id
int64
59
4.83M
tag
stringlengths
1
12.4k
cite
stringlengths
1
4.52k
fullcite
stringlengths
1
105k
summary
stringlengths
1
62.2k
spoken
stringlengths
1
35k
fulltext
stringlengths
4
388k
textLength
int64
4
388k
markup
stringlengths
35
397k
pocket
stringlengths
1
8k
hat
stringlengths
1
7.13k
block
stringlengths
1
16.2k
bucketId
int64
1
1.95M
duplicateCount
int64
1
5.63k
fileId
int64
1
172k
filePath
stringlengths
49
182
roundId
float64
565k
998k
side
stringclasses
2 values
tournament
stringlengths
1
95
round
stringclasses
56 values
opponent
stringlengths
1
65
judge
stringlengths
1
128
report
stringlengths
1
53.7k
opensourcePath
stringlengths
37
170
caselistUpdatedAt
stringlengths
19
19
teamId
float64
48.4k
86.5k
teamName
stringlengths
2
8
teamDisplayName
stringlengths
6
45
notes
stringclasses
631 values
debater1First
stringclasses
269 values
debater1Last
stringclasses
306 values
debater2First
stringclasses
224 values
debater2Last
stringclasses
259 values
schoolId
float64
18.7k
28.2k
schoolName
stringlengths
3
35
schoolDisplayName
stringlengths
3
40
state
stringclasses
49 values
chapterId
float64
23
114k
caselistId
float64
1k
2.01k
caselistName
stringclasses
40 values
caselistDisplayName
stringclasses
39 values
year
float64
2.01k
2.02k
event
stringclasses
3 values
level
stringclasses
2 values
teamSize
float64
1
2
4,592,176
Multilat is an impact filter for Existential threats.
Lederer 21
Lederer 21 Edith Lederer 9-11-2021 “UN chief: World is at `pivotal moment' and must avert crises” https://www.washingtonpost.com/world/un-chief-world-is-at-pivotal-moment-and-must-avert-crises/2021/09/11/ff58806c-1323-11ec-baca-86b144fc8a2d_story.html //Elmer
Guterres issued a dire warning the world is moving in the wrong direction and faces “a pivotal moment” continuing business as usual could lead to a breakdown of global order and a future of perpetual crisis the world’s nations must choose “the breakthrough scenario.” The world is under “enormous stress this extends beyond COVID to climate crisis and the collapse of biodiversity unchecked inequality undermining cohesion of societies and technology’s advances without guard rails the extreme risk from nuclear war and a climate breakdown and inequality, discrimination and injustice bringing people into the streets breakthrough is driven by working together recognizing that we are bound to each other and that no country can solve challenges alone multilateral institutions have proven to be “too weak What’s needed is more effective multilateral institutions immediate action is needed to protect the planet’s “most precious” assets from oceans to outer space and to deliver peace and good health issues go beyond traditional security threats “to strengthen global governance of tech and space to manage future risks and crises It would consider a New Agenda including measures to reduce risks from nuclear weapons cyber warfare and autonomous weapons humanity’s most destabilizing inventions.
the world faces “a pivotal moment could lead to a breakdown of global order and perpetual crisis beyond COVID to climate biod cohesion and tech without guard rails from nuc war and climate breakdown breakthrough is driven by working together no country can solve alone What’s needed is effective multilat strengthen global governance to manage crises reduce risks from nuc s, cyber and autonomous weapons
UNITED NATIONS — U.N. Secretary-General Antonio Guterres issued a dire warning that the world is moving in the wrong direction and faces “a pivotal moment” where continuing business as usual could lead to a breakdown of global order and a future of perpetual crisis. Changing course could signal a breakthrough to a greener and safer future, he said. The U.N. chief said the world’s nations and people must reverse today’s dangerous trends and choose “the breakthrough scenario.” The world is under “enormous stress” on almost every front, he said, and the COVID-19 pandemic was a wake-up call demonstrating the failure of nations to come together and take joint decisions to help all people in the face of a global life-threatening emergency. Guterres said this “paralysis” extends far beyond COVID-19 to the failures to tackle the climate crisis and “our suicidal war on nature and the collapse of biodiversity,” the “unchecked inequality” undermining the cohesion of societies, and technology’s advances “without guard rails to protect us from its unforeseen consequences.” In other signs of a more chaotic and insecure world, he pointed to rising poverty, hunger and gender inequality after decades of decline, the extreme risk to human life and the planet from nuclear war and a climate breakdown, and the inequality, discrimination and injustice bringing people into the streets to protest “while conspiracy theories and lies fuel deep divisions within societies.” In a horizon-scanning report presented to the General Assembly and at a press conference Friday, Guterres said his vision for the “breakthrough scenario” to a greener and safer world is driven by “the principle of working together, recognizing that we are bound to each other and that no community or country, however powerful, can solve its challenges alone.” The report -- “Our Common Agenda” -- is a response to last year’s declaration by world leaders on the 75th anniversary of the United Nations and the request from the assembly’s 193 member nations for the U.N. chief to make recommendations to address the challenges for global governance. In today’s world, Guterres said, “Global decision-making is fixed on immediate gain, ignoring the long-term consequences of decisions -- or indecision.” He said multilateral institutions have proven to be “too weak and fragmented for today’s global challenges and risks.” What’s needed, Guterres said, is not new multilateral bureaucracies but more effective multilateral institutions including a United Nations “2.0” more relevant to the 21st century. “And we need multilateralism with teeth,” he said. In the report outlining his vision “to fix” the world, Guterres said immediate action is needed to protect the planet’s “most precious” assets from oceans to outer space, to ensure it is livable, and to deliver on the aspirations of people everywhere for peace and good health. He called for an immediate global vaccination plan implemented by an emergency task force, saying “investing $50 billion in vaccinations now could add an estimated $9 trillion to the global economy in the next four years.” The report proposes that a global Summit of the Future take place in 2023 that would not only look at all these issues but go beyond traditional security threats “to strengthen global governance of digital technology and outer space, and to manage future risks and crises,” he said. It would also consider a New Agenda for Peace including measures to reduce strategic risks from nuclear weapons, cyber warfare and lethal autonomous weapons, which Guterres called one of humanity’s most destabilizing inventions.
3,636
<h4>Multilat is an <u>impact filter</u> for Existential threats. </h4><p><strong>Lederer 21</strong> Edith Lederer 9-11-2021 “UN chief: World is at `pivotal moment' and must avert crises” https://www.washingtonpost.com/world/un-chief-world-is-at-pivotal-moment-and-must-avert-crises/2021/09/11/ff58806c-1323-11ec-baca-86b144fc8a2d_story.html<u> //Elmer </p><p></u>UNITED NATIONS — U.N. Secretary-General Antonio <u>Guterres issued a dire warning</u> that <u><strong><mark>the world </mark>is moving in the wrong direction</u></strong> <u>and <mark>faces “a <strong>pivotal moment</strong></mark>”</u> where <u>continuing business as usual <mark>could lead to a <strong>breakdown of global order</strong> and </mark>a <strong>future of <mark>perpetual crisis</u></strong></mark>. Changing course could signal a breakthrough to a greener and safer future, he said. The U.N. chief said <u>the world’s nations</u> and people <u>must</u> reverse today’s dangerous trends and <u>choose “the breakthrough scenario.” The world is under “<strong>enormous stress</u></strong>” on almost every front, he said, and the COVID-19 pandemic was a wake-up call demonstrating the failure of nations to come together and take joint decisions to help all people in the face of a global life-threatening emergency. Guterres said <u>this</u> “paralysis” <u>extends</u> far <u><mark>beyond <strong>COVID</u></strong></mark>-19 <u><mark>to</u> </mark>the failures to tackle the <u><strong><mark>climate </mark>crisis</u></strong> and “our suicidal war on nature <u>and the <strong>collapse of <mark>biod</mark>iversity</u></strong>,” the “<u><strong>unchecked inequality</u></strong>” <u>undermining</u> the <u><strong><mark>cohesion</mark> of societies</u></strong>, <u><strong><mark>and tech</mark>nology’s advances</u></strong> “<u><mark>without guard rails</u></mark> to protect us from its unforeseen consequences.” In other signs of a more chaotic and insecure world, he pointed to rising poverty, hunger and gender inequality after decades of decline, <u>the extreme risk</u> to human life and the planet <u><strong><mark>from nuc</mark>lear <mark>war and</mark> a <mark>climate breakdown</u></strong></mark>, <u>and</u> the <u>inequality, discrimination and injustice bringing people into the streets</u> to protest “while conspiracy theories and lies fuel deep divisions within societies.” In a horizon-scanning report presented to the General Assembly and at a press conference Friday, Guterres said his vision for the “<u><strong><mark>breakthrough</u></strong> </mark>scenario” to a greener and safer world <u><mark>is driven by</u> </mark>“the principle of <u><strong><mark>working together</u></strong></mark>, <u>recognizing that we are bound to each other and that <strong><mark>no</u></strong> </mark>community or <u><strong><mark>country</u></strong></mark>, however powerful, <u><strong><mark>can solve</u></strong> </mark>its <u><strong>challenges <mark>alone</u></strong></mark>.” The report -- “Our Common Agenda” -- is a response to last year’s declaration by world leaders on the 75th anniversary of the United Nations and the request from the assembly’s 193 member nations for the U.N. chief to make recommendations to address the challenges for global governance. In today’s world, Guterres said, “Global decision-making is fixed on immediate gain, ignoring the long-term consequences of decisions -- or indecision.” He said <u>multilateral institutions have proven to be “too weak</u> and fragmented for today’s global challenges and risks.” <u><mark>What’s needed</u></mark>, Guterres said, <u><mark>is</u> </mark>not new multilateral bureaucracies but <u><strong>more <mark>effective multilat</mark>eral institutions</u></strong> including a United Nations “2.0” more relevant to the 21st century. “And we need multilateralism with teeth,” he said. In the report outlining his vision “to fix” the world, Guterres said <u><strong>immediate action</strong> is needed to protect the planet’s <strong>“most precious</strong>” assets from <strong>oceans</strong> to <strong>outer space</u></strong>, to ensure it is livable, <u>and to deliver</u> on the aspirations of people everywhere for <u><strong>peace and good health</u></strong>. He called for an immediate global vaccination plan implemented by an emergency task force, saying “investing $50 billion in vaccinations now could add an estimated $9 trillion to the global economy in the next four years.” The report proposes that a global Summit of the Future take place in 2023 that would not only look at all these <u>issues</u> but <u>go beyond traditional security threats “to <mark>strengthen <strong>global governance</u></strong></mark> <u>of </u>digital <u><strong>tech</u></strong>nology <u>and</u> outer <u><strong>space</u></strong>, and <u><mark>to manage <strong></mark>future risks and <mark>crises</u></strong></mark>,” he said. <u>It would</u> also <u>consider a New Agenda</u> for Peace <u>including measures to <strong><mark>reduce</u></strong> </mark>strategic <u><strong><mark>risks from nuc</mark>lear weapon<mark>s</u></strong>, <u><strong>cyber </mark>warfare</u></strong> <u><mark>and</u> </mark>lethal <u><strong><mark>autonomous weapons</u></strong></mark>, which Guterres called one of <u>humanity’s most destabilizing inventions.</p></u>
null
null
1AC: ASEAN v2
496,911
237
152,338
./documents/hsld22/SanMateo/YeRa/SanMateo-YeRa-Aff-CPS-LD-Invitational-Octas.docx
962,518
A
CPS LD Invitational
Octas
Westridge TW
Lichtman, Bittner, Kilpatrick
1ac - asean 1nc - wto mfn consult cp, myanmar pic, populism da, t, case 1ar - all 2nr - wto mfn consult 2ar - case, cp
hsld22/SanMateo/YeRa/SanMateo-YeRa-Aff-CPS-LD-Invitational-Octas.docx
2023-01-13 16:17:19
80,665
YeRa
San Mateo YeRa
null
Ye.....
Ra.....
null
null
27,080
SanMateo
San Mateo
CA
null
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
345,262
Interpretation- Federal is not states
OED 89
OED 89 (Oxford English Dictionary, 2ed. XIX, p. 795)
political unity so constituted distinguished from separate states composing it
political unity distinguished from separate states composing it
b. Of or pertaining to the political unity so constituted, as distinguished from the separate states composing it.
114
<h4>Interpretation- Federal is not states</h4><p><strong>OED 89</strong> (Oxford English Dictionary, 2ed. XIX, p. 795)</p><p>b. Of or pertaining to the <u><mark>political unity</mark> so constituted</u>, as <u><mark>distinguished from</u></mark> the <u><mark>separate states composing it</u></mark>.</p>
Other Off Case
T - Federal
1NC Shell
16,293
274
4,412
./documents/openev/2015/SDI/Welfare Surveillance Negative - SDI 2015.docx
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
584,944
Ban fails – too early to understand, no verification, and states will break it if war starts.
Noyes '19
Noyes '19 [Matthew Freeman; 6/14/19; Masters of Art and Science in the Art of War from the U.S. Army Command and General Staff College, MPP from the Harvard Kennedy School; "Autonomous Weapons: The Future Behind Us," https://apps.dtic.mil/sti/pdfs/AD1085435.pdf]
due to the competitive and chaotic nature of the international system. Establishing effective arms control regimes is a significant challenge; national interests and military effectiveness is often the foremost concern in conflict, presenting the risk that agreements may collapse in the event of war absent demonstrated examples of the harms of a particular weapon, as was the case with land mines and chemical weapons, it is unclear whether there is sufficient political motivation to adopt an arms control agreement. Even for existing military capabilities, like offensive cyber operations, twenty years of UN discussions have resulted in only limited progress in establishing constraints on state use Beyond the first order policy question of whether there should be policy or legal constraints on the development or use of autonomous weapons, developing specific technical, verifiable, and enforceable measures to constrain development or adoption of autonomous weapons is a substantial challenge. Such an effort ought to be informed by an ex ante assessment of what is likely to exist absent such a constraint being adopted, to enable subsequent assessment of the effectiveness of a control regime. Therefore, this work limits the scope of the analysis to likely potential military uses of autonomous weapons in the absence of effective ethical, policy, or legal constraints.
due to competitive nature of international system effective arms control is a significant challenge military effectiveness is the foremost concern in conflict, presenting risk agreements collapse in the event of war absent demonstrated examples of the harms it is unclear whether there is political motivation to agree Even for existing capabilities years of discussions resulted in limited progress Beyond whether there should be constraints on autonomous weapons, developing specific technical, verifiable, and enforceable measures is a substantial challenge effort ought to be informed by ex ante assessment of what is likely to exist to enable effectiveness of a control regime
This delimitation is reasonable due to the competitive and chaotic nature of the international system. Establishing effective arms control regimes is a significant challenge; national interests and military effectiveness is often the foremost concern in conflict, presenting the risk that agreements may collapse in the event of war.8 Moreover, absent demonstrated examples of the harms of a particular weapon, as was the case with land mines and chemical weapons, it is unclear whether there is sufficient political motivation to adopt an arms control agreement. Even for existing military capabilities, like offensive cyber operations, twenty years of UN discussions have resulted in only limited progress in establishing constraints on state use.9 Beyond the first order policy question of whether there should be policy or legal constraints on the development or use of autonomous weapons, developing specific technical, verifiable, and enforceable measures to constrain development or adoption of autonomous weapons is a substantial challenge. Such an effort ought to be informed by an ex ante assessment of what is likely to exist absent such a constraint being adopted, to enable subsequent assessment of the effectiveness of a control regime. Therefore, this work limits the scope of the analysis to likely potential military uses of autonomous weapons in the absence of effective ethical, policy, or legal constraints.
1,427
<h4>Ban fails – too early to understand, no verification, and states will break it if war starts.</h4><p><strong>Noyes '19 </strong>[Matthew Freeman; 6/14/19; Masters of Art and Science in the Art of War from the U.S. Army Command and General Staff College, MPP from the Harvard Kennedy School; "Autonomous Weapons: The Future Behind Us," https://apps.dtic.mil/sti/pdfs/AD1085435.pdf]</p><p>This delimitation is reasonable <u><mark>due to</mark> the <strong><mark>competitive</strong></mark> and <strong>chaotic</strong> <mark>nature of</mark> the <mark>international system</mark>. Establishing <mark>effective <strong>arms control</strong></mark> regimes <mark>is a <strong>significant challenge</strong></mark>; <strong>national interests</strong> and <strong><mark>military effectiveness</strong> is</mark> often <mark>the <strong>foremost concern</strong> in conflict, presenting</mark> the <mark>risk</mark> that <strong><mark>agreements</mark> may <mark>collapse in the event of war</u></strong></mark>.8 Moreover, <u><mark>absent <strong>demonstrated examples</strong> of the harms</mark> of a particular weapon, as was the case with <strong>land mines</strong> and <strong>chemical weapons</strong>, <mark>it is <strong>unclear</strong> whether there is</mark> sufficient <strong><mark>political motivation</strong> to</mark> adopt an arms control <mark>agree</mark>ment. <mark>Even for existing</mark> military <mark>capabilities</mark>, like <strong>o</strong>ffensive <strong>c</strong>yber <strong>o</strong>peration<strong>s</strong>, twenty <mark>years of</mark> UN <mark>discussions</mark> have <mark>resulted in</mark> only <strong><mark>limited progress</strong></mark> in establishing <strong>constraints</strong> on state use</u>.9</p><p><u><mark>Beyond</mark> the first order <strong>policy question</strong> of <mark>whether there <strong>should</strong> be</mark> policy or legal <strong><mark>constraints</strong> on</mark> the development or use of <strong><mark>autonomous weapons</strong>, developing <strong>specific</strong> <strong>technical</strong>, <strong>verifiable</strong>, and <strong>enforceable</strong> measures</mark> to constrain development or adoption of autonomous weapons <mark>is a <strong>substantial challenge</strong></mark>. Such an <mark>effort ought to be informed by</mark> an <strong><mark>ex ante assessment</strong> of what is likely to exist</mark> absent such a constraint being adopted, <mark>to enable</mark> <strong>subsequent assessment</strong> of the <strong><mark>effectiveness</strong> of a <strong>control regime</mark>. Therefore, this work limits the scope of the analysis to likely potential military uses of autonomous weapons in the absence of effective ethical, policy, or legal constraints.</p></u></strong>
null
Solvency
NC – Ban Fails
351,192
208
9,555
./documents/hsld20/Harker/Sh/Harker-Shah-Neg-Peninsula-Round2.docx
859,725
N
Peninsula
2
West Ranch KT
Vanessa Nguyen
1AC - Whole Rez 1NC - DA-Dictators DA-Hegemony 2NR - Hegemony
hsld20/Harker/Sh/Harker-Shah-Neg-Peninsula-Round2.docx
null
73,080
DeSh
Harker DeSh
null
De.....
Sh.....
null
null
24,534
Harker
Harker
CA
null
1,028
hsld20
HS LD 2020-21
2,020
ld
hs
1
2,363,704
Attacks on LAWs threaten weapon capabilities, accurate info, and national security
Heinl 17
Heinl 17 Caitríona Heinl (Executive Strategist/Lead Strategist for Asia Pacific), 10-9-2017, “Maturing autonomous cyber weapons systems: Implications for international security cyber and autonomous weapons systems regimes,” Oxford Handbook of Cyber Security, Oxford University Press, available at https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=3255104, SJBE
The increasing reliance on AI for autonomous decision-making is increasing the number of new vulnerabilities to cyber attacks Moreover, there is a risk that AI systems are susceptible to tactics that are not necessarily easy to predict, and the compromising of automated systems may allow for disruption to critical infrastructure or national security networks. In other words, the purpose of winning ‘cyber supremacy’ over an opponent could be to ensure that these physical platforms or systems could be shut down or controlled.85 Thus, a key question is whether increasing autonomy could drive the development of cyber weapons in order to exploit the vulnerability of AWS.86 Information might even be intercepted, or possibly manipulated The fear is that it will become increasingly difficult to guarantee the accuracy and reliability of data. This might mean that decision-making will be affected, that trust in systems may decline, or that there may even be adverse physical effects Experts note the challenge in ensuring against reliability and vulnerability problems in autonomous weapons software, “cautioning that failure could lead to unintended fatalities” - false or missing software requirements, incorrect algorithms or code, insufficient testing, incorrect or unexpected use of software, and possible vulnerabilities to cyber attacks could expose systems to risk.
compromising of automated systems may allow for disruption to critical infrastructure or national security networks winning ‘cyber supremacy’ could ensure systems could be shut down or controlled Information might be manipulated it will become increasingly difficult to guarantee the reliability of data. decision-making will be affected trust in systems may decline failure could lead to unintended fatalities
The increasing reliance on AI for autonomous decision-making is increasing the number of new vulnerabilities to cyber attacks.80 This is also exacerbating those difficulties already associated with attribution. The 2016 ODNI Worldwide Threat Assessment Report explains that such increased use of AI means “increased vulnerability to cyber attack, difficulty in ascertaining attribution, facilitation of advances in foreign weapon and intelligence systems, the risk of accidents and related liability issues, and unemployment”.81 Moreover, there is a risk that AI systems are susceptible to tactics that are not necessarily easy to predict, and the compromising of automated systems may allow for disruption to critical infrastructure or national security networks.82 In the case of maturing autonomous technologies, in some quarters, these are expected to replace remotely piloted air and ground vehicles in the domains of air, sea, undersea, land and space. 83 As a result, the vulnerability of their underlying systems to cyber attack is particularly significant as it may become more difficult to protect these systems. Such technologies could be taken over so that cyber may become the “high ground”.84 In other words, the purpose of winning ‘cyber supremacy’ over an opponent could be to ensure that these physical platforms or systems could be shut down or controlled.85 Thus, a key question is whether increasing autonomy could drive the development of cyber weapons in order to exploit the vulnerability of AWS.86 Information might even be intercepted, or possibly manipulated. A plethora of information assurance issues may then arise too, such as how to be certain of the integrity of data. In situations where decisions are increasingly informed by advanced computer systems, it is essential that the information presented is accurate. There is a growing concern within the cyber community currently over the danger associated with data manipulation. The fear is that it will become increasingly difficult to guarantee the accuracy and reliability of data. This might mean that decision-making will be affected, that trust in systems may decline, or that there may even be adverse physical effects.87 While AWS (both physical platforms and cyber systems) are vulnerable to cyber operations, at face value this may seem no different to other fields or technologies. However, there is a difference insofar as there could be a case for limits on these technologies if the consequences of AWS and a cyber operation on such a system(s) are not yet fully understood. The ICRC similarly argues that a key concern about the interaction between cyber operations and AWS is how to maintain human control with the possibility of cyber attack – in other words, these systems may be manipulated which is why there may be good cause for limits to autonomy.88 This means that technical safeguards are extremely important. Experts note the challenge in ensuring against reliability and vulnerability problems in autonomous weapons software, “cautioning that failure could lead to unintended fatalities” - false or missing software requirements, incorrect algorithms or code, insufficient testing, incorrect or unexpected use of software, and possible vulnerabilities to cyber attacks could expose systems to risk.89
3,310
<h4>Attacks on LAWs threaten weapon capabilities, accurate info, and national security</h4><p><strong>Heinl 17 </strong>Caitríona Heinl (Executive Strategist/Lead Strategist for Asia Pacific), 10-9-2017, “Maturing autonomous cyber weapons systems: Implications for international security cyber and autonomous weapons systems regimes,” Oxford Handbook of Cyber Security, Oxford University Press, available at https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=3255104, SJBE</p><p><u>The increasing reliance on AI for autonomous decision-making is increasing the number of new vulnerabilities to cyber attacks</u>.80 This is also exacerbating those difficulties already associated with attribution. The 2016 ODNI Worldwide Threat Assessment Report explains that such increased use of AI means “increased vulnerability to cyber attack, difficulty in ascertaining attribution, facilitation of advances in foreign weapon and intelligence systems, the risk of accidents and related liability issues, and unemployment”.81 <u>Moreover, there is a risk that AI systems are susceptible to tactics that are not necessarily easy to predict, and the <mark>compromising of automated systems may allow for disruption to critical infrastructure or national security networks</mark>.</u>82 In the case of maturing autonomous technologies, in some quarters, these are expected to replace remotely piloted air and ground vehicles in the domains of air, sea, undersea, land and space. 83 As a result, the vulnerability of their underlying systems to cyber attack is particularly significant as it may become more difficult to protect these systems. Such technologies could be taken over so that cyber may become the “high ground”.84 <u>In other words, the purpose of <mark>winning ‘cyber supremacy’ </mark>over an opponent <mark>could</mark> be to <mark>ensure</mark> that these physical platforms or <mark>systems could be shut down or controlled</mark>.85 Thus, a key question is whether increasing autonomy could drive the development of cyber weapons in order to exploit the vulnerability of AWS.86 <mark>Information might</mark> even <mark>be </mark>intercepted, or possibly <mark>manipulated</u></mark>. A plethora of information assurance issues may then arise too, such as how to be certain of the integrity of data. In situations where decisions are increasingly informed by advanced computer systems, it is essential that the information presented is accurate. There is a growing concern within the cyber community currently over the danger associated with data manipulation. <u>The fear is that <mark>it will become increasingly difficult to guarantee the</mark> accuracy and <mark>reliability of data. </mark>This might mean that <mark>decision-making will be affected</mark>, that <mark>trust in systems may decline</mark>, or that there may even be adverse physical effects</u>.87 While AWS (both physical platforms and cyber systems) are vulnerable to cyber operations, at face value this may seem no different to other fields or technologies. However, there is a difference insofar as there could be a case for limits on these technologies if the consequences of AWS and a cyber operation on such a system(s) are not yet fully understood. The ICRC similarly argues that a key concern about the interaction between cyber operations and AWS is how to maintain human control with the possibility of cyber attack – in other words, these systems may be manipulated which is why there may be good cause for limits to autonomy.88 This means that technical safeguards are extremely important. <u>Experts note the challenge in ensuring against reliability and vulnerability problems in autonomous weapons software, “cautioning that <mark>failure could lead to unintended fatalities</mark>” - false or missing software requirements, incorrect algorithms or code, insufficient testing, incorrect or unexpected use of software, and possible vulnerabilities to cyber attacks could expose systems to risk.</u>89</p>
null
null
Advantage
355,999
175
75,299
./documents/hsld20/StrakeJesuit/At/Strake%20Jesuit-Atkins-Aff-Golden%20Desert-Round2.docx
874,644
A
Golden Desert
2
Iowa City West JS
William Phong
1AC - stock 1NC - truth testing contracts nc poaching pic case 1AR - case truth testing contracts nc poaching pic 2NR - truth testing contracts nc case 2AR - case truth testing contracts nc
hsld20/StrakeJesuit/At/Strake%20Jesuit-Atkins-Aff-Golden%20Desert-Round2.docx
null
73,801
AiAt
Strake Jesuit AiAt
null
Ai.....
At.....
null
null
24,736
StrakeJesuit
Strake Jesuit
TX
null
1,028
hsld20
HS LD 2020-21
2,020
ld
hs
1
1,502,674
We’ll defend normal means as the signatories of the OST adding an optional protocol under Article II.
Tronchetti 7
Tronchetti 7[Fabio Tronchetti is a professor at the International Institute of Air and Space Law, Leiden University, The Netherlands, 2007, https://iislweb.org/docs/Diederiks2007.pdf, 12-15-2021 amrita]
The legal content of Article II of the Outer Space Treaty is one of the most debated and analysed topic in the field of space law ”. The text of Article II represents the final point of a process, formally initiated with Resolution 1721, aimed at conferring to outer space the status of res communis omnium, namely a thing open for the free exploration and use by all States without the possibility of being appropriated , Article II makes clear that the customary procedures of international law allowing subjects to obtain sovereignty rights over un-owed lands, namely discovery, occupatio and effective possession, do not apply to outer space the question of whether both States and private individuals are subjected to the provisions of Article II. Indeed, while Article II forbids expressis verbis the national appropriation by claims of sovereignty, by means of use and occupation or other means of outer space, it does not make any explicit mention to its private appropriation some authors have argued that the private appropriation of outer space and celestial bodies is allowed. The same argument is used today by the enterprises selling extraterrestrial acres. They base their claim to the Moon and other celestial bodies on the consideration that Article II does not explicitly forbid private individuals and enterprises to claim, exploit or appropriate the celestial bodies for profit there is a general consensus on the fact that both national appropriation and private property rights are denied under the Outer Space Treaty Private entities are allowed to carry out space activities but, according to Article VI of the Outer Space Treaty, they must be authorized to conduct such activities by the appropriate State of nationality. But if the State is prohibited from engaging in certain conduct, then it lacks the authority to license its nationals or other entities subject to its jurisdiction to engage in that prohibited activity the prohibition of national appropriation implies prohibition of private appropriation because the latter cannot exist independently from the former10. In order to exist, indeed, private property requires a superior authority to enforce it, be in the form of a State or some other recognised entity Moreover, it is possible to use some historical elements to support the argument that both the acquisition of State sovereignty and the creation of private property rights are forbidden by the words of Article II. . Thus, summing up, we may say that prohibition of appropriation of outer space and its parts is a rule which is valid for both private and public entity. The theory that private operators are not subject to this rule represents a myth that is not supported by any valid legal argument. Therefore, the need to protect the non-appropriative nature of outer space emerges in all its relevance.
The text of Article II represents free exploration without the possibility of being appropriated makes clear that i law allowing sovereignty rights over un-owed lands do not apply to space. while Article II forbids appropriation by sovereignty it does not a mention to private both national appropriation and private are denied Private entities are allowed to carry out activities but must be authorized by the State the prohibition of national implies prohibition of private prohibition of appropriation of outer space is valid for both private and public entity the need to protect the non-appropriative nature o space emerges
ARTICLE II OF THE OUTER SPACE TREATY: A MATTER OF DEBATE The legal content of Article II of the Outer Space Treaty is one of the most debated and analysed topic in the field of space law. Indeed, several interpretations have been put forward to explain the meaning of its provisions. Article II states that: “Outer space, including the Moon and other celestial bodies, is not subject to national appropriation by claim of sovereignty, by means of use or occupation, or by any other means”. The text of Article II represents the final point of a process, formally initiated with Resolution 1721, aimed at conferring to outer space the status of res communis omnium, namely a thing open for the free exploration and use by all States without the possibility of being appropriated. By prohibiting the possibility of making territorial claims over outer space or any part thereof based on use or occupation, Article II makes clear that the customary procedures of international law allowing subjects to obtain sovereignty rights over un-owed lands, namely discovery, occupatio and effective possession, do not apply to outer space. This prohibition was considered by the drafters of the Outer Space Treaty the best guarantee for preserving outer space for peaceful activities only and for stimulating the exploration and use of the space environment in the name of all mankind. What has been the object of controversy among legal scholars is the question of whether both States and private individuals are subjected to the provisions of Article II. Indeed, while Article II forbids expressis verbis the national appropriation by claims of sovereignty, by means of use and occupation or other means of outer space, it does not make any explicit mention to its private appropriation. Relying on this consideration, some authors have argued that the private appropriation of outer space and celestial bodies is allowed. For instance, in 1968 Gorove wrote: “Thus, at present an individual acting on his own behalf or on behalf of another individual or private association or an international organisation could lawfully appropriate any parts of outer space…”6 . The same argument is used today by the enterprises selling extraterrestrial acres. They base their claim to the Moon and other celestial bodies on the consideration that Article II does not explicitly forbid private individuals and enterprises to claim, exploit or appropriate the celestial bodies for profit7 . However, it must be said, that nowadays there is a general consensus on the fact that both national appropriation and private property rights are denied under the Outer Space Treaty. Several way of reasoning have been advanced to support this view. Sters and Tennen affirm that the argument that Article II does not apply to private entities since they are not expressly mentioned fails for the reason that they do not need to be explicitly listed in Article II to be fully subject to the non-appropriation principle8 . Private entities are allowed to carry out space activities but, according to Article VI of the Outer Space Treaty, they must be authorized to conduct such activities by the appropriate State of nationality. But if the State is prohibited from engaging in certain conduct, then it lacks the authority to license its nationals or other entities subject to its jurisdiction to engage in that prohibited activity. Jenks argues that “States bear international responsibility for national activities in space; it follows that what is forbidden to a State is not permitted to a chartered company created by a State or to one of its nationals acting as a private adventurer”9 . It has been also suggested that the prohibition of national appropriation implies prohibition of private appropriation because the latter cannot exist independently from the former10. In order to exist, indeed, private property requires a superior authority to enforce it, be in the form of a State or some other recognised entity. In outer space, however, this practice of State endorsement is forbidden. Should a State recognise or protect the territorial acquisitions of any of its subjects, this would constitute a form of national appropriation in violation of Article II. Moreover, it is possible to use some historical elements to support the argument that both the acquisition of State sovereignty and the creation of private property rights are forbidden by the words of Article II. During the negotiations of the Outer Space Treaty, the Delegate of Belgium affirmed that his delegation “had taken note of the interpretation of the non-appropriation advanced by several delegations-apparently without contradiction-as covering both the establishment of sovereignty and the creation of titles to property in private law”11. The French Delegate stated that: “…there was reason to be satisfied that three basic principles were affirmed, namely: the prohibition of any claim of sovereignty or property rights in space…”12. The fact that the accessions to the Outer Space Treaty were not accompanied by reservations or interpretations of the meaning of Article II, it is an evidence of the fact that this issue was considered to be settled during the negotiation phase. Thus, summing up, we may say that prohibition of appropriation of outer space and its parts is a rule which is valid for both private and public entity. The theory that private operators are not subject to this rule represents a myth that is not supported by any valid legal argument. Moreover, it can be also added that if any subject was allowed to appropriate parts of outer space, the basic aim of the drafters of the Treaty, namely to prevent a colonial competition in outer space and to create the conditions and premises for an exploration and use of outer space carried out for the benefit of all States, would be betrayed. Therefore, the need to protect the non-appropriative nature of outer space emerges in all its relevance.
5,966
<h4>We’ll defend normal means as the signatories of the OST adding an optional protocol under Article II.</h4><p><u><strong>Tronchetti 7</u></strong>[Fabio Tronchetti is a professor at the International Institute of Air and Space Law, Leiden University, The Netherlands, 2007, https://iislweb.org/docs/Diederiks2007.pdf<u>, 12-15-2021 amrita]</p><p></u>ARTICLE II OF THE OUTER SPACE TREATY: A MATTER OF DEBATE <u>The legal content of Article II of the Outer Space Treaty is one of the most debated and analysed topic in the field of space law</u>. Indeed, several interpretations have been put forward to explain the meaning of its provisions. Article II states that: “Outer space, including the Moon and other celestial bodies, is not subject to national appropriation by claim of sovereignty, by means of use or occupation, or by any other means<u>”. <strong><mark>The text of Article II represents</strong> </mark>the final point of a process, formally initiated with Resolution 1721, aimed at conferring to outer space the status of res communis omnium, namely a thing open for the <strong><mark>free exploration</strong> </mark>and use by all States <strong><mark>without the possibility of being appropriated</u></strong></mark>. By prohibiting the possibility of making territorial claims over outer space or any part thereof based on use or occupation<u>, Article II <strong><mark>makes clear that</strong> </mark>the customary procedures of <strong><mark>i</strong></mark>nternational <strong><mark>law allowing</strong> </mark>subjects to obtain <strong><mark>sovereignty rights over un-owed lands</strong></mark>, namely discovery, occupatio and effective possession, <strong><mark>do not apply to</strong> </mark>outer <strong><mark>space</u>.</strong> </mark>This prohibition was considered by the drafters of the Outer Space Treaty the best guarantee for preserving outer space for peaceful activities only and for stimulating the exploration and use of the space environment in the name of all mankind. What has been the object of controversy among legal scholars is <u>the question of whether both States and private individuals are subjected to the provisions of Article II. Indeed, <strong><mark>while Article II forbids</strong> </mark>expressis verbis the national <strong><mark>appropriation by</strong></mark> claims of <strong><mark>sovereignty</strong></mark>, by means of use and occupation or other means of outer space, <strong><mark>it does not</strong> </mark>make <strong><mark>a</strong></mark>ny explicit <strong><mark>mention</strong> <strong>to</strong></mark> its <strong><mark>private</strong></mark> appropriation</u>. Relying on this consideration, <u>some authors have argued that the private appropriation of outer space and celestial bodies is allowed.</u> For instance, in 1968 Gorove wrote: “Thus, at present an individual acting on his own behalf or on behalf of another individual or private association or an international organisation could lawfully appropriate any parts of outer space…”6 . <u>The same argument is used today by the enterprises selling extraterrestrial acres. They base their claim to the Moon and other celestial bodies on the consideration that Article II does not explicitly forbid private individuals and enterprises to claim, exploit or appropriate the celestial bodies for profit</u>7 . However, it must be said, that nowadays <u>there is a general consensus on the fact that <strong><mark>both national appropriation and private</strong> </mark>property rights <strong><mark>are denied</strong></mark> under the Outer Space Treaty</u>. Several way of reasoning have been advanced to support this view. Sters and Tennen affirm that the argument that Article II does not apply to private entities since they are not expressly mentioned fails for the reason that they do not need to be explicitly listed in Article II to be fully subject to the non-appropriation principle8 . <u><strong><mark>Private entities are allowed to carry out</strong> </mark>space <strong><mark>activities but</strong></mark>, according to Article VI of the Outer Space Treaty, they <strong><mark>must be authorized</strong> </mark>to conduct such activities <strong><mark>by the</strong> </mark>appropriate <strong><mark>State</strong></mark> of nationality. But if the State is prohibited from engaging in certain conduct, then it lacks the authority to license its nationals or other entities subject to its jurisdiction to engage in that prohibited activity</u>. Jenks argues that “States bear international responsibility for national activities in space; it follows that what is forbidden to a State is not permitted to a chartered company created by a State or to one of its nationals acting as a private adventurer”9 . It has been also suggested that <u><strong><mark>the prohibition of national</strong> </mark>appropriation <strong><mark>implies prohibition of private</strong> </mark>appropriation because the latter cannot exist independently from the former10. In order to exist, indeed, private property requires a superior authority to enforce it, be in the form of a State or some other recognised entity</u>. In outer space, however, this practice of State endorsement is forbidden. Should a State recognise or protect the territorial acquisitions of any of its subjects, this would constitute a form of national appropriation in violation of Article II. <u>Moreover, it is possible to use some historical elements to support the argument that both the acquisition of State sovereignty and the creation of private property rights are forbidden by the words of Article II.</u> During the negotiations of the Outer Space Treaty, the Delegate of Belgium affirmed that his delegation “had taken note of the interpretation of the non-appropriation advanced by several delegations-apparently without contradiction-as covering both the establishment of sovereignty and the creation of titles to property in private law”11. The French Delegate stated that: “…there was reason to be satisfied that three basic principles were affirmed, namely: the prohibition of any claim of sovereignty or property rights in space…”12. The fact that the accessions to the Outer Space Treaty were not accompanied by reservations or interpretations of the meaning of Article II, it is an evidence of the fact that this issue was considered to be settled during the negotiation phase<u>. Thus, summing up, we may say that <strong><mark>prohibition of appropriation of outer space</strong> </mark>and its parts is a rule which <strong><mark>is valid for both private and public entity</strong></mark>. The theory that private operators are not subject to this rule represents a myth that is not supported by any valid legal argument.</u> Moreover, it can be also added that if any subject was allowed to appropriate parts of outer space, the basic aim of the drafters of the Treaty, namely to prevent a colonial competition in outer space and to create the conditions and premises for an exploration and use of outer space carried out for the benefit of all States, would be betrayed. <u>Therefore, <strong><mark>the need to protect the non-appropriative nature o</strong></mark>f outer <strong><mark>space emerges</strong> </mark>in all its relevance.</p></u>
1AC
1AC—Plan
null
334,988
245
42,489
./documents/hsld21/MontaVista/Ra/Monta%20Vista-Rastogi-Aff-Harvard%20Westlake-Round2.docx
895,075
A
Harvard Westlake
2
Peninsula SM
Nick Fleming
1AC - mining 1NC - US PIC DIB DA 1AR - all 2NR - all 2AR - all
hsld21/MontaVista/Ra/Monta%20Vista-Rastogi-Aff-Harvard%20Westlake-Round2.docx
null
75,115
KeRa
Monta Vista KeRa
null
Ke.....
Ra.....
null
null
25,087
MontaVista
Monta Vista
CA
null
1,029
hsld21
HS LD 2021-22
2,021
ld
hs
1
1,056,067
2. Challenges---A federal PTD creates a path to challenge federal, state and private actors increasing emissions as failing to protect water resources. Solves emissions.
Kelly ’19
Kelly ’19 — Carolyn Kelly, Assistant District Counsel at the New York District of the U.S. Army Corps of Engineers, J.D., NYU School of Law, B.A. from the University of Chicago; (2019; “ARTICLE: WHERE THE WATER MEETS THE SKY: HOW AN UNBROKEN LINE OF PRECEDENT FROM JUSTINIAN TO JULIANA SUPPORTS THE POSSIBILITY OF A FEDERAL ATMOSPHERIC PUBLIC TRUST DOCTRINE”; University of Michigan Libraries, Nexus Uni; New York University Environmental Law Journal, Vol. 27; //LFS—JCM)
courts will continue to define the scope and applicability of the public trust doctrine as Juliana and its sister atmospheric public trust cases advance in the federal courts Modern science has shown a clear connection between air and water quality science has shown a connection between increased atmospheric concentrations of greenhouse gases and warmer oceans and navigable waters ocean acidity and lower oxygen levels Elevated levels of greenhouse gases have been directly linked to public resources held in trust by the federal government Puerto Rico and the Virgin Islands have been devastated by stronger storms made more probable by a warmer wetter world These territories' navigable waters held in trust by the federal government have been threatened by the risk of flooding traditional public trust uses including navigation and fishing have been compromised by the storm greenhouse gases also raise the temperature of the territorial seas affecting the fish population at every stage of the life cycle This puts stress on deep sea fisheries at a time when stocks are already falling Climate change is threatening the most traditional of public trust uses the federal government is the sovereign and trustee of the territorial seas with a responsibility to preserve the seas in trust for the people When considering air within the public trust the connection between air and navigable waters and other public trust resources and federal authority over trust resources in the U.S. territories and territorial seas points to the existence of a federal atmospheric public trust plaintiffs have fleshed out the nexus between water and sky between aquatic public trust resources and the atmosphere concentration of CO2 and methane in the atmosphere has endangered the water they drink and the fish they eat we cannot safeguard the aquatic public trust without protecting the atmospheric public trust This connection between the aquatic and the atmospheric public trust has also laid the groundwork for other plaintiffs industry might sue federal or state government agencies for failing to restrain the fossil fuel industry They could credibly argue concentrations of CO2 in the atmosphere acidify the ocean decimating oysters crabs mussels and any sea creature fishing could argue that warming air leads to warming waters which threatens fish stocks communities hit by hurricanes could sue federal or state governments for failing to rein in the fossil fuel industry can point to science showing that rising atmospheric temperatures lead to high ocean surface temperatures which fuel destructive hurricanes They can trace the damage to waterways as storm surge and inland flooding causes the sewers to overrun and the manure lagoons to overflow fouling surface waters and threatening supply of drinking water and fresh water fish
science has shown a connection between increased g h g s and warmer navigable waters levels of gases have been linked to public resources held in trust by the federal government territories' waters held by the fed been threatened by flooding the connection between air waters and federal authority points to a federal atmospheric trust CO2 and methane endangered water This has laid the groundwork for plaintiffs sue state s for failing to restrain the fossil industry They can trace damage to supply of water
The courts will certainly continue to define the scope and applicability of the public trust doctrine as Juliana and its sister atmospheric public trust cases advance or are dismissed in the federal and state courts. There are no easy answers when it comes [*237] to the public trust doctrine, but history, science, and law point to the possibility of including air within a federal public trust doctrine. Air has been included as a public trust resource since the time of the Institute of Justinian, 410 and U.S. courts have treated it as a public resource. 411 Modern science, which has shaped the evolution of the public trust doctrine in this country, has shown a clear connection between air and water quality. Specifically, science has shown a connection between increased atmospheric concentrations of greenhouse gases and warmer oceans and navigable waters, greater ocean acidity, and lower oxygen levels. 412 Elevated levels of greenhouse gases have also been directly linked to compromises in public resources held in trust by the federal government. 413 Puerto Rico and the U.S. Virgin Islands have been devastated by stronger storms made more probable by a warmer, wetter world. 414 These territories' navigable waters, which are held in trust by the federal government for the benefit of the people and potential future states, have been threatened by the risk of flooding of superfund sites. 415 Additionally, traditional public trust uses including navigation and fishing have been compromised by the storm. 416 Elevated levels of greenhouse gases also raise the temperature of the territorial seas, affecting the fish population at every stage of the life cycle. 417 This puts additional stress on deep sea fisheries at a time when fish stocks are already falling. 418 Climate change is threatening one of the most traditional of public trust uses - the right to fish the seas. 419 In this scenario, the federal government is [*238] the sovereign and trustee of the territorial seas, with a concomitant responsibility to preserve the seas in trust for the people. 420 When considering these issues together - the traditional inclusion of air within the public trust, the connection between air and navigable waters and other well-established public trust resources, and federal authority over trust resources in the U.S. territories and territorial seas - points to the existence of a federal atmospheric public trust. With the retirement of Justice Kennedy from the Supreme Court, it is difficult to know whether the plaintiffs will prevail if their case is appealed all the way to the Supreme Court. But they have, in any case, fleshed out the nexus between water and sky, between aquatic public trust resources and the atmosphere. 421 They have shown how the concentration of CO2 and methane in the atmosphere has endangered the water they drink and the fish they eat. 422 They have shown that we cannot safeguard the aquatic public trust without protecting the atmospheric public trust. 423 This connection between the aquatic and the atmospheric public trust has also laid the groundwork for other plaintiffs. For example, the fishing industry might sue federal or state government agencies for failing to restrain the fossil fuel industry. They could credibly argue that high concentrations of CO2 in the atmosphere acidify the ocean, decimating oysters, crabs, mussels, and any sea creature that grows a shell. Similarly, the fishing industry could argue that warming air leads to warming waters, which threatens already faltering fish stocks. Furthermore, communities hit by hurricanes could sue federal or state governments for failing to rein in the fossil fuel industry. These communities can now point to emerging science showing [*239] that rising atmospheric temperatures lead to high ocean surface temperatures, which fuel more powerful and destructive hurricanes. 424 They can trace the damage to their waterways, as storm surge and inland flooding causes the sewers to overrun and the manure lagoons to overflow, fouling surface waters and threatening the supply of drinking water and fresh water fish.
4,135
<h4>2. <u>Challenges</u>---A <u>federal</u> PTD creates a <u>path</u> to challenge <u>federal</u>, <u>state</u> and <u>private actors</u> increasing emissions as failing to <u>protect water resources</u>. Solves emissions.</h4><p><strong>Kelly ’19</strong> — Carolyn Kelly, Assistant District Counsel at the New York District of the U.S. Army Corps of Engineers, J.D., NYU School of Law, B.A. from the University of Chicago; (2019; “ARTICLE: WHERE THE WATER MEETS THE SKY: HOW AN UNBROKEN LINE OF PRECEDENT FROM JUSTINIAN TO JULIANA SUPPORTS THE POSSIBILITY OF A FEDERAL ATMOSPHERIC PUBLIC TRUST DOCTRINE”; University of Michigan Libraries, Nexus Uni; New York University Environmental Law Journal, Vol. 27; //LFS—JCM)</p><p>The <u>courts will</u> certainly <u>continue to</u> <u>define the scope</u> <u>and applicability</u> <u>of the <strong>public trust doctrine</u></strong> <u>as Juliana</u> <u>and its sister</u> <u>atmospheric public trust</u> <u>cases <strong>advance</u></strong> or are dismissed <u>in the federal</u> and state <u>courts</u>. There are no easy answers when it comes [*237] to the public trust doctrine, but history, science, and law point to the possibility of including air within a federal public trust doctrine. Air has been included as a public trust resource since the time of the Institute of Justinian, 410 and U.S. courts have treated it as a public resource. 411 <u>Modern <mark>science</u></mark>, which has shaped the evolution of the public trust doctrine in this country, <u><mark>has shown a</mark> <strong>clear <mark>connection</strong> between</u></mark> <u><strong>air and water</strong> quality</u>. Specifically, <u>science has shown</u> <u>a connection</u> <u>between</u> <u><mark>increased</u></mark> <u>atmospheric concentrations</u> <u>of <strong><mark>g</mark>reen<mark>h</mark>ouse <mark>g</mark>ase<mark>s</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>and</mark> <strong><mark>warmer</mark> oceans</u></strong> <u>and <mark>navigable waters</u></mark>, greater <u><strong>ocean acidity</u></strong>, <u>and lower <strong>oxygen levels</u></strong>. 412</p><p><u>Elevated <mark>levels</u> <u>of</mark> greenhouse <mark>gases</u> <u>have</u></mark> also <u><mark>been</mark> directly <mark>linked</u> <u>to</u></mark> compromises in <u><strong><mark>public resources</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>held in trust</u></mark> <u><mark>by the</u></mark> <u><mark>federal government</u></mark>. 413 <u><strong>Puerto Rico</strong> and the</u> U.S. <u><strong>Virgin Islands</u></strong> <u>have been</u> <u>devastated by <strong>stronger storms</u></strong> <u>made more probable</u> <u>by a warmer</u>, <u>wetter world</u>. 414 <u>These <mark>territories'</u></mark> <u>navigable <mark>waters</u></mark>, which are <u><mark>held</mark> in trust <mark>by</u> <u>the</mark> <strong><mark>fed</mark>eral government</u></strong> for the benefit of the people and potential future states, <u>have <mark>been threatened</u> <u>by</mark> the <strong>risk of <mark>flooding</u></strong></mark> of superfund sites. 415 Additionally, <u>traditional public trust uses</u> <u>including <strong>navigation and fishing</u></strong> <u>have been</u> <u>compromised by the</u> <u>storm</u>. 416</p><p>Elevated levels of <u><strong>greenhouse gases</u></strong> <u>also raise the</u> <u>temperature of the</u> <u>territorial seas</u>, <u><strong>affecting the fish population</u></strong> <u>at every stage</u> <u>of the life cycle</u>. 417 <u>This puts</u> additional <u>stress on deep sea</u> <u>fisheries at a time when</u> fish <u>stocks are already falling</u>. 418 <u>Climate change</u> <u>is threatening</u> one of <u>the most</u> <u>traditional of</u> <u><strong>public trust uses</u></strong> - the right to fish the seas. 419 In this scenario, <u>the <strong>federal</strong> government is</u> [*238] <u>the sovereign and</u> <u><strong>trustee of the territorial seas</u></strong>, <u>with a</u> concomitant <u>responsibility to preserve</u> <u>the <strong>seas in trust</u></strong> <u>for the people</u>. 420</p><p><u>When considering</u> these issues together - the traditional inclusion of <u>air within</u> <u>the public trust</u>, <u><mark>the connection</u></mark> <u><mark>between <strong>air </mark>and navigable <mark>waters</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>and</mark> other</u> well-established <u><strong>public trust resources</u></strong>, <u>and <mark>federal authority</u></mark> <u>over trust resources</u> <u>in the U.S.</u> <u>territories and</u> <u>territorial seas</u> - <u><mark>points to</mark> the existence</u> <u>of <mark>a <strong>federal</mark> <mark>atmospheric</mark> public <mark>trust</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>With the retirement of Justice Kennedy from the Supreme Court, it is difficult to know whether the <u>plaintiffs</u> will prevail if their case is appealed all the way to the Supreme Court. But they <u>have</u>, in any case, <u>fleshed out the</u> <u><strong>nexus between water and sky</u></strong>, <u>between aquatic</u> <u><strong>public trust resources</u></strong> <u>and the <strong>atmosphere</u></strong>. 421 They have shown how the <u>concentration of</u> <u><strong><mark>CO2 and methane</u></strong></mark> <u>in the atmosphere</u> <u>has <mark>endangered</mark> the <mark>water</u></mark> <u>they drink and</u> <u>the fish they eat</u>. 422 They have shown that <u>we cannot safeguard</u> <u>the aquatic</u> <u>public trust</u> <u>without protecting</u> <u>the <strong>atmospheric public trust</u></strong>. 423</p><p><u><mark>This</u></mark> <u>connection</u> <u>between</u> <u>the aquatic</u> <u>and the</u> <u>atmospheric public trust</u> <u><mark>has</mark> also <strong><mark>laid the groundwork</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>for</mark> other <mark>plaintiffs</u></mark>. For example, the fishing <u>industry might</u> <u><mark>sue</mark> <strong>federal or <mark>state</mark> government</u></strong> <u>agencie<mark>s</mark> <mark>for failing</u> <u>to</mark> <mark>restrain</u></mark> <u><mark>the</mark> <strong><mark>fossil</mark> fuel <mark>industry</u></strong></mark>. <u>They could</u> <u>credibly argue</u> that high <u>concentrations of CO2</u> <u>in the atmosphere</u> <u><strong>acidify the ocean</u></strong>, <u>decimating</u> <u>oysters</u>, <u>crabs</u>, <u>mussels</u>, <u>and <strong>any sea creature</u></strong> that grows a shell. Similarly, the <u>fishing</u> industry <u>could argue that</u> <u><strong>warming air</strong> leads</u> <u>to <strong>warming waters</u></strong>, <u>which threatens</u> already faltering <u>fish stocks</u>.</p><p>Furthermore, <u>communities hit by hurricanes could</u> <u><strong>sue federal or state governments</u></strong> <u>for failing to rein</u> <u>in the <strong>fossil fuel industry</u></strong>. These communities <u>can</u> now <u>point to</u> emerging <u>science showing</u> [*239] <u>that rising atmospheric</u> <u>temperatures lead to</u> <u>high ocean <strong>surface temperatures</u></strong>, <u>which fuel</u> more powerful and <u>destructive hurricanes</u>. 424 <u><mark>They can <strong>trace</mark> the <mark>damage</strong></mark> to</u> their <u>waterways</u>, <u>as storm surge</u> <u>and inland flooding causes</u> <u>the sewers <mark>to</u></mark> <u>overrun and the</u> <u>manure lagoons to overflow</u>, <u>fouling surface waters</u> <u>and threatening</u> the <u><mark>supply of</mark> <strong>drinking <mark>water</u></strong></mark> <u>and <strong>fresh water fish</u></strong>.</p>
1AC---Alta
1AC---Full Text
1AC---Water Resources ADV
33,689
203
25,490
./documents/hspolicy21/Alpharetta/JiMo/Alpharetta-Jivangikar-Momin-Aff-Alta-Round1.docx
743,439
A
Alta
1
Presentation BR
Josh Johnwell
1AC - PTD 2NR - SetCol
hspolicy21/Alpharetta/JiMo/Alpharetta-Jivangikar-Momin-Aff-Alta-Round1.docx
null
63,315
JiMo
Alpharetta JiMo
null
Sa.....
