into good behavior.</u> Even as one critiques the harnessing of gender and sexuality by neo-liberal capitalism, <u>the rejection of all feminist- queer politics oriented towards the state as part of a biopolitical agenda is disingenuous state-phobic rhetoric.</p><p>Postcolonial-queer-feminists are caught in an ambivalent, double-bind vis-à-vis the state: On the one hand, the state has historically been the source of violence and repression</u> through the criminalization and pathologization of non-normative sexual practices. <u>And yet, queer strategies seek to instru- mentalize the state to promote sexual justice. <mark>Even as the state </mark>is known to <mark>perpetuate heteronormative ideologies, which are <strong>founding myths of nations,</u></strong> <u></mark>the hope is that <mark>the state can function as a <strong>site of redress</u></strong></mark> of gender and sexual inequality. <u><mark>Despite the problematic track-record</mark> with regard to sexual politics of all nation-states</u>, whether European or non-European, <u><mark>it is <strong>dangerous to disregard the </mark>immense <mark>political implications of state-phobic positions,</mark> </u></strong>which are <u>increasingly popular in radical discourses</u> in the West.</p><p>As the recent re-criminalization of homosexuality in Uganda, India and Nigeria demonstrate, negotiations with state are indispensable and imperative for emancipatory queer politics in the global South. <u><mark>This is not a plea for statism;</mark> rather, one must be aware of the dangers of the replacement of state with non-state actors as motors of justice</u>. Against this background, <u>the recent anti-statist stance within postcolonial queer scholarship is alarming, as it ignores the importance of the state for those citizens who do not have access to transnational counterpublic spheres to address their grievances</u>. </p><p><u><mark>Decolonization</mark>, whether in USA, Israel or India<strong>, <mark>cannot be achieved</u></strong> <u>merely through</mark> a strategy of <strong><mark>shaming the state</mark>.</u></strong> <u>Rather</u> in the Gramscian- Spivakian sense, <u>it is imperative to enable vulnerable disenfranchised indi- viduals and groups to <strong>access the state</u></strong> (Dhawan ). <u>Accordingly, <strong><mark>instead of a for or against position</mark> vis-à-vis the state,</u></strong> <u><mark>the </mark>more challenging <mark>question is</u> <u><strong>how to reconfigure the state,</u></strong></mark> <u>given that its institutions and policies are the</u> <u><strong>mobile effect of a regime of multiple governmentalities</u></strong>. Thus <u><mark>the chal- lenge is</mark> how to <mark>pursue a <strong>non-statephobic queer politics</u></strong> <u>that</mark> at the same time</u> <u><strong><mark>neither rationalizes the biopolitical state</u></strong></mark> project <u><strong><mark>nor makes </mark>the <mark>queer bodies governable</strong></mark>. In postcolonial contexts, <mark>the state is like a pharmakon</u></mark> , namely, <u><mark>both poison and medicine</mark>. Postcolonial <mark>queer politics must explore</mark> strategies of <mark>converting poison into counterpoison</u></mark> (Spivak : <u>).</p><p></u>Herein <u>the ambivalent function of the state must be addressed</u>. As Pharmakon, <u><mark>the</mark> inherent <mark>condradictions must be engaged with</mark>: Violence and justice, ideology and emancipation, law and discipline. If,</u> following Foucault, <u><mark>the state has no stable essence</mark>, then <mark>it is marked by undecidability</mark> or doubleness. <mark>The sole focus on the negative aspects</mark> of the Pharmakon, namely the destructive and repressive traits, <strong><mark>neutralizes</mark> and ignores <mark>the enabling and empowering aspects</u></strong></mark>. Thus <u>postcolonial-queer-feminist poli- tics must transform poison into remedy and formulate critique of the state <strong>beyond state-phobia</strong>. A challenging task, but <strong>anything else would be too risky</strong>!</p></u> | 2AC Round 4 Minnesota | K | Perm | 66,647 | 201 | 24,347 | ./documents/ndtceda21/Navy/RoKo/Navy-Rock-Korlacki-Aff-Minnesota-Round4.docx | 626,600 | A | Minnesota | 4 | Western Washington HK | Natalie Bennie | 1AC - Pharma
1NC - Trans Rage | ndtceda21/Navy/RoKo/Navy-Rock-Korlacki-Aff-Minnesota-Round4.docx | null | 52,836 | RoKo | Navy RoKo | null | Ka..... | Ro..... | An..... | Ko..... | 19,404 | Navy | Navy | null | null | 1,011 | ndtceda21 | NDT/CEDA 2021-22 | 2,021 | cx | college | 2 |
2,371,746 | Aff solves – helps the economy, ensures employment, and beats UBI benefits. | Smith 18 | Smith 18 Yves Smith, 4-28-2018, "The Federal Job Guarantee Is Not Just "Better" Than a Universal Basic Income. It's the Only Reasonable Option. Universal Basic Income Is Sinister," naked capitalism, https://www.nakedcapitalism.com/2018/04/federal-job-guarantee-not-just-better-universal-basic-income-reasonable-option-universal-basic-income-sinister.html SJCP//JG | The Federal Job Guarantee is not just better than Universal Basic Income, it’s the only good option. UBI adds money to the economy without increasing production or output. This is how you cause inflation: The creation of money without consideration of the real resources available to you This incentivizes private industry to further reduce wages, which logically extends to the reduction – or elimination – of minimum wage laws. Then what’s the point of social safety net programs such as welfare, food stamps, subsidized housing, Medicaid, Social Security, etc.? These programs would necessarily be eliminated. Competing with everyone for the same stuff, with no increase in productive capacity. UBI is therefore, by its very definition, inflationary FJG adds money to the economy by increasing productivity and output. This is how you avoid, or greatly reduce the severity of, inflation. It forces private industry and the military to up their game, in order to be competitive with the FJG: better than bare-minimum living wage, benefits, and working conditions. | F J G better than U B I UBI cause inflation reduce wages extends to reduction or elimination minimum wage laws what’s point of welfare subsidized housing Medicaid necessarily be eliminated FJG adds money to the economy increasing productivity and output greatly reduce the severity of inflation | UBI destroys economy – overinflation
UBI harms human rights – safety net programs eliminated
FJG boosts economy and ensures jobs
FJG > UBI No. That’s not right. The Federal Job Guarantee is not just better than Universal Basic Income, it’s the only good option. The UBI is a Trojan Horse for the reduction and elimination of wages and safety net programs for the powerless. UBI is sinister. Universal Basic Income: UBI adds money to the economy without increasing production or output. This is how you cause inflation: The creation of money without consideration of the real resources available to you. (Sure, everyone can have a pony, but not tomorrow!) If the government is now paying your salary, even if you are performing poorly, even if you are not working: This incentivizes private industry to further reduce wages, which logically extends to the reduction – or elimination – of minimum wage laws. Then what’s the point of social safety net programs such as welfare, food stamps, subsidized housing, Medicaid, Social Security, etc.? These programs would necessarily be eliminated. Then what’s the point of fighting so hard for free healthcare and free tuition and lower prescription drug costs and so on? Now people can, at least somewhat, at least temporarily, afford the private industry alternatives. The fights for these progressive programs would just…end. Now, all of the sudden, everyone can afford shit. All at the same time. Competing with everyone for the same stuff, with no increase in productive capacity. UBI is therefore, by its very definition, inflationary. This governmental salary, this “negative tax” for those at the bottom, is instantly devalued. At best, income and wealth inequality is not reduced. Would this increase or decrease the incentive to get or keep a job? At least at first… Here’s the true sinister plot behind UBI: Picture a future and less-friendly Congress, after all these safety nets have been reduced or eliminated. They come in and eliminate or dramatically reduce the UBI program because “these deadbeats want everything for free?!” Our nation is instantly plunged into a private corporation slave-wage hellscape. No wage or workplace protections, no safety net programs at all. UBI risks putting the United States into a much much worse position than it already is today…. Well, that is, if you care about the powerless. The Federal Job Guarantee: INCLUDEPICTURE "https://s.w.org/images/core/emoji/13.0.0/svg/1f44c.svg" \* MERGEFORMATINET FJG adds money to the economy by increasing productivity and output. This is how you avoid, or greatly reduce the severity of, inflation. It forces private industry and the military to up their game, in order to be competitive with the FJG: better than bare-minimum living wage, benefits, and working conditions. It takes away the excuse of “I’m not hiring you… You’ve been unemployed. Ewww.” If a future, less-friendly Congress were to come in and eliminate or reduce the FJG program, then those FJG job people would indeed once again be unemployed. But everyone else would still have those better jobs with better wages, benefits, and working conditions. Yes, without the “public option” FJG to compete with private industry, these things will start to degrade. But we would revert back to a position still substantially better than we are today. | 3,342 | <h4>Aff solves – helps the economy, ensures employment, and beats UBI benefits.</h4><p><strong>Smith 18</strong> Yves Smith, 4-28-2018, "The Federal Job Guarantee Is Not Just "Better" Than a Universal Basic Income. It's the Only Reasonable Option. Universal Basic Income Is Sinister," naked capitalism, https://www.nakedcapitalism.com/2018/04/federal-job-guarantee-not-just-better-universal-basic-income-reasonable-option-universal-basic-income-sinister.html SJCP//JG</p><p>UBI destroys economy – overinflation</p><p>UBI harms human rights – safety net programs eliminated</p><p>FJG boosts economy and ensures jobs</p><p>FJG > UBI No. That’s not right. <u><strong>The <mark>F</mark>ederal <mark>J</mark>ob <mark>G</mark>uarantee is not just <mark>better than</mark> <mark>U</mark>niversal <mark>B</mark>asic <mark>I</mark>ncome, it’s the only good option.</u></strong> The UBI is a Trojan Horse for the reduction and elimination of wages and safety net programs for the powerless. UBI is sinister. Universal Basic Income: <u><strong><mark>UBI</mark> adds money to the economy without increasing production or output. This is how you <mark>cause inflation</mark>: The creation of money without consideration of the real resources available to you</u></strong>. (Sure, everyone can have a pony, but not tomorrow!) If the government is now paying your salary, even if you are performing poorly, even if you are not working: <u><strong>This incentivizes private industry to further <mark>reduce wages</mark>, which logically <mark>extends to </mark>the <mark>reduction</mark> – <mark>or elimination</mark> – of <mark>minimum wage laws</mark>. Then <mark>what’s</mark> the <mark>point</mark> <mark>of</mark> social safety net programs such as <mark>welfare</mark>, food stamps, <mark>subsidized housing</mark>, <mark>Medicaid</mark>, Social Security, etc.? These programs would <mark>necessarily be eliminated</mark>. </u></strong>Then what’s the point of fighting so hard for free healthcare and free tuition and lower prescription drug costs and so on? Now people can, at least somewhat, at least temporarily, afford the private industry alternatives. The fights for these progressive programs would just…end. Now, all of the sudden, everyone can afford shit. All at the same time. <u><strong>Competing with everyone for the same stuff, with no increase in productive capacity. UBI is therefore, by its very definition, inflationary</u></strong>. This governmental salary, this “negative tax” for those at the bottom, is instantly devalued. At best, income and wealth inequality is not reduced. Would this increase or decrease the incentive to get or keep a job? At least at first… Here’s the true sinister plot behind UBI: Picture a future and less-friendly Congress, after all these safety nets have been reduced or eliminated. They come in and eliminate or dramatically reduce the UBI program because “these deadbeats want everything for free?!” Our nation is instantly plunged into a private corporation slave-wage hellscape. No wage or workplace protections, no safety net programs at all. UBI risks putting the United States into a much much worse position than it already is today…. Well, that is, if you care about the powerless. The Federal Job Guarantee: INCLUDEPICTURE "https://s.w.org/images/core/emoji/13.0.0/svg/1f44c.svg" \* MERGEFORMATINET <u><strong><mark>FJG adds money to the economy</mark> by <mark>increasing productivity and output</mark>. This is how you avoid, or <mark>greatly reduce the severity of</mark>, <mark>inflation</mark>. It forces private industry and the military to up their game, in order to be competitive with the FJG: better than bare-minimum living wage, benefits, and working conditions.</u></strong> It takes away the excuse of “I’m not hiring you… You’ve been unemployed. Ewww.” If a future, less-friendly Congress were to come in and eliminate or reduce the FJG program, then those FJG job people would indeed once again be unemployed. But everyone else would still have those better jobs with better wages, benefits, and working conditions. Yes, without the “public option” FJG to compete with private industry, these things will start to degrade. But we would revert back to a position still substantially better than we are today.</p> | Blue Key RR R3 – 1AC v St Michael CS | Advantage 2: Automation | null | 354,551 | 103 | 75,653 | ./documents/hsld20/StrakeJesuit/Xi/Strake%20Jesuit-Xie-Aff-Florida%20Blue%20Key%20RR-Round3.docx | 874,942 | A | Florida Blue Key RR | 3 | St Michael Albertville CS | Amanda Ciocca, Olivia Stoneman | 1ac - stock
1nc - transgender body ptx youth shelther pic disability accomodations cp cap k aff
1ar - pics bad cps without solvency advocate bad aff offs
2nr - transgender body ptx 1ar theory
2ar - cps without solvency advocate bad | hsld20/StrakeJesuit/Xi/Strake%20Jesuit-Xie-Aff-Florida%20Blue%20Key%20RR-Round3.docx | null | 73,805 | JaXi | Strake Jesuit JaXi | null | Ja..... | Xi..... | null | null | 24,736 | StrakeJesuit | Strake Jesuit | TX | null | 1,028 | hsld20 | HS LD 2020-21 | 2,020 | ld | hs | 1 |
2,302,985 | Second is hard power collapse—US military spending high now but Chinese LAW development is the largest threat to overturn American hard power dominance—they view war as inevitable and will try to win the arms race at all costs. | Brock 17 | [John Brock (4-13-2017), Major in the US Army, MS in Advance Military Studies from the US Army Command and General Staff College, "Why the United States Must Adopt Lethal Autonomous Weapon Systems," United States Army, https://apps.dtic.mil/dtic/tr/fulltext/u2/1038884.pdf]//CHS PK | United States military spending dwarfs the rest of the world. one-third of the world and more than the next 14 countries combined. the United States’ technological superiority continues to shrink countries such as China are using artificial intelligence and robotics modernization strategies to level the military playing field at a fraction of the cost Though Russia will probably not achieve this automation goal, China has also prioritized the development of Lethal Autonomous Weapon Systems. China views Lethal Autonomous Weapon Systems differently than the United States. China wants a military capable of winning future wars against the United States. Chinese General Chi Haitian asserts "War with the United States is inevitable; we cannot avoid it.” China will use ‘unrestricted warfare’ with no rules, no boundaries, and no moral concerns in the use of Lethal Autonomous Weapon Systems China believes that the United States’ current technological advantage will become nonexistent this belief stems from the US military's “ultimate concern” of protecting innocent civilian lives and the environment China concludes that the consequences of the United States’ technology shortsightedness will result in the US military being forced to fight yesterday’s war with outdated technologies China examines all emerging and novel technologies to determine how they could be used to develop new weapon systems. They seek new technologies that could be a prelude to a revolution in military affairs giving them an advantage over the United States biological human constraints will no longer remain relevant with the development of Lethal Autonomous Weapon Systems. Future lethal autonomous armies will be capable of fighting continuously, at tremendous speeds, and require no breaks or rest. | U S military spending dwarfs the rest of the world tech superiority continues to shrink China are using a i modernization level the field Russia will not achieve this goal China prioritized development of L A W S China views L A W S differently than the U S China asserts War with the U S is inevitable China will use ‘unrestricted warfare’ with no moral concerns in the use of L A W S this stems from US concern of protecting innocent lives the consequences will result in the US being forced to fight yesterday’s war with outdated tech China seek a revolution biological human constraints will no longer remain relevant | Currently, United States military spending dwarfs the rest of the world. The United States spends over one-third of the world's military budget and more than the next 14 countries combined. Regardless, the US military is still the smallest since the Interwar Period and will continue to shrink as soldier costs grow. While the United States’ military spending continues to remain high, its technological superiority continues to shrink. The United States’ rising personnel costs are not giving an improved capability, but instead are reducing funding available for the research and development of new technologies. In contrast, countries such as Russia and China are using artificial intelligence and robotics modernization strategies to level the military playing field at a fraction of the cost. Russia’s modernization strategy prioritizes the adoption of autonomous weapon systems and artificial intelligence. Russia has committed to developing a technologically superior robotic military force capable of fighting in the 21st century. Russia’s Chief of the Generals Staff stated, “In the near future, it is possible that a complete robotic unit will be capable of independently conducting military operations.”107 Demonstrating this belief, Russia announced plans to deploy armed autonomous sentry robots to protect five strategic missile installations.108 These sentry robots will use artificial intelligence to make decisions on their own and require no human operators. Russia recognizes that artificial intelligence and robots are resulting in a third military revolution and fundamentally changing warfare. Russia’s modernization strategy is now moving away from crewed vehicles and is transitioning to fully autonomous vehicles. Their defense industry plans to release an autonomous T14 tank prototype within the next two years.109 To accelerate these changes, Russia’s Army Chief of Staff announced that they plan to robotize onethird of their military by the year 2020.110 Though Russia will probably not achieve this automation goal, it signals Russia's vision of modern warfare and how future wars will likely be won.111 China has also prioritized the development of Lethal Autonomous Weapon Systems. The US Deputy Secretary of Defense, Bob Work recognizes that China views Lethal Autonomous Weapon Systems differently than the United States. Work stated “We know that China is already investing heavily in robotics and autonomy.”112 China has invested in artificial intelligence because it wants a military capable of winning future wars against the United States. Chinese General Chi Haitian asserts "War with the United States is inevitable; we cannot avoid it.”113 To win this war, China will use ‘unrestricted warfare’ with no rules, no boundaries, and no moral concerns in the use of Lethal Autonomous Weapon Systems. The People’s Liberation Army insists “War is still the ground of death and life, the path of survival and destruction and even the slightest innocence is not tolerated.”114 China believes that the United States’ current technological advantage will become nonexistent as time goes on. The primary reason for this belief stems from the US military's “ultimate concern” of protecting innocent civilian lives and the environment. These concerns result in the United States continually developing weapons to become "kinder" not "stronger." China also contends that the United States only considers the short-term uses of new technology and fails to adopt novel technologies into future weapon systems. China concludes that the consequences of the United States’ technology shortsightedness will result in the US military being forced to fight yesterday’s war with outdated technologies. In contrast, China examines all emerging and novel technologies to determine how they could be used to develop new weapon systems. They seek new technologies that could be a prelude to a revolution in military affairs giving them an advantage over the United States. China believes yesterday's "high technology" likely represents today's "low technology," while today's "new technology" will turn into tomorrow's "old technology."115Throughout history, there are numerous examples of militaries refusing to acknowledge that a new technology had completely transformed war. Jean De Bloch, a Polish banker and railway financier, authored Is War Now Impossible? in 1898. In his book, Bloch argued that advancements in weapons technology during the industrial revolution made previous Napoleonic open warfare impossible. Bloch concluded that for armies to survive in the 20th century, they must resort to trench warfare. Bloch was an outspoken voice who predicted the carnage that would occur in Europe during World War I. He anticipated the change in the operational environment, but could not convince the world’s leaders that the current methods of warfare were no longer feasible.116 As a result of this failure to adapt, 17 million soldiers and civilians died during World War I.117 Innumerable lives could have been saved if leaders had been quicker to accept the new realities in warfare. Johnson & Johnson CEO Alex Gorsky summarized it best: “You must understand when the environment you are in changes, because you must change also, and if you don’t, you will die.”118 During World War I, the ‘cult of the bayonet' dominated military thinking for the way to fight wars. The European ‘cult of the bayonet’ represents one of history’s prime examples illustrating the flawed belief that a soldier with enough determination will always prevail regardless of warfare’s technological advancements. The European military professionals believed a passionate soldier wielding a bayonet had proven an undefeatable terror weapon during the wars of the 18th and 19th -century.119 However, by the 20th century, the development of machine guns, artillery fire, and poison gas had rendered bayonets only useful for chopping wood, opening tin cans, and hanging up clothing.120 During World War I, senior officers refused to accept that these new technologies made mass infantry bayonet charges irrelevant. Officers with no comprehension of the fundamental changes in warfare continued to send their soldiers on heroic charges, only to die in the thousands.121 The Battle of the Somme illustrates this point where British commanders foolishly ordered a bayonet charge at the machine gun defended German lines, resulting in 60,000 casualties.122 The French operated on a similar tactical doctrine believing infantry morale was superior to firepower. This misconception resulted in over 500,000 French casualties in August 1914.123 Following World War I, even with these staggering European casualties, some US officers still argued that spirited bayonet-wielding soldiers and horses should remain the US military’s decisive capability.124 During World War II, the Japanese believed the human aspect of their Bushido warrior culture could defeat the United States’ superior military technology and firepower. The successful Japanese use of ‘banzai’ bayonet charges against the numerically superior Chinese reinforced these beliefs of the ‘invincible’ Japanese human spirit. Tragically, similar to World War I, these spirited attacks resulted in horrific losses for the Japanese army, which could not overcome the superior American technology and firepower.125 During the Battle of Guadalcanal, the Japanese conducted banzai charges towards the American lines protecting Henderson Field. These charges resulted in the horrific losses of Japanese soldiers. Japan’s Admiral Raizo Tanaka commented "This tragedy should have taught us the hopelessness of ‘bamboo spear’ tactics."126 These historical examples should serve as a dire warning to the United States. Similar to Jean de Bloch’s World War I predictions, a third military revolution will render modern warfare no longer feasible without tremendous United States’ casualties. General Patton once asserted “Many, who should know better, think that wars can be decided by soulless machines, rather than by the blood and anguish of brave men.”127 However, the US military’s people, institutions, and culture are no longer enough to overcome the technological advantages provided by Lethal Autonomous Weapon Systems. The United States must acknowledge that warfare’s environment has changed and begin to adapt. The United States’ Third Offset Strategy currently doubles down on Patton’s military of the past. Over the past 5,000 years of war, the tempo of warfare has grown with the development of new technologies. Soldiers transitioned from walking, to riding horses, to riding in rail cars, to driving in trucks, to flying in aircraft. The speed with which wars are now won or lost depends directly on these new technologies.128 During the 1870-1871 Franco-Prussian War, Prussian Prince Otto von Bismarck required over nine months to force the French surrender.129 In contrast, during World War II, Adolf Hitler only needed forty-six days to force the French capitulation.130 Current technology already allows militaries to fight wars across vast distances, during the nighttime, in adverse weather, and in extreme temperatures. The only limiting factor to increasing the speed of future warfare are the human soldiers fighting it. Due to biology, people require rest and can only maintain a high tempo for short periods of time. These biological human constraints will no longer remain relevant with the development of Lethal Autonomous Weapon Systems. Future lethal autonomous armies will be capable of fighting continuously, at tremendous speeds, and require no breaks or rest. | 9,639 | <h4>Second is hard power collapse—US military spending high now but Chinese LAW development is the <u>largest threat</u> to overturn American hard power dominance—they view war as inevitable and will try to win the arms race <u>at all costs</u>.</h4><p>[John <u><strong>Brock</u></strong> (4-13-20<u><strong>17</u></strong>), Major in the US Army, MS in Advance Military Studies from the US Army Command and General Staff College, "Why the United States Must Adopt Lethal Autonomous Weapon Systems," United States Army, https://apps.dtic.mil/dtic/tr/fulltext/u2/1038884.pdf]//CHS PK</p><p>Currently, <u><strong><mark>U</mark>nited <mark>S</mark>tates <mark>military spending dwarfs the rest of the world</mark>.</u></strong> The United States spends over <u><strong>one-third of the world</u></strong>'s military budget <u><strong>and more than the next 14 countries combined.</u></strong> Regardless, the US military is still the smallest since the Interwar Period and will continue to shrink as soldier costs grow. While <u><strong>the United States’</u></strong> military spending continues to remain high, its <u><strong><mark>tech</mark>nological <mark>superiority continues to shrink</u></strong></mark>. The United States’ rising personnel costs are not giving an improved capability, but instead are reducing funding available for the research and development of new technologies. In contrast, <u><strong>countries such as</u></strong> Russia and <u><strong><mark>China are using a</mark>rtificial <mark>i</mark>ntelligence and robotics <mark>modernization</mark> strategies to <mark>level the</mark> military playing <mark>field</mark> at a fraction of the cost</u></strong>. Russia’s modernization strategy prioritizes the adoption of autonomous weapon systems and artificial intelligence. Russia has committed to developing a technologically superior robotic military force capable of fighting in the 21st century. Russia’s Chief of the Generals Staff stated, “In the near future, it is possible that a complete robotic unit will be capable of independently conducting military operations.”107 Demonstrating this belief, Russia announced plans to deploy armed autonomous sentry robots to protect five strategic missile installations.108 These sentry robots will use artificial intelligence to make decisions on their own and require no human operators. Russia recognizes that artificial intelligence and robots are resulting in a third military revolution and fundamentally changing warfare. Russia’s modernization strategy is now moving away from crewed vehicles and is transitioning to fully autonomous vehicles. Their defense industry plans to release an autonomous T14 tank prototype within the next two years.109 To accelerate these changes, Russia’s Army Chief of Staff announced that they plan to robotize onethird of their military by the year 2020.110 <u><strong>Though <mark>Russia will</mark> probably <mark>not achieve this</mark> automation <mark>goal</mark>,</u></strong> it signals Russia's vision of modern warfare and how future wars will likely be won.111 <u><strong><mark>China</mark> has also <mark>prioritized</mark> the <mark>development of L</mark>ethal <mark>A</mark>utonomous <mark>W</mark>eapon <mark>S</mark>ystems.</u></strong> The US Deputy Secretary of Defense, Bob Work recognizes that <u><strong><mark>China views L</mark>ethal <mark>A</mark>utonomous <mark>W</mark>eapon <mark>S</mark>ystems <mark>differently than the U</mark>nited <mark>S</mark>tates.</u></strong> Work stated “We know that China is already investing heavily in robotics and autonomy.”112 <u><strong><mark>China</u></strong></mark> has invested in artificial intelligence because it <u><strong>wants a military capable of winning future wars against the United States. Chinese General Chi Haitian <mark>asserts</mark> "<mark>War with</mark> <mark>the U</mark>nited <mark>S</mark>tates <mark>is inevitable</mark>; we cannot avoid it.”</u></strong>113 To win this war, <u><strong><mark>China will use ‘unrestricted warfare’ with</mark> no rules, no boundaries, and <mark>no moral concerns in the use of L</mark>ethal <mark>A</mark>utonomous <mark>W</mark>eapon <mark>S</mark>ystems</u></strong>. The People’s Liberation Army insists “War is still the ground of death and life, the path of survival and destruction and even the slightest innocence is not tolerated.”114 <u><strong>China believes that the United States’ current technological advantage will become nonexistent</u></strong> as time goes on. The primary reason for <u><strong><mark>this</mark> belief <mark>stems from</mark> the <mark>US</mark> military's “ultimate <mark>concern</mark>” <mark>of protecting innocent</mark> civilian <mark>lives</mark> and the environment</u></strong>. These concerns result in the United States continually developing weapons to become "kinder" not "stronger." China also contends that the United States only considers the short-term uses of new technology and fails to adopt novel technologies into future weapon systems. <u><strong>China concludes that <mark>the consequences </mark>of the United States’ technology shortsightedness <mark>will result in the US</mark> military <mark>being forced to fight yesterday’s war with outdated tech</mark>nologies</u></strong>. In contrast, <u><strong><mark>China</mark> examines all emerging and novel technologies to determine how they could be used to develop new weapon systems. They <mark>seek</mark> new technologies that could be a prelude to <mark>a revolution</mark> in military affairs giving them an advantage over the United States</u></strong>. China believes yesterday's "high technology" likely represents today's "low technology," while today's "new technology" will turn into tomorrow's "old technology."115Throughout history, there are numerous examples of militaries refusing to acknowledge that a new technology had completely transformed war. Jean De Bloch, a Polish banker and railway financier, authored Is War Now Impossible? in 1898. In his book, Bloch argued that advancements in weapons technology during the industrial revolution made previous Napoleonic open warfare impossible. Bloch concluded that for armies to survive in the 20th century, they must resort to trench warfare. Bloch was an outspoken voice who predicted the carnage that would occur in Europe during World War I. He anticipated the change in the operational environment, but could not convince the world’s leaders that the current methods of warfare were no longer feasible.116 As a result of this failure to adapt, 17 million soldiers and civilians died during World War I.117 Innumerable lives could have been saved if leaders had been quicker to accept the new realities in warfare. Johnson & Johnson CEO Alex Gorsky summarized it best: “You must understand when the environment you are in changes, because you must change also, and if you don’t, you will die.”118 During World War I, the ‘cult of the bayonet' dominated military thinking for the way to fight wars. The European ‘cult of the bayonet’ represents one of history’s prime examples illustrating the flawed belief that a soldier with enough determination will always prevail regardless of warfare’s technological advancements. The European military professionals believed a passionate soldier wielding a bayonet had proven an undefeatable terror weapon during the wars of the 18th and 19th -century.119 However, by the 20th century, the development of machine guns, artillery fire, and poison gas had rendered bayonets only useful for chopping wood, opening tin cans, and hanging up clothing.120 During World War I, senior officers refused to accept that these new technologies made mass infantry bayonet charges irrelevant. Officers with no comprehension of the fundamental changes in warfare continued to send their soldiers on heroic charges, only to die in the thousands.121 The Battle of the Somme illustrates this point where British commanders foolishly ordered a bayonet charge at the machine gun defended German lines, resulting in 60,000 casualties.122 The French operated on a similar tactical doctrine believing infantry morale was superior to firepower. This misconception resulted in over 500,000 French casualties in August 1914.123 Following World War I, even with these staggering European casualties, some US officers still argued that spirited bayonet-wielding soldiers and horses should remain the US military’s decisive capability.124 During World War II, the Japanese believed the human aspect of their Bushido warrior culture could defeat the United States’ superior military technology and firepower. The successful Japanese use of ‘banzai’ bayonet charges against the numerically superior Chinese reinforced these beliefs of the ‘invincible’ Japanese human spirit. Tragically, similar to World War I, these spirited attacks resulted in horrific losses for the Japanese army, which could not overcome the superior American technology and firepower.125 During the Battle of Guadalcanal, the Japanese conducted banzai charges towards the American lines protecting Henderson Field. These charges resulted in the horrific losses of Japanese soldiers. Japan’s Admiral Raizo Tanaka commented "This tragedy should have taught us the hopelessness of ‘bamboo spear’ tactics."126 These historical examples should serve as a dire warning to the United States. Similar to Jean de Bloch’s World War I predictions, a third military revolution will render modern warfare no longer feasible without tremendous United States’ casualties. General Patton once asserted “Many, who should know better, think that wars can be decided by soulless machines, rather than by the blood and anguish of brave men.”127 However, the US military’s people, institutions, and culture are no longer enough to overcome the technological advantages provided by Lethal Autonomous Weapon Systems. The United States must acknowledge that warfare’s environment has changed and begin to adapt. The United States’ Third Offset Strategy currently doubles down on Patton’s military of the past. Over the past 5,000 years of war, the tempo of warfare has grown with the development of new technologies. Soldiers transitioned from walking, to riding horses, to riding in rail cars, to driving in trucks, to flying in aircraft. The speed with which wars are now won or lost depends directly on these new technologies.128 During the 1870-1871 Franco-Prussian War, Prussian Prince Otto von Bismarck required over nine months to force the French surrender.129 In contrast, during World War II, Adolf Hitler only needed forty-six days to force the French capitulation.130 Current technology already allows militaries to fight wars across vast distances, during the nighttime, in adverse weather, and in extreme temperatures. The only limiting factor to increasing the speed of future warfare are the human soldiers fighting it. Due to biology, people require rest and can only maintain a high tempo for short periods of time. These <u><strong><mark>biological human constraints will no longer remain relevant</mark> with the development of Lethal Autonomous Weapon Systems</strong>. Future lethal autonomous armies will be capable of fighting continuously, at tremendous speeds, and require no breaks or rest.</p></u> | null | null | 1AC—Militaristic Dominance | 20,641 | 152 | 72,560 | ./documents/hsld20/Oxford/Me/Oxford-Mehta-Aff-Harvard%20Westlake-Round2.docx | 869,987 | A | Harvard Westlake | 2 | Greenhill KD | Devane Murphy | 1AC - China
1NC - Afropessimism K
1AR - All
2NR - Afropessimism K
2AR - Same | hsld20/Oxford/Me/Oxford-Mehta-Aff-Harvard%20Westlake-Round2.docx | null | 73,609 | ViMe | Oxford ViMe | null | Vi..... | Me..... | null | null | 24,667 | Oxford | Oxford | CA | null | 1,028 | hsld20 | HS LD 2020-21 | 2,020 | ld | hs | 1 |
1,834,602 | FISA abuses are spurring both external backlash by Congress, Courts, and the FISC, AND excessive internal restraint by prosecutors, FBI, and DOJ—decimating broader intel-gathering | Pletka et al. 20 | Pletka et al. 20, Marc Thiessen is a resident fellow at the American Enterprise Institute (AEI) where he studies and writes about American presidential leadership and counterterrorism; Danielle Pletka is a senior fellow in foreign and defense policy studies at the American Enterprise Institute (AEI), where she focuses on US foreign policy generally and the Middle East specifically; John Yoo is a Professor of Law at the University of California, Berkeley, and a visiting scholar at AEI, served as a deputy assistant attorney general in the Office of the Legal Counsel of the US Department of Justice, as General Counsel of the US Senate Committee on the Judiciary, and as a law clerk to Justice Clarence Thomas, “WTH is going on with the Foreign Intelligence Surveillance Act? John Yoo discusses the future of the FISA Court,” American Enterprise Institute, WTH podcast, Episode #35, 3/11/20, https://www.aei.org/wp-content/uploads/2020/03/3.11.20-John-Yoo-transcript.pdf
Danielle Pletka: Well, and, right, and we know that because we've read James Comey's book and, yeah. But what I'm wondering about is why should Marc Thiessen be worried about this? Why should average Joe Blow be worried about this? Why is the reform of the FISA Court something that is so important to average Americans, not just to the President and his vendetta against the FBI for the Russia investigation? | the thing that worries me is that this one misuse of FISA to surveil Trump's campaign could energize that side of the debate that wants to get rid of FISA altogether. You commonly hear people like Senator Paul and people like that who want to just get rid of FISA. Want to try to get rid of surveillance of terrorists and have it all just considered crime. The problem is that to protect the country's security from foreign attack, you need something like FISA. Although by my druthers I would just have it rather go back to the President's ordering it and then they are taking responsibility for it.
with FISA you are surveilling people, targets, a status. Sometimes you're not even following specific known people that you can name, which is another thing you need for a criminal warrant. You need an actual person's name and their conduct. With FISA you can try to surveil places, organizations, people you think might be potential terrorists, but you're not investigating them because they've already done something criminal. That's the main thing.
FISA, like signals intelligence in the military is designed to surveil people and events for what they might do in the future. Criminal warrants, the things that are outside FISA, you are surveilling people because they already did things in the past They already took some criminal activity. They've already taken steps to conspire. With FISA you're not trying to catch people for crimes that have already happened. You're trying to stop people from launching future attacks on the country. It's going to be probabilities and risks and less defined.
But you still need to be able to do it, so I worry that we're going to overreact to what happened with Trump and narrow FISA surveillance so much that it puts us back into the box we were in before 9/11 where the government and the FBI, Justice Department and the FISA Court were afraid to use FISA properly. That's one of the few things I can look at that would have stopped the 9/11 attacks.
every four years or so ... there have been these big fights to try to narrow FISA significantly this next go-around is going to be an opportunity
John Yoo: One of the main fights has been over a different program I worked on, which is what's called the Terrorist Surveillance Program. That was done outside of FISA initially and then it was brought into FISA. This is the idea, can you try to intercept streams of communications coming in from abroad by email, phone call? You know within, say, a certain stream of emails, say, right after 9/11, the government just said, "We're going to try to intercept all emails coming from Afghanistan into the United States. We're going to try to sift through it to try to detect patterns of communication that look like they're from terrorists." But you don't know any specific phone number or email address is actually Osama bin Laden's email address, so you're just searching through this huge hay stack for the needles.
what's at stake, is in this new age of communications for the FISA statute in the courts to allow that kind of surveillance to continue. Because that's the most important kind of electronic surveillance that the government can undertake to stop future terrorist attacks.
But the fight about Trump and Carter Page and the Steele Dossier might provide people the political grounds to get rid of this other program
Or get rid of the FISA Court entirely
Trump is always accused of doing untold damage to our democratic institutions But in this case, it's his foes who did enormous damage to our institutions Judge Collyer the FISA judge said in her letter to the Justice Department that this abuse calls into question whether the information contained in other FISA applications is reliable. The result will be that the court will now be much more skeptical of the presentations that the Justice Department makes to the court not just on this but in terrorist cases and everything else It could slow down in a case where we're trying to capture a terrorist or stop a terrorist attack on our country. That could be deadly
Then second, it gives ammunition to the critics of the existence of the FISA Court and the whole FISA process to try and undermine it
In the short-term what you could see is not necessarily a collapse, but a level of distrust and then a reduction in the effectiveness of FISA.
what if the courts, the judges just say, "We're not going to do this anymore." the judges could just say, "Find somebody else to issue your window dressing That's also something that could end up happening. That's what this order from the FISA Court might foreshadow. You need the cooperation of the judges to make this work. They don't have to cooperate if they don't want to. They could say, "We think all this is unconstitutional. | one misuse of FISA could energize the debate to get rid of FISA altogether and have it just considered crime to protect security you need FISA
FISA surveil places, organizations potential terrorists
Criminal warrants surveil people because they already did things FISA stop future attacks
we're going to overreact to Trump so much it puts us back to where the FBI, Justice and FIS C were afraid to use FISA properly That would have stopped 9/11
what's at stake, is the most important kind of surveillance to stop attacks
But Page provide political grounds to get rid of this program
the court will now be much more skeptical of the Justice Department in terrorist cases and everything else. It could slow a case That could be deadly
you could see distrust and reduction in effectiveness
what if judges say We're not going to do this anymore You need the judges to make this work They could say, "We think all this is unconstitutional | John Yoo: It's a good question, Dany, because the thing that worries me is that this one misuse of FISA to surveil Trump's campaign could, I think, energize that side of the debate that wants to get rid of FISA altogether. You commonly hear people like Senator Rand Paul and people like that who want to just get rid of FISA. Want to try to get rid of surveillance of terrorists altogether and have it all just considered crime. The problem is that, I think, to protect the country's security from foreign attack, you need to have something like FISA. Although by my druthers I would just have it rather go back to the President's ordering it and then they are taking responsibility for it.
John Yoo: Let me give you an example. Again, with FISA you are surveilling people, targets, a status. Sometimes you're not even following specific known people that you can name, which is another thing you need for a criminal warrant. You need an actual person's name and their conduct. With FISA you can try to surveil places, organizations, people you think might be potential terrorists, but you're not investigating them because they've already done something criminal. That's the main thing.
John Yoo: FISA, like signals intelligence in the military is not designed to surveil people and events for what they might do in the future. Criminal warrants, the things that are outside FISA, you are surveilling people because they already did things in the past. They already took some criminal activity. They've already taken steps to conspire. With FISA you're not trying to catch people for crimes that have already happened. You're trying to stop people from launching future attacks on the country. It's going to be probabilities and risks and less defined.
John Yoo: But you still need to be able to do it, so I worry that we're going to overreact to what happened with Trump and narrow FISA surveillance so much that it puts us back into the box we were in before 9/11 where the government and the FBI, Justice Department and the FISA Court were afraid to use FISA properly. That's one of the few things I can look at that would have stopped the 9/11 attacks.
Danielle Pletka: Just to contextualize this for folks, so FISA, the original Foreign Intelligence Surveillance Act is passed in the '70s. It is then amended by the Patriot Act after 9/11 to broaden it. Those changes expired at the end of last year and they were extended just until March of this year. What are the changes? What's the debate that's going on here?
John Yoo: It's interesting. As you say, the Patriot Act Amendments have a sunset provision on them that require their periodic renewal. I think in the last two renewals ... It's roughly about every four years or so ... there have been these big fights actually to try to narrow FISA significantly. I think, Dany, you're suggesting what I think will happen is that this next go-around is going to be an opportunity for people to try to narrow FISA.
John Yoo: One of the main fights has been over a different program I worked on, which is what's called the Terrorist Surveillance Program. That was done outside of FISA initially and then it was brought into FISA. This is the idea, can you try to intercept streams of communications coming in from abroad by email, phone call? You know within, say, a certain stream of emails, say, right after 9/11, the government just said, "We're going to try to intercept all emails coming from Afghanistan into the United States. We're going to try to sift through it to try to detect patterns of communication that look like they're from terrorists." But you don't know any specific phone number or email address is actually Osama bin Laden's email address, so you're just searching through this huge hay stack for the needles.
John Yoo: Initially that wasn't done under FISA because you couldn't get a warrant because you had no particular target in mind. You couldn't name a specific person. You couldn't name a specific phone number or email address. One of the things that the Patriot Act Amendments did in their periodic renewals is to bring that whole program under FISA and the FISA judges authorize it. That's what people have been fighting about. It's not really part of the things we've been talking about with Trump and Carter Page and so on. But that's, I think, really what's at stake, is in this new age of communications for the FISA statute in the courts to allow that kind of surveillance to continue. Because that's, I think, maybe the most important kind of electronic surveillance that the government can undertake to stop future terrorist attacks.
John Yoo: But the whole fight about Trump and Carter Page and the Steele Dossier, that might provide people the political grounds to try to get rid of this other program, which they've been trying to get at for about eight, 10 years now.
Marc Thiessen: Or just get rid of the FISA Court entirely, which some have proposed.
John Yoo: Yeah, look. The way it was before Nixon, and maybe Nixon was a one-time only or a rare case. But before Nixon, what would happen is that presidents would order its use. But you couldn't really use it in court to prosecute anybody. The point was you would gather this intelligence. The President would order it under his own authority, and you would use it to try to stop a direct and immediate attack on the country or stop a dire threat to the national security. If it had to become public, if it had to be used in court, then the President would have to take personal responsibility for it. He could appoint ... If you think about the FISA Court, it's a great responsibility shifting mechanism. Look at what's going on now. Everyone can say, "Oh, it was the FBI. It was those FISA judges," and so it's not really President Obama and Loretta Lynch, the Attorney General under President Obama. Or, Eric Holder, the previous Attorney General, who's responsible. The FISA Court just defuses responsibility by shifting the blame to the bureaucracy and the courts.
Marc Thiessen: If the FISA Court didn't exist, Barack Obama would have to order the surveillance?
John Yoo: Right. He would have had to order the surveillance himself personally and then, and his National Security Advisor Susan Rice and the Attorney General, they would be responsible for it. I mean, imagine what Trump would make of that.
Marc Thiessen: Yep.
John Yoo: Right? But that's how it used to work.
Marc Thiessen: Here's the thing. President Trump is always accused of doing untold damage to our democratic institutions. Right? But in this case, it's his foes who did enormous damage to our institutions. I mean, first of all, Judge Collyer, the FISA judge, said in her letter to the Justice Department that this abuse calls into question whether the information contained in other FISA applications is reliable. The result will be that the court will now be much more skeptical of the presentations that the Justice Department makes to the court not just on this but in terrorist cases and everything else. It could slow down in a case where we're trying to capture a terrorist or stop a terrorist attack on our country. That could be deadly.
Marc Thiessen: Then second, it gives ammunition to the critics of the existence of the FISA Court and the whole FISA process to try and undermine it. It seems to me like they've done a lot more damage to our institutions through this whole process than Trump ever did.
John Yoo: It might have a good long-term effect if you look at the longer constitutional picture. What happened is we give a lot of power to these bureaucracies. You can look at Comey as a good example of this. FISA and maybe what's happened with Ukraine and the National Security Council, you saw the civil service sort of rise up against Trump. It's very interesting. What Trump, you could say, is trying to do is re-exert democratic control over these bureaucracies, and they are trying to stop him. When you talked about impeachment, you hear talk about the interagency process. That's just bureaucracy versus Trump. I don't agree with his foreign policy, but he was elected to carry out this foreign policy. You see this struggle, and this is yet another example of it.
John Yoo: You're right. In the short-term what you could see is not necessarily a collapse, but a level of distrust and then a reduction in the effectiveness of FISA. But maybe that might prompt us to rely less on these bureaucracies and put more democratic control over all of this policymaking that's been going on. Sometimes it seems to run on autopilot.
John Yoo: You definitely can see in the attitude of Comey and certainly the attitude of the FISA bureaucracy that they know best how to protect the national security and the selections with politicians and the dirty politics was beneath them and even something they had to observe. But then there's this question, who guards the guardians? It’s certainly the question here. In the longer term you worry that these bureaucracies are gaining so much power in the national security area that it's not ultimately responsible to anyone who's elected.
Danielle Pletka: I think you make a good point. For a lot of us the notion that a court exists and that a process exists and that law enforcement has to, in fact, prove things to that court is actually reassuring. Because when you think about a person like Donald Trump having sole authority over such warrants, you can only imagine what Donald Trump would do. I mean, at least I could only imagine what Donald Trump could do. It could be everybody. It could be anybody. It could be Bernie. It could be anybody he doesn't like. It could Wolf Blitzer at CNN. You never know what is passing through the President's mind, and he has certainly proved himself enormously, let's say, grandiose in his interpretation of his own authority.
Danielle Pletka: On the other hand, as you say, who's watching the watchers? That is really, really frightening. The FISA Court has attempted, and the FBI through it, to destroy the lives of two people who worked on the Trump campaign. I don't give a damn whether people don't like them. They weren't Russian agents. This is what we need to weigh in the balance. Is there any better third way? Is there some way of doing this that doesn't empower the deep state and doesn't empower capricious people like Donald Trump or even Susan Rice who used her authorities unbelievable unadvisedly when she was National Security Advisor?
John Yoo: That's a good point. One other possibility that could occur we haven’t even discussed this, what if the courts, the judges just say, "We're not going to do this anymore." No matter what FISA laws we pass, no matter what amendments are added, the judges could just say, "Find somebody else to issue your window dressing after the fact. The legitimization of all this stuff you're doing." That's also something that could end up happening. That's also what this order from the FISA Court might foreshadow. You need the cooperation of the judges to make this work. They don't have to cooperate if they don't want to. They could say, "We think all this is unconstitutional. If you want to go back and do surveillance, you and the President and Congress figure it out." | 11,257 | <h4>FISA abuses are spurring both <u>external backlash</u> by Congress, Courts, and the FISC, AND excessive <u>internal restraint</u> by <u>prosecutors</u>, <u>FBI</u>, and <u>DOJ</u>—decimating <u>broader</u> intel-gathering</h4><p><strong>Pletka et al. 20</strong>, Marc Thiessen is a resident fellow at the American Enterprise Institute (AEI) where he studies and writes about American presidential leadership and counterterrorism; Danielle Pletka is a senior fellow in foreign and defense policy studies at the American Enterprise Institute (AEI), where she focuses on US foreign policy generally and the Middle East specifically; John Yoo is a Professor of Law at the University of California, Berkeley, and a visiting scholar at AEI, served as a deputy assistant attorney general in the Office of the Legal Counsel of the US Department of Justice, as General Counsel of the US Senate Committee on the Judiciary, and as a law clerk to Justice Clarence Thomas, “WTH is going on with the Foreign Intelligence Surveillance Act? John Yoo discusses the future of the FISA Court,” American Enterprise Institute, WTH podcast, Episode #35, 3/11/20, https://www.aei.org/wp-content/uploads/2020/03/3.11.20-John-Yoo-transcript.pdf</p><p>Danielle Pletka: Well, and, right, and we know that because we've read James Comey's book and, yeah. But what I'm wondering about is why should Marc Thiessen be worried about this? Why should average Joe Blow be worried about this? <u>Why is the reform of the FISA Court something that is <strong>so important to average Americans</u></strong>, not just to the President and his vendetta against the FBI for the Russia investigation?</p><p>John Yoo: It's a good question, Dany, because <u>the thing that <strong>worries me</u></strong> <u>is that this <strong><mark>one misuse</u></strong> <u>of FISA</mark> to surveil Trump's campaign <mark>could</u></mark>, I think, <u><strong><mark>energize</mark> that side of <mark>the debate</u></strong></mark> <u>that wants <mark>to <strong>get rid of FISA altogether</strong></mark>. You commonly hear people like</u> <u><strong>Senator</u></strong> Rand <u><strong>Paul</u></strong> <u>and people like that who want to just <strong>get rid of FISA</strong>. Want to try to <strong>get rid of surveillance of terrorists</u></strong> altogether <u><mark>and have it</mark> all <mark>just considered <strong>crime</strong></mark>. The problem is that</u>, I think, <u><mark>to protect</mark> the country's <strong><mark>security</mark> from foreign attack</strong>, <mark>you <strong>need</u></strong></mark> to have <u><strong>something like <mark>FISA</strong></mark>. Although by my druthers I would just have it rather go back to the President's ordering it and then they are taking responsibility for it.</p><p></u>John Yoo: Let me give you an example. Again, <u>with FISA you are surveilling <strong>people, targets, a status</strong>. Sometimes you're not even following specific known people that you can <strong>name</strong>, which is another thing you need for a <strong>criminal</strong> warrant. You need an actual person's name and their conduct. With <mark>FISA</mark> you can try to <mark>surveil <strong>places</strong>, <strong>organizations</strong></mark>, people you think might be <strong><mark>potential</strong> terrorists</mark>, but you're not investigating them because they've <strong>already</u></strong> <u>done something criminal. That's the main thing.</p><p></u>John Yoo: <u>FISA, like signals intelligence in the military is</u> not <u>designed to surveil people and events for what they might do in the <strong>future</strong>. <strong><mark>Criminal</u></strong> <u>warrants</mark>, the things that are outside FISA, you are <strong><mark>surveil</strong></mark>ling <strong><mark>people</strong> because they <strong>already</strong> did things</mark> in the <strong>past</u></strong>. <u>They <strong>already</strong> took some criminal activity. They've already taken steps to conspire. With <mark>FISA</mark> you're not trying to catch people for crimes that have already happened. You're trying to <strong><mark>stop</mark> people from launching <mark>future attacks</mark> on the country</strong>. It's going to be <strong>probabilities</strong> and risks and less defined.</p><p></u>John Yoo: <u>But you <strong>still need to be able to do it</strong>, so I worry that <mark>we're going to <strong>overreact</strong> to</mark> what happened with <mark>Trump</mark> and narrow FISA surveillance <mark>so much</mark> that <mark>it puts us <strong>back</strong></mark> in<strong><mark>to</u></strong></mark> <u>the box we were in before 9/11</u> <u><mark>where</mark> the government and <mark>the <strong>FBI</strong>, <strong>Justice</mark> Department</strong> <mark>and</mark> the <strong><mark>FIS</strong></mark>A <strong><mark>C</strong></mark>ourt <mark>were</u> <u><strong>afraid to use FISA properly</strong></mark>. <strong><mark>That</strong></mark>'s one of the few things I can look at that <strong><mark>would have stopped</mark> the <mark>9/11</mark> attacks</strong>.</p><p></u>Danielle Pletka: Just to contextualize this for folks, so FISA, the original Foreign Intelligence Surveillance Act is passed in the '70s. It is then amended by the Patriot Act after 9/11 to broaden it. Those changes expired at the end of last year and they were extended just until March of this year. What are the changes? What's the debate that's going on here?</p><p>John Yoo: It's interesting. As you say, the Patriot Act Amendments have a sunset provision on them that require their periodic renewal. I think in the last two renewals ... It's roughly about <u>every four years or so ... there have been these</u> <u><strong>big fights</u></strong> actually <u>to try to <strong>narrow FISA significantly</u></strong>. I think, Dany, you're suggesting what I think will happen is that <u>this</u> <u><strong>next go-around</u></strong> <u>is going to be an <strong>opportunity</u></strong> for people to try to narrow FISA.</p><p><u>John Yoo: One of the main fights has been over a different program I worked on, which is what's called the Terrorist Surveillance Program. That was done outside of FISA initially and then it was brought into FISA. This is the idea, can you try to intercept streams of communications coming in from abroad by email, phone call? You know within, say, a certain stream of emails, say, right after 9/11, the government just said, "We're going to try to intercept all emails coming from Afghanistan into the United States. We're going to try to sift through it to try to detect patterns of communication that look like they're from terrorists." But you don't know any specific phone number or email address is actually Osama bin Laden's email address, so you're just searching through this huge hay stack for the needles.</p><p></u>John Yoo: Initially that wasn't done under FISA because you couldn't get a warrant because you had no particular target in mind. You couldn't name a specific person. You couldn't name a specific phone number or email address. One of the things that the Patriot Act Amendments did in their periodic renewals is to bring that whole program under FISA and the FISA judges authorize it. That's what people have been fighting about. It's not really part of the things we've been talking about with Trump and Carter Page and so on. But that's, I think, really <u><mark>what's at stake, is</mark> in this new age of communications for the FISA statute in the courts to allow that kind of surveillance to continue. Because that's</u>, I think, maybe <u><mark>the</u> <u><strong>most important kind of</mark> electronic <mark>surveillance</u></strong></mark> <u>that the government can undertake <mark>to stop</mark> future terrorist <mark>attacks</mark>.</p><p></u>John Yoo: <u><mark>But</mark> the</u> whole <u><strong>fight</u></strong> <u>about Trump and Carter <strong><mark>Page</strong></mark> and the Steele Dossier</u>, that <u>might <mark>provide</mark> people the <strong><mark>political grounds to</u></strong></mark> try to <u><strong><mark>get rid of this</mark> other <mark>program</u></strong></mark>, which they've been trying to get at for about eight, 10 years now.</p><p>Marc Thiessen: <u>Or</u> just <u><strong>get rid of the FISA Court entirely</u></strong>, which some have proposed.</p><p>John Yoo: Yeah, look. The way it was before Nixon, and maybe Nixon was a one-time only or a rare case. But before Nixon, what would happen is that presidents would order its use. But you couldn't really use it in court to prosecute anybody. The point was you would gather this intelligence. The President would order it under his own authority, and you would use it to try to stop a direct and immediate attack on the country or stop a dire threat to the national security. If it had to become public, if it had to be used in court, then the President would have to take personal responsibility for it. He could appoint ... If you think about the FISA Court, it's a great responsibility shifting mechanism. Look at what's going on now. Everyone can say, "Oh, it was the FBI. It was those FISA judges," and so it's not really President Obama and Loretta Lynch, the Attorney General under President Obama. Or, Eric Holder, the previous Attorney General, who's responsible. The FISA Court just defuses responsibility by shifting the blame to the bureaucracy and the courts.</p><p>Marc Thiessen: If the FISA Court didn't exist, Barack Obama would have to order the surveillance?</p><p>John Yoo: Right. He would have had to order the surveillance himself personally and then, and his National Security Advisor Susan Rice and the Attorney General, they would be responsible for it. I mean, imagine what Trump would make of that.</p><p>Marc Thiessen: Yep.</p><p>John Yoo: Right? But that's how it used to work.</p><p>Marc Thiessen: Here's the thing. President <u>Trump is always <strong>accused</strong> of doing untold damage to our democratic institutions</u>. Right? <u>But in this case, it's his <strong>foes</strong> who did enormous damage to our institutions</u>. I mean, first of all, <u>Judge</u> <u><strong>Collyer</u></strong>, <u>the <strong>FISA judge</u></strong>, <u>said in her letter to the Justice Department that this abuse calls into question whether the information contained in <strong>other FISA applications</strong> is reliable. The result will be that <mark>the <strong>court</u></strong> <u>will now be <strong>much more skeptical of the</mark> presentations that the <mark>Justice Department</mark> makes to the court</u></strong> <u>not just on this but <mark>in <strong>terrorist cases</strong> and <strong>everything else</u></strong>. <u>It could <strong>slow</mark> down</strong> in <mark>a case</mark> where we're trying to capture a terrorist or stop a terrorist attack on our country. <mark>That could be <strong>deadly</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>Marc Thiessen: <u>Then</u> <u><strong>second</strong>, it gives <strong>ammunition</u></strong> <u>to the critics of the existence of the FISA Court and the whole FISA process to try and <strong>undermine it</u></strong>. It seems to me like they've done a lot more damage to our institutions through this whole process than Trump ever did. </p><p>John Yoo: It might have a good long-term effect if you look at the longer constitutional picture. What happened is we give a lot of power to these bureaucracies. You can look at Comey as a good example of this. FISA and maybe what's happened with Ukraine and the National Security Council, you saw the civil service sort of rise up against Trump. It's very interesting. What Trump, you could say, is trying to do is re-exert democratic control over these bureaucracies, and they are trying to stop him. When you talked about impeachment, you hear talk about the interagency process. That's just bureaucracy versus Trump. I don't agree with his foreign policy, but he was elected to carry out this foreign policy. You see this struggle, and this is yet another example of it.</p><p>John Yoo: You're right. <u>In the <strong>short-term</u></strong> <u>what <mark>you could see</mark> is not necessarily a collapse, but a level of <strong><mark>distrust</strong> and</mark> then a <strong><mark>reduction in</mark> the <mark>effectiveness</mark> of FISA.</u></strong> But maybe that might prompt us to rely less on these bureaucracies and put more democratic control over all of this policymaking that's been going on. Sometimes it seems to run on autopilot.</p><p>John Yoo: You definitely can see in the attitude of Comey and certainly the attitude of the FISA bureaucracy that they know best how to protect the national security and the selections with politicians and the dirty politics was beneath them and even something they had to observe. But then there's this question, who guards the guardians? It’s certainly the question here. In the longer term you worry that these bureaucracies are gaining so much power in the national security area that it's not ultimately responsible to anyone who's elected.</p><p>Danielle Pletka: I think you make a good point. For a lot of us the notion that a court exists and that a process exists and that law enforcement has to, in fact, prove things to that court is actually reassuring. Because when you think about a person like Donald Trump having sole authority over such warrants, you can only imagine what Donald Trump would do. I mean, at least I could only imagine what Donald Trump could do. It could be everybody. It could be anybody. It could be Bernie. It could be anybody he doesn't like. It could Wolf Blitzer at CNN. You never know what is passing through the President's mind, and he has certainly proved himself enormously, let's say, grandiose in his interpretation of his own authority.</p><p>Danielle Pletka: On the other hand, as you say, who's watching the watchers? That is really, really frightening. The FISA Court has attempted, and the FBI through it, to destroy the lives of two people who worked on the Trump campaign. I don't give a damn whether people don't like them. They weren't Russian agents. This is what we need to weigh in the balance. Is there any better third way? Is there some way of doing this that doesn't empower the deep state and doesn't empower capricious people like Donald Trump or even Susan Rice who used her authorities unbelievable unadvisedly when she was National Security Advisor?</p><p>John Yoo: That's a good point. One other possibility that could occur we haven’t even discussed this, <u><mark>what if</mark> the courts, the <mark>judges</mark> just <mark>say</mark>, "<strong><mark>We're not going to do this anymore</mark>."</u></strong> No matter what FISA laws we pass, no matter what amendments are added, <u>the judges <strong>could</u></strong> <u>just say, "<strong>Find somebody else to issue your window dressing</u></strong> after the fact. The legitimization of all this stuff you're doing." <u>That's also something that could end up happening. That's</u> also <u>what this <strong>order from the FISA Court might foreshadow</strong>. <mark>You <strong>need the</mark> cooperation of the <mark>judges to make this work</strong></mark>. They don't have to cooperate if they don't want to. <mark>They could say, "We think <strong>all this is unconstitutional</strong></mark>.</u> If you want to go back and do surveillance, you and the President and Congress figure it out." </p> | null | null | 1AC—Intel-Gathering | 52,720 | 222 | 53,756 | ./documents/hspolicy20/AmericanHeritageSchoolPlantation/RaGu/American%20Heritage%20School%20Plantation-Randazzo-Gupta-Aff-NSDA%20Nationals-Round1.docx | 724,171 | A | NSDA Nationals | 1 | 102 | Brenden Lucas and Matthew Parnell | 1ac- FISA
1nc- judiciary CP executive CP MORE DA infrastructure DA tons of case defense
2ac- responses
2nc- responses more case defense CPs
1ar- responses condo
1nr- responses infrastructure
2nr- responses
2ar- responses | hspolicy20/AmericanHeritageSchoolPlantation/RaGu/American%20Heritage%20School%20Plantation-Randazzo-Gupta-Aff-NSDA%20Nationals-Round1.docx | null | 61,809 | RaGu | American Heritage School Plantation RaGu | null | Ni..... | Ra..... | Pr..... | Gu..... | 21,500 | AmericanHeritageSchoolPlantation | American Heritage School Plantation | FL | null | 1,019 | hspolicy20 | HS Policy 2020-21 | 2,020 | cx | hs | 2 |