Ji.....
Es.....
Mo.....
21,871
Alpharetta
Alpharetta
GA
null
1,020
hspolicy21
HS Policy 2021-22
2,021
cx
hs
2
4,749,958
Asia War escalates – outweighs.
Gady 17
Gady 17 Franz-Stefan Gady 8-3-2017 “The Coming War in Asia: Why It Is Hard to Imagine the Unimaginable” https://thediplomat.com/2017/08/the-coming-war-in-asia-why-it-is-hard-to-imagine-the-unimaginable/ (Research Fellow with the International Institute for Strategic Studies in London)//Elmer
the Asia-Pacific region is the most militarized region in the world the three largest defense budgets in the world (the United States, China, and Russia) are by countries with significant military assets in the region. Six Asia-Pacific powers were under the top ten global military spenders in 2016. The world’s seven largest militaries are all in Asia out of the seven six are nuclear powers. profound neglected dangers lurk behind the increasing militarization of the region with its numerous territorial disputes on both land and sea and frozen conflicts, and which at the same time lacks a regional security structure if you only have a hammer, sooner or later most problems will look like nails Given the growing military arsenals, Asia-Pacific policymakers may be more willing to use military force to achieve political objectives and settle disputes while all Asia-Pacific powers are expanding their militaries, no military force save the United States’ has had any extensive combat experience, nor any nation firsthand knowledge of what it means to fight an interstate conflict in the 21st century lack of understanding of what it means to go to war, combined with a regional arms race, and various territorial disputes, can create a fertile habitat for strategic miscalculations over the use of military power. a risk cycle governs interstate relations in Asia, which consists of uncertainty, insecurity, and instability Asian nations have gone through numerous iterations of this cycle without ever succeeding in reversing it. As a result, the Asia-Pacific region remains stuck in instability, the last stage of the cycle that can cause large-scale military conflict once the risk cycle reaches this last stage, instability, the immediate question is how bad it will become and whether minor flare-ups will turn into serious clashes.” whether a small military clash can lead to large-scale war We have become so used to this perpetual cycle of instability and constant confrontations, whether on the Korean Peninsula, in the East China Sea, or along the Indo-Pakistan border that we have lost sight of the inherent danger that each of these confrontations pose to the general peace in the Asia-Pacific region the next big war in the Asia-Pacific may come as an apparent surprise when we least expect it. the current instability in the Asia-Pacific cannot endure indefinitely.
Asia- is the most militarized region The world’s seven largest militaries are all in Asia out of the seven six are nuclear powers. profound dangers lurk behind increasing militarization territorial disputes lacks a regional security structure Given military arsenals, Asia policymakers more willing to use military force can create a fertile habitat for miscalculations over the use of military power. a small clash can lead to large-scale war
There has not been a large-scale war in Asia since 1945. Interstate conflicts in the region over the past decades included the 1962 Sino-Indian War, the 1971 Indo-Pakistani War, the 1979 Sino-Vietnamese Border War, and the 1999 Kargil War. With the exception of the 1971 clash between India and Pakistan (along with the Bangladesh Liberation War), these wars were low in casualties and involved limited military resources. Nevertheless, the Asia-Pacific region is the most militarized region in the world. According to the International Institute of Strategic Studies’ Military Balance 2017, the three largest defense budgets in the world (the United States, China, and Russia) are by countries with significant military assets in the region. Six Asia-Pacific powers were under the top ten global military spenders in 2016. The world’s seven largest militaries including China, the United States, India, North Korea, Russia, Pakistan, and South Korea are all (at least partly) found in Asia. Furthermore, out of the seven six are nuclear powers. While these statistics are nothing new to Diplomat readers, they are worth restating to illustrate the profound and often neglected dangers that lurk behind the increasing militarization of the region with its numerous territorial disputes on both land and sea and frozen conflicts, and which at the same time lacks a regional security structure and political community akin to, for example, NATO and the European Union in Europe. The old maxim that if you only have a hammer, sooner or later most problems will look like nails is in particular pertinent in that respect: Given the growing military arsenals, Asia-Pacific policymakers may be more willing to use military force to achieve political objectives and settle disputes. This is further accentuated by the fact that while all Asia-Pacific powers are expanding their militaries, no military force save the United States’ has had any extensive combat experience, nor any nation firsthand knowledge of what it means to fight an interstate conflict in the 21st century. Based on historical evidence (e.g. European militaries prior to the First World War), this lack of understanding of what it means to go to war, combined with a regional arms race, and various territorial disputes, can create a fertile habitat for strategic miscalculations over the use of military power. In his book The End of the Asian Century, Michael R. Auslin outlines a risk cycle that he thinks governs interstate relations in Asia, which consists of three components: uncertainty, insecurity, and instability. Auslin argues that Asian nations have gone through numerous iterations of this cycle (which begins with uncertainty, followed by insecurity, and ends in instability) over the last decades without, however, ever succeeding in reversing it. As a result, the Asia-Pacific region remains stuck in instability, the last stage of the cycle that can cause large-scale military conflict. “War is not preordained, but once the risk cycle reaches this last stage, instability, the immediate question is how bad it will become and whether minor flare-ups will turn into serious clashes.” The question whether a small military clash can lead to large-scale war has indeed plagued decision-makers throughout history. We have become so used to this perpetual cycle of instability and constant confrontations, whether on the Korean Peninsula, in the East China Sea, or along the Indo-Pakistan border that we have lost sight of the inherent danger that each of these confrontations pose to the general peace in the Asia-Pacific region. As a result, despite our best efforts, the next big war in the Asia-Pacific, like most military conflicts, may come as an apparent surprise when we least expect it. For what is clear is that the current instability in the Asia-Pacific cannot endure indefinitely.
3,871
<h4>Asia War <u>escalates</u> – outweighs. </h4><p><strong>Gady 17</strong> Franz-Stefan Gady 8-3-2017 “The Coming War in Asia: Why It Is Hard to Imagine the Unimaginable” https://thediplomat.com/2017/08/the-coming-war-in-asia-why-it-is-hard-to-imagine-the-unimaginable/<u> (Research Fellow with the International Institute for Strategic Studies in London)//Elmer </p><p></u> There has not been a large-scale war in Asia since 1945. Interstate conflicts in the region over the past decades included the 1962 Sino-Indian War, the 1971 Indo-Pakistani War, the 1979 Sino-Vietnamese Border War, and the 1999 Kargil War. With the exception of the 1971 clash between India and Pakistan (along with the Bangladesh Liberation War), these wars were low in casualties and involved limited military resources. Nevertheless, <u>the <mark>Asia-</mark>Pacific region <mark>is the <strong>most militarized region</strong> </mark>in the world</u>. According to the International Institute of Strategic Studies’ Military Balance 2017, <u>the three largest defense budgets in the world (the United States, China, and Russia) are by countries with significant military assets in the region. <strong>Six</strong> Asia-Pacific powers were under the <strong>top ten</strong> global military <strong>spenders</strong> in 2016. <mark>The world’s <strong>seven largest militaries</strong></mark> </u>including China, the United States, India, North Korea, Russia, Pakistan, and South Korea <u><mark>are all</u></mark> (at least partly) found <u><mark>in Asia</u></mark>. Furthermore, <u><strong><mark>out of the seven six are nuclear powers</strong>.</mark> </u>While these statistics are nothing new to Diplomat readers, they are worth restating to illustrate the <u><mark>profound</u></mark> and often <u>neglected <mark>dangers</u></mark> that <u><mark>lurk behind</mark> the <strong><mark>increasing militarization</strong></mark> of the region with its numerous <strong><mark>territorial disputes</strong></mark> on both land and sea and frozen conflicts, and which at the same time <mark>lacks a <strong>regional security structure</u></strong></mark> and political community akin to, for example, NATO and the European Union in Europe. The old maxim that <u>if you only have a hammer, sooner or later most problems will look like nails</u> is in particular pertinent in that respect: <u><strong><mark>Given</strong> </mark>the growing <strong><mark>military arsenals, Asia</strong></mark>-Pacific <mark>policymakers </mark>may be <strong><mark>more willing</strong> to use military <strong>force</strong></mark> to achieve political objectives and settle disputes</u>. This is further accentuated by the fact that <u>while all Asia-Pacific powers are expanding their militaries, <strong>no</strong> military force save the United States’ has had any extensive <strong>combat experience</strong>, nor any nation firsthand knowledge of what it means to fight an interstate conflict in the 21st century</u>. Based on historical evidence (e.g. European militaries prior to the First World War), this <u>lack of understanding of what it means to go to war, combined with a regional arms race, and various territorial disputes, <mark>can create a <strong>fertile habitat</strong> for </mark>strategic <strong><mark>miscalculations over the use of military power</strong>. </u></mark>In his book The End of the Asian Century, Michael R. Auslin outlines <u>a risk cycle</u> that he thinks <u>governs interstate relations in Asia, which consists of</u> three components: <u>uncertainty, insecurity, and instability</u>. Auslin argues that <u>Asian nations have gone through numerous iterations of this cycle</u> (which begins with uncertainty, followed by insecurity, and ends in instability) over the last decades <u>without</u>, however, <u>ever succeeding in reversing it. As a result, the Asia-Pacific region remains stuck in <strong>instability</strong>, the last stage of the cycle that can cause <strong>large-scale military conflict</u></strong>. “War is not preordained, but <u>once the risk cycle reaches this last stage, instability, the immediate question is how bad it will become and whether minor flare-ups will turn into serious clashes.” </u>The question <u>whether <mark>a <strong>small </mark>military <mark>clash</strong> can lead to <strong>large-scale war</u></strong></mark> has indeed plagued decision-makers throughout history. <u>We have become so used to this perpetual cycle of instability and constant confrontations, <strong>whether on the Korean Peninsula, in the East China Sea, or along the Indo-Pakistan border that we have lost sight of the inherent danger that each of these confrontations pose to the general peace in the Asia-Pacific region</u></strong>. As a result, despite our best efforts, <u>the next big war in the Asia-Pacific</u>, like most military conflicts, <u>may come as an apparent surprise when we least expect it.</u> For what is clear is that <u>the current instability in the Asia-Pacific cannot endure indefinitely.</p></u>
TOC R5 AC v BASIS Silicon Valley SK
null
1AC: ASEAN
109,110
259
166,135
./documents/hsld22/MercerIsland/KaSh/MercerIsland-KaSh-Aff-TOC-Round-5.docx
996,288
A
TOC
5
BASIS Silicon Valley SK
Jack Quisenberry
1ac- asean v4 1nc- t-conditional, csa, util bad, tt, zombies, t-resolved, cap, idk, reid-brinkley, case 1ar-th all 2nr- th tt 2ar- comp worlds tt
hsld22/MercerIsland/KaSh/MercerIsland-KaSh-Aff-TOC-Round-5.docx
2023-04-17 16:04:12
80,193
KaSh
Mercer Island KaSh
null
Ka.....
Sh.....
null
null
26,963
MercerIsland
Mercer Island
WA
null
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
4,790,327
Outweighs on magnitude---populism undermines response to every large impact
Leigh 21
Dr. Andrew Leigh 21, PhD from Harvard, Member of the Australian House of Representatives, former Professor in the Economics Program of the Research School of Social Sciences at Australian National University, “What's the Worst That Could Happen: Existential Risk and Extreme Politics”, MIT University Press, ebook
humanity could become extinct with out-of-control superintelligence, bioterrorism, and totalitarianism among the largest risks we are playing a game of Russian roulette with humanity’s future imagine our species becoming extinct due to a catastrophe such as nuclear war, asteroids, or a pandemic the danger surpasses plenty of perils we already worry about Extinction risk outstrips other dangers we have another one billion years before the increasing heat of our sun brings most plant life to an end That’s plenty of time to figure out how to become an interstellar species and move to a more suitable solar system humans aren’t good at understanding extinction risk Our thinking about dangers is skewed by an “availability bias”: a tendency to focus on familiar risks we are lousy at judging the probability of rare but catastrophic events our instincts fail us as the magnitudes grow larger In this environment, a special style of politics has thrived: populism Populists see politics as a conflict between crooked elites and the pure mass of people populists make a stronger attack on elites, claiming that they are dishonest or corrupt. Populists then claim that they—and only they—represent the “real people The political strategy of populists involves critiquing intellectuals, institutions, and internationalism. The political style of populists tends to be fierce They have little respect for experts and the systems of government electoral success of populists has served to sideline work on long-term dangers such as climate change and nuclear war Trump lost but transformed the Republican Party while the strength of populism threatened to sideline issues of catastrophic risk, coronavirus did the opposite COVID-19 never threatened to extinguish humanity, but it highlighted our vulnerability to infectious diseases But it’s still an open question as to how COVID-19 will affect humanity’s ability to think about the long term accentuating the long term requires taking risk more seriously and placing greater emphasis on saving our species the biggest risks facing humanity such as the next virus might combine the infectiousness of COVID-19 with the deadliness of Ebola bioterrorism, and danger of extremists developing their own versions of smallpox or the bubonic plague climate change could be catastrophic rendering large sections of the planet uninhabitable threat from new nuclear powers has made the problem less predictable what we used to call an arms race now looks more like a bar fight, with hazards coming from unexpected directions, including terrorist groups sensible strategies can reduce the odds of nuclear catastrophe superintelligence has been dubbed the “last invention” we’ll ever make a i whose abilities exceed our own could spell disaster Once a superintelligence can improve itself, it is unstoppable we need to build the guardrails before the highway also consider unknown unknowns other doomsday scenarios could be lurking around the corner tackling existential risks is a political problem preventing nuclear war, averting bioterrorism, and curbing greenhouse emissions are problems of government the values of those who run the country will determine how much of a priority the nation places on averting catastrophe. That’s why the rise of populists is crucial to humanity’s long- term survival populists tend to be uninterested in dealing with long-term threats. Populists’ focus on the short term means we’re in danger of missing the threats that could kill us Most critics of populism have concentrated on the present day. They’re missing the bigger picture. Populists are primarily endangering the unborn Bad politics doesn’t just exacerbate other dangers; it represents a risk factor in itself through the possibility of a totalitarian turn in which democracy is replaced by an enduring autocracy For each of the existential risks we face, there are sensible approaches that could curtail the dangers Because of its focus on the urgent over the important, populist politics should bear the label, “Warning: populism can harm your children what is the alternative? A stoic approach to politics isn’t about favoring one side of the ideological fence over another. Instead, it’s about the temperament of good political leadership Decisions are based on empirical evidence, not emotion. Anger has no place in effective leadership
humanity could become extinct with superintelligence, totalitarianism nuclear war, asteroids a pandemic Extinction risk outstrips other dangers populists critiq institutions, and internationalism sideline work on climate change and nuclear war the biggest risks such as next virus combine infectiousness with deadliness extremists developing versions of plague climate change rendering the planet uninhabitable nuclear catastrophe superintelligence could spell disaster unknown unknowns could be lurking tackling ex risks is a political problem rise of populists is crucial to humanity’s survival populists tend to be uninterested in long-term threats Bad politics doesn’t just exacerbate other dangers a risk factor in itself
How likely is it that humanity could end? Experts working on catastrophic risk have estimated the chances of disaster for a wide range of the hazards that our species faces. Adding up the threats, philosopher Toby Ord estimates the odds that humanity could become extinct over the next century at one in six, with an out-of-control superintelligence, bioterrorism, and totalitarianism among the largest risks. He argues that most of the risks have arisen because technology has advanced more rapidly than safeguards to keep it in check. To encapsulate the situation facing humanity, Ord titled his book The Precipice. A one in six chance of going the way of dodos and dinosaurs effectively means we are playing a game of Russian roulette with humanity’s future. Six chambers. One bullet. Even the most foolhardy soldier usually finds an excuse not to play Russian roulette. And that’s when just their own life is at stake. In considering extinction risk, we’re contemplating not one fatality but the death of billions or possibly trillions of people—not to mention countless animals. It can seem impossible to imagine our species becoming extinct due to a catastrophe such as nuclear war, asteroids, or a pandemic. But in reality, the danger surpasses plenty of perils we already worry about. One way to put catastrophic risk into perspective is to compare it with more familiar risks. If extinction risk poses a one in six risk to our species over the next century, then it means that it is far more hazardous than many everyday risks. Specifically, it suggests that the typical US resident is fifteen times more likely to die from a catastrophic risk—such as nuclear war or bioterrorism—than in car crash.2 Extinction risk outstrips other dangers too. Ask people about their greatest fears, and you’ll get answers like “street violence,” “snakes,” “heights,” and “terrorism."4 But in reality, these are much less hazardous than catastrophic risks. People in the United States are 31 times more likely to die from a catastrophic risk than from homicide. Catastrophic risk is 3,519 times likelier to kill than falls from a height, and 6,194 times more likely to kill than venomous plants and animals. If you have ever worried about any of these threats, you should be more fearful about cata- strophic risk. Extinction risks aren’t just more dangerous than any of them; they are more hazardous than all of them put together. Catastrophic risk poses a greater danger to the life of the typical US resident than car accidents, murder, drowning, high falls, electrocution, and rattlesnakes put together. A one in six risk is just the danger in a single century. Suppose that the risk of extinction remains at one in six for each century. That means there’s a five in six chance humanity makes it to the end of the twenty-first century, but less than an even chance we survive to the end of the twenty-fourth century. The odds that we survive all the way to the year 3000 are just one in six. In other words, if we continue playing Russian roulette once a century, it’s probable that we blow our brains out before the millennium is halfway through, and there’s only a small chance that we make it to the end of the millennium. Part of the reason humans undervalue the future is that it’s hard to get our heads around the idea that our genetic code could live on for millions of years. At present, the best estimates are that our species, Homo sapiens, evolved around three hundred thousand years ago.1 That means we have existed for about ten thousand generations. But we have another one billion years before the increasing heat of our sun brings most plant life to an end.1 That’s plenty of time to figure out how to become an interstellar species and move to a more suitable solar system. Humans could live to enjoy another thirty million generations on earth. Thinking about the mind-boggling scale of these numbers, I’m reminded of the Total Perspective Vortex machine, created by Douglas Adams in The Restaurant at the End of the Universe. Anyone brave enough to enter sees a scale model of the entire universe, with an arrow indicating their current position. As a result, their brain explodes. As Adams reflects, the machine proves that “if life is going to exist in a universe of this size, then the one thing it cannot afford to have is a sense of proportion.” Still, let’s try. Imagine your ancestors a hundred generations ago. They are your great-great-great-great-great-great-great- great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great- great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great- great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great- great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great- great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great- great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great- great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great- great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great- great-great-great-grandparents. These people lived around 1000 BCE, at the start of the Iron Age. They might have been part of Homeric Greece, ancient Egypt, Vedic age India, the preclassic Maya, or Zhou Dynasty China. Contemplate for a moment about what the hundred genera- tions between our Iron Age ancestors and today have achieved. They built the Taj Mahal and Sistine Chapel, the Angkor Wat and Empire State Building. Thanks to them, we can relish the poetry of Maya Angelou, novels of Leo Tolstoy, and music of Ludwig van Beethoven. An abundance of inventions has delivered us deli- cious food, homes that are comfortable year-round, and technol- ogy that provides online access to a bottomless well of entertain- ment. If time machines existed, we might pop in to visit our great100 grandparents, but few would volunteer to stay in the Iron Age. Yet humanity is really just getting started. If things go well, it’s ten thousand generations down, thirty million to go. Imagine what those future generations could do, and how much time they have to enjoy. Here’s one way to think about what it means to have thirty million generations ahead. Suppose humanity’s potential time on the planet was shrunk down to a single eighty- year life span. In that event, we would now be a newborn baby— just nine days old. Homo sapiens is a mere 0.03 percent through all we could experience on earth. We won’t meet most of those who follow us on the planet, but we should cherish future generations all the same. If you value humanity’s past achievements—the Aztec and Roman civiliza- tions, art of the Renaissance, and breakthroughs of the Industrial Revolution—then the generations to come are just as worthy. This is what political philosopher Edmund Burke meant when he described society as “a partnership not only between those who are living, but between those who are living, those who are dead, and those who are to be born.’- To appreciate the past is akin to admiring the achievements of distant places. Like geography, his- tory helps us better understand the way of the world. Politicians like me like to speak fondly about looking after "our children and our grandchildren.” But it usually stops after a generation or two. Policy pays little heed to the many generations that will follow. For my own part, it took a coronavirus-induced shutdown to have the time to spend reflecting deeply about the long term. This book had been rattling around in my head for years, but it was only when all my meetings, events, and travel were canceled that I had the time to write it. Pandemics are one of the threats to humanity that I’ll discuss in this book, but in this instance, it provided a chance to reflect on the long term. It’s tempting to ignore the distant future. It’s easier to love the grandchildren whom we hug than the great-great-great-grand- children whom we’ll never get to smile on. But that doesn’t make those far-flung generations any less important. Via my wife, our children can trace their lineage to Benjamin Franklin, but I’m more excited about the potential achievements of the generations yet to be born. For companies and governments, a major impediment to long- term thinking is the idea of discounting the future. When investing money, this is a reasonable approach. A dollar in a decade’s time is less valuable than a dollar today for the simple reason that a dollar today could be invested and earn a real return. Share markets have good and bad years, but based on returns from the past 120 years, someone who put $1,000 into the US stock market for an average year could expect it to be worth $1,065 after twelve months (accounting for dividends and inflation).2 Approximating these returns, when governments contemplate making investments, they often apply a discount rate of around 5 percent, while companies use rates that are higher still.2 When it comes to growing your greenbacks, this makes perfect sense. If Kanesha offered you $ 1,000 today, and Jane offered you $ 1,000 in a year’s time, most of us would think that Kanesha was making the more generous offer. Kanesha’s cash can be put to productive use and would be worth more than Jane’s when the year is out. But what if we’re talking about Kanesha and Jane themselves? Suppose Kanesha is alive today, and Jane is yet to be born. When discounting is applied to lives, it suggests that Kanesha’s life to- day is worth twice as much as Jane’s life in fifteen years’ time. It implies that Kanesha today is worth 132 times as much as Jane in a century’s time. So if we’re spending money to keep them safe, a 5 percent discount rate indicates that we should spend more than a hundred times as much to protect Kanesha today than to pro- tect Jane in a century’s time. The further we stretch the time period, the more ridiculous the results become. Discounting at a rate of 5 percent implies that Christopher Columbus is worth more than all eight billion people on the planet today.— Naturally, it also implies that your life is worth more than eight billion lives in five hundred years’ time. Even if you value the hug of a loved one over the unseen successes of next century’s generations, is it fair to ruthlessly dis- miss the distant future? Discounting is the enemy of the long term. As philosopher Will MacAskill points out, there is something morally repugnant about concluding that the happiness of those who will be alive in the 2100s is inconsequential simply because they live in the future. MacAskill coined the term “presentism” to refer to prejudice against people who are yet unborn.” Just like racism, sexism, or other forms of bigotry, he argues that mis- treating those who live a long way in the future is unfair. To dis- criminate in favor of Kanesha against unborn Jane is a form of presentism. If you traveled back in time to the 1500s and met someone who claimed that they were worth more than everyone alive in the 2000s, you’d rightly regard them as an egomaniac. Isn’t it equally narcissistic to ignore the happiness of people in the 2500s? Some have contended that we should favor the living over the unborn for the same reason that philanthropy favors the down- trodden over the wealthy. If incomes rise over time, the argument goes, then asking today’s citizens to help those in the future is like taking from the poor to give to the rich.— But this reasoning ignores the fact that we are talking about the survival of future generations. Theoretical riches won’t do them any good if they are practically dead—or if planetary apocalypse snuffs out their chance to be born. Similarly, it misses the possibility that future pandemics, wars, or climate disasters could make coming genera- tions significantly poorer.— Insights from behavioral science help explain why humans aren’t good at understanding extinction risk.— Our thinking about dangers is skewed by an “availability bias”: a tendency to focus on familiar risks. Like the traders who failed to forecast the collapse of the securitized housing debt market, we are lousy at judging the probability of rare but catastrophic events. Most important, our instincts fail us as the magnitudes grow larger. In research titled "The More Who Die, the Less We Care,” psychologists Paul Slovic and Daniel Vastfjall argue that we become numb to suffering as the body count grows.— Humans’ compassionate instincts are aroused by stories, not statistics. Indeed, one study found that people were more likely to donate to help a single victim than they were to assist eight victims. This may help explain why the international community has been so slow to respond to genocide, including recent incidents in Rwanda, Darfur, and Myanmar. As artificial intelligence researcher Eliezer Yudkowsky notes, human neurotransmitters are unable to feel sorrow that is thousands of times stronger than a single funeral.— The problem is starker still when it comes to extinction risk. Our emotional brains cannot multiply by billions. Add to this a media cycle that has become a media cyclone, in which stories explode in a matter of minutes, and “outrage porn” seems to drive the news choices of many outlets. In the 2016 US election, researchers found that for every piece of professional news shared on Twitter, there was one piece of “junk news.’’— Conflict fueled by social media keeps us in a primal state of rage and retaliation. And this isn’t the only force that makes politics myopic. Campaign contributions tend to come from donors who have an immediate interest in a “today” issue rather than from people aiming to solve long-term problems. This kind of “instant noodle” politics prioritizes quick results and sidelines fundamental challenges. In this environment, a special style of politics has thrived: populism. The term “populist" gets thrown around a lot—typically as an insult—so it’s worth taking a moment to define it precisely.— Populists see politics as a conflict between crooked elites and the pure mass of people. Many candidates trying to defeat an incumbent will criticize “insiders,” but populists make a stronger attack on elites, claiming that they are dishonest or corrupt. Populists then claim that they—and only they—represent the “real people.” Populists combine a fierce critique of elites and personal appeal to the “silent majority.” The political strategy of populists involves critiquing intellectuals, institutions, and internationalism. The political style of populists tends to be fierce. They do not strive for unity and calm consensus. Populists share with revolutionaries a desire for sudden and dramatic change. They have little respect for experts and the systems of government. Populists’ priorities tend to be immediate issues such as crime, migration, jobs, and taxes. Consequently, the electoral success of populists has served to sideline work on long-term dangers such as climate change and nuclear war. Donald Trump may have lost his presidential reelection bid, but he has transformed the Republican Party, which has jettisoned its longstanding commitment to free trade, immigration, and global alliances. Many moderate Republicans, who might have served comfortably under Ronald Reagan or George H. W. Bush, have quit the party or been defeated by Trump-supporting populists. The Republican Party, which holds nearly half the seats in Congress and controls a majority of state legislatures, has embraced populism to a degree that was unimaginable when it was led by George W. Bush, John McCain, or Mitt Romney. After four years under President Trump, the Republican Party is now more cynical and isolationist, focused on immediate grievances rather than long-term challenges. Yet while the strength of populism threatened to sideline issues of catastrophic risk, coronavirus did the opposite. The worst pandemic in a century led to the most severe economic crisis since the Great Depression. Churches and concert halls fell silent. International travel collapsed. The Summer Olympics were postponed. Stocks plunged, and for a brief moment, the price of a barrel of oil went negative. Globally, millions lost their jobs, and millions more faced famine. COVID-19 never threatened to extinguish humanity, but it highlighted our vulnerability to infectious diseases. More than at any time in living memory, people focused on the dangers of pandemics. The popularity of Geraldine Brooks’s Year of Wonders, Stephen King’s The Stand, Emily St. John Mandel’s Station Eleven, and Albert Camus’s The Plague vividly illustrates the way in which fear of pandemics has become more acute. We know that disasters can remake society. The black death helped usher in the Renaissance.— The Great Depression made a generation of investors more risk averse.— World War II spawned the United Nations and formed the modern welfare state. In autocracies, droughts and floods can topple dictators.— Coronavirus is reshaping the world in numerous ways.— Handwashing is in. Cheek kissing is out. The rise of big cities is slowing as people consider the downsides of density. Firms that automated their production systems to deal with physical dis- tancing requirements and stay-at-home orders are discovering that they can get by permanently with fewer staff. More tele- working and less business travel is leading to a drop in demand for receptionists, bus drivers, office cleaners, and security guards. When it comes to our use of technology, coronavirus suddenly accelerated the world to 2030. When it comes to globalization, the pandemic took us back to 2010. But it’s still an open question as to how COVID-19 will affect humanity’s ability to think about the long term. Most of the examples I’ve listed are instances in which crises affected societies organically: the shock came, and it changed our behavior. But accentuating the long term requires taking risk more seriously and placing greater emphasis on saving our species. Linebackers are swift to respond when an offensive player suddenly takes a step to the right. But it takes longer to recognize that a team’s offensive plays are skewed to the right and modify the defensive formation accordingly. Like a football team that adapts its tactics, this book argues that we should lengthen our thinking. At minimal cost, society can massively reduce the odds of catastrophe. By ensuring that the big threats get the attention and resources they need, we can safeguard the future of our species. As insurance policies go, this one is a bargain. In the chapters that follow, I’ll outline the biggest risks facing humanity. I’ll begin in chapter 2 with pandemics, such as the possibility that the next virus might combine the infectiousness of COVID-19 with the deadliness of Ebola. What can we do to shut down exotic animal markets, speed up vaccine develop- ment, and create surge capacity in hospitals? I’ll then delve into bioterrorism, and the danger of extremists developing their own versions of smallpox or the bubonic plague. How difficult is it for them to create these devilish diseases, and what can we do to prevent it? In chapter 3, I’ll then explore climate change—perhaps the in- tergenerational issue that has received the most public attention in recent years. While much of the modeling looks at how global warming could be bad, my focus is on the chances that it’s catastrophic. This isn’t about climate change shortening the ski season; it’s about the possibility of temperatures rising by 18°F (10°C), rendering large sections of the planet uninhabitable. What does the risk of cataclysmic climate change mean for energy policy? Next, I’ll turn to nukes. As a child in the 1980s, I vividly re- member watching The Day After. My classmates and I agreed that a nuclear war was inevitable. When the Cold War ended, the world seemed safer, but in the three decades since, the threat from new nuclear powers has made the problem less predictable. As I discuss in chapter 4, what we used to call an arms race now looks more like a bar fight, with hazards coming from unexpected directions, including terrorist groups. Yet just as there are practical ways to avoid pub brawls (don’t drink past midnight, avoid the stairs, look out for the glass), so too are there sensible strategies that can reduce the odds of nuclear catastrophe (adopt a “no first use" policy, reduce the stockpiles, control loose nukes). A superintelligence has been dubbed the “last invention” we’ll ever make. An artificial intelligence machine whose abilities exceed our own could turbocharge productivity and living stan- dards. But it could also spell disaster. If we program our artificial intelligence to maximize human happiness, it could fulfill our wishes literally by immobilizing everyone and attaching electrodes to the pleasure centers of our brains. As chapter 5 notes, what makes artificial intelligence different from every other risky technology is its runaway potential. Once a superintelligence can improve itself, it is unstoppable. So we need to build the guardrails before the highway. What are the odds? In chapter 6,1 complete the discussion of catastrophic danger by examining less risky risks, including asteroids and supervolcanoes. I also consider the prospect of “unknown unknowns.” For example, prior to the first atomic bomb test, some scientists thought there was a chance it could set the atmosphere on fire, destroying the planet. When the Large Hadron Collider was being built, critics warned that the particle collisions inside it could create micro black holes. Although neither situation eventuated, they raise the question of what other doomsday scenarios could be lurking around the corner. How should the prospect of these unexpected risks change our approach to cutting-edge science? Drawing together these dangers with the major hazards, I report the likely probability of each, benchmarking existential risks such as nuclear war and pandemics against individual risks such as being struck by lightning or dying on the battlefield. Ultimately, tackling existential risks is a political problem. Private citizens can achieve many things, but preventing nuclear war, averting bioterrorism, and curbing greenhouse emissions are fundamentally problems of government. Governments control the military, levy taxes, and provide public goods. So the values of those who run the country will determine how much of a priority the nation places on averting catastrophe. That’s why the rise of populists is crucial to humanity’s long- term survival. In chapter 7,1 discuss the factors that have led to the electoral success of populists during recent decades, and why populists tend to be uninterested in dealing with long-term threats. Populists’ focus on the short term means that—like a driver distracted by a back seat squabble—we’re in danger of missing the threats that could kill us. I’ll explore why populists around the world struggled to respond to COVID-19, and what this says about the dangers that populism poses to our species. Most critics of populism have concentrated on the present day. They’re missing the bigger picture. Populists are primarily endangering the unborn. Bad politics doesn’t just exacerbate other dangers; it represents a risk factor in itself through the possibility of a totalitarian turn —in which democracy is replaced by an enduring autocracy. The road to democracy is not a one-way street. Over the centuries, dozens of countries have backslid from democracy into autocracy —abandoning the institutions of fair elections, protection for minorities, and free expression. Such an outcome could be deadly for dissenters and miserable for the multitudes. Chapter 8 explores why democracy dies and identifies the signs that institutions are being undermined. Chapter 9 suggests how we might strengthen democracies to allow citizens to have a greater say, and lower the chances of the few taking over from the many. Chapter 10 concludes the book. When COVID-19 hit, many rushed out to buy life insurance.— In our personal lives, we know that spending a small amount on insurance can guard against financial ruin. Societies can take a similar approach: implementing modest measures today to safe- guard the immense future of our species. For each of the existential risks we face, there are sensible approaches that could curtail the dangers. For all the risks we face, a better politics will lead to a safer world. Because of its focus on the urgent over the important, populist politics should perhaps bear the label, “Warning: populism can harm your children." But what is the alternative? In the conclusion, I argue that the answer lies in the ancient philosophy of stoicism. A stoic approach to politics isn’t about favoring one side of the ideological fence over another. Instead, it’s about the temperament of good political leadership. Stoicism emphasizes that character matters and holds that virtue is the only good. Decisions are based on empirical evidence, not emotion. Anger has no place in effective leadership. Strength comes from civility, courage, and endurance. Stoics make a sharp distinction between the things they can change and those they cannot.
25,184
<h4>Outweighs on <u>magnitude</u>---populism undermines <u>response</u> to <u>every large impact</h4><p></u>Dr. Andrew <strong>Leigh 21</strong>, PhD from Harvard, Member of the Australian House of Representatives, former Professor in the Economics Program of the Research School of Social Sciences at Australian National University, “What's the Worst That Could Happen: Existential Risk and Extreme Politics”, MIT University Press, ebook</p><p>How likely is it that humanity could end? Experts working on catastrophic risk have estimated the chances of disaster for a wide range of the hazards that our species faces. Adding up the threats, philosopher Toby Ord estimates the odds that <u><mark>humanity could <strong>become extinct</u></strong></mark> over the next century at one in six, <u><mark>with</u></mark> an <u>out-of-control <mark>superintelligence, <strong></mark>bioterror</strong>ism, and <strong><mark>totalitarianism</strong></mark> among the largest risks</u>. He argues that most of the risks have arisen because technology has advanced more rapidly than safeguards to keep it in check. To encapsulate the situation facing humanity, Ord titled his book The Precipice.</p><p>A one in six chance of going the way of dodos and dinosaurs effectively means <u>we are playing a game of Russian roulette with humanity’s future</u>. Six chambers. One bullet. Even the most foolhardy soldier usually finds an excuse not to play Russian roulette. And that’s when just their own life is at stake. In considering extinction risk, we’re contemplating not one fatality but the death of billions or possibly trillions of people—not to mention countless animals.</p><p>It can seem impossible to <u>imagine our species becoming extinct due to a <strong>catastrophe</strong> such as <strong><mark>nuclear war</strong>, <strong>asteroids</strong></mark>, or <mark>a <strong>pandemic</u></strong></mark>. But in reality, <u>the danger surpasses plenty of perils we already worry about</u>. One way to put catastrophic risk into perspective is to compare it with more familiar risks. If extinction risk poses a one in six risk to our species over the next century, then it means that it is far more hazardous than many everyday risks. Specifically, it suggests that the typical US resident is fifteen times more likely to die from a catastrophic risk—such as nuclear war or bioterrorism—than in car crash.2</p><p><u><strong><mark>Extinction risk</strong> outstrips <strong>other dangers</u></strong></mark> too. Ask people about their greatest fears, and you’ll get answers like “street violence,” “snakes,” “heights,” and “terrorism."4 But in reality, these are much less hazardous than catastrophic risks. People in the United States are 31 times more likely to die from a catastrophic risk than from homicide. Catastrophic risk is 3,519 times likelier to kill than falls from a height, and 6,194 times more likely to kill than venomous plants and animals. If you have ever worried about any of these threats, you should be more fearful about cata- strophic risk. Extinction risks aren’t just more dangerous than any of them; they are more hazardous than all of them put together. Catastrophic risk poses a greater danger to the life of the typical US resident than car accidents, murder, drowning, high falls, electrocution, and rattlesnakes put together.</p><p>A one in six risk is just the danger in a single century. Suppose that the risk of extinction remains at one in six for each century. That means there’s a five in six chance humanity makes it to the end of the twenty-first century, but less than an even chance we survive to the end of the twenty-fourth century. The odds that we survive all the way to the year 3000 are just one in six. In other words, if we continue playing Russian roulette once a century, it’s probable that we blow our brains out before the millennium is halfway through, and there’s only a small chance that we make it to the end of the millennium.</p><p>Part of the reason humans undervalue the future is that it’s hard to get our heads around the idea that our genetic code could live on for millions of years. At present, the best estimates are that our species, Homo sapiens, evolved around three hundred thousand years ago.1 That means we have existed for about ten thousand generations. But <u>we have another one billion years before the increasing heat of our sun brings most plant life to an end</u>.1 <u>That’s plenty of time to figure out how to become an interstellar species and move to a more suitable solar system</u>. Humans could live to enjoy another thirty million generations on earth.</p><p>Thinking about the mind-boggling scale of these numbers, I’m reminded of the Total Perspective Vortex machine, created by Douglas Adams in The Restaurant at the End of the Universe. Anyone brave enough to enter sees a scale model of the entire universe, with an arrow indicating their current position. As a result, their brain explodes. As Adams reflects, the machine proves that “if life is going to exist in a universe of this size, then the one thing it cannot afford to have is a sense of proportion.”</p><p>Still, let’s try. Imagine your ancestors a hundred generations ago. They are your great-great-great-great-great-great-great- great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great- great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great- great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great- great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great- great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great- great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great- great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great- great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great-great- great-great-great-grandparents. These people lived around 1000 BCE, at the start of the Iron Age. They might have been part of Homeric Greece, ancient Egypt, Vedic age India, the preclassic Maya, or Zhou Dynasty China.</p><p>Contemplate for a moment about what the hundred genera- tions between our Iron Age ancestors and today have achieved. They built the Taj Mahal and Sistine Chapel, the Angkor Wat and Empire State Building. Thanks to them, we can relish the poetry of Maya Angelou, novels of Leo Tolstoy, and music of Ludwig van Beethoven. An abundance of inventions has delivered us deli- cious food, homes that are comfortable year-round, and technol- ogy that provides online access to a bottomless well of entertain- ment. If time machines existed, we might pop in to visit our great100 grandparents, but few would volunteer to stay in the Iron Age.</p><p>Yet humanity is really just getting started. If things go well, it’s ten thousand generations down, thirty million to go. Imagine what those future generations could do, and how much time they have to enjoy. Here’s one way to think about what it means to have thirty million generations ahead. Suppose humanity’s potential time on the planet was shrunk down to a single eighty- year life span. In that event, we would now be a newborn baby— just nine days old. Homo sapiens is a mere 0.03 percent through all we could experience on earth.</p><p>We won’t meet most of those who follow us on the planet, but we should cherish future generations all the same. If you value humanity’s past achievements—the Aztec and Roman civiliza- tions, art of the Renaissance, and breakthroughs of the Industrial Revolution—then the generations to come are just as worthy. This is what political philosopher Edmund Burke meant when he described society as “a partnership not only between those who are living, but between those who are living, those who are dead, and those who are to be born.’- To appreciate the past is akin to admiring the achievements of distant places. Like geography, his- tory helps us better understand the way of the world.</p><p>Politicians like me like to speak fondly about looking after "our children and our grandchildren.” But it usually stops after a generation or two. Policy pays little heed to the many generations that will follow. For my own part, it took a coronavirus-induced shutdown to have the time to spend reflecting deeply about the long term. This book had been rattling around in my head for years, but it was only when all my meetings, events, and travel were canceled that I had the time to write it. Pandemics are one of the threats to humanity that I’ll discuss in this book, but in this instance, it provided a chance to reflect on the long term. It’s tempting to ignore the distant future. It’s easier to love the grandchildren whom we hug than the great-great-great-grand- children whom we’ll never get to smile on. But that doesn’t make those far-flung generations any less important. Via my wife, our children can trace their lineage to Benjamin Franklin, but I’m more excited about the potential achievements of the generations yet to be born.</p><p>For companies and governments, a major impediment to long- term thinking is the idea of discounting the future. When investing money, this is a reasonable approach. A dollar in a decade’s time is less valuable than a dollar today for the simple reason that a dollar today could be invested and earn a real return. Share markets have good and bad years, but based on returns from the past 120 years, someone who put $1,000 into the US stock market for an average year could expect it to be worth $1,065 after twelve months (accounting for dividends and inflation).2 Approximating these returns, when governments contemplate making investments, they often apply a discount rate of around 5 percent, while companies use rates that are higher still.2</p><p>When it comes to growing your greenbacks, this makes perfect sense. If Kanesha offered you $ 1,000 today, and Jane offered you $ 1,000 in a year’s time, most of us would think that Kanesha was making the more generous offer. Kanesha’s cash can be put to productive use and would be worth more than Jane’s when the year is out.</p><p>But what if we’re talking about Kanesha and Jane themselves? Suppose Kanesha is alive today, and Jane is yet to be born. When discounting is applied to lives, it suggests that Kanesha’s life to- day is worth twice as much as Jane’s life in fifteen years’ time. It implies that Kanesha today is worth 132 times as much as Jane in a century’s time. So if we’re spending money to keep them safe, a 5 percent discount rate indicates that we should spend more than a hundred times as much to protect Kanesha today than to pro- tect Jane in a century’s time.</p><p>The further we stretch the time period, the more ridiculous the results become. Discounting at a rate of 5 percent implies that Christopher Columbus is worth more than all eight billion people on the planet today.— Naturally, it also implies that your life is worth more than eight billion lives in five hundred years’ time. Even if you value the hug of a loved one over the unseen successes of next century’s generations, is it fair to ruthlessly dis- miss the distant future? Discounting is the enemy of the long term.</p><p>As philosopher Will MacAskill points out, there is something morally repugnant about concluding that the happiness of those who will be alive in the 2100s is inconsequential simply because they live in the future. MacAskill coined the term “presentism” to refer to prejudice against people who are yet unborn.” Just like racism, sexism, or other forms of bigotry, he argues that mis- treating those who live a long way in the future is unfair. To dis- criminate in favor of Kanesha against unborn Jane is a form of presentism. If you traveled back in time to the 1500s and met someone who claimed that they were worth more than everyone alive in the 2000s, you’d rightly regard them as an egomaniac. Isn’t it equally narcissistic to ignore the happiness of people in the 2500s?</p><p>Some have contended that we should favor the living over the unborn for the same reason that philanthropy favors the down- trodden over the wealthy. If incomes rise over time, the argument goes, then asking today’s citizens to help those in the future is like taking from the poor to give to the rich.— But this reasoning ignores the fact that we are talking about the survival of future generations. Theoretical riches won’t do them any good if they are practically dead—or if planetary apocalypse snuffs out their chance to be born. Similarly, it misses the possibility that future pandemics, wars, or climate disasters could make coming genera- tions significantly poorer.—</p><p>Insights from behavioral science help explain why <u>humans aren’t good at understanding extinction risk</u>.— <u>Our thinking about dangers is skewed by an “availability bias”: a tendency to focus on <strong>familiar risks</u></strong>. Like the traders who failed to forecast the collapse of the securitized housing debt market, <u>we are lousy at judging the probability of rare but catastrophic events</u>. Most important, <u>our instincts fail us as the magnitudes grow larger</u>. In research titled "The More Who Die, the Less We Care,” psychologists Paul Slovic and Daniel Vastfjall argue that we become numb to suffering as the body count grows.— Humans’ compassionate instincts are aroused by stories, not statistics. Indeed, one study found that people were more likely to donate to help a single victim than they were to assist eight victims. This may help explain why the international community has been so slow to respond to genocide, including recent incidents in Rwanda, Darfur, and Myanmar. As artificial intelligence researcher Eliezer Yudkowsky notes, human neurotransmitters are unable to feel sorrow that is thousands of times stronger than a single funeral.— The problem is starker still when it comes to extinction risk. Our emotional brains cannot multiply by billions.</p><p>Add to this a media cycle that has become a media cyclone, in which stories explode in a matter of minutes, and “outrage porn” seems to drive the news choices of many outlets. In the 2016 US election, researchers found that for every piece of professional news shared on Twitter, there was one piece of “junk news.’’— Conflict fueled by social media keeps us in a primal state of rage and retaliation. And this isn’t the only force that makes politics myopic. Campaign contributions tend to come from donors who have an immediate interest in a “today” issue rather than from people aiming to solve long-term problems. This kind of “instant noodle” politics prioritizes quick results and sidelines fundamental challenges.</p><p><u>In this environment, a <strong>special style of politics has thrived: populism</u></strong>. The term “populist" gets thrown around a lot—typically as an insult—so it’s worth taking a moment to define it precisely.— <u>Populists see politics as a conflict between <strong>crooked elites and the pure mass of people</u></strong>. Many candidates trying to defeat an incumbent will criticize “insiders,” but <u>populists make a stronger attack on elites, claiming that they are dishonest or corrupt. Populists then claim that they—and only they—represent the “real people</u>.” Populists combine a fierce critique of elites and personal appeal to the “silent majority.”</p><p><u>The political strategy of <mark>populists</mark> involves <strong><mark>critiq</mark>uing intellectuals, <mark>institutions, and internationalism</strong></mark>. The political style of populists tends to be fierce</u>. They do not strive for unity and calm consensus. Populists share with revolutionaries a desire for sudden and dramatic change. <u>They have little respect for experts and the systems of government</u>. Populists’ priorities tend to be immediate issues such as crime, migration, jobs, and taxes. Consequently, the <u>electoral success of populists has served to <strong><mark>sideline work on</mark> long-term dangers such as <mark>climate change and nuclear war</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>Donald <u>Trump</u> may have <u><strong>lost</u></strong> his presidential reelection bid, <u><strong>but</u></strong> he has <u><strong>transformed the Republican Party</u></strong>, which has jettisoned its longstanding commitment to free trade, immigration, and global alliances. Many moderate Republicans, who might have served comfortably under Ronald Reagan or George H. W. Bush, have quit the party or been defeated by Trump-supporting populists. The Republican Party, which holds nearly half the seats in Congress and controls a majority of state legislatures, has embraced populism to a degree that was unimaginable when it was led by George W. Bush, John McCain, or Mitt Romney. After four years under President Trump, the Republican Party is now more cynical and isolationist, focused on immediate grievances rather than long-term challenges.</p><p>Yet <u>while the strength of populism threatened to sideline issues of catastrophic risk, coronavirus did the opposite</u>. The worst pandemic in a century led to the most severe economic crisis since the Great Depression. Churches and concert halls fell silent. International travel collapsed. The Summer Olympics were postponed. Stocks plunged, and for a brief moment, the price of a barrel of oil went negative. Globally, millions lost their jobs, and millions more faced famine.</p><p><u>COVID-19 never threatened to extinguish humanity, but it highlighted our vulnerability to infectious diseases</u>. More than at any time in living memory, people focused on the dangers of pandemics. The popularity of Geraldine Brooks’s Year of Wonders, Stephen King’s The Stand, Emily St. John Mandel’s Station Eleven, and Albert Camus’s The Plague vividly illustrates the way in which fear of pandemics has become more acute.</p><p>We know that disasters can remake society. The black death helped usher in the Renaissance.— The Great Depression made a generation of investors more risk averse.— World War II spawned the United Nations and formed the modern welfare state. In autocracies, droughts and floods can topple dictators.—</p><p>Coronavirus is reshaping the world in numerous ways.— Handwashing is in. Cheek kissing is out. The rise of big cities is slowing as people consider the downsides of density. Firms that automated their production systems to deal with physical dis- tancing requirements and stay-at-home orders are discovering that they can get by permanently with fewer staff. More tele- working and less business travel is leading to a drop in demand for receptionists, bus drivers, office cleaners, and security guards. When it comes to our use of technology, coronavirus suddenly accelerated the world to 2030. When it comes to globalization, the pandemic took us back to 2010.</p><p><u>But it’s still an open question as to how COVID-19 will affect humanity’s ability to think about the long term</u>. Most of the examples I’ve listed are instances in which crises affected societies organically: the shock came, and it changed our behavior. But <u>accentuating the long term requires taking risk more seriously and placing greater emphasis on <strong>saving our species</u></strong>. Linebackers are swift to respond when an offensive player suddenly takes a step to the right. But it takes longer to recognize that a team’s offensive plays are skewed to the right and modify the defensive formation accordingly.</p><p>Like a football team that adapts its tactics, this book argues that we should lengthen our thinking. At minimal cost, society can massively reduce the odds of catastrophe. By ensuring that the big threats get the attention and resources they need, we can safeguard the future of our species. As insurance policies go, this one is a bargain.</p><p>In the chapters that follow, I’ll outline <u><mark>the <strong>biggest risks</mark> facing humanity</u></strong>. I’ll begin in chapter 2 with pandemics, <u><mark>such as</u></mark> the possibility that <u>the <strong><mark>next virus</strong></mark> might <mark>combine</mark> the <mark>infectiousness</mark> of COVID-19 <mark>with</mark> the <mark>deadliness</mark> of Ebola</u>. What can we do to shut down exotic animal markets, speed up vaccine develop- ment, and create surge capacity in hospitals? I’ll then delve into <u><strong>bioterrorism</strong>, and</u> the <u>danger of <mark>extremists developing</mark> their own <mark>versions of</mark> smallpox or the bubonic <mark>plague</u></mark>. How difficult is it for them to create these devilish diseases, and what can we do to prevent it?</p><p>In chapter 3, I’ll then explore <u><strong><mark>climate change</u></strong></mark>—perhaps the in- tergenerational issue that has received the most public attention in recent years. While much of the modeling looks at how global warming <u>could be</u> bad, my focus is on the chances that it’s <u><strong>catastrophic</u></strong>. This isn’t about climate change shortening the ski season; it’s about the possibility of temperatures rising by 18°F (10°C), <u><mark>rendering</mark> large sections of <mark>the planet uninhabitable</u></mark>. What does the risk of cataclysmic climate change mean for energy policy?</p><p>Next, I’ll turn to nukes. As a child in the 1980s, I vividly re- member watching The Day After. My classmates and I agreed that a nuclear war was inevitable. When the Cold War ended, the world seemed safer, but in the three decades since, the <u>threat from <strong>new nuclear powers</strong> has made the problem less predictable</u>. As I discuss in chapter 4, <u>what we used to call an arms race now looks more like a bar fight, with hazards coming from <strong>unexpected directions</strong>, including <strong>terrorist groups</u></strong>. Yet just as there are practical ways to avoid pub brawls (don’t drink past midnight, avoid the stairs, look out for the glass), so too are there <u>sensible strategies</u> that <u>can <strong>reduce the odds of <mark>nuclear catastrophe</u></strong></mark> (adopt a “no first use" policy, reduce the stockpiles, control loose nukes).</p><p>A <u><strong><mark>superintelligence</strong></mark> has been dubbed the “last invention” we’ll ever make</u>. An <u><strong>a</u></strong>rtificial <u><strong>i</u></strong>ntelligence machine <u>whose abilities exceed our own <mark>could</u></mark> turbocharge productivity and living stan- dards. But it could also <u><strong><mark>spell disaster</u></strong></mark>. If we program our artificial intelligence to maximize human happiness, it could fulfill our wishes literally by immobilizing everyone and attaching electrodes to the pleasure centers of our brains. As chapter 5 notes, what makes artificial intelligence different from every other risky technology is its runaway potential. <u>Once a superintelligence can improve itself, it is <strong>unstoppable</u></strong>. So <u>we need to build the guardrails before the highway</u>.</p><p>What are the odds? In chapter 6,1 complete the discussion of catastrophic danger by examining less risky risks, including asteroids and supervolcanoes. I <u>also consider</u> the prospect of “<u><strong><mark>unknown unknowns</u></strong></mark>.” For example, prior to the first atomic bomb test, some scientists thought there was a chance it could set the atmosphere on fire, destroying the planet. When the Large Hadron Collider was being built, critics warned that the particle collisions inside it could create micro black holes. Although neither situation eventuated, they raise the question of what <u><strong>other doomsday scenarios</strong> <mark>could be <strong>lurking</mark> around the corner</u></strong>. How should the prospect of these unexpected risks change our approach to cutting-edge science? Drawing together these dangers with the major hazards, I report the likely probability of each, benchmarking existential risks such as nuclear war and pandemics against individual risks such as being struck by lightning or dying on the battlefield.</p><p>Ultimately, <u><mark>tackling <strong>ex</strong></mark>istential <mark>risks is a <strong>political problem</u></strong></mark>. Private citizens can achieve many things, but <u>preventing nuclear war, averting bioterrorism, and curbing greenhouse emissions are</u> fundamentally <u>problems of government</u>. Governments control the military, levy taxes, and provide public goods. So <u>the <strong>values</strong> of those who run the country will determine how much of a priority the nation places on averting catastrophe<strong>.</p><p></strong>That’s why the <strong><mark>rise of populists is crucial to humanity’s</mark> long- term <mark>survival</u></strong></mark>. In chapter 7,1 discuss the factors that have led to the electoral success of populists during recent decades, and why <u><mark>populists tend to be <strong>uninterested in</mark> dealing with <mark>long-term threats</strong></mark>. Populists’ focus on the short term means</u> that—like a driver distracted by a back seat squabble—<u>we’re in danger of <strong>missing the threats that could kill us</u></strong>. I’ll explore why populists around the world struggled to respond to COVID-19, and what this says about the dangers that populism poses to our species. <u>Most critics of populism have concentrated on the present day. They’re missing the bigger picture. Populists are primarily <strong>endangering the unborn</u></strong>.</p><p><u><mark>Bad politics <strong>doesn’t just exacerbate other dangers</strong></mark>; it represents <mark>a <strong>risk factor in itself</strong> </mark>through the possibility of a totalitarian turn</u> —<u>in which democracy is replaced by an enduring autocracy</u>. The road to democracy is not a one-way street. Over the centuries, dozens of countries have backslid from democracy into autocracy —abandoning the institutions of fair elections, protection for minorities, and free expression. Such an outcome could be deadly for dissenters and miserable for the multitudes. Chapter 8 explores why democracy dies and identifies the signs that institutions are being undermined. Chapter 9 suggests how we might strengthen democracies to allow citizens to have a greater say, and lower the chances of the few taking over from the many. Chapter 10 concludes the book.</p><p>When COVID-19 hit, many rushed out to buy life insurance.— In our personal lives, we know that spending a small amount on insurance can guard against financial ruin. Societies can take a similar approach: implementing modest measures today to safe- guard the immense future of our species. <u>For each of the existential risks we face, there are sensible approaches that could curtail the dangers</u>. For all the risks we face, a better politics will lead to a safer world.</p><p><u>Because of its focus on the urgent over the important, populist politics should</u> perhaps <u>bear the label, “Warning: populism can harm your children</u>." But <u>what is the alternative?</u> In the conclusion, I argue that the answer lies in the ancient philosophy of stoicism. <u>A stoic approach to politics isn’t about favoring one side of the ideological fence over another. Instead, it’s about the temperament of good political leadership</u>. Stoicism emphasizes that character matters and holds that virtue is the only good. <u><strong>Decisions are based on empirical evidence</strong>, not emotion. Anger has no place in effective leadership</u>. Strength comes from civility, courage, and endurance. Stoics make a sharp distinction between the things they can change and those they cannot.</p>
1NC
Populism DA
null
5,221
269
167,811
./documents/hsld22/SouthlakeCarroll/AdRa/SouthlakeCarroll-AdRa-Neg-Emory-Round-6.docx
969,874
N
6 - Emory
6
Isidore Newman EE
Jasmine Stidham
1ac - baudy borders 1nc - tfw populism da util nc security good case 1ar - all 2nr - security good util nc populism da 1ar - all
hsld22/SouthlakeCarroll/AdRa/SouthlakeCarroll-AdRa-Neg-Emory-Round-6.docx
2023-02-13 04:42:05
79,475
AdRa
Southlake Carroll AdRa
null
Ad.....