1,608,050 | Representations and epistemology perpetuate settler practices – the way we understand and discuss the structures around us overdetermines our praxis. The 1AC is an epistemological interrogation and re-orientation that challenges hegemonic norms. | Seawright 14 | Seawright 14 Gardner Seawright is a doctoral candidate in the Education, Culture, and Society department at the University of Utah. “Settler Traditions of Place: Making Explicit the Epistemological Legacy of White Supremacy and Settler Colonialism for Place-Based Education.” EDUCATIONAL STUDIES, 50: 554–572, 2014, American Educational Studies Association. JJN | Settler traditions of place are an epistemic genealogy—the ethics, logics, and ideologies foundational to a knowledge system that have been passed down across generations, a knowledge framework that establishes what is known how things come to be known how the world is to be interpreted according to what is known and how the self is known in relation to perceived reality Tradition is used allowing for domination to be empha- sized as an on-going historical process, while also allowing as tradition to simultaneously be evolutionary and a cherished cultural artifact. settler traditions of place are transmitted across generations through discipline, teaching, modeling and other forms of direct and subtle so- cial communication resulting in normalized habits, beliefs, values, and practices. there are “epistemic and moral limitations” embedded in traditions—these normalized habits—that perpetuate hierarchized notions of the world that privi- lege white-hetero-landowning males these subtle discourses manifest as taken-for-granted cultural assumptions that are rooted in racism, sexism, classism that intertwine with and reflect the cultivation of violent relationships with the more-than-human world and natural systems that we depend on for life epistemology can im- pact every aspect of life while remaining removed from a deterministic position. Embedded in discourse, tradition appears as ever-present; despite this, individual social actors have the agency to break tradition. When an individual epistemically transgresses, they employ an epistemic praxis that goes against the grain and is counter to the tradition that defines the social environment. this break in tradition is absolutely desirable and can inspire epistemic friction. Epistemic friction is contained in those uncomfortable moments in which our taken-for-granted assumptions about the world begin to crack. These moments can be transformative and cat- alyze critical consciousness to imagine and hopefully actualize an alternative epistemology. | Settler traditions of place are an epistemic genealogy ethics, logics ideologies a framework that establishes how the world is to be interpreted Tradition allow for domination as an on-going historical process settler traditions of place transmitted through teaching and normalize practices epistemic limitations in traditions perpetuate hierarchized world discourses manifest as cultural assumptions individual actors have the agency to break tradition epistemic transgress praxis that goes against the grain this break can inspire epistemic friction those uncomfortable moments assumptions begin to crack cat- alyze critical consciousness | Situating Settler Traditions Settler traditions of place are an epistemic genealogy—the ethics, logics, and ideologies foundational to a knowledge system that have been passed down across generations, a knowledge framework that establishes what is known (the socially constructed commonsense of a culture), how things come to be known (the process of attaining new knowledge), how the world is to be interpreted according to what is known (the social construction of reality), and how the self is known in relation to perceived reality (the politics of self). Tradition is used as a conceptual tool allowing for domination to be empha- sized as an on-going historical process, while also allowing for epistemology as tradition to simultaneously be evolutionary and a cherished cultural artifact. As a cultural product, settler traditions of place are transmitted across generations through discipline, teaching, modeling and other forms of direct and subtle so- cial communication resulting in normalized habits, beliefs, values, and practices. In speaking about “western cultural traditions,” Val Plumood (2002) argues that there are “epistemic and moral limitations” embedded in these traditions—these normalized habits—that perpetuate hierarchized notions of the world that privi- lege white-hetero-landowning males (99). As Martusewicz et al. (2011) explain, these subtle discourses manifest as taken-for-granted cultural assumptions that are rooted in racism, sexism, classism that intertwine with and reflect the cultivation of violent relationships with the more-than-human world and natural systems that we depend on for life (119). The tradition in question here is the social air that penetrates the Western world, interacting with human beings whether they want it to or not. Using tradition as a metaphor for epistemology allows me to emphasize the way epistemology can im- pact every aspect of life while remaining removed from a deterministic position. Embedded in discourse, tradition appears as ever-present; despite this, individual social actors have the agency to break tradition. Consequently, in the same way that an individual breaks from familial, cultural, or religious tradition and faces the ramifications for transgressing, epistemic transgression can also incur social fallout and cause friction. When an individual epistemically transgresses, they employ an epistemic praxis (the operationalization of an alternative or critical epistemology) that goes against the grain and is counter to the tradition that defines the social environment. For conversations concerning the cultivation of criticality (like the one herein) this break in tradition is absolutely desirable and can inspire what Jose ́ Medina (2013) calls epistemic friction. Epistemic friction is contained in those uncomfortable moments in which our taken-for-granted assumptions about the world begin to crack. These moments can be transformative and cat- alyze critical consciousness to imagine and hopefully actualize an alternative epistemology. | 3,042 | <h4>Representations and epistemology perpetuate settler practices – the way we understand and discuss the structures around us overdetermines our praxis. The 1AC is an epistemological interrogation and re-orientation that challenges hegemonic norms. </h4><p><strong>Seawright 14 <u></strong>Gardner Seawright is a doctoral candidate in the Education, Culture, and Society department at the University of Utah. “Settler Traditions of Place: Making Explicit the Epistemological Legacy of White Supremacy and Settler Colonialism for Place-Based Education.” EDUCATIONAL STUDIES, 50: 554–572, 2014, American Educational Studies Association. JJN</p><p></u>Situating Settler Traditions <u><mark>Settler traditions of place are an epistemic genealogy</mark>—the <mark>ethics, logics</mark>, and <mark>ideologies </mark>foundational to a knowledge system that have been passed down across generations, <mark>a</mark> knowledge <mark>framework that establishes </mark>what is known</u> (the socially constructed commonsense of a culture), <u>how things come to be known</u> (the process of attaining new knowledge), <u><mark>how the world is to be interpreted</mark> according to what is known </u>(the social construction of reality), <u>and how the self is known in relation to perceived reality</u> (the politics of self). <u><mark>Tradition</mark> is used</u> as a conceptual tool <u><mark>allow</mark>ing <mark>for domination</mark> to be empha- sized <mark>as an on-going historical process</mark>, while also allowing</u> for epistemology <u>as tradition to simultaneously be evolutionary and a cherished cultural artifact. </u>As a cultural product, <u><mark>settler traditions of place</mark> are <mark>transmitted</mark> across generations <mark>through</mark> discipline, <mark>teaching</mark>, modeling and other forms of direct <mark>and </mark>subtle so- cial communication resulting in <mark>normalize</mark>d habits, beliefs, values, and <mark>practices</mark>.</u> In speaking about “western cultural traditions,” Val Plumood (2002) argues that <u>there are “<mark>epistemic</mark> and moral <mark>limitations</mark>” embedded <mark>in</u></mark> these <u><mark>traditions</mark>—these normalized habits—that <mark>perpetuate hierarchized </mark>notions of the<mark> world</mark> that privi- lege white-hetero-landowning males</u> (99). As Martusewicz et al. (2011) explain, <u>these subtle <mark>discourses manifest as</mark> taken-for-granted <mark>cultural assumptions</mark> that are rooted in racism, sexism, classism that intertwine with and reflect the cultivation of violent relationships with the more-than-human world and natural systems that we depend on for life</u> (119). The tradition in question here is the social air that penetrates the Western world, interacting with human beings whether they want it to or not. Using tradition as a metaphor for epistemology allows me to emphasize the way <u>epistemology can im- pact every aspect of life while remaining removed from a deterministic position. Embedded in discourse, tradition appears as ever-present; despite this, <mark>individual </mark>social <mark>actors have the agency to break tradition</mark>.</u> Consequently, in the same way that an individual breaks from familial, cultural, or religious tradition and faces the ramifications for transgressing, epistemic transgression can also incur social fallout and cause friction. <u>When an individual <mark>epistemic</mark>ally <mark>transgress</mark>es, they employ an epistemic <mark>praxis</u></mark> (the operationalization of an alternative or critical epistemology) <u><mark>that goes against the grain</mark> and is counter to the tradition that defines the social environment. </u>For conversations concerning the cultivation of criticality (like the one herein) <u><mark>this break</mark> in tradition is absolutely desirable and <mark>can inspire</u></mark> what Jose ́ Medina (2013) calls <u><mark>epistemic friction</mark>. Epistemic friction is contained in <mark>those uncomfortable moments</mark> in which our taken-for-granted <mark>assumptions</mark> about the world <mark>begin to crack</mark>.</u> <u>These moments can be transformative and <mark>cat- alyze critical consciousness</mark> to imagine and hopefully actualize an alternative epistemology.</p></u> | 1ac | null | fwk! | 721,192 | 105 | 46,921 | ./documents/hsld21/WestridgeSchool/We/Westridge%20School-Wei-Aff-palm%20classic-Round6.docx | 902,106 | A | palm classic | 6 | st agnes eh | grant brown | 1ac - astrocolonialism v5
1nc - tfw megaconstellations pic africa da
1ar - all
2nr - pic case
2ar - case pic | hsld21/WestridgeSchool/We/Westridge%20School-Wei-Aff-palm%20classic-Round6.docx | null | 75,501 | TaWe | Westridge School TaWe | null | Ta..... | We..... | null | null | 25,218 | WestridgeSchool | Westridge School | CA | null | 1,029 | hsld21 | HS LD 2021-22 | 2,021 | ld | hs | 1 |
605,506 | Modern empire is unsustainable -- multiple intertwined crises make collapse inevitable which means its try-or-die -- we got charts. | von Weizsäcker and Wijkman ’17 | von Weizsäcker and Wijkman ’17 Ernest Ulrich von Weizsäcker, Professor and Director of the United Nation Centre for Science and Technology for Development, Founder and President of the Wuppertal Institute, Member of the German Bundestag, chairing the Committees on Globalization and the Environment, Dean of the graduate School of Environmental Science and Management at the University of California, appointed Co-Chair of UNEP’s International Resource Panel, Anders Wijkman, chairman of the Swedish Association of Recycling Industries, member of the Board of the Swedish Development Authority (SIDA), appointed chair of the Swedish Cross-Party Committee on Environmental Objectives, member of the European Parliament, Assistant Secretary-General of the United Nations and Policy Director of UNDP, Secretary General of the Swedish Red Cross and Director General of the Swedish Agency for Research Cooperation with Developing Countries, Member of the Swedish Royal Academy of Sciences, the World Future Council and the International Resource Panel, 2017 (“Come On! Capitalism, Short-termism, Population and the Destruction of the Planet – A Report to the Club”, November 11th, Available Online via Subscription to Springer, Accessed 03-20-2018) | the world is in crisis almost half of the top soils on earth have been depleted nearly 90% of fish stocks are either overfished or fully fished earth is now in the sixth mass extinction period The human ability to do has outstripped the ability to understand civilization is faced with a perfect storm driven by overpopulation overconsumption the use of environmentally malign technologies and gross inequalities’ The rapidly deteriorating biophysical situation is barely recognized infected by the irrational belief that economies can grow forever’ The crisis is not cyclical but growing The crisis consists of deepened poverty the loss of jobs Billions of people don’t trust their government symptoms of crisis are found nearly everywhere. The ‘Arab Spring’ was followed by a series of wars human rights violations and refugees the temporary economic upswing several lost its dynamism Land grabbing is plaguing Africa other parts of the world leading to involuntary dislocations The response of governments has been concentrated on managing their own political image not the cause the political class in the world is strongly influenced by and private companies the current crisis is also a crisis of global capitalism capitalism has moved from economic development and then to a large extent profits The term ‘shareholder value’ it served to narrow business down to short-term gains at the expense of social and ecological values A different feature is the rise of rightwing movements against globalization in OECD countries referred to as populism Trump is part of a broad populist
populism remains an opposition movement This phenomenon of right-wing populism can be explained by the ‘trunk valley of the elephant curve’ showing the decline of world middle classes OECD’s middle classes suffered losses caused mainly deindustrialization and job losses What remains invisible on the picture is the far end of ‘the trunk of the elephant’: The richest 1% of the world the richest eight persons own as much wealth as the poorest half of the world population combined The ‘elephant curve’ gives an incomplete picture The Oxford Poverty and Human Development Initiative going beyond income and including health, education and living standards counts 1.6 billion people living in ‘multidimensional poverty’ nearly twice as many as the number of people living in extreme poverty the curve requires people in each percentile group the massive shift of money and income from the manufacturing financialization’ is the cause of income inequality falling wages and the poor performance Reagan’s director agrees, describing our current situation as ‘corrosive that has turned the economy into a giant casino the strongest trigger has been the millions of refugees Even the most generous European countries have reached their own assumed limits The populist right-wing movements criticize the EU as the culprit The irony is that continuing the success story would require more powers these very measures of which nationalist populists are most afraid Free market principles have come to dominate policymaking austerity policies pursued many benign investments and led to unnecessary suffering shortcomings should never be used to put in question the objectives the report sees a consistent decay of parameters as civil rights, free and fair elections, freedom of opinion and of press freedom of assembly and separation of powers the number of countries which authoritarian dogmas influence political decision making rose Symptoms of tyranny are spreading anger and indignation are the emotions that are most likely to get viral meaning they multiplied faster and stronger humanity’s conflicts occurred between different countries using terror attacks with intention of making people feel insecure religions remained quiet confined to stable territories globalized populations moving or being forced factions of Islam have expanded geographically and are claiming strong influence understand the radicalization of Islam, one must not underestimate the West, the troublesome situations mentioned are only the surface One trend is digitization trend or development can be observed in sciences and technologies acceleration of genetic engineering is causing fears of monster creation or extinction An important part of the disorientation relates to financial markets looking at the explosion in bank balance backed up by declining levels of equity The other was a massive increase in financialization risk-taking developed into a crisis that was close to bringing the whole financial system to a halt Governments caught by the new mind-set intimately involved had it not been for the systematic deregulation of the banks with the purpose of stimulating economic growth the situation would have been radically different Excessive lending by the banking industry Lack of action on regulators excessive lending exotic financial instruments pure speculative transactions Opaque tax havens Securitization and distribution by investment banks vehicles transferring the credit risk lender to the ultimate bondholders A deeper analysis is presented by economists about the main causes behind the financial crisis banks borrowed far too much with far too little equit from trading the multitrillion-dollar markets Banks believed they had invented instruments that removed the risk they counted with the state to underwrite their risks They made themselves ‘too big to fail’ – 2008 financial crisis was mostly caused by that irresponsible greed nine million households had to abandon their homes Financialization refers to the dominance of the financial sector and tendency for accumulated profits . Debt is an intrinsic element household debt and private sector debt doubled financial products and transactions lead to monetary crashes, sovereign debt crises and systemic crashes with more than ten countries in crisis every year Practices within the financial sector demonstrate a disregard for the impact That includes a distinct short-termism We have a system that accumulates oversupply of money that produce high financial and low environmental returns The failure to account for environmental risks means pressure on natural resources accelerates trees are felled, waterways polluted wetlands drained and oil, gas and coal accelerating . It also means that huge savings, among them pension funds, are locked in fossil-based assets assets are increasingly looked upon as high-risk assets | the world is in crisis half of the top soils have been depleted 90% of fish stocks are overfished civilization is faced with overpopulation, overconsumption environmentally malign technologies and gross inequalities’ The crisis is growing Billions of people don’t trust their government Land grabbing is plaguing other parts of the world the current crisis is a crisis of global capitalism
This phenomenon of right-wing populism can be explained by the ‘trunk valley of the elephant curve’ financialization’ is the cause of income inequality falling wages and poor performance that has turned the economy into a giant casino the report sees a consistent decay of parameters as civil rights elections freedom of opinion and freedom 08 crisis was caused by irresponsible greed debt doubled financial products lead to monetary crashes, sovereign debt crises and systemic crashes with an ten countries in crisis every year The failure to account for environmental risks means pressure on natural resources trees felled waterways polluted, wetlands drained and coal accelerating | 1.1 Introduction: The World in Disarray We all know that the world is in crisis. Science tells us that almost half of the top soils on earth have been depleted in the last 150 years1 ; nearly 90% of fish stocks are either overfished or fully fished.2 Climate stability is in real danger (Sects. 1.5 and 3.7); and the earth is now in the sixth mass extinction period in history.3 Perhaps the most accurate account of the ecological situation is the 2012 ‘Imperative to act’,4 launched by all the 18 recipients (till 2012) of the Blue Planet Prize, including Gro Harlem Brundtland, James Hansen, Amory Lovins, James Lovelock and Susan Solomon. Its key message reads, ‘The human ability to do has vastly outstripped the ability to understand. As a result, civilization is faced with a perfect storm of problems, driven by overpopulation, overconsumption by the rich, the use of environmentally malign technologies and gross inequalities’. And further, ‘The rapidly deteriorating biophysical situation is barely recognized by a global society infected by the irrational belief that physical economies can grow forever’. 1.1.1 Different Types of Crisis and a Feeling of Helplessness The crisis is not cyclical but growing. And it is not limited to the nature around us. There are also a social crisis, a political and a cultural crisis, a moral crisis, as well as a crisis of democracy, of ideologies and of the capitalist system. The crisis also consists of deepened poverty in many countries and the loss of jobs for a considerable part of the population worldwide. Billions of people have reached a state of mind where they don’t trust their government anymore.5 Seen from a geographic point of view, symptoms of crisis are found nearly everywhere. The ‘Arab Spring’ was followed by a series of wars and civil wars, serious human rights violations and many millions of refugees. The internal situation is not better in Eritrea, South Sudan, Somalia, Yemen or Honduras. Venezuela and Argentina, once among the richer states of the world, face huge economic challenges, and neighbouring Brazil has gone through many years of recession and political turmoil. Russia and several East European countries are struggling with major economic and political problems in their post-communist phase. Japan finds it difficult to overcome decadelong stagnation, and to deal with the 2011 tsunami and ensuing nuclear disaster. And the temporary economic upswing several African countries have enjoyed lost its dynamism as soon as the prices of mineral resources collapsed, and partly due to very unusual droughts. Land grabbing is plaguing much of Africa, but also other parts of the world, leading to involuntary dislocations of millions of people and the related problems with refugees both within countries and abroad.6 The response of governments has been concentrated, at worst, on managing their own political image, and at best to treat the symptoms of the crisis, not the cause. The problem is that the political class in the whole world is strongly influenced by investors and by powerful private companies. This indicates that the current crisis is also a crisis of global capitalism. Since the 1980s, capitalism has moved from furthering the economic development of countries, regions and the world towards maximizing profits, and then to a large extent profits from speculation. In addition, the capitalism unleashed since 1980 in the Anglo-Saxon world, and since 1990 worldwide, is mainly financial. This trend was supported by excessive deregulation and liberalization of the economy (see Sect. 2.4). The term ‘shareholder value’ popped up in the business pages of the media worldwide, as if that was now the new epiphany and guardrail for all economic action. In reality, it served to narrow business down to short-term gains, often at the expense of social and ecological values. The myth of shareholder value has been effectively debunked in a recent book by Lynn Stout.7 A different, if related, feature of ‘disarray’ is the rise of aggressive, mostly rightwing movements against globalization in OECD countries, often referred to as populism. These have become overt through Brexit and the Trump victory in the United States. As Fareed Zakaria observes, ‘Trump is part of a broad populist
upsurge running through the Western world. … In most (countries), populism remains an opposition movement, although one that is growing in strength; in others, such as Hungary, it is now the reigning ideology’.8 This phenomenon of right-wing populism can be explained to an extent by the ‘trunk valley of the elephant curve’ (Fig. 1.1) 9 showing the decline of developed world middle classes, during a 20-year period. While more than half of the world’s population was enjoying over 60% income rises, OECD’s middle classes suffered losses caused mainly by the deindustrialization and job losses in major parts of the United States, Britain and other countries. In the United States, the median income increased by a meagre 1.2% since 1979. The stunning income growth on the left-hand side of the curve, the ‘back of the elephant’, lifting some two billion people out of poverty, was caused mainly by China’s and some other countries’ economic success. What remains invisible on the picture is the far end of ‘the trunk of the elephant’: The richest 1% of the world and, more revolting, the richest eight persons of the world now own as much wealth as the poorest half of the world population combined, a figure publicized by Oxfam during the 2017 World Economic Forum.10 The ‘elephant curve’ gives an incomplete picture for a second reason. The Oxford Poverty and Human Development Initiative (OPHI) has proposed a Multidimensional Poverty Index (MPI) going beyond just income and including ten indicators around health, education and living standards. Using that MPI, OPHI counts 1.6 billion people living in ‘multidimensional poverty’ in 2016 – nearly twice as many as the number of people living in extreme poverty measured by income alone.11 Thirdly, the interpretation of the curve requires an analysis of the people in each percentile group. In fact, they tend to move. And the curve does not distinguish those in Russia and East European countries who lost much of their income after 1990 from those in Detroit or middle England who, for very different reasons, also were among the losers.12 Another fact cannot be seen in the picture: the massive shift of money and income from the manufacturing and trade sectors to the financial sector.13 Bruce Bartlett, a senior policy advisor to both the Reagan and Bush administrations, argues that this ‘financialization’ of the economy is the cause of income inequality, falling wages and the poor performance. David Stockman, Reagan’s director of the Office of Management and Budget, agrees, describing our current situation as ‘corrosive financialization that has turned the economy into a giant casino since the 1970s’.14 Populist politicians in the OECD countries see themselves as speaking for the forgotten ‘ordinary’ people and for genuine patriotism, but they tend to fight and antagonize the people representing democratic institutions – what an irony! For the European Union (EU), the strongest trigger for populism has been the millions of refugees who came or would like to come to Europe from the Near East, from Afghanistan and from Africa. Even the most generous European countries have reached their own assumed limits for receiving these masses of refugees. The EU institutions were too weak (not too powerful, as they are depicted by the new nationalists) to deal with the ‘refugee crisis’, resulting eventually in an identity crisis in the EU. Once a success story of an entity ensuring peace and economic development, the EU has lost some of its unifying narrative. The populist right-wing movements or parties see and criticize the EU as the culprit for all kinds of undesired events. The irony is that continuing the success story would require more, not less, powers for the Union. The Union should be entrusted with border protection, a well-funded common asylum and refugee policy to deal with the refugee crisis and maintain the advantages of the Schengen agreement. And for the re-stabilization of the Euro, the EU or at least the Euro zone needs a common fiscal policy, as the new French President Emmanuel Macron is proposing. But it is these very measures of which nationalist populists are most afraid. The EU in its present form is not without shortcomings. Free market principles have come to dominate EU policymaking, leading to a subordination of other policies, like environment. Notably the UK wanted that priority, as it preferred to see the EU chiefly as a union for mutual trade. And the austerity policies pursued have blocked many benign investments and led to unnecessary suffering among tens of millions of Europeans. Such shortcomings, however, should never be used to put in question the overall objectives of the EU – a union of peace, the rule of law, human rights, cultural understanding and sustainability. Addressing the global crisis of democracy, the German Bertelsmann Foundation has published a 3000-page empirical report on progress (or lack thereof) on democracy and a social market economy, as measured by the Bertelsmann Transformation Index (BTI).15 Over the last few years, the report sees a consistent decay of such parameters as civil rights, free and fair elections, freedom of opinion and of press, freedom of assembly and separation of powers. Within the same time frame, the number of countries in which authoritarian, mostly religious, dogmas influence political decision making rose from 22% to 33%. That report was published before the assaults on democracy and civil rights that occurred in summer 2016 in Turkey or the Philippines. Symptoms of tyranny are spreading, including in some of the countries with a solid tradition of freedom and democracy.16 Let us briefly turn to a different kind of crisis. Well, not exactly a crisis but an unpleasant feature in an otherwise fruitful communication tool, the ‘social media’. Aside from being practical and useful for everyday arrangements and exchange of news and reasonable opinions, social media also have become vehicles for enhancing conflicts and vilification of mostly innocent individuals, and for spreading ‘post truth’ nonsense. Much of the contents of social media political conversation is selfenhancing political rubbish, as those media serve as ‘echo chambers’ for networks of like-minded frustrated citizens.17 An empirical study from China found that anger and indignation are the emotions that are most likely to get viral in the social media, meaning they are multiplied faster and stronger than other emotions.18 The Internet and the social media are also vehicles for ‘bots’ (short for robots) that can disrupt or destroy messages, multiply nonsense and create all kinds of mischief. There are dozens of types of malicious bots (and botnets) to harvest email addresses, to grab content of websites and reuse it without permission, to spread viruses and worms, to buy up good seats for entertainment events, to increase views for YouTube videos or to increase traffic counts in order to extract money from advertisers. A more frightening cause of disarray relates to terrorism. In earlier times, humanity’s violent conflicts occurred mostly between different countries. In recent times, systemic and at least partly religious conflicts prevail, using terror attacks with the explicit intention of making people feel insecure. During much of the twentieth century, religions remained quiet, non-aggressive and geographically confined to rather stable territories. This no longer is true. Partly because of globalized populations moving or being forced to leave their home territories, some factions of Islam have expanded geographically and are claiming strong influence over national states, for example, attacking countries like France with its tradition of laicism that does not permit religion to dominate politics. What tends to be underrepresented in the media is the positive role of religions. In Christian-dominated Europe, liberal and tolerant religion became part of the European identity a century after the Enlightenment successfully discredited the earlier doctrinaire, authoritarian and colonialist-missionary manifestations of the faith. During the Cold War, Christian goals of social cohesion helped build the system of ‘Western values’, often described as the social welfare state, or the ‘social market economy’ (for its partial demise, see Sect. 2.4). With a view towards leading Islam into an equally benign and co-operative social role, some Islamic scholars, such as Syrian born Bassam Tibi, call on Muslims in Europe to integrate into democratic society.19 Tibi, however, is not popular among radical Muslims, to put it mildly. But to understand the radicalization of Islam, one must not underestimate the role played by the West, in particular the United States, in interfering with Near Eastern states. Some would say that the troublesome situations mentioned so far, the recurring topics of media headlines, are only the surface of our world’s ‘disarray’. Deeper and more systemic problems include the breath-taking speed of technological development that may very easily run out of control. One trend is digitization that potentially threatens millions of jobs (see Sect. 1.11.4). Another trend or development can be observed in the biological sciences and technologies. The enormous acceleration of genetic engineering through the CRISPR-Cas9 technology20 is causing fears of monster creation or the extinction of species or varieties not seen as valuable under human utilitarian criteria. Generally, a non-specific feeling is spreading that ‘progress’ has scary sides and that the genie may already have left the bottle (see Sect. 1.11.3). No doubt there is a need to analyse and understand the symptoms and roots of the variety of crises, political, economic, social, technological and environmental. It is also important to recognize the extent to which people perceive the various phenomena of disarray and feel disoriented, and to recognize that the reality and the feelings of disarray have a moral and even religious dimension. 