Ra.....
null
null
26,649
SouthlakeCarroll
Southlake Carroll
TX
26,976
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
3,106,719
Antiblackness isn’t historically calcified and their reading runs counter to the Black radical tradition
Kelley, 17
Kelley, 17—Gary B. Nash Professor of American History at UCLA (Robin D.G., “Robin D.G. Kelley & Fred Moten In Conversation,” transcribed from https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=fP-2F9MXjRE, 1:57:36-2:02:56, dml)
I don't always recognize that black politics have been structured or defined by white supremacy not everything is about, or in response to, white supremacy it's simply not true because much of what people do in terms of social formation, community building may be structured in dominance in some ways, but not defined by it Cedric talks about the ontological totality structured by enslavement and dispossession but one in which western hegemony didn't work part of the Black radical tradition is a refusal to be property, to even admit that human beings could be property we sometimes give white supremacy way too much credit The way we have tended to more recently treat slavery, Jim Crow and mass incarceration as the reinstantiation of the same thing, the continuation, that denies the fact that these systems are actually distinct, that they are historically specific, and in fact they’re responses to the weakness of this as a racial regime Jim Crow was not the continuation of slavery Jim Crow was a response to the Black Democratic upsurge after slavery It was a way to try to suppress that That's why there's a huge gap between 1877 at the official end of Reconstruction and the rise of Jim Crow the 1890s, disfranchisement, lynching you've had 13, 14, 15, 20, 25 years of a democratic possibility and struggle. The same thing with mass incarceration—yes, we've had incarceration, but that upward swing has a lot to do with, again, responses to the struggles in the 1960s if we don't acknowledge that what we end up doing is thinking that somehow there's a structure of white supremacy that's unchanging, fixed, and so powerful we can't do anything about it when in fact it's the opposite. White supremacy is fragile. White supremacy is weak. Racial regimes actually are always having to shore themselves up precisely because they're unstable We can't see it because the whole system is to give us the impression that it is so powerful, there's no space out. And yet it’s working overtime to respond to our opposition
not everything is about, or in response to, white supremacy social formation may be structured in dominance but not defined by part of Black radical tradition is refusal to be property, to even admit human beings could be property give white supremacy too much credit treat slavery, Jim Crow and mass incarceration as the same thing denies that these systems are distinct historically specific, and responses to the weakness of a racial regime Jim Crow was not the continuation of slavery Jim Crow was a response to the Black Democratic upsurge after slavery a huge gap between the end of Reconstruction and rise of Jim Crow 25 years of democratic possibility and struggle same with mass incarceration upward swing with responses to the 60s if we don't acknowledge that we end up thinking white supremacy that's unchanging, fixed, and so powerful we can't do anything White supremacy is fragile weak Racial regimes always shore themselves up because they're unstable system give the impression it is so powerful yet it’s working overtime to respond to our opposition
KELLEY: Um, Fred—Fred will take most of these questions. So that's why I'm going to begin first because he's gonna, he's gonna—he's gonna end it because he, he, he has the answer to all these questions ‘cause I turn to him for these questions. On the specific, on the first question, I just want to make sure I understand it because I'm, you know, I don't always recognize, uh, it may be because I'm just old, but I don't always recognize, uh, that black politics, black [unclear—maybe “guys”] work politics have been structured or defined by white supremacy. I mean, white supremacy is there. And I guess maybe because I'm such a student of Cedric Robinson, you know, not everything is about, or in response to, white supremacy. And in fact, one of the critiques coming out of doing Southern history was this idea that race relations framework, that race relations defines, uh, African-American history or Black history. And it's simply not true because much of what people do in terms of, of social formation, community building, um, is, is, is what Raymond Williams might call alternative cultures. In other words, it may be structured in dominance in some ways, but not defined by it. And Cedric's Black Marxism, you know, really made this point. He talks about the ontological totality, you know, the, this sense of being and making ourselves whole, in that we come out of an experience, again, structured by white supremacy, structured by violence, structured by enslavement and dispossession, but, but one in which western hegemony didn't work, you know, that modes of thinking wasn't defined by Enlightenment modes of thinking. In other words, that, that part of the Black radical tradition is a refusal to be property, to even admit that human beings could be property. You know, so we sometimes give white supremacy way too much credit, and maybe I misunderstood the question. And so I think that there's lots of things that happen outside of joy and survival, and survival is important, but survival is not the end all, you know. So I think, and I'll give you one very, very specific example, and now I'm not gonna say anything else after this. The way we have tended to more recently treat slavery, Jim Crow and mass incarceration as a piece, as the reinstantiation of the same thing, the continuation, that denies the fact that these systems are actually distinct, that they are historically specific, and in fact they’re responses to, in many ways, to the weakness of this as a racial regime. So if you think of like the whole idea of the new Jim Crow to me is very, very problematic. Um, although that book by Michelle Alexander is very, very powerful and very useful in terms of educating people about prisons. Jim Crow was not the continuation of slavery. It was not. Jim Crow was a response to the Black Democratic, uh, upsurge after slavery. It was a revolution of Reconstruction. It was a way to try to suppress that. The fact that, that, you know, there was this incredible response. That's why there's a, there's a huge gap between 1877 at the official end of Reconstruction and the rise of Jim Crow, which is the 1890s, disfranchisement, lynching. That's because you've had 13, 14, 15, 20, 25 years of a democratic possibility and struggle. The same thing with mass incarceration—yes, we've had incarceration, but it's, but that, that, that, that upward swing has a lot to do with, again, responses to the struggles in the 1960s, the assault on the Keynesian welfare-warfare state, the fact that you know the, the war on political, the formation of political prisoners, those struggles in fact was the state's response to opposition. And so if we don't acknowledge that, then what we end up doing is thinking that somehow there's a structure of white supremacy that's unchanging, fixed, and so powerful we can't do anything about it when in fact it's the opposite. White supremacy is fragile. White supremacy is weak. Racial regimes actually are always having to shore themselves up precisely because they're unstable. We can see that. We can't see it because the whole system of hegemony is to give us the impression that it is so powerful, there's no space out. And yet it’s working overtime to, to respond to our opposition. Right. That may not answer your question, but that's sort of a way I think about it. Maybe it’s not satisfactory, but yeah.
4,374
<h4>Antiblackness isn’t historically calcified and their reading runs <u>counter</u> to the Black radical tradition</h4><p><strong>Kelley, 17</strong>—Gary B. Nash Professor of American History at UCLA (Robin D.G., “Robin D.G. Kelley & Fred Moten In Conversation,” transcribed from https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=fP-2F9MXjRE, 1:57:36-2:02:56, dml)</p><p>KELLEY: Um, Fred—Fred will take most of these questions. So that's why I'm going to begin first because he's gonna, he's gonna—he's gonna end it because he, he, he has the answer to all these questions ‘cause I turn to him for these questions. On the specific, on the first question, I just want to make sure I understand it because I'm, you know, I don't always recognize, uh, it may be because I'm just old, but <u>I don't always recognize</u>, uh, <u>that black politics</u>, black [unclear—maybe “guys”] work politics <u>have been <strong>structured</strong> or <strong>defined</strong> by white supremacy</u>. I mean, white supremacy is there. And I guess maybe because I'm such a student of Cedric Robinson, you know, <u><strong><mark>not everything is about</strong>, or <strong>in response to</strong>, white supremacy</u></mark>. And in fact, one of the critiques coming out of doing Southern history was this idea that race relations framework, that race relations defines, uh, African-American history or Black history. And <u>it's <strong>simply not true</strong> because much of what people do in terms of</u>, of <u><strong><mark>social formation</strong></mark>, <strong>community building</u></strong>, um, is, is, is what Raymond Williams might call alternative cultures. In other words, it <u><mark>may be <strong>structured in dominance</strong></mark> in some ways, <mark>but <strong>not defined by</mark> it</u></strong>. And <u>Cedric</u>'s Black Marxism, you know, really made this point. He <u>talks about the <strong>ontological totality</u></strong>, you know, the, this sense of being and making ourselves whole, in that we come out of an experience, again, structured by white supremacy, structured by violence, <u><strong>structured by enslavement</strong> and <strong>dispossession</u></strong>, but, <u>but one in which <strong>western hegemony didn't work</u></strong>, you know, that modes of thinking wasn't defined by Enlightenment modes of thinking. In other words, that, that <u><mark>part of</mark> the <mark>Black radical tradition is</mark> a <strong><mark>refusal to be property</strong>, to <strong>even</mark> <mark>admit</mark> that <mark>human beings could be property</u></strong></mark>. You know, so <u>we sometimes <mark>give white</mark> <mark>supremacy</mark> <strong>way <mark>too much credit</u></strong></mark>, and maybe I misunderstood the question. And so I think that there's lots of things that happen outside of joy and survival, and survival is important, but survival is not the end all, you know. So I think, and I'll give you one very, very specific example, and now I'm not gonna say anything else after this. <u>The way we have tended to more recently <mark>treat <strong>slavery</strong>, <strong>Jim Crow</strong> and <strong>mass incarceration</u></strong></mark> as a piece, <u><mark>as</mark> the <strong>reinstantiation of <mark>the same thing</strong></mark>, the <strong>continuation</strong>, that <strong><mark>denies </mark>the fact</strong> <mark>that these systems are</mark> <strong>actually <mark>distinct</strong></mark>, that they are <strong><mark>historically specific</strong>, and</mark> in fact they’re <strong><mark>responses</u></strong></mark> to, in many ways, <u><mark>to</mark> <mark>the <strong>weakness</strong> of</mark> this as <mark>a racial regime</u></mark>. So if you think of like the whole idea of the new Jim Crow to me is very, very problematic. Um, although that book by Michelle Alexander is very, very powerful and very useful in terms of educating people about prisons. <u><mark>Jim Crow was <strong>not the continuation of slavery</u></strong></mark>. It was not. <u><mark>Jim Crow was a <strong>response to</mark> <mark>the Black Democratic</u></strong></mark>, uh, <u><strong><mark>upsurge</strong> after slavery</u></mark>. It was a revolution of Reconstruction. <u>It was a way to try to suppress that</u>. The fact that, that, you know, there was this incredible response. <u>That's why</u> there's a, <u>there's <mark>a <strong>huge gap</strong> between </mark>1877 at <mark>the</mark> official <mark>end of Reconstruction and</mark> the <mark>rise of Jim Crow</u></mark>, which is <u>the 1890s, disfranchisement, lynching</u>. That's because <u>you've had <strong>13</strong>, <strong>14</strong>, <strong>15</strong>, <strong>20</strong>, <strong><mark>25 years</strong> of</mark> a <strong><mark>democratic possibility</strong> and <strong>struggle</strong></mark>. The <strong><mark>same</mark> thing <mark>with mass incarceration</strong></mark>—yes, we've had incarceration, but</u> it's, but that, that, that, <u>that <strong><mark>upward swing</strong></mark> has a lot to do <mark>with</mark>, again, <strong><mark>responses</strong> to</mark> the struggles in <mark>the</mark> 19<mark>60s</u></mark>, the assault on the Keynesian welfare-warfare state, the fact that you know the, the war on political, the formation of political prisoners, those struggles in fact was the state's response to opposition. And so <u><mark>if we <strong>don't acknowledge that</u></strong></mark>, then <u>what <mark>we end up</mark> doing is <mark>thinking</mark> that somehow there's a structure of <mark>white supremacy that's <strong>unchanging</strong>, <strong>fixed</strong>, and <strong>so powerful we can't do anything</mark> about it</strong> when in fact it's the <strong>opposite</strong>. <mark>White supremacy is <strong>fragile</strong></mark>. White supremacy is <strong><mark>weak</strong></mark>. <mark>Racial regimes</mark> actually are <strong><mark>always</mark> having to <mark>shore themselves up</strong></mark> precisely <mark>because they're <strong>unstable</u></strong></mark>. We can see that. <u>We <strong>can't see it</strong> because the whole <mark>system</u></mark> of hegemony <u>is to <mark>give</mark> us <mark>the impression</mark> that <mark>it is <strong>so powerful</strong></mark>, there's <strong>no space out</strong>. And <mark>yet it’s <strong>working overtime</u></strong></mark> to, <u><mark>to <strong>respond to our opposition</u></strong></mark>. Right. That may not answer your question, but that's sort of a way I think about it. Maybe it’s not satisfactory, but yeah. </p>
2AC
Warren K
2AC---Social Death
9,179
321
101,148
./documents/ndtceda18/Michigan/RoJa/Michigan-Roche-Jacobs-Aff-Navy-Round5.docx
605,910
A
Navy
5
USMC MC
Cerja
1AC - NFU Crisis adv 1NC - Framing Consult CP Wake Work K Warren K 2NR - Framing Wake Work
ndtceda18/Michigan/RoJa/Michigan-Roche-Jacobs-Aff-Navy-Round5.docx
null
51,448
RoJa
Michigan RoJa
null
Br.....
Ro.....
Jo.....
Ja.....
19,200
Michigan
Michigan
null
null
1,008
ndtceda18
NDT/CEDA 2018-19
2,018
cx
college
2
1,124,448
Bio-d loss isn’t existential
Kareiva and Carranza, 18
Kareiva and Carranza, 18—Institute of the Environment and Sustainability, University of California, Los Angeles (Peter and Valerie, “Existential risk due to ecosystem collapse: Nature strikes back,” Futures, available online January 5, 2018, ScienceDirect, dml)
One boundary often mentioned as a concern for the fate of global civilization is biodiversity There is little evidence that this is a threshold—and it is hard to imagine any data that would allow one to identify where the threshold was A better question is whether one can imagine any scenario by which the loss of too many species leads to the collapse of societies and environmental disasters, even though one cannot know the absolute number of extinctions While there are data that relate local reductions to altered ecosystem function, these results do not point to substantial existential risks. The data are small-scale experiments in which plant productivity, or nutrient retention is reduced or are local observations Those are not existential risks. To make the link even more tenuous, there is little evidence that biodiversity is even declining at local scales Total planetary biodiversity may be in decline, but local and regional biodiversity is often staying the same because species from elsewhere replace local losses there is growing skepticism regarding the strength of evidence linking trends in biodiversity loss to an existential risk for humans Obviously if all biodiversity disappeared civilization would end—but no one is forecasting the loss of all species. It seems plausible that the loss of 90% of the world’s species could also be apocalyptic, but not one is predicting that degree of biodiversity loss either If global biodiversity were halved, but at the same time locally the number of species stayed relatively stable, what would be the mechanism for an end-of-civilization or even end of human prosperity scenario? biodiversity loss are ethical and spiritual losses, but perhaps not an existential risk
little ev and hard to imagine any data would identify the threshold results do not point to existential risks data are small-scale experiments or local observations Those are not existential there is little ev biod is even declining at local scales local and regional biod is staying the same species from elsewhere replace local losses no one is forecasting loss of 90% species If global biod were halved what would be the mechanism for end-of-civilization
The interesting question is whether any of the planetary thresholds other than CO2 could also portend existential risks. Here the answer is not clear. One boundary often mentioned as a concern for the fate of global civilization is biodiversity (Ehrlich & Ehrlich, 2012), with the proposed safety threshold being a loss of greater than 0.001% per year (Rockström et al., 2009). There is little evidence that this particular 0.001% annual loss is a threshold—and it is hard to imagine any data that would allow one to identify where the threshold was (Brook, Ellis, Perring, Mackay, & Blomqvist, 2013; Lenton & Williams, 2013). A better question is whether one can imagine any scenario by which the loss of too many species leads to the collapse of societies and environmental disasters, even though one cannot know the absolute number of extinctions that would be required to create this dystopia. While there are data that relate local reductions in species richness to altered ecosystem function, these results do not point to substantial existential risks. The data are small-scale experiments in which plant productivity, or nutrient retention is reduced as species numbers decline locally (Vellend, 2017), or are local observations of increased variability in fisheries yield when stock diversity is lost (Schindler et al., 2010). Those are not existential risks. To make the link even more tenuous, there is little evidence that biodiversity is even declining at local scales (Vellend et al., 2013, 2017). Total planetary biodiversity may be in decline, but local and regional biodiversity is often staying the same because species from elsewhere replace local losses, albeit homogenizing the world in the process. Although the majority of conservation scientists are likely to flinch at this conclusion, there is growing skepticism regarding the strength of evidence linking trends in biodiversity loss to an existential risk for humans (Maier, 2012; Vellend, 2014). Obviously if all biodiversity disappeared civilization would end—but no one is forecasting the loss of all species. It seems plausible that the loss of 90% of the world’s species could also be apocalyptic, but not one is predicting that degree of biodiversity loss either. Tragic, but plausible is the possibility of our planet suffering a loss of as many as half of its species. If global biodiversity were halved, but at the same time locally the number of species stayed relatively stable, what would be the mechanism for an end-of-civilization or even end of human prosperity scenario? Extinctions and biodiversity loss are ethical and spiritual losses, but perhaps not an existential risk.
2,668
<h4>Bio-d loss isn’t existential</h4><p><strong>Kareiva and Carranza, 18</strong>—Institute of the Environment and Sustainability, University of California, Los Angeles (Peter and Valerie, “Existential risk due to ecosystem collapse: Nature strikes back,” Futures, available online January 5, 2018, ScienceDirect, dml)</p><p>The interesting question is whether any of the planetary thresholds other than CO2 could also portend existential risks. Here the answer is not clear. <u>One boundary often mentioned as a concern for the fate of global civilization is <strong>biodiversity</u></strong> (Ehrlich & Ehrlich, 2012), with the proposed safety threshold being a loss of greater than 0.001% per year (Rockström et al., 2009). <u>There is <strong><mark>little ev</mark>idence</strong> that this</u> particular 0.001% annual loss <u>is a threshold—<mark>and</mark> it is <strong><mark>hard to imagine any data</strong></mark> that <mark>would</mark> allow one to <strong><mark>identify</mark> where <mark>the threshold</mark> was</u></strong> (Brook, Ellis, Perring, Mackay, & Blomqvist, 2013; Lenton & Williams, 2013). <u>A better question is whether one can imagine <strong>any scenario</strong> by which the loss of too many species leads to the <strong>collapse of societies</strong> and <strong>environmental disasters</strong>, even though one <strong>cannot know the absolute number of extinctions</u></strong> that would be required to create this dystopia. <u>While there are data that relate local reductions</u> in species richness <u>to altered ecosystem function, these <mark>results <strong>do not point to</mark> substantial <mark>existential risks</strong></mark>. The <mark>data are <strong>small-scale experiments</strong></mark> in which plant productivity, or nutrient retention is reduced</u> as species numbers decline locally (Vellend, 2017), <u><mark>or</mark> are <strong><mark>local observations</u></strong></mark> of increased variability in fisheries yield when stock diversity is lost (Schindler et al., 2010). <u><mark>Those are <strong>not existential</mark> risks</strong>. To make the link <strong>even more tenuous</strong>, <mark>there is <strong>little ev</mark>idence</strong> that <mark>biod</mark>iversity <mark>is <strong>even declining at local scales</u></strong></mark> (Vellend et al., 2013, 2017). <u><strong>Total</strong> planetary biodiversity may be in decline, but <mark>local and regional biod</mark>iversity <mark>is <strong></mark>often <mark>staying the same</strong></mark> because <mark>species from elsewhere <strong>replace local losses</u></strong></mark>, albeit homogenizing the world in the process. Although the majority of conservation scientists are likely to flinch at this conclusion, <u>there is <strong>growing skepticism</strong> regarding the <strong>strength of evidence</strong> linking trends in biodiversity loss to an <strong>existential risk for humans</u></strong> (Maier, 2012; Vellend, 2014). <u><strong>Obviously</strong> if all biodiversity disappeared civilization would end—but <strong><mark>no one is forecasting</mark> the loss of all species</strong>. It seems plausible that the <mark>loss of <strong>90%</strong></mark> of the world’s <mark>species</mark> could also be apocalyptic, but <strong>not one is predicting that degree of biodiversity loss either</u></strong>. Tragic, but plausible is the possibility of our planet suffering a loss of as many as half of its species. <u><mark>If global biod</mark>iversity <mark>were halved</mark>, but at the same time locally the number of species stayed relatively stable, <strong><mark>what would be the mechanism</strong> for</mark> an <mark>end-of-civilization</mark> or even end of human prosperity scenario?</u> Extinctions and <u>biodiversity loss are <strong>ethical</strong> and <strong>spiritual losses</strong>, but perhaps <strong>not an existential risk</u></strong>.</p>
LASA DW - BASIS Semis COMPILED
1NC
Case
1,651,128
1,331
27,699
./documents/hspolicy21/LiberalArtsAndScienceAcademy/DoWi/Liberal%20Arts%20And%20Science%20Academy-Dollinger-Witchel-Neg-Brandeis-Semis.docx
749,925
N
Brandeis
Semis
Brandeis JH
AJ Garcia
1AC - River Rights 1NC - T Protection - States CP - EPA Tradeoff - Con Con CP - Oil DA 2NC - T Protection - Oil DA - Con Con CP 1NR - Growth Turn - 2 NR - T Protection
hspolicy21/LiberalArtsAndScienceAcademy/DoWi/Liberal%20Arts%20And%20Science%20Academy-Dollinger-Witchel-Neg-Brandeis-Semis.docx
null
63,985
DoWi
Liberal Arts And Science Academy DoWi
null
Ja.....
Do.....
Gi.....
Wi.....
22,033
LiberalArtsAndScienceAcademy
Liberal Arts And Science Academy
TX
null
1,020
hspolicy21
HS Policy 2021-22
2,021
cx
hs
2
2,281,863
[4] Working within the state functions to expose hidden oppression and to fully understand the state – we’re a prerequisite to the kritik.
Zanotti 14
Zanotti 14 Dr. Laura Zanotti, Associate Professor of PoliSci, Virginia Tech. “Governmentality, Ontology, Methodology: Re-thinking Political Agency in the Global World.” Alternatives: Global, Local, Political, Vol. 38, p. 288-304. A little unclear if this is late 2013 or early 2014 – the stated “Version of Record” is Feb 20, 2014, but was originally published online on December 30th, 2013.
Options for resistance are not limited to rejection It is found in contingent struggles that are constituted within the scripts of governmental rationalities and transform them. This approach questions oversimplifications power interacts in complex ways with diverse political spaces Governmentality as a heuristic invites situated explorations and careful differentiations rather than overarching demonizations of power alternative formulations foster an ethics of political engagement that demand continuous attention to what happens instead of fixations on what ought to be
Options for resistance are not limited to rejection It is found in contingent struggles that are constituted within the scripts of governmental rationalities and transform them. This approach questions oversimplifications power interacts in complex ways with diverse political spaces Governmentality as a heuristic invites situated explorations and careful differentiations rather than overarching demonizations of power alternative formulations foster an ethics of political engagement that demand continuous attention to what happens’’ instead of fixations on what ought to be
By questioning substantialist representations of power and subjects, inquiries on the possibilities of political agency are reframed in a way that focuses on power and subjects’ relational character and the contingent processes of their (trans)formation in the context of agonic relations. Options for resistance to governmental scripts are not limited to ‘‘rejection,’’ ‘‘revolution,’’ or ‘‘dispossession’’ to regain a pristine ‘‘freedom from all constraints’’ or an immanent ideal social order. It is found instead in multifarious and contingent struggles that are constituted within the scripts of governmental rationalities and at the same time exceed and transform them. This approach questions oversimplifications of the complexities of liberal political rationalities and of their interactions with non-liberal political players and nurtures a radical skepticism about identifying universally good or bad actors or abstract solutions to political problems. International power interacts in complex ways with diverse political spaces and within these spaces it is appropriated, hybridized, redescribed, hijacked, and tinkered with. Governmentality as a heuristic focuses on performing complex diagnostics of events. It invites historically situated explorations and careful differentiations rather than overarching demonizations of ‘‘power,’’ romanticizations of the ‘‘rebel’’ or the ‘‘the local.’’ More broadly, theoretical formulations that conceive the subject in non-substantialist terms and focus on processes of subjectification, on the ambiguity of power discourses, and on hybridization as the terrain for political transformation, open ways for reconsidering political agency beyond the dichotomy of oppression/rebellion. These alternative formulations also foster an ethics of political engagement, to be continuously taken up through plural and uncertain practices, that demand continuous attention to ‘‘what happens’’ instead of fixations on ‘‘what ought to be.’’83
1,983
<h4>[4] Working within the state functions to expose hidden oppression and to fully understand the state – we’re a prerequisite to the kritik.</h4><p><strong>Zanotti 14 </strong>Dr. Laura Zanotti, Associate Professor of PoliSci, Virginia Tech. “Governmentality, Ontology, Methodology: Re-thinking Political Agency in the Global World.” Alternatives: Global, Local, Political, Vol. 38, p. 288-304. A little unclear if this is late 2013 or early 2014 – the stated “Version of Record” is Feb 20, 2014, but was originally published online on December 30th, 2013.</p><p>By questioning substantialist representations of power and subjects, inquiries on the possibilities of political agency are reframed in a way that focuses on power and subjects’ relational character and the contingent processes of their (trans)formation in the context of agonic relations. <u><strong><mark>Options for resistance</u></strong></mark> to governmental scripts <u><strong><mark>are not limited to </u></strong></mark>‘‘<u><strong><mark>rejection</u></strong></mark>,’’ ‘‘revolution,’’ or ‘‘dispossession’’ to regain a pristine ‘‘freedom from all constraints’’ or an immanent ideal social order. <u><strong><mark>It is found</u></strong></mark> instead <u><strong><mark>in</u></strong></mark> multifarious and <u><strong><mark>contingent struggles that are constituted within the scripts of governmental rationalities and</u></strong></mark> at the same time exceed and <u><strong><mark>transform them. This approach questions oversimplifications</u></strong></mark> of the complexities of liberal political rationalities and of their interactions with non-liberal political players and nurtures a radical skepticism about identifying universally good or bad actors or abstract solutions to political problems. International <u><strong><mark>power interacts in complex ways with diverse political spaces</u></strong></mark> and within these spaces it is appropriated, hybridized, redescribed, hijacked, and tinkered with. <u><strong><mark>Governmentality as a heuristic</u></strong></mark> focuses on performing complex diagnostics of events. It <u><strong><mark>invites</u></strong></mark> historically <u><strong><mark>situated explorations and careful differentiations rather than overarching demonizations of </u></strong></mark>‘‘<u><strong><mark>power</u></strong></mark>,’’ romanticizations of the ‘‘rebel’’ or the ‘‘the local.’’ More broadly, theoretical formulations that conceive the subject in non-substantialist terms and focus on processes of subjectification, on the ambiguity of power discourses, and on hybridization as the terrain for political transformation, open ways for reconsidering political agency beyond the dichotomy of oppression/rebellion. These <u><strong><mark>alternative formulations</u></strong></mark> also <u><strong><mark>foster an ethics of political engagement</u></strong></mark>, to be continuously taken up through plural and uncertain practices, <u><strong><mark>that demand continuous attention to</u></strong></mark> ‘‘<u><strong><mark>what happens</u></strong>’’</mark> <u><strong><mark>instead of fixations on</u></strong></mark> ‘‘<u><strong><mark>what ought to be</u></strong></mark>.’’83 </p>
null
FW
Underview
37,382
1,475
71,532
./documents/hsld20/McDowell/Zh/McDowell-Zhao-Aff-Bronx-Round3.docx
867,954
A
Bronx
3
Lynbrook KD
Quisenberry, Jack
1AC - US Election
hsld20/McDowell/Zh/McDowell-Zhao-Aff-Bronx-Round3.docx
null
73,467
SeZh
McDowell SeZh
null
Se.....
Zh.....
null
null
24,615
McDowell
McDowell
PA
null
1,028
hsld20
HS LD 2020-21
2,020
ld
hs
1
1,419,182
Mining solves extinction from scarcity.
Pelton 17
Pelton 17—(Director Emeritus of the Space and Advanced Communications Research Institute at George Washington University, PHD in IR from Georgetown).. Pelton, Joseph N. 2017. The New Gold Rush: The Riches of Space Beckon! Springer. Accessed 8/30/19.
Are Humans Doomed to Extinction? What will we do when Earth’s resources are used up ? The world is over populated, with billions crammed into our overcrowded cities. These will be more vulnerable to terrorist attack, natural disaster, and other plights that come with overcrowding . We are rapidly running out of water and minerals. Climate change is threatening our very existence. All humanity is at tremendous risk. we envision a new space economy that recognizes there is more water in the skies that all our oceans. The new space frontier can literally open up a “gold rush in the skies.” there is new hope for humanity. we have overlooked the great abundance available to us in the skies above. there is already the beginning of a new gold rush in space—a pathway to astral abundance. new pathways to the stars could prove vital to human survival. entrepreneurial New Space initiatives are changing everything . entrepreneurs are taking over. developing new tech and establishing space enterprises that can bring the wealth of outer space down to Earth. This is not a pipe dream, but will increasingly be the economic reality of the 2020s. Some will say this is sci-fi hogwash this is what people said about planes and nuclear devices. The skeptics laughed at Columbus and his plan to sail across the oceans . When Seward bought Alaska, there were plenty of naysayers . Info technology, robotics, artificial intelligence and commercial space have set us on course to harvest riches in the skies—new natural resources, new energy, and new ways of looking at the purpose of human existence. if we don’t seek to realize our ultimate destiny Homo sapiens can end up in the dustbin of history like millions of already failed species the way of the T. Rex, the woolly mammoth, and the Dodo bird along with extinct ferns, grasses and cacti. space materials, energy and wealth save us from excesses of the past. bold leaders such as Paul Allen Richard Branson Jeff Bezos of Amazon Blue Origin Robert Bigelow not only dream of the space industry but also have billions in assets. are the bright stars of an entirely new industry . space billionaires are proponents of astral abundance. Each of them is launching new commercial space industries. These New Space enterprises give new promise of transforming our world . Near-Earth asteroids composed of platinum and rare earth metals have an incredible value. Helium-3 isotopes space could provide clean and abundant energy. There is more water in space than in our oceans. These can take place by the end of this century. if these changes do not take place we will be in trouble. the struggle between “haves” and “have nots” will grow increasingly ugly. A lack of affordable and readily available water, natural resources, food, health care and medical supplies, plus systematic threats to urban security and systemic warfare are the alternatives to astral abundance. Within the next few decades these problems will be increasingly real. the world may almost be begging for new, out of- the-box thinking.
over populated crowded cities will be vulnerable to terrorist attack, natural disaster, running out of water and Climate change . All humanity is at risk. new tech can bring the wealth to Earth. the reality of the 2020s. robotics, a i and commercial space have set us on course . Allen Branson Bezos Bigelow have billions . Each of them is launching space industries. asteroids rare earth metals have value. Helium-3 provide clean energy. There is more water in space than oceans. lack of food, health care and systemic warfare are the alternatives Within the next few decades .
Are We Humans Doomed to Extinction? What will we do when Earth’s resources are used up by humanity? The world is now hugely over populated, with billions and billions crammed into our overcrowded cities. By 2050, we may be 9 billion strong, and by 2100 well over 11 billion people on Planet Earth. Some at the United Nations say we might even be an amazing 12 billion crawling around this small globe. And over 80 % of us will be living in congested cities. These cities will be ever more vulnerable to terrorist attack, natural disaster, and other plights that come with overcrowding and a dearth of jobs that will be fueled by rapid automation and the rise of artifi cial intelligence across the global economy. We are already rapidly running out of water and minerals. Climate change is threatening our very existence. Political leaders and even the Pope have cautioned us against inaction. Perhaps the naysayers are right. All humanity is at tremendous risk. Is there no hope for the future? This book is about hope. We think that there is literally heavenly hope for humanity. But we are not talking here about divine intervention. We are envisioning a new space economy that recognizes that there is more water in the skies that all our oceans. Th ere is a new wealth of natural resources and clean energy in the reaches of outer space—more than most of us could ever dream possible. There are those that say why waste money on outer space when we have severe problems here at home? Going into space is not a waste of money. It is our future. It is our hope for new jobs and resources. The great challenge of our times is to reverse public thinking to see space not as a resource drain but as the doorway to opportunity. The new space frontier can literally open up a “gold rush in the skies.” In brief, we think there is new hope for humanity. We see a new a pathway to the future via new ventures in space. For too long, space programs have been seen as a money pit. In the process, we have overlooked the great abundance available to us in the skies above. It is important to recognize there is already the beginning of a new gold rush in space—a pathway to astral abundance. “New Space” is a term increasingly used to describe radical new commercial space initiatives—many of which have come from Silicon Valley and often with backing from the group of entrepreneurs known popularly as the “space billionaires.” New space is revolutionizing the space industry with lower cost space transportation and space systems that represent significant cost savings and new technological breakthroughs. “New Commercial Space” and the “New Space Economy” represent more than a new way of looking at outer space. These new pathways to the stars could prove vital to human survival. If one does not believe in spending money to probe the mysteries of the universe then perhaps we can try what might be called “calibrated greed” on for size. One only needs to go to a cubesat workshop, or to Silicon Valley or one of many conferences like the “Disrupt Space” event in Bremen, Germany, held in April 2016 to recognize that entrepreneurial New Space initiatives are changing everything [ 1 ]. In fact, the very nature and dimensions of what outer space activities are today have changed forever. It is no longer your grandfather’s concept of outer space that was once dominated by the big national space agencies. The entrepreneurs are taking over. The hopeful statements in this book and the hard economic and technical data that backs them up are more than a minority opinion. It is a topic of growing interest at the World Economic Forum, where business and political heavyweights meet in Davos, Switzerland, to discuss how to stimulate new patterns of global economic growth. It is even the growing view of a group that call themselves “space ethicists.” Here is how Christopher J. Newman, at the University of Sunderland in the United Kingdom has put it: Space ethicists have offered the view that space exploration is not only desirable; it is a duty that we, as a species, must undertake in order to secure the survival of humanity over the longer term. Expanding both the resource base and, eventually, the habitats available for humanity means that any expenditure on space exploration, far from being viewed as frivolous, can legitimately be rationalized as an ethical investment choice. (Newman) On the other hand there are space ethicists and space exobiologists who argue that humans have created ecological ruin on the planet—and now space debris is starting to pollute space. Th ese countervailing thoughts by the “no growth” camp of space ethicists say we have no right to colonize other planets or to mine the Moon and asteroids—or at least no right to do so until we can prove we can sustain life here on Earth for the longer term. However, for most who are planning for the new space economy the opinion of space philosophers doesn’t really fl oat their boat. Legislators, bankers, and aspiring space entrepreneurs are far more interested in the views of the super-rich capitalists called the space billionaires. A number of these billionaires and space executives have already put some very serious money into enterprises intent on creating a new pathway to the stars. No less than five billionaires with established space ventures—Elon Musk, Paul Allen, Jeff Bezos, Sir Richard Branson, and Robert Bigelow—have invested millions if not billions of dollars into commercializing space. They are developing new technologies and establishing space enterprises that can bring the wealth of outer space down to Earth. This is not a pipe dream, but will increasingly be the economic reality of the 2020s. These wealthy space entrepreneurs see major new economic opportunities. To them space represents the last great frontier for enterprising pioneers. Th us they see an ever-expanding space frontier that offers opportunities in low-cost space transportation, satellite solar power satellites to produce clean energy 24h a day, space mining, space manufacturing and production, and eventually space habitats and colonies as a trajectory to a better human future. Some even more visionary thinkers envision the possibility of terraforming Mars, or creating new structures in space to protect our planet from cosmic hazards and even raising Earth’s orbit to escape the rising heat levels of the Sun in millennia to come. Some, of course, will say this is sci-fi hogwash. It can’t be done. We say that this is what people would have said in 1900 about airplanes, rocket ships, cell phones and nuclear devices. The skeptics laughed at Columbus and his plan to sail across the oceans to discover new worlds. When Thomas Jefferson bought the Louisiana Purchase from France or Seward bought Alaska, there were plenty of naysayers that said such investment in the unknown was an extravagant waste of money. A healthy skepticism is useful and can play a role in economic and business success. Before one dismisses the idea of an impending major new space economy and a new gold rush, it might useful to see what has already transpired in space development in just the past five decades. The world’s first geosynchronous communications satellite had a throughput capability of about 500 kb / s. In contrast, today’s state of the art Viasat 2 —a half century later— has an impressive throughput of some 140 Gb/s. Th is means that the relative throughput is nearly 300,000 greater, while its lifetime is some ten times longer (Figs. 1.1 and 1.2 ). Each new generation of communications satellite has had more power, better antenna systems, improved pointing and stabilization, and an extended lifetime. And the capabilities represented by remote sensing satellites , meteorological satellites , and navigation and timing satellites have also expanded their capabilities and performance in an impressive manner. When satellite applications first started, the market was measured in millions of dollars. Today commercial satellite services exceed a quarter of a billion dollars. Vital services such as the Internet, aircraft traffi c control and management, international banking, search and rescue and much, much more depend on application satellites. Th ose that would doubt the importance of satellites to the global economy might wish to view on You Tube the video “If Th ere Were a Day Without Satellites?” [ 2 ]. Let’s check in on what some of those very rich and smart guys think about the new space economy and its potential. (We are sorry to say that so far there are no female space billionaires, but surely this, too, will come someday soon.) Of course this twenty-fi rst century breakthrough that we call the New Space economy will not come just from new space commerce. It will also come from the amazing new technologies here on Earth. Vital new terrestrial technologies will accompany this cosmic journey into tomorrow. Information technology, robotics, artificial intelligence and commercial space travel systems have now set us on a course to allow us humans to harvest the amazing riches in the skies—new natural resources, new energy, and even totally new ways of looking at the purpose of human existence. If we pursue this course steadfastly, it can be the beginning of a New Space renaissance. But if we don’t seek to realize our ultimate destiny in space, Homo sapiens can end up in the dustbin of history—just like literally millions of already failed species. In each and every one of the five mass extinction events that have occurred over the last 1.5 billion years on Earth, some 50–80 % of all species have gone the way of the T. Rex, the woolly mammoth, and the Dodo bird along with extinct ferns, grasses and cacti. On the other hand, the best days of the human race could be just beginning. If we are smart about how we go about discovering and using these riches in the skies and applying the best of our new technologies, it could be the start of a new beginning for humanity. Konstantin Tsiokovsky, the Russian astronautics pioneer, who fi rst conceived of practical designs for spaceships, famously said: “A planet is the cradle of mankind, but one cannot live in a cradle forever.” Well before Tsiokovsky another genius, Leonardo da Vinci, said, quite poetically: “Once you have tasted flight, you will forever walk the earth with your eyes turned skyward, for there you have been, and there you will always long to return.” The founder of the X-Prize and of Planetary Resources, Inc., Dr. Peter Diamandis, has much more brashly said much the same thing in quite diff erent words when he said: “The meek shall inherit the Earth. The rest of us will go to Mars.” The New Space Billionaires Peter Diamandis is not alone in his thinking. From the list of “visionaries” quoted earlier, Elon Musk, the founder of SpaceX; Sir Richard Branson, the founder of Virgin Galactic; and Paul Allen, the co-founder of Microsoft and the man who financed SpaceShipOne, the world’s first successful spaceplane have all said the future will include a vibrant new space economy. Th ey, and others, have said that we can, we should and we soon shall go into space and realize the bounty that it can offer to us. Th e New Space enterprise is today indeed being led by those so-called space billionaires , who have an exciting vision of the future. They and others in the commercial space economy believe that the exploitation of outer space may open up a new golden age of astral abundance. They see outer space as a new frontier that can be a great source of new materials, energy and various forms of new wealth that might even save us from excesses of the past. Th is gold rush in the skies represents a new beginning. We are not talking about expensive new space ventures funded by NASA or other space agencies in Europe, Japan, China or India. No, these eff orts which we and others call New Space are today being forged by imaginative and resourceful commercial entrepreneurs. Th ese twenty-fi rst century visionaries have the fortitude and zeal to look to the abundance above. New breakthroughs in technology and New Space enterprises may be able to create an “astral life raft” for humanity. Just as Columbus and the Vikings had the imaginative drive that led them to discover the riches of a new world, we now have a cadre of space billionaires that are now leading us into this New Space era of tomorrow. These bold leaders, such as Paul Allen and Sir Richard Branson, plus other space entrepreneurs including Jeff Bezos of Amazon and Blue Origin, and Robert Bigelow, Chairman of Budget Suites and Bigelow Aerospace, not only dream of their future in the space industry but also have billions of dollars in assets. These are the bright stars of an entirely new industry that are leading us into the age of New Space commerce. These space billionaires, each in their own way, are proponents of a new age of astral abundance. Each of them is launching new commercial space industries. They are literally transforming our vision of tomorrow. These new types of entrepreneurial aerospace companies—the New Space enterprises—give new hope and new promise of transforming our world as we know it today. The New Space Frontier What happens in space in the next few decades, plus corresponding new information technologies and advanced robotics, will change our world forever. These changes will redefi ne wealth, change our views of work and employment and upend almost everything we think we know about economics, wealth, jobs, and politics. Th ese changes are about truly disruptive technologies of the most fundamental kinds. If you thought the Internet, smart phones, and spandex were disruptive technologies, just hang on. You have not seen anything yet. In short, if you want to understand a transition more fundamental than the changes brought to the twentieth century world by computers, communications and the Internet, then read this book. There are truly riches in the skies. Near-Earth asteroids largely composed of platinum and rare earth metals have an incredible value. Helium-3 isotopes accessible in outer space could provide clean and abundant energy. There is far more water in outer space than is in our oceans. In the pages that follow we will explain the potential for a cosmic shift in our global economy, our ecology, and our commercial and legal systems. These can take place by the end of this century. And if these changes do not take place we will be in trouble. Our conventional petro-chemical energy systems will fail us economically and eventually blanket us with a hydrocarbon haze of smog that will threaten our health and our very survival. Our rare precious metals that we need for modern electronic appliances will skyrocket in price, and the struggle between “haves” and “have nots” will grow increasingly ugly. A lack of affordable and readily available water, natural resources, food, health care and medical supplies, plus systematic threats to urban security and systemic warfare are the alternatives to astral abundance. The choices between astral abundance and a downward spiral in global standards of living are stark. Within the next few decades these problems will be increasingly real. By then the world may almost be begging for new, out of- the-box thinking. International peace and security will be an indispensable prerequisite for exploitation of astral abundance, as will good government for all. No one nation can be rich and secure when everyone else is poor and insecure. In short, global space security and strategic space defense, mediated by global space agreements, are part of this new pathway to the future.
15,681
<h4>Mining solves extinction from <u>scarcity</u>.</h4><p><strong>Pelton 17</strong>—(Director Emeritus of the Space and Advanced Communications Research Institute at George Washington University, PHD in IR from Georgetown).. Pelton, Joseph N. 2017. The New Gold Rush: The Riches of Space Beckon! Springer. Accessed 8/30/19.</p><p><u>Are </u>We<u> Humans Doomed to <strong>Extinction</strong>? What will we do when Earth’s resources are used up </u>by humanity<u>? The world is</u> now hugely <u><strong><mark>over populated</strong></mark>, with billions</u> and billions <u>crammed into our over<strong><mark>crowded</strong> cities</mark>. </u>By 2050, we may be 9 billion strong, and by 2100 well over 11 billion people on Planet Earth. Some at the United Nations say we might even be an amazing 12 billion crawling around this small globe. And over 80 % of us will be living in congested cities. <u>These</u> cities <u><mark>will be</u></mark> ever <u>more <mark>vulnerable to <strong>terrorist attack</strong>, <strong>natural disaster</strong>,</mark> and other plights that come with overcrowding </u>and a dearth of jobs that will be fueled by rapid automation and the rise of artifi cial intelligence across the global economy<u>.</u> <u>We are </u>already <u>rapidly <strong><mark>running out of water</strong> and <strong></mark>minerals</strong>. <strong><mark>Climate change</strong> </mark>is threatening our very <strong>existence</strong><mark>.</u></mark> Political leaders and even the Pope have cautioned us against inaction. Perhaps the naysayers are right. <u><strong><mark>All humanity is at </mark>tremendous <mark>risk.</u></strong></mark> Is there no hope for the future? This book is about hope. We think that there is literally heavenly hope for humanity. But <u>we</u> are not talking here about divine intervention. We are <u>envision</u>ing <u>a new space economy that recognizes</u> that <u>there is more water in the skies that all our oceans. </u>Th ere is a new wealth of natural resources and clean energy in the reaches of outer space—more than most of us could ever dream possible. There are those that say why waste money on outer space when we have severe problems here at home? Going into space is not a waste of money. It is our future. It is our hope for new jobs and resources. The great challenge of our times is to reverse public thinking to see space not as a resource drain but as the doorway to opportunity. <u>The new space frontier can literally open up a “gold rush in the skies.” </u>In brief, we think <u>there is new hope for humanity.</u> We see a new a pathway to the future via new ventures in space. For too long, space programs have been seen as a money pit. In the process, <u>we have overlooked the great abundance available to us in the skies above.</u> It is important to recognize <u>there is already the beginning of a new gold rush in space—a pathway to astral abundance.</u> “New Space” is a term increasingly used to describe radical new commercial space initiatives—many of which have come from Silicon Valley and often with backing from the group of entrepreneurs known popularly as the “space billionaires.” New space is revolutionizing the space industry with lower cost space transportation and space systems that represent significant cost savings and new technological breakthroughs. “New Commercial Space” and the “New Space Economy” represent more than a new way of looking at outer space. These <u>new pathways to the stars could prove vital to <strong>human survival</strong>. </u>If one does not believe in spending money to probe the mysteries of the universe then perhaps we can try what might be called “calibrated greed” on for size. One only needs to go to a cubesat workshop, or to Silicon Valley or one of many conferences like the “Disrupt Space” event in Bremen, Germany, held in April 2016 to recognize that <u>entrepreneurial New Space initiatives are changing everything</u> [ 1 ]<u>.</u> In fact, the very nature and dimensions of what outer space activities are today have changed forever. It is no longer your grandfather’s concept of outer space that was once dominated by the big national space agencies. The <u>entrepreneurs are taking over.</u> The hopeful statements in this book and the hard economic and technical data that backs them up are more than a minority opinion. It is a topic of growing interest at the World Economic Forum, where business and political heavyweights meet in Davos, Switzerland, to discuss how to stimulate new patterns of global economic growth. It is even the growing view of a group that call themselves “space ethicists.” Here is how Christopher J. Newman, at the University of Sunderland in the United Kingdom has put it: Space ethicists have offered the view that space exploration is not only desirable; it is a duty that we, as a species, must undertake in order to secure the survival of humanity over the longer term. Expanding both the resource base and, eventually, the habitats available for humanity means that any expenditure on space exploration, far from being viewed as frivolous, can legitimately be rationalized as an ethical investment choice. (Newman) On the other hand there are space ethicists and space exobiologists who argue that humans have created ecological ruin on the planet—and now space debris is starting to pollute space. Th ese countervailing thoughts by the “no growth” camp of space ethicists say we have no right to colonize other planets or to mine the Moon and asteroids—or at least no right to do so until we can prove we can sustain life here on Earth for the longer term. However, for most who are planning for the new space economy the opinion of space philosophers doesn’t really fl oat their boat. Legislators, bankers, and aspiring space entrepreneurs are far more interested in the views of the super-rich capitalists called the space billionaires. A number of these billionaires and space executives have already put some very serious money into enterprises intent on creating a new pathway to the stars. No less than five billionaires with established space ventures—Elon Musk, Paul Allen, Jeff Bezos, Sir Richard Branson, and Robert Bigelow—have invested millions if not billions of dollars into commercializing space. They are <u>developing <strong><mark>new tech</u></strong></mark>nologies<u> and establishing space enterprises that <mark>can bring the wealth</mark> of outer space down <mark>to Earth. </mark>This is not a pipe dream, but will increasingly be <mark>the</mark> <strong>economic <mark>reality</strong> of the 2020s.</mark> </u>These wealthy space entrepreneurs see major new economic opportunities. To them space represents the last great frontier for enterprising pioneers. Th us they see an ever-expanding space frontier that offers opportunities in low-cost space transportation, satellite solar power satellites to produce clean energy 24h a day, space mining, space manufacturing and production, and eventually space habitats and colonies as a trajectory to a better human future. Some even more visionary thinkers envision the possibility of terraforming Mars, or creating new structures in space to protect our planet from cosmic hazards and even raising Earth’s orbit to escape the rising heat levels of the Sun in millennia to come. <u><strong>Some</u></strong>, of course, <u>will say this is <strong>sci-fi hogwash</u></strong>.<u> </u>It can’t be done. We say that <u>this is what people</u> would have <u>said</u> in 1900 <u>about </u>air<u><strong>planes</u></strong>, rocket ships, cell phones <u>and nuclear devices.</u> <u>The skeptics <strong>laughed</strong> at</u> <u><strong>Columbus</u></strong> <u>and his plan to sail across the oceans</u> to discover new worlds<u>. When</u> Thomas Jefferson bought the Louisiana Purchase from France or <u>Seward bought Alaska, there were plenty of naysayers</u> that said such investment in the unknown was an extravagant waste of money<u>. </u>A healthy skepticism is useful and can play a role in economic and business success. Before one dismisses the idea of an impending major new space economy and a new gold rush, it might useful to see what has already transpired in space development in just the past five decades. The world’s first geosynchronous communications satellite had a throughput capability of about 500 kb / s. In contrast, today’s state of the art Viasat 2 —a half century later— has an impressive throughput of some 140 Gb/s. Th is means that the relative throughput is nearly 300,000 greater, while its lifetime is some ten times longer (Figs. 1.1 and 1.2 ). Each new generation of communications satellite has had more power, better antenna systems, improved pointing and stabilization, and an extended lifetime. And the capabilities represented by remote sensing satellites , meteorological satellites , and navigation and timing satellites have also expanded their capabilities and performance in an impressive manner. When satellite applications first started, the market was measured in millions of dollars. Today commercial satellite services exceed a quarter of a billion dollars. Vital services such as the Internet, aircraft traffi c control and management, international banking, search and rescue and much, much more depend on application satellites. Th ose that would doubt the importance of satellites to the global economy might wish to view on You Tube the video “If Th ere Were a Day Without Satellites?” [ 2 ]. Let’s check in on what some of those very rich and smart guys think about the new space economy and its potential. (We are sorry to say that so far there are no female space billionaires, but surely this, too, will come someday soon.) Of course this twenty-fi rst century breakthrough that we call the New Space economy will not come just from new space commerce. It will also come from the amazing new technologies here on Earth. Vital new terrestrial technologies will accompany this cosmic journey into tomorrow. <u>Info</u>rmation<u> technology, <mark>robotics, <strong>a</strong></mark>rtificial <strong><mark>i</strong></mark>ntelligence <mark>and commercial space</mark> </u>travel systems<u> <mark>have</mark> </u>now<u> <mark>set us on</mark> </u>a <u><mark>course</mark> to </u>allow us humans to<u> harvest </u>the amazing<u> riches in the skies—new natural resources, new energy, and</u> even totally <u>new ways of looking at the <strong>purpose of human existence</strong><mark>.</u></mark> If we pursue this course steadfastly, it can be the beginning of a New Space renaissance. But <u>if we don’t seek to realize our <strong>ultimate destiny</u></strong> in space, <u>Homo sapiens can end up in the <strong>dustbin of history</u></strong>—just <u>like </u>literally<u> <strong>millions of already failed species</u></strong>. In each and every one of the five mass extinction events that have occurred over the last 1.5 billion years on Earth, some 50–80 % of all species have gone <u>the way of the <strong>T. Rex</strong>, the <strong>woolly mammoth</strong>, and the <strong>Dodo bird</u></strong> <u>along with extinct <strong>ferns</strong>, <strong>grasses</strong> and <strong>cacti</strong>.</u> On the other hand, the best days of the human race could be just beginning. If we are smart about how we go about discovering and using these riches in the skies and applying the best of our new technologies, it could be the start of a new beginning for humanity. Konstantin Tsiokovsky, the Russian astronautics pioneer, who fi rst conceived of practical designs for spaceships, famously said: “A planet is the cradle of mankind, but one cannot live in a cradle forever.” Well before Tsiokovsky another genius, Leonardo da Vinci, said, quite poetically: “Once you have tasted flight, you will forever walk the earth with your eyes turned skyward, for there you have been, and there you will always long to return.” The founder of the X-Prize and of Planetary Resources, Inc., Dr. Peter Diamandis, has much more brashly said much the same thing in quite diff erent words when he said: “The meek shall inherit the Earth. The rest of us will go to Mars.” The New Space Billionaires Peter Diamandis is not alone in his thinking. From the list of “visionaries” quoted earlier, Elon Musk, the founder of SpaceX; Sir Richard Branson, the founder of Virgin Galactic; and Paul Allen, the co-founder of Microsoft and the man who financed SpaceShipOne, the world’s first successful spaceplane have all said the future will include a vibrant new space economy. Th ey, and others, have said that we can, we should and we soon shall go into space and realize the bounty that it can offer to us. Th e New Space enterprise is today indeed being led by those so-called space billionaires , who have an exciting vision of the future. They and others in the commercial space economy believe that the exploitation of outer space may open up a new golden age of astral abundance. They see outer <u>space</u> as a new frontier that can be a great source of new <u>materials, energy and</u> various forms of new <u>wealth</u> that might even <u>save us from excesses of the past.</u> Th is gold rush in the skies represents a new beginning. We are not talking about expensive new space ventures funded by NASA or other space agencies in Europe, Japan, China or India. No, these eff orts which we and others call New Space are today being forged by imaginative and resourceful commercial entrepreneurs. Th ese twenty-fi rst century visionaries have the fortitude and zeal to look to the abundance above. New breakthroughs in technology and New Space enterprises may be able to create an “astral life raft” for humanity. Just as Columbus and the Vikings had the imaginative drive that led them to discover the riches of a new world, we now have a cadre of space billionaires that are now leading us into this New Space era of tomorrow. These <u><strong>bold leaders</u></strong>, <u>such as <strong>Paul <mark>Allen</u></strong></mark> and Sir <u><strong>Richard <mark>Branson</u></strong></mark>, plus other space entrepreneurs including <u><strong>Jeff <mark>Bezos</mark> of Amazon</u></strong> and <u><strong>Blue Origin</u></strong>, and <u><strong>Robert <mark>Bigelow</u></strong></mark>, Chairman of Budget Suites and Bigelow Aerospace, <u>not only dream of</u> their future in <u>the space industry but also <mark>have billions</u></mark> of dollars <u>in assets<mark>.</u></mark> These <u>are the</u> <u><strong>bright stars of an entirely new industry</u></strong> that are leading us into the age of New Space commerce<u>.</u> These <u>space billionaires</u>, each in their own way, <u>are proponents of </u>a new age of <u>astral abundance. <mark>Each of them is launching</mark> new commercial <mark>space industries.</mark> </u>They are literally transforming our vision of tomorrow. <u>These</u> new types of entrepreneurial aerospace companies—the <u>New Space enterprises</u>—<u>give</u> new hope and <u>new promise of transforming our world</u> as we know it today<u>.</u> The New Space Frontier What happens in space in the next few decades, plus corresponding new information technologies and advanced robotics, will change our world forever. These changes will redefi ne wealth, change our views of work and employment and upend almost everything we think we know about economics, wealth, jobs, and politics. Th ese changes are about truly disruptive technologies of the most fundamental kinds. If you thought the Internet, smart phones, and spandex were disruptive technologies, just hang on. You have not seen anything yet. In short, if you want to understand a transition more fundamental than the changes brought to the twentieth century world by computers, communications and the Internet, then read this book. There are truly riches in the skies.<u> Near-Earth <mark>asteroids</mark> </u>largely<u> composed of platinum and <strong><mark>rare earth metals</strong> have</mark> an incredible <mark>value. Helium-3</mark> isotopes </u>accessible in outer<u> space could <mark>provide <strong>clean</mark> and abundant <mark>energy</strong>. There is</mark> </u>far<u> <mark>more water in</mark> </u>outer<u> <mark>space than</mark> </u>is<u> in our <mark>oceans.</mark> </u>In the pages that follow we will explain the potential for a cosmic shift in our global economy, our ecology, and our commercial and legal systems.<u> These can take place by the end of this century. </u>And <u>if these changes do not take place we will be in trouble.</u> Our conventional petro-chemical energy systems will fail us economically and eventually blanket us with a hydrocarbon haze of smog that will threaten our health and our very survival. Our rare precious metals that we need for modern electronic appliances will skyrocket in price, and <u>the struggle between “haves” and “have nots” will grow increasingly <strong>ugly</strong>. A <mark>lack of</mark> affordable and readily available <strong>water</strong>, natural <strong>resources</strong>, <strong><mark>food</strong>, <strong>health care</strong> and</mark> medical supplies, plus systematic threats to <strong>urban security</strong> and <strong><mark>systemic warfare</strong> are the alternatives</mark> to astral abundance. </u>The choices between astral abundance and a downward spiral in global standards of living are stark. <u><mark>Within the next few decades</mark> these problems will be increasingly real<mark>.</u></mark> By then <u>the world may almost be <strong>begging</strong> for new, out of- the-box thinking. </u>International peace and security will be an indispensable prerequisite for exploitation of astral abundance, as will good government for all. No one nation can be rich and secure when everyone else is poor and insecure. In short, global space security and strategic space defense, mediated by global space agreements, are part of this new pathway to the future. </p>
null
3
null
335,965
353
38,737
./documents/hsld21/HarvardWestlake/Le/Harvard%20Westlake-Lee-Neg-UNLV-Round2.docx
888,099
N
UNLV
2
Brentwood ARu
Joseph Barquin
1AC - Capitalism Space Gap (Structural Violence) 1NC - Enforcement Spec Asteroid Mines CP Space-for-Space DA Case 1AR - all 2NR - DA Case 2AR - all
hsld21/HarvardWestlake/Le/Harvard%20Westlake-Lee-Neg-UNLV-Round2.docx
null
74,737
AlLe
Harvard Westlake AlLe
null
Al.....
Le.....
null
null
25,010
HarvardWestlake
Harvard Westlake
CA
null
1,029
hsld21
HS LD 2021-22
2,021
ld
hs
1
2,566,840
The aff is ineffective in face of the aff. Mere theorization cannot alone solve material impacts and because violence is material not rhetorical, violence must be theorized on that plane
Zack 16
Naomi Zack 16. professor of philosophy at the University of Oregon. She is author and editor of a dozen books, including White Privilege and Black Rights: The Injustice of U.S. Police Racial Profiling and Homicide (2015); The Ethics and Mores of Race: Equality after the History of Philosophy (2011); Ethics for Disaster (2009). Applicative Justice: A Pragmatic Empirical Approach to Racial Injustice. Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Incorporated. Pages 125-134.
Just law can coexist with unjust practice and both are parts of “empirical law” or what Bendey called “the process of government Empirical law is constantly changing theorists hope that someday public political discourse on behalf of those who are treated unjustly will have the power to interrupt a cycle of just written law accompanied by continued unjust practice That is, the “right” discourse perennially holds the promise of changing the beliefs, values, and goals of everyone in the public auditorium so that the same kind of unjust practices do not perpetually chase the same kinds of just laws This search for “magic words” is futile for academics who are professionally confined to dry and abstract prose Our verbiage does not have the power to move the multitudes who do not read or listen to it anyway. even when multitudes are inspired and emotionally stirred by great orators, action that follows is unlikely to result in lasting change, without the support of powerful interests Academic political discourse has been swimming upstream against a more rarefied tradition In the United States, everything now points to both the existence of real academic freedom and its real ineffectiveness Progressive academic writers ply a craft of formal speech that deals with contemporary injustice through complex theoretical frameworks with requisite scholarly apparatuses and without translation into more simple views of the world there is often also a lack of translation from one discipline to The audience is other academics and students there is a problem with the delusional nature of so much of this work The delusion consists of a naive view of the power of academic speech to directly change reality The rhetorical mode of address used by academics writing cultural criticism often proceeds as though its authors are making grand entries in a planetary cabala where words have the immediate power to become their intended referents Those subscribe to the Trickle-Down Good Ideas Theory that is immediately self-flattering but it lacks reliable empirical support even very good academic political discourse about justice cannot be relied upon to attract implementation or application in real life This may be because there has not been sufficient time for the development of training programs for a new profession of “bridgers,” who could translate good ideas in the academy for those who govern and make policy Public media, as a democratic analogue to disagreement within academic discourse, supports the idea that views have immediate practical results It is not evident how there could be such results when opposing views and opinions are treated with the same respect and have equal access to the same mass auditorium that lacks rules for evidence or valid argument As with academic discourse, there is no structured connection to official decision processes. The only reliable result of participation in such unbinding referenda is that those who participate are able to express themselves The shared judgment throughout the American atmosphere of race in the early twenty-first century is that racism is morally bad This judgment is a general principle that leaves the nature of racism undefined The overriding shared judgment is a bitter and ineffective refuge The “racial climate” has a history of meaning “micro-aggressions” based on race In using the term “racial atmosphere,” reference may be made to other issues of harm to people of color, such as ignorance and discrimination The implication of these meanings is that the micro-aggressions add up to what is perceived as a general predisposition of white people to treat people of color in unjust ways. But, at this time, ideas of racial atmosphere and climate also work as metaphors Except for what academics write and say and how important they think their discourse is American discourse of racial liberation is at a standstill And insofar as academic discourse is uttered and received in a closed system, with a semicaptive audience and no reliable means for it to affect the real world that standstill remains at the disposal of unpredictable contingent events
law is constantly changing theorists hope political discourse on behalf of those who are treated unjustly will interrupt unjust practice That is, the “right” discourse holds the promise of changing beliefs of everyone in the public This search for “magic words” is futile verbiage does not have the power to move the multitudes who do not read or listen to it even when multitudes are inspired action that follows is unlikely to result in lasting change, without the support of powerful interests there is often a lack of translation to reality Trickle-Down Good Ideas Theory is self-flattering, but lacks empirical support even very good discourse about justice cannot be relied on to attract implementation in real life because there has not been sufficient bridgers who translate ideas in the academy for those who make policy The only reliable result is that participate express themselves The judgment is a bitter and ineffective refuge American discourse is at a standstill. And in a closed system, with a semicaptive audience that standstill remains at the disposal of contingent events
ACADEMIC INJUSTICE DISCOURSE Just law can coexist with unjust practice and both are parts of “empirical law” or what Bendey called “the process of government.” Empirical law is constantly changing and some theorists are optimistic that verbal discourse has the ability to make written law more just, even though the same unjust practices recur or new ones emerge. These theorists, some of whom are or may aspire to become public intellectuals, hope that someday public political discourse on behalf of those who are treated unjustly will have the power to interrupt a cycle of just written law accompanied by continued unjust practice. That is, the “right” discourse perennially holds the promise of changing the beliefs, values, and goals of everyone in the public auditorium, so that the same kind of unjust practices do not perpetually chase the same kinds of just laws.11 This search for “magic words” is futile for academics who are professionally confined to dry and abstract prose. Our verbiage does not have the power to move the multitudes who do not read or listen to it anyway. But even when multitudes are inspired and emotionally stirred by great orators, action that follows is unlikely to result in lasting change, without the support of powerful interests. After the 1960s, academics began a robust practice of liberatory discourse about injustice that seems to grow more impassioned and intense each year. The quest for demographic diversity among students and faculty in higher education has weathered judicial defeat of explicit affirmative action policies, but only partly for the sake of justice. There are pragmatic prizes if the academy can justify itself by producing a racially integrated leadership and managerial class for business, politics, and the military. Top leaders throughout society realize that they need such racial diversity for broad consumption, voter support, and boots on the ground, and the expression of that need is evident in amicus curiae briefs submitted to the US Supreme Court as it has been torturously dismantling affirmative action, piece by piece, since Bakke in 1978.12 Academic political discourse has been deeper than polemics and debate, exactly because of its disciplined intellectual origins in different fields of study (i.e., discipline imposed by distinct “disciplines”). But it has been swimming upstream against a more rarefied and older academic tradition, particularly among many philosophers and their gate keepers outside of the profession. Even Hannah Arendt (see chapter 2) spoke approvingly of the life of the mind as cut off from real political activity that occurred in the realm of “opinion.” In her 1970 interview with Adelbert Reif, Arendt addressed the phenomenon of college-stu-dent protestors, noting that they had brought social change through optimistic belief in their ability to make a better world, while at the same time discovering joy in civic participation. Arendt credited such protests with the success of the civil rights movement and progress toward ending the Vietnam War.13 As discussed in chapter 4, it is doubtful that Arendt was correct that student protests caused the success of the civil rights movement. A historical analysis of the end to the Vietnam War is beyond the present scope, but what we already know about empirical Bentleyan analyses would warrant skepticism about Arendt’s causal thesis there as well. In the same interview, Arendt warned that demonstrations by student activists could be self-defeating in democratic Euro-American contexts, because in attacking their universities, they were attacking the very entities that made their protests possible, American universities, especially large state schools that were the sites of the protests Arendt had in mind, have perforce developed very different financial structures since 1970. These schools have become increasingly dependent on private corporate and philanthropic funding, with state government funds now a much reduced part of their budget. While this structural change is not generally viewed as an incursion on academic freedom, it has been coincident with a very flat era of student protest and activism. Still, Arendt's notion of the "life of the mind” remains useful if we consider that the progressive/change-seeking output of professional academics since 1970 has been professionally accepted in the institutions that employ its participants. Also, much of today’s liberatory academic discourse can be viewed as the legacy of earlier student protest, furthering a tradition that may have been founded when some of the 1960s student radicals became professors. This indicates that the connection between academic radicals and the hands that feed them is not as simple as Arendt thought. In the United States, everything now points to both the existence of real academic freedom and its real ineffectiveness. Progressive academic writers ply a craft of formal speech that deals with contemporary injustice through complex theoretical frameworks, with requisite scholarly apparatuses and without translation into more simple views of the world; there is often also a lack of translation from one discipline to another or between subdisciplines in the same field. The audience is other academics and students. Neither specialization nor the limited and partly captive audience should be viewed as problematic because that is the nature of academic work, given broad social divisions of labor. But there is a problem with the delusional nature of so much of this work. The delusion consists of a naive view of the power of academic speech to directly change reality. The rhetorical mode of address used by academics writing cultural criticism, political philosophy, social philosophy, or what is now called social-political philosophy (which combines the other subfield approaches), often proceeds as though its authors are making grand entries in a planetary cabala, where words have the immediate power to become their intended referents. Those who do not write and speak cabalistically may subscribe to the Trickle-Down Good Ideas Theory that can be traced from Plato to John Stuart Mill to John Rawls. Subscription to that theory is immediately self-flattering, but it lacks reliable empirical support.16 Although, after the US civil rights movement, there has been an uncanny coincidence of race-blind formal racial equality with the hegemony in political philosophy of Rawls’s requirement that those who plan fundamental social institutions do so in ignorance of their own societal environments. As we saw in chapter 1, Rawls was quite explicit about this: I assume that the parties do not know the particular circumstances of their own society. That is, they do not know its economic or political situation, or the level of civilization and culture it has been able to achieve. The persons in the original position have no information as to which generation they belong.17 Both race-blind racial equality and Rawlsian ideals are compatible with race-based real inequality. There are, of course, counter-examples, such as Katherine MacKinnon’s work on sexual harassment in the workplace as expressed in current law and institutional policy.18 Nevertheless even very good academic political discourse about justice and injustice cannot be relied upon to attract implementation or application in real life. This may be because there has not been sufficient time for the development of training programs for a new profession of “bridgers,” who could translate good ideas in the academy for those who govern and make policy. An internal problem for such translators would be to decide where to anchor their bridges in fields—every humanistic field—where experts disagree. However, the current tradition of progressive academic writing and speech is less than half a century old and if and when such translators emerge, they will develop their own professional criteria for choosing among contending experts. Public media, as a democratic analogue to disagreement within academic discourse, supports the idea that expressing and airing views in day-to-day practices or special “national conversations” also have immediate practical results. It is not evident how there could be such results, when opposing views and opinions are treated with the same respect and have equal access to the same mass auditorium that lacks rules for evidence or valid argument. As with academic discourse, there is no structured connection to official decision processes. The only reliable result of participation in such unbinding referenda is that those who participate are able to express themselves and get attention that may benefit them in the marketplace of their related endeavors. Public expression also serves to, represent and create collective atmospheres of belief, attitude, and opinion. These atmospheres are implicitly known by a majority of people in the culture, even though such knowledge is difficult to validate. Ambiguities cannot be resolved by recourse to public opinion polls, because understanding the results of those polls requires creative interpretive skills that draw on what is already known about relevant atmospheres. For example, suppose that more blacks than whites believe that white privilege is real and that O.J. Simpson was innocent, or that more whites than blacks believe that white American police officers are not, in general, racially biased. Are the views of whites evidence of racial bias or racial oblivion? Are the views of blacks evidence of racial preference or paranoia? Moreover, such polls almost always have a large racial overlap of opinion: If 29 percent of blacks compared to 71 percent of whites believe X, then 71 percent of blacks and 29 percent of whites do not believe X. Does this mean that the percentages of each group that does not contribute to the discrepancy in belief recorded in the polls are in some degree of agreement? Experiments in social psychology could be designed to answer such questions and others like them, but it is important to decide beforehand why the data is important and what it does and does not indicate. For instance, testing the claim that white privilege is a reality of contemporary life requires some prior definition of what is meant by “white privilege,” which can range from injustice to social courtesies. In a widely discussed 2013 experiment conducted in Queensland, Australia, economists Redzo Mujcic and Paul Frijters found that the majority of free bus rides, based on conductor generosity, were dispensed to whites, with blacks least likely to receive this courtesy, compared to all other racial groups among commuters. Journalist Britni Danielle, writing for a general audience on Yahoo News, touted this study as evidence that “white privilege is real,” without distinguishing between an amenity such as a free bus ride and recognition of one’s rights by not being subject to arbitrary stops and frisks by police officers.19 Conservatives reading Mujcic and Frijter’s study might say that the bus driver may have been acting rationally based on past experience with unruly black passengers. From a progressive perspective, more specifics would need to be introduced to defend the claim that this study revealed white privilege, such as controls for the apparent social class and gender of passengers, as well as the preexisting racial climate among bus commuters in Queensland, as well as the broader racial atmosphere throughout Australia in 2013. The 2015 Academy Awards What is racial atmosphere and climate? A US example that is also global could help clarify these vague ideas, provided that it is understood beforehand that in this context, as in most public references to "race," ‘racial” means “pertaining to racism.” From beginning to end, the 2015 Academy Awards ceremony hit racist notes that slid by unchecked, because it was an occasion of celebration. Neil Patrick Harris, the host, began with what might have been a critical remark about the lack of racial diversity among audience members and award winners: “Tonight we honor Hollywood’s best and whitest, sorry, bright est.” For those who were uncomfortable with the lack of robust racial diversity among audience members and award winners, his remark might have validated their unease. But those who would have been uncomfortable with more racial diversity may have been heard “best and whitest” as support for their social values. (The discourse of white privilege as a critique of contemporary anti-nonwhite racism is, as indicated, that kind of double-edged sword.) Midway through the ceremony, Patricia Arquette called for people of color and members of the lesbian, bisexual, gay, and transgender (LBGT) community to support legislation for equal pay for women and to commit themselves to supporting women, thereby overlooking the women who were either or both people of color and members of the LGВТ community. This kind of oversight may perhaps be excused by Arquette’s ignorance of what academics have been for decades analyzing as “intersectionality.” But Sean Penn’s remark at the grand finale awarding for Best Picture to Alejandro Gonzalez Inarritu, the Mexican director of Birdman, was simply, explicitly, racist: "Who gave this son of a bitch a green card?” Inarritu later brushed off the insult by saying he found it "hilarious,” because “Sean and I have that kind of brutal relationship. I think it was very funny.”20 Inarritu attempt at a “save” for Penn does not address the impact of Penn’s insult on other Mexicans and Mexican Americans, including those without green cards who struggle to remain employed in the face of anti-immigrant prejudice and discrimination. (That such a moment of maximum recognition was brought so low by a racist crack is not unusual in US culture, where the nastiest forms of racist insult are often let loose on people of color who have succeeded.) As a spectacle watched by almost thirty-four million, the 2015 Oscars, despite ratings lower than recent years, was a global public event.21 Symbolically, it has no peer for the display of beauty, talent, and artistic creativity. Its subtext inevitably has implications about current American race relations, which influence their future. The racial implications of the Oscars replays in millions of minds at countless other public celebrations and entertainment venues, as well as in private interactions (for a year at least). Such spectacles are forms of public discourse and what they represent or fail to represent about US racial demographics and the attitude of the dominant white group creates or augments a specific racial climate that in 2015 is part of a more general racial atmosphere of ambiguity and indeterminacy. At the 2015 Academy Awards, for many critical observers, the issue or subject pertaining to race (insofar as it is understood that subjects of race are subjects of racism), was recognition.22 The beauty, talent, and artistic creativity of people of color was not fully recognized. Some people of color did get awards and some audience members were people of color, so recognition, along with diversity, was not completely absent. But there appeared to be insufficient racial diversity for audience and award winners to be considered racially integrated. And that appearance was symbolic. However, the symbolic meaning is ambiguous: Were there people of color who were deserving of awards but did not get them because they were people of color? Is race a factor in who I becomes a member of the Academy of Motion Picture Arts and Sciences? In the future, will the racial makeup of award winners become more or less representative of their proportions in the motion picture industry? If the proportion of people of color in the motion picture industry is not proportional to their presence in the population at large, why is that? The answers to these questions are undetermined in the symbolic spectacle of the 2015 Academy Awards. The observer does not know if recognition of the achievements of people of color in the movie industry will improve, stay the same, or get worse, and she does not know how to find out. The racial (i.e., in regards to racism) climate of the Academy Awards is cloudy, subject to many different interpretations, some of them conflicting. It is an epistemologically unstable racial climate, because people of color do not know what the weather is in that climate, as a basis for prediction, and neither do they know how to find out. The shared judgment throughout the American atmosphere of race in the early twenty-first century is that racism is morally bad. This judgment is a general principle that leaves the nature of racism undefined throughout the atmosphere and most of the climates and subclimates of race. The overriding shared judgment is a bitter and ineffective refuge for nonwhites, because it does not protect them from either First Amendment-protected racist expressions or actions that turn out to be indirectly racist. Energetic self-aware racist whites can try to evade the judgment that they are racist through coded language for racial difference, and the use of intermediate activities and traits as subjects of direct action. That is, something other than race, which nonetheless does a good job of picking out members of a specific racial group, can be used instead of the race of that group to maintain prejudice and legitimize discrimination. The term “racial climate” has a history of meaning “micro-aggressions” based on race, small cuts, insults, and slights that can have a cumulative effect of individual harm.24 In using the term “racial atmosphere,” reference may be made to other issues of harm to people of color, such as ignorance of black history and contemporary racism or discrimination in career advancement.25 The implication of these meanings is that the micro-aggressions add up to what is perceived as a general predisposition of white people to treat people of color in unjust ways. But, at this time, ideas of racial atmosphere and climate also work as metaphors for what is unknown about race relations and attitudes; they capture the vagueness and unpredictability of racial prejudice and discrimination that occur in a society where nonwhites remain disadvantaged, even though there is formal equality. This “vague weather” aspect of atmosphere and climate is an epistemological condition of indecision that may or may not constitute a lasting crisis, although some syndromes of political injustice should be viewed as crises. A crisis is a period of indecision and uncertainty that requires a resolution before life can go on. Will blacks and other people of color achieve more equality with whites, or is the United States—and with it the world, because US racism is exported with business practices, tour-ism, and entertainment products—on the brink of a new era of explicitlу direct oppression of people of color? Are most white Americans, whose race-neutral economic and social activities have racist effects on nonwhites, genuinely ignorant of how the system in which they operate works, or are they secretly but knowingly hearts-and-minds not clear that this indeterminate aspect of present racial atmosphere and climates must be resolved now. We do not know if life can go on if it is not resolved or what it means for life to go on, or not. We do not even know if the putative crisis can be resolved at this time, because there is as yet no systematic and sustained, impassioned, liberatory dis- course for our condition of ambiguity, a time with a black president and police killing with impunity of unarmed black youth, a time of voting rights for everyone but new restrictions and requirements that disproportionately affect African Americans.26 Except for what academics write and say and how important they think their discourse is (among themselves), American discourse of racial liberation is at a standstill. And insofar as academic discourse is uttered and received in a closed system, with a semicaptive audience and no reliable means for it to affect the real world, that standstill remains at the disposal of history, where history is understood to be the unpredictable result of contingent events. However, if academic oppositional political discourse can be related to a longer historical trend, a more coherent and optimistic picture might emerge. Cornel West's ideas about the American black prophetic tradition appears to be a relation to such a trend.
20,523
<h4>The aff is ineffective in face of the aff. Mere theorization cannot alone solve material impacts and because violence is material not rhetorical, violence must be theorized on that plane </h4><p>Naomi <strong>Zack 16</strong>. professor of philosophy at the University of Oregon. She is author and editor of a dozen books, including White Privilege and Black Rights: The Injustice of U.S. Police Racial Profiling and Homicide (2015); The Ethics and Mores of Race: Equality after the History of Philosophy (2011); Ethics for Disaster (2009). Applicative Justice: A Pragmatic Empirical Approach to Racial Injustice. Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Incorporated. Pages 125-134. </p><p>ACADEMIC INJUSTICE DISCOURSE <u>Just law can <strong>coexist with unjust practice</u></strong> <u>and both are parts of “<strong>empirical law</strong>”</u> <u>or what Bendey called “the</u> <u><strong>process of government</u></strong>.” <u>Empirical <mark>law is <strong>constantly changing</u></strong></mark> and some theorists are optimistic that verbal discourse has the ability to make written law more just, even though the same unjust practices recur or new ones emerge. These <u><mark>theorists</u></mark>, some of whom are or may aspire to become public intellectuals, <u><mark>hope</mark> that someday <strong>public <mark>political discourse on behalf of those who are treated unjustly</u></strong> <u>will</mark> have the power to <strong><mark>interrupt</mark> a cycle of just written law</u></strong> <u>accompanied by continued <strong><mark>unjust practice</u></strong></mark>. <u><mark>That is, the “right” discourse</mark> perennially <mark>holds the promise of <strong>changing</mark> the <mark>beliefs</mark>, values, and goals <mark>of everyone in the public</mark> auditorium</u></strong>, <u>so that the same kind of unjust practices do not perpetually chase the same kinds of just laws</u>.11 <u><mark>This search for “<strong>magic words</strong>”</u> <u>is <strong>futile</mark> for academics</u></strong> <u>who are professionally confined to dry and abstract prose</u>. <u>Our <mark>verbiage <strong>does not have the power to move the multitudes who do not read or listen to it</mark> anyway</strong>.</u> But <u><mark>even when multitudes are inspired</mark> and emotionally stirred by great orators, <mark>action that follows is <strong>unlikely to result in lasting change, without the support of powerful interests</u></strong></mark>. After the 1960s, academics began a robust practice of liberatory discourse about injustice that seems to grow more impassioned and intense each year. The quest for demographic diversity among students and faculty in higher education has weathered judicial defeat of explicit affirmative action policies, but only partly for the sake of justice. There are pragmatic prizes if the academy can justify itself by producing a racially integrated leadership and managerial class for business, politics, and the military. Top leaders throughout society realize that they need such racial diversity for broad consumption, voter support, and boots on the ground, and the expression of that need is evident in amicus curiae briefs submitted to the US Supreme Court as it has been torturously dismantling affirmative action, piece by piece, since Bakke in 1978.12 <u>Academic political discourse</u> has been deeper than polemics and debate, exactly because of its disciplined intellectual origins in different fields of study (i.e., discipline imposed by distinct “disciplines”). But it <u>has been <strong>swimming upstream</u></strong> <u>against a more</u> <u><strong>rarefied</u></strong> and older academic <u><strong>tradition</u></strong>, particularly among many philosophers and their gate keepers outside of the profession. Even Hannah Arendt (see chapter 2) spoke approvingly of the life of the mind as cut off from real political activity that occurred in the realm of “opinion.” In her 1970 interview with Adelbert Reif, Arendt addressed the phenomenon of college-stu-dent protestors, noting that they had brought social change through optimistic belief in their ability to make a better world, while at the same time discovering joy in civic participation. Arendt credited such protests with the success of the civil rights movement and progress toward ending the Vietnam War.13 As discussed in chapter 4, it is doubtful that Arendt was correct that student protests caused the success of the civil rights movement. A historical analysis of the end to the Vietnam War is beyond the present scope, but what we already know about empirical Bentleyan analyses would warrant skepticism about Arendt’s causal thesis there as well. In the same interview, Arendt warned that demonstrations by student activists could be self-defeating in democratic Euro-American contexts, because in attacking their universities, they were attacking the very entities that made their protests possible, American universities, especially large state schools that were the sites of the protests Arendt had in mind, have perforce developed very different financial structures since 1970. These schools have become increasingly dependent on private corporate and philanthropic funding, with state government funds now a much reduced part of their budget. While this structural change is not generally viewed as an incursion on academic freedom, it has been coincident with a very flat era of student protest and activism. Still, Arendt's notion of the "life of the mind” remains useful if we consider that the progressive/change-seeking output of professional academics since 1970 has been professionally accepted in the institutions that employ its participants. Also, much of today’s liberatory academic discourse can be viewed as the legacy of earlier student protest, furthering a tradition that may have been founded when some of the 1960s student radicals became professors. This indicates that the connection between academic radicals and the hands that feed them is not as simple as Arendt thought. <u>In the United States, everything now points to both the existence of <strong>real academic freedom</strong> and its <strong>real ineffectiveness</u></strong>. <u>Progressive academic writers ply a craft of formal speech that deals with contemporary injustice through complex theoretical frameworks</u>, <u>with requisite <strong>scholarly apparatuses</strong> and <strong>without translation into more simple views of the world</u></strong>; <u><mark>there is often</mark> also <mark>a <strong>lack of translation</u></strong></mark> <u>from one discipline</u> <u><mark>to</u></mark> another or between subdisciplines in the same field. <u>The audience is other <strong>academics</strong> and <strong>students</u></strong>. Neither specialization nor the limited and partly captive audience should be viewed as problematic because that is the nature of academic work, given broad social divisions of labor. But <u>there is a problem with the <strong>delusional nature</strong> of so much of this work</u>. <u>The delusion consists of a naive view of the power of academic speech to <strong>directly change <mark>reality</u></strong></mark>. <u>The <strong>rhetorical mode of address</u></strong> <u>used by academics writing cultural criticism</u>, political philosophy, social philosophy, or what is now called social-political philosophy (which combines the other subfield approaches), <u>often proceeds as though its authors are making <strong>grand entries in a planetary cabala</u></strong>, <u>where words have the <strong>immediate power to become their intended referents</u></strong>. <u>Those</u> who do not write and speak cabalistically may <u>subscribe to the <strong><mark>Trickle-Down Good Ideas Theory</u></strong></mark> that can be traced from Plato to John Stuart Mill to John Rawls. Subscription to <u>that</u> theory <u><mark>is</mark> <strong>immediately <mark>self-flattering</u></strong>, <u>but</mark> it <strong><mark>lacks</mark> reliable <mark>empirical support</u></strong></mark>.16 Although, after the US civil rights movement, there has been an uncanny coincidence of race-blind formal racial equality with the hegemony in political philosophy of Rawls’s requirement that those who plan fundamental social institutions do so in ignorance of their own societal environments. As we saw in chapter 1, Rawls was quite explicit about this: I assume that the parties do not know the particular circumstances of their own society. That is, they do not know its economic or political situation, or the level of civilization and culture it has been able to achieve. The persons in the original position have no information as to which generation they belong.17 Both race-blind racial equality and Rawlsian ideals are compatible with race-based real inequality. There are, of course, counter-examples, such as Katherine MacKinnon’s work on sexual harassment in the workplace as expressed in current law and institutional policy.18 Nevertheless <u><mark>even <strong>very good</mark> academic political <mark>discourse about justice</u></strong></mark> and injustice <u><mark>cannot be relied</mark> up<mark>on to attract <strong>implementation</mark> or application <mark>in real life</u></strong></mark>. <u>This may be <mark>because there has not been sufficient</mark> time for the development of training programs for a new profession of <strong>“<mark>bridgers</mark>,” <mark>who</mark> could <mark>translate</mark> good <mark>ideas in the academy for those who</mark> govern and <mark>make policy</u></strong></mark>. An internal problem for such translators would be to decide where to anchor their bridges in fields—every humanistic field—where experts disagree. However, the current tradition of progressive academic writing and speech is less than half a century old and if and when such translators emerge, they will develop their own professional criteria for choosing among contending experts. <u>Public media, as a democratic analogue to disagreement within academic discourse, supports the idea that</u> expressing and airing <u>views</u> in day-to-day practices or special “national conversations” also <u>have immediate practical results</u>. <u>It is <strong>not evident how there could be such results</u></strong>, <u>when opposing views and opinions are treated with the same respect and have equal access to the same mass auditorium that <strong>lacks rules for evidence or valid argument</u></strong>. <u>As with academic discourse, there is no structured connection to official decision processes. <mark>The only reliable result</mark> of participation in such <strong>unbinding referenda</u></strong> <u><mark>is that</mark> those who <mark>participate</mark> are able to <strong><mark>express themselves</u></strong></mark> and get attention that may benefit them in the marketplace of their related endeavors. Public expression also serves to, represent and create collective atmospheres of belief, attitude, and opinion. These atmospheres are implicitly known by a majority of people in the culture, even though such knowledge is difficult to validate. Ambiguities cannot be resolved by recourse to public opinion polls, because understanding the results of those polls requires creative interpretive skills that draw on what is already known about relevant atmospheres. For example, suppose that more blacks than whites believe that white privilege is real and that O.J. Simpson was innocent, or that more whites than blacks believe that white American police officers are not, in general, racially biased. Are the views of whites evidence of racial bias or racial oblivion? Are the views of blacks evidence of racial preference or paranoia? Moreover, such polls almost always have a large racial overlap of opinion: If 29 percent of blacks compared to 71 percent of whites believe X, then 71 percent of blacks and 29 percent of whites do not believe X. Does this mean that the percentages of each group that does not contribute to the discrepancy in belief recorded in the polls are in some degree of agreement? Experiments in social psychology could be designed to answer such questions and others like them, but it is important to decide beforehand why the data is important and what it does and does not indicate. For instance, testing the claim that white privilege is a reality of contemporary life requires some prior definition of what is meant by “white privilege,” which can range from injustice to social courtesies. In a widely discussed 2013 experiment conducted in Queensland, Australia, economists Redzo Mujcic and Paul Frijters found that the majority of free bus rides, based on conductor generosity, were dispensed to whites, with blacks least likely to receive this courtesy, compared to all other racial groups among commuters. Journalist Britni Danielle, writing for a general audience on Yahoo News, touted this study as evidence that “white privilege is real,” without distinguishing between an amenity such as a free bus ride and recognition of one’s rights by not being subject to arbitrary stops and frisks by police officers.19 Conservatives reading Mujcic and Frijter’s study might say that the bus driver may have been acting rationally based on past experience with unruly black passengers. From a progressive perspective, more specifics would need to be introduced to defend the claim that this study revealed white privilege, such as controls for the apparent social class and gender of passengers, as well as the preexisting racial climate among bus commuters in Queensland, as well as the broader racial atmosphere throughout Australia in 2013. The 2015 Academy Awards What is racial atmosphere and climate? A US example that is also global could help clarify these vague ideas, provided that it is understood beforehand that in this context, as in most public references to "race," ‘racial” means “pertaining to racism.” From beginning to end, the 2015 Academy Awards ceremony hit racist notes that slid by unchecked, because it was an occasion of celebration. Neil Patrick Harris, the host, began with what might have been a critical remark about the lack of racial diversity among audience members and award winners: “Tonight we honor Hollywood’s best and whitest, sorry, bright est.” For those who were uncomfortable with the lack of robust racial diversity among audience members and award winners, his remark might have validated their unease. But those who would have been uncomfortable with more racial diversity may have been heard “best and whitest” as support for their social values. (The discourse of white privilege as a critique of contemporary anti-nonwhite racism is, as indicated, that kind of double-edged sword.) Midway through the ceremony, Patricia Arquette called for people of color and members of the lesbian, bisexual, gay, and transgender (LBGT) community to support legislation for equal pay for women and to commit themselves to supporting women, thereby overlooking the women who were either or both people of color and members of the LGВТ community. This kind of oversight may perhaps be excused by Arquette’s ignorance of what academics have been for decades analyzing as “intersectionality.” But Sean Penn’s remark at the grand finale awarding for Best Picture to Alejandro Gonzalez Inarritu, the Mexican director of Birdman, was simply, explicitly, racist: "Who gave this son of a bitch a green card?” Inarritu later brushed off the insult by saying he found it "hilarious,” because “Sean and I have that kind of brutal relationship. I think it was very funny.”20 Inarritu attempt at a “save” for Penn does not address the impact of Penn’s insult on other Mexicans and Mexican Americans, including those without green cards who struggle to remain employed in the face of anti-immigrant prejudice and discrimination. (That such a moment of maximum recognition was brought so low by a racist crack is not unusual in US culture, where the nastiest forms of racist insult are often let loose on people of color who have succeeded.) As a spectacle watched by almost thirty-four million, the 2015 Oscars, despite ratings lower than recent years, was a global public event.21 Symbolically, it has no peer for the display of beauty, talent, and artistic creativity. Its subtext inevitably has implications about current American race relations, which influence their future. The racial implications of the Oscars replays in millions of minds at countless other public celebrations and entertainment venues, as well as in private interactions (for a year at least). Such spectacles are forms of public discourse and what they represent or fail to represent about US racial demographics and the attitude of the dominant white group creates or augments a specific racial climate that in 2015 is part of a more general racial atmosphere of ambiguity and indeterminacy. At the 2015 Academy Awards, for many critical observers, the issue or subject pertaining to race (insofar as it is understood that subjects of race are subjects of racism), was recognition.22 The beauty, talent, and artistic creativity of people of color was not fully recognized. Some people of color did get awards and some audience members were people of color, so recognition, along with diversity, was not completely absent. But there appeared to be insufficient racial diversity for audience and award winners to be considered racially integrated. And that appearance was symbolic. However, the symbolic meaning is ambiguous: Were there people of color who were deserving of awards but did not get them because they were people of color? Is race a factor in who I becomes a member of the Academy of Motion Picture Arts and Sciences? In the future, will the racial makeup of award winners become more or less representative of their proportions in the motion picture industry? If the proportion of people of color in the motion picture industry is not proportional to their presence in the population at large, why is that? The answers to these questions are undetermined in the symbolic spectacle of the 2015 Academy Awards. The observer does not know if recognition of the achievements of people of color in the movie industry will improve, stay the same, or get worse, and she does not know how to find out. The racial (i.e., in regards to racism) climate of the Academy Awards is cloudy, subject to many different interpretations, some of them conflicting. It is an epistemologically unstable racial climate, because people of color do not know what the weather is in that climate, as a basis for prediction, and neither do they know how to find out. <u>The shared judgment throughout the American atmosphere of race in the early twenty-first century is that racism is morally bad</u>. <u>This judgment is a <strong>general principle</u></strong> <u>that leaves the <strong>nature of racism undefined</u></strong> throughout the atmosphere and most of the climates and subclimates of race. <u><mark>The</mark> overriding shared <mark>judgment is a <strong>bitter and ineffective refuge</u></strong></mark> for nonwhites, because it does not protect them from either First Amendment-protected racist expressions or actions that turn out to be indirectly racist. Energetic self-aware racist whites can try to evade the judgment that they are racist through coded language for racial difference, and the use of intermediate activities and traits as subjects of direct action. That is, something other than race, which nonetheless does a good job of picking out members of a specific racial group, can be used instead of the race of that group to maintain prejudice and legitimize discrimination. <u>The</u> term <u><strong>“racial climate”</u></strong> <u>has a history of meaning “micro-aggressions” based on race</u>, small cuts, insults, and slights that can have a cumulative effect of individual harm.24 <u>In using the term “racial atmosphere,” reference may be made to other issues of harm to people of color, such as <strong>ignorance</u></strong> of black history <u>and</u> contemporary racism or <u><strong>discrimination</u></strong> in career advancement.25 <u>The implication of these meanings is that the micro-aggressions add up to what is perceived as a <strong>general predisposition of white people</u></strong> <u>to treat people of color in unjust ways. But, at this time, ideas of racial atmosphere and climate also work as metaphors</u> for what is unknown about race relations and attitudes; they capture the vagueness and unpredictability of racial prejudice and discrimination that occur in a society where nonwhites remain disadvantaged, even though there is formal equality. This “vague weather” aspect of atmosphere and climate is an epistemological condition of indecision that may or may not constitute a lasting crisis, although some syndromes of political injustice should be viewed as crises. A crisis is a period of indecision and uncertainty that requires a resolution before life can go on. Will blacks and other people of color achieve more equality with whites, or is the United States—and with it the world, because US racism is exported with business practices, tour-ism, and entertainment products—on the brink of a new era of explicitlу direct oppression of people of color? Are most white Americans, whose race-neutral economic and social activities have racist effects on nonwhites, genuinely ignorant of how the system in which they operate works, or are they secretly but knowingly hearts-and-minds not clear that this indeterminate aspect of present racial atmosphere and climates must be resolved now. We do not know if life can go on if it is not resolved or what it means for life to go on, or not. We do not even know if the putative crisis can be resolved at this time, because there is as yet no systematic and sustained, impassioned, liberatory dis- course for our condition of ambiguity, a time with a black president and police killing with impunity of unarmed black youth, a time of voting rights for everyone but new restrictions and requirements that disproportionately affect African Americans.26 <u>Except for what academics <strong>write and say</strong> and <strong>how important they think their discourse is</u></strong> (among themselves), <u><mark>American discourse</mark> of racial liberation <mark>is at a <strong>standstill</u></strong>. <u>And</mark> insofar as academic discourse is uttered and received <mark>in a <strong>closed system</strong>,</u> <u>with a <strong>semicaptive audience</u></strong></mark> <u>and <strong>no reliable means for it to affect the real world</u></strong>, <u><mark>that standstill remains <strong>at the disposal of</u></strong></mark> history, where history is understood to be the <u><strong>unpredictable</u></strong> result of <u><strong><mark>contingent events</u></strong></mark>. However, if academic oppositional political discourse can be related to a longer historical trend, a more coherent and optimistic picture might emerge. Cornel West's ideas about the American black prophetic tradition appears to be a relation to such a trend. </p>
1NC vs Texas AL
Case
Alt Fails---1NC
14,625
285
82,555
./documents/ndtceda19/MissouriState/VaRe/Missouri%20State-VanDyke-Reeves-Neg-UMKC-Round6.docx
614,196
N
UMKC
6
Texas AL
Scott Harris
1AC - "Indigenous Storytelling" 2NR - T Case
ndtceda19/MissouriState/VaRe/Missouri%20State-VanDyke-Reeves-Neg-UMKC-Round6.docx
null
51,985
VaRe
Missouri State VaRe
null
Al.....