1.1.2 Financialization: A Phenomenon of Disarray An important part of the disorientation relates to financial markets. Historians will look back at the last 30 years with concern, when looking at the explosion in bank balance sheets, backed up by declining levels of equity and massive borrowing. One of the results was a temporary private-sector-led boom. The other was a massive increase in the world’s financial sector (finance, insurance, real estate – FIRE), often called financialization, and subsequently the financial crisis of 2008–2009. Excessive risk-taking developed into a crisis that was close to bringing the whole financial system to a halt. When the bubble burst, many governments were forced to step in with broad support programmes. Governments caught by the new mind-set (see Sect. 2.4) were intimately involved in all of this. True, there are many examples of serious malpractices within the private financial sector. But had it not been for the systematic deregulation of the banks by governments, with the purpose of stimulating economic growth by issuing more debt, the situation would have been radically different. The causes behind the crisis were many and varied: – Excessive lending by the banking industry – Lack of action on the part of regulators and central banks to stop (i) excessive lending, (ii) the spread of exotic financial instruments (synthetic assets and bonds, collateralized mortgage obligations/CMOs, structured debt issues, etc.) and (iii) pure speculative transactions – Opaque tax havens, and the absence of a binding legal framework that is accepted and implemented by the international community, in general, and the major jurisdictions and financial centres – Securitization and distribution by investment banks and other financial actors of mortgage-related assets and investment vehicles transferring the credit risk from the original lender to the ultimate bondholders – Failure by some rating agencies and auditing firms to properly assess and report the inherent risks posed by many of the financial products A deeper analysis is presented by economists Anat Admati and Martin Hellwig21 about the main causes behind the financial crisis. Western banks borrowed far too much with far too little equity in their balance sheets to act as a buffer if things went wrong in their business – from trading in the multitrillion-dollar derivatives markets to often reckless lending on real estate. In the decades following the Second World War, banks operated with between 20% and 30% of their liabilities as equity. By 2008, that had shrunk to just 3%. Banks obviously believed that they had invented instruments that removed the risk, allowing them to run their banks with a tenth of the buffer they had before. It proved to be very unrealistic. But they counted with the state to underwrite their risks. Bankers have enriched themselves spectacularly in the process. They made themselves ‘too big to fail’ – and too big to jail. The 2008 financial crisis was mostly caused by that irresponsible greed.22 Yet, in 2009, not only did bankers avoid criminal prosecutions and receive hundreds of billions in government bailouts, but some still paid themselves record bonuses. At the same time, almost nine million households in the United States had to abandon their homes when the value of their houses plummeted and they could no longer service the adjustable-rate mortgages – the so-called foreclosure crisis.23 Financialization refers to the dominance of the financial sector in the global economy and the tendency for accumulated profits (and leverage) to flow into real estate and other speculative investment. Debt is an intrinsic element in this process. In the United States, for example, both household debt and private sector debt more than doubled relative to GDP between 1980 and 2007.24 The same is true for most OECD countries. At the same time, ‘the value of financial assets grew from four times GDP in 1980 to ten times GDP in 2007 and the finance sector’s share of corporate profits grew from about 10% in the early 1980s to almost 40% by 2006’.25 Adair Turner, chair of the UK’s Financial Services Authority in the years following the 2007–2008 crisis, regards unchecked private credit creation as the key system fault that led to that crisis with its devastating consequences.26 From this follows that the financial sector constitutes a significant and increasing risk factor in the economy. The degree of financialization varies from country to country but the increase in the power of finance is general. The current finance sector evolved in the context of the deregulation that gathered pace from the late 1970s and expanded dramatically after the 1999 removal of the separation between commercial and investment banking in the United States.27 This barrier had been put in place in 1933 by the Roosevelt administration in response to the Wall Street Crash of 1929, when a period of rampant credit creation and financial speculation collapsed. Similar speculation preceded the crisis of 2007–2008: The face value of financial products reached US$640 trillion in September 2008, 14 times the GDP of all the countries on earth.28 Lietaer et al.29 compare speculation with ordinary money transfers paying for goods and services: ‘In 2010, the volume of foreign exchange transactions reached $4 trillion per day’, which does not even include derivatives. In comparison, ‘one day’s exports or imports of all goods and services in the world amount to about 2% of those $4 trillion’. Transactions not paying for goods and services, almost by definition are speculative. Such financial products and transactions, the authors continue, lead regularly to monetary crashes, sovereign debt crises and systemic crashes with an average of more than ten countries in crisis every year. One of the consequences of this development is that a significant part of economic growth has been distributed to the wealthy, as mentioned with the new Oxfam figures in the previous subchapter. Practices within the financial sector demonstrate a disregard for the impact they have on both people and the planet. That includes a distinct short-termism, the ratio of banks’ reserves to their loans, the ratio of banks’ lending that support the real economy versus speculation in property and derivatives, unchecked credit creation – in fact money creation – and the failure to account for long-term climate and environmental risks. In the words of Otto Scharmer at MIT,30 ‘We have a system that accumulates oversupply of money in areas that produce high financial and low environmental and social returns, while at the same an undersupply of money in areas that serve important societal investment needs’. The failure to account for environmental risks means that the pressure on already scarce natural resources accelerates – trees are felled, waterways polluted, wetlands drained and the exploitation of oil, gas and coal accelerating, as long as there is demand. It also means that huge savings, among them pension funds, are locked into investments in fossil-based assets. Such assets are increasingly looked upon as high-risk assets (see Sect. 3.4). | 21,534 | <h4>Modern empire is <u>unsustainable</u> -- multiple intertwined crises make collapse <u>inevitable</u> which means its <u>try-or-die</u> -- we got <u>charts</u>.</h4><p><strong>von Weizsäcker and Wijkman ’17 </strong>Ernest Ulrich von Weizsäcker, Professor and Director of the United Nation Centre for Science and Technology for Development, Founder and President of the Wuppertal Institute, Member of the German Bundestag, chairing the Committees on Globalization and the Environment, Dean of the graduate School of Environmental Science and Management at the University of California, appointed Co-Chair of UNEP’s International Resource Panel, Anders Wijkman, chairman of the Swedish Association of Recycling Industries, member of the Board of the Swedish Development Authority (SIDA), appointed chair of the Swedish Cross-Party Committee on Environmental Objectives, member of the European Parliament, Assistant Secretary-General of the United Nations and Policy Director of UNDP, Secretary General of the Swedish Red Cross and Director General of the Swedish Agency for Research Cooperation with Developing Countries, Member of the Swedish Royal Academy of Sciences, the World Future Council and the International Resource Panel, 2017 (“Come On! Capitalism, Short-termism, Population and the Destruction of the Planet – A Report to the Club”, November 11th, Available Online via Subscription to Springer, Accessed 03-20-2018) </p><p>1.1 Introduction: The World in Disarray We all know that <u><mark>the world is in crisis</u></mark>. Science tells us that <u><strong>almost <mark>half of the top soils</strong></mark> on earth <mark>have been depleted</u></mark> in the last 150 years1 ; <u>nearly <strong><mark>90% of fish stocks</strong> are</mark> either <mark>overfished</mark> or fully fished</u>.2 Climate stability is in real danger (Sects. 1.5 and 3.7); and the <u>earth is now in the sixth mass extinction period </u>in history.3 Perhaps the most accurate account of the ecological situation is the 2012 ‘Imperative to act’,4 launched by all the 18 recipients (till 2012) of the Blue Planet Prize, including Gro Harlem Brundtland, James Hansen, Amory Lovins, James Lovelock and Susan Solomon. Its key message reads, ‘<u>The</u> <u>human ability to do has</u> vastly <u>outstripped the ability to understand</u>. As a result, <u><mark>civilization is</u> <u>faced with</mark> a perfect storm </u>of problems, <u>driven by <strong><mark>overpopulation</u></strong>, <u><strong>overconsumption</u></strong></mark> by the rich, <u>the use of</u> <u><strong><mark>environmentally</mark> <mark>malign technologies</strong> and <strong>gross inequalities’</u></strong></mark>. And further, ‘<u>The rapidly deteriorating biophysical situation is barely recognized</u> by a global society <u>infected by the irrational belief that</u> physical <u>economies can grow forever’</u>. 1.1.1 Different Types of Crisis and a Feeling of Helplessness <u><mark>The crisis is</mark> not cyclical <strong>but <mark>growing</u></strong></mark>. And it is not limited to the nature around us. There are also a social crisis, a political and a cultural crisis, a moral crisis, as well as a crisis of democracy, of ideologies and of the capitalist system. <u>The crisis</u> also <u>consists of deepened poverty</u> in many countries and <u>the loss of jobs</u> for a considerable part of the population worldwide. <u><mark>Billions of people</u></mark> have reached a state of mind where they <u><mark>don’t</u> <u>trust their government</u></mark> anymore.5 Seen from a geographic point of view, <u>symptoms of crisis are</u> <u>found nearly everywhere. The ‘Arab Spring’ was followed by a series of wars</u> and civil wars, serious <u>human rights violations and</u> many millions of <u>refugees</u>. The internal situation is not better in Eritrea, South Sudan, Somalia, Yemen or Honduras. Venezuela and Argentina, once among the richer states of the world, face huge economic challenges, and neighbouring Brazil has gone through many years of recession and political turmoil. Russia and several East European countries are struggling with major economic and political problems in their post-communist phase. Japan finds it difficult to overcome decadelong stagnation, and to deal with the 2011 tsunami and ensuing nuclear disaster. And <u>the temporary economic upswing several</u> African countries have enjoyed <u>lost its dynamism</u> as soon as the prices of mineral resources collapsed, and partly due to very unusual droughts. <u><mark>Land grabbing is <strong>plaguing</u></strong></mark> much of <u>Africa</u>, but also <u><mark>other parts of the world</u></mark>, <u>leading to involuntary dislocations</u> of millions of people and the related problems with refugees both within countries and abroad.6 <u>The response of</u> <u>governments has been concentrated</u>, at worst, <u>on managing their own political image</u>, and at best to treat the symptoms of the crisis, <u>not the cause</u>. The problem is that <u>the political class in</u> <u>the</u> whole <u>world is strongly influenced by</u> investors <u>and</u> by powerful <u>private companies</u>. This indicates that <u><mark>the current crisis is </mark>also <mark>a <strong>crisis of</mark> <mark>global capitalism</u></strong></mark>. Since the 1980s, <u>capitalism has moved from</u> furthering the <u>economic development</u> of countries, regions and the world towards maximizing profits, <u>and then to <strong>a large extent profits</u></strong> from speculation. In addition, the capitalism unleashed since 1980 in the Anglo-Saxon world, and since 1990 worldwide, is mainly financial. This trend was supported by excessive deregulation and liberalization of the economy (see Sect. 2.4). <u>The term ‘shareholder value’</u> popped up in the business pages of the media worldwide, as if that was now the new epiphany and guardrail for all economic action. In reality, <u>it served to narrow business down to short-term gains</u>, often <u>at</u> <u>the expense of social and ecological values</u>. The myth of shareholder value has been effectively debunked in a recent book by Lynn Stout.7 <u>A different</u>, if related, <u>feature</u> of ‘disarray’ <u>is the rise</u> <u>of</u> aggressive, mostly <u>rightwing movements against globalization in OECD countries</u>, often <u>referred to as <strong>populism</u></strong>. These have become overt through Brexit and the Trump victory in the United States. As Fareed Zakaria observes, ‘<u>Trump is part of a broad populist</u> </p><p>upsurge running through the Western world. … In most (countries), <u>populism remains an</u> <u>opposition movement</u>, although one that is growing in strength; in others, such as Hungary, it is now the reigning ideology’.8 <u><mark>This phenomenon of right-wing populism can be</mark> <mark>explained</u></mark> to an extent <u><mark>by the ‘<strong>trunk valley of the elephant curve’</u></strong></mark> (Fig. 1.1) 9 <u>showing the decline of</u> developed <u>world middle classes</u>, during a 20-year period. While more than half of the world’s population was enjoying over 60% income rises, <u>OECD’s middle classes suffered losses caused</u> <u>mainly</u> by the <u>deindustrialization and job losses</u> in major parts of the United States, Britain and other countries. In the United States, the median income increased by a meagre 1.2% since 1979. The stunning income growth on the left-hand side of the curve, the ‘back of the elephant’, lifting some two billion people out of poverty, was caused mainly by China’s and some other countries’ economic success. <u>What remains invisible on the picture is the far end of ‘the trunk of the</u> <u>elephant’: The richest 1% of the world</u> and, more revolting, <u>the richest eight persons</u> of the world now <u>own as much wealth as the <strong>poorest half</u></strong> <u>of the world population combined</u>, a figure publicized by Oxfam during the 2017 World Economic Forum.10 <u>The ‘elephant curve’ gives an</u> <u>incomplete picture</u> for a second reason. <u>The Oxford Poverty and Human Development Initiative</u> (OPHI) has proposed a Multidimensional Poverty Index (MPI) <u>going beyond </u>just <u>income and</u> <u>including</u> ten indicators around <u>health, education and living standards</u>. Using that MPI, OPHI <u>counts 1.6 billion people living in ‘<strong>multidimensional poverty’</u></strong> in 2016 – <u>nearly <strong>twice</strong> as many as the number of people living in extreme poverty</u> measured by income alone.11 Thirdly, <u>the</u> interpretation of the <u>curve requires</u> an analysis of the <u>people in each percentile group</u>. In fact, they tend to move. And the curve does not distinguish those in Russia and East European countries who lost much of their income after 1990 from those in Detroit or middle England who, for very different reasons, also were among the losers.12 Another fact cannot be seen in the picture: <u>the massive shift of money and income from the manufacturing</u> and trade sectors to the financial sector.13 Bruce Bartlett, a senior policy advisor to both the Reagan and Bush administrations, argues that this ‘<u><mark>financialization’</u></mark> of the economy <u><mark>is the cause of income</u> <u>inequality</u></mark>, <u><mark>falling wages and</mark> the <mark>poor performance</u></mark>. David Stockman, <u>Reagan’s director</u> of the Office of Management and Budget, <u>agrees, describing our current situation as ‘corrosive</u> financialization <u><mark>that has turned the <strong>economy</mark> <mark>into a giant casino</u></strong></mark> since the 1970s’.14 Populist politicians in the OECD countries see themselves as speaking for the forgotten ‘ordinary’ people and for genuine patriotism, but they tend to fight and antagonize the people representing democratic institutions – what an irony! For the European Union (EU), <u>the strongest trigger</u> for populism <u>has been the millions of refugees</u> who came or would like to come to Europe from the Near East, from Afghanistan and from Africa. <u>Even the most generous European countries have</u> <u>reached their own assumed limits</u> for receiving these masses of refugees. The EU institutions were too weak (not too powerful, as they are depicted by the new nationalists) to deal with the ‘refugee crisis’, resulting eventually in an identity crisis in the EU. Once a success story of an entity ensuring peace and economic development, the EU has lost some of its unifying narrative. <u>The populist right-wing movements</u> or parties see and <u>criticize the EU as the culprit</u> for all kinds of undesired events. <u>The irony is that continuing the success story would require more</u>, not less, <u>powers</u> for the Union. The Union should be entrusted with border protection, a well-funded common asylum and refugee policy to deal with the refugee crisis and maintain the advantages of the Schengen agreement. And for the re-stabilization of the Euro, the EU or at least the Euro zone needs a common fiscal policy, as the new French President Emmanuel Macron is proposing. But it is <u>these very measures of which nationalist populists are</u> <u><strong>most afraid</u></strong>. The EU in its present form is not without shortcomings. <u>Free market principles have come to dominate</u> EU <u>policymaking</u>, leading to a subordination of other policies, like environment. Notably the UK wanted that priority, as it preferred to see the EU chiefly as a union for mutual trade. And the <u>austerity policies pursued</u> have blocked <u>many benign investments and led to unnecessary</u> <u>suffering</u> among tens of millions of Europeans. Such <u>shortcomings</u>, however, <u>should never be</u> <u>used to put in question the</u> overall <u>objectives</u> of the EU – a union of peace, the rule of law, human rights, cultural understanding and sustainability. Addressing the global crisis of democracy, the German Bertelsmann Foundation has published a 3000-page empirical report on progress (or lack thereof) on democracy and a social market economy, as measured by the Bertelsmann Transformation Index (BTI).15 Over the last few years, <u><mark>the report sees a consistent</u> <u>decay of</u></mark> such <u><mark>parameters as civil rights</mark>, free and fair <mark>elections</mark>, <mark>freedom of opinion and</mark> of press</u>, <u><mark>freedom</mark> of assembly and separation of powers</u>. Within the same time frame, <u>the number of</u> <u>countries</u> in <u>which authoritarian</u>, mostly religious, <u>dogmas influence political decision making</u> <u>rose</u> from 22% to 33%. That report was published before the assaults on democracy and civil rights that occurred in summer 2016 in Turkey or the Philippines. <u>Symptoms of tyranny are</u> <u>spreading</u>, including in some of the countries with a solid tradition of freedom and democracy.16 Let us briefly turn to a different kind of crisis. Well, not exactly a crisis but an unpleasant feature in an otherwise fruitful communication tool, the ‘social media’. Aside from being practical and useful for everyday arrangements and exchange of news and reasonable opinions, social media also have become vehicles for enhancing conflicts and vilification of mostly innocent individuals, and for spreading ‘post truth’ nonsense. Much of the contents of social media political conversation is selfenhancing political rubbish, as those media serve as ‘echo chambers’ for networks of like-minded frustrated citizens.17 An empirical study from China found that <u>anger and indignation are the emotions that are most likely to get viral</u> in the social media, <u>meaning they</u> are <u>multiplied faster and stronger</u> than other emotions.18 The Internet and the social media are also vehicles for ‘bots’ (short for robots) that can disrupt or destroy messages, multiply nonsense and create all kinds of mischief. There are dozens of types of malicious bots (and botnets) to harvest email addresses, to grab content of websites and reuse it without permission, to spread viruses and worms, to buy up good seats for entertainment events, to increase views for YouTube videos or to increase traffic counts in order to extract money from advertisers. A more frightening cause of disarray relates to terrorism. In earlier times, <u>humanity’s</u> violent <u>conflicts occurred</u> mostly <u>between different countries</u>. In recent times, systemic and at least partly religious conflicts prevail, <u>using terror attacks with</u> the explicit <u>intention of making people feel insecure</u>. During much of the twentieth century, <u>religions</u> <u>remained quiet</u>, non-aggressive and geographically <u>confined to</u> rather <u>stable territories</u>. This no longer is true. Partly because of <u>globalized populations moving or being forced</u> to leave their home territories, some <u>factions of Islam have <strong>expanded geographically</strong> and are claiming strong</u> <u>influence</u> over national states, for example, attacking countries like France with its tradition of laicism that does not permit religion to dominate politics. What tends to be underrepresented in the media is the positive role of religions. In Christian-dominated Europe, liberal and tolerant religion became part of the European identity a century after the Enlightenment successfully discredited the earlier doctrinaire, authoritarian and colonialist-missionary manifestations of the faith. During the Cold War, Christian goals of social cohesion helped build the system of ‘Western values’, often described as the social welfare state, or the ‘social market economy’ (for its partial demise, see Sect. 2.4). With a view towards leading Islam into an equally benign and co-operative social role, some Islamic scholars, such as Syrian born Bassam Tibi, call on Muslims in Europe to integrate into democratic society.19 Tibi, however, is not popular among radical Muslims, to put it mildly. But to <u>understand the radicalization of</u> <u>Islam, one must <strong>not underestimate</u></strong> the role played by <u>the West,</u> in particular the United States, in interfering with Near Eastern states. Some would say that <u>the troublesome situations</u> <u>mentioned</u> so far, the recurring topics of media headlines, <u>are only the surface</u> of our world’s ‘disarray’. Deeper and more systemic problems include the breath-taking speed of technological development that may very easily run out of control. <u>One trend is digitization</u> that potentially threatens millions of jobs (see Sect. 1.11.4). Another <u>trend or development can be observed in</u> the biological <u>sciences and technologies</u>. The enormous <u>acceleration of genetic engineering</u> through the CRISPR-Cas9 technology20 <u>is causing fears of monster creation or</u> the <u>extinction</u> of species or varieties not seen as valuable under human utilitarian criteria. Generally, a non-specific feeling is spreading that ‘progress’ has scary sides and that the genie may already have left the bottle (see Sect. 1.11.3). No doubt there is a need to analyse and understand the symptoms and roots of the variety of crises, political, economic, social, technological and environmental. It is also important to recognize the extent to which people perceive the various phenomena of disarray and feel disoriented, and to recognize that the reality and the feelings of disarray have a moral and even religious dimension. 1.1.2 Financialization: A Phenomenon of Disarray <u>An important part of the disorientation relates to financial markets</u>. Historians will look back at the last 30 years with concern, when <u>looking at the explosion in bank balance</u> sheets, <u>backed up by declining levels of equity</u> and massive borrowing. One of the results was a temporary private-sector-led boom. <u>The other was a massive increase in</u> the world’s financial sector (finance, insurance, real estate – FIRE), often called <u>financialization</u>, and subsequently the financial crisis of 2008–2009. Excessive <u>risk-taking developed into a crisis that was close to</u> <u>bringing the whole financial system to a halt</u>. When the bubble burst, many governments were forced to step in with broad support programmes. <u>Governments caught by the new mind-set</u> (see Sect. 2.4) were <u>intimately involved</u> in all of this. True, there are many examples of serious malpractices within the private financial sector. But <u>had it not been for the systematic</u> <u>deregulation of the banks</u> by governments, <u>with the purpose of stimulating economic growth</u> by issuing more debt, <u>the situation would have been <strong>radically different</u></strong>. The causes behind the crisis were many and varied: – <u>Excessive lending by the banking industry</u> – <u>Lack of action on</u> the part of <u>regulators</u> and central banks to stop (i) <u>excessive lending</u>, (ii) the spread of <u>exotic financial instruments</u> (synthetic assets and bonds, collateralized mortgage obligations/CMOs, structured debt issues, etc.) and (iii) <u>pure speculative transactions</u> – <u>Opaque tax havens</u>, and the absence of a binding legal framework that is accepted and implemented by the international community, in general, and the major jurisdictions and financial centres – <u>Securitization and</u> <u>distribution by investment banks</u> and other financial actors of mortgage-related assets and investment <u>vehicles transferring the credit risk</u> from the original <u>lender to the ultimate</u> <u>bondholders</u> – Failure by some rating agencies and auditing firms to properly assess and report the inherent risks posed by many of the financial products <u>A deeper analysis is presented by</u> <u>economists</u> Anat Admati and Martin Hellwig21 <u>about the main causes behind the financial</u> <u>crisis</u>. Western <u>banks <strong>borrowed far too much</strong> with far too little equit</u>y in their balance sheets to act as a buffer if things went wrong in their business – <u>from trading</u> in <u>the multitrillion-dollar</u> derivatives <u>markets</u> to often reckless lending on real estate. In the decades following the Second World War, banks operated with between 20% and 30% of their liabilities as equity. By 2008, that had shrunk to just 3%. <u>Banks</u> obviously <u>believed</u> that <u>they had invented instruments that</u> <u>removed the risk</u>, allowing them to run their banks with a tenth of the buffer they had before. It proved to be very unrealistic. But <u>they counted with the state to underwrite their risks</u>. Bankers have enriched themselves spectacularly in the process. <u>They made themselves ‘too big to fail’ –</u> and too big to jail. The <u>20<mark>08</mark> financial <mark>crisis was</mark> mostly <mark>caused by</mark> that <strong><mark>irresponsible greed</u></strong></mark>.22 Yet, in 2009, not only did bankers avoid criminal prosecutions and receive hundreds of billions in government bailouts, but some still paid themselves record bonuses. At the same time, almost <u>nine million households</u> in the United States <u>had to abandon their homes</u> when the value of their houses plummeted and they could no longer service the adjustable-rate mortgages – the so-called foreclosure crisis.23 <u>Financialization refers to the dominance of the financial sector</u> in the global economy <u>and</u> the <u>tendency for accumulated profits</u> (and leverage) to flow into real estate and other speculative investment<u>. Debt is an intrinsic element</u> in this process. In the United States, for example, both <u>household debt and private sector <mark>debt</u></mark> more than <u><strong><mark>doubled</u></strong></mark> relative to GDP between 1980 and 2007.24 The same is true for most OECD countries. At the same time, ‘the value of financial assets grew from four times GDP in 1980 to ten times GDP in 2007 and the finance sector’s share of corporate profits grew from about 10% in the early 1980s to almost 40% by 2006’.25 Adair Turner, chair of the UK’s Financial Services Authority in the years following the 2007–2008 crisis, regards unchecked private credit creation as the key system fault that led to that crisis with its devastating consequences.26 From this follows that the financial sector constitutes a significant and increasing risk factor in the economy. The degree of financialization varies from country to country but the increase in the power of finance is general. The current finance sector evolved in the context of the deregulation that gathered pace from the late 1970s and expanded dramatically after the 1999 removal of the separation between commercial and investment banking in the United States.27 This barrier had been put in place in 1933 by the Roosevelt administration in response to the Wall Street Crash of 1929, when a period of rampant credit creation and financial speculation collapsed. Similar speculation preceded the crisis of 2007–2008: The face value of financial products reached US$640 trillion in September 2008, 14 times the GDP of all the countries on earth.28 Lietaer et al.29 compare speculation with ordinary money transfers paying for goods and services: ‘In 2010, the volume of foreign exchange transactions reached $4 trillion per day’, which does not even include derivatives. In comparison, ‘one day’s exports or imports of all goods and services in the world amount to about 2% of those $4 trillion’. Transactions not paying for goods and services, almost by definition are speculative. Such <u><mark>financial products</mark> and transactions</u>, the authors continue, <u><mark>lead</u></mark> regularly <u><mark>to monetary crashes, sovereign debt crises and systemic</mark> <mark>crashes</u> <u>with</u> an</mark> average of <u>more than <mark>ten countries in crisis every year</u></mark>. One of the consequences of this development is that a significant part of economic growth has been distributed to the wealthy, as mentioned with the new Oxfam figures in the previous subchapter. <u>Practices within the financial</u> <u>sector demonstrate a disregard for the impact</u> they have on both people and the planet. <u>That includes a distinct short-termism</u>, the ratio of banks’ reserves to their loans, the ratio of banks’ lending that support the real economy versus speculation in property and derivatives, unchecked credit creation – in fact money creation – and the failure to account for long-term climate and environmental risks. In the words of Otto Scharmer at MIT,30 ‘<u>We have a system</u> <u>that accumulates oversupply of money</u> in areas <u>that produce high financial and low</u> <u>environmental</u> and social <u>returns</u>, while at the same an undersupply of money in areas that serve important societal investment needs’. <u><mark>The</mark> <mark>failure to account for environmental risks</u> <u>means</u></mark> that the <u><mark>pressure on</mark> </u>already scarce <u><mark>natural resources</mark> accelerates</u> – <u><mark>trees</mark> are <mark>felled</mark>,</u> <u><strong><mark>waterways polluted</u></strong>, <u><strong>wetlands drained</strong> and</u></mark> the exploitation of <u>oil, gas and <mark>coal accelerating</u></mark>, as long as there is demand<u>. It also means that huge savings, among them pension funds, are <strong>locked</u></strong> into investments <u>in fossil-based assets</u>. Such <u>assets are increasingly looked upon as high-risk assets</u> (see Sect. 3.4). </p> | null | 3- K | null | 335,486 | 145 | 10,537 | ./documents/hsld21/CardinalGibbons/so/Cardinal%20Gibbons-sosa-Neg-mid%20america%20cup-Round5.docx | 884,460 | N | mid america cup | 5 | saratoga ag | akshay manglik | AC- insulin
NC- T IPP spec IPP dread v4 case
1AR- condo bad vague alts bad all
2NR- K case
2AR- case K | hsld21/CardinalGibbons/so/Cardinal%20Gibbons-sosa-Neg-mid%20america%20cup-Round5.docx | null | 74,463 | roso | Cardinal Gibbons roso | null | ro..... | so..... | null | null | 24,936 | CardinalGibbons | Cardinal Gibbons | FL | null | 1,029 | hsld21 | HS LD 2021-22 | 2,021 | ld | hs | 1 |
606,552 | The plan clarifies customary law to ban private satellite mega-constellations that appropriate Low Earth Orbit and solves otherwise detrimental space debris. | Johnson 20 ] brett | Johnson 20 [Chris, Space Law Advisor for Secure World Foundation, 9 years of professional experience in international space law and policy. J.D. from New York Law School; 2020; “The Legal Status of MegaLEO Constellations and Concerns About Appropriation of Large Swaths of Earth Orbit,” https://swfound.org/media/206951/johnson2020_referenceworkentry_thelegalstatusofmegaleoconstel.pdf] brett | This Is Impermissible Appropriation
Article II of the O S T is clear that the appropriation of outer space, including of void space or of celestial bodies is impermissible and prohibited under international law No means or methods of possession of outer space will legitimize the appropriation or ownership of outer space, or subsections thereof.