Va.....
Pe.....
Re.....
19,273
MissouriState
Missouri State
null
null
1,009
ndtceda19
NDT/CEDA 2019-20
2,019
cx
college
2
2,725,835
Root cause explanations of international politics don’t exist – methodological pluralism is necessary to reclaim IR as emancipatory praxis and avoid endless political violence.
Bleiker 14
Bleiker 14 – (6/17, Roland, Professor of International Relations at the University of Queensland, “International Theory Between Reification and Self-Reflective Critique,” International Studies Review, Volume 16, Issue 2, pages 325–327)
the key challenge in IR is “unchecked reification” the widespread and dangerous process of forgetting “the distinction between theoretical concepts and the real-world things they mean to describe The dangers are real because IR deals with some of the most difficult issues, from genocides to war Upholding one subjective position without critical scrutiny can have far-reaching consequences Levine detects self-reflective and critical moments in straightforward positivist positions outlines why while explicitly post-positivist IR scholarship, often lacked critical self-awareness respective authors failed to appreciate sufficiently that reification is a consequence of all thinking sustainable critique not just something that is directed outwards, against particular theories or theorists It is also inward-oriented, ongoing, and sensitive to the “limitations of thought itself” He starts off with depicting reification not as a flaw that is meant to be expunged, but as an a priori condition for scholarship. The challenge then is not to let it go unchecked. Methodological pluralism lies at the heart of Levine's sustainable critique multiple methods to understand the same event or phenomena He writes of the need to validate “multiple and mutually incompatible ways of seeing” a scholar oscillates back and forth between different methods and paradigms trying to understand the event in question from multiple perspectives No single method can ever adequately represent the event or should gain the upper hand But each should recognize and capture details or perspectives that the others cannot In practical terms, this means combining a range of methods even when or, rather, precisely when they are deemed incompatible They can range from poststructual deconstruction to the tools pioneered and championed by positivist social sciences The benefit of such methodological polyphony is not just the opportunity to bring out nuances and new perspectives Once the false hope of a smooth synthesis has been abandoned, the very incompatibility of the respective perspectives can then be used to identify the reifying tendencies in each of them reification may be “checked at the source” and a “critically reflexive moment might thus be rendered sustainable” Levine's approach is not really post-foundational but an attempt to “balance foundationalisms against one another”
the key challenge in is “unchecked reification” dangerous because IR deals with some of the most difficult issues, from genocides to war Upholding one subjective position without critical scrutiny can have far-reaching consequences Levine detects self-reflective moments in positivist positions outlines why explicitly post-positivist IR often lacked critical self-awareness reification is a consequence of all thinking . The challenge then is not to let it go unchecked. Methodological pluralism lies at the heart of sustainable critique multiple methods to understand the same event or phenomena a scholar oscillates back and forth between different methods and paradigms trying to understand from multiple perspectives No single method can ever adequately represent the event or should gain the upper hand But each should recognize and capture details or perspectives that the others cannot In practical terms, this means combining methods precisely when they are deemed incompatible They can range from poststructual deconstruction to positivist social sciences The benefit of methodological polyphony is not just the opportunity to bring out nuances and new perspectives reification may be “checked at the source”
This book is part of an increasing trend of scholarly works that have embraced poststructural critique but want to ground it in more positive political foundations, while retaining a reluctance to return to the positivist tendencies that implicitly underpin much of constructivist research. The path that Daniel Levine has carved out is innovative, sophisticated, and convincing. A superb scholarly achievement. For Levine, the key challenge in international relations (IR) scholarship is what he calls “unchecked reification”: the widespread and dangerous process of forgetting “the distinction between theoretical concepts and the real-world things they mean to describe or to which they refer” (p. 15). The dangers are real, Levine stresses, because IR deals with some of the most difficult issues, from genocides to war. Upholding one subjective position without critical scrutiny can thus have far-reaching consequences. Following Theodor Adorno—who is the key theoretical influence on this book—Levine takes a post-positive position and assumes that the world cannot be known outside of our human perceptions and the values that are inevitably intertwined with them. His ultimate goal is to overcome reification, or, to be more precise, to recognize it as an inevitable aspect of thought so that its dangerous consequences can be mitigated. Levine proceeds in three stages: First he reviews several decades of IR theories to resurrect critical moments when scholars displayed an acute awareness of the dangers of reification. He refreshingly breaks down distinctions between conventional and progressive scholarship, for he detects self-reflective and critical moments in scholars that are usually associated with straightforward positivist positions (such as E.H. Carr, Hans Morgenthau, or Graham Allison). But Levine also shows how these moments of self-reflexivity never lasted long and were driven out by the compulsion to offer systematic and scientific knowledge. The second stage of Levine's inquiry outlines why IR scholars regularly closed down critique. Here, he points to a range of factors and phenomena, from peer review processes to the speed at which academics are meant to publish. And here too, he eschews conventional wisdom, showing that work conducted in the wake of the third debate, while explicitly post-positivist and critiquing the reifying tendencies of existing IR scholarship, often lacked critical self-awareness. As a result, Levine believes that many of the respective authors failed to appreciate sufficiently that “reification is a consequence of all thinking—including itself” (p. 68). The third objective of Levine's book is also the most interesting one. Here, he outlines the path toward what he calls “sustainable critique”: a form of self-reflection that can counter the dangers of reification. Critique, for him, is not just something that is directed outwards, against particular theories or theorists. It is also inward-oriented, ongoing, and sensitive to the “limitations of thought itself” (p. 12). The challenges that such a sustainable critique faces are formidable. Two stand out: First, if the natural tendency to forget the origins and values of our concepts are as strong as Levine and other Adorno-inspired theorists believe they are, then how can we actually recognize our own reifying tendencies? Are we not all inevitably and subconsciously caught in a web of meanings from which we cannot escape? Second, if one constantly questions one's own perspective, does one not fall into a relativism that loses the ability to establish the kind of stable foundations that are necessary for political action? Adorno has, of course, been critiqued as relentlessly negative, even by his second-generation Frankfurt School successors (from Jürgen Habermas to his IR interpreters, such as Andrew Linklater and Ken Booth). The response that Levine has to these two sets of legitimate criticisms are, in my view, both convincing and useful at a practical level. He starts off with depicting reification not as a flaw that is meant to be expunged, but as an a priori condition for scholarship. The challenge then is not to let it go unchecked. Methodological pluralism lies at the heart of Levine's sustainable critique. He borrows from what Adorno calls a “constellation”: an attempt to juxtapose, rather than integrate, different perspectives. It is in this spirit that Levine advocates multiple methods to understand the same event or phenomena. He writes of the need to validate “multiple and mutually incompatible ways of seeing” (p. 63, see also pp. 101–102). In this model, a scholar oscillates back and forth between different methods and paradigms, trying to understand the event in question from multiple perspectives. No single method can ever adequately represent the event or should gain the upper hand . But each should, in a way, recognize and capture details or perspectives that the others cannot (p. 102). In practical terms, this means combining a range of methods even when—or, rather, precisely when—they are deemed incompatible. They can range from poststructual deconstruction to the tools pioneered and championed by positivist social sciences. The benefit of such a methodological polyphony is not just the opportunity to bring out nuances and new perspectives. Once the false hope of a smooth synthesis has been abandoned, the very incompatibility of the respective perspectives can then be used to identify the reifying tendencies in each of them. For Levine, this is how reification may be “checked at the source” and this is how a “critically reflexive moment might thus be rendered sustainable” (p. 103). It is in this sense that Levine's approach is not really post-foundational but, rather, an attempt to “balance foundationalisms against one another” (p. 14). There are strong parallels here with arguments advanced by assemblage thinking and complexity theory—links that could have been explored in more detail.
5,990
<h4><strong>Root cause explanations of international politics don’t exist – methodological pluralism is necessary to reclaim IR as emancipatory praxis and avoid endless political violence.</h4><p>Bleiker 14</strong> – (6/17, Roland, Professor of International Relations at the University of Queensland, “International Theory Between Reification and Self-Reflective Critique,” International Studies Review, Volume 16, Issue 2, pages 325–327)</p><p>This book is part of an increasing trend of scholarly works that have embraced poststructural critique but want to ground it in more positive political foundations, while retaining a reluctance to return to the positivist tendencies that implicitly underpin much of constructivist research. The path that Daniel Levine has carved out is innovative, sophisticated, and convincing. A superb scholarly achievement.</p><p>For Levine, <u><mark>the key challenge in</u></mark> international relations (<u><strong>IR</u></strong>) scholarship <u><mark>is</u></mark> what he calls <u><strong><mark>“unchecked reification”</u></strong></mark>: <u>the widespread and <mark>dangerous</mark> process of forgetting “the distinction between theoretical concepts and the real-world things they mean to describe</u> or to which they refer” (p. 15). <u>The dangers are real</u>, Levine stresses, <u><mark>because <strong>IR deals with</strong> some of the most difficult issues, from <strong>genocides to war</u></strong></mark>. <u><mark>Upholding one subjective position without critical scrutiny can</u></mark> thus <u><mark>have <strong>far-reaching consequences</u></strong></mark>. Following Theodor Adorno—who is the key theoretical influence on this book—Levine takes a post-positive position and assumes that the world cannot be known outside of our human perceptions and the values that are inevitably intertwined with them. His ultimate goal is to overcome reification, or, to be more precise, to recognize it as an inevitable aspect of thought so that its dangerous consequences can be mitigated.</p><p><u><mark>Levine</u></mark> proceeds in three stages: First he reviews several decades of IR theories to resurrect critical moments when scholars displayed an acute awareness of the dangers of reification. He refreshingly breaks down distinctions between conventional and progressive scholarship, for he <u><mark>detects self-reflective</mark> and critical <mark>moments in</u></mark> scholars that are usually associated with <u>straightforward <mark>positivist positions</u></mark> (such as E.H. Carr, Hans Morgenthau, or Graham Allison). But Levine also shows how these moments of self-reflexivity never lasted long and were driven out by the compulsion to offer systematic and scientific knowledge.</p><p>The second stage of Levine's inquiry <u><mark>outlines why</u></mark> IR scholars regularly closed down critique. Here, he points to a range of factors and phenomena, from peer review processes to the speed at which academics are meant to publish. And here too, he eschews conventional wisdom, showing that work conducted in the wake of the third debate, <u>while <mark>explicitly post-positivist</u></mark> and critiquing the reifying tendencies of existing <u><mark>IR</u></mark> <u>scholarship, <mark>often lacked critical self-awareness</u></mark>. As a result, Levine believes that many of the <u>respective authors failed to appreciate sufficiently that</u> “<u><strong><mark>reification is a consequence of all thinking</u></strong></mark>—including itself” (p. 68).</p><p>The third objective of Levine's book is also the most interesting one. Here, he outlines the path toward what he calls “<u>sustainable critique</u>”: a form of self-reflection that can counter the dangers of reification. Critique, for him, is <u>not just something that is directed outwards, against particular theories or theorists</u>. <u>It is also inward-oriented, ongoing, and sensitive to the “limitations of thought itself”</u> (p. 12).</p><p>The challenges that such a sustainable critique faces are formidable. Two stand out: First, if the natural tendency to forget the origins and values of our concepts are as strong as Levine and other Adorno-inspired theorists believe they are, then how can we actually recognize our own reifying tendencies? Are we not all inevitably and subconsciously caught in a web of meanings from which we cannot escape? Second, if one constantly questions one's own perspective, does one not fall into a relativism that loses the ability to establish the kind of stable foundations that are necessary for political action? Adorno has, of course, been critiqued as relentlessly negative, even by his second-generation Frankfurt School successors (from Jürgen Habermas to his IR interpreters, such as Andrew Linklater and Ken Booth).</p><p>The response that Levine has to these two sets of legitimate criticisms are, in my view, both convincing and useful at a practical level. <u>He starts off with depicting reification not as a flaw that is meant to be expunged, but as an a priori condition for scholarship<strong><mark>. The challenge then is not to let it go unchecked.</p><p>Methodological pluralism lies at the heart of</mark> Levine's <mark>sustainable critique</u></strong></mark>. He borrows from what Adorno calls a “constellation”: an attempt to juxtapose, rather than integrate, different perspectives. It is in this spirit that Levine advocates <u><strong><mark>multiple methods to understand the same event or phenomena</u></strong></mark>. <u>He writes of the need to validate “multiple and mutually incompatible ways of seeing”</u> (p. 63, see also pp. 101–102). In this model, <u><mark>a scholar oscillates back and forth between different methods and paradigms</u></mark>, <u><mark>trying to understand</mark> the event in question <mark>from multiple perspectives</u></mark>. <u><strong><mark>No single method can ever adequately represent the event or should gain the upper hand</p><p></u></strong></mark>. <u><mark>But each should</u></mark>, in a way, <u><strong><mark>recognize and capture details or perspectives that the others cannot</u></strong></mark> (p. 102). <u><mark>In practical terms, this means <strong>combining</mark> a range of <mark>methods</strong></mark> even when</u>—<u><strong>or, rather, <mark>precisely when</u></strong></mark>—<u><mark>they are deemed incompatible</u></mark>. <u><mark>They can <strong>range from poststructual deconstruction</strong> to</mark> the tools pioneered and championed by</u> <u><strong><mark>positivist social sciences</u></strong></mark>.</p><p><u><mark>The benefit of</mark> such</u> a <u><strong><mark>methodological polyphony</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>is not just the opportunity to bring out nuances and new perspectives</u></mark>. <u>Once the false hope of a smooth synthesis has been abandoned, the very incompatibility of the respective perspectives can then be used to identify the reifying tendencies in each of them</u>. For Levine, this is how <u><strong><mark>reification may be “checked at the source”</u></strong></mark> <u>and</u> this is how <u>a “critically reflexive moment might thus be rendered sustainable”</u> (p. 103). It is in this sense that <u>Levine's approach is not really post-foundational but</u>, rather, <u>an attempt to “balance foundationalisms against one another”</u> (p. 14). There are strong parallels here with arguments advanced by assemblage thinking and complexity theory—links that could have been explored in more detail.</p>
1AC
null
1AC – Yemen
10,116
1,568
86,453
./documents/hspolicy19/KentDenver/HaSu/Kent%20Denver-Halverson-Sullivan-Aff-Greenhill%20RR-Round2.docx
713,806
A
Greenhill RR
2
Georgetown Day PR
Mason Marriott-Voss, Cody Morrow
1AC - Saudi Arabia 1NC - Gerard K Assurances DA Disclosure Theory 2NR - Gerard K
hspolicy19/KentDenver/HaSu/Kent%20Denver-Halverson-Sullivan-Aff-Greenhill%20RR-Round2.docx
null
60,868
HaSu
Kent Denver HaSu
null
Wi.....
Ha.....
El.....
Su.....
21,262
KentDenver
Kent Denver
CO
null
1,018
hspolicy19
HS Policy 2019-20
2,019
cx
hs
2
2,868,202
Fifth, root cause claims and focus on overarching structures ignore application to material injustice.
Pappas 2.
Pappas 2. The Pragmatists Approach to Injustice, by Gregory Fernando Pappas. The Pluralist, Volume 11, Number 1, Spring 2016, pp. 58-77. Published by University of Illinois Press.
The pragmatists’ approach should be distinguished from nonideal theories whose starting point seems to be the injustices of society at large that have a history and persist through time this approach assumes that¶ a philosophical critique of specific social situations can be accomplished only under the assumption of a broader and full blown critique of soci- ety in its entirety: as a critique of capitalism, of modernity, of western civilization, of rationality itself Pragmatism does not deny the importance of power structures and seeing the connections be- tween injustices through time To capture the legacy of the past on present injustices, we must study history but also seek present evidence of the weight of the past on the present injustice.¶ pragmatists’ approach takes as its main focus diagnosing and treating the particular present illness, that is, the particular situation-bound injustice and not a global “social pathology” or some single transhistorical source of injustice concepts and categories “white supremacy” and “colonialism are nothing more than tools to make reference to and ameliorate particular injustices experienced (suffered) in the midst of a particular and unique re- lationship in a situation complexity of a problem of injustice does not always stop at the level of being a member of a historical group or even a member of many groups, as insisted on by intersectional analysis. There may be unique cir- cumstances to particular countries, towns, neighborhoods, institutions, and ultimately situations that we must be open to in a context-sensitive inquiry the forces that cause and sustain domination vary tremendously context by context, and there isn’t necessarily a single causal explanation theories fail to focus on the concrete problems which arise in experience, allowing such problems to be buried under their sweeping generalizations principles are nothing more than historically grounded tools to use in present problematic situations that call for our analysis principles are falsifiable and open to revision
pragmatists’ approach should be distinguished from theories whose starting point seems injustices at large this assumes philosophical critique can be accomplished under critique of capitalism modernity Pragmatism does not deny the importance of power structures we must study history bu seek present evidence of the weight of the past pragmatists’ approach takes treating the particular situation and not a global “social pathology concepts white supremacy” and “colonialism are tools to ameliorate particular injustices complexity of injustice insist on intersectional analysis the forces that cause and sustain domination vary there isn’t a single causal explanation principles are falsifiable and open to revision
The pragmatists’ approach should be distinguished from nonideal theories whose starting point seems to be the injustices of society at large that have a history and persist through time, where the task of political philosophy is to detect and diagnose the presence of these historical injustices in particular situations of injustice. For example, critical theory today has inherited an approach to social philosophy characteristic of the European tradition that goes back to Rousseau, Marx, Weber, Freud, Marcuse, and others. Accord- ing to Roberto Frega, this tradition takes society to be “intrinsically sick” with a malaise that requires adopting a critical historical stance in order to understand how the systematic sickness affects present social situations. In other words, this approach assumes that¶ a philosophical critique of specific social situations can be accomplished only under the assumption of a broader and full blown critique of soci- ety in its entirety: as a critique of capitalism, of modernity, of western civilization, of rationality itself. The idea of social pathology becomes intelligible only against the background of a philosophy of history or of an anthropology of decline, according to which the distortions of actual social life are but the inevitable consequence of longstanding historical processes. (“Between Pragmatism and Critical Theory” 63)¶ However, this particular approach to injustice is not limited to critical theory. It is present in those Latin American and African American political philosophies that have used and transformed the critical intellectual tools of ¶ critical theory to deal with the problems of injustice in the Americas. For instance, Charles W. Mills claims that the starting point and alternative to the abstractions of ideal theory that masked injustices is to diagnose and rectify a history of an illness—the legacy of white supremacy in our actual society.11 The critical task of revealing this illness is achieved by adopting a historical perspective where the injustices of today are part of a larger historical narrative about the development of modern societies that goes back to how Europeans have progressively dehumanized or subordinated others. Similary, radical feminists as well as Third World scholars, as reaction to the hege- monic Eurocentric paradigms that disguise injustices under the assumption of a universal or objective point of view, have stressed how our knowledge is always situated. This may seem congenial with pragmatism except the locus of the knower and of injustices is often described as power structures located in “global hierarchies” and a “world-system” and not situations.12¶ Pragmatism only questions that we live in History or a “World-System” (as a totality or abstract context) but not that we are in history (lowercase): in a present situation continuous with others where the past weighs heavily in our memories, bodies, habits, structures, and communities. It also does not deny the importance of power structures and seeing the connections be- tween injustices through time, but there is a difference between (a) inquiring into present situations of injustice in order to detect, diagnose, and cure an injustice (a social pathology) across history, and (b) inquiring into the his- tory of a systematic injustice in order to facilitate inquiry into the present unique, context-bound injustice. To capture the legacy of the past on present injustices, we must study history but also seek present evidence of the weight of the past on the present injustice.¶ If injustice is an illness, then the pragmatists’ approach takes as its main focus diagnosing and treating the particular present illness, that is, the particular situation-bound injustice and not a global “social pathology” or some single transhistorical source of injustice. The diagnosis of a particular injustice is not always dependent on adopting a broader critical standpoint of society in its entirety, but even when it is, we must be careful to not forget that such standpoints are useful only for understanding the present evil. The concepts and categories “white supremacy” and “colonialism” can be great tools that can be of planetary significance. One could even argue that they pick out much larger areas of people’s lives and injustices than the categories of class and gender, but in spite of their reach and explanatory theoretical value, they are nothing more than tools to make reference to and ameliorate particular injustices experienced (suffered) in the midst of a particular and unique re- lationship in a situation. No doubt many, but not all, problems of injustice are a consequence of being a member of a group in history, but even in these cases, we cannot a priori assume that injustices are homogeneously equal for all members of that group. Why is this important? The possible pluralism and therefore complexity of a problem of injustice does not always stop at the level of being a member of a historical group or even a member of many groups, as insisted on by intersectional analysis. There may be unique cir- cumstances to particular countries, towns, neighborhoods, institutions, and ultimately situations that we must be open to in a context-sensitive inquiry. If an empirical inquiry is committed to capturing and ameliorating all of the harms in situations of injustice in their raw pretheoretical complexity, then this requires that we try to begin with and return to the concrete, particular, and unique experiences of injustice.¶ Pragmatism agrees with Sally Haslanger’s concern about Charles Mills’s view. She writes: “The goal is not just a theory that is historical (v. ahistori- cal), but is sensitive to historical particularity, i.e., that resists grand causal narratives purporting to give an account of how domination has come about and is perpetuated everywhere and at all times” (1). For “the forces that cause and sustain domination vary tremendously context by context, and there isn’t necessarily a single causal explanation; a theoretical framework that is useful as a basis for political intervention must be highly sensitive to the details of the particular social context” (1).13¶ Although each situation is unique, there are commonalities among the cases that permit inquiry about common causes. We can “formulate tentative general principles from investigation of similar individual cases, and then . . . check the generalizations by applying them to still further cases” (Dewey, Lectures in China 53). But Dewey insists that the focus should be on the indi- vidual case, and was critical of how so many sociopolitical theories are prone to starting and remaining at the level of “sweeping generalizations.” He states that they “fail to focus on the concrete problems which arise in experience, allowing such problems to be buried under their sweeping generalizations” (Lectures in China 53).¶ The lesson pragmatism provides for nonideal theory today is that it must be careful to not reify any injustice as some single historical force for which particular injustice problems are its manifestation or evidence for its exis- tence. Pragmatism welcomes the wisdom and resources of nonideal theories that are historically grounded on actual injustices, but it issues a warning about how they should be understood and implemented. It is, for example, sympathetic to the critical resources found in critical race theory, but with an important qualification. It understands Derrick Bell’s valuable criticism as context-specific to patterns in the practice of American law. Through his inquiry into particular cases and civil rights policies at a particular time and place, Bell learned and proposed certain general principles such as the one of “interest convergence,” that is, “whites will promote racial advantages for blacks only when they also promote white self-interest.”14 But, for pragma- tism, these principles are nothing more than historically grounded tools to use in present problematic situations that call for our analysis, such as deliberation in establishing public policies or making sense of some concrete injustice. The principles are falsifiable and open to revision as we face situation-specific injustices. In testing their adequacy, we need to consider their function in making us see aspects of injustices we would not otherwise appreciate.15
8,396
<h4>Fifth, root cause claims and focus on overarching structures ignore application to material injustice.</h4><p><strong>Pappas 2.</strong> The Pragmatists Approach to Injustice, by Gregory Fernando Pappas. The Pluralist, Volume 11, Number 1, Spring 2016, pp. 58-77. Published by University of Illinois Press. </p><p><u>The <mark>pragmatists’ approach should be distinguished from</mark> nonideal <mark>theories whose starting point seems</mark> to be the <mark>injustices</mark> of society <mark>at large</mark> that have a history and persist through time</u>, where the task of political philosophy is to detect and diagnose the presence of these historical injustices in particular situations of injustice. For example, critical theory today has inherited an approach to social philosophy characteristic of the European tradition that goes back to Rousseau, Marx, Weber, Freud, Marcuse, and others. Accord- ing to Roberto Frega, this tradition takes society to be “intrinsically sick” with a malaise that requires adopting a critical historical stance in order to understand how the systematic sickness affects present social situations. In other words, <u><mark>this</mark> approach <mark>assumes</mark> that<strong>¶</strong> a <mark>philosophical critique</mark> of specific social situations <mark>can be accomplished</mark> only <mark>under</mark> the assumption of a broader and full blown <mark>critique of</mark> soci- ety in its entirety: as a critique of <mark>capitalism</mark>, of <mark>modernity</mark>, of western civilization, of rationality itself</u>. The idea of social pathology becomes intelligible only against the background of a philosophy of history or of an anthropology of decline, according to which the distortions of actual social life are but the inevitable consequence of longstanding historical processes. (“Between Pragmatism and Critical Theory” 63)¶ However, this particular approach to injustice is not limited to critical theory. It is present in those Latin American and African American political philosophies that have used and transformed the critical intellectual tools of ¶ critical theory to deal with the problems of injustice in the Americas. For instance, Charles W. Mills claims that the starting point and alternative to the abstractions of ideal theory that masked injustices is to diagnose and rectify a history of an illness—the legacy of white supremacy in our actual society.11 The critical task of revealing this illness is achieved by adopting a historical perspective where the injustices of today are part of a larger historical narrative about the development of modern societies that goes back to how Europeans have progressively dehumanized or subordinated others. Similary, radical feminists as well as Third World scholars, as reaction to the hege- monic Eurocentric paradigms that disguise injustices under the assumption of a universal or objective point of view, have stressed how our knowledge is always situated. This may seem congenial with pragmatism except the locus of the knower and of injustices is often described as power structures located in “global hierarchies” and a “world-system” and not situations.12¶ <u><mark>Pragmatism</u></mark> only questions that we live in History or a “World-System” (as a totality or abstract context) but not that we are in history (lowercase): in a present situation continuous with others where the past weighs heavily in our memories, bodies, habits, structures, and communities. It also <u><mark>does not deny the importance of power structures</mark> and seeing the connections be- tween injustices through time</u>, but there is a difference between (a) inquiring into present situations of injustice in order to detect, diagnose, and cure an injustice (a social pathology) across history, and (b) inquiring into the his- tory of a systematic injustice in order to facilitate inquiry into the present unique, context-bound injustice. <u>To capture the legacy of the past on present injustices, <mark>we must study history bu</mark>t also <strong><mark>seek present evidence of the weight of the past</u></strong></mark> <u>on the present injustice.<strong>¶</strong> </u>If injustice is an illness, then the <u><mark>pragmatists’ approach takes</mark> as its main focus diagnosing and <mark>treating</mark> the particular present illness, that is, <mark>the particular situation</mark>-bound injustice <mark>and not a global “social pathology</mark>” or some single transhistorical source of injustice</u>. The diagnosis of a particular injustice is not always dependent on adopting a broader critical standpoint of society in its entirety, but even when it is, we must be careful to not forget that such standpoints are useful only for understanding the present evil. The <u><mark>concepts</mark> and categories “<mark>white supremacy” and “colonialism</u></mark>” can be great tools that can be of planetary significance. One could even argue that they pick out much larger areas of people’s lives and injustices than the categories of class and gender, but in spite of their reach and explanatory theoretical value, they <u><mark>are</mark> nothing more than <mark>tools to</mark> make reference to and <mark>ameliorate particular injustices</mark> experienced (suffered) in the midst of a particular and unique re- lationship in a situation</u>. No doubt many, but not all, problems of injustice are a consequence of being a member of a group in history, but even in these cases, we cannot a priori assume that injustices are homogeneously equal for all members of that group. Why is this important? The possible pluralism and therefore <u><mark>complexity of</mark> a problem of <mark>injustice</mark> does not always stop at the level of being a member of a historical group or even a member of many groups, as <mark>insist</mark>ed <mark>on</mark> by <mark>intersectional analysis</mark>. There may be unique cir- cumstances to particular countries, towns, neighborhoods, institutions, and ultimately situations that we must be open to in a context-sensitive inquiry</u>. If an empirical inquiry is committed to capturing and ameliorating all of the harms in situations of injustice in their raw pretheoretical complexity, then this requires that we try to begin with and return to the concrete, particular, and unique experiences of injustice.¶ Pragmatism agrees with Sally Haslanger’s concern about Charles Mills’s view. She writes: “The goal is not just a theory that is historical (v. ahistori- cal), but is sensitive to historical particularity, i.e., that resists grand causal narratives purporting to give an account of how domination has come about and is perpetuated everywhere and at all times” (1). For “<u><mark>the forces that cause and sustain domination vary</mark> tremendously context by context, and <mark>there isn’t</mark> necessarily <mark>a single causal explanation</u></mark>; a theoretical framework that is useful as a basis for political intervention must be highly sensitive to the details of the particular social context” (1).13¶ Although each situation is unique, there are commonalities among the cases that permit inquiry about common causes. We can “formulate tentative general principles from investigation of similar individual cases, and then . . . check the generalizations by applying them to still further cases” (Dewey, Lectures in China 53). But Dewey insists that the focus should be on the indi- vidual case, and was critical of how so many sociopolitical <u>theories</u> are prone to starting and remaining at the level of “sweeping generalizations.” He states that they “<u>fail to focus on the concrete problems which arise in experience, allowing such problems to be buried under their sweeping generalizations</u>” (Lectures in China 53).¶ The lesson pragmatism provides for nonideal theory today is that it must be careful to not reify any injustice as some single historical force for which particular injustice problems are its manifestation or evidence for its exis- tence. Pragmatism welcomes the wisdom and resources of nonideal theories that are historically grounded on actual injustices, but it issues a warning about how they should be understood and implemented. It is, for example, sympathetic to the critical resources found in critical race theory, but with an important qualification. It understands Derrick Bell’s valuable criticism as context-specific to patterns in the practice of American law. Through his inquiry into particular cases and civil rights policies at a particular time and place, Bell learned and proposed certain general principles such as the one of “interest convergence,” that is, “whites will promote racial advantages for blacks only when they also promote white self-interest.”14 But, for pragma- tism, these <u>principles are nothing more than historically grounded tools to use in present problematic situations that call for our analysis</u>, such as deliberation in establishing public policies or making sense of some concrete injustice. The <u><mark>principles are falsifiable and open to revision</u></mark> as we face situation-specific injustices. In testing their adequacy, we need to consider their function in making us see aspects of injustices we would not otherwise appreciate.15</p>
SO Prag AC [4:50]
Underview
null
359,994
209
91,470
./documents/hsld19/HunterCollege/Di/Hunter%20College-Dittgen-Aff-Yale-Round2.docx
840,574
A
Yale
2
Roslyn AG
Wiora
I read an ac they responded with an nc then we debated
hsld19/HunterCollege/Di/Hunter%20College-Dittgen-Aff-Yale-Round2.docx
null
71,742
MaDi
Hunter College MaDi
null
Ma.....
Di.....
null
null
24,137
HunterCollege
Hunter College
NY
null
1,027
hsld19
HS LD 2019-20
2,019
ld
hs
1
2,021,893
This is a change in the world order. Decolonization is the creation of alternative political realities outside of the settler state that seeks to destroy indigenous communities. This opens the possibilities for new forms of life and relationships with the people and the land this directly disrupts settler attempts at reconciliation by destabilizing the settler psyche. The 1AC unsettles the innocence of the settler by making an “impossible” demand that accepts nothing but the physical return of indigenous land, the abolition of slavery and property and the dismantlement of the imperial metropole.
Tuck & Yang 12
Tuck & Yang 12 [Eve Tuck is Associate Professor of Critical Race and Indigenous Studies at the Ontario Institute for Studies in Education (OISE), University of Toronto. She is Canada Research Chair of Indigenous Methodologies with Youth and Communities. K. Wayne Yang writes about decolonization and everyday epic organizing, particularly from underneath ghetto colonialism, often with his frequent collaborator, Eve Tuck. Currently, they are convening The Land Relationships Super Collective, editing the book series, Indigenous and Decolonizing Studies in Education, and editing the journal, Critical Ethnic Studies. He is interested in the complex role of cities in global affairs: cities as sites of settler colonialism, as stages for empire, as places of resettlement and gentrification, and as always-already on Indigenous lands. *Sometimes he writes as la paperson, an avatar that irregularly calls.“Decolonization is not a metaphor,” Decolonization: Indigeneity, Education & Society Vol 1 No 1 (2012) //tjb]
Having elaborated on settler moves to innocence, we give a synopsis of the imbrication of settler colonialism with transnationalist, abolitionist, and critical pedagogy movements - efforts that are often thought of as exempt from Indigenous decolonizing analyses - as a synthesis of how decolonization as material, not metaphor, unsettles the innocence of these movements. These are interruptions which destabilize, un-balance, and repatriate the very terms and assumptions of some of the most radical efforts to reimagine human power relations. We argue that the opportunities for solidarity lie in what is incommensurable rather than what is common across these efforts. We offer these perspectives on unsettling innocence because they are examples of what we might call an ethic of incommensurability, which recognizes what is distinct, what is sovereign for project(s) of decolonization in relation to human and civil rights based social justice projects. We make these notations to highlight opportunities for what can only ever be strategic and contingent collaborations, and to indicate the reasons that lasting solidarities may be elusive, even undesirable. The anti-colonial turn towards the transnational can sometimes involve ignoring the settler colonial context where one resides and how that inhabitation is implicated in settler colonialism, in order to establish “global” solidarities that presumably suffer fewer complicities and complications. For people writing on Third World decolonizations, but who do so upon Native land, we invite you to consider the permanent settler war as the theater for all imperial wars The abolition of slavery often presumes the expansion of settlers who own Native land and life via inclusion of emancipated slaves and prisoners into the settler nation-state. Communal ownership of land has figured centrally in various movements for autonomous, self-determined communities. “The land belongs to those who work it,” disturbingly parrots Lockean justifications for seizing Native land as property, ‘earned’ through one’s labor in clearing and cultivating ‘virgin’ land. Thus, abolition is likewise twofold, requiring the repatriation of land and the abolition of property (land and bodies). Incommensurability is an acknowledgement that decolonization will require a change in the order of the world This is not to say that Indigenous peoples or Black and brown peoples take positions of dominance over white settlers; the goal is not for everyone to merely swap spots on the settler-colonial triad, to take another turn on the merry-go-round. The goal is to break the relentless structuring of the triad - a break and not a compromise Breaking the settler colonial triad, in direct terms, means repatriating land to sovereign Native tribes and nations, abolition of slavery in its contemporary forms, and the dismantling of the imperial metropole. Decolonization “here” is intimately connected to anti-imperialism elsewhere. However, decolonial struggles here/there are not parallel, not shared equally, nor do they bring neat closure to the concerns of all involved - particularly not for settlers. There is so much that is incommensurable, so many overlaps that can’t be figured, that cannot be resolved. Settler colonialism fuels imperialism all around the globe. “Indian Country” was/is the term used in Viet Nam, Afghanistan, Iraq by the U.S. military for ‘enemy territory’. The technologies of the permanent settler war are reserviced for foreign wars, including boarding schools, colonial schools, urban schools run by military personnel.
transnationalist, abolitionist, and critical pedagogy efforts are often thought of as exempt from Indigenous decolonizing analyses - decolonization unsettles the innocence of these movements. These are interruptions which destabilize the terms of radical efforts to reimagine power relations. opportunities for solidarity lie in what is incommensurable rather than what is common . an ethic of incommensurability recognizes what is distinct for decolonization . lasting solidarities may be elusive, even undesirable. Incommensurability is an acknowledgement that decolonization will require a change in the order of the world This is not to say that Indigenous peoples or Black and brown peoples take positions of dominance over white settlers; the goal is not for everyone to merely swap spots on the settler-colonial triad . e goal is to break the relentless structuring of the triad - a break and not a compromise . Breaking the settler colonial triad, means repatriating land to sovereign Native tribes and nations, abolition of slavery in its contemporary forms, and the dismantling of the imperial metropole. Decolonization “here” is intimately connected to anti-imperialism elsewhere. decolonial struggles are not parallel, not shared equally, nor do they bring neat closure to the concerns of all involved - particularly not for settlers. There is so much that is incommensurable, so many overlaps that can’t be figured, that cannot be resolved.
Having elaborated on settler moves to innocence, we give a synopsis of the imbrication of settler colonialism with transnationalist, abolitionist, and critical pedagogy movements - efforts that are often thought of as exempt from Indigenous decolonizing analyses - as a synthesis of how decolonization as material, not metaphor, unsettles the innocence of these movements. These are interruptions which destabilize, un-balance, and repatriate the very terms and assumptions of some of the most radical efforts to reimagine human power relations. We argue that the opportunities for solidarity lie in what is incommensurable rather than what is common across these efforts. We offer these perspectives on unsettling innocence because they are examples of what we might call an ethic of incommensurability, which recognizes what is distinct, what is sovereign for project(s) of decolonization in relation to human and civil rights based social justice projects. There are portions of these projects that simply cannot speak to one another, cannot be aligned or allied. We make these notations to highlight opportunities for what can only ever be strategic and contingent collaborations, and to indicate the reasons that lasting solidarities may be elusive, even undesirable. Below we point to unsettling themes that challenge the coalescence of social justice endeavors broadly assembled into three areas: Transnational or Third World decolonizations, Abolition, and Critical Space-Place Pedagogies. For each of these areas, we offer entry points into the literature - beginning a sort of bibliography of incommensurability. Third world decolonizations The anti-colonial turn towards the transnational can sometimes involve ignoring the settler colonial context where one resides and how that inhabitation is implicated in settler colonialism, in order to establish “global” solidarities that presumably suffer fewer complicities and complications. This deliberate not-seeing is morally convenient but avoids an important feature of the aforementioned selective collapsibility of settler colonial-nations states. Expressions such as “the Global South within the Global North” and “the Third World in the First World” neglect the Four Directions via a Flat Earth perspective and ambiguate First Nations with Third World migrants. For people writing on Third World decolonizations, but who do so upon Native land, we invite you to consider the permanent settler war as the theater for all imperial wars: ● the Orientalism of Indigenous Americans (Berger, 2004; Marez, 2007) ● discovery, invasion, occupation, and Commons as the claims of settler sovereignty (Ford, 2010) ● heteropatriarchy as the imposition of settler sexuality (Morgensen, 2011) ● citizenship as coercive and forced assimilation into the white settler normative (Bruyneel, 2004; Somerville, 2010) ● religion as covenant for settler nation-state (A.J. Barker, 2009; Maldonado-Torres, 2008) ● the frontier as the first and always the site of invasion and war (Byrd, 2011), ● U.S. imperialism as the expansion of settler colonialism (ibid) ● Asian settler colonialism (Fujikane, 2012; Fujikane, & Okamura, 2008, Saranillio, 2010a, 2010b) ● the frontier as the language of ‘progress’ and discovery (Maldonado-Torres, 2008) ● rape as settler colonial structure (Deer, 2009; 2010) ● the discourse of terrorism as the terror of Native retribution (Tuck & Ree, forthcoming) ● Native Feminisms as incommensurable with other feminisms (Arvin, Tuck, Morrill, forthcoming; Goeman & Denetdale, 2009). Abolition The abolition of slavery often presumes the expansion of settlers who own Native land and life via inclusion of emancipated slaves and prisoners into the settler nation-state. As we have noted, it is no accident that the U.S. government promised 40 acres of Indian land as reparations for plantation slavery. Likewise, indentured European laborers were often awarded tracts of ‘unsettled’ Indigenous land as payment at the end of their service (McCoy, forthcoming). Communal ownership of land has figured centrally in various movements for autonomous, self-determined communities. “The land belongs to those who work it,” disturbingly parrots Lockean justifications for seizing Native land as property, ‘earned’ through one’s labor in clearing and cultivating ‘virgin’ land. For writers on the prison industrial complex, il/legality, and other forms of slavery, we urge you to consider how enslavement is a twofold procedure: removal from land and the creation of property (land and bodies). Thus, abolition is likewise twofold, requiring the repatriation of land and the abolition of property (land and bodies). Abolition means self-possession but not object-possession, repatriation but not reparation: ● “The animals of the world exist for their own reasons. They were not made for humans any more than black people were made for white, or women created for men” (Alice Walker, describing the work of Marjorie Spiegel, in the in the preface to Spigel’s 1988 book, The Dreaded Comparison). ● Enslavement/removal of Native Americans (Gallay, 2009) ● Slaves who become slave-owners, savagery as enslavability, chattel slavery as a sign of civilization (Gallay, 2009) ● Black fugitivity, undercommons, and radical dispossession (Moten, 2008; Moten & Harney, 2004; Moten & Harney, 2010) ● Incarceration as a settler colonialism strategy of land dispossession (Ross, 1998; Watson, 2007) ● Native land and Native people as co-constituitive (Meyer, 2008; Kawagley, 2010) Critical pedagogies The many critical pedagogies that engage emancipatory education, place based education, environmental education, critical multiculturalism, and urban education often position land as public Commons or seek commonalities between struggles. Although we believe that “we must be fluent” in each other’s stories and struggles (paraphrasing Alexander, 2002, p.91), we detect precisely this lack of fluency in land and Indigenous sovereignty. Yupiaq scholar, Oscar Kawagley’s assertion, “We know that Mother Nature has a culture, and it is a Native culture” (2010, p. xiii), directs us to think through land as “more than a site upon which humans make history or as a location that accumulates history” (Goeman, 2008, p.24). The forthcoming special issue in Environmental Education Research, “Land Education: Indigenous, postcolonial, and decolonizing perspectives on place and environmental education research” might be a good starting point to consider the incommensurability of place-based, environmentalist, urban pedagogies with land education. ● The urban as Indigenous (Bang, 2009; Belin, 1999; Friedel, 2011; Goeman, 2008; Intertribal Friendship House & Lobo, 2002) ● Indigenous storied land as disrupting settler maps (Goeman, 2008) ● Novels, poetry, and essays by Greg Sarris, Craig Womack, Joy Harjo, Gerald Vizenor ● To Remain an Indian (Lomawaima & McCarty, 2006) ● Shadow Curriculum (Richardson, 2011) ● Red Pedagogy (Grande, 2004) ● Land Education (McCoy, Tuck, McKenzie, forthcoming) More on incommensurability Incommensurability is an acknowledgement that decolonization will require a change in the order of the world (Fanon, 1963). This is not to say that Indigenous peoples or Black and brown peoples take positions of dominance over white settlers; the goal is not for everyone to merely swap spots on the settler-colonial triad, to take another turn on the merry-go-round. The goal is to break the relentless structuring of the triad - a break and not a compromise (Memmi, 1991). Breaking the settler colonial triad, in direct terms, means repatriating land to sovereign Native tribes and nations, abolition of slavery in its contemporary forms, and the dismantling of the imperial metropole. Decolonization “here” is intimately connected to anti-imperialism elsewhere. However, decolonial struggles here/there are not parallel, not shared equally, nor do they bring neat closure to the concerns of all involved - particularly not for settlers. Decolonization is not equivocal to other anti-colonial struggles. It is incommensurable. There is so much that is incommensurable, so many overlaps that can’t be figured, that cannot be resolved. Settler colonialism fuels imperialism all around the globe. Oil is the motor and motive for war and so was salt, so will be water. Settler sovereignty over these very pieces of earth, air, and water is what makes possible these imperialisms. The same yellow pollen in the water of the Laguna Pueblo reservation in New Mexico, Leslie Marmon Silko reminds us, is the same uranium that annihilated over 200,000 strangers in 2 flashes. The same yellow pollen that poisons the land from where it came. Used in the same war that took a generation of young Pueblo men. Through the voice of her character Betonie, Silko writes, “Thirty thousand years ago they were not strangers. You saw what the evil had done; you saw the witchery ranging as wide as the world" (Silko, 1982, p. 174). In Tucson, Arizona, where Silko lives, her books are now banned in schools. Only curricular materials affirming the settler innocence, ingenuity, and right to America may be taught. In “No”, her response to the 2003 United States invasion of Iraq, Mvskoke/Creek poet Joy Harjo (2004) writes, “Yes, that was me you saw shaking with bravery, with a government issued rifle on my back. I’m sorry I could not greet you, as you deserved, my relative.” Don’t Native Americans participate in greater rates in the military? asks the young-ish man from Viet Nam. “Indian Country” was/is the term used in Viet Nam, Afghanistan, Iraq by the U.S. military for ‘enemy territory’. The first Black American President said without blinking, “There was a point before folks had left, before we had gotten everybody back on the helicopter and were flying back to base, where they said Geronimo has been killed, and Geronimo was the code name for bin Laden.” Elmer Pratt, Black Panther leader, falsely imprisoned for 27 years, was a Vietnam Veteran, was nicknamed ‘Geronimo’. Geronimo is settler nickname for the Bedonkohe Apache warrior who fought Mexican and then U.S. expansion into Apache tribal lands. The Colt .45 was perfected to kill Indigenous people during the ‘liberation’ of what became the Philippines, but it was first invented for the ‘Indian Wars’ in North America alongside The Hotchkiss Canon- a gattling gun that shot canonballs. The technologies of the permanent settler war are reserviced for foreign wars, including boarding schools, colonial schools, urban schools run by military personnel. It is properly called Indian Country. Ideologies of US settler colonialism directly informed Australian settler colonialism. South African apartheid townships, the kill-zones in what became the Philippine colony, then nation-state, the checkerboarding of Palestinian land with checkpoints, were modeled after U.S. seizures of land and containments of Indian bodies to reservations. The racial science developed in the U.S. (a settler colonial racial science) informed Hitler’s designs on racial purity (“This book is my bible” he said of Madison Grant’s The Passing of the Great Race). The admiration is sometimes mutual, the doctors and administrators of forced sterilizations of black, Native, disabled, poor, and mostly female people - The Sterilization Act accompanied the Racial Integrity Act and the Pocohontas Exception - praised the Nazi eugenics program. Forced sterilizations became illegal in California in 1964.
11,502
<h4>This is a change in the world order. Decolonization is the creation of alternative political realities outside of the settler state that seeks to destroy indigenous communities. This opens the possibilities for new forms of life and relationships with the people and the land this directly disrupts settler attempts at reconciliation by destabilizing the settler psyche. The 1AC unsettles the innocence of the settler by making an “impossible” demand that accepts nothing but the physical return of indigenous land, the abolition of slavery and property and the dismantlement of the imperial metropole. </h4><p><strong>Tuck & Yang 12</strong> [Eve Tuck is Associate Professor of Critical Race and Indigenous Studies at the Ontario Institute for Studies in Education (OISE), University of Toronto. She is Canada Research Chair of Indigenous Methodologies with Youth and Communities. K. Wayne Yang writes about decolonization and everyday epic organizing, particularly from underneath ghetto colonialism, often with his frequent collaborator, Eve Tuck. Currently, they are convening The Land Relationships Super Collective, editing the book series, Indigenous and Decolonizing Studies in Education, and editing the journal, Critical Ethnic Studies. He is interested in the complex role of cities in global affairs: cities as sites of settler colonialism, as stages for empire, as places of resettlement and gentrification, and as always-already on Indigenous lands. *Sometimes he writes as la paperson, an avatar that irregularly calls.“Decolonization is not a metaphor,” Decolonization: Indigeneity, Education & Society Vol 1 No 1 (2012) //tjb]</p><p><u><strong>Having elaborated on settler moves to innocence, we give a synopsis of the imbrication of settler colonialism with <mark>transnationalist, abolitionist, and critical pedagogy </mark>movements - <mark>efforts</mark> that <mark>are often thought of as exempt from Indigenous decolonizing analyses</mark> <mark>-</mark> as a synthesis of how <mark>decolonization</mark> as material, not metaphor, <mark>unsettles the innocence of these movements.</u></strong></mark> <u><strong><mark>These are interruptions which destabilize</mark>, un-balance, and repatriate <mark>the</mark> very <mark>terms</mark> and assumptions <mark>of</mark> some of the most <mark>radical efforts to reimagine</mark> human <mark>power relations.</mark> We argue that the <mark>opportunities for solidarity lie in what is incommensurable rather than what is common</mark> across these efforts<mark>.</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>We offer these perspectives on unsettling innocence because they are examples of what we might call <mark>an ethic of incommensurability</mark>, which <mark>recognizes what is distinct</mark>, what is sovereign <mark>for</mark> project(s) of <mark>decolonization</mark> in relation to human and civil rights based social justice projects<mark>.</u></strong></mark> There are portions of these projects that simply cannot speak to one another, cannot be aligned or allied. <u><strong>We make these notations to highlight opportunities for what can only ever be strategic and contingent collaborations, and to indicate the reasons that <mark>lasting solidarities may be elusive, even undesirable.</u></strong></mark> Below we point to unsettling themes that challenge the coalescence of social justice endeavors broadly assembled into three areas: Transnational or Third World decolonizations, Abolition, and Critical Space-Place Pedagogies. For each of these areas, we offer entry points into the literature - beginning a sort of bibliography of incommensurability. Third world decolonizations <u><strong>The anti-colonial turn towards the transnational can sometimes involve ignoring the settler colonial context where one resides and how that inhabitation is implicated in settler colonialism, in order to establish “global” solidarities that presumably suffer fewer complicities and complications.</u></strong> This deliberate not-seeing is morally convenient but avoids an important feature of the aforementioned selective collapsibility of settler colonial-nations states. Expressions such as “the Global South within the Global North” and “the Third World in the First World” neglect the Four Directions via a Flat Earth perspective and ambiguate First Nations with Third World migrants. <u><strong>For people writing on Third World decolonizations, but who do so upon Native land, we invite you to consider the permanent settler war as the theater for all imperial wars</u></strong>: ● the Orientalism of Indigenous Americans (Berger, 2004; Marez, 2007) ● discovery, invasion, occupation, and Commons as the claims of settler sovereignty (Ford, 2010) ● heteropatriarchy as the imposition of settler sexuality (Morgensen, 2011) ● citizenship as coercive and forced assimilation into the white settler normative (Bruyneel, 2004; Somerville, 2010) ● religion as covenant for settler nation-state (A.J. Barker, 2009; Maldonado-Torres, 2008) ● the frontier as the first and always the site of invasion and war (Byrd, 2011), ● U.S. imperialism as the expansion of settler colonialism (ibid) ● Asian settler colonialism (Fujikane, 2012; Fujikane, & Okamura, 2008, Saranillio, 2010a, 2010b) ● the frontier as the language of ‘progress’ and discovery (Maldonado-Torres, 2008) ● rape as settler colonial structure (Deer, 2009; 2010) ● the discourse of terrorism as the terror of Native retribution (Tuck & Ree, forthcoming) ● Native Feminisms as incommensurable with other feminisms (Arvin, Tuck, Morrill, forthcoming; Goeman & Denetdale, 2009). Abolition <u><strong>The abolition of slavery often presumes the expansion of settlers who own Native land and life via inclusion of emancipated slaves and prisoners into the settler nation-state. </u></strong>As we have noted, it is no accident that the U.S. government promised 40 acres of Indian land as reparations for plantation slavery. Likewise, indentured European laborers were often awarded tracts of ‘unsettled’ Indigenous land as payment at the end of their service (McCoy, forthcoming). <u><strong>Communal ownership of land has figured centrally in various movements for autonomous, self-determined communities. “The land belongs to those who work it,” disturbingly parrots Lockean justifications for seizing Native land as property, ‘earned’ through one’s labor in clearing and cultivating ‘virgin’ land.</u></strong> For writers on the prison industrial complex, il/legality, and other forms of slavery, we urge you to consider how enslavement is a twofold procedure: removal from land and the creation of property (land and bodies). <u><strong>Thus, abolition is likewise twofold, requiring the repatriation of land and the abolition of property (land and bodies).</u></strong> Abolition means self-possession but not object-possession, repatriation but not reparation: ● “The animals of the world exist for their own reasons. They were not made for humans any more than black people were made for white, or women created for men” (Alice Walker, describing the work of Marjorie Spiegel, in the in the preface to Spigel’s 1988 book, The Dreaded Comparison). ● Enslavement/removal of Native Americans (Gallay, 2009) ● Slaves who become slave-owners, savagery as enslavability, chattel slavery as a sign of civilization (Gallay, 2009) ● Black fugitivity, undercommons, and radical dispossession (Moten, 2008; Moten & Harney, 2004; Moten & Harney, 2010) ● Incarceration as a settler colonialism strategy of land dispossession (Ross, 1998; Watson, 2007) ● Native land and Native people as co-constituitive (Meyer, 2008; Kawagley, 2010) Critical pedagogies The many critical pedagogies that engage emancipatory education, place based education, environmental education, critical multiculturalism, and urban education often position land as public Commons or seek commonalities between struggles. Although we believe that “we must be fluent” in each other’s stories and struggles (paraphrasing Alexander, 2002, p.91), we detect precisely this lack of fluency in land and Indigenous sovereignty. Yupiaq scholar, Oscar Kawagley’s assertion, “We know that Mother Nature has a culture, and it is a Native culture” (2010, p. xiii), directs us to think through land as “more than a site upon which humans make history or as a location that accumulates history” (Goeman, 2008, p.24). The forthcoming special issue in Environmental Education Research, “Land Education: Indigenous, postcolonial, and decolonizing perspectives on place and environmental education research” might be a good starting point to consider the incommensurability of place-based, environmentalist, urban pedagogies with land education. ● The urban as Indigenous (Bang, 2009; Belin, 1999; Friedel, 2011; Goeman, 2008; Intertribal Friendship House & Lobo, 2002) ● Indigenous storied land as disrupting settler maps (Goeman, 2008) ● Novels, poetry, and essays by Greg Sarris, Craig Womack, Joy Harjo, Gerald Vizenor ● To Remain an Indian (Lomawaima & McCarty, 2006) ● Shadow Curriculum (Richardson, 2011) ● Red Pedagogy (Grande, 2004) ● Land Education (McCoy, Tuck, McKenzie, forthcoming) More on incommensurability <u><strong><mark>Incommensurability is an acknowledgement that decolonization will require a change in the order of the world</u></strong></mark> (Fanon, 1963). <u><strong><mark>This is not to say that Indigenous peoples or Black and brown peoples take positions of dominance over white settlers; the goal is not for everyone to merely swap spots on the settler-colonial triad</mark>, to take another turn on the merry-go-round<mark>.</mark> Th<mark>e goal is to break the relentless structuring of the triad - a break and not a compromise</u></strong></mark> (Memmi, 1991)<mark>.</mark> <u><strong><mark>Breaking the settler colonial triad,</mark> in direct terms, <mark>means repatriating land to sovereign Native tribes and nations, abolition of slavery in its contemporary forms, and the dismantling of the imperial metropole.</mark> <mark>Decolonization “here” is intimately connected to anti-imperialism elsewhere.</mark> However, <mark>decolonial struggles</mark> here/there <mark>are not parallel, not shared equally, nor do they bring neat closure to the concerns of all involved - particularly not for settlers.</u></strong></mark> Decolonization is not equivocal to other anti-colonial struggles. It is incommensurable. <u><strong><mark>There is so much that is incommensurable, so many overlaps that can’t be figured, that cannot be resolved.</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>Settler colonialism fuels imperialism all around the globe.</u></strong> Oil is the motor and motive for war and so was salt, so will be water. Settler sovereignty over these very pieces of earth, air, and water is what makes possible these imperialisms. The same yellow pollen in the water of the Laguna Pueblo reservation in New Mexico, Leslie Marmon Silko reminds us, is the same uranium that annihilated over 200,000 strangers in 2 flashes. The same yellow pollen that poisons the land from where it came. Used in the same war that took a generation of young Pueblo men. Through the voice of her character Betonie, Silko writes, “Thirty thousand years ago they were not strangers. You saw what the evil had done; you saw the witchery ranging as wide as the world" (Silko, 1982, p. 174). In Tucson, Arizona, where Silko lives, her books are now banned in schools. Only curricular materials affirming the settler innocence, ingenuity, and right to America may be taught. In “No”, her response to the 2003 United States invasion of Iraq, Mvskoke/Creek poet Joy Harjo (2004) writes, “Yes, that was me you saw shaking with bravery, with a government issued rifle on my back. I’m sorry I could not greet you, as you deserved, my relative.” Don’t Native Americans participate in greater rates in the military? asks the young-ish man from Viet Nam. <u><strong>“Indian Country” was/is the term used in Viet Nam, Afghanistan, Iraq by the U.S. military for ‘enemy territory’. </u></strong>The first Black American President said without blinking, “There was a point before folks had left, before we had gotten everybody back on the helicopter and were flying back to base, where they said Geronimo has been killed, and Geronimo was the code name for bin Laden.” Elmer Pratt, Black Panther leader, falsely imprisoned for 27 years, was a Vietnam Veteran, was nicknamed ‘Geronimo’. Geronimo is settler nickname for the Bedonkohe Apache warrior who fought Mexican and then U.S. expansion into Apache tribal lands. The Colt .45 was perfected to kill Indigenous people during the ‘liberation’ of what became the Philippines, but it was first invented for the ‘Indian Wars’ in North America alongside The Hotchkiss Canon- a gattling gun that shot canonballs. <u><strong>The technologies of the permanent settler war are reserviced for foreign wars, including boarding schools, colonial schools, urban schools run by military personnel.</u></strong> It is properly called Indian Country. Ideologies of US settler colonialism directly informed Australian settler colonialism. South African apartheid townships, the kill-zones in what became the Philippine colony, then nation-state, the checkerboarding of Palestinian land with checkpoints, were modeled after U.S. seizures of land and containments of Indian bodies to reservations. The racial science developed in the U.S. (a settler colonial racial science) informed Hitler’s designs on racial purity (“This book is my bible” he said of Madison Grant’s The Passing of the Great Race). The admiration is sometimes mutual, the doctors and administrators of forced sterilizations of black, Native, disabled, poor, and mostly female people - The Sterilization Act accompanied the Racial Integrity Act and the Pocohontas Exception - praised the Nazi eugenics program. Forced sterilizations became illegal in California in 1964. </p>
1AC
null
null
7,038
1,258
59,839
./documents/hspolicy20/SiouxFallsRoosevelt/LuTo/Sioux%20Falls%20Roosevelt-Luckett-Torguson-Aff-Grapevine-Doubles.docx
739,604
A
Grapevine
Doubles
Jesuit RM
panel
1AC - aff 2NR - Framework
hspolicy20/SiouxFallsRoosevelt/LuTo/Sioux%20Falls%20Roosevelt-Luckett-Torguson-Aff-Grapevine-Doubles.docx
null
63,023
LuTo
Sioux Falls Roosevelt LuTo
null
Ja.....
Lu.....
Ry.....
To.....
21,804
SiouxFallsRoosevelt
Sioux Falls Roosevelt
SD
null
1,019
hspolicy20
HS Policy 2020-21
2,020
cx
hs
2
2,081,241
Heg decline causes prolif and unstable nuclear alliances -- that leads to war.
Hayes 18
Peter Hayes, 6-16-2018, [Peter Hayes is Honorary Professor, Center for International Security Studies, Sydney University, Australia and Director, Nautilus Institute in Berkeley, California. His main research interests are nuclear weapons, climate change and energy security, particularly in Northeast Asia.]"Trump and the Interregnum of American Nuclear Hegemony," Taylor & Francis, https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/full/10.1080/25751654.2018.1532525//CHS PK
During a post-hegemonic era nuclear alliances are likely to be replaced by ad hoc nuclear coalitions, aligning and realigning around different congeries of threat and even actual nuclear wars with much higher levels of uncertainty and unpredictability these dynamics are likely to be inconsistent and contradictory the potency of political, military service and corporate interests, may ensure that residual aspects of the formerly hegemonic postures are adhered these states may be forced to adjust and retrench strategically, or start to take their own nuclear risks by making increasingly explicit nuclear threats and deployments against nuclear-armed adversaries Under full-blown American nuclear hegemony, fewer states had nuclear weapons In a nuclear duel, it was clear that only one of two sides could fire first; with nine nuclear weapons states, and conflicts conceivably involving three, four or more of them it will not be evident . In a highly proliferated world states may feel driven to obtain larger nuclear forces configured to fight more than one protracted nuclear war at a time especially in nuclear states torn apart by civil war and post-nuclear attack reconstruction nuclear weapons will be the new normal
nuclear alliances are replaced by ad hoc coalitions, aligning around threat and nuclear wars, with higher unpredictability interests ensure formerly hegemonic postures are adhered these states may or start to take nuclear risks Under American hegemony, fewer states had nuclear weapons states feel driven to obtain larger forces configured to fight more than one war at a time nuclear weapons will be the new normal
During a post-hegemonic era, long-standing nuclear alliances are likely to be replaced by ad hoc nuclear coalitions, aligning and realigning around different congeries of threat and even actual nuclear wars, with much higher levels of uncertainty and unpredictability than was the case in the nuclear hegemonic system. There are a number of ways that this dynamic could play out during the interregnum, and these dynamics are likely to be inconsistent and contradictory. In some instances, the sheer momentum of past policy combined with bureaucratic inertia and the potency of political, military service and corporate interests, may ensure that residual aspects of the formerly hegemonic postures are adhered to even as formal nuclear alliances rupture. Even as they reach for the old anchors, these states may be forced to adjust and retrench strategically, or start to take their own nuclear risks by making increasingly explicit nuclear threats and deployments against nuclear-armed adversaries – as Japan has begun to do with reference to its “technological deterrent” since about 2012.9 This period could last for many years until and when nuclear war breaks out and leads to a post-nuclear war disorder; or a new, post-hegemonic strategic framework is established to manage and/or abolish nuclear threat. Under full-blown American nuclear hegemony, fewer states had nuclear weapons, the major nuclear weapons states entered into legally binding restraints on force levels and they learned from nuclear near-misses to promulgate rules of the road and tacit understandings. The lines drawn during full-blown collisions involving nuclear weapons were stark and concentrated the minds of leaders greatly. In a nuclear duel, it was clear that only one of two sides could fire first; the only question was which one. Now, with nine nuclear weapons states, and conflicts conceivably involving three, four or more of them, no matter how much leaders concentrate, it will not be evident who is aiming at who, who may fire first, and during a volley, who fired first and even who hit whom. In a highly proliferated world, nuclear-armed states may feel driven to obtain larger nuclear forces able to deter multiple adversaries at the same time, sufficient to conduct not only a few nuclear attacks but configured to fight more than one protracted nuclear war at a time, especially in nuclear states torn apart by civil war and post-nuclear attack reconstruction. The first time nuclear weapons are used since 1945 will be shocking, the second time, less so, the third time, the new normal.
2,586
<h4>Heg decline causes prolif and unstable nuclear alliances -- that leads to war.</h4><p>Peter <u><strong>Hayes</u></strong>, 6-16-20<u><strong>18</u></strong>, [Peter Hayes is Honorary Professor, Center for International Security Studies, Sydney University, Australia and Director, Nautilus Institute in Berkeley, California. His main research interests are nuclear weapons, climate change and energy security, particularly in Northeast Asia.]"Trump and the Interregnum of American Nuclear Hegemony," Taylor & Francis, https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/full/10.1080/25751654.2018.1532525//CHS PK</p><p><u><strong>During a post-hegemonic era</u></strong>, long-standing <u><strong><mark>nuclear alliances are</mark> likely to be <mark>replaced by ad hoc</mark> nuclear <mark>coalitions, aligning</mark> and realigning <mark>around</mark> different congeries of <mark>threat and</mark> even actual <mark>nuclear wars</u></strong>, <u><strong>with </mark>much <mark>higher</mark> levels of uncertainty and <mark>unpredictability</u></strong></mark> than was the case in the nuclear hegemonic system. There are a number of ways that this dynamic could play out during the interregnum, and <u><strong>these dynamics are likely to be inconsistent and contradictory</u></strong>. In some instances, the sheer momentum of past policy combined with bureaucratic inertia and <u><strong>the potency of political, military service and corporate <mark>interests</mark>, may <mark>ensure </mark>that residual aspects of the <mark>formerly hegemonic postures are adhered</mark> </u></strong>to even as formal nuclear alliances rupture. Even as they reach for the old anchors, <u><strong><mark>these states may</mark> be forced to adjust and retrench strategically, <mark>or start to take</mark> their own <mark>nuclear risks</mark> by making increasingly explicit nuclear threats and deployments against nuclear-armed adversaries</u></strong> – as Japan has begun to do with reference to its “technological deterrent” since about 2012.9 This period could last for many years until and when nuclear war breaks out and leads to a post-nuclear war disorder; or a new, post-hegemonic strategic framework is established to manage and/or abolish nuclear threat. <u><strong><mark>Under</mark> full-blown <mark>American</mark> nuclear <mark>hegemony, fewer states had nuclear weapons</u></strong></mark>, the major nuclear weapons states entered into legally binding restraints on force levels and they learned from nuclear near-misses to promulgate rules of the road and tacit understandings. The lines drawn during full-blown collisions involving nuclear weapons were stark and concentrated the minds of leaders greatly. <u><strong>In a nuclear duel, it was clear that only one of two sides could fire first;</u></strong> the only question was which one. Now, <u><strong>with nine nuclear weapons states, and conflicts conceivably involving three, four or more of them</u></strong>, no matter how much leaders concentrate, <u><strong>it will not be evident</u></strong> who is aiming at who, who may fire first, and during a volley, who fired first and even who hit whom<u><strong>. In a highly proliferated world</u></strong>, nuclear-armed <u><strong><mark>states</mark> may <mark>feel driven to obtain larger</mark> nuclear <mark>forces</u></strong></mark> able to deter multiple adversaries at the same time, sufficient to conduct not only a few nuclear attacks but <u><strong><mark>configured to fight more than one</mark> protracted nuclear <mark>war at a time</u></strong></mark>, <u><strong>especially in nuclear states torn apart by civil war and post-nuclear attack reconstruction</u></strong>. The first time <u><strong><mark>nuclear weapons</u></strong></mark> are used since 1945 <u><strong><mark>will be</u></strong></mark> shocking, the second time, less so, the third time, <u><strong><mark>the new normal</u></strong></mark>.</p>
null
null
1AC—Advantage: Partisanship
44,573
321
62,014
./documents/hsld20/Aragon/Ab/Aragon-Abraham-Aff-Voices-Round3.docx
853,434
A
Voices
3
Lynbrook AM
Lena Mizrahi
1AC US aff V2 1NC Pyscho K T A Dementia pic Trump Diversionary War DA 1AR T Case The offs 2NR Diversionary War Da 2AR Case
hsld20/Aragon/Ab/Aragon-Abraham-Aff-Voices-Round3.docx
null
72,682
ZaAb
Aragon ZaAb
null
Za.....
Ab.....
null
null
24,414
Aragon
Aragon
CA
null
1,028
hsld20
HS LD 2020-21
2,020
ld
hs
1
2,322,368
New lethal autonomous systems will target nuclear second-strike systems – that causes accidental escalation and preemptive strikes from the US, Russia, and China
Klare 19
Klare 19 [Michael T. Klare is a professor emeritus of peace and world security studies at Hampshire College and senior visiting fellow at the Arms Control Association. This is the second in the “Arms Control Tomorrow” series, in which he considers disruptive emerging technologies and their implications for war-fighting and arms control. This installment provides an assessment of autonomous weapons systems development and prospects, the dangers they pose, and possible strategies for their control. "Autonomous Weapons Systems and the Laws of War." https://www.armscontrol.org/act/2019-03/features/autonomous-weapons-systems-laws-war]
Arms racing behavior is a perennial concern for the great powers, because efforts by competing states to gain a technological advantage over their rivals, or to avoid falling behind, often lead to excessive and destabilizing arms buildups. A race in autonomy poses a particular danger because the consequences of investing machines with increased intelligence and decision-making authority are largely unknown and could prove catastrophic. In their haste to match the presumed progress of likely adversaries states might field robotic weapons with considerable autonomy well before their abilities and limitations have been fully determined, resulting in unintended fatalities or uncontrolled escalation. China, Russia, the U S will deploy increasingly autonomous robotic weapons in the years ahead, policymakers must identify and weigh the potential risks of such deployments. These include not only the potential for accident and unintended escalation, as would be the case with any new weapons that are unleashed on the battlefield, but also a wide array of moral, ethical, and legal concerns arising from the diminishing role of humans in life-and-death decision-making. In war, accidents and mishaps, some potentially catastrophic, are almost inevitable. Another danger arises from the speed with which automated systems operate, along with plans for deploying autonomous weapons systems in coordinated groups, or swarms. The Pentagon envisions a time when large numbers of drone ships and aircraft are released to search for enemy missile-launching submarines and other critical assets, including mobile ballistic missile launchers adversaries rely on those missile systems to serve as an invulnerable second-strike deterrent to a U.S. disarming first strike Should Russia or China ever perceive that swarming U.S. drones threaten the survival of their second-strike systems, those countries could feel pressured to launch their missiles when such swarms are detected, lest they lose their missiles to a feared U.S. first strike Strategies for Control analysts in the arms control and human rights communities, joined by sympathetic diplomats and others, have sought to devise strategies for regulating such systems or banning them entirely. The first and most unequivocal would be the adoption under the CCW of a legally binding international ban on the development, deployment, or use of fully autonomous weapons systems Today, very few truly autonomous robotic weapons are in active combat use Nations are determined to field these weapons quickly lest their competitors outpace them in an arms race in autonomy. Diplomats and policymakers must seize this moment before fully autonomous weapons systems become widely deployed to weigh the advantages of a total ban and consider other measures to ensure they will never be used to commit unlawful acts or trigger catastrophic escalation
Arms racing is perennial for the great powers efforts lead to excessive destabilizing arms buildups. A race in autonomy poses a particular danger investing machines with authority could prove catastrophic. In their haste states field weapons with autonomy well before abilities have been determined, resulting in uncontrolled escalation China, Russia, the U S will deploy autonomous weapons accidents and mishaps are inevitable Another danger arises from the speed along with coordinated groups The Pentagon envisions drone ships released to search for submarines and ballistic missile launchers adversaries rely on those as second-strike deterrent Should Russia or China perceive that swarming U.S. drones threaten second-strike systems, those countries could launch their missiles analysts in the arms control joined diplomats and others to devise strategies for banning them entirely unequivocal would be a legally binding international ban of fully autonomous weapons systems Nations are determined to field weapons quickly policymakers must seize this moment to weigh the advantages of a total ban
Arms racing behavior is a perennial concern for the great powers, because efforts by competing states to gain a technological advantage over their rivals, or to avoid falling behind, often lead to excessive and destabilizing arms buildups. A race in autonomy poses a particular danger because the consequences of investing machines with increased intelligence and decision-making authority are largely unknown and could prove catastrophic. In their haste to match the presumed progress of likely adversaries, states might field robotic weapons with considerable autonomy well before their abilities and limitations have been fully determined, resulting in unintended fatalities or uncontrolled escalation. Supposedly, those risks would be minimized by maintaining some degree of human control over all such machines, but the race to field increasingly capable robotic weapons could result in ever-diminishing oversight. “Despite [the Defense Department’s] insistence that a ‘man in the loop’ capability will always be part of RAS systems,” the CRS noted in 2018, “it is possible if not likely, that the U.S. military could feel compelled to develop…fully autonomous weapon systems in response to comparable enemy ground systems or other advanced threat systems that make any sort of ‘man in the loop’ role impractical.”8 Assessing the Risks Given the likelihood that China, Russia, the United States, and other nations will deploy increasingly autonomous robotic weapons in the years ahead, policymakers must identify and weigh the potential risks of such deployments. These include not only the potential for accident and unintended escalation, as would be the case with any new weapons that are unleashed on the battlefield, but also a wide array of moral, ethical, and legal concerns arising from the diminishing role of humans in life-and-death decision-making. The potential dangers associated with the deployment of AI-empowered robotic weapons begin with the fact that much of the technology involved is new and untested under the conditions of actual combat, where unpredictable outcomes are the norm. For example, it is one thing to test self-driving cars under controlled conditions with human oversight; it is another to let such vehicles loose on busy highways. If that self-driving vehicle is covered with armor, equipped with a gun, and released on a modern battlefield, algorithms can never anticipate all the hazards and mutations of combat, no matter how well “trained” the algorithms governing the vehicle’s actions may be. In war, accidents and mishaps, some potentially catastrophic, are almost inevitable. Extensive testing of AI image-classification algorithms has shown that such systems can easily be fooled by slight deviations from standardized representations—in one experiment, a turtle was repeatedly identified as a rifle9—and are vulnerable to trickery, or “spoofing,” as well as hacking by adversaries. Former Navy Secretary Richard Danzig, who has studied the dangers of employing untested technologies on the battlefield, has been particularly outspoken in cautioning against the premature deployment of AI-empowered weaponry. “Unfortunately, the uncertainties surrounding the use and interaction of new military technologies are not subject to confident calculation or control,” he wrote in 2018.10 This poses obvious challenges because virtually all human ethical and religious systems view the taking of a human life, whether in warfare or not, as a supremely moral act requiring some valid justification. Humans, however imperfect, are expected to abide by this principle, and most societies punish those who fail to do so. Faced with the horrors of war, humans have sought to limit the conduct of belligerents in wartime, aiming to prevent cruel and excessive violence. Beginning with the Hague Convention of 1898 and in subsequent agreements forged in Geneva after World War I, international jurists have devised a range of rules, collectively, the laws of war, proscribing certain behaviors in armed conflict, such as the use of poisonous gas. Following World War II and revelations of the Holocaust, diplomats adopted additional protocols to the Hague and Geneva conventions intended to better define the obligations of belligerents in sparing civilians from the ravages of war, measures generally known as international humanitarian law. So long as humans remain in control of weapons, in theory they can be held accountable under the laws of war and international humanitarian law for any violations committed when using those devices. What happens when a machine makes the decision to take a life and questions arise over the legitimacy of that action? Who is accountable for any crimes found to occur, and how can a chain of responsibility be determined? These questions arise with particular significance regarding two key aspects of international humanitarian law, the requirement for distinction and proportionality in the use of force against hostile groups interspersed with civilian communities. Distinction requires warring parties to discriminate between military and civilian objects and personnel during the course of combat and spare the latter from harm to the greatest extent possible. Proportionality requires militaries to apply no more force than needed to achieve the intended objective, while sparing civilian personnel and property from unnecessary collateral damage.11 These principles pose a particular challenge to fully autonomous weapons systems because they require a capacity to make fine distinctions in the heat of battle. It may be relatively easy in a large tank-on-tank battle, for example, to distinguish military from civilian vehicles; but in many recent conflicts, enemy combatants have armed ordinary pickup trucks and covered them with a tarpaulins, making them almost indistinguishable from civilian vehicles. Perhaps a hardened veteran could spot the difference, but an intelligent robot? Unlikely. Similarly, how does one gauge proportionality when attempting to attack enemy snipers firing from civilian-occupied tenement buildings? For robots, this could prove an insurmountable challenge. Advocates and critics of autonomous weaponry disagree over whether such systems can be equipped with algorithms sufficiently adept to distinguish between targets to satisfy the laws of war. “Humans possess the unique capacity to identify with other human beings and are thus equipped to understand the nuances of unforeseen behavior in ways that machines, which must be programmed in advance, simply cannot,” analysts from Human Rights Watch (HRW) and the International Human Rights Clinic of Harvard Law School wrote in 2016.12 Another danger arises from the speed with which automated systems operate, along with plans for deploying autonomous weapons systems in coordinated groups, or swarms. The Pentagon envisions a time when large numbers of drone ships and aircraft are released to search for enemy missile-launching submarines and other critical assets, including mobile ballistic missile launchers. At present, U.S. adversaries rely on those missile systems to serve as an invulnerable second-strike deterrent to a U.S. disarming first strike. Should Russia or China ever perceive that swarming U.S. drones threaten the survival of their second-strike systems, those countries could feel pressured to launch their missiles when such swarms are detected, lest they lose their missiles to a feared U.S. first strike. Strategies for Control Since it first became evident that strides in AI would permit the deployment of increasingly autonomous weapons systems and that the major powers were seeking to exploit those breakthroughs for military advantage, analysts in the arms control and human rights communities, joined by sympathetic diplomats and others, have sought to devise strategies for regulating such systems or banning them entirely. As part of that effort, parties to the Convention on Certain Conventional Weapons (CCW), a 1980 treaty that restricts or prohibits the use of particular types of weapons that are deemed to cause unnecessary suffering to combatants or to harm civilians indiscriminately, established a group of governmental experts to assess the dangers posed by fully autonomous weapons systems and to consider possible control mechanisms. Some governments also have sought to address these questions independently, while elements of civil society have entered the fray. Out of this process, some clear strategies for limiting these systems have emerged. The first and most unequivocal would be the adoption under the CCW of a legally binding international ban on the development, deployment, or use of fully autonomous weapons systems. Such a ban could come in the form a new CCW protocol, a tool used to address weapon types not envisioned in the original treaty, as has happened with a 1995 ban on blinding laser weapons and a 1996 measure restricting the use of mines, booby traps, and other such devices.13 Two dozen states, backed by civil society groups such as the Campaign to Stop Killer Robots, have called for negotiating an additional CCW protocol banning fully autonomous weapons systems altogether. Autonomous weapons systems and would allow some states to field weapons with dangerous and unpredictable capabilities. Others say a total ban may not be achievable and argue that a nonbinding measure of this sort is the best option available. Yet another approach gaining attention is a concentrated focus on the ethical dimensions of fielding fully autonomous weapons systems. This outlook holds that international law and common standards of ethical practice ordain that only humans possess the moral capacity to justify taking another human’s life and that machines can never be vested with that power. Proponents of this approach point to the Martens clause of the Hague Convention of 1899, also inscribed in Additional Protocol I of the Geneva Conventions, stating that even when not covered by other laws and treaties, civilians and combatants “remain under the protection and authority of the principles of international law derived from established custom, from the principles of humanity and from the dictates of human conscience.” Opponents of fully autonomous weapons systems claim that such weapons, by removing humans from life-and-death decision-making, are inherently contradicting principles of humanity and dictates of human conscience and so should be banned. Reflecting awareness of this issue, the Defense Department has reportedly begun to develop a set of guiding principles for the “safe, ethical, and responsible use” of AI and autonomous weapons systems by the military services. Today, very few truly autonomous robotic weapons are in active combat use, but many countries are developing and testing a wide range of machines possessing high degrees of autonomy. Nations are determined to field these weapons quickly, lest their competitors outpace them in an arms race in autonomy. Diplomats and policymakers must seize this moment before fully autonomous weapons systems become widely deployed to weigh the advantages of a total ban and consider other measures to ensure they will never be used to commit unlawful acts or trigger catastrophic escalation.
11,306
<h4>New <u>lethal autonomous systems</u> will target <u>nuclear second-strike</u> systems – that causes <u>accidental escalation</u> and <u>preemptive strikes</u> from the US, Russia, and China </h4><p><strong>Klare 19</strong> [Michael T. Klare<u> is a professor emeritus of peace and world security studies at Hampshire College and senior visiting fellow at the Arms Control Association. This is the second in the “Arms Control Tomorrow” series, in which he considers disruptive emerging technologies and their implications for war-fighting and arms control. This installment provides an assessment of autonomous weapons systems development and prospects, the dangers they pose, and possible strategies for their control. "Autonomous Weapons Systems and the Laws of War." https://www.armscontrol.org/act/2019-03/features/autonomous-weapons-systems-laws-war]</p><p><strong><mark>Arms racing</strong></mark> behavior <mark>is</mark> a <mark>perennial</mark> concern <mark>for the <strong>great powers</strong></mark>, because <mark>efforts</mark> by competing states to gain a technological advantage over their <strong>rivals</strong>, or to avoid falling behind, often <mark>lead to excessive</mark> and <strong><mark>destabilizing arms buildups</strong>. A race in <strong>autonomy</strong> poses a <strong>particular danger</strong></mark> because the consequences of <mark>investing machines with</mark> increased <strong>intelligence</strong> and <strong>decision-making <mark>authority</u></strong></mark> <u>are largely unknown and <mark>could prove <strong>catastrophic</strong>. In their <strong>haste</strong></mark> to match the presumed progress of likely <strong>adversaries</u></strong>, <u><mark>states</mark> might <mark>field</mark> robotic <mark>weapons with</mark> considerable <strong><mark>autonomy</strong> well before</mark> their <strong><mark>abilities</strong></mark> and <strong>limitations</strong> <mark>have been</mark> fully <strong><mark>determined</strong>, resulting in</mark> <strong>unintended fatalities or <mark>uncontrolled escalation</strong></mark>.</p><p></u>Supposedly, those risks would be minimized by maintaining some degree of human control over all such machines, but the race to field increasingly capable robotic weapons could result in ever-diminishing oversight. “Despite [the Defense Department’s] insistence that a ‘man in the loop’ capability will always be part of RAS systems,” the CRS noted in 2018, “it is possible if not likely, that the U.S. military could feel compelled to develop…fully autonomous weapon systems in response to comparable enemy ground systems or other advanced threat systems that make any sort of ‘man in the loop’ role impractical.”8</p><p>Assessing the Risks</p><p>Given the likelihood that <u><strong><mark>China</strong>, <strong>Russia</strong>, the</u></mark> <u><strong><mark>U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates, and other nations <u><mark>will deploy</mark> increasingly <mark>autonomous</mark> robotic <mark>weapons</mark> in the years ahead, policymakers must identify and weigh the potential risks of such deployments. These include not only the potential for accident and unintended escalation, as would be the case with any new weapons that are unleashed on the battlefield, but also a wide array of moral, ethical, and legal concerns arising from the diminishing role of humans in life-and-death decision-making.</p><p></u>The potential dangers associated with the deployment of AI-empowered robotic weapons begin with the fact that much of the technology involved is new and untested under the conditions of actual combat, where unpredictable outcomes are the norm. For example, it is one thing to test self-driving cars under controlled conditions with human oversight; it is another to let such vehicles loose on busy highways. If that self-driving vehicle is covered with armor, equipped with a gun, and released on a modern battlefield, algorithms can never anticipate all the hazards and mutations of combat, no matter how well “trained” the algorithms governing the vehicle’s actions may be. <u>In war, <strong><mark>accidents and mishaps</strong></mark>, some potentially catastrophic, <mark>are </mark>almost <strong><mark>inevitable</strong></mark>.</p><p></u>Extensive testing of AI image-classification algorithms has shown that such systems can easily be fooled by slight deviations from standardized representations—in one experiment, a turtle was repeatedly identified as</p><p>a rifle9—and are vulnerable to trickery, or “spoofing,” as well as hacking by adversaries.</p><p>Former Navy Secretary Richard Danzig, who has studied the dangers of employing untested technologies on the battlefield, has been particularly outspoken in cautioning against the premature deployment of AI-empowered weaponry. “Unfortunately, the uncertainties surrounding the use and interaction of new military technologies are not subject to confident calculation or control,” he wrote in 2018.10</p><p>This poses obvious challenges because virtually all human ethical and religious systems view the taking of a human life, whether in warfare or not, as a supremely moral act requiring some valid justification. Humans, however imperfect, are expected to abide by this principle, and most societies punish those who fail to do so. Faced with the horrors of war, humans have sought to limit the conduct of belligerents in wartime, aiming to prevent cruel and excessive violence. Beginning with the Hague Convention of 1898 and in subsequent agreements forged in Geneva after World War I, international jurists have devised a range of rules, collectively, the laws of war, proscribing certain behaviors in armed conflict, such as the use of poisonous gas. Following World War II and revelations of the Holocaust, diplomats adopted additional protocols to the Hague and Geneva conventions intended to better define the obligations of belligerents in sparing civilians from the ravages of war, measures generally known as international humanitarian law. So long as humans remain in control of weapons, in theory they can be held accountable under the laws of war and international humanitarian law for any violations committed when using those devices. What happens when a machine makes the decision to take a life and questions arise over the legitimacy of that action? Who is accountable for any crimes found to occur, and how can a chain of responsibility be determined?</p><p>These questions arise with particular significance regarding two key aspects of international humanitarian law, the requirement for distinction and proportionality in the use of force against hostile groups interspersed with civilian communities. Distinction requires warring parties to discriminate between military and civilian objects and personnel during the course of combat and spare the latter from harm to the greatest extent possible. Proportionality requires militaries to apply no more force than needed to achieve the intended objective, while sparing civilian personnel and property from unnecessary collateral damage.11</p><p>These principles pose a particular challenge to fully autonomous weapons systems because they require a capacity to make fine distinctions in the heat of battle. It may be relatively easy in a large tank-on-tank battle, for example, to distinguish military from civilian vehicles; but in many recent conflicts, enemy combatants have armed ordinary pickup trucks and covered them with a tarpaulins, making them almost indistinguishable from civilian vehicles. Perhaps a hardened veteran could spot the difference, but an intelligent robot? Unlikely. Similarly, how does one gauge proportionality when attempting to attack enemy snipers firing from civilian-occupied tenement buildings? For robots, this could prove an insurmountable challenge.</p><p>Advocates and critics of autonomous weaponry disagree over whether such systems can be equipped with algorithms sufficiently adept to distinguish between targets to satisfy the laws of war. “Humans possess the unique capacity to identify with other human beings and are thus equipped to understand the nuances of unforeseen behavior in ways that machines, which must be programmed in advance, simply cannot,” analysts from Human Rights Watch (HRW) and the International Human Rights Clinic of Harvard Law School wrote in 2016.12</p><p><u><mark>Another danger arises from the <strong>speed</strong></mark> with which automated systems <strong>operate</strong>, <mark>along with</mark> plans for deploying autonomous weapons systems in <strong><mark>coordinated groups</strong></mark>, or swarms. <mark>The <strong>Pentagon</strong> envisions</mark> a time when large numbers of <mark>drone ships </mark>and aircraft are <mark>released to search for</mark> enemy missile-launching <strong><mark>submarines</strong> and</mark> other critical assets, including <strong>mobile <mark>ballistic missile launchers</u></strong></mark>. At present, U.S. <u><mark>adversaries rely on those</mark> missile systems to serve <mark>as</mark> an invulnerable <strong><mark>second-strike deterrent</strong></mark> to a U.S. disarming first strike</u>. <u><mark>Should <strong>Russia</strong> or <strong>China</strong></mark> ever <mark>perceive that <strong>swarming U.S. drones</u></strong> <u>threaten</mark> the survival of their <mark>second-strike systems, those countries could</mark> feel pressured to <strong><mark>launch their missiles</strong></mark> when such swarms are detected, lest they lose their missiles to a feared <strong>U.S. first strike</u></strong>.</p><p><u><strong>Strategies for Control</p><p></u></strong>Since it first became evident that strides in AI would permit the deployment of increasingly autonomous weapons systems and that the major powers were seeking to exploit those breakthroughs for military advantage, <u><mark>analysts in the arms control</mark> and human rights communities, <mark>joined</mark> by sympathetic <mark>diplomats and others</mark>, have sought <mark>to devise strategies for</mark> regulating such systems or <strong><mark>banning them entirely</mark>.</p><p></u></strong>As part of that effort, parties to the Convention on Certain Conventional Weapons (CCW), a 1980 treaty that restricts or prohibits the use of particular types of weapons that are deemed to cause unnecessary suffering to combatants or to harm civilians indiscriminately, established a group of governmental experts to assess the dangers posed by fully autonomous weapons systems and to consider possible control mechanisms. Some governments also have sought to address these questions independently, while elements of civil society have entered the fray.</p><p>Out of this process, some clear strategies for limiting these systems have emerged. <u>The first and most <strong><mark>unequivocal</strong> would be</u></mark> <u>the adoption under the CCW of <mark>a legally binding <strong>international ban</u></strong></mark> <u>on the development, deployment, or use <mark>of <strong>fully autonomous weapons systems</u></strong></mark>. Such a ban could come in the form a new CCW protocol, a tool used to address weapon types not envisioned in the original treaty, as has happened with a 1995 ban on blinding laser weapons and a 1996 measure restricting the use of mines, booby traps, and other such devices.13 Two dozen states, backed by civil society groups such as the Campaign to Stop Killer Robots, have called for negotiating an additional CCW protocol banning fully autonomous weapons systems altogether.</p><p>Autonomous weapons systems and would allow some states to field weapons with dangerous and unpredictable capabilities. Others say a total ban may not be achievable and argue that a nonbinding measure of this sort is the best option available.</p><p>Yet another approach gaining attention is a concentrated focus on the ethical dimensions of fielding fully autonomous weapons systems. This outlook holds that international law and common standards of ethical practice ordain that only humans possess the moral capacity to justify taking another human’s life and that machines can never be vested with that power. Proponents of this approach point to the Martens clause of the Hague Convention of 1899, also inscribed in Additional Protocol I of the Geneva Conventions, stating that even when not covered by other laws and treaties, civilians and combatants “remain under the protection and authority of the principles of international law derived from established custom, from the principles of humanity and from the dictates of human conscience.” Opponents of fully autonomous weapons systems claim that such weapons, by removing humans from life-and-death decision-making, are inherently contradicting principles of humanity and dictates of human conscience and so should be banned. Reflecting awareness of this issue, the Defense Department has reportedly begun to develop a set of guiding principles for the “safe, ethical, and responsible use” of AI and autonomous weapons systems by the military services.</p><p><u>Today, very few truly autonomous robotic weapons are in active combat use</u>, but many countries are developing and testing a wide range of machines possessing high degrees of autonomy. <u><mark>Nations are determined to field</mark> these <mark>weapons <strong>quickly</u></strong></mark>, <u>lest their competitors outpace them in an arms race in autonomy. Diplomats and <mark>policymakers must</mark> <strong><mark>seize this moment</strong></mark> before fully autonomous weapons systems become widely deployed <mark>to weigh the advantages of a <strong>total ban</strong></mark> and consider other measures to ensure they will never be used to commit unlawful acts or trigger <strong>catastrophic escalation</u></strong>.</p>
null
null
AC – Cyberwar
1,249,692
559
73,501
./documents/hsld20/Princeton/Ko/Princeton-Kothari-Aff-Cougar%20Classic-Round1.docx
871,547
A
Cougar Classic
1
Michael Stuckert
ZAC DAVIS
AC- cyberwar NC- CP T DA 1ar- all 2nr-cp da 2ar- aff cp da
hsld20/Princeton/Ko/Princeton-Kothari-Aff-Cougar%20Classic-Round1.docx
null
73,671
TaKo
Princeton TaKo
null
Ta.....
Ko.....
null
null
24,686
Princeton
Princeton
NJ
null
1,028
hsld20
HS LD 2020-21
2,020
ld
hs
1
4,386,985
Free movement can save intra-African trade – ratification of the FMP is key
PSC Report 22
PSC Report 22 {The PSC Report is an initiative of the Institute for Security Studies (ISS)} - ("Africa’s prosperity depends on free trade and mobility," ISS Africa, published 10-28-2022, accessed 12-13-2022, https://issafrica.org/pscreport/psc-insights/africas-prosperity-depends-on-free-trade-and-mobility)//marlborough-wr/
Regional integration is key for Africa’s prosperity. To achieve it, policies, systems and practices must reduce barriers to access, facilitate people’s freedom of movement encourage intraregional trade and develop joint strategies. Processes brokered by the African Union supported by the free movement of people are instrumental. AU heads of state adopted two complementary instruments AfCFTA Free Movement Protocol Establishing a continental economic community in which goods, services and people move freely is regarded as important in addressing Africa’s developmental challenges Mobility is thus intimately intertwined with trade. The continent is well on track to achieve the free trade milestone, but free movement of people is lagging. these elements go hand in hand, the pace of ratification and implementation of the two instruments remains asymmetrical. States show more political will for trade.¶ Unlocking Africa’s potential through trade¶ The AfCFTA is anticipated to transform Africa and be a significant driver of economic growth and industrialisation. intra-African exports by the end of 2021 were only 14.4%. the AfCFTA could change this dramatically. AfCFTA could increase exports by 3%, augmenting the value of intra-African trade by between 15% and 25% (US$50 billion and US$70 billion) by 2040. informal cross-border trade is significant and widespread. The value of informal commerce may equal or surpass the value of formal trade for specific goods and countries. informal cross-border trade constituted 7% to 16% of all formal intra-African trade flows. , informal cross-border trade ranges from 30% to 72% of formal trade. a few major regional players continue to dominate intra-African trade. This has led to concerns about the uneven distribution of gains between middle-income countries and smaller economies, particularly the least-developed countries.¶ Migration also plays a crucial role in Africa’s regional integration agenda, by contributing to socio-economic development in countries of both origin and destination. studies definitively show increased bilateral trade between recipient and origin countries due to the presence of migrants in a country. establishing linkages through capital investment, philanthropy, knowledge transfer and entrepreneurship is crucial. The diaspora is, thus, a key resource. regular migration could significantly contribute to the development of host countries by providing them with the experience, knowledge and services they require from both skilled and unskilled labour. the resultant trade imbalance for origin countries could be rectified through remittances and direct investment.¶ Why free movement?¶ Africa can advance economic development through better migration management and governance. For the AU, member states and regional economic communities (RECs) need to formulate policies that use migration for development.¶ While the Free Movement Protocol is a continental agreement, its effective governance and implementation are national and regional. its implementation can help to build resilience in Africa for unanticipated mobility and support the transition to a borderless continent progress on ratifying and implementing the protocol is slow – slower than that for the AfCFTA.
Regional integration is key Processes brokered by the A U supported by free movement are instrumental. Mobility is intertwined with trade. The continent is to achieve free trade but free movement is lagging these elements go hand in hand ratification and implementation remains asymmetrical AfCFTA is to transform Africa and be a driver of growth intra-African exports were only 14.4%. AfCFTA could increase the value by 25% informal trade is widespread Migration plays a crucial role studies definitively show increased bilateral trade investment knowledge transfer and entrepreneurship regular migration significantly contribute to development from labour trade imbalance could be rectified through remittances and investment
Regional integration is key for Africa’s prosperity. To achieve it, policies, systems and practices must be adopted to reduce barriers to access, facilitate people’s freedom of movement, encourage intraregional trade and develop joint strategies. Processes brokered by the African Union (AU) aimed at a single African market for goods and services supported by the free movement of people are instrumental.¶ In 2018, AU heads of state adopted two complementary instruments. The first was the African Continental Free Trade Area (AfCFTA) agreement. The second was the Protocol to the Treaty Establishing the African Economic Community Relating to Free Movement of Persons, Right of Residence and Right of Establishment (Free Movement Protocol).¶ Establishing a continental economic community in which goods, services and people move freely is regarded as important in addressing Africa’s developmental challenges and realising the aspirations of Agenda 2063. Mobility is thus intimately intertwined with trade. Several progressive continental policies strengthen the aims of the AfCFTA and the Free Movement Protocol. These include the Migration Policy Framework for Africa, the Single African Air Transport Market and the AU Strategy for a Better Integrated Border Governance. ¶ The AU hopes that, by 2023, people will be able to move freely among member countries, by, among others, eliminating visa requirements for intra-African travel. A 2023 target is also set for completing the first two phases of the AfCFTA.¶ The continent is well on track to achieve the free trade milestone, but free movement of people is lagging. Despite understanding that these elements go hand in hand, the pace of ratification and implementation of the two instruments remains asymmetrical. States show more political will for trade.¶ Unlocking Africa’s potential through trade¶ The AfCFTA is anticipated to transform Africa and be a significant driver of economic growth and industrialisation. The United Nations Conference on Trade and Development (UNCTAD) estimates that intra-African exports by the end of 2021 were only 14.4%. Both UNCTAD and the UN Economic Commission for Africa (UNECA) believe that the AfCFTA could change this dramatically.¶ UNECA predicts that the AfCFTA could increase exports by 3%, augmenting the value of intra-African trade by between 15% and 25% (US$50 billion and US$70 billion) by 2040. Informal trade is not included in these statistics.¶ In Africa, informal cross-border trade is significant and widespread. The value of informal commerce may equal or surpass the value of formal trade for specific goods and countries. African borders are frequently crossed by unregistered companies and informal traders, especially women, who buy and sell goods throughout the continent. However, accurate data is still lacking.¶ In 2021, UNECA estimates found that informal cross-border trade constituted 7% to 16% of all formal intra-African trade flows. Significantly, between neighbouring countries, informal cross-border trade ranges from 30% to 72% of formal trade. According to UNECA, this has important implications for Africa and collecting data on informal cross-border trade will be key to accurately tracing intracontinental trade flows.¶ For fragile and conflict-affected states, informal cross-border trade is particularly significant as formal trade channels may be adversely affected. The former provides traders with a market outside the fragmented and potentially failing domestic market. However, even as most states are on board for the free trade area, a few major regional players continue to dominate intra-African trade. This has led to concerns about the uneven distribution of gains between middle-income countries and smaller economies, particularly the least-developed countries.¶ Mobility and free trade¶ Migration also plays a crucial role in Africa’s regional integration agenda, by contributing to socio-economic development in countries of both origin and destination. Some studies definitively show increased bilateral trade between recipient and origin countries due to the presence of migrants in a country. It is clear that establishing linkages through capital investment, philanthropy, knowledge transfer and entrepreneurship is crucial. The diaspora is, thus, a key resource.¶ In addition, regular migration could significantly contribute to the development of host countries by providing them with the experience, knowledge and services they require from both skilled and unskilled labour. While the positive impact of migration and trade tends to tilt towards recipient countries, the resultant trade imbalance for origin countries could be rectified through remittances and direct investment.¶ A further dimension is that under the AfCFTA, African countries must give each other progressively better access to services within their markets. In 2018, African member states agreed on five priority services as the starting point for engagement. These are financial services, communication, transport, tourism and business services. By September 2022, initial offers on the trade in services had been received from 43 countries. This means that the continent is on course to finalising this essential element of the process.¶ Why free movement?¶ The AU’s Migration Policy Framework and the African Common Position on Migration and Development articulate clearly that Africa can advance economic development through better migration management and governance. For the AU, member states and regional economic communities (RECs) need to formulate policies that use migration for development.¶ While the Free Movement Protocol is a continental agreement, its effective governance and implementation are national and regional. Already many African countries have participated through RECs in freedom of movement declarations and, thus, are aware of the responsibility that comes with freedom of mobility. For the protocol to be successful, the agreement must be translated and contextualised to take into account domestic realities and the long-term strategy of the continent (and its member states).¶ This includes ways in which its implementation can help to build resilience in Africa for unanticipated mobility and support the transition to a borderless continent. It also extends to providing a framework for policy coherence on the digitalisation of civil registers and helping to meet the long-term aspirations of ‘making Africa a home’. Still, progress on ratifying and implementing the protocol is slow – slower than that for the AfCFTA.