Excludes Others
constellations so overwhelmingly possess particular orbits through the use of multiple satellites to occupy orbital planes in a manner that precludes other actors from using those exact planes, constitute an appropriation of those orbits orbits closer to Earth are unique and when any actor utilizes that orbit to such an extent to these proposed constellations will, it means that other actors simply cannot go there
To allow SpaceX to so overwhelmingly occupy a number of altitudes with so many of their spacecraft means that SpaceX will henceforth be the sole owner and user of that orbit No other actors can realistically operate there the sole occupant will be SpaceX then SpaceX appears to be the owner of that orbit
Additionally, SpaceX and other operators of megaconstellations are doing so without any real international conversation or agreement, which is especially egregious and transgressive of the norms of outer space. Compared to the regime for GSO, as administered by the ITU and national frequency administrators, Low Earth Orbit is essentially ungoverned, and SpaceX and others are attempting to seize this lack of authority to claim entire portions of LEO for itself; and before any international agreement, consensus, or even discussion is had. They are operating on a purely “first come, first served” basis that smacks of unilateralism, if not colonialism.
Governments Are Ultimately Implicated
what a nongovernmental entity does, a State is responsible for the prohibition on nonappropriation imposed upon States applies equally to nongovernmental private entities such as SpaceX
through the launching and bringing into use of the Starlink constellation, SpaceX will be the sole occupant, and thereby, possessor, both fact and in law, of 550 km, 1100 km, 1130 km, 1275 km, and 1325 km above our planet or whatever orbits they finally come to occupy The same is true for the other operators of these large constellations which will be solely occupying entire orbits.
Long-Term Occupation Constitutes Appropriation
altitudes are additionally significant the altitudes selected for the Starlink constellation, while technologically desirable for their purposes, also mean that any spacecraft which are not de-orbited from these regions may be there for decades, or possibly even hundreds of years the granting of rights for orbital slots at GSO is in 15-year increments, a length of time much less than what the altitudes of the megaconstellations threaten Such long spans of time at these altitudes by these megaconstellations further bolster the contention that this occupation rises to the level of appropriation of these orbits.
Prevents Others from Using Space
Article I of the O S T establishes that the exploration and use of outer space is “the province of all mankind.” It further requires exploration and use shall be by all States “without discrimination of any kind when one private corporation so overwhelmingly possesses entire portions of outer space, their use is discriminatory to other potential users and interferes with their freedom to access, explore, and use outer space these actors exclude others from using them massive occupation effectively defeats others from enjoying the use of outer space
That these megaconstellations violate the prohibition on appropriation in Article II is additionally supported by Article IX of the Outer Space Treaty. Article IX requires that in the exploration and use of outer space, States “shall be guided by the principle of cooperation and mutual assistance and shall conduct all their activities in outer space... with due regard to the corresponding interests of other States...” There is hardly any way to view this deployment of megaconstellations as showing any type of due regard to the corresponding interests of others. This lack of regard further supports the notion of their unilateral transgressive violations of the purposes of space law norms.
Harmful Contamination
megaconstellations threaten mega-debris failure rate of these comparatively cheap satellites should give pause if 5% of a constellation of 100 satellites fails, this is 5 guaranteed new pieces of debris to the fragile space domain. Article IX of the Outer Space Treaty warns of harmful contamination of the space environment and requires States to take appropriate measures to prevent this harmful contamination. A responsible government could not, in all seriousness, permit the intentional release of such amounts of space debris, especially in the already fraught orbits that many megaconstellations are headed towards. While the threat of space debris is not directly relevant to the accusation of appropriation of outer space, it goes towards the argument that these actors are conducting activities in a manner lacking in regard to others, and in fact, amounts to excluding others from using the space domain. By excluding others, this has the effect of taking orbits for themselves, which IS occupation.
If This Isn’t Appropriation, Then What Is?
if these megaconstellations could be considered to not be appropriation what would be appropriation? What use of void space, including orbits of the Earth, would constitute actual appropriation? the lack of a formal claim of sovereignty should not be the deciding criteria in arriving at the conclusion that megaconstellations constitute appropriation of orbits.
Conclusion
megaconstellations effectively occupy entire orbital regions and preclude other actors from sharing those domains They have done so, or are attempting to do so which is egregious for a domain outside of State sovereignty and which no State can own constellations significantly prevent others from using those regions, which therefore interferes with others’ right to explore and use space this reckless ambition shows absolutely no due regard for the corresponding rights of others these megaconstellations constitute an impermissible appropriation of particular regions of outer space, regardless of any formal, official claim of such by a responsible, authorizing government | appropriation of outer space including void space is impermissible and prohibited
constellations precludes other actors constitute appropriation
to overwhelmingly occupy a number of altitudes means that SpaceX will be the sole owner
Long-Term Occupation Constitutes Appropriation
altitudes mean any spacecraft may be there for decades that rises to the level of appropriation
megaconstellations threaten mega-debris
the lack of formal sovereignty should not be the deciding criteria
megaconstellations constitute an impermissible appropriation of outer space regardless of any formal claim by a responsible, authorizing government | Yes, This Is Impermissible Appropriation
Article II of the Outer Space Treaty, discussed above, is clear on the point that the appropriation of outer space, including the appropriation of either void space or of celestial bodies, is an impermissible and prohibited action under international law. No means or methods of possession of outer space will legitimize the appropriation or ownership of outer space, or subsections thereof.
Excludes Others
The constellations above, because they seem to so overwhelmingly possess particular orbits through the use of multiple satellites to occupy orbital planes, and in a manner that precludes other actors from using those exact planes, constitute an appropriation of those orbits. While the access to outer space is nonrivalrous – in the sense that anyone with the technological capacity to launch space objects can therefore explore space – it is also true that orbits closer to Earth are unique, and when any actor utilizes that orbit to such an extent to these proposed constellations will, it means that other actors simply cannot go there.
To allow SpaceX, for example, to so overwhelmingly occupy a number of altitudes with so many of their spacecraft, essentially means that SpaceX will henceforth be the sole owner and user of that orbit (at least until their satellites are removed). No other actors can realistically expect to operate there until that time. No other operator would dare run the risk of possible collision with so many other spacecraft in that orbit. Consequently, the sole occupant will be SpaceX, and if “possession is 9/10th of the law,” then SpaceX appears to be the owner of that orbit.
Done Without Coordination
Additionally, SpaceX and other operators of megaconstellations are doing so without any real international conversation or agreement, which is especially egregious and transgressive of the norms of outer space. Compared to the regime for GSO, as administered by the ITU and national frequency administrators, Low Earth Orbit is essentially ungoverned, and SpaceX and others are attempting to seize this lack of authority to claim entire portions of LEO for itself; and before any international agreement, consensus, or even discussion is had. They are operating on a purely “first come, first served” basis that smacks of unilateralism, if not colonialism.
Governments Are Ultimately Implicated
As we know, under international space law, what a nongovernmental entity does, a State is responsible for. Article VI of the Outer Space Treaty requires that at least one State authorize and supervise its nongovernmental entities and assure their continuing compliance with international law. As such, the prohibition on nonappropriation imposed upon States under Article II of the Outer Space Treaty applies equally to nongovernmental private entities such as SpaceX.
Nevertheless, through the launching and bringing into use of the Starlink constellation, SpaceX will be the sole occupant, and thereby, possessor, both fact and in law, of 550 km, 1100 km, 1130 km, 1275 km, and 1325 km above our planet (or whatever orbits they finally come to occupy). The same is true for the other operators of these large constellations which will be solely occupying entire orbits.
Long-Term Occupation Constitutes Appropriation
These altitudes are additionally significant, as nonfunctional spacecraft in orbits lower than around 500 km will re-enter the Earth’s atmosphere in months or a few years, but the altitudes selected for the Starlink constellation, while technologically desirable for their purposes, also mean that any spacecraft which are not de-orbited from these regions may be there for decades, or possibly even hundreds of years. By comparison, the granting of rights for orbital slots at GSO is in 15-year increments, a length of time much less than what the altitudes of the megaconstellations threaten. Such long spans of time at these altitudes by these megaconstellations further bolster the contention that this occupation rises to the level of appropriation of these orbits.
Prevents Others from Using Space
Article I of the Outer Space Treaty establishes that the exploration and use of outer space is “the province of all mankind.” It further requires that this exploration and use shall be by all States “without discrimination of any kind, on a basis of equality and in accordance with international law...” However, when one private corporation so overwhelmingly possesses entire portions of outer space, their use is discriminatory to other potential users and interferes with their freedom to access, explore, and use outer space. So long as these actors are so dominantly possessing and occupying those orbits, their actions exclude others from using them. What other operator would dare use orbits where there are already hundreds of satellites operating as part of a constellation? It would be an extremely unwise and risky decision to try to share these orbits with a mega constellation, so they will likely choose other altitudes and orbits. This massive occupation of particular orbits effectively defeats others from enjoying the use of outer space. While a State can issue permits for one of its corporations allowing them to launch and operate satellites to this extent, that does not automatically mean that their activities in outer space, an area beyond national sovereignty, are therefore in perfect accordance with the strictures of international law. Indeed, national permissions offer no such guarantee.
No Due Regard for Others
That these megaconstellations violate the prohibition on appropriation in Article II is additionally supported by Article IX of the Outer Space Treaty. Article IX requires that in the exploration and use of outer space, States “shall be guided by the principle of cooperation and mutual assistance and shall conduct all their activities in outer space... with due regard to the corresponding interests of other States...” There is hardly any way to view this deployment of megaconstellations as showing any type of due regard to the corresponding interests of others. This lack of regard further supports the notion of their unilateral transgressive violations of the purposes of space law norms.
Harmful Contamination
The impacts of the spacecraft on the pressing issue of space debris need not be gone into detail here. Suffice it to say, megaconstellations threaten mega-debris. The failure rate of these comparatively cheap satellites should give pause, because if 5% of a constellation of 100 satellites fails, this is 5 guaranteed new pieces of debris intentionally introduced to the fragile space domain. Article IX of the Outer Space Treaty warns of harmful contamination of the space environment and requires States to take appropriate measures to prevent this harmful contamination. A responsible government could not, in all seriousness, permit the intentional release of such amounts of space debris, especially in the already fraught orbits that many megaconstellations are headed towards. While the threat of space debris is not directly relevant to the accusation of appropriation of outer space, it goes towards the argument that these actors are conducting activities in a manner lacking in regard to others, and in fact, amounts to excluding others from using the space domain. By excluding others, this has the effect of taking orbits for themselves, which IS occupation.
If This Isn’t Appropriation, Then What Is?
Arguing in the alternative, if these megaconstellations — in their dominant occupation of entire orbits in orbital planes with numerous satellites — could be considered (merely for the sake of argument) to not be appropriation, we must therefore ask: what would be appropriation? What use of void space, including orbits of the Earth, would constitute actual appropriation? What further, additional fact of these uses of space, if added to the scenario, would cause that constellation to cross over the line into clearly prohibited appropriation? Perhaps the exact same scenario, but supplemented with an actual, formal claim of sovereignty, issued by a government, is the only element which could be added to megaconstellations which would then cross the threshold into appropriation. However, a formal claim of sovereignty would be merely an act occurring on Earth and would not change any actual facts in the space domain. Consequently, the lack of a formal claim of sovereignty should not be the deciding criteria in arriving at the conclusion that megaconstellations constitute appropriation of orbits.
Conclusion
In conclusion, these megaconstellations effectively occupy entire orbital regions with their vast fleet of spacecraft and in so doing effectively preclude other actors from sharing those domains. They have done so, or are attempting to do so, without any international consensus or discussion, which is most egregious for a domain outside of State sovereignty and which no State can own. Governments will ultimately be responsible for this appropriation, and both are prohibited from appropriating space. In distinction to GSO, their permission to go there means that they could occupy these regions for incredibly long periods — which again shows their appropriation. These constellations significantly prevent others from using those regions, which therefore interferes with others’ right to explore and use space. And ultimately, this reckless ambition shows absolutely no due regard (as per Article IX) for the corresponding rights of others. As such, these megaconstellations constitute an impermissible appropriation of particular regions of outer space, regardless of any formal, official claim of such by a responsible, authorizing government. | 9,754 | <h4>The plan <u>clarifies</u> customary law to <u>ban</u> private satellite <u>mega</u>-constellations that <u>appropriate</u> Low Earth Orbit and solves <u>otherwise detrimental</u> space debris.</h4><p><strong>Johnson 20</strong> [Chris, Space Law Advisor for Secure World Foundation, 9 years of professional experience in international space law and policy. J.D. from New York Law School; 2020; “The Legal Status of MegaLEO Constellations and Concerns About Appropriation of Large Swaths of Earth Orbit,” https://swfound.org/media/206951/johnson2020_referenceworkentry_thelegalstatusofmegaleoconstel.pdf<u><strong>] brett</p><p></u></strong>Yes, <u><strong>This Is Impermissible Appropriation</p><p></strong>Article II of the</u> <u><strong>O</u></strong>uter <u><strong>S</u></strong>pace <u><strong>T</u></strong>reaty, discussed above, <u>is clear</u> on the point <u>that the <strong><mark>appropriation of outer space</strong></mark>, <mark>including</u></mark> the appropriation <u>of</u> either <u><strong><mark>void space</strong></mark> or of celestial bodies</u>, <u><mark>is</u></mark> an <u><strong><mark>impermissible</strong></mark> <mark>and</mark> <strong><mark>prohibited</u></strong></mark> action <u><strong>under international law</u></strong>. <u><strong>No means</strong> or methods of <strong>possession</strong> of outer space will legitimize the <strong>appropriation</strong> or ownership of outer space, or subsections thereof<strong>.</p><p>Excludes Others</p><p></u></strong>The <u><strong><mark>constellations</u></strong></mark> above, because they seem to <u>so overwhelmingly possess particular orbits through the use of multiple satellites to occupy orbital planes</u>, and <u>in a manner that <strong><mark>precludes other actors</strong></mark> from using those exact planes, <mark>constitute</mark> an <strong><mark>appropriation</strong></mark> of those orbits</u>. While the access to outer space is nonrivalrous – in the sense that anyone with the technological capacity to launch space objects can therefore explore space – it is also true that <u><strong>orbits closer to Earth are unique</u></strong>, <u>and when any actor utilizes that orbit to such an extent to these proposed <strong>constellations</strong> will, it means that other actors simply cannot go there</u>.</p><p><u>To allow <strong>SpaceX</u></strong>, for example, <u><mark>to</mark> so <mark>overwhelmingly occupy a <strong>number of altitudes</strong></mark> with so many of their spacecraft</u>, essentially <u><mark>means that SpaceX will</mark> henceforth <mark>be the <strong>sole owner</strong></mark> and user of that orbit</u> (at least until their satellites are removed). <u>No other actors can realistically</u> expect to <u><strong>operate</strong> there</u> until that time. No other operator would dare run the risk of possible collision with so many other spacecraft in that orbit. Consequently, <u>the sole occupant will be SpaceX</u>, and if “possession is 9/10th of the law,” <u>then SpaceX appears to be the owner of that orbit</u>.</p><p>Done Without Coordination</p><p><u><strong>Additionally, SpaceX and other operators of megaconstellations are doing so without any real international conversation or agreement, which is especially egregious and transgressive of the norms of outer space. Compared to the regime for GSO, as administered by the ITU and national frequency administrators, Low Earth Orbit is essentially ungoverned, and SpaceX and others are attempting to seize this lack of authority to claim entire portions of LEO for itself; and before any international agreement, consensus, or even discussion is had. They are operating on a purely “first come, first served” basis that smacks of unilateralism, if not colonialism.</p><p>Governments Are Ultimately Implicated</p><p></u></strong>As we know, under international space law, <u>what a nongovernmental entity does, a State is responsible for</u>. Article VI of the Outer Space Treaty requires that at least one State authorize and supervise its nongovernmental entities and assure their continuing compliance with international law. As such, <u>the prohibition on nonappropriation imposed upon States</u> under Article II of the Outer Space Treaty <u><strong>applies equally to nongovernmental private entities such as SpaceX</u></strong>.</p><p>Nevertheless, <u>through the launching and bringing into use of the Starlink constellation, SpaceX will be the sole occupant, and thereby, possessor, both fact and in law, of 550 km, 1100 km, 1130 km, 1275 km, and 1325 km above our planet</u> (<u>or whatever orbits they finally come to occupy</u>). <u>The same is true for the other operators of these large constellations which will be solely occupying entire orbits<strong>.</p><p><mark>Long-Term Occupation Constitutes Appropriation</p><p></u></strong></mark>These <u>altitudes are additionally significant</u>, as nonfunctional spacecraft in orbits lower than around 500 km will re-enter the Earth’s atmosphere in months or a few years, but <u>the <mark>altitudes</mark> selected for the Starlink constellation, while technologically desirable for their purposes, also <mark>mean</mark> that <mark>any spacecraft</mark> which are not de-orbited from these regions <mark>may be there for <strong>decades</strong></mark>, or possibly even hundreds of years</u>. By comparison, <u>the granting of rights for orbital slots at GSO is in 15-year increments, a length of time much less than what the altitudes of the megaconstellations threaten</u>. <u>Such long spans of time at these altitudes by these megaconstellations further bolster the contention <mark>that</mark> this occupation <mark>rises to the level of <strong>appropriation</strong></mark> of these orbits<strong>.</p><p>Prevents Others from Using Space</p><p></strong>Article I of the</u> <u>O</u>uter <u>S</u>pace <u>T</u>reaty <u>establishes that the exploration and use of outer space is “the province of all mankind.”</u> <u>It further requires</u> that this <u>exploration and use shall be by all States “without discrimination of any kind</u>, on a basis of equality and in accordance with international law...” However, <u>when one private corporation so overwhelmingly possesses entire portions of outer space, their use is discriminatory to other potential users and interferes with their freedom to access, explore, and use outer space</u>. So long as <u>these actors</u> are so dominantly possessing and occupying those orbits, their actions <u>exclude others from using them</u>. What other operator would dare use orbits where there are already hundreds of satellites operating as part of a constellation? It would be an extremely unwise and risky decision to try to share these orbits with a mega constellation, so they will likely choose other altitudes and orbits. This <u><strong>massive occupation</u></strong> of particular orbits <u>effectively defeats others from enjoying the use of outer space</u>. While a State can issue permits for one of its corporations allowing them to launch and operate satellites to this extent, that does not automatically mean that their activities in outer space, an area beyond national sovereignty, are therefore in perfect accordance with the strictures of international law. Indeed, national permissions offer no such guarantee.</p><p>No Due Regard for Others</p><p><u><strong>That these megaconstellations violate the prohibition on appropriation in Article II is additionally supported by Article IX of the Outer Space Treaty. Article IX requires that in the exploration and use of outer space, States “shall be guided by the principle of cooperation and mutual assistance and shall conduct all their activities in outer space... with due regard to the corresponding interests of other States...” There is hardly any way to view this deployment of megaconstellations as showing any type of due regard to the corresponding interests of others. This lack of regard further supports the notion of their unilateral transgressive violations of the purposes of space law norms.</p><p>Harmful Contamination</p><p></u></strong>The impacts of the spacecraft on the pressing issue of space debris need not be gone into detail here. Suffice it to say, <u><strong><mark>megaconstellations</strong> threaten <strong>mega-debris</u></strong></mark>. The <u>failure rate of these comparatively cheap satellites should give pause</u>, because <u>if 5% of a constellation of 100 satellites fails, this is 5 guaranteed new pieces of debris</u> intentionally introduced <u>to the fragile space domain<strong>. Article IX of the Outer Space Treaty warns of harmful contamination of the space environment and requires States to take appropriate measures to prevent this harmful contamination. A responsible government could not, in all seriousness, permit the intentional release of such amounts of space debris, especially in the already fraught orbits that many megaconstellations are headed towards. While the threat of space debris is not directly relevant to the accusation of appropriation of outer space, it goes towards the argument that these actors are conducting activities in a manner lacking in regard to others, and in fact, amounts to excluding others from using the space domain. By excluding others, this has the effect of taking orbits for themselves, which IS occupation.</p><p>If This Isn’t Appropriation, Then What Is?</p><p></u></strong>Arguing in the alternative, <u>if these megaconstellations</u> — in their dominant occupation of entire orbits in orbital planes with numerous satellites — <u>could be considered</u> (merely for the sake of argument) <u>to not be appropriation</u>, we must therefore ask: <u>what would be appropriation?</u> <u>What use of <strong>void space</strong>, including orbits of the Earth, would <strong>constitute actual appropriation</strong>?</u> What further, additional fact of these uses of space, if added to the scenario, would cause that constellation to cross over the line into clearly prohibited appropriation? Perhaps the exact same scenario, but supplemented with an actual, formal claim of sovereignty, issued by a government, is the only element which could be added to megaconstellations which would then cross the threshold into appropriation. However, a formal claim of sovereignty would be merely an act occurring on Earth and would not change any actual facts in the space domain. Consequently, <u><mark>the lack of</mark> a <strong><mark>formal</strong></mark> claim of <strong><mark>sovereignty</strong></mark> <mark>should not be the deciding criteria</mark> in arriving at the conclusion that megaconstellations constitute appropriation of orbits<strong>.</p><p>Conclusion</p><p></u></strong>In conclusion, these <u>megaconstellations effectively occupy entire orbital regions</u> with their vast fleet of spacecraft <u>and</u> in so doing effectively <u>preclude other actors from sharing those domains</u>. <u>They have done so, or are attempting to do so</u>, without any international consensus or discussion, <u>which is</u> most <u>egregious for a domain outside of State sovereignty and which no State can own</u>. Governments will ultimately be responsible for this appropriation, and both are prohibited from appropriating space. In distinction to GSO, their permission to go there means that they could occupy these regions for incredibly long periods — which again shows their appropriation. These <u>constellations significantly prevent others from using those regions, which therefore interferes with others’ right to explore and use space</u>. And ultimately, <u>this reckless ambition shows absolutely no due regard</u> (as per Article IX) <u>for the corresponding rights of others</u>. As such, <u>these <strong><mark>megaconstellations</strong></mark> <mark>constitute an <strong>impermissible</strong> appropriation of</mark> <strong>particular regions</strong> of <strong><mark>outer space</strong></mark>, <mark>regardless of any formal</mark>, official <mark>claim</mark> of such <strong><mark>by a responsible, authorizing government</u></strong></mark>.</p> | 1AC---Debris // Constellations | null | Plan | 339,322 | 150 | 10,587 | ./documents/hsld21/CarnegieVanguard/Hu/Carnegie%20Vanguard-Huang-Aff-University%20of%20Houston%20Cougar%20Classic-Octas.docx | 884,611 | A | University of Houston Cougar Classic | Octas | Dulles VN | Panel | 1ac - constellations
1nc - uv theory kant truth testing
1ar - all
2nr - uv theory
2ar - uv theory | hsld21/CarnegieVanguard/Hu/Carnegie%20Vanguard-Huang-Aff-University%20of%20Houston%20Cougar%20Classic-Octas.docx | null | 74,467 | LaHu | Carnegie Vanguard LaHu | null | La..... | Hu..... | null | null | 24,939 | CarnegieVanguard | Carnegie Vanguard | TX | null | 1,029 | hsld21 | HS LD 2021-22 | 2,021 | ld | hs | 1 |
1,523,798 | Mining creates space debris | Boley and Byers 20 | Boley and Byers 20 (Arron, Department of Physics and Astronomy, University of British Columbia; Michael, Department of Political Science, University of British Columbia) U.S. policy puts the safe development of space at risk, SCIENCE, 9 Oct 2020, Vol 370, Issue 6513, pp. 174-175 https://www.science.org/doi/full/10.1126/science.abd3402 EE | Mining can generate serious operational concerns. Lunar dust is a known challenge to operations on the Moon Any surface activity could exacerbate lunar dust migration, including by lofting dust onto trajectories that cross lunar orbits, such as that of NASA's proposed Lunar Gateway without cooperation by all actors, the limited number of useful lunar orbits could quickly become filled with space debris.