6,587
<h4>Free movement can save intra-African trade – ratification of the FMP is key</h4><p><strong>PSC Report 22<u></strong> {The PSC Report is an initiative of the Institute for Security Studies (ISS)} - ("Africa’s prosperity depends on free trade and mobility," ISS Africa, published 10-28-2022, accessed 12-13-2022, https://issafrica.org/pscreport/psc-insights/africas-prosperity-depends-on-free-trade-and-mobility)//marlborough-wr/</p><p><strong><mark>Regional</mark> <mark>integration</strong></mark> <mark>is</mark> <mark>key</mark> for Africa’s prosperity. To achieve it, policies, systems and practices must</u> be adopted to <u>reduce barriers to access, <strong>facilitate people’s freedom of movement</u></strong>, <u>encourage intraregional trade and develop joint strategies. <mark>Processes brokered by the A</mark>frican <mark>U</mark>nion</u> (AU) aimed at a single African market for goods and services <u><strong><mark>supported</mark> <mark>by</mark> the <mark>free</mark> <mark>movement</mark> of people</strong> <mark>are <strong>instrumental</strong>.</u></mark>¶ In 2018, <u>AU heads of state adopted</u> <u>two complementary instruments</u>. The first was the African Continental Free Trade Area (<u>AfCFTA</u>) agreement. The second was the Protocol to the Treaty Establishing the African Economic Community Relating to Free Movement of Persons, Right of Residence and Right of Establishment (<u>Free Movement Protocol</u>).¶ <u>Establishing a <strong>continental economic community</strong> in which goods, services and people move freely is regarded as important in addressing Africa’s developmental challenges</u> and realising the aspirations of Agenda 2063. <u><strong><mark>Mobility</mark> <mark>is</mark> thus intimately <mark>intertwined</mark> <mark>with</mark> <mark>trade</strong>.</u></mark> Several progressive continental policies strengthen the aims of the AfCFTA and the Free Movement Protocol. These include the Migration Policy Framework for Africa, the Single African Air Transport Market and the AU Strategy for a Better Integrated Border Governance. ¶ The AU hopes that, by 2023, people will be able to move freely among member countries, by, among others, eliminating visa requirements for intra-African travel. A 2023 target is also set for completing the first two phases of the AfCFTA.¶ <u><mark>The</mark> <mark>continent</mark> <mark>is</mark> well on track <mark>to</mark> <mark>achieve</mark> the <mark>free trade</mark> milestone, <mark>but <strong>free movement</mark> of people <mark>is lagging</strong></mark>.</u> Despite understanding that <u><strong><mark>these</mark> <mark>elements</mark> <mark>go hand in hand</strong></mark>, the pace of <mark>ratification</mark> <mark>and</mark> <mark>implementation</mark> of the two instruments <mark>remains</mark> <strong><mark>asymmetrical</strong></mark>. States show more political will for trade.¶ <strong>Unlocking Africa’s potential through trade¶ </strong>The <mark>AfCFTA</mark> <mark>is</mark> anticipated <mark>to transform Africa</mark> <mark>and</mark> <mark>be</mark> <mark>a</mark> significant <mark>driver</mark> <mark>of</mark> economic <mark>growth</mark> and industrialisation.</u> The United Nations Conference on Trade and Development (UNCTAD) estimates that <u><mark>intra-African exports</mark> by the end of 2021 <mark>were only 14.4%.</u></mark> Both UNCTAD and the UN Economic Commission for Africa (UNECA) believe that <u>the AfCFTA could change this dramatically.</u>¶ UNECA predicts that the <u><mark>AfCFTA</mark> <mark>could</mark> <mark>increase</mark> exports by 3%, augmenting <mark>the</mark> <mark>value</mark> of intra-African trade <mark>by</mark> between 15% and <mark>25%</mark> (US$50 billion and US$70 billion) by 2040.</u> Informal trade is not included in these statistics.¶ In Africa, <u><mark>informal</mark> cross-border <mark>trade</mark> <mark>is</mark> <strong>significant and <mark>widespread</strong></mark>. The value of informal commerce may equal or surpass the value of formal trade for specific goods and countries.</u> African borders are frequently crossed by unregistered companies and informal traders, especially women, who buy and sell goods throughout the continent. However, accurate data is still lacking.¶ In 2021, UNECA estimates found that <u>informal cross-border trade constituted 7% to 16% of all formal intra-African trade flows.</u> Significantly, between neighbouring countries<u>, informal cross-border trade ranges from 30% to 72% of formal trade.</u> According to UNECA, this has important implications for Africa and collecting data on informal cross-border trade will be key to accurately tracing intracontinental trade flows.¶ For fragile and conflict-affected states, informal cross-border trade is particularly significant as formal trade channels may be adversely affected. The former provides traders with a market outside the fragmented and potentially failing domestic market. However, even as most states are on board for the free trade area, <u>a few major regional players continue to dominate intra-African trade. This has led to concerns about the <strong>uneven distribution of gains</strong> between middle-income countries and smaller economies, particularly the least-developed countries.¶ </u>Mobility and free trade¶ <u><strong><mark>Migration</mark> also <mark>plays a crucial role</strong></mark> in Africa’s regional integration agenda, by contributing to <strong>socio-economic development</strong> in countries of both origin and destination.</u> Some <u><mark>studies</mark> <mark>definitively</mark> <mark>show</mark> <strong><mark>increased bilateral trade</strong></mark> between recipient and origin countries due to the presence of migrants in a country.</u> It is clear that <u>establishing <strong>linkages through capital <mark>investment</mark>, philanthropy, <mark>knowledge transfer and entrepreneurship</strong></mark> is crucial. The diaspora is, thus, a key resource.</u>¶ In addition, <u><mark>regular</mark> <mark>migration</mark> could <strong><mark>significantly</mark> <mark>contribute</mark> <mark>to</mark> the <mark>development</mark> of host countries</strong> by providing them with the experience, knowledge and services they require <mark>from</mark> both skilled and unskilled <mark>labour</mark>. </u>While the positive impact of migration and trade tends to tilt towards recipient countries, <u>the resultant <mark>trade</mark> <mark>imbalance</mark> for origin countries <mark>could be <strong>rectified through remittances and </mark>direct <mark>investment</mark>.¶ </u></strong>A further dimension is that under the AfCFTA, African countries must give each other progressively better access to services within their markets. In 2018, African member states agreed on five priority services as the starting point for engagement. These are financial services, communication, transport, tourism and business services. By September 2022, initial offers on the trade in services had been received from 43 countries. This means that the continent is on course to finalising this essential element of the process.¶ <u>Why free movement?¶ </u>The AU’s Migration Policy Framework and the African Common Position on Migration and Development articulate clearly that <u>Africa can advance economic development through better migration management and governance. For the AU, member states and regional economic communities (RECs) need to <strong>formulate policies that use migration for development.</strong>¶ While the Free Movement Protocol is a continental agreement, its <strong>effective governance and implementation are national and regional</strong>.</u> Already many African countries have participated through RECs in freedom of movement declarations and, thus, are aware of the responsibility that comes with freedom of mobility. For the protocol to be successful, the agreement must be translated and contextualised to take into account domestic realities and the long-term strategy of the continent (and its member states).¶ This includes ways in which <u>its implementation can help to build resilience in Africa for unanticipated mobility and support the transition to a borderless continent</u>. It also extends to providing a framework for policy coherence on the digitalisation of civil registers and helping to meet the long-term aspirations of ‘making Africa a home’. Still, <u>progress on ratifying and implementing the protocol is slow – slower than that for the AfCFTA.</p></u>
Middle School AC
Advantage 1: FMP Boosts the Economy
null
1,699,034
435
165,588
./documents/hsld22/Marlborough/ElPi/Marlborough-ElPi-Aff-Marlborough-MSNovice-Invitational-Round-2.docx
985,446
A
Marlborough MS/Novice Invitational
2
Modern Brain CZ
Phumchun, Kitiny
AC: boosts econ Nc: meat consumption rise, terrorism
hsld22/Marlborough/ElPi/Marlborough-ElPi-Aff-Marlborough-MSNovice-Invitational-Round-2.docx
2023-03-04 20:41:03
85,980
ElPi
Marlborough ElPi
null
El.....
Pi.....
null
null
26,925
Marlborough
Marlborough
CA
null
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
3,058,000
No risk of Russia war---neither side will escalate
Tsygankov 16
Andrei Tsygankov 16, Professor at the Departments of Political Science and International Relations at San Francisco State University, PhD from USC, “5 reasons why the threat of a global war involving Russia is overstated,” Feb 19 2016, http://www.russia-direct.org/opinion/5-reasons-why-threat-great-power-war-involving-russia-overstated
Experts and politicians are warning of high likelihood of a military conflict – possibly a nuclear one – between Russia and the U.S. or NATO In the West, many argue the dangers associated with a “resurgent” Russia and tensions have been growing since the Ukraine crisis possible military conflict with Istanbul and alleged preparations to invade the Baltic States alarmist views and arguments are misplaced because they underestimate the dangers of the Cold War and overestimate those of today’s world whatever the rhetoric, major powers are not inclined towards risky behavior when their core interests are at stake. This concerns not only the nuclear superpowers, but also Turkey. The prospect of confronting Russia's military should give pause even to Erdogan NATO has been careful to not be drawn into highly provocative actions, whether responding to Russia seizing the Pristina Airport in June 1999, getting involved on Georgia’s side or providing support for Ukraine. Unless Russia is the clear and proven aggressor, NATO is unlikely to begin World War III. Russia remains a defensive power aware of its responsibility for maintaining international stability. Moscow wants to work with major powers, not against them the U S has important interests to prevent regional conflicts from escalating U.S. military and diplomatic resources are sufficient to restrain key regional players proxy wars are happening, but they are unlikely to escalate Despite the dangers the world contains a number of important underappreciated, checks threat talk may be a way to pressure the opponent into concessions rather than to signal real intentions. When such pressures do not bring expected results rhetoric of war subsides Then a dialogue begins. increasing frequency of exchanges between Obama and Putin including phone conversation following the Munich conference - suggest recognition that the record of pressuring has been mixed at best.
alarmist views are misplaced because the dangers overestimate those of today’s world NATO has been careful to not be drawn in Russia remains a defensive power aware of responsibility for stability U S has interests to restrain regional players the world contains underappreciated, checks threat talk may be a way to pressure the opponent dialogue begins exchanges between Obama and Putin suggest recognition
The contemporary discussion of security interactions among major powers is depressing to participants and observers alike. Experts and politicians are warning us of an increasingly high likelihood of a military conflict – possibly a nuclear one – between Russia, on the one hand, and the U.S. or NATO, on the other.¶ In the West, many argue the dangers associated with a “resurgent” Russia and vow to defend themselves from Russian President Vladimir Putin’s “aggressive” actions in Eastern Europe and the Middle East. Last month, U.S. Defense Secretary Ash Carter accused Russia of threatening the world order and starkly warned: “Make no mistake, the United States will defend our interests, our allies, the principled international order, and the positive future it affords us all.”¶ The tensions have been growing and have become especially high since the 2014 Ukraine crisis. Russian military flights over the Baltic and Black Sea in response to NATO’s active buildup on Russia’s European borders has done little to calm these fears. The Turkish decision to shoot down a Russian warplane by claiming violation of its airspace in November 2015 revived the discussion of Moscow’s possible military conflict with Istanbul and NATO, of which Turkey is a member. More recently, the hype has been over the Kremlin’s alleged preparations to invade the Baltic States and the West’s need to respond.¶ In Russia, these threats and discussions are taken seriously, and the responsibility for these security tensions has been squarely placed on the Western powers. The frequently repeated charges are that the West and NATO have encircled Russia with military bases and refused to recognize Moscow’s global interests. Russian media have actively discussed the U.S. National Security Archive’s Cold War documents on a nuclear attack against Russia and China declassified on Dec. 22, 2015.¶ Last week, while attending the Munich Security Conference, Prime Minister Dmitry Medvedev compared the contemporary security environment with the one that led to the Cuban Missile Crisis and reminded the audience of U.S. President John F. Kennedy’s words that “foreign policy can kill us."¶ In the meantime, contradicting Medvedev, Russian experts often bemoan the fact that the Cold War was far more predictable and less dangerous than today’s multipolar world. What many have initially viewed as a generally positive transition from the U.S. “diktat” is now presented as leading toward a great power war.¶ This increasingly apocalyptic mood on both sides reflects a growing international instability and breakdown of important communication channels between Russia and the West. Since the beginning of Ukraine crisis and up until the G20 meeting in Antalya in December 2015, the two sides have barely interacted. Appalled by Russia’s annexation of Crimea and support for Ukrainian separatists, Western leaders pursued policies of sanctions and isolation, whereas the indignant Kremlin has sought to demonstrate its indifference toward such policies.¶ Only since Antalya have Putin and U.S. President Barack Obama resumed their attempts to regularly discuss issues of importance. Western and Russia military, too, severed their contacts although the two sides have recently begun to coordinate their actions in the Syrian airspace. The aforementioned alarmist views and arguments are misplaced because they underestimate the dangers of the Cold War and overestimate those of today’s world.¶ Despite some attempts to present the Cold War as generally stable, predictable, and peaceful, this is not the time to feel nostalgic about it. Multiple crises from Berlin to Cuba and Afghanistan extended across much of the Cold War era. State propaganda on both sides was reinforced by an intense ideological confrontation accompanied by drills and necessary preparations for a nuclear war.¶ The Oscar-nominated film “Bridge of Spies” directed by Steven Spielberg reproduces some of that hysterical atmosphere in the United States where the public was mobilized for any actions in support of the government. In the Soviet Union it was no different. For the world outside the West and the U.S.S.R., this was not a peaceful, but rather an increasingly chaotic and violent time – the conclusion well documented by scholars of the Third World.¶ Why today's world is less dangerous than the Cold War¶ Today’s world, while threatening and uncertain, is hardly more dangerous than the Cold War, for the following reasons.¶ First, whatever the rhetoric, major powers are not inclined towards risky behavior when their core interests are at stake. This concerns not only the nuclear superpowers, but also countries such as Turkey. The prospect of confronting Russia's overwhelmingly superior military should give pause even to someone as hot-tempered as Turkish President Tayyip Erdogan. Even if Erdogan wanted to pit Russia against NATO, it wouldn’t work.¶ So far, NATO has been careful to not be drawn into highly provocative actions, whether it is by responding to Russia seizing the Pristina International Airport in June 1999, getting involved on Georgia’s side during the military conflict in August 2008 or by providing lethal military assistance and support for Ukraine. Unless Russia is the clear and proven aggressor, NATO is unlikely to support Turkey and begin World War III.¶ Second, Russia remains a defensive power aware of its responsibility for maintaining international stability. Moscow wants to work with major powers, not against them. Its insistence on Western recognition of Russia’s interests must not be construed as a drive to destroy the foundations of the international order, such as sovereignty, multilateralism, and arms control.¶ Third, the United States has important interests to prevent regional conflicts from escalating or becoming trans-regional. Although its relative military capabilities are not where they were ten years ago, the U.S. military and diplomatic resources are sufficient to restrain key regional players in any part of the world. Given the power rivalry across several regions, proxy wars are possible and indeed are happening, but they are unlikely to escalate.¶ Fourth, unlike the Cold War era, the contemporary world has no rigid alliance structure. The so-called Russia-China-Iran axis is hardly more than a figment of the imagination by American neoconservatives and some Russia conspiracy-minded thinkers. The world remains a space in which international coalitions overlap and are mostly formed on an ad hoc basis.¶ Fifth, with the exception of the Islamic State of Iraq and the Greater Syria (ISIS), there is no fundamental conflict of values and ideologies. Despite the efforts to present as incompatible the so-called “traditional” and “Western” values by Russia or “democracy” to “autocracy” by the United States and Europe, the world majority does not think that this cultural divide is worth fighting for.¶ Despite the dangers of the world we live in, it contains a number of important, even underappreciated, checks on great powers’ militarism. The threat talk coming from politicians is often deceiving. Such talk may be a way to pressure the opponent into various political and military concessions rather than to signal real intentions. When such pressures do not bring expected results, the rhetoric of war and isolation subsides.¶ Then a dialogue begins. Perhaps, the increasing frequency of exchanges between Obama and Putin since December 2015 - including their recent phone conversation following the Munich conference - suggest a growing recognition that the record of pressuring Russia has been mixed at best.
7,653
<h4>No risk of Russia war---neither side will escalate</h4><p>Andrei <strong>Tsygankov 16<u></strong>, Professor at the Departments of Political Science and International Relations at San Francisco State University, PhD from USC, “5 reasons why the threat of a global war involving Russia is overstated,” Feb 19 2016, http://www.russia-direct.org/opinion/5-reasons-why-threat-great-power-war-involving-russia-overstated</p><p></u>The contemporary discussion of security interactions among major powers is depressing to participants and observers alike. <u>Experts and politicians are warning</u> us <u>of</u> an increasingly <u><strong>high likelihood of a military conflict – possibly</strong> a <strong>nuclear</strong> one – between Russia</u>, on the one hand, <u>and the U.S. or NATO</u>, on the other.¶ <u>In the West, many argue the dangers associated with a “resurgent” Russia and</u> vow to defend themselves from Russian President Vladimir Putin’s “aggressive” actions in Eastern Europe and the Middle East. Last month, U.S. Defense Secretary Ash Carter accused Russia of threatening the world order and starkly warned: “Make no mistake, the United States will defend our interests, our allies, the principled international order, and the positive future it affords us all.”¶ The <u>tensions have been growing</u> and have become especially high <u>since the</u> 2014 <u>Ukraine crisis</u>. Russian military flights over the Baltic and Black Sea in response to NATO’s active buildup on Russia’s European borders has done little to calm these fears. The Turkish decision to shoot down a Russian warplane by claiming violation of its airspace in November 2015 revived the discussion of Moscow’s <u>possible military conflict with Istanbul and</u> NATO, of which Turkey is a member. More recently, the hype has been over the Kremlin’s <u><strong>alleged preparations to invade</strong> the Baltic States</u> and the West’s need to respond.¶ In Russia, these threats and discussions are taken seriously, and the responsibility for these security tensions has been squarely placed on the Western powers. The frequently repeated charges are that the West and NATO have encircled Russia with military bases and refused to recognize Moscow’s global interests. Russian media have actively discussed the U.S. National Security Archive’s Cold War documents on a nuclear attack against Russia and China declassified on Dec. 22, 2015.¶ Last week, while attending the Munich Security Conference, Prime Minister Dmitry Medvedev compared the contemporary security environment with the one that led to the Cuban Missile Crisis and reminded the audience of U.S. President John F. Kennedy’s words that “foreign policy can kill us."¶ In the meantime, contradicting Medvedev, Russian experts often bemoan the fact that the Cold War was far more predictable and less dangerous than today’s multipolar world. What many have initially viewed as a generally positive transition from the U.S. “diktat” is now presented as leading toward a great power war.¶ This increasingly apocalyptic mood on both sides reflects a growing international instability and breakdown of important communication channels between Russia and the West. Since the beginning of Ukraine crisis and up until the G20 meeting in Antalya in December 2015, the two sides have barely interacted. Appalled by Russia’s annexation of Crimea and support for Ukrainian separatists, Western leaders pursued policies of sanctions and isolation, whereas the indignant Kremlin has sought to demonstrate its indifference toward such policies.¶ Only since Antalya have Putin and U.S. President Barack Obama resumed their attempts to regularly discuss issues of importance. Western and Russia military, too, severed their contacts although the two sides have recently begun to coordinate their actions in the Syrian airspace. The aforementioned <u><mark>alarmist views</mark> and arguments <mark>are <strong>misplaced</u></strong> <u>because </mark>they underestimate <mark>the dangers</mark> of the Cold War and <strong><mark>overestimate those of today’s world</u></strong></mark>.¶ Despite some attempts to present the Cold War as generally stable, predictable, and peaceful, this is not the time to feel nostalgic about it. Multiple crises from Berlin to Cuba and Afghanistan extended across much of the Cold War era. State propaganda on both sides was reinforced by an intense ideological confrontation accompanied by drills and necessary preparations for a nuclear war.¶ The Oscar-nominated film “Bridge of Spies” directed by Steven Spielberg reproduces some of that hysterical atmosphere in the United States where the public was mobilized for any actions in support of the government. In the Soviet Union it was no different. For the world outside the West and the U.S.S.R., this was not a peaceful, but rather an increasingly chaotic and violent time – the conclusion well documented by scholars of the Third World.¶ Why today's world is less dangerous than the Cold War¶ Today’s world, while threatening and uncertain, is hardly more dangerous than the Cold War, for the following reasons.¶ First, <u>whatever the rhetoric, major powers are not inclined towards risky behavior when their core interests are at stake. This concerns not only the nuclear superpowers, but also</u> countries such as <u>Turkey. The prospect of confronting Russia's</u> overwhelmingly superior <u>military should give pause even to</u> someone as hot-tempered as Turkish President Tayyip <u>Erdogan</u>. Even if Erdogan wanted to pit Russia against NATO, it wouldn’t work.¶ So far, <u><mark>NATO has been <strong>careful to not be drawn in</mark>to highly provocative actions</strong>, whether</u> it is by <u>responding to Russia seizing the Pristina</u> International <u>Airport in June 1999, getting involved on Georgia’s side</u> during the military conflict in August 2008 <u>or</u> by <u>providing</u> lethal military assistance and <u>support for Ukraine. Unless Russia is the clear and proven aggressor, NATO is unlikely to</u> support Turkey and <u><strong>begin World War III</strong>.</u>¶ Second, <u><mark>Russia <strong>remains a defensive power</u></strong> <u>aware of </mark>its <mark>responsibility for</mark> maintaining international <mark>stability</mark>. Moscow wants to work with major powers, not against them</u>. Its insistence on Western recognition of Russia’s interests must not be construed as a drive to destroy the foundations of the international order, such as sovereignty, multilateralism, and arms control.¶ Third, <u>the</u> <u><strong><mark>U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates <u><mark>has</mark> important <mark>interests to</u> <u></mark>prevent regional conflicts from escalating</u> or becoming trans-regional. Although its relative military capabilities are not where they were ten years ago, the <u>U.S. military and diplomatic resources are sufficient to</u> <u><strong><mark>restrain</mark> key <mark>regional players</u></strong> </mark>in any part of the world. Given the power rivalry across several regions, <u>proxy wars are</u> possible and indeed are <u>happening, but they are <strong>unlikely to escalate</u></strong>.¶ Fourth, unlike the Cold War era, the contemporary world has no rigid alliance structure. The so-called Russia-China-Iran axis is hardly more than a figment of the imagination by American neoconservatives and some Russia conspiracy-minded thinkers. The world remains a space in which international coalitions overlap and are mostly formed on an ad hoc basis.¶ Fifth, with the exception of the Islamic State of Iraq and the Greater Syria (ISIS), there is no fundamental conflict of values and ideologies. Despite the efforts to present as incompatible the so-called “traditional” and “Western” values by Russia or “democracy” to “autocracy” by the United States and Europe, the world majority does not think that this cultural divide is worth fighting for.¶ <u>Despite the dangers</u> of <u><mark>the world</u></mark> we live in, it <u><mark>contains</mark> a number of important</u>, even <u><strong><mark>underappreciated</strong>, checks</u></mark> on great powers’ militarism. The <u><mark>threat talk</u></mark> coming from politicians is often deceiving. Such talk <u><mark>may be a way to <strong>pressure the opponent</strong></mark> into</u> various political and military <u>concessions rather than to signal real intentions. When such pressures do not bring expected results</u>, the <u>rhetoric of war</u> and isolation <u>subsides</u>.¶ <u><strong>Then a <mark>dialogue begins</mark>.</u></strong> Perhaps, the <u><strong>increasing</strong> frequency of <strong><mark>exchanges between Obama and Putin</u></strong></mark> since December 2015 - <u>including</u> their recent <u>phone conversation following the Munich conference -</u> <u><mark>suggest</u></mark> a growing <u><mark>recognition </mark>that the record of pressuring</u> Russia <u>has been mixed at best.</p></u>
1NC Doubles vs. Northwestern GY
PGS Deterrence
1NC—AT: Russia
12,970
589
99,937
./documents/ndtceda18/Georgia/RaAg/Georgia-Ramanan-Agrawal-Neg-Kentucky-Quarters.docx
603,941
N
Kentucky
Quarters
Northwestern JW
T Leburu, T Rebrovik, T Glinecki
1AC Operational NFU Ambiguity PGS Deterrence Good 1NC T Vagueness CP ESR CP Middle East PIC DA War Powers DA Japan Prolif DA Midterms TURN TNW Good TURN PGS Bad 2NR DA Midterms CP ESR
ndtceda18/Georgia/RaAg/Georgia-Ramanan-Agrawal-Neg-Kentucky-Quarters.docx
null
51,342
RaAg
Georgia RaAg
null
Ad.....
Ra.....
Sw.....
Ag.....
19,184
Georgia
Georgia
null
null
1,008
ndtceda18
NDT/CEDA 2018-19
2,018
cx
college
2
1,833,101
The best studies confirm our impact – err on the side of a consensus of empirical research – our evidence assumes every skeptic.
Brooks & Wohlforth 16
Stephen Brooks & William Wohlforth 16. William, Daniel Webster Professor in the Department of Government at Dartmouth College. Stephen Brooks, Ph. D in Political Science from Yale, Associate Professor of Government at Dartmouth College, Senior Fellow at the Belfer Center for Science and International Affairs at Harvard University. Page 103-108
Consistency with influential relevant theories lends credence to the expectation that US security commitments actually can shape the strategic environment as deep engagement presupposes to model the strategy’s expected effects we had to simplify things by selecting two mechanisms assurance and deterrence and examining their effects independently, thus missing potentially powerful positive interactions between them. major bodies of evidence are most important empirical findings and regionally focused research General Patterns of Evidence Three key questions about US security provision have received the most extensive analysis. First, do alliances such as those sustained by the United States actually deter war and increase security? Second, does such security provision actually hinder nuclear proliferation? And third, does limiting proliferation actually increase security? The determinants of deterrence success and failure have attracted case study tests deterrence is much harder in practice than in theory Many quantitative findings are mutually contradictory or are clearly not relevant to extended deterrence. But some relevant results receive broad support: Alliances have a deterrent effect In a study spanning two centuries Johnson and Leeds found “support for the hypothesis that defensive alliances deter the initiation of disputes defensive alliances lower the probability of international conflict and are thus a good policy option for states seeking to maintain peace Fuhrmann similarly find that formal defense pacts with nuclear states The overall balance of military forces does not appear to influence deterrence; the local balance of military forces in the specific theater in which deterrence is actually practiced, however, is key Forward- deployed troops enhance the deterrent effect Strong mutual interests and ties enhance deterrence Case studies strongly ratify the theoretical expectation that it is easier to defend a given status quo than to challenge it forcefully compellence is extremely hard. The most important finding is that alliances with nuclear- armed allies like the United States actually work in deterring conflict selection bias works against it The United States is more inclined to offer alliance rela- tionships in settings where the probability of military conflicts is higher than average The fact that alliances work to deter conflict in precisely the situations where deterrence is likely to be especially hard is noteworthy. the United States is interested in deterring military challenges , relying only on latent military capabilities in the US homeland is likely to be far less effective than having an overseas military posture forward deterrence posture is strongly appealing because defending a given status quo is far cheaper than overturning it, and, once a favorable status quo is successfully overturned, restoring the status quo ante can be expected to be fearsomely costly Recognizing the significance of these findings clearly casts doubt on the wait on the sidelines and decide whether to intervene later” approach favored by retrenchment proponents Fear that nuclear proliferation might deter [US leaders] from using military intervention to pursue their interests, reduce the effectiveness of their coercive diplomacy, trigger regional instability, undermine their alliance structures, dissipate their strategic attention, and set off further nuclear proliferation within their sphere of influence also notable are the enhanced prospects of nuclear accidents and the greater risk of leakage of nuclear material to terrorists Do security ties serve to contain t nuclear weapons findings are decidedly mixed. Alliance relationships are just one piece of this complex puzzle empirical studies face the same selection bias problem just discussed alliance guarantees might be offered to states actively considering the nuclear option precisely in order to try to forestall that decision the most relevant findings that emerge from this literature are The most recent statistical analysis concludes that “security guarantees significantly reduce proliferation proclivity states with such guarantees are less likely to export sensitive nuclear material and technology Case study research underscores that the complexity of motivations for acquiring nuclear weapons cannot be reduced to security Multiple independently conceived and executed recent case studies nonetheless reveal that security alliances help explain numerous allied decisions not to proliferate even when security is not always the main driver of leaders’ interest States whose security goals are subsumed by their sponsors’ own aims have never acquired the bomb This finding highlights the role of U.S. security commitments in stymieing nuclear proliferation .S. protégés will only seek the bomb if they doubt U.S. protection Multiple independently case research projects further unpack the conditions that decrease the likelihood of allied proliferation, centering on the credibility of the alliance commitment. in cases of prevention failure, the alliances allow the patron to influence the ally’s nuclear program subsequently, decreasing further proliferation risks Security alliances lower the likelihood of proliferation cascades many predicted cascades did not occur. security provision, mainly by the United States, is a key reason why The most comprehensive statistical analysis finds that states are more likely to proliferate in response to neighbors when three conditions are met there is an intense security rivalry between the two countries the proliferating state does not have a security guarantee from a nuclear- armed patron and the potential proliferator has the industrial and technical capacity to launch an indigenous program the spread of nuclear weapons decelerated with the end of the Cold War Their research, as well as that of scores of scholars using multiple methods and representing many contrasting theoretical perspectives shows that US security guarantees and the counter- proliferation policy deep engagement allows are a big part of the reason why some of the same realist precepts that generate the theoretical prediction that retrenchment would increase demand for nuclear weapons also suggest that proliferation might increase security nuclear optimists like Waltz contend that deterrence essentially solves the security problem for all nuclear- armed states largely eliminating the direct use of force US retrenchment might generate an initial decrease in security followed by an increase as insecure states acquire nuclear capabilities ultimately leaving no net effect on international security This perspective is countered by nuclear pessimists they see major security downsides from new nuclear states. Copious research casts doubt on the expectation that governments can be relied upon to create secure and controlled nuclear forces. The more nuclear states there are, the higher the probability that the organizational, psychological, and civil- military pathologies Sagan identifies will turn an episode like one of the numerous “near misses” he uncovers One day a warning system will fail an official will panic or a terrorist attack will be misconstrued, and the missiles will fly. powerful reasons to question the assessment of proliferation optimists also emerge even if one assumes, as they do, that states are rational and seek only to maximize their security nuclear deterrence can only work by raising the risk of nuclear war. For deterrence to be credible there has to be a nonzero chance of nuclear use If nuclear use is impossible, deterrence cannot be credible every nuclear deterrence relationship depends on some probability The more such relationships there are the greater the risk of nuclear war Nuclear crisis bargaining is about a “competition in risk taking Kroenig counts some twenty cases in which states ran real risks of nuclear war in order to prevail in crises , “By asking whether states can be deterred or not … proliferation optimists are asking the wrong question. The right question to ask is: what risk of nuclear war is a specific state willing to run against a particular opponent in a given crisis The more nuclear- armed states there are, the more the opportunities for such risk- taking and the greater the probability of nuclear use
to model effects we simplify assurance and deterrence examining effects independently miss powerful interactions deterrence attracted tests findings are contradictory some results receive broad support Alliances have a deterrent In a study spanning two centuries Leeds found “support for defensive alliances lower conflict military forces in the theater which deterrence is practiced is key Forward- deployed troops enhance the effect studies ratify the expectation it is easier to defend than challenge alliances with nuclear allies work selection bias” works against it. The U S is inclined to offer in settings where probability of conflict is higher relying on latent capabilities in the homeland is far less effective forward deterrence is appealing because defending is cheaper than overturning Recognizing these findings casts doubt on the wait on the sidelines and decide to intervene later” approach Do security ties contain nuclear weapons findings are mixed the most relevant are statistical analysis concludes security guarantees reduce proliferation states with guarantees are less likely to export material and tech Multiple independent studies reveal security alliances explain decisions not to proliferate protégés only seek the bomb if they doubt U.S. protection research center on credibility of the alliance commitment alliances lower proliferation cascades provision by the U S , is a key reason The most comprehensive analysis finds states proliferate when there is an intense rivalry the state does not have a security guarantee and capacity spread decelerated with the end of the Cold War scores of scholars using multiple methods representing contrasting perspectives, shows US guarantees and deep engagement are why pessimists see major downsides research casts doubt governments can be relied upon warning system fail an official will panic attack will be misconstrued missiles will fly deterrence only work by raising the risk of nuclear war If use is impossible, deterrence cannot be credible The more the greater the risk crisis is a “competition in risk taking The more armed states the greater the probability
Consistency with influential relevant theories lends credence to the expectation that US security commitments actually can shape the strategic environment as deep engagement presupposes. But it is far from conclusive. Not all analysts endorse the theories we discussed in chapter 5. These theories make strong assumptions that states generally act rationally and focus primarily on security. Allowing misperceptions, emotions, domestic politics, desire for status, or concern for honor into the picture might alter the verdict on the strategy’s net expected effects. And to model the strategy’s expected effects we had to simplify things by selecting two mechanisms— assurance and deterrence— and examining their effects independently, thus missing potentially powerful positive interactions between them. This chapter moves beyond theory to examine patterns of evidence. If the theoretical arguments about the security effects of deep engagement are right, what sort of evidence should we see? Two major bodies of evidence are most important: general empirical findings concerning the strategy’s key mechanisms and regionally focused research. General Patterns of Evidence Three key questions about US security provision have received the most extensive analysis. First, do alliances such as those sustained by the United States actually deter war and increase security? Second, does such security provision actually hinder nuclear proliferation? And third, does limiting proliferation actually increase security? Deterrence Effectiveness The determinants of deterrence success and failure have attracted scores of quantitative and case study tests. Much of the case study work yields a cautionary finding: that deterrence is much harder in practice than in theory, because standard models assume away the complexities of human psychology and domestic politics that tend to make some states hard to deter and might cause deterrence policies to backfire. 1 Many quantitative findings, mean- while, are mutually contradictory or are clearly not relevant to extended deterrence. But some relevant results receive broad support: Alliances generally do have a deterrent effect. In a study spanning nearly two centuries, Johnson and Leeds found “support for the hypothesis that defensive alliances deter the initiation of disputes.” They conclude that “defensive alliances lower the probability of international conflict and are thus a good policy option for states seeking to maintain peace in the world.” Sechser and Fuhrmann similarly find that formal defense pacts with nuclear states have significant deterrence benefits. 2 3 The overall balance of military forces (including nuclear) between states does not appear to influence deterrence; the local balance of military forces in the specific theater in which deterrence is actually practiced, however, is key. 4 Forward- deployed troops enhance the deterrent effect of alliances with overseas allies. 5 Strong mutual interests and ties enhance deterrence. 6 Case studies strongly ratify the theoretical expectation that it is easier to defend a given status quo than to challenge it forcefully: compellence (sometimes termed “coercion” or “coercive diplomacy”) is extremely hard. The most important finding to emerge from this voluminous research is that alliances— especially with nuclear- armed allies like the United States— actually work in deterring conflict. This is all the more striking in view of the fact that what scholars call “selection bias” probably works against it. The United States is more inclined to offer— and protégés to seek— alliance rela- tionships in settings where the probability of military conflicts is higher than average. The fact that alliances work to deter conflict in precisely the situations where deterrence is likely to be especially hard is noteworthy. More specifically, these findings buttress the key theoretical implication that if the United States is interested in deterring military challenges to the status quo in key regions, relying only on latent military capabilities in the US homeland is likely to be far less effective than having an overseas military posture. Similarly, they lend support to the general proposition that a forward deterrence posture is strongly appealing to a status quo power, because defending a given status quo is far cheaper than overturning it, and, once a favorable status quo is successfully overturned, restoring the status quo ante can be expected to be fearsomely costly. Recognizing the significance of these findings clearly casts doubt on the “wait on the sidelines and decide whether to intervene later” approach that is so strongly favored by retrenchment proponents. The Causes of Nuclear Proliferation Matthew Kroenig highlights a number of reasons why US policymakers seek to limit the spread of nuclear weapons: “Fear that nuclear proliferation might deter [US leaders] from using military intervention to pursue their interests, reduce the effectiveness of their coercive diplomacy, trigger regional instability, undermine their alliance structures, dissipate their strategic attention, and set off further nuclear proliferation within their sphere of influence.” These are not the only reasons for concern about nuclear proliferation; also notable are the enhanced prospects of nuclear accidents and the greater risk of leakage of nuclear material to terrorists. 9 8 Do deep engagement’s security ties serve to contain the spread of nuclear weapons? The literature on the causes of proliferation is massive and faces challenges as great as any in international relations. With few cases to study, severe challenges in gathering evidence about inevitably secretive nuclear programs, and a large number of factors in play on both the demand and the supply sides, findings are decidedly mixed. Alliance relationships are just one piece of this complex puzzle, one that is hard to isolate from all the other factors in play. And empirical studies face the same selection bias problem just discussed: Nuclear powers are more likely to offer security guarantees to states confronting a serious threat and thus facing above- average incentives to acquire nuclear weapons. Indeed, alliance guarantees might be offered to states actively considering the nuclear option precisely in order to try to forestall that decision. Like a strong drug given only to very sick patients, alliances thus may have a powerful effect even if they sometimes fail to work as hoped. 10 Bearing these challenges in mind, the most relevant findings that emerge from this literature are: The most recent statistical analysis of the precise question at issue concludes that “security guarantees significantly reduce proliferation proclivity among their recipients.” In addition, states with such guarantees are less likely to export sensitive nuclear material and technology to other nonnuclear states. 12 11 Case study research underscores that the complexity of motivations for acquiring nuclear weapons cannot be reduced to security: domestic politics, economic interests, and prestige all matter. 13 Multiple independently conceived and executed recent case studies nonetheless reveal that security alliances help explain numerous allied decisions not to proliferate even when security is not always the main driver of leaders’ interest in a nuclear program. As Nuno Monteiro and Alexandre Debs stress, “States whose security goals are subsumed by their sponsors’ own aims have never acquired the bomb. … This finding highlights the role of U.S. security commitments in stymieing nuclear proliferation: U.S. protégés will only seek the bomb if they doubt U.S. protection of their core security goals.” 15 14 Multiple independently conceived and executed recent case research projects further unpack the conditions that decrease the likelihood of allied proliferation, centering on the credibility of the alliance commitment. In addition, in some cases of prevention failure, the alliances allow the patron to influence the ally’s nuclear program subsequently, decreasing further proliferation risks. 17 Security alliances lower the likelihood of proliferation cascades. To be sure, many predicted cascades did not occur. But security provision, mainly by the United States, is a key reason why. The most comprehensive statistical analysis finds that states are more likely to proliferate in response to neighbors when three conditions are met: (1) there is an intense security rivalry between the two countries; (2) the prospective proliferating state does not have a security guarantee from a nuclear- armed patron; and (3) the potential proliferator has the industrial and technical capacity to launch an indigenous nuclear program. 18 19 16 In sum, as Monteiro and Debs note, “Despite grave concerns that more states would seek a nuclear deterrent to counter U.S. power preponderance,” in fact “the spread of nuclear weapons decelerated with the end of the Cold War in 1989.” Their research, as well as that of scores of scholars using multiple methods and representing many contrasting theoretical perspectives, shows that US security guarantees and the counter- proliferation policy deep engagement allows are a big part of the reason why. 20 The Costs of Nuclear Proliferation General empirical findings thus lend support to the proposition that security alliances impede nuclear proliferation. But is this a net contributor to global security? Most practitioners and policy analysts would probably not even bring this up as a question and would automatically answer yes if it were raised. Yet a small but very prominent group of theorists within the academy reach a different answer: some of the same realist precepts that generate the theoretical prediction that retrenchment would increase demand for nuclear weapons also suggest that proliferation might increase security such that the net effect of retrenchment could be neutral. Most notably, “nuclear optimists” like Kenneth Waltz contend that deterrence essentially solves the security problem for all nuclear- armed states, largely eliminating the direct use of force among them. It follows that US retrenchment might generate an initial decrease in security followed by an increase as insecure states acquire nuclear capabilities, ultimately leaving no net effect on international security. 21 This perspective is countered by “nuclear pessimists” such as Scott Sagan. Reaching outside realism to organization theory and other bodies of social science research, they see major security downsides from new nuclear states. Copious research produced by Sagan and others casts doubt on the expectation that governments can be relied upon to create secure and controlled nuclear forces. The more nuclear states there are, the higher the probability that the organizational, psychological, and civil- military pathologies Sagan identifies will turn an episode like one of the numerous “near misses” he uncovers into actual nuclear use. As Campbell Craig warns, “One day a warning system will fail, or an official will panic, or a terrorist attack will be misconstrued, and the missiles will fly.” 22 23 Looking beyond these kinds of factors, it is notable that powerful reasons to question the assessment of proliferation optimists also emerge even if one assumes, as they do, that states are rational and seek only to maximize their security. First, nuclear deterrence can only work by raising the risk of nuclear war. For deterrence to be credible, there has to be a nonzero chance of nuclear use. If nuclear use is impossible, deterrence cannot be credible. It follows that every nuclear deterrence relationship depends on some probability of 24 nuclear use. The more such relationships there are, the greater the risk of nuclear war. Proliferation therefore increases the chances of nuclear war even in a perfectly rationalist world. Proliferation optimists cannot logically deny that nuclear spread increases the risk of nuclear war. Their argument must be that the security gains of nuclear spread outweigh this enhanced risk. Estimating that risk is not simply a matter of pondering the conditions under which leaders will choose to unleash nuclear war. Rather, as Schelling established, the question is whether states will run the risk of using nuclear weapons. Nuclear crisis bargaining is about a “competition in risk taking.” Kroenig counts some twenty cases in which states—including prominently the United States—ran real risks of nuclear war in order to prevail in crises. As Kroenig notes, “By asking whether states can be deterred or not … proliferation optimists are asking the wrong question. The right question to ask is: what risk of nuclear war is a specific state willing to run against a particular opponent in a given crisis?” The more nuclear- armed states there are, the more the opportunities for such risk- taking and the greater the probability of nuclear use. 27 26 25
12,978
<h4>The <u>best</u> studies confirm our <u>impact</u> – err on the side of a <u>consensus</u> of <u>empirical</u> research – our evidence assumes <u>every skeptic</u>.</h4><p>Stephen<strong> Brooks & </strong>William<strong> Wohlforth 16<u></strong>. William, Daniel Webster Professor in the Department of Government at Dartmouth College. Stephen Brooks, Ph. D in Political Science from Yale, Associate Professor of Government at Dartmouth College, Senior Fellow at the Belfer Center for Science and International Affairs at Harvard University. Page 103-108</p><p>Consistency with influential relevant theories lends <strong>credence</u></strong> <u>to the expectation that <strong>US security commitments</u></strong> <u>actually can shape the strategic environment as deep engagement presupposes</u>. But it is far from conclusive. Not all analysts endorse the theories we discussed in chapter 5. These theories make strong assumptions that states generally act rationally and focus primarily on security. Allowing misperceptions, emotions, domestic politics, desire for status, or concern for honor into the picture might alter the verdict on the strategy’s net expected effects. And <u><mark>to model</mark> the strategy’s expected <mark>effects we</mark> had to <mark>simplify</mark> things by selecting two mechanisms</u>— <u><strong><mark>assurance</u></strong> <u>and</u> <u><strong>deterrence</u></strong></mark>— <u>and <mark>examining </mark>their <mark>effects independently</mark>, thus <mark>miss</mark>ing potentially <strong><mark>powerful</mark> positive <mark>interactions</strong></mark> between them.</p><p></u>This chapter moves beyond theory to examine patterns of evidence. If the theoretical arguments about the security effects of deep engagement are right, what sort of evidence should we see? Two <u>major bodies of evidence are most important</u>: general <u><strong>empirical findings</u></strong> concerning the strategy’s key mechanisms <u>and</u> <u><strong>regionally focused research</u></strong>.</p><p><u>General Patterns of Evidence Three key questions about US security provision have received the most extensive analysis. First, do alliances such as those sustained by the United States actually deter war and increase security? Second, does such security provision actually hinder nuclear proliferation? And third, does limiting proliferation actually increase security?</p><p></u>Deterrence Effectiveness <u>The determinants of <mark>deterrence </mark>success and failure have <mark>attracted</u></mark> scores of quantitative and <u>case study <mark>tests</u></mark>. Much of the case study work yields a cautionary finding: that <u>deterrence is much harder in practice than in theory</u>, because standard models assume away the complexities of human psychology and domestic politics that tend to make some states hard to deter and might cause deterrence policies to backfire. 1 <u>Many quantitative <mark>findings</u></mark>, mean- while, <u><mark>are</mark> mutually <mark>contradictory</mark> or are clearly not relevant to extended deterrence. But <strong><mark>some</mark> relevant <mark>results receive broad support</mark>:</strong> </p><p><strong><mark>Alliances</u></strong></mark> generally do <u><strong><mark>have a deterrent </mark>effect</u></strong>. <u><mark>In a study spanning</u></mark> nearly <u><strong><mark>two centuries</u></strong></mark>, <u><strong>Johnson</u></strong> <u>and</u> <u><strong><mark>Leeds</u></strong> <u>found “support for</mark> the hypothesis that defensive alliances deter the <strong>initiation of disputes</u></strong>.” They conclude that “<u><mark>defensive alliances lower </mark>the <strong>probability of international <mark>conflict</strong></mark> and are thus a good policy option for states seeking to maintain peace </u>in the world.” Sechser and <u>Fuhrmann similarly find that formal defense pacts with nuclear states</u> have significant deterrence benefits. 2 3 </p><p><u>The overall balance of military forces</u> (including nuclear) between states <u>does not appear to influence deterrence; the <strong>local balance of <mark>military forces </strong>in the <strong></mark>specific <mark>theater</strong></mark> in <mark>which <strong>deterrence</strong> is</mark> actually <strong><mark>practiced</strong></mark>, however, <strong><mark>is key</u></strong></mark>. 4 </p><p><u><strong><mark>Forward- deployed troops enhance the </mark>deterrent <mark>effect</u></strong></mark> of alliances with overseas allies. 5 </p><p><u>Strong mutual interests and ties enhance deterrence</u>. 6 </p><p><u>Case <mark>studies <strong></mark>strongly <mark>ratify</mark> </strong><mark>the</mark> theoretical <mark>expectation</mark> that <mark>it is easier to <strong>defend</strong></mark> a given status</u> <u>quo <mark>than</mark> to <strong><mark>challenge</mark> it forcefully</u></strong>: <u>compellence</u> (sometimes termed “coercion” or “coercive diplomacy”) <u>is extremely hard.</p><p>The most important finding</u> to emerge from this voluminous research <u>is that <mark>alliances</u></mark>— especially <u><mark>with</u> <u><strong>nuclear</mark>- armed <mark>allies</u></strong></mark> <u>like the United States</u>— <u><strong>actually <mark>work</u></strong></mark> <u>in deterring conflict</u>. This is all the more striking in view of the fact that what scholars call “<u><mark>selection bias</u>”</mark> probably <u><strong><mark>works against it</u></strong>.</mark> <u><mark>The</mark> <strong><mark>U</strong></mark>nited <mark>S</mark>tates <mark>is</mark> more <mark>inclined to offer</u></mark>— and protégés to seek— <u>alliance rela- tionships <mark>in settings where</mark> the <strong><mark>probability</strong> of</mark> military <strong><mark>conflict</mark>s</strong> <mark>is <strong>higher </mark>than average</u></strong>. <u>The fact that alliances work to deter conflict in precisely the situations where <strong>deterrence</strong> is likely to be <strong>especially hard</strong> is noteworthy.</p><p></u>More specifically, these findings buttress the key theoretical implication that if <u>the United States is interested in deterring military challenges</u> to the status quo in key regions<u>, <mark>relying</mark> only <mark>on</mark> <strong><mark>latent</mark> military <mark>capabilities</strong> in the</mark> US <strong><mark>homeland</strong></mark> <mark>is</mark> likely to be <strong><mark>far less effective</u></strong> <u></mark>than having an <strong>overseas military posture</u></strong>. Similarly, they lend support to the general proposition that a <u><mark>forward deterrence</mark> posture <mark>is</u> <u><strong></mark>strongly <mark>appealing</u></strong></mark> to a status quo power, <u><mark>because defending</mark> a given status quo <mark>is <strong></mark>far <mark>cheaper than overturning</mark> it</strong>, and, once a favorable status quo is successfully overturned, <strong>restoring</strong> the status quo ante can be expected to be <strong>fearsomely costly</u></strong>. <u><mark>Recognizing</mark> the significance of <mark>these <strong>findings</mark> clearly <mark>casts doubt</strong> on the</u></mark> “<u><strong><mark>wait on the sidelines and decide</mark> whether <mark>to intervene later” approach</u></strong></mark> that is so strongly <u>favored by <strong>retrenchment proponents</u></strong>.</p><p>The Causes of Nuclear Proliferation Matthew Kroenig highlights a number of reasons why US policymakers seek to limit the spread of nuclear weapons: “<u>Fear that nuclear proliferation might deter [US leaders] from using military <strong>intervention</strong> to pursue their interests, reduce the effectiveness of their <strong>coercive diplomacy</strong>, trigger <strong>regional instability</strong>, undermine their <strong>alliance structures</strong>, dissipate their strategic attention, and set off <strong>further nuclear proliferation</strong> within their sphere of influence</u>.” These are not the only reasons for concern about nuclear proliferation; <u>also notable are the enhanced prospects of</u> <u><strong>nuclear accidents</u></strong> <u>and the greater risk of <strong>leakage</strong> of</u> <u><strong>nuclear material to terrorists</u></strong>. 9 8</p><p><u><mark>Do</u></mark> deep engagement’s <u><mark>security ties</u></mark> <u>serve to <mark>contain</mark> t</u>he spread of <u><strong><mark>nuclear weapons</u></strong></mark>? The literature on the causes of proliferation is massive and faces challenges as great as any in international relations. With few cases to study, severe challenges in gathering evidence about inevitably secretive nuclear programs, and a large number of factors in play on both the demand and the supply sides, <u><strong><mark>findings are </mark>decidedly <mark>mixed</strong></mark>. Alliance relationships are just one piece of this complex puzzle</u>, one that is hard to isolate from all the other factors in play. And <u>empirical studies face the same selection bias problem just discussed</u>: Nuclear powers are more likely to offer security guarantees to states confronting a serious threat and thus facing above- average incentives to acquire nuclear weapons. Indeed, <u>alliance guarantees might be offered to states actively considering the nuclear option precisely in order to try to forestall that decision</u>. Like a strong drug given only to very sick patients, alliances thus may have a powerful effect even if they sometimes fail to work as hoped. 10</p><p>Bearing these challenges in mind, <u><mark>the <strong>most relevant</strong></mark> findings that emerge <strong>from this literature <mark>are</u></strong></mark>:</p><p><u>The</u> <u><strong>most recent <mark>statistical analysis</u></strong></mark> of the precise question at issue <u><mark>concludes</mark> that “<mark>security guarantees <strong></mark>significantly <mark>reduce proliferation</u></strong></mark> <u>proclivity</u> among their recipients.” In addition, <u><mark>states</mark> <mark>with</mark> such <mark>guarantees are less likely to <strong>export</strong></mark> sensitive</u> <u><strong>nuclear <mark>material and tech</mark>nology</u></strong> to other nonnuclear states. 12 11 </p><p><u><strong>Case study research</u></strong> <u>underscores that the complexity of motivations for acquiring nuclear weapons cannot be reduced to security</u>: domestic politics, economic interests, and prestige all matter. 13 </p><p><u><mark>Multiple <strong>independent</mark>ly conceived</strong> and</u> <u><strong>executed</u></strong> <u>recent case <mark>studies</mark> nonetheless <mark>reveal</mark> that <strong><mark>security alliances</u></strong></mark> <u>help <mark>explain</mark> numerous allied <mark>decisions not to proliferate</mark> even when security is not always the main driver of leaders’ interest</u> in a nuclear program. As Nuno Monteiro and Alexandre Debs stress, “<u>States whose security goals are subsumed by their sponsors’ own aims have <strong>never acquired the bomb</u></strong>. … <u>This finding highlights the role of U.S. security commitments in <strong>stymieing nuclear proliferation</u></strong>: U<u>.S. <mark>protégés</mark> will <mark>only <strong>seek the bomb</strong> if they <strong>doubt U.S. protection</u></strong></mark> of their core security goals.” 15 14 </p><p><u><strong>Multiple independently</u></strong> conceived and executed recent <u><strong>case <mark>research</u></strong></mark> <u>projects further unpack the conditions that decrease the likelihood of allied proliferation, <mark>center</mark>ing<mark> on</mark> the <strong><mark>credibility</strong> of the <strong>alliance commitment</mark>. </u></strong>In addition, <u>in</u> some <u>cases of prevention failure, the alliances allow the patron to influence the ally’s nuclear program subsequently, decreasing further proliferation risks</u>. 17 </p><p><u>Security <mark>alliances lower</mark> the likelihood of <strong><mark>proliferation cascades</u></strong></mark>. To be sure, <u>many predicted cascades did not occur.</u> But <u>security <strong><mark>provision</strong></mark>, mainly <mark>by the <strong>U</mark>nited<mark> S</mark>tates</strong><mark>, is a <strong>key</strong> reason </mark>why</u>. <u><mark>The <strong>most comprehensive</mark> statistical <mark>analysis</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>finds</mark> that <mark>states</mark> are more likely to <mark>proliferate</mark> in response to neighbors <mark>when</mark> <strong>three conditions are met</u></strong>: (1) <u><mark>there is an <strong>intense</mark> security <mark>rivalry</mark> </strong>between the two countries</u>; (2) <u><mark>the</u></mark> prospective <u>proliferating <mark>state <strong>does not have a security guarantee</strong></mark> from a <strong>nuclear</strong>- armed <strong>patron</u></strong>; <u><mark>and</u></mark> (3) <u>the potential proliferator has the industrial and technical <mark>capacity</mark> to launch an indigenous</u> nuclear <u>program</u>. 18 19 16</p><p>In sum, as Monteiro and Debs note, “Despite grave concerns that more states would seek a nuclear deterrent to counter U.S. power preponderance,” in fact “<u>the <mark>spread</mark> of nuclear weapons <strong><mark>decelerated</strong> with the <strong>end of the Cold War</u></strong></mark> in 1989.” <u>Their research, as well as that of <strong><mark>scores of scholars</u></strong> <u>using</u> <u><strong>multiple methods</u></strong></mark> <u>and <mark>representing </mark>many <strong><mark>contrasting</mark> theoretical <mark>perspectives</u></strong>, <u>shows</mark> that <mark>US</mark> <strong>security <mark>guarantees</strong> and</mark> the counter- proliferation policy <strong><mark>deep engagement</u></strong></mark> <u>allows <mark>are</mark> a <strong>big part</strong> of the <strong>reason <mark>why</u></strong></mark>. 20</p><p>The Costs of Nuclear Proliferation General empirical findings thus lend support to the proposition that security alliances impede nuclear proliferation. But is this a net contributor to global security? Most practitioners and policy analysts would probably not even bring this up as a question and would automatically answer yes if it were raised. Yet a small but very prominent group of theorists within the academy reach a different answer: <u>some of the same realist precepts that generate the theoretical prediction that retrenchment would increase demand for nuclear weapons also suggest that proliferation might <strong>increase security</u></strong> such that the net effect of retrenchment could be neutral. Most notably, “<u><strong>nuclear optimists</u></strong>” <u>like</u> Kenneth <u><strong>Waltz</u></strong> <u>contend that <strong>deterrence</strong> essentially solves the security problem for all <strong>nuclear- armed states</u></strong>, <u>largely eliminating the direct use of force </u>among them. It follows that <u>US retrenchment might generate an initial decrease in security followed by an <strong>increase as insecure states acquire nuclear capabilities</u></strong>, <u>ultimately leaving no net effect on international security</u>. 21</p><p><u>This perspective is countered by </u>“<u><strong>nuclear <mark>pessimists</u></strong></mark>” such as Scott Sagan. Reaching outside realism to organization theory and other bodies of social science research, <u>they <mark>see major</mark> security <mark>downsides </mark>from <strong>new nuclear states</strong>. <strong>Copious <mark>research</u></strong></mark> produced by Sagan and others <u><mark>casts doubt</mark> on the expectation that <strong><mark>governments</strong> can be <strong>relied upon</strong></mark> to create <strong>secure</strong> and <strong>controlled</strong> <strong>nuclear forces</strong>. The more nuclear states there are, the higher the probability that the organizational, psychological, and civil- military pathologies Sagan identifies will turn an episode like one of the numerous “<strong>near misses” he uncovers</u></strong> into actual nuclear use. As Campbell Craig warns, “<u>One day a <strong><mark>warning system</mark> will <mark>fail</u></strong></mark>, or <u><strong><mark>an</mark> <mark>official will panic</u></strong></mark>, <u>or a terrorist <strong><mark>attack will be misconstrued</strong></mark>, and <strong>the <mark>missiles will fly</strong></mark>.</u>” 22 23</p><p>Looking beyond these kinds of factors, it is notable that <u>powerful reasons to question the assessment of proliferation optimists also emerge even if one assumes, as they do, that states are rational and seek only to maximize their security</u>. First, <u>nuclear <mark>deterrence </mark>can <mark>only work by <strong>raising the risk of nuclear</mark> <mark>war</strong></mark>. For deterrence to be <strong>credible</u></strong>, <u>there has to be a</u> <u><strong>nonzero chance </strong>of nuclear use</u>. <u><mark>If </mark>nuclear <mark>use is <strong>impossible</strong>, <strong>deterrence cannot be credible</u></strong></mark>. It follows that <u>every nuclear deterrence relationship depends on some probability</u> of 24 nuclear use. <u><mark>The more </mark>such relationships there are</u>, <u><strong><mark>the greater the risk</mark> of nuclear war</u></strong>. Proliferation therefore increases the chances of nuclear war even in a perfectly rationalist world. Proliferation optimists cannot logically deny that nuclear spread increases the risk of nuclear war. Their argument must be that the security gains of nuclear spread outweigh this enhanced risk. </p><p>Estimating that risk is not simply a matter of pondering the conditions under which leaders will choose to unleash nuclear war. Rather, as Schelling established, the question is whether states will run the risk of using nuclear weapons. <u>Nuclear <mark>crisis </mark>bargaining <mark>is </mark>about <mark>a “<strong>competition in risk taking</u></strong></mark>.” <u>Kroenig counts some twenty cases in which states</u>—including prominently the United States—<u>ran real risks of nuclear war in order to prevail in crises</u>. As Kroenig notes<u>, “By asking whether states can be deterred or not … proliferation optimists are <strong>asking the wrong question</strong>.</u> <u>The right question to ask is: <strong>what risk of nuclear war</u></strong> <u>is a specific state willing to run against a <strong>particular opponent</strong> in a</u> <u><strong>given crisis</u></strong>?” <u><mark>The more</mark> nuclear- <mark>armed states </mark>there are, the more the opportunities for such risk- taking and <mark>the <strong>greater the probability</mark> of nuclear use</u></strong>. 27 26 25</p>
1NC
OFF
1NC – DA
10,734
771
53,706
./documents/hspolicy20/Alpharetta/NaTh/Alpharetta-Nayak-Thatiparthi-Neg-Westminster-Round5.docx
723,950
N
Westminster
5
Lindale JS
Spencer Williams
1AC - Dark Deleuze 1NC - - T-USFG - Heg DA 2NC - - T-USFG 1NR - - Case 2NR - - T-USFG
hspolicy20/Alpharetta/NaTh/Alpharetta-Nayak-Thatiparthi-Neg-Westminster-Round5.docx
null
61,799
NaTh
Alpharetta NaTh
null
An.....