On asteroids, low escape speeds will make it difficult to prevent the loss of surface material. Mining could also lead to uncontrolled outbursts of volatile sublimation after the removal of surface layers Because the asteroids targeted for mining are likely to be those with small minimum orbit intersection distances, the resulting meteoroid debris streams could threaten lunar operations as well as satellites in Earth's orbit In a worst-case scenario, a trajectory change resulting from mining could eventually lead to an Earth-impact emergency
Space missions already provide some evidence of these risks a small impactor was used to make a crater on (162173) Ryugu (13). In 2022, NASA will test its ability to deflect an asteroid by striking (65803) Didymos B (Dimorphos) with the Double Asteroid Redirection Test spacecraft. This impact will produce anthropogenic meteoroids, with the possibility of immediate delivery to Earth (14). | Mining can generate serious operational concerns Any surface activity could loft dust onto trajectories that cross lunar orbits useful lunar orbits could quickly become filled with debris
On asteroids, low escape speeds make it difficult to prevent loss of surface material Mining could lead to uncontrolled bursts of sublimation the resulting debris streams could threaten lunar operations as well as satellites a trajectory change could lead to an Earth-impact emergency
Space missions already provide evidence a small impactor was used to make a crater on Ryugu | Mining can generate serious operational concerns. Lunar dust is a known challenge to operations on the Moon. Any surface activity could exacerbate lunar dust migration, including by lofting dust onto trajectories that cross lunar orbits, such as that of NASA's proposed Lunar Gateway (11). Moreover, without cooperation by all actors, the limited number of useful lunar orbits could quickly become filled with space debris.
On asteroids, low escape speeds will make it difficult to prevent the loss of surface material. Even if full enclosures are used, waste material may be purposefully jettisoned. Mining could also lead to uncontrolled outbursts of volatile sublimation after the removal of surface layers. Because the asteroids targeted for mining are likely to be those with small minimum orbit intersection distances, the resulting meteoroid debris streams could threaten lunar operations as well as satellites in Earth's orbit (12). In a worst-case scenario, a trajectory change resulting from mining could eventually lead to an Earth-impact emergency.
Space missions already provide some evidence of these risks. In 2019, during the course of Japan's Hayabusa2 mission, a small impactor was used to make a crater on (162173) Ryugu (13). Some of the resulting anthropogenic meteoroids could begin reaching Earth during the 2033 apparition. In 2022, NASA will test its ability to deflect an asteroid by striking (65803) Didymos B (Dimorphos) with the Double Asteroid Redirection Test spacecraft. This impact will produce anthropogenic meteoroids, with the possibility of immediate delivery to Earth (14). Although these risks are small, they demonstrate how easily human actions can change the near-Earth environment. | 1,724 | <h4>Mining creates space debris</h4><p><strong>Boley and Byers 20</strong> (Arron, Department of Physics and Astronomy, University of British Columbia; Michael, Department of Political Science, University of British Columbia) U.S. policy puts the safe development of space at risk, SCIENCE, 9 Oct 2020, Vol 370, Issue 6513, pp. 174-175 https://www.science.org/doi/full/10.1126/science.abd3402<u> EE</p><p><mark>Mining can generate <strong>serious operational concerns</strong></mark>. <strong>Lunar dust is a known challenge</strong> to operations on the Moon</u>. <u><mark>Any surface activity could </mark>exacerbate lunar dust migration, including by <mark>loft</mark>ing <mark>dust</mark> <mark>onto trajectories that cross lunar orbits</mark>, such as that of NASA's proposed Lunar Gateway</u> (11). Moreover, <u>without cooperation by all actors, the limited number of <mark>useful lunar orbits could quickly become filled with</mark> space <mark>debris</mark>.</p><p><mark>On asteroids, low escape speeds</mark> will <mark>make it difficult to prevent</mark> the <mark>loss of surface material</mark>.</u> Even if full enclosures are used, waste material may be purposefully jettisoned. <u><mark>Mining could</mark> also <mark>lead to uncontrolled</mark> out<mark>bursts</mark> <mark>of</mark> volatile <mark>sublimation</mark> after the removal of surface layers</u>. <u>Because the asteroids targeted for mining are likely to be those with small minimum orbit intersection distances, <mark>the resulting</mark> meteoroid <mark>debris streams could threaten lunar operations</mark> <strong><mark>as well as satellites</strong></mark> in Earth's orbit</u> (12). <u>In a worst-case scenario, <mark>a trajectory change</mark> resulting from mining <mark>could</mark> eventually <mark>lead to an Earth-impact emergency</u></mark>.</p><p><u><mark>Space missions already provide </mark>some <mark>evidence</mark> of these risks</u>. In 2019, during the course of Japan's Hayabusa2 mission, <u><mark>a small impactor was used to make a crater</mark> <mark>on</mark> (162173) <mark>Ryugu</mark> (13).</u> Some of the resulting anthropogenic meteoroids could begin reaching Earth during the 2033 apparition. <u>In 2022, NASA will test its ability to deflect an asteroid by striking (65803) Didymos B (Dimorphos) with the Double Asteroid Redirection Test spacecraft. This impact will produce anthropogenic meteoroids, with the possibility of immediate delivery to Earth (14).</u> Although these risks are small, they demonstrate how easily human actions can change the near-Earth environment.</p> | Round 2 – AC UNLV | 1AC—Advantages | Advantage – Collisions | 346,832 | 120 | 43,370 | ./documents/hsld21/Portola/Si/Portola-Singh-Aff-UNLV-Round6.docx | 896,841 | A | UNLV | 6 | Harker SS | Gibson, Bobby | AC - mining
NC - Ptx da regs cp case
ar - all
2nr - da cp case
2ar - same | hsld21/Portola/Si/Portola-Singh-Aff-UNLV-Round6.docx | null | 75,248 | AmSi | Portola AmSi | null | Am..... | Si..... | null | null | 25,133 | Portola | Portola | CA | null | 1,029 | hsld21 | HS LD 2021-22 | 2,021 | ld | hs | 1 |
912,165 | Goes nuclear. | Klare 19 | Klare 19—(professor emeritus of peace and world security studies at Hampshire College). Michael Klare. November 2019. “Cyber Battles, Nuclear Outcomes? Dangerous New Pathways to Escalation.” Arms Control Association. https://www.armscontrol.org/act/2019-11/features/cyber-battles-nuclear-outcomes-dangerous-new-pathways-escalation. | escalation could arise from a cascading series of cyberstrikes against vital national infrastructure All major powers have developed and deployed cyberweapons designed to disrupt and destroy major elements of an adversary’s key economic systems, such as power grids Russia has infiltrated the U.S. electrical grid
economic attacks of this sort could lead to an escalating series of tit-for-tat attacks against ever more vital elements of an adversary’s critical infrastructure, producing widespread chaos and harm and leading one side to initiate kinetic attacks on critical military targets, risking the slippery slope to nuclear conflict. a Russian cyberattack on the U.S. power grid could trigger U.S. attacks on Russian energy and financial systems, causing widespread disorder in both countries and generating an impulse for even more devastating attacks. such attacks “could lead to major conflict and possibly nuclear war.” | escalation arise from cascading cyberstrikes against vital infrastructure All powers have developed cyberweapons to destroy grids
economic attacks lead to tit-for-tat attacks leading to kinetic attacks risking slippery slope to nuclear conflict Russian cyberattack on grid could trigger attacks on Russian systems, causing disorder and an impulse for more devastating attacks lead to nuclear war.” | Yet another pathway to escalation could arise from a cascading series of cyberstrikes and counterstrikes against vital national infrastructure rather than on military targets. All major powers, along with Iran and North Korea, have developed and deployed cyberweapons designed to disrupt and destroy major elements of an adversary’s key economic systems, such as power grids, financial systems, and transportation networks. As noted, Russia has infiltrated the U.S. electrical grid, and it is widely believed that the United States has done the same in Russia.12 The Pentagon has also devised a plan known as “Nitro Zeus,” intended to immobilize the entire Iranian economy and so force it to capitulate to U.S. demands or, if that approach failed, to pave the way for a crippling air and missile attack.13
The danger here is that economic attacks of this sort, if undertaken during a period of tension and crisis, could lead to an escalating series of tit-for-tat attacks against ever more vital elements of an adversary’s critical infrastructure, producing widespread chaos and harm and eventually leading one side to initiate kinetic attacks on critical military targets, risking the slippery slope to nuclear conflict. For example, a Russian cyberattack on the U.S. power grid could trigger U.S. attacks on Russian energy and financial systems, causing widespread disorder in both countries and generating an impulse for even more devastating attacks. At some point, such attacks “could lead to major conflict and possibly nuclear war.”14 | 1,541 | <h4>Goes nuclear.</h4><p><strong>Klare 19</strong>—(professor emeritus of peace and world security studies at Hampshire College). Michael Klare. November 2019. “Cyber Battles, Nuclear Outcomes? Dangerous New Pathways to Escalation.” Arms Control Association. https://www.armscontrol.org/act/2019-11/features/cyber-battles-nuclear-outcomes-dangerous-new-pathways-escalation.</p><p>Yet another pathway to <u><strong><mark>escalation</mark> could <mark>arise from </mark>a <mark>cascading</mark> series of <mark>cyberstrikes</u></strong></mark> and counterstrikes <u><strong><mark>against vital</mark> national <mark>infrastructure</mark> </u></strong>rather than on military targets. <u><strong><mark>All</mark> major <mark>powers</u></strong></mark>, along with Iran and North Korea, <u><strong><mark>have developed</mark> and deployed <mark>cyberweapons</mark> designed <mark>to</mark> disrupt and <mark>destroy</mark> major elements of an adversary’s key economic systems, such as power <mark>grids</u></strong></mark>, financial systems, and transportation networks. As noted, <u><strong>Russia has infiltrated the U.S. electrical grid</u></strong>, and it is widely believed that the United States has done the same in Russia.12 The Pentagon has also devised a plan known as “Nitro Zeus,” intended to immobilize the entire Iranian economy and so force it to capitulate to U.S. demands or, if that approach failed, to pave the way for a crippling air and missile attack.13</p><p>The danger here is that<u><strong> <mark>economic attacks</mark> of this sort</u></strong>, if undertaken during a period of tension and crisis, <u><strong>could <mark>lead to</mark> an escalating series of <mark>tit-for-tat attacks</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>against ever more vital elements of an adversary’s critical infrastructure, producing widespread chaos and harm and</u></strong> eventually <u><strong><mark>leading</mark> one side <mark>to</mark> initiate <mark>kinetic attacks</mark> on critical military targets, <mark>risking</mark> the <mark>slippery slope to nuclear conflict</mark>.</u></strong> For example, <u><strong>a <mark>Russian cyberattack on</mark> the U.S. power <mark>grid</mark> <mark>could trigger</mark> U.S. <mark>attacks on Russian</mark> energy and financial <mark>systems, causing</mark> widespread <mark>disorder</mark> in both countries <mark>and</mark> generating <mark>an impulse for</mark> even <mark>more devastating attacks</mark>.</u></strong> At some point, <u><strong>such attacks “could <mark>lead to</mark> major conflict and possibly <mark>nuclear war.”</u></strong></mark>14</p> | null | 1NC | 4 | 55 | 1,568 | 22,197 | ./documents/ndtceda21/Minnesota/AmPr/Minnesota-Amundsen-Prost-Neg-Harvard-Round1.docx | 626,027 | N | Harvard | 1 | Emory PR | David Bernstein | 1AC - Worker Welfare
1NC - States CP Chilling DA Infrastructure DA WTO CP CWS DA Monopsony Turn Dual Enforcement Turn
Block - Chilling DA Infrastructure DA Monopsony Turn Dual Enforcement Turn
2NR - Infrastructure DA | ndtceda21/Minnesota/AmPr/Minnesota-Amundsen-Prost-Neg-Harvard-Round1.docx | null | 52,794 | AmPr | Minnesota AmPr | null | Ab..... | Am..... | Ca..... | Pr..... | 19,401 | Minnesota | Minnesota | null | null | 1,011 | ndtceda21 | NDT/CEDA 2021-22 | 2,021 | cx | college | 2 |
1,045,704 | 6. 2007 crisis thumps. | Puma 17 | Dr. Michael Puma 17, research scientist at the NASA Goddard Institute for Space Studies and a Center for Climate and Life Fellow; Peter de Menocal, dean of science at Columbia University and director of the Center for Climate and Life; 3/2/2017, “Trump’s Unifying Opportunity: Food Security,” https://news.climate.columbia.edu/2017/03/02/trumps-unifying-opportunity-food-security/, pacc | U.S. trade inevitably changes food security the U.S. is a world superpower to global food production
A minor disruption in U.S. food supply could produce cascading effects that spread rapidly and cause a major shock to the system The world experienced this during the global food crisis of 2007/2008 Wheat and corn prices doubled
“tipping points” leading to such crises are unpredictable Yet the severe effects are clear the 2007/2008 crisis was not isolated to the developing world | U.S. trade changes food security the U.S. is a superpower to global production
A minor disruption in U.S. supply cascading rapidly and cause a shock
tipping points are unpredictable Importantly, the 2007 crisis was not isolated in the U.S., food prices spiked, leading to hardship | The reality is that Trump’s coming transformation of U.S. trade policies will inevitably lead to changes in food security that dwarf even the most substantial of outcomes from the bipartisan Global Food Security Act. Why? First, the U.S. is a world superpower when it comes to global food production, so any shift in U.S. agriculture policy can have significant consequences both at home and abroad. But there is more to the story than just U.S. trade policy changes.
It turns out that our global food system is highly sensitive — even to small changes. A minor disruption in the U.S. food supply could potentially produce cascading effects that spread rapidly and cause a major shock to the system. The world experienced this type of sensitivity firsthand when, much like a flu epidemic, food riots spread from country to country in Africa and other developing countries during the global food crisis of 2007/2008. Wheat and corn prices doubled over about two years prior to the crisis, and rice prices tripled over just a few months in late 2007 and early 2008.
Economists continue to debate what caused these price spikes, offering explanations that include long-run drivers like greater biofuel demand and changes in Asian diets together with short-run factors such as trade restrictions, speculation, and depreciation of the U.S. dollar, hoarding, and panic purchases.
Unfortunately, it turns out that “tipping points” leading to such crises (a term popularized by the author Malcolm Gladwell) are generally unpredictable. Yet the severe effects of the food-price spike, which included increases in poverty and malnourishment as well as violent protests in multiple countries, are clear. Importantly, the 2007/2008 crisis was not isolated to the developing world. Even in the U.S., food prices spiked, leading to hardship for many everyday Americans. | 1,855 | <h4>6. 2007 crisis thumps.</h4><p>Dr. Michael <strong>Puma 17</strong>, research scientist at the NASA Goddard Institute for Space Studies and a Center for Climate and Life Fellow; Peter de Menocal, dean of science at Columbia University and director of the Center for Climate and Life; 3/2/2017, “Trump’s Unifying Opportunity: Food Security,” https://news.climate.columbia.edu/2017/03/02/trumps-unifying-opportunity-food-security/, pacc </p><p>The reality is that Trump’s coming transformation of <u><strong><mark>U.S. trade</u></strong></mark> policies will <u><strong>inevitably</u></strong> lead to <u><mark>changes</u></mark> in <u><mark>food security</u></mark> that dwarf even the most substantial of outcomes from the bipartisan Global Food Security Act. Why? First, <u><mark>the U.S. is <strong>a</mark> world <mark>superpower</u></strong></mark> when it comes <u><mark>to <strong>global</mark> food <mark>production</u></strong></mark>, so any shift in U.S. agriculture policy can have significant consequences both at home and abroad. But there is more to the story than just U.S. trade policy changes.</p><p>It turns out that our global food system is highly sensitive — even to small changes. <u><strong><mark>A minor disruption</strong> in</u></mark> the <u><strong><mark>U.S.</mark> food <mark>supply</strong></mark> could</u> potentially <u>produce <strong><mark>cascading</mark> effects</strong> that <strong>spread <mark>rapidly</strong> and cause <strong>a</mark> major <mark>shock</strong></mark> to the system</u>. <u>The world experienced this</u> type of sensitivity firsthand when, much like a flu epidemic, food riots spread from country to country in Africa and other developing countries <u>during <strong>the global food crisis</strong> of <strong>2007/2008</u></strong>. <u>Wheat and corn <strong>prices doubled</u></strong> over about two years prior to the crisis, and rice prices tripled over just a few months in late 2007 and early 2008.</p><p>Economists continue to debate what caused these price spikes, offering explanations that include long-run drivers like greater biofuel demand and changes in Asian diets together with short-run factors such as trade restrictions, speculation, and depreciation of the U.S. dollar, hoarding, and panic purchases.</p><p>Unfortunately, it turns out that <u>“<strong><mark>tipping points</strong></mark>” leading to such crises</u> (a term popularized by the author Malcolm Gladwell) <u><mark>are</u></mark> generally <u><strong><mark>unpredictable</u></strong></mark>. <u>Yet <strong>the severe effects</u></strong> of the food-price spike, which included increases in poverty and malnourishment as well as violent protests in multiple countries, <u>are clear</u>. <mark>Importantly, <u>the 2007</mark>/2008 <mark>crisis was <strong>not isolated</strong></mark> to the developing world</u>. Even <mark>in the U.S., food prices spiked, leading to hardship</mark> for many everyday Americans.</p> | null | Regulation | 1NC – Ag Collapse – T/L | 26,376 | 255 | 25,284 | ./documents/hspolicy21/Bellarmine/IyGo/Bellarmine-Iyengar-Gorthi-Neg-2%20-%20Greenhill-Octas.docx | 743,963 | N | 2 - Greenhill | Octas | New Trier JW | Panel | 1AC - Fracking
2NR - Infrastructure DA States CP | hspolicy21/Bellarmine/IyGo/Bellarmine-Iyengar-Gorthi-Neg-2%20-%20Greenhill-Octas.docx | null | 63,367 | IyGo | Bellarmine IyGo | null | Ak..... | Iy..... | Ra..... | Go..... | 21,887 | Bellarmine | Bellarmine | CA | null | 1,020 | hspolicy21 | HS Policy 2021-22 | 2,021 | cx | hs | 2 |
4,760,011 | Terrorism causes global nuclear war – draw in, economic depression, and social unrest. | Arguello & Buis 18 | Arguello & Buis 18 (Irma Arguello & Emiliano J. Buis, 2-21-2018, "The global impacts of a terrorist nuclear attack: What would happen? What should we do?," Taylor & Francis, https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/full/10.1080/00963402.2018.1436812) // Han | terrorism can occur anywhere, at any time
the detonation of a nuclear device–by states or non-state actors–is today a plausible scenario the threat of nuclear terrorism is here and increasing. For more than a decade, Al Qaeda, Aum Shinrikyo, and other terrorist groups have expressed their desire to acquire fissile mate-rial to build and detonate an improvised nuclear bomb
there is evidence of an illicit market for nuclear weapons-usable materials. There are sellers in search of potential buyers, as shown by the dismantlement of a nuclear smuggling network in Moldova in 2015 no country in possession of nuclear weapons or weapons-usable materials can guarantee their full protection against nuclear terrorism or nuclear smuggling
consequences would go far beyond the effects in the target country national security, economy international governance political systems, and the behavior of governments and individuals would all be put under severe trial. , would depend on the countries’ level of development, geopolitical location, and resilience.
increase in global distrust would spark rising tensions among countries and blocs, that could even lead to the brink of nuclear weapons use by states a decrease in states’ self-control, an escalation of present conflicts and the emergence of new ones, accompanied by an increase in military unilateralism and military expenditures.
a severe global economic depression would rise lasting for years 2 percent fall of growth in global Gross Domestic Product, and a4 percent decline of international trade in the two years following the attack (cf. Figure 3). In the case of developing and less-developed countries, the economic impacts would also include a shortage of high-technology products such as medicines, as well as a fall in foreign direct investment and a severe decline of inter-national humanitarian aid toward low-income countries about 4 percent after the attack, which implies that at least 30 million more people would be living in extreme poverty, in addition to the current estimated 767 million.
collapse of the nuclear order as we know it today, with a consequent setback of nuclear disarmament and nonproliferation commitments. In other words, the whole system based on the Nuclear Non- Proliferation Treaty would be put under severe trial. After the attack, there would be a re-assessment of existing security doctrines, and a deep review of concepts such as nuclear deterrence, no-first-use, proportionality, and negative security assurances.
Internal chaos fueled by the media and social networks would threaten governance at all levels, with greater impact on those countries with weak institutional frameworks. Social turbulence would emerge in most countries, with con-sequent attempts by governments to impose restrictions on personal freedoms to preserve order–possibly by declaring a state of siege or state of emergency–and legislation would surely become tougher on human rights. There would also be a significant increase in social fragmentation–with a deepening of antagonistic views, mistrust, and intolerance, both within countries and towards others–and a resurgence of large-scale social movements fostered by ideological interests and easily mobilized through social media | terrorism can occur anywhere, at any time
detonation of a nuclear device–by non-state actors–is a plausible scenario the threat of nuclear terrorism is here and increasing terrorist groups have expressed desire to acquire fissile mate-rial to build and detonate an improvised nuclear bomb
sellers in search of potential buyers shown by the smuggling network in Moldova no country can guarantee their full protection against nuclear terrorism or nuclear smuggling
consequences would go beyond the target country national security, economy international governance political systems, and behavior of governments and individuals would be under severe trial
increase in global distrust spark rising tensions among countries and blocs, that even lead to nuclear weapons use a decrease in states’ self-control escalation of present conflicts emergence of new ones, accompanied by an increase in military unilateralism
a severe global economic depression would rise lasting for years
collapse of the nuclear order with a setback of nuclear disarmament and nonproliferation commitments
Internal chaos fueled by the media and social networks threaten governance increase in social fragmentation deepening of antagonistic views, mistrust, and intolerance within countries and towards others | ABSTRACT As seen by recent events such as the bombing in Manchester, UK, terrorism can occur anywhere, at any time. So far, the terrorist incidents have been relatively low-tech–such as improvised explosive devices detonating inside pressure cookers, trucks driving down crowded sidewalks, or bombs exploding in backpacks containing metal bolts and screws. But what if terrorists were to build a dirty bomb that contained radioactive materials instead of bits of metal shrapnel, and set it off in a major city? Or, worse, what if they managed to build a fully functioning nuclear weapon, cart it to the downtown of a city, and then detonate it–even a small, rudimentary one that was much smaller than the atomic bomb dropped on Hiroshima? What would the social, economic, and political impacts of the successful terrorist use of a nuclear weapon look like? What planning has the international community done for such an event?
Though hard to accept, the detonation of a nuclear device–by states or non-state actors–is today a plausible scenario. And while much of the world’s focus has been on the current nuclear weapons arsenals possessed by states–about 14,550 warheads, all of which carry the risk of intentional or unintentional use–the threat of nuclear terrorism is here and increasing. For more than a decade, Al Qaeda, Aum Shinrikyo, and other terrorist groups have expressed their desire to acquire fissile mate-rial to build and detonate an improvised nuclear bomb. None of them could fulfill that goal–so far. But that does not mean that they will not succeed in the future.
Making matters worse, there is evidence of an illicit market for nuclear weapons-usable materials. There are sellers in search of potential buyers, as shown by the dismantlement of a nuclear smuggling network in Moldova in 2015. There certainly are plenty of sites from which to obtain nuclear material. According to the 2016 Nuclear Security Index by the Nuclear Threat Initiative, 24 countries still host inventories of nuclear weapons-usable materials, stored in facilities with different degrees of security. And in terms of risk, it is not necessary for a given country to possess nuclear weapons, weapons-usable materials, or nuclear facilities for it to be useful to nuclear terrorists: Structural and institutional weaknesses in a country may make it favorable for the illicit trade of materials. Permeable boundaries, high levels of corruption, weaknesses in judicial systems, and consequent impunity may give rise to a series of transactions and other events, which could end in a nuclear attack. The truth is that, at this stage, no country in possession of nuclear weapons or weapons-usable materials can guarantee their full protection against nuclear terrorism or nuclear smuggling. Because we live in a world of growing insecurity, where explicit and tacit agreements between the relevant powers–which upheld global stability during the post-Cold War–are giving way to increasing mistrust and hostility, a question arises: How would our lives be affected if a current terrorist group such as the Islamic State (ISIS), or new terrorist groups in the future, succeed in evolving from today’s Manchester style “low-tech” attacks to a “high-tech” one, involving a nuclear bomb, detonated in a capital city, anywhere in the world? We attempted to answer this question in a report developed by a high-level multidisciplinary expert group convened by the NPS Global Foundation for the Latin American and Caribbean Leadership Network. We found that there would be multiple harmful effects that would spread promptly around the globe (Arguello and Buis 2016); a more detailed analysis is below, which highlights the need for the creation of a comprehensive nuclear security system.
The consequences of a terrorist nuclear attack A small and primitive 1-kiloton fission bomb (with a yield of about one-fifteenth of the one dropped on Hiroshima, and certainly much less sophisticated; cf. Figure 1), detonated in any large capital city of the developed world, would cause an unprecedented catastrophic scenario. An estimate of direct effects in the attacks location includes a death toll of 7,300-to-23,000 people and 12,600-to-57,000 people injured, depending on the target’s geography and population density. Total physical destruction of the city’s infrastructure, due to the blast (shockwave) and thermal radiation, would cover a radius of about500 meters from the point of detonation (also known as ground zero), while ionizing radiation greater than 5Sieverts–compatible with the deadly acute radiation syn-drome–would expand within an 850-meter radius. From the environmental point of view, such an area would be unusable for years. In addition, radioactive fallout would expand in an area of about 300 square kilometers, depending on meteorological conditions (cf. Figure 2).
But the consequences would go far beyond the effects in the target country, however, and promptly propagate worldwide. Global and national security, economy and finance, international governance and its framework, national political systems, and the behavior of governments and individuals would all be put under severe trial. The severity of the effects at a national level, how-ever, would depend on the countries’ level of development, geopolitical location, and resilience.
Global security and regional/national defense schemes would be strongly affected. An increase in global distrust would spark rising tensions among countries and blocs, that could even lead to the brink of nuclear weapons use by states (if, for instance, a sponsor country is identified). The consequences of such a shocking scenario would include a decrease in states’ self-control, an escalation of present conflicts and the emergence of new ones, accompanied by an increase in military unilateralism and military expenditures.
Regarding the economic and financial impacts, a severe global economic depression would rise from the attack, likely lasting for years. Its duration would be strongly dependent on the course of the crisis. The main results of such a crisis would include a 2 percent fall of growth in global Gross Domestic Product, and a4 percent decline of international trade in the two years following the attack (cf. Figure 3). In the case of developing and less-developed countries, the economic impacts would also include a shortage of high-technology products such as medicines, as well as a fall in foreign direct investment and a severe decline of inter-national humanitarian aid toward low-income countries. We expect an increase of unemployment and poverty in all countries. Global poverty would raise about 4 percent after the attack, which implies that at least 30 million more people would be living in extreme poverty, in addition to the current estimated 767 million.
In the area of international relations, we would expect a breakdown of key doctrines involving politics, security, and relations among states. These international tensions could lead to a collapse of the nuclear order as we know it today, with a consequent setback of nuclear disarmament and nonproliferation commitments. In other words, the whole system based on the Nuclear Non- Proliferation Treaty would be put under severe trial. After the attack, there would be a re-assessment of existing security doctrines, and a deep review of concepts such as nuclear deterrence, no-first-use, proportionality, and negative security assurances.
Finally, the behavior of governments and individuals would also change radically. Internal chaos fueled by the media and social networks would threaten governance at all levels, with greater impact on those countries with weak institutional frameworks. Social turbulence would emerge in most countries, with con-sequent attempts by governments to impose restrictions on personal freedoms to preserve order–possibly by declaring a state of siege or state of emergency–and legislation would surely become tougher on human rights. There would also be a significant increase in social fragmentation–with a deepening of antagonistic views, mistrust, and intolerance, both within countries and towards others–and a resurgence of large-scale social movements fostered by ideological interests and easily mobilized through social media. | 8,330 | <h4>Terrorism causes <u>global nuclear war</u> – draw in, <u>economic depression</u>, and social unrest. </h4><p><strong>Arguello & Buis 18</strong> (Irma Arguello & Emiliano J. Buis, 2-21-2018, "The global impacts of a terrorist nuclear attack: What would happen? What should we do?," Taylor & Francis, https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/full/10.1080/00963402.2018.1436812) // Han</p><p>ABSTRACT As seen by recent events such as the bombing in Manchester, UK, <u><strong><mark>terrorism can occur anywhere, at any time</u></strong></mark>. So far, the terrorist incidents have been relatively low-tech–such as improvised explosive devices detonating inside pressure cookers, trucks driving down crowded sidewalks, or bombs exploding in backpacks containing metal bolts and screws. But what if terrorists were to build a dirty bomb that contained radioactive materials instead of bits of metal shrapnel, and set it off in a major city? Or, worse, what if they managed to build a fully functioning nuclear weapon, cart it to the downtown of a city, and then detonate it–even a small, rudimentary one that was much smaller than the atomic bomb dropped on Hiroshima? What would the social, economic, and political impacts of the successful terrorist use of a nuclear weapon look like? What planning has the international community done for such an event?</p><p>Though hard to accept, <u>the <mark>detonation of a nuclear device–by</mark> states or <mark>non-state actors–is</mark> today <strong><mark>a plausible scenario</u></strong></mark>. And while much of the world’s focus has been on the current nuclear weapons arsenals possessed by states–about 14,550 warheads, all of which carry the risk of intentional or unintentional use–<u><strong><mark>the threat of nuclear terrorism is here and increasing</strong></mark>. For more than a decade, Al Qaeda, Aum Shinrikyo, and other <strong><mark>terrorist groups have expressed</strong></mark> their <strong><mark>desire to acquire fissile mate-rial to build and detonate an improvised nuclear bomb</u></strong></mark>. None of them could fulfill that goal–so far. But that does not mean that they will not succeed in the future.</p><p>Making matters worse, <u>there is evidence of an illicit market for nuclear weapons-usable materials. There are <mark>sellers in search of potential buyers</mark>, as <strong><mark>shown by the</strong></mark> dismantlement of a nuclear <mark>smuggling network in Moldova</mark> in 2015</u>. There certainly are plenty of sites from which to obtain nuclear material. According to the 2016 Nuclear Security Index by the Nuclear Threat Initiative, 24 countries still host inventories of nuclear weapons-usable materials, stored in facilities with different degrees of security. And in terms of risk, it is not necessary for a given country to possess nuclear weapons, weapons-usable materials, or nuclear facilities for it to be useful to nuclear terrorists: Structural and institutional weaknesses in a country may make it favorable for the illicit trade of materials. Permeable boundaries, high levels of corruption, weaknesses in judicial systems, and consequent impunity may give rise to a series of transactions and other events, which could end in a nuclear attack. The truth is that, at this stage, <u><strong><mark>no country</mark> in possession of nuclear weapons or weapons-usable materials <mark>can guarantee their full protection against nuclear terrorism or nuclear smuggling</u></strong></mark>. Because we live in a world of growing insecurity, where explicit and tacit agreements between the relevant powers–which upheld global stability during the post-Cold War–are giving way to increasing mistrust and hostility, a question arises: How would our lives be affected if a current terrorist group such as the Islamic State (ISIS), or new terrorist groups in the future, succeed in evolving from today’s Manchester style “low-tech” attacks to a “high-tech” one, involving a nuclear bomb, detonated in a capital city, anywhere in the world? We attempted to answer this question in a report developed by a high-level multidisciplinary expert group convened by the NPS Global Foundation for the Latin American and Caribbean Leadership Network. We found that there would be multiple harmful effects that would spread promptly around the globe (Arguello and Buis 2016); a more detailed analysis is below, which highlights the need for the creation of a comprehensive nuclear security system.</p><p>The consequences of a terrorist nuclear attack A small and primitive 1-kiloton fission bomb (with a yield of about one-fifteenth of the one dropped on Hiroshima, and certainly much less sophisticated; cf. Figure 1), detonated in any large capital city of the developed world, would cause an unprecedented catastrophic scenario. An estimate of direct effects in the attacks location includes a death toll of 7,300-to-23,000 people and 12,600-to-57,000 people injured, depending on the target’s geography and population density. Total physical destruction of the city’s infrastructure, due to the blast (shockwave) and thermal radiation, would cover a radius of about500 meters from the point of detonation (also known as ground zero), while ionizing radiation greater than 5Sieverts–compatible with the deadly acute radiation syn-drome–would expand within an 850-meter radius. From the environmental point of view, such an area would be unusable for years. In addition, radioactive fallout would expand in an area of about 300 square kilometers, depending on meteorological conditions (cf. Figure 2).</p><p>But the <u><mark>consequences would go</mark> far <mark>beyond</mark> the effects in <mark>the target country</u></mark>, however, and promptly propagate worldwide. Global and <u><strong><mark>national security, economy</u></strong></mark> and finance, <u><strong><mark>international governance</strong></mark> </u>and its framework, national <u><strong><mark>political systems, and</mark> the <mark>behavior of governments and individuals would</mark> all <mark>be</mark> put <mark>under severe trial</mark>.</u> </strong>The severity of the effects at a national level, how-ever<u><strong>, would depend on the countries’ level of development, geopolitical location, and resilience.</p><p></u></strong>Global security and regional/national defense schemes would be strongly affected. An <u><strong><mark>increase in global distrust</mark> would <mark>spark rising tensions among countries and blocs, that</mark> could <mark>even lead to </mark>the brink of <mark>nuclear weapons use</mark> by states</u></strong> (if, for instance, a sponsor country is identified). The consequences of such a shocking scenario would include <u><strong><mark>a decrease in states’ self-control</mark>, an <mark>escalation of present conflicts</mark> and the <mark>emergence of new ones, accompanied by an increase in military unilateralism</mark> and military expenditures.</p><p></u></strong>Regarding the economic and financial impacts, <u><mark>a severe global economic depression would rise</u></mark> from the attack, likely <u><strong><mark>lasting for years</u></strong></mark>. Its duration would be strongly dependent on the course of the crisis. The main results of such a crisis would include a <u>2 percent fall of growth in global Gross Domestic Product, and a4 percent decline of international trade in the two years following the attack (cf. Figure 3). In the case of developing and less-developed countries, the economic impacts would also include a shortage of high-technology products such as medicines, as well as a fall in foreign direct investment and a severe decline of inter-national humanitarian aid toward low-income countries</u>. We expect an increase of unemployment and poverty in all countries. Global poverty would raise<u> about 4 percent after the attack, which implies that at least 30 million more people would be living in extreme poverty, in addition to the current estimated 767 million.</p><p></u>In the area of international relations, we would expect a breakdown of key doctrines involving politics, security, and relations among states. These international tensions could lead to a <u><strong><mark>collapse of the nuclear order</strong></mark> as we know it today, <strong><mark>with a</mark> consequent <mark>setback of nuclear disarmament and nonproliferation commitments</mark>.</strong> In other words, the whole system based on the Nuclear Non- Proliferation Treaty would be put under severe trial. After the attack, there would be a re-assessment of existing security doctrines, and a deep review of concepts such as nuclear deterrence, no-first-use, proportionality, and negative security assurances.</p><p></u>Finally, the behavior of governments and individuals would also change radically. <u><strong><mark>Internal chaos fueled by the media and social networks </mark>would <mark>threaten governance</strong></mark> at all levels, with greater impact on those countries with weak institutional frameworks. Social turbulence would emerge in most countries, with con-sequent attempts by governments to impose restrictions on personal freedoms to preserve order–possibly by declaring a state of siege or state of emergency–and legislation would surely become tougher on human rights. There would also be a <strong>significant <mark>increase in social fragmentation</mark>–with a <mark>deepening of antagonistic views, mistrust, and intolerance</mark>, both <mark>within countries and towards others</mark>–and a resurgence of large-scale social movements fostered by ideological interests and easily mobilized through social media</u></strong>.</p> | null | null | 1NC---Terror DA | 251 | 1,960 | 166,625 | ./documents/hsld22/Peninsula/AlBo/Peninsula-AlBo-Neg-Berkeley-Triples.docx | 982,219 | N | Berkeley | Triples | BASIS Independent Silicon Valley SK | Narayanan, Jankovsky, Harvey | 1ac- asean, pragmatic pluralism. 1nc- T-quota borders, Asean terror DA, Skilled Labor PIC, util. 1ar- asean, conceded util, AFC. 2nr- Asean terror DA. 2ar- AFC, all | hsld22/Peninsula/AlBo/Peninsula-AlBo-Neg-Berkeley-Triples.docx | 2023-02-20 21:17:53 | 80,397 | AlBo | Peninsula AlBo | null | Al..... | Bo..... | null | null | 26,744 | Peninsula | Peninsula | CA | null | 2,003 | hsld22 | HS LD 2022-23 | 2,022 | ld | hs | 1 |
4,753,287 | EU-style border integration fractures ASEAN and causes war. | McMaken ’20 | McMaken ’20 [Ryan; 2-7-20; bachelor's degree in economics and a master's degree in public policy and international relations from the University of Colorado; “Why Open Borders Between States in America Might Lead to Disaster,” https://mises.org/wire/why-open-borders-between-states-america-might-lead-disaster] brett | open borders between states within a confederation
EU member state to another in Europe
pave the way for greater consolidation of power
So long as there are internal borders unregulated by a central government, each member state can control — or not control — the flow of migrants, goods, and services locally if one state has legalized a dangerous substance or device, neighboring states have the legal prerogative to stop those substances and devices at the member state's border There is no need for a universal policy, because each member state is responsible for regulating those persons or goods it claims must be controled
Without union-wide and uniform laws, pro-regulation activists insist that "bad actors" and prohibited goods can too-easily cross from less regulated areas to more regulated ones
the central government will assume the cost of border control, transferring border control activities to the new union-wide border encompassing all member states. Within this border, lawmakers seek union-wide uniform policies. "Bad actors" are declared to be criminals in all jurisdictions and the "dangerous" substances and devices can now only legally enter by crossing international boundaries The central government is now expected to provide enforcement
problem is increasing threats to "self-determination." political "self-determination" for individuals is often best secured through a decentralized political structure where local laws are created and controlled by the local population removing local control of borders, self-determination is lessened
This process is now underway in Europe, where the EU government is moving closer to demanding "harmonization" of tax rates and that all states within the open-border zone adopt more stringent gun control laws
economic integration imposed from above with the goal that low-regulation states would not provide a haven from high-regulation states seen in political fights over alcohol, over migrants, and with guns
a lack of functioning borders between member states—instead of promoting unity and cooperation—may actually be promoting conflict and further centralization
By ending legal and physical separations between culturally and legally diverse political jurisdictions opposing sides end up fighting bitterly over who controls the central government erasing borders increased the stakes of who the central government influences policymakers likely to bring ever greater regional conflict | open borders within a confederation
pave the way for consolidation of power
each state can control flow of migrants locally if one has a dangerous substance neighboring states stop those
central government assume policies
threats to "self-determination." best secured through decentralized political structure removing local control
is underway in Europe
integration from above
promoting conflict
erasing borders increased the stakes of the central government likely to bring greater regional conflict | We hear far less about the issue of open borders between member states within a confederation or union of states.
After all, no one thinks twice of crossing the borders between member states within the United States of America. Increasingly, one is similarly unimpressed when crossing from one EU member state to another in Europe.
Often unnoticed is the way that disappearing patrolled orders between states have helped pave the way for advocates of ever greater consolidation of power in the hands of the central government.1
It's a process that has taken decades—or even centuries in some cases—but it is real.
This process of centralization often proceeds in four steps:
One: So long as there are internal borders unregulated by a central government, each member state can control — or not control — the flow of migrants, goods, and services locally. Thus, if one state has legalized a dangerous substance or device, neighboring states have the legal prerogative to stop those substances and devices at the member state's border. The degree to which each state does this — if at all — will vary. There is no need for a universal policy, because each member state is responsible for regulating those persons or goods it claims must be controled. Only the residents within that specific state are subject to these rules, while outsiders are free to ignore them.
Two: But some activists and lawmakers recognize there are benefits to open borders.2 So, seeking greater ease in the movement of goods, capital, and workers—and in some cases seeking to transfer the cost of border enforcement to taxpayers outside its jurisdiction—member states lobby the central government to minimize or abolish state-level control of borders.
Three: But this does not come without risks and externalities. Without union-wide and uniform laws, pro-regulation activists insist that "bad actors" and prohibited goods can too-easily cross from less regulated areas to more regulated ones.
Four: So a solution is proposed: the central government will assume the cost of border control, transferring border control activities to the new union-wide border encompassing all member states. Within this border, lawmakers seek union-wide uniform policies. "Bad actors" are declared to be criminals in all jurisdictions and the "dangerous" substances and devices can now only legally enter by crossing international boundaries. The central government is now expected to provide enforcement to maintain this new status quo. What had once been the responsibility of the member states has been transferred to a newly empowered central government.
The problem is one of increasing threats to "self-determination." As Ludwig von Mises notes in Liberalism, political "self-determination" for individuals is often best secured through a decentralized political structure where local laws are created and controlled by the local population. By removing local control of borders, self-determination is lessened.
This process is now underway in Europe, where the EU government is moving closer to demanding "harmonization" of tax rates and that all states within the open-border zone adopt more stringent gun control laws. But for now, we'll stick to examples in the United States:
Cross-Border Travel as an Excuse for National Gun Control
In the gun control debate, it has long been argued that the lack of patrolled borders between states means a greater need for uniform nationwide gun control. In an analysis from National Public Radio, for example, the author concludes that the high homicide rates in Washington, DC, and Chicago are partly to blame on gun laws in neighboring states. According to political scientist Philip Cook, the stringent gun laws in places like Chicago are "only at best partially effective, because the borders are permeable."
Were there not free movement from state to state, of course, it would be more difficult to argue that Wisconsin is to blame for Chicago's homicide rate.
The argument by gun control advocates in this case follows a now familiar pattern: the presence of a relatively low amount of regulation in one member state (i.e., Indiana) is viewed as a threat to surrounding member states, who then insist that open borders between states mean that low-regulation states must change their policies to match the high-regulation states.
The Federalization of Immigration
Up until the late nineteenth century, immigration control had been regarded as a state matter. States heavily impacted by immigration—especially New York and Massachusetts—had imposed a variety of laws restricting the movement of immigrant paupers and requiring that bonds be paid on new immigrants to ensure that they did not become a burden on public funds. As late as the 1870s, bills aimed at federalizing immigration policy were killed by majorities in Congress.
Part of the reason that there was a lack of a national consensus was that views of immigrants nationwide were hardly uniform. Some frontier states actively sought immigrants in order to increase the development of farmland and increase state populations. These ongoing regional differences are a reason President Cleveland in 1897 vetoed legislation further restricting immigration because many states and territories of the US—especially those bordering Canada, which provided migrant labor to American farmers—benefited from migrants. Cleveland noted that these parts of the country "have separate and especial interests which in many cases make an interchange of labor between their people and their alien neighbors most important."
Nevertheless, it was recognized that migrants could move freely from immigrant-friendly states to immigrant-unfriendly states. So, anti-immigrant forces had increasingly lobbied for greater federal controls on the external border.1 No long after, the US Supreme Court in 1876 ruled that it was necessary to provide "a system of laws in this matter applicable to all ports and all vessels" in order to settle a long-standing "matter of contest and complaint." By the twentieth century, the autonomy once granted to states on the immigration issue was all but forgotten.
Prohibition and the Drug War
Regulating guns and migrants haven't been the only excuses given for expanding federal power in the name of national uniformity. Centralized control was also deemed to be necessary in order to control the transport and manufacture of alcoholic beverages. In the years leading up to the adoption of nationwide prohibition, all but sixteen states had adopted their own versions of prohibition. For the moralists, however, this wasn't enough. Those states where alcohol remained legal—mostly states with large numbers of Catholics and ethnic Germans—offered a haven to residents of "dry" states, who could easily cross over into the "wet" states. Even worse, people could illegally import alcohol into dry states from wet ones with relative ease. By imposing nationwide prohibition on everyone, however, access to alcohol could be more easily attacked.
We see similar issues today as some states have begun to legalize recreational marijuana much to the dismay of officials in neighboring states. Once again, the answer is alleged to be the federalization of policy and the abolition of local prerogatives. In 2014, two marijuana prohibitionist states, Oklahoma and Nebraska, unsuccessfully sued Colorado in response to its legalization of recreational marijuana. The two states were concerned that the lack of a patrolled border between Colorado and its neighbors was an unacceptable threat to the public in prohibitionist states. Thus, the two states petitioned the court to declare state law null and void and to rule that federal law reigns supreme in matters of drug prohibition. Fortunately, on this particular issue the federal courts have not yet decided to declare federal law supreme, as they have many times before.
When Erasing Borders Isn't a Problem
Unfortunately, economic integration between member states in the US did not come organically or unilaterally. It was imposed from above, often with the goal that low-regulation states would not provide a haven from high-regulation states. We have seen this in political fights over alcohol, over migrants, and with guns.
Experience with these political fight now strongly suggests the lowering of borders do not pose a threat to self-determination and do not enhance the power of the central state only under the following conditions:
Border controls are decreased unilaterally by each member state in an ad hoc and decentralized manner.
The central government is too weak (or lacks the legal authority) to impose uniform nationwide laws without widespread consensus.
Member states bring to the table a significant amount of tolerance for their neighbors, and for the fact that people might do things differently in other places. In decades past, for instance, it was more often accepted that some places have stringent gun laws and other places don't. In the minds of many policymakers, this created certain risks and externalities, but these were tolerated in light of the ideological notion that not every aspect of daily life ought to be regulated from the center.
It is no longer clear, however, that we live in a political environment where this sort of tolerance or decentralization is still valued. It now appears that a lack of functioning borders between member states—instead of promoting unity and cooperation—may actually be promoting conflict and further centralization. For example, were there a meaningful border between California and the rest of the United States it is unlikely that the rest of the nation would regard foreign migration as the high-stakes political issue it now is. Similarly, if it were not so easy to travel unobstructed from gun-friendly Indiana to gun prohibitionist Chicago, we wouldn't be hearing about how we need federal action on gun control.
The result is something similar to what we see from political centralization in general. By ending legal and physical separations between culturally and legally diverse political jurisdictions, opposing sides end up fighting bitterly over who controls the central government. Ironically, the attempt at building unity through erasing borders has increased the stakes of who controls the central government and influences its policymakers. In the long term, this is likely to bring ever greater regional conflict. | 10,441 | <h4><u>EU-style</u> border integration <u>fractures ASEAN</u> and causes <u>war</u>.</h4><p><u><strong>McMaken ’20</u></strong> [Ryan; 2-7-20; bachelor's degree in economics and a master's degree in public policy and international relations from the University of Colorado; “Why Open Borders Between States in America Might Lead to Disaster,” https://mises.org/wire/why-open-borders-between-states-america-might-lead-disaster] brett</p><p>We hear far less about the issue of <u><strong><mark>open borders</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>between</u></strong> member <u><strong>states <mark>within a confederation</u></strong></mark> or union of states.</p><p>After all, no one thinks twice of crossing the borders between member states within the United States of America. Increasingly, one is similarly unimpressed when crossing from one <u><strong>EU member state to another in Europe</u></strong>. </p><p>Often unnoticed is the way that disappearing patrolled orders between states have helped <u><strong><mark>pave the way for</u></strong></mark> advocates of ever <u><strong>greater <mark>consolidation of power</u></strong></mark> in the hands of the central government.1</p><p>It's a process that has taken decades—or even centuries in some cases—but it is real.</p><p>This process of centralization often proceeds in four steps:</p><p>One: <u><strong>So long as there are internal borders unregulated by a central government, <mark>each</mark> member <mark>state can control</mark> — or not control — the <mark>flow of migrants</mark>, goods, and services <mark>locally</u></strong></mark>. Thus, <u><strong><mark>if one</mark> state <mark>has</mark> legalized <mark>a dangerous substance</mark> or device, <mark>neighboring states </mark>have the legal prerogative to <mark>stop those</mark> substances and devices at the member state's border</u></strong>. The degree to which each state does this — if at all — will vary. <u><strong>There is no need for a universal policy, because each member state is responsible for regulating those persons or goods it claims must be controled</u></strong>. Only the residents within that specific state are subject to these rules, while outsiders are free to ignore them.</p><p>Two: But some activists and lawmakers recognize there are benefits to open borders.2 So, seeking greater ease in the movement of goods, capital, and workers—and in some cases seeking to transfer the cost of border enforcement to taxpayers outside its jurisdiction—member states lobby the central government to minimize or abolish state-level control of borders.</p><p>Three: But this does not come without risks and externalities. <u><strong>Without union-wide and uniform laws, pro-regulation activists insist that "bad actors" and prohibited goods can too-easily cross from less regulated areas to more regulated ones</u></strong>. </p><p>Four: So a solution is proposed: <u><strong>the <mark>central government</mark> will <mark>assume</mark> the cost of border control, transferring border control activities to the new union-wide border encompassing all member states. Within this border, lawmakers seek union-wide uniform <mark>policies</mark>. "Bad actors" are declared to be criminals in all jurisdictions and the "dangerous" substances and devices can now only legally enter by crossing international boundaries</u></strong>. <u><strong>The central government</u></strong> <u><strong>is now expected to provide enforcement</u></strong> to maintain this new status quo. What had once been the responsibility of the member states has been transferred to a newly empowered central government.</p><p>The <u><strong>problem is</u></strong> one of <u><strong>increasing <mark>threats to "self-determination."</u></strong></mark> As Ludwig von Mises notes in Liberalism, <u><strong>political "self-determination" for individuals is often <mark>best secured through</mark> a <mark>decentralized political structure</mark> where local laws are created and controlled by the local population</u></strong>. By <u><strong><mark>removing local control</mark> of borders, self-determination is lessened</u></strong>.</p><p><u><strong>This process <mark>is</mark> now <mark>underway in Europe</mark>, where the EU government is moving closer to demanding "harmonization" of tax rates and that all states within the open-border zone adopt more stringent gun control laws</u></strong>. But for now, we'll stick to examples in the United States:</p><p>Cross-Border Travel as an Excuse for National Gun Control</p><p>In the gun control debate, it has long been argued that the lack of patrolled borders between states means a greater need for uniform nationwide gun control. In an analysis from National Public Radio, for example, the author concludes that the high homicide rates in Washington, DC, and Chicago are partly to blame on gun laws in neighboring states. According to political scientist Philip Cook, the stringent gun laws in places like Chicago are "only at best partially effective, because the borders are permeable."</p><p>Were there not free movement from state to state, of course, it would be more difficult to argue that Wisconsin is to blame for Chicago's homicide rate.</p><p>The argument by gun control advocates in this case follows a now familiar pattern: the presence of a relatively low amount of regulation in one member state (i.e., Indiana) is viewed as a threat to surrounding member states, who then insist that open borders between states mean that low-regulation states must change their policies to match the high-regulation states.</p><p>The Federalization of Immigration</p><p>Up until the late nineteenth century, immigration control had been regarded as a state matter. States heavily impacted by immigration—especially New York and Massachusetts—had imposed a variety of laws restricting the movement of immigrant paupers and requiring that bonds be paid on new immigrants to ensure that they did not become a burden on public funds. As late as the 1870s, bills aimed at federalizing immigration policy were killed by majorities in Congress.</p><p>Part of the reason that there was a lack of a national consensus was that views of immigrants nationwide were hardly uniform. Some frontier states actively sought immigrants in order to increase the development of farmland and increase state populations. These ongoing regional differences are a reason President Cleveland in 1897 vetoed legislation further restricting immigration because many states and territories of the US—especially those bordering Canada, which provided migrant labor to American farmers—benefited from migrants. Cleveland noted that these parts of the country "have separate and especial interests which in many cases make an interchange of labor between their people and their alien neighbors most important."</p><p>Nevertheless, it was recognized that migrants could move freely from immigrant-friendly states to immigrant-unfriendly states. So, anti-immigrant forces had increasingly lobbied for greater federal controls on the external border.1 No long after, the US Supreme Court in 1876 ruled that it was necessary to provide "a system of laws in this matter applicable to all ports and all vessels" in order to settle a long-standing "matter of contest and complaint." By the twentieth century, the autonomy once granted to states on the immigration issue was all but forgotten.</p><p>Prohibition and the Drug War</p><p>Regulating guns and migrants haven't been the only excuses given for expanding federal power in the name of national uniformity. Centralized control was also deemed to be necessary in order to control the transport and manufacture of alcoholic beverages. In the years leading up to the adoption of nationwide prohibition, all but sixteen states had adopted their own versions of prohibition. For the moralists, however, this wasn't enough. Those states where alcohol remained legal—mostly states with large numbers of Catholics and ethnic Germans—offered a haven to residents of "dry" states, who could easily cross over into the "wet" states. Even worse, people could illegally import alcohol into dry states from wet ones with relative ease. By imposing nationwide prohibition on everyone, however, access to alcohol could be more easily attacked.</p><p>We see similar issues today as some states have begun to legalize recreational marijuana much to the dismay of officials in neighboring states. Once again, the answer is alleged to be the federalization of policy and the abolition of local prerogatives. In 2014, two marijuana prohibitionist states, Oklahoma and Nebraska, unsuccessfully sued Colorado in response to its legalization of recreational marijuana. The two states were concerned that the lack of a patrolled border between Colorado and its neighbors was an unacceptable threat to the public in prohibitionist states. Thus, the two states petitioned the court to declare state law null and void and to rule that federal law reigns supreme in matters of drug prohibition. Fortunately, on this particular issue the federal courts have not yet decided to declare federal law supreme, as they have many times before.</p><p>When Erasing Borders Isn't a Problem</p><p>Unfortunately, <u><strong>economic <mark>integration</u></strong></mark> between member states in the US did not come organically or unilaterally. It was <u><strong>imposed <mark>from above</u></strong></mark>, often <u><strong>with the goal that low-regulation states would not provide a haven from high-regulation states</u></strong>. We have <u><strong>seen</u></strong> this <u><strong>in political fights over alcohol, over migrants, and with guns</u></strong>.</p><p>Experience with these political fight now strongly suggests the lowering of borders do not pose a threat to self-determination and do not enhance the power of the central state only under the following conditions:</p><p> Border controls are decreased unilaterally by each member state in an ad hoc and decentralized manner.</p><p>The central government is too weak (or lacks the legal authority) to impose uniform nationwide laws without widespread consensus.</p><p>Member states bring to the table a significant amount of tolerance for their neighbors, and for the fact that people might do things differently in other places. In decades past, for instance, it was more often accepted that some places have stringent gun laws and other places don't. In the minds of many policymakers, this created certain risks and externalities, but these were tolerated in light of the ideological notion that not every aspect of daily life ought to be regulated from the center.</p><p>It is no longer clear, however, that we live in a political environment where this sort of tolerance or decentralization is still valued. It now appears that <u><strong>a lack of functioning borders between member states—instead of promoting unity and cooperation—may actually be <mark>promoting conflict</mark> and further centralization</u></strong>. For example, were there a meaningful border between California and the rest of the United States it is unlikely that the rest of the nation would regard foreign migration as the high-stakes political issue it now is. Similarly, if it were not so easy to travel unobstructed from gun-friendly Indiana to gun prohibitionist Chicago, we wouldn't be hearing about how we need federal action on gun control.</p><p>The result is something similar to what we see from political centralization in general. <u><strong>By ending legal and physical separations between culturally and legally diverse political jurisdictions</u></strong>, <u><strong>opposing sides</u></strong> <u><strong>end up fighting bitterly over who controls the central government</u></strong>. Ironically, the attempt at building unity through <u><strong><mark>erasing borders</u></strong></mark> has <u><strong><mark>increased the stakes of</mark> who</u></strong> controls <u><strong><mark>the</u></strong> <u><strong>central government</u></strong></mark> and <u><strong>influences</u></strong> its <u><strong>policymakers</u></strong>. In the long term, this is <u><strong><mark>likely to bring</mark> ever <mark>greater regional conflict</u></strong></mark>.</p> | 1NC | CASE | General | 1,699,569 | 99 | 166,298 | ./documents/hsld22/MontaVista/KeRa/MontaVista-KeRa-Neg-National-Debate-Coaches-Association-National-Championships-Round-1.docx | 990,598 | N | National Debate Coaches Association National Championships | 1 | Lynbrook BZ | Fleming | 1AC - asean
1NC - t-spec, edsm, adv cp, terror
1AR - all
rest - edsm, case | hsld22/MontaVista/KeRa/MontaVista-KeRa-Neg-National-Debate-Coaches-Association-National-Championships-Round-1.docx | 2023-03-25 15:54:14 | 80,360 | KeRa | Monta Vista KeRa | hola. | Ke..... | Ra..... | null | null | 26,996 | MontaVista | Monta Vista | CA | null | 2,003 | hsld22 | HS LD 2022-23 | 2,022 | ld | hs | 1 |
4,609,463 | Anticipation breeds empathy and entangled care. Distancing ourselves from considering extinction reifies detached elitism. | Offord ‘17 | Offord ‘17 (Faculty of Humanities, School of Humanities Research and Graduate Studies, Bentley Campus; Baden, “BEYOND OUR NUCLEAR ENTANGLEMENT,” Angelaki, 22:3, 17-25, dml) [ableist language modifications denoted by brackets] | You are steered towards overwhelming and inexplicable pain when you consider the nuclear entanglement that the species finds itself in the fact of living in the nuclear age presents an existential, aesthetic, ethical and psychological challenge that defines human consciousness. Although an immanent threat and ever-present danger to the very existence of the human species, living with the possibility of nuclear war has infiltrated the matrix of modernity so profoundly as to [shut down] our mind-set to respond adequately. We have chosen to ignore the facts at the heart of the nuclear program we have chosen to live with the capacity and possibility of a collective, pervasive and even planetary-scale suicide; and the techno-industrial-national powers that claim there is “no immediate danger” ad infinitum
The question of our times is whether we have an equal or more compelling capacity and willingness to end this impoverished but ever-present logic of pain and uncertainty. How not simply to bring about disarmament, but to go beyond this politically charged nuclear algorithm?
responding to the nuclear algorithm is an imperative. Your politics, ethics and scholarship are indivisible in this cause. An acute sense of care for the world, informed by pacifist and non-violent, de-colonialist approaches to knowledge and practice, pervades your concern. You are aware that there are other ways of knowing than those you are familiar and credentialed with You use your scholarship to shake up the world to unsettle the epistemic and structural violence that is ubiquitous to neoliberalism and its machinery; to create dialogic and learning spaces for the work of critical human rights and critical justice to take place. All this, and to enable an ethics of intervention through understanding what is at the very heart of the impulse
living in a nuclear armed world, your challenge is to reconceptualise the human community to see how we can learn to co-exist with others in conviviality and also learn to co-survive with the non-human, even to flourish the planet itself is inherently involved as a participant in its future
you realise that your struggle is not confined to legislation, and law, though they have their role. It must go further to produce “creative intellectual exchange | existential challenge We have chosen to live with
The question is whether we have capacity to end this logic
responding is an imperative sense of care informed by pacifist and non-violent, de-colonialist approaches unsettle violence
reconceptualise the human community to see how we can learn to co-survive
struggle produce “creative intellectual exchange | You are steered towards overwhelming and inexplicable pain when you consider the nuclear entanglement that the species Homo sapiens finds itself in. This is because the fact of living in the nuclear age presents an existential, aesthetic, ethical and psychological challenge that defines human consciousness. Although an immanent threat and ever-present danger to the very existence of the human species, living with the possibility of nuclear war has infiltrated the matrix of modernity so profoundly as to paralyse [shut down] our mind-set to respond adequately. We have chosen to ignore the facts at the heart of the nuclear program with its dangerous algorithm; we have chosen to live with the capacity and possibility of a collective, pervasive and even planetary-scale suicide; and the techno-industrial-national powers that claim there is “no immediate danger” ad infinitum.8
This has led to one of the key logics of modernity's insanity. As Harari writes: “Nuclear weapons have turned war between superpowers into a mad act of collective suicide, and therefore forced the most powerful nations on earth to find alternative and peaceful ways to resolve conflicts.”9 This is the nuclear algorithm at work, a methodology of madness. In revisiting Jacques Derrida in “No Apocalypse, Not Now (Full Speed Ahead, Seven Missiles, Seven Missives),”10 who described nuclear war as a “non-event,” it is clear that the pathology of the “non-event” remains as active as ever even in the time of Donald Trump and Kim Jong-un with their stichomythic nuclear posturing.
The question of our times is whether we have an equal or more compelling capacity and willingness to end this impoverished but ever-present logic of pain and uncertainty. How not simply to bring about disarmament, but to go beyond this politically charged, as well as mythological and psychological nuclear algorithm? How to find love amidst the nuclear entanglement; the antidote to this entanglement? Is it possible to end the pathology of power that exists with nuclear capacity? Sadly, the last lines of Nitin Sawhney's “Broken Skin” underscore this entanglement:
Just 5 miles from India's nuclear test site
Children play in the shade of the village water tank
Here in the Rajasthan desert people say
They're proud their country showed their nuclear capability.11
As an activist scholar working in the fields of human rights and cultural studies, responding to the nuclear algorithm is an imperative. Your politics, ethics and scholarship are indivisible in this cause. An acute sense of care for the world, informed by pacifist and non-violent, de-colonialist approaches to knowledge and practice, pervades your concern. You are aware that there are other ways of knowing than those you are familiar and credentialed with. You are aware that you are complicit in the prisons that you choose to live inside,12 and that there is no such thing as an innocent bystander. You use your scholarship to shake up the world from its paralysis, abjection and amnesia; to unsettle the epistemic and structural violence that is ubiquitous to neoliberalism and its machinery; to create dialogic and learning spaces for the work of critical human rights and critical justice to take place. All this, and to enable an ethics of intervention through understanding what is at the very heart of the critical human rights impulse, creating a “dialogue for being, because I am not without the other.”13
Furthermore, as a critical human rights advocate living in a nuclear armed world, your challenge is to reconceptualise the human community as Ashis Nandy has argued, to see how we can learn to co-exist with others in conviviality and also learn to co-survive with the non-human, even to flourish. A dialogue for being requires a leap into a human rights frame that includes a deep ecological dimension, where the planet itself is inherently involved as a participant in its future. This requires scholarship that “thinks like a mountain.”14 A critical human rights approach understands that it cannot be simply human-centric. It requires a nuanced and arresting clarity to present perspectives on co-existence and co-survival that are from human and non-human viewpoints.15
Ultimately, you realise that your struggle is not confined to declarations, treaties, legislation, and law, though they have their role. It must go further to produce “creative intellectual exchange | 4,421 | <h4>Anticipation breeds <u>empathy</u> and <u>entangled care</u>. Distancing ourselves from considering extinction <u>reifies</u> detached elitism.</h4><p><strong>Offord ‘17</strong> (Faculty of Humanities, School of Humanities Research and Graduate Studies, Bentley Campus; Baden, “BEYOND OUR NUCLEAR ENTANGLEMENT,” Angelaki, 22:3, 17-25, dml) [ableist language modifications denoted by brackets]</p><p><u>You are steered towards <strong>overwhelming</strong> and <strong>inexplicable pain</strong> when you consider the <strong>nuclear entanglement</strong> that the species</u> Homo sapiens <u>finds itself in</u>. This is because <u>the fact of living in the nuclear age presents an <strong><mark>existential</strong></mark>, <strong>aesthetic</strong>, <strong>ethical</strong> and <strong>psychological <mark>challenge</strong></mark> that defines human consciousness. Although an <strong>immanent threat</strong> and <strong>ever-present danger</strong> to the <strong>very existence</strong> of the human species, living with the possibility of nuclear war has <strong>infiltrated the matrix of modernity so profoundly</strong> as to</u> paralyse <u>[<strong>shut down</strong>] our mind-set to respond adequately. <mark>We have chosen </mark>to <strong>ignore the facts</strong> at the heart of the nuclear program</u> with its dangerous algorithm; <u>we have chosen <mark>to <strong>live with </mark>the capacity</strong> and <strong>possibility</strong> of a <strong>collective</strong>, <strong>pervasive</strong> and even <strong>planetary-scale suicide</strong>; and the techno-industrial-national powers that claim there is “<strong>no immediate danger</strong>” ad infinitum</u>.8</p><p>This has led to one of the key logics of modernity's insanity. As Harari writes: “Nuclear weapons have turned war between superpowers into a mad act of collective suicide, and therefore forced the most powerful nations on earth to find alternative and peaceful ways to resolve conflicts.”9 This is the nuclear algorithm at work, a methodology of madness. In revisiting Jacques Derrida in “No Apocalypse, Not Now (Full Speed Ahead, Seven Missiles, Seven Missives),”10 who described nuclear war as a “non-event,” it is clear that the pathology of the “non-event” remains as active as ever even in the time of Donald Trump and Kim Jong-un with their stichomythic nuclear posturing.</p><p><u><mark>The question</mark> of our times <mark>is whether we have</mark> an <strong>equal</strong> or <strong>more compelling <mark>capacity</strong></mark> and <strong>willingness</strong> <mark>to <strong>end this</mark> impoverished but ever-present <mark>logic</strong></mark> of pain and uncertainty. How not simply to <strong>bring about disarmament</strong>, but to <strong>go beyond</strong> this politically charged</u>, as well as mythological and psychological <u><strong>nuclear algorithm</strong>?</u> How to find love amidst the nuclear entanglement; the antidote to this entanglement? Is it possible to end the pathology of power that exists with nuclear capacity? Sadly, the last lines of Nitin Sawhney's “Broken Skin” underscore this entanglement:</p><p>Just 5 miles from India's nuclear test site</p><p>Children play in the shade of the village water tank</p><p>Here in the Rajasthan desert people say</p><p>They're proud their country showed their nuclear capability.11</p><p>As an activist scholar working in the fields of human rights and cultural studies, <u><mark>responding </mark>to the nuclear algorithm <mark>is an <strong>imperative</strong></mark>. Your <strong>politics</strong>, <strong>ethics</strong> and <strong>scholarship are indivisible</strong> in this cause. An <strong>acute <mark>sense of care</mark> for the world</strong>, <mark>informed by <strong>pacifist</strong> and <strong>non-violent</strong>, <strong>de-colonialist approaches</strong></mark> to knowledge and practice, <strong>pervades your concern</strong>. You are <strong>aware</strong> that there are <strong>other ways of knowing</strong> than those you are familiar and credentialed with</u>. You are aware that you are complicit in the prisons that you choose to live inside,12 and that there is no such thing as an innocent bystander. <u>You use your scholarship to <strong>shake up the world</u></strong> from its paralysis, abjection and amnesia; <u>to <strong><mark>unsettle </mark>the epistemic</strong> and <strong>structural <mark>violence</strong></mark> that is ubiquitous to neoliberalism and its machinery; to <strong>create dialogic</strong> and <strong>learning spaces</strong> for the work of critical human rights and critical justice to take place. All this, and to <strong>enable an ethics of intervention</strong> through understanding what is at the very heart of the</u> critical human rights <u>impulse</u>, creating a “dialogue for being, because I am not without the other.”13</p><p>Furthermore, as a critical human rights advocate <u>living in a nuclear armed world, your challenge is to <strong><mark>reconceptualise the human community</u></strong></mark> as Ashis Nandy has argued, <u><mark>to see how we can learn to <strong></mark>co-exist with others in conviviality</strong> and also learn to <strong><mark>co-survive </mark>with the non-human</strong>, even to <strong>flourish</u></strong>. A dialogue for being requires a leap into a human rights frame that includes a deep ecological dimension, where <u>the planet itself is <strong>inherently involved as a participant</strong> in its future</u>. This requires scholarship that “thinks like a mountain.”14 A critical human rights approach understands that it cannot be simply human-centric. It requires a nuanced and arresting clarity to present perspectives on co-existence and co-survival that are from human and non-human viewpoints.15</p><p>Ultimately, <u>you realise that your <mark>struggle</mark> is <strong>not confined to</u></strong> declarations, treaties, <u><strong>legislation</strong>, and <strong>law</strong>, <strong>though they have their role</strong>. It must go further to <mark>produce “<strong>creative intellectual exchange</strong></mark> </p></u> | 1AC | null | 1AC—Framing | 9,167 | 308 | 152,861 | ./documents/hsld22/StrakeJesuitCollegePreparatory/KaSh/StrakeJesuitCollegePreparatory-KaSh-Aff-The-48th-Churchill-Classic-TOC-and-NIETOC-Qualifier-Round-5.docx | 960,609 | A | The 48th Churchill Classic TOC and NIETOC Qualifier | 5 | ClaTay Arjun Patel | Walker | 1AC - Romania and Bulgaria and Osource
1NC - Extra T, T Policy, Conflict DA, Case
1AR - All
2NR - T Policy, Conflict DA, Osource
2AR - Case, T | hsld22/StrakeJesuitCollegePreparatory/KaSh/StrakeJesuitCollegePreparatory-KaSh-Aff-The-48th-Churchill-Classic-TOC-and-NIETOC-Qualifier-Round-5.docx | 2023-01-07 20:32:46 | 80,549 | KaSh | Strake Jesuit College Preparatory KaSh | Pronouns: He/Him
Contact Info: Phone- 8323962580
Preface with name, round and etc DONT CALL UNLESS NECESSARY
Facebook Messenger- Karan Shah
Email: [email protected] or [email protected]
Messenger and Text are the best bets
If there is any way you would like me to accommodate your needs in any way before and during the round, just contact me! I'm happy to do so.
Please tell me if there are any specific interps you would like me to meet before round (spikes on top, rob spec, etc.)
Feel free to hmu if my wiki is acting up and there are some docs you can't access - I'll send them to you directly.
Let me know any trigger warnings or pronouns before the round so we can make the debate as comfortable as possible for both of us.
Good luck! | Ka..... | Sh..... | null | null | 27,049 | StrakeJesuitCollegePreparatory | Strake Jesuit College Preparatory | TX | 36,501 | 2,003 | hsld22 | HS LD 2022-23 | 2,022 | ld | hs | 1 |
1,397,761 | Extinction outweighs | Bostrom 12 (Nick, directs Oxford's Future of Humanity Institute, Interview with Ross Andersen, correspondent at The Atlantic, 3/6, “We're Underestimating the Risk of Human Extinction”, http://www.theatlantic.com/technology/archive/2012/03/were-underestimating-the-risk-of-human-extinction/253821/)//BB | Bostrom 12 - Professor of Philosophy at Oxford (Nick, directs Oxford's Future of Humanity Institute, Interview with Ross Andersen, correspondent at The Atlantic, 3/6, “We're Underestimating the Risk of Human Extinction”, http://www.theatlantic.com/technology/archive/2012/03/were-underestimating-the-risk-of-human-extinction/253821/)//BB | extinction risks are underestimated existential risk mitigation may be a dominant moral priority over alleviation of present suffering A human life is a human life future generations matter existential risk mitigation has a much higher utility than anything else There are so many people that could come into existence in the future if humanity survives even a very small reduction in the probability of realizing this enormous good will tend to outweigh eliminating poverty | extinction risks are underestimated existential risk mitigation a dominant moral priority over the alleviation of present suffering human life is a human life future generations matter existential risk mitigation has a much higher utility than anything else so many people that could come into existence in the future if humanity survives even a small reduction in the probability of realizing this enormous good will tend to outweigh eliminating poverty | Bostrom, who directs Oxford's Future of Humanity Institute, has argued over the course of several papers that human extinction risks are poorly understood and, worse still, severely underestimated by society. Some of these existential risks are fairly well known, especially the natural ones. But others are obscure or even exotic. Most worrying to Bostrom is the subset of existential risks that arise from human technology, a subset that he expects to grow in number and potency over the next century.¶ Despite his concerns about the risks posed to humans by technological progress, Bostrom is no luddite. In fact, he is a longtime advocate of transhumanism---the effort to improve the human condition, and even human nature itself, through technological means. In the long run he sees technology as a bridge, a bridge we humans must cross with great care, in order to reach new and better modes of being. In his work, Bostrom uses the tools of philosophy and mathematics, in particular probability theory, to try and determine how we as a species might achieve this safe passage. What follows is my conversation with Bostrom about some of the most interesting and worrying existential risks that humanity might encounter in the decades and centuries to come, and about what we can do to make sure we outlast them.¶ Some have argued that we ought to be directing our resources toward humanity's existing problems, rather than future existential risks, because many of the latter are highly improbable. You have responded by suggesting that existential risk mitigation may in fact be a dominant moral priority over the alleviation of present suffering. Can you explain why? ¶ Bostrom: Well suppose you have a moral view that counts future people as being worth as much as present people. You might say that fundamentally it doesn't matter whether someone exists at the current time or at some future time, just as many people think that from a fundamental moral point of view, it doesn't matter where somebody is spatially---somebody isn't automatically worth less because you move them to the moon or to Africa or something. A human life is a human life. If you have that moral point of view that future generations matter in proportion to their population numbers, then you get this very stark implication that existential risk mitigation has a much higher utility than pretty much anything else that you could do. There are so many people that could come into existence in the future if humanity survives this critical period of time---we might live for billions of years, our descendants might colonize billions of solar systems, and there could be billions and billions times more people than exist currently. Therefore, even a very small reduction in the probability of realizing this enormous good will tend to outweigh even immense benefits like eliminating poverty or curing malaria, which would be tremendous under ordinary standards. | 2,945 | <h4>Extinction outweighs</h4><p><strong>Bostrom 12</strong> - Professor of Philosophy at Oxford <strong>(Nick, directs Oxford's Future of Humanity Institute, Interview with Ross Andersen, correspondent at The Atlantic, 3/6, “We're Underestimating the Risk of Human Extinction”, http://www.theatlantic.com/technology/archive/2012/03/were-underestimating-the-risk-of-human-extinction/253821/)//BB</p><p></strong>Bostrom, who directs Oxford's Future of Humanity Institute, has argued over the course of several papers that human <u><mark>extinction risks are</u></mark> poorly understood and, worse still, severely<u><strong> <mark>underestimated</u></strong></mark> by society. Some of these existential risks are fairly well known, especially the natural ones. But others are obscure or even exotic. Most worrying to Bostrom is the subset of existential risks that arise from human technology, a subset that he expects to grow in number and potency over the next century.¶ Despite his concerns about the risks posed to humans by technological progress, Bostrom is no luddite. In fact, he is a longtime advocate of transhumanism---the effort to improve the human condition, and even human nature itself, through technological means. In the long run he sees technology as a bridge, a bridge we humans must cross with great care, in order to reach new and better modes of being. In his work, Bostrom uses the tools of philosophy and mathematics, in particular probability theory, to try and determine how we as a species might achieve this safe passage. What follows is my conversation with Bostrom about some of the most interesting and worrying existential risks that humanity might encounter in the decades and centuries to come, and about what we can do to make sure we outlast them.¶ Some have argued that we ought to be directing our resources toward humanity's existing problems, rather than future existential risks, because many of the latter are highly improbable. You have responded by suggesting that <u><mark>existential risk mitigation </mark>may</u> in fact <u>be <mark>a <strong>dominant moral priority</strong> over</u> the <u>alleviation of present suffering</u></mark>. Can you explain why? ¶ Bostrom: Well suppose you have a moral view that counts future people as being worth as much as present people. You might say that fundamentally it doesn't matter whether someone exists at the current time or at some future time, just as many people think that from a fundamental moral point of view, it doesn't matter where somebody is spatially---somebody isn't automatically worth less because you move them to the moon or to Africa or something. <u>A <mark>human life is a human life</u></mark>. If you have that moral point of view that <u><mark>future generations matter</mark> </u>in proportion to their population numbers, then you get this very stark implication that<u> <mark>existential risk mitigation has a <strong>much higher utility than</strong></mark> </u>pretty much<u> <strong><mark>anything else</u></strong></mark> that you could do.<u> There are <mark>so many people that could come into existence in the future if humanity survives</mark> </u>this critical period of time---we might live for billions of years, our descendants might colonize billions of solar systems, and there could be billions and billions times more people than exist currently. Therefore,<u> <mark>even a</mark> very <mark>small reduction in the probability of realizing this enormous good <strong>will</strong> tend to <strong>outweigh</strong></mark> </u>even immense benefits like<u> <strong><mark>eliminating poverty</strong></mark> </u>or curing malaria, which would be tremendous under ordinary standards.</p> | null | 2nc | topicality | 1,240,482 | 818 | 37,387 | ./documents/hspolicy14/NotreDame/DiPi/Notre%20Dame-Dille-Pismarov-Neg-Alta-Round5.docx | 636,773 | N | Alta | 5 | Copper Hills LR | Kristof Weakley | 1NC - TFramework Biod Loss Good and Anthro Good
2NC - T and Biod Loss Good
1NR - Anthro Good
2NR - Biod Loss Good and Anthro Good | hspolicy14/NotreDame/DiPi/Notre%20Dame-Dille-Pismarov-Neg-Alta-Round5.docx | null | 53,743 | DiPi | Notre Dame DiPi | null | Za..... | Di..... | Vi..... | Pi..... | 19,623 | NotreDame | Notre Dame | null | null | 1,013 | hspolicy14 | HS Policy 2014-15 | 2,014 | cx | hs | 2 |
764,527 | Death is the ultimate evil – it obliterates metaphysics and ontology preventing it is apriori | Paterson 3 | Paterson 3 - Department of Philosophy, Providence College, Rhode Island | Craig, “A Life Not Worth Living?”, Studies in Christian Ethics, SAGE
it is death that is really the objective evil , death in itself is an evil to us because it ontologically destroys the current existent subject — it is the ultimate in metaphysical lightening strikes. death is truly an ontological evil borne by the person who already exists, independently of calculations about better or worse possible lives. Such an evil need not be consciously experienced in order to be an evil for the kind of being a human person is. Death is an evil because of the change in kind it brings about, a change that is destructive of the type of entity that we essentially are. Anything that drastically interferes in the process of maintaining the person in existence is an objective evil for the person death is a radical interference with the current life process of the kind of being that we are death itself can be credibly thought of as a ‘primitive evil’ for all persons, regardless of the extent to which they are currently or prospectively capable of participating in a full array of the goods of life. concerning willed human actions any intentional rejection of human life cannot therefore be warranted since it is an expression of an ultimate disvalue for the subject, the destruction of the present person; a radical ontological good that we cannot begin to weigh objectively against the travails of life in a rational manner. To deal with the sources of disvalue we should not seek to irrationally destroy the person, the very source and condition of all human possibility. | death is the objective evil death ontologically destroys the subject it is an ontological evil independent of calculations about better or worse lives Death brings about destructive the entity we are. Anything that interferes in maintaining existence is an objective evil death is a interference with the life process death can be credibly thought of as a evil’ for all persons regardless to which they are capable of participating in goods of life any intentional rejection of life cannot be warranted it is an expression of disvalue for the subject we should not seek irrationally destroy the person, the source of all possibility. | Craig, “A Life Not Worth Living?”, Studies in Christian Ethics, SAGE
Contrary to those accounts, I would argue that it is death per se that is really the objective evil for us, not because it deprives us of a prospective future of overall good judged better than the alternative of non-being. It cannot be about harm to a former person who has ceased to exist, for no person actually suffers from the sub-sequent non-participation. Rather, death in itself is an evil to us because it ontologically destroys the current existent subject — it is the ultimate in metaphysical lightening strikes. 80 The evil of death is truly an ontological evil borne by the person who already exists, independently of calculations about better or worse possible lives. Such an evil need not be consciously experienced in order to be an evil for the kind of being a human person is. Death is an evil because of the change in kind it brings about, a change that is destructive of the type of entity that we essentially are. Anything, whether caused naturally or caused by human intervention (intentional or unintentional) that drastically interferes in the process of maintaining the person in existence is an objective evil for the person. What is crucially at stake here, and is dialectically supportive of the self-evidency of the basic good of human life, is that death is a radical interference with the current life process of the kind of being that we are. In consequence, death itself can be credibly thought of as a ‘primitive evil’ for all persons, regardless of the extent to which they are currently or prospectively capable of participating in a full array of the goods of life. 81 In conclusion, concerning willed human actions, it is justifiable to state that any intentional rejection of human life itself cannot therefore be warranted since it is an expression of an ultimate disvalue for the subject, namely, the destruction of the present person; a radical ontological good that we cannot begin to weigh objectively against the travails of life in a rational manner. To deal with the sources of disvalue (pain, suffering, etc.) we should not seek to irrationally destroy the person, the very source and condition of all human possibility. | 2,237 | <h4><strong>Death is the ultimate evil – it obliterates metaphysics and ontology preventing it is apriori</h4><p>Paterson 3</strong> - Department of Philosophy, Providence College, Rhode Island </p><p><u>Craig, “A Life Not Worth Living?”, Studies in Christian Ethics, SAGE</p><p></u>Contrary to those accounts, I would argue that <u><strong>it is <mark>death</u></strong></mark> per se <u><strong>that <mark>is</mark> really <mark>the objective evil</u></strong></mark> for us, not because it deprives us of a prospective future of overall good judged better than the alternative of non-being. It cannot be about harm to a former person who has ceased to exist, for no person actually suffers from the sub-sequent non-participation. Rather<u>, <strong><mark>death</mark> in itself is an evil to us because it <mark>ontologically destroys the</mark> current existent <mark>subject</mark> — <mark>it is</mark> the ultimate in metaphysical lightening strikes.</strong> </u>80 The evil of <u><strong>death is truly <mark>an ontological evil</mark> borne by the person who already exists, <mark>independent</mark>ly<mark> of</mark> <mark>calculations about better or worse</mark> possible <mark>lives</mark>. Such an evil need not be consciously experienced in order to be an evil for the kind of being a human person is. <mark>Death </mark>is an evil because of the change in kind it <mark>brings about</mark>, a change that is <mark>destructive</mark> of <mark>the</mark> type of <mark>entity</mark> that <mark>we</mark> essentially <mark>are.</mark> <mark>Anything</u></strong></mark>, whether caused naturally or caused by human intervention (intentional or unintentional) <u><strong><mark>that</mark> drastically <mark>interferes in </mark>the process of <mark>maintaining </mark>the person in <mark>existence</mark> <mark>is an objective evil</mark> for the person</u></strong>. What is crucially at stake here, and is dialectically supportive of the self-evidency of the basic good of human life, is that <u><strong><mark>death is a </mark>radical <mark>interference with the </mark>current <mark>life process </mark>of the kind of being that we are</u></strong>. In consequence, <u><strong><mark>death</mark> itself <mark>can be credibly thought of</mark> <mark>as a </mark>‘primitive <mark>evil’ for all persons</mark>, <mark>regardless </mark>of the extent <mark>to which they are</mark> currently or prospectively <mark>capable of participating in </mark>a full array of the <mark>goods of life</mark>.</strong> </u>81 In conclusion, <u><strong>concerning willed human actions</u></strong>, it is justifiable to state that<u> <strong><mark>any intentional rejection of </mark>human <mark>life</u></strong></mark> itself <u><strong><mark>cannot</mark> therefore <mark>be warranted</mark> since <mark>it is an expression of </mark>an ultimate <mark>disvalue for the subject</mark>,</u></strong> namely, <u><strong>the destruction of the present person; a radical ontological good that we cannot begin to weigh objectively against the travails of life in a rational manner. To deal with the sources of disvalue</u></strong> (pain, suffering, etc.) <u><strong><mark>we should not seek </mark>to <mark>irrationally destroy the person, the </mark>very <mark>source </mark>and condition <mark>of all </mark>human <mark>possibility.</p></u></strong></mark> | null | null | 1NC – Death Bad | 32,578 | 1,478 | 17,861 | ./documents/ndtceda14/Kansas/FoGo/Kansas-Foreman-Goh-Neg-NDT-Round3.docx | 567,426 | N | NDT | 3 | Texas KS | Erob, Kyle Vint, Shae Bunas | 1AC-PAS agency medicalization
1NC-physician administered death cp brown da federal preemption cp fw trust da
Block-PAD cp trust da brown da
2NR-pad cp | ndtceda14/Kansas/FoGo/Kansas-Foreman-Goh-Neg-NDT-Round3.docx | null | 48,639 | FoGo | Kansas FoGo | null | Ci..... | Fo..... | Hu..... | Go..... | 18,784 | Kansas | Kansas | null | null | 1,004 | ndtceda14 | NDT/CEDA 2014-15 | 2,014 | cx | college | 2 |