Na.....
An.....
Th.....
21,498
Alpharetta
Alpharetta
GA
null
1,019
hspolicy20
HS Policy 2020-21
2,020
cx
hs
2
4,784,269
Global populism upsurge is bad—laundry list of impacts
Leigh 21
Leigh 21 Andrew Leigh 2021 “What's the Worst that Could Happen?: Existential Risk and Extreme Politics” (Ph.D. in Public Policy from the John F. Kennedy School of Government at Harvard University)//Elmer
populists pose a threat to long-termism Because long-term threats requires science institutions, global engagement, and cooperation populists are anti-intellectual Because populists view politics as a contest This led to clashes between populist leaders and scientists called climate change nonexistent virtually all climate deniers are populists anti-vaccination movement has been bolstered rise of populist parties has been accompanied by an increase in anti-vaxxer sentiment sidelined technocrats and touted unproven health measures skepticism manifests in support for debunked conspiracy theories Populist leaders build political support by pushing conspiracy theories populists are anti-institution suspicious of institutions bureaucracy, judiciary, and media populists are anti-international hostile toward global bodies During COVID populists undermined international cooperation Trump fomented conflict with Chin Trump and Bolsonaro worked together to drive out 10,000 Cuban doctors and nurses from Brazil, Ecuador, Bolivia and El Salvador, increasing the death toll of the virus in impoverished communities When populists turn from international trade, they make it harder to address future pandemics nations built comparative advantages in medical supplies over eighty countries implemented export controls leading to cascading closure of the global medical trade rhetoric of self-reliance misleads Populists create scapegoats out of minority communities and deploy racism to win votes By fostering a suspicion of foreigners separating the world into “us” and “them,” populists make it harder to solve problems that cross international boundaries. existential threats are global problems International tensions increase the chances of nuclear war and make it more difficult to control bioterrorism Anti-internationalism raises the risks of artificial intelligence dismissed concerns a machine that can “perform at the level of, or better than a human We need to move from international values statements on artificial intelligence to treaties such agreements founder on the tendency of populist governments to oppose international pacts If populists prevent global artificial intelligence safety standards, the world risks a race to the bottom. populists are anti-irenic. they benefit from division and disagreement Populists thrive off chaos But when external crises hit, populist leaders struggle Populist politics risks exacerbating the catastrophic risks of nuclear war, pandemics, dangerous superintelligence, and climate change
populists pose a threat to long-termism Because long-term threats requires science institutions engagement and cooperation populists are anti-intellectual climate deniers anti-vaccination conspiracy theories populists are suspicious of institutions During COVID populists undermined international cooperation make it harder to address pandemics closure of global trade scapegoats of minorit ies suspicion of foreigners make it harder to solve existential threats tensions increase nuclear war make it difficult to control bioterrorism Anti-internationalism risks a i Populist politics exacerbating catastrophic risks of nuclear war, pandemics, dangerous superintelligence, and climate change
Why do populists pose a threat to long-termism? Because tackling long-term threats requires four things: strong science, effective institutions, global engagement, and a sense of cooperation and order. Populists are anti-intellectual, anti-institutional, anti-international, and anti-irenic (“irenic” means to strive for peace and consensus). This is not an accident. Each of the four antis forms part of the electoral appeal of populism, just as each makes it impossible for populists to effectively address challenges to humanity’s future. First, populists are anti-intellectual. Because populists view politics as a contest between a pure mass of people and vile elite, their characterization of the elite often includes experts. This has led to a spate of clashes between populist leaders and scientists. According to the Union of Concerned Scientists, Trump attacked science more than 150 times.75 Research on child health and pollution, the environmental impacts of coal mining, and species extinction was ignored or criticized. In the 2017 “Sharpiegate” affair, the White House redrew a meteorologic map to make it consistent with an erroneous presidential tweet. Trump called climate change “mythical” and “nonexistent.” In a similar fashion, Bolsonaro has questioned his own government’s data on deforestation in the Amazon, while Dutch far-right leader Thierry Baudet rails against “climate change hysteria.” Not every populist is a climate denier, but virtually all climate deniers are populists.76 One analysis of the twenty-one largest right-wing populist parties in Europe found that one-third were outright climate deniers, while many others were hostile to climate action.77 Right-wing populists make up 15 percent of the European Parliament, but account for around half of the votes against climate and energy resolutions. One study in the United Kingdom identified voters who held populist beliefs about politics, such as agreeing that people rather than politicians should make policy decisions, or that elected officials talk too much and take too little action.78 These populist voters were significantly less likely to agree that global warming is caused by human action and less likely to support measures to protect the environment. Importantly, this pattern held across the political spectrum; populism explains climate denial among both left- and right-wing voters. The anti-vaccination movement, with its conspiracy theories about large pharmaceutical companies, has been bolstered by populists. In Italy, the populist Five Star Movement criticized a 2017 law making it compulsory for children to be vaccinated against measles, mumps, and rubella, sometimes repeating falsehoods about the vaccine. In France, the populist National Rally party (formerly the National Front) condemned an increase in the number of mandatory childhood vaccines. Across Europe, the rise of populist parties has been accompanied by an increase in anti-vaxxer sentiment. One in seven Europeans say that they do not believe vaccines are important, while half wrongly believe that vaccines can often cause serious side effects.79 As vaccination rates fell, the number of European measles cases more than doubled between 2011 and 2019.80 Confirming the role of politics, a study that analyzed data across fourteen European countries found a strong relationship between the share of people who vote for populist parties and the proportion who believe that vaccination is not important.81 Before becoming president, Trump expressed support for a prominent anti-vaxxer conspiracy theory: the debunked claim that vaccines cause autism. As president, Trump tweeted about the dangers of vaccines more than thirty times.82 It was much the same with COVID-19. Trump’s overconfidence led him initially to dismiss the coronavirus threat. In January 2020, he said, “We have it totally under control. It’s one person coming in from China, and we have it under control. It’s going to be just fine.” In February, he referred to coronavirus as a “new hoax” being peddled by the Democrats. Gainsaying the experts, Trump was dismissive of mask wearing, slowed down testing, and touted the ineffective drug hydroxychloroquine. It soon became clear that Trump saw the disease primarily in terms of politics rather than public health.83 As a satirical headline in the Onion put it, “Trump: ‘Even One Death That Makes Me Look Bad Is a Tragedy.’”84 Bolsonaro was similarly dismissive of medical expertise. He initially described coronavirus as a media “trick,” arguing that Brazilians were naturally immune to the disease. “The Brazilian needs to be studied,” said Bolsonaro. “He doesn’t catch anything. You see a guy jumping into sewage, diving in, right? Nothing happens to him. I think a lot of people were already infected in Brazil, weeks or months ago, and they already have the antibodies that help it not proliferate.” Bolsonaro urged the premature relaxation of physical distancing measures, supported street protests against quarantines, and fired two health ministers.85 Relative to population, Brazil has one of the highest COVID-19 death rates in the world.86 Like populist leaders Johnson and Trump, Bolsonaro contracted coronavirus himself. Three of Brazil’s 81 senators have died from the disease. Similarly, in Indonesia and the Philippines, populist leaders sidelined technocrats and touted unproven health measures. Widodo was slow to implement lockdowns in Indonesia, saying that he did not want to cause “panic” and claiming that lockdowns were ineffective. His ministers variously promoted prayer and a necklace made of eucalyptus as protections against COVID-19.87 In the Philippines, President Duterte advocated gasoline as a disinfectant and created a coronavirus task force led by retired generals rather than epidemiologists.88 Indonesia and the Philippines have among the highest rates of coronavirus deaths in the Asia-Pacific region.89 Hostility toward scientists and intellectuals shows up among supporters too. In a 2019 survey, 62 percent of Democrats—but only 44 percent of Republicans—agreed that scientists’ judgments are based solely on the facts.90 Populists’ skepticism of intellectuals also manifests in support for debunked conspiracy theories.91 A global survey of twenty-two thousand voters across nineteen democracies found that populist voters were far more likely to be conspiracy minded. Populists are more than twice as likely to think that global warming is a hoax. They are almost twice as likely to believe that AIDS was invented by the US Central Intelligence Agency, that supposedly harmful effects of vaccines are being hidden from the public, and that the US government knowingly helped the September 11 attackers. Populists are more likely to believe that alien contact is being hidden from the public. Populist leaders frequently build political support by pushing conspiracy theories. Among the falsehoods peddled by populist actors are that the Holocaust is a hoax, former German chancellor Angela Merkel is the secret daughter of Adolf Hitler, the European Union is resurrecting the Roman Empire as a communist superstate, and there is a worldwide cabal of Satan-worshipping pedophiles who rule the world (the QAnon theory).92 In November 2020, Georgia Republican Marjorie Taylor Greene was the first QAnon supporter to be elected to the US Congress.93 Half of all Republican voters believe one of QAnon’s key tenets: that top Democrats are involved in child sex trafficking.94 A majority of Republicans believe that the January 2021 assault on the United States Capitol was “mostly an antifa-inspired attack.”95 Second, populists are anti-institution. Campaigning as outsiders, populist leaders tend to be suspicious of institutions such as the bureaucracy, judiciary, and media. Journalist Michael Lewis highlights the plethora of programs run by the two million people employed by the federal government, including child nutrition, veterans’ health, air traffic control, and national security. Yet the day after the 2016 election, Lewis writes, The hundreds of people who had prepared to brief the incoming Trump administration sat waiting. A day became a week and a week became a month . . . and no one showed up. The parking spots that had been set aside for Trump’s people remained empty, and the briefing books were never opened. You could walk into almost any department of the US government and hear people asking the same question: where were these people who were meant to be running the place?96 This approach to the federal bureaucracy characterized the Trump administration. By the time coronavirus struck, ten cabinet members had departed, and four-fifths of senior White House positions had turned over.97 Trump was on his fifth secretary of the Department of Homeland Security, his fourth national security adviser, and his third chief of staff. As journalists Jennifer Steinhauer and Zolan Kanno-Youngs note, “Between Mr. Trump’s history of firing people and the choice by many career officials and political appointees to leave, he now finds himself with a government riddled with vacancies, acting department chiefs and, in some cases, leaders whose professional backgrounds do not easily match up to the task of managing a pandemic.”98 Populists regard regulatory bodies and oversight mechanisms not as an appropriate check on power but rather as a creation of self-serving insiders. In Poland and Hungary, populist governments have changed the rules on the appointment of judges and imposed age limits to remove unwanted ones.99 Elsewhere, populists have encouraged lawbreaking. In Brazil and the Philippines, populist leaders advocate the extrajudicial murder of suspected criminals. Kenneth Roth, executive director of Human Rights Watch, fears that populism “threatens to reverse the accomplishments of the modern human rights movement” created in the aftermath of the atrocities of World War II.100 Universities—the institutional home of many intellectuals—are a particular focus of populist ire. Populists claim that university research is irrelevant to real-world problems. and teaching amounts to indoctrination. Colleges are accused of lacking legitimacy and being out of touch with popular opinion. Amid the populist takeover of the Republican Party, the share of Republicans who thought that universities had a negative effect on the country jumped by 22 percentage points between 2015 and 2019.101 Another trademark of populists are their attacks on the mainstream media—or what Palin dubbed the “lamestream media.” Describing journalists as “human scum,” “low life reporters,” “corrupt,” “dishonest,” and “the enemy of the people,” Trump sought to undercut the credibility of the press. As Chris Wallace of Fox News summed it up, “He has done everything he can to undercut the media, to try and delegitimize us, and I think his purpose is clear: to raise doubts, when we report critically about him and his administration, that we can be trusted.”102 Ethical journalism—with its adherence to accuracy, independence, impartiality, and public accountability—is an important check on the abuse of power. Without an ethical media, it becomes more difficult to have a conversation about the long term. The overall importance of institutions is reinforced by a four-country study that found people who were less trusting of national institutions were also less supportive of policies to protect the well-being of future generations.103 COVID-19 also reflected Trump’s undermining of institutions. Experts had long warned about the need for the United States to work with China on potential disease hot spots. As early as 2007, microbiologists warned that “coronaviruses are well known to undergo genetic recombination, which may lead to new genotypes and outbreaks.” They went on to note that “the presence of a large reservoir of SARS-CoV-like viruses in horseshoe bats, together with the culture of eating exotic mammals in southern China, is a time bomb.”104 Despite this, Trump reduced the number of China-based staff from the CDC by two-thirds during his first two years in office.105 In his proposed budgets prior to the pandemic, Trump sought to cut CDC funding by 10 to 20 percent, with a particular emphasis on reducing CDC funding for emerging diseases, global health, and public health preparedness.106 The Trump administration also shut down the entire global health security unit of the National Security Council.107 As a report from the Environmental Data and Governance Initiative put it, “[Trump’s] efforts to reduce spending have dramatically and consistently taken aim at programs most likely to reveal and tackle potential pandemic origin points around the world.”108 The problem wasn’t just underinvestment in global health. The United States is the only advanced nation without universal health coverage, despite spending more on health care as a share of the economy than any other nation in the world. The lack of universal health care is one reason the United States has experienced so many COVID deaths and suffered difficulties in rolling out the vaccine. Minorities were both more likely to contract COVID in 2020 and less likely to be vaccinated in 2021. Populist opposition to the institutional framework of universal health care made the impact of COVID more severe and more inequitable. Third, populists are anti-international. Populist political slogans include “I Want My Country Back,” “Law and Border,” “Patriotism, Protection, and Prosperity,” “Finland for the Finns,” “Courage to Stand Up for Germany,” and “America First.” Populists typically distrust immigration, trade, and foreign investment. They tend to be hostile toward global bodies such as the World Bank, International Criminal Court, World Trade Organization, and United Nations. Many European populists advocate dissolving the European Union. Had he won a second term, experts anticipated that Trump would have tried to withdraw the United States from NATO, destabilizing the power balance in Europe.109 During the COVID-19 crisis, populists also undermined international cooperation. President Trump deliberately fomented conflict with China, calling COVID-19 “the China Virus” and “Kung Flu.” The Trump administration withdrew from the World Health Organization and cut funding to the Pan-American Health Organization, Latin America’s leading health agency. President Bolsonaro bizarrely claimed that the World Health Organization was encouraging same-sex relationships in four-year-olds, sexual experiences for nine-year-olds, and masturbation in children from birth.110 Trump and Bolsonaro worked together to drive out 10,000 Cuban doctors and nurses from Brazil, Ecuador, Bolivia and El Salvador, increasing the death toll of the virus in impoverished communities.111 When populists turn their countries away from international trade, they make it harder to address the impact of future pandemics. Over time, nations have built up comparative advantages in producing certain kinds of medical supplies. Switzerland is a major manufacturer of pharmaceuticals. Malaysia is a substantial exporter of surgical gloves. The United States is the world’s largest exporter of medical instruments. China is the world’s biggest producer of face masks. South Korea mass-produces in vitro diagnostics products. Nine-tenths of the personal protective equipment sold in the European Union is imported.112 Unfortunately, during the COVID-19 crisis, over eighty countries implemented export controls on medical supplies and medicines, leading to concerns about a cascading closure of the global medical trade.113 Such a slide into autarky would be especially damaging for developing nations. The rhetoric of self-reliance misleads; rather than banning trade, countries should build stockpiles. By allowing nations to specialize in what they do best, we end up with more production of higher-quality goods at cheaper prices—and a world that is better able to respond to disease threats. At its best, patriotism fosters a sense of pride in what our ancestors have built and a love of local communities. But the antiglobal movement frequently stokes unfounded fears. Populists often create scapegoats out of minority communities and deploy racism to win votes. By fostering a suspicion of foreigners, and separating the world into “us” and “them,” populists make it harder to solve problems that cross international boundaries. By definition, existential threats to humanity are global problems, and are much harder to solve when countries are unwilling to work together. International tensions increase the chances of nuclear war and make it more difficult to control bioterrorism. Anti-internationalism also raises the risks of artificial intelligence. In 2020, President Trump issued an executive order on artificial intelligence, which touched briefly on safety issues. But in implementing it, his administration dismissed concerns about a machine that can “perform at the level of, or better than a human agent,” saying that such issues were “beyond the scope” of the executive order.114 Trump’s chief technology officer, Michael Kratsios, stated the goal simply: for the United States to “win the race for artificial intelligence.”115 This is dangerously narrow-minded. We need to move from international values statements on artificial intelligence to binding treaties. But such global agreements could founder on the tendency of populist governments to oppose international pacts. If populists prevent the development of global artificial intelligence safety standards, the world risks a race to the bottom. Fourth, populists are anti-irenic. Rather than striving for an irenic calm consensus, they benefit from division and disagreement. The politics of division requires that the temperature be at boiling point, the volume at full blast, the gas pedal flat to the floor. To persuade voters that politics is broken, there must be a villain. Populists thrive on bombast and blame—not compromise and community building. Throughout his four years as president, Trump averaged a false or misleading statement every ninety minutes, according to analysis by the Washington Post.116 Many of his lies were deliberately designed to provoke outrage. Describing the effect of his most incendiary statements, Trump said, “I used to watch it like a rocket ship when I put out a beauty.”117 A perpetual culture war not only served to mobilize the Republican base; it also engendered a sense of stress and anxiety that has been shown by psychologists to foster hostility toward outsiders.118 Two-fifths of Republicans think their political opponents are evil. One-fifth regard Democrats as animals.119 When stressed, people can develop tunnel vision—overvaluing short-term priorities at the expense of future needs. Scarcity, argue researchers Sendhil Mullainathan and Eldar Shafir, “makes us dumber. It makes us more impulsive. We must get by with less mind available, with less fluid intelligence.”120 Stressful politics and a perpetual state of fear can act as a “cognitive tax” on voters, promoting a politics of short-termism. If every day is a crisis, long-term planning is a luxury. In a battle, soldiers aren’t thinking about whether they’ve put enough money into their retirement accounts. Populists may not be bonkers, but they revel in being agitators and stirrers, fighting against a system that they regard as having served the elites for too long. If populism was a computer program, its volatility and unpredictability would be regarded as a feature, not a bug. To attack the establishment is to attack the institutions and rules that have sustained the status quo. If we could rank the world’s leaders on a spectrum, starting with the most calm and cerebral, and ending with the crankiest and craziest, populists would be at the end of the line. Remember from chapter 4 the nuclear war study “War with Crazy Types”? Populists are more likely to be “crazy types.” If anyone collapses the nuclear deterrence house of cards, it’s likely to be a populist. Divisive politics also acts as a counterweight against the sort of cooperation that is essential to long-run planning. Where politicians have taken significant actions to reduce long-term threats, it has often involved a measure of bipartisanship. A program to contain “loose nukes” after the breakup of the Soviet Union was driven by Democratic senator Nunn and Republican senator Richard Lugar. California’s 2006 cap-and-trade emissions reduction program was passed by a Democratic legislature and signed into law by Republican governor Arnold Schwarzenegger. But voters who believe their political opponents are “evil” or “animals” are less likely to support bipartisan collaboration on long-term issues. Populists thrive off chaos of their own making. But when external crises hit, populist leaders struggle. According to one study on crisis leadership, effective disaster response requires providing clear direction, putting public safety first, being compassionate toward victims, and learning lessons afterward.121 As COVID-19 showed, many populist leaders were erratic, put politics first, were unsympathetic toward the most vulnerable, and covered up their policy failings. The qualities that make populists electorally successful also make them abysmal crisis managers. We should no more expect populists to be good crisis leaders than we should expect jockeys to succeed at basketball. The characteristics of populists that threaten long-termism—anti-intellectual, anti-institutional, anti-international, and anti-irenic—are frequently celebrated by populists themselves. Populist talk show host Rush Limbaugh used to call government, academia, science, and media “the four corners of deceit.”122 For Limbaugh, hostility to intellectualism and institutions wasn’t a mark of shame, it was a badge of honor. For much of the postwar era, a centrist consensus in many advanced nations held that decisions should be guided by experts, globalization is fundamentally a force for good, established institutions deserve respect, and the media is an essential check on power. The rise of populism—driven primarily by jobs, snobs, race, pace, and luck—has upended these views. The greatest consequence of this transformation could be on the future. Populist politics risks exacerbating the catastrophic risks of nuclear war, pandemics, dangerous superintelligence, and climate change. But there is another risk too: that populist democrats become authoritarian demagogues—quashing democracy and ushering in a frightening future. It is to that danger that I now turn.
22,681
<h4>Global populism upsurge is bad—laundry list of impacts</h4><p><strong>Leigh 21</strong> Andrew Leigh 2021 “What's the Worst that Could Happen?: Existential Risk and Extreme Politics” (Ph.D. in Public Policy from the John F. Kennedy School of Government at Harvard University)//Elmer </p><p>Why do <u><strong><mark>populists</strong> <strong>pose a threat to long-termism</u></strong></mark>? <u><strong><mark>Because</u></strong> </mark>tackling <u><strong><mark>long-term threats requires</u></strong> </mark>four things: strong <u><strong><mark>science</u></strong></mark>, effective <u><strong><mark>institutions</strong></mark>, global <strong><mark>engagement</strong></mark>, <strong><mark>and</u></strong> </mark>a sense of <u><strong><mark>cooperation</u></strong> </mark>and order. Populists are anti-intellectual, anti-institutional, anti-international, and anti-irenic (“irenic” means to strive for peace and consensus). This is not an accident. Each of the four antis forms part of the electoral appeal of populism, just as each makes it impossible for populists to effectively address challenges to humanity’s future. First, <u><strong><mark>populists are anti-intellectual</u></strong></mark>. <u>Because populists view politics as a contest </u>between a pure mass of people and vile elite, their characterization of the elite often includes experts. <u>This</u> has <u>led to</u> a spate of <u>clashes between populist leaders and scientists</u>. According to the Union of Concerned Scientists, Trump attacked science more than 150 times.75 Research on child health and pollution, the environmental impacts of coal mining, and species extinction was ignored or criticized. In the 2017 “Sharpiegate” affair, the White House redrew a meteorologic map to make it consistent with an erroneous presidential tweet. Trump <u>called climate change</u> “mythical” and “<u>nonexistent</u>.” In a similar fashion, Bolsonaro has questioned his own government’s data on deforestation in the Amazon, while Dutch far-right leader Thierry Baudet rails against “climate change hysteria.” Not every populist is a climate denier, but <u>virtually all <strong><mark>climate deniers</strong> </mark>are populists</u>.76 One analysis of the twenty-one largest right-wing populist parties in Europe found that one-third were outright climate deniers, while many others were hostile to climate action.77 Right-wing populists make up 15 percent of the European Parliament, but account for around half of the votes against climate and energy resolutions. One study in the United Kingdom identified voters who held populist beliefs about politics, such as agreeing that people rather than politicians should make policy decisions, or that elected officials talk too much and take too little action.78 These populist voters were significantly less likely to agree that global warming is caused by human action and less likely to support measures to protect the environment. Importantly, this pattern held across the political spectrum; populism explains climate denial among both left- and right-wing voters. The <u><strong><mark>anti-vaccination</strong> </mark>movement</u>, with its conspiracy theories about large pharmaceutical companies, <u>has been bolstered</u> by populists. In Italy, the populist Five Star Movement criticized a 2017 law making it compulsory for children to be vaccinated against measles, mumps, and rubella, sometimes repeating falsehoods about the vaccine. In France, the populist National Rally party (formerly the National Front) condemned an increase in the number of mandatory childhood vaccines. Across Europe, the <u>rise of populist parties has been accompanied by an increase in <strong>anti-vaxxer sentiment</u></strong>. One in seven Europeans say that they do not believe vaccines are important, while half wrongly believe that vaccines can often cause serious side effects.79 As vaccination rates fell, the number of European measles cases more than doubled between 2011 and 2019.80 Confirming the role of politics, a study that analyzed data across fourteen European countries found a strong relationship between the share of people who vote for populist parties and the proportion who believe that vaccination is not important.81 Before becoming president, Trump expressed support for a prominent anti-vaxxer conspiracy theory: the debunked claim that vaccines cause autism. As president, Trump tweeted about the dangers of vaccines more than thirty times.82 It was much the same with COVID-19. Trump’s overconfidence led him initially to dismiss the coronavirus threat. In January 2020, he said, “We have it totally under control. It’s one person coming in from China, and we have it under control. It’s going to be just fine.” In February, he referred to coronavirus as a “new hoax” being peddled by the Democrats. Gainsaying the experts, Trump was dismissive of mask wearing, slowed down testing, and touted the ineffective drug hydroxychloroquine. It soon became clear that Trump saw the disease primarily in terms of politics rather than public health.83 As a satirical headline in the Onion put it, “Trump: ‘Even One Death That Makes Me Look Bad Is a Tragedy.’”84 Bolsonaro was similarly dismissive of medical expertise. He initially described coronavirus as a media “trick,” arguing that Brazilians were naturally immune to the disease. “The Brazilian needs to be studied,” said Bolsonaro. “He doesn’t catch anything. You see a guy jumping into sewage, diving in, right? Nothing happens to him. I think a lot of people were already infected in Brazil, weeks or months ago, and they already have the antibodies that help it not proliferate.” Bolsonaro urged the premature relaxation of physical distancing measures, supported street protests against quarantines, and fired two health ministers.85 Relative to population, Brazil has one of the highest COVID-19 death rates in the world.86 Like populist leaders Johnson and Trump, Bolsonaro contracted coronavirus himself. Three of Brazil’s 81 senators have died from the disease. Similarly, in Indonesia and the Philippines, populist leaders <u>sidelined technocrats and touted unproven health measures</u>. Widodo was slow to implement lockdowns in Indonesia, saying that he did not want to cause “panic” and claiming that lockdowns were ineffective. His ministers variously promoted prayer and a necklace made of eucalyptus as protections against COVID-19.87 In the Philippines, President Duterte advocated gasoline as a disinfectant and created a coronavirus task force led by retired generals rather than epidemiologists.88 Indonesia and the Philippines have among the highest rates of coronavirus deaths in the Asia-Pacific region.89 Hostility toward scientists and intellectuals shows up among supporters too. In a 2019 survey, 62 percent of Democrats—but only 44 percent of Republicans—agreed that scientists’ judgments are based solely on the facts.90 Populists’ <u>skepticism</u> of intellectuals also <u>manifests in support for <strong>debunked <mark>conspiracy theories</u></strong></mark>.91 A global survey of twenty-two thousand voters across nineteen democracies found that populist voters were far more likely to be conspiracy minded. Populists are more than twice as likely to think that global warming is a hoax. They are almost twice as likely to believe that AIDS was invented by the US Central Intelligence Agency, that supposedly harmful effects of vaccines are being hidden from the public, and that the US government knowingly helped the September 11 attackers. Populists are more likely to believe that alien contact is being hidden from the public. <u>Populist leaders</u> frequently <u>build political support by pushing conspiracy theories</u>. Among the falsehoods peddled by populist actors are that the Holocaust is a hoax, former German chancellor Angela Merkel is the secret daughter of Adolf Hitler, the European Union is resurrecting the Roman Empire as a communist superstate, and there is a worldwide cabal of Satan-worshipping pedophiles who rule the world (the QAnon theory).92 In November 2020, Georgia Republican Marjorie Taylor Greene was the first QAnon supporter to be elected to the US Congress.93 Half of all Republican voters believe one of QAnon’s key tenets: that top Democrats are involved in child sex trafficking.94 A majority of Republicans believe that the January 2021 assault on the United States Capitol was “mostly an antifa-inspired attack.”95 Second, <u><strong><mark>populists are</strong> <strong></mark>anti-institution</u></strong>. Campaigning as outsiders, populist leaders tend to be <u><strong><mark>suspicious of institutions</u></strong> </mark>such as the <u>bureaucracy, judiciary, and media</u>. Journalist Michael Lewis highlights the plethora of programs run by the two million people employed by the federal government, including child nutrition, veterans’ health, air traffic control, and national security. Yet the day after the 2016 election, Lewis writes, The hundreds of people who had prepared to brief the incoming Trump administration sat waiting. A day became a week and a week became a month . . . and no one showed up. The parking spots that had been set aside for Trump’s people remained empty, and the briefing books were never opened. You could walk into almost any department of the US government and hear people asking the same question: where were these people who were meant to be running the place?96 This approach to the federal bureaucracy characterized the Trump administration. By the time coronavirus struck, ten cabinet members had departed, and four-fifths of senior White House positions had turned over.97 Trump was on his fifth secretary of the Department of Homeland Security, his fourth national security adviser, and his third chief of staff. As journalists Jennifer Steinhauer and Zolan Kanno-Youngs note, “Between Mr. Trump’s history of firing people and the choice by many career officials and political appointees to leave, he now finds himself with a government riddled with vacancies, acting department chiefs and, in some cases, leaders whose professional backgrounds do not easily match up to the task of managing a pandemic.”98 Populists regard regulatory bodies and oversight mechanisms not as an appropriate check on power but rather as a creation of self-serving insiders. In Poland and Hungary, populist governments have changed the rules on the appointment of judges and imposed age limits to remove unwanted ones.99 Elsewhere, populists have encouraged lawbreaking. In Brazil and the Philippines, populist leaders advocate the extrajudicial murder of suspected criminals. Kenneth Roth, executive director of Human Rights Watch, fears that populism “threatens to reverse the accomplishments of the modern human rights movement” created in the aftermath of the atrocities of World War II.100 Universities—the institutional home of many intellectuals—are a particular focus of populist ire. Populists claim that university research is irrelevant to real-world problems. and teaching amounts to indoctrination. Colleges are accused of lacking legitimacy and being out of touch with popular opinion. Amid the populist takeover of the Republican Party, the share of Republicans who thought that universities had a negative effect on the country jumped by 22 percentage points between 2015 and 2019.101 Another trademark of populists are their attacks on the mainstream media—or what Palin dubbed the “lamestream media.” Describing journalists as “human scum,” “low life reporters,” “corrupt,” “dishonest,” and “the enemy of the people,” Trump sought to undercut the credibility of the press. As Chris Wallace of Fox News summed it up, “He has done everything he can to undercut the media, to try and delegitimize us, and I think his purpose is clear: to raise doubts, when we report critically about him and his administration, that we can be trusted.”102 Ethical journalism—with its adherence to accuracy, independence, impartiality, and public accountability—is an important check on the abuse of power. Without an ethical media, it becomes more difficult to have a conversation about the long term. The overall importance of institutions is reinforced by a four-country study that found people who were less trusting of national institutions were also less supportive of policies to protect the well-being of future generations.103 COVID-19 also reflected Trump’s undermining of institutions. Experts had long warned about the need for the United States to work with China on potential disease hot spots. As early as 2007, microbiologists warned that “coronaviruses are well known to undergo genetic recombination, which may lead to new genotypes and outbreaks.” They went on to note that “the presence of a large reservoir of SARS-CoV-like viruses in horseshoe bats, together with the culture of eating exotic mammals in southern China, is a time bomb.”104 Despite this, Trump reduced the number of China-based staff from the CDC by two-thirds during his first two years in office.105 In his proposed budgets prior to the pandemic, Trump sought to cut CDC funding by 10 to 20 percent, with a particular emphasis on reducing CDC funding for emerging diseases, global health, and public health preparedness.106 The Trump administration also shut down the entire global health security unit of the National Security Council.107 As a report from the Environmental Data and Governance Initiative put it, “[Trump’s] efforts to reduce spending have dramatically and consistently taken aim at programs most likely to reveal and tackle potential pandemic origin points around the world.”108 The problem wasn’t just underinvestment in global health. The United States is the only advanced nation without universal health coverage, despite spending more on health care as a share of the economy than any other nation in the world. The lack of universal health care is one reason the United States has experienced so many COVID deaths and suffered difficulties in rolling out the vaccine. Minorities were both more likely to contract COVID in 2020 and less likely to be vaccinated in 2021. Populist opposition to the institutional framework of universal health care made the impact of COVID more severe and more inequitable. Third, <u>populists are <strong>anti-international</u></strong>. Populist political slogans include “I Want My Country Back,” “Law and Border,” “Patriotism, Protection, and Prosperity,” “Finland for the Finns,” “Courage to Stand Up for Germany,” and “America First.” Populists typically distrust immigration, trade, and foreign investment. They tend to be <u>hostile toward global bodies</u> such as the World Bank, International Criminal Court, World Trade Organization, and United Nations. Many European populists advocate dissolving the European Union. Had he won a second term, experts anticipated that Trump would have tried to withdraw the United States from NATO, destabilizing the power balance in Europe.109 <u><strong><mark>During</u></strong> </mark>the <u><strong><mark>COVID</u></strong></mark>-19 crisis, <u><strong><mark>populists</u></strong> </mark>also <u><strong><mark>undermined international cooperation</u></strong></mark>. President <u>Trump</u> deliberately <u>fomented conflict with Chin</u>a, calling COVID-19 “the China Virus” and “Kung Flu.” The Trump administration withdrew from the World Health Organization and cut funding to the Pan-American Health Organization, Latin America’s leading health agency. President Bolsonaro bizarrely claimed that the World Health Organization was encouraging same-sex relationships in four-year-olds, sexual experiences for nine-year-olds, and masturbation in children from birth.110 <u><strong>Trump and Bolsonaro worked together to drive out 10,000 Cuban doctors and nurses from Brazil, Ecuador, Bolivia and El Salvador, increasing the death toll of the virus in impoverished communities</u></strong>.111 <u>When populists turn</u> their countries away <u>from international trade, they <strong><mark>make it harder to address</u></strong> </mark>the impact of <u><strong>future <mark>pandemics</u></strong></mark>. Over time, <u>nations</u> have <u>built</u> up <u>comparative advantages in</u> producing certain kinds of <u>medical supplies</u>. Switzerland is a major manufacturer of pharmaceuticals. Malaysia is a substantial exporter of surgical gloves. The United States is the world’s largest exporter of medical instruments. China is the world’s biggest producer of face masks. South Korea mass-produces in vitro diagnostics products. Nine-tenths of the personal protective equipment sold in the European Union is imported.112 Unfortunately, during the COVID-19 crisis, <u>over eighty countries implemented export controls</u> on medical supplies and medicines, <u>leading to </u>concerns about a <u>cascading <strong><mark>closure of</strong> </mark>the <strong><mark>global</strong> </mark>medical <strong><mark>trade</u></strong></mark>.113 Such a slide into autarky would be especially damaging for developing nations. The <u>rhetoric of self-reliance <strong>misleads</u></strong>; rather than banning trade, countries should build stockpiles. By allowing nations to specialize in what they do best, we end up with more production of higher-quality goods at cheaper prices—and a world that is better able to respond to disease threats. At its best, patriotism fosters a sense of pride in what our ancestors have built and a love of local communities. But the antiglobal movement frequently stokes unfounded fears. <u>Populists</u> often <u>create <mark>scapegoats</mark> out <mark>of minorit</mark>y communit<mark>ies</mark> and deploy racism to win votes</u>. <u>By</u> <u><strong>fostering a <mark>suspicion of foreigners</u></strong></mark>, and <u>separating the world into “us” and “them,” populists <strong><mark>make it harder to solve </mark>problems that cross international boundaries.</u></strong> By definition, <u><strong><mark>existential threats</u></strong> </mark>to humanity <u>are global problems</u>, and are much harder to solve when countries are unwilling to work together. <u>International <strong><mark>tensions</strong> <strong>increase</strong> </mark>the chances of <strong><mark>nuclear war </strong></mark>and <strong><mark>make it</strong> <strong></mark>more <mark>difficult to control bioterrorism</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong><mark>Anti-internationalism</u></strong> </mark>also <u><strong>raises the <mark>risks </mark>of <mark>a</strong></mark>rtificial <strong><mark>i</strong></mark>ntelligence</u>. In 2020, President Trump issued an executive order on artificial intelligence, which touched briefly on safety issues. But in implementing it, his administration <u>dismissed concerns</u> about <u>a machine that can “perform at the level of, or better than a human</u> agent,” saying that such issues were “beyond the scope” of the executive order.114 Trump’s chief technology officer, Michael Kratsios, stated the goal simply: for the United States to “win the race for artificial intelligence.”115 This is dangerously narrow-minded. <u>We need to move from international values statements on <strong>a</strong>rtificial <strong>i</strong>ntelligence to </u>binding<u> treaties</u>. But <u>such</u> global <u>agreements</u> could <u>founder on the tendency of populist governments to oppose international pacts</u>. <u>If populists prevent</u> the development of <u>global <strong>a</strong>rtificial <strong>i</strong>ntelligence safety standards, the world risks a <strong>race to the bottom.</u></strong> Fourth, <u>populists are <strong>anti-irenic</strong>.</u> Rather than striving for an irenic calm consensus, <u>they benefit from division and disagreement</u>. The politics of division requires that the temperature be at boiling point, the volume at full blast, the gas pedal flat to the floor. To persuade voters that politics is broken, there must be a villain. Populists thrive on bombast and blame—not compromise and community building. Throughout his four years as president, Trump averaged a false or misleading statement every ninety minutes, according to analysis by the Washington Post.116 Many of his lies were deliberately designed to provoke outrage. Describing the effect of his most incendiary statements, Trump said, “I used to watch it like a rocket ship when I put out a beauty.”117 A perpetual culture war not only served to mobilize the Republican base; it also engendered a sense of stress and anxiety that has been shown by psychologists to foster hostility toward outsiders.118 Two-fifths of Republicans think their political opponents are evil. One-fifth regard Democrats as animals.119 When stressed, people can develop tunnel vision—overvaluing short-term priorities at the expense of future needs. Scarcity, argue researchers Sendhil Mullainathan and Eldar Shafir, “makes us dumber. It makes us more impulsive. We must get by with less mind available, with less fluid intelligence.”120 Stressful politics and a perpetual state of fear can act as a “cognitive tax” on voters, promoting a politics of short-termism. If every day is a crisis, long-term planning is a luxury. In a battle, soldiers aren’t thinking about whether they’ve put enough money into their retirement accounts. Populists may not be bonkers, but they revel in being agitators and stirrers, fighting against a system that they regard as having served the elites for too long. If populism was a computer program, its volatility and unpredictability would be regarded as a feature, not a bug. To attack the establishment is to attack the institutions and rules that have sustained the status quo. If we could rank the world’s leaders on a spectrum, starting with the most calm and cerebral, and ending with the crankiest and craziest, populists would be at the end of the line. Remember from chapter 4 the nuclear war study “War with Crazy Types”? Populists are more likely to be “crazy types.” If anyone collapses the nuclear deterrence house of cards, it’s likely to be a populist. Divisive politics also acts as a counterweight against the sort of cooperation that is essential to long-run planning. Where politicians have taken significant actions to reduce long-term threats, it has often involved a measure of bipartisanship. A program to contain “loose nukes” after the breakup of the Soviet Union was driven by Democratic senator Nunn and Republican senator Richard Lugar. California’s 2006 cap-and-trade emissions reduction program was passed by a Democratic legislature and signed into law by Republican governor Arnold Schwarzenegger. But voters who believe their political opponents are “evil” or “animals” are less likely to support bipartisan collaboration on long-term issues. <u>Populists thrive off chaos</u> of their own making. <u>But when external crises hit, populist leaders struggle</u>. According to one study on crisis leadership, effective disaster response requires providing clear direction, putting public safety first, being compassionate toward victims, and learning lessons afterward.121 As COVID-19 showed, many populist leaders were erratic, put politics first, were unsympathetic toward the most vulnerable, and covered up their policy failings. The qualities that make populists electorally successful also make them abysmal crisis managers. We should no more expect populists to be good crisis leaders than we should expect jockeys to succeed at basketball. The characteristics of populists that threaten long-termism—anti-intellectual, anti-institutional, anti-international, and anti-irenic—are frequently celebrated by populists themselves. Populist talk show host Rush Limbaugh used to call government, academia, science, and media “the four corners of deceit.”122 For Limbaugh, hostility to intellectualism and institutions wasn’t a mark of shame, it was a badge of honor. For much of the postwar era, a centrist consensus in many advanced nations held that decisions should be guided by experts, globalization is fundamentally a force for good, established institutions deserve respect, and the media is an essential check on power. The rise of populism—driven primarily by jobs, snobs, race, pace, and luck—has upended these views. The greatest consequence of this transformation could be on the future. <u><strong><mark>Populist politics</strong> </mark>risks <strong><mark>exacerbating</strong> </mark>the <strong><mark>catastrophic risks of nuclear war, pandemics, dangerous superintelligence, and climate change</u></strong></mark>. But there is another risk too: that populist democrats become authoritarian demagogues—quashing democracy and ushering in a frightening future. It is to that danger that I now turn.</p>
1AC
1AC—Democracy
null
317,258
212
167,627
./documents/hsld22/SevenLakes/KiTr/SevenLakes-KiTr-Aff-TFA-State-Round-4.docx
987,408
A
TFA State
4
SanAng Dariyen Dale
Stanley
1AC - HR5140 1NC - 8 Seats CP, Instability DA 1AR - All 2NR - CP, Case 2AR - Case, CP
hsld22/SevenLakes/KiTr/SevenLakes-KiTr-Aff-TFA-State-Round-4.docx
2023-03-10 19:15:24
84,063
KiTr
Seven Lakes KiTr
null
Ki.....
Tr.....
null
null
26,945
SevenLakes
Seven Lakes
TX
null
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
4,774,345
Futurist imaginaries to prevent extinction are valuable.
Stevens ’18
Stevens ’18 [Tim; 2018; Senior Lecturer in Global Security at Kings College London; Millennium: Journal of International Studies, “Exeunt Omnes? Survival, Pessimism and Time in the Work of John H. Herz,” p. 283-302]
implicit recognition of an open yet linear temporality allowed him to imagine possible futures aligned with the survival ethic, whilst at the same time imagining futures in which humans become extinct pessimism about the latter did not preclude working towards the former. it was one thing to develop an ethics of survival but quite another to translate theory into practice. What was required was a collective, transnational and inherently interdisciplinary effort to address nuclear and environmental issues and to problematize notions of security in the context of nuclear geopolitics The principal responsibilities of researchers were two-fold. One, to raise awareness of survival issues in the minds of policy-makers and the public, and to demonstrate the link between political inaction now and its effect on subsequent human survival ‘In our age of global survival concerns, it should be the primary responsibility of scholars to engage in survival issues’ IR should not be afraid to think the worst, if the worst is at all possible, and to establish the various requirements of ‘a livable world’. Of significance here is not the appeal to futurism per se but the suggestion this is ‘the first time’ futurism is necessary to ensuring human survival This ‘promise for the future’ was not, however, a simple liberal view of a better future consonant with human progress experiences of Nazism and the Holocaust destroyed all remnants of any original belief in ‘inevitable progress 78 ditions to draw fir of international politics both cyclical and linear-progressive ways of perceiving historical time each marginalizes and diminishes the contingency of the social world in and through time, and the agency of political actors in effecting change the possibility of agency is a product of a temporality ‘neither temporally closed nor deterministic, neither cyclical nor linear-progressive; it is rooted in contingency’
imagine futures with ethic, whilst at the same time imagining futures in which humans become extinct pessimism did not preclude a collective effort to address nuclear issues and problematize geopolitics The responsibilities of researchers were two to raise awareness of survival in the minds of policy-makers inaction now and subsequent survival scholars should not be afraid to think the worst and establish the requirements of ‘a livable world’ futurism is necessary to survival This future’ was not a liberal view of progress cyclical ways of perceiving time marginalizes and diminishes contingency and the agency of actors in change
Herz explicitly combined, therefore, a political realism with an ethical idealism, resulting in what he termed a ‘survival ethic’.65 This was applicable to all humankind and its propagation relied on the generation of what he termed ‘world-consciousness’.66 Herz’s implicit recognition of an open yet linear temporality allowed him to imagine possible futures aligned with the survival ethic, whilst at the same time imagining futures in which humans become extinct. His pessimism about the latter did not preclude working towards the former. As Herz recognized, it was one thing to develop an ethics of survival but quite another to translate theory into practice. What was required was a collective, transnational and inherently interdisciplinary effort to address nuclear and environmental issues and to problematize notions of security, sustainability and survival in the context of nuclear geopolitics and the technological transformation of society. Herz proposed various practical ways in which young people in particular could become involved in this project. One idea floated in the 1980s, which would alarm many in today’s more cosmopolitan and culturally-sensitive IR, was for a Peace Corps-style ‘peace and development service’, which would ‘crusade’ to provide ‘something beneficial for people living under unspeakably sordid conditions’ in the ‘Third World’.67 He expended most of his energy, however, from the 1980s onwards, in thinking about and formulating ‘a new subdiscipline of the social sciences’, which he called ‘Survival Research’. 68 Informed by the survival ethic outlined above, and within the overarching framework of his realist liberal internationalism, Survival Research emerged as Herz’s solution to the shortcomings of academic research, public education and policy development in the face of global catastrophe.69 It was also Herz’s plea to scholars to venture beyond the ivory tower and become – excusing the gendered language of the time – ‘homme engagé, if not homme révolté’.70 His proposals for Survival Research were far from systematic but they reiterated his life-long concerns with nuclear and environmental issues, and with the necessity to act in the face of threats to human survival. The principal responsibilities of survival researchers were two-fold. One, to raise awareness of survival issues in the minds of policy-makers and the public, and to demonstrate the link between political inaction now and its effect on subsequent human survival. Two, to suggest and shape new attitudes more ‘appropriate to the solution of new and unfamiliar survival problems’, rather than relying on ingrained modes of thought and practice.71 The primary initial purpose, therefore, of Survival Research would be to identify scientific, sociocultural and political problems bearing on the possibilities of survival, and to begin to develop ways of overcoming these. This was, admittedly, non-specific and somewhat vague, but the central thrust of his proposal was clear: ‘In our age of global survival concerns, it should be the primary responsibility of scholars to engage in survival issues’.72 Herz considered IR an essential disciplinary contributor to this endeavour, one that should be promiscuous across the social and natural sciences. It should not be afraid to think the worst, if the worst is at all possible, and to establish the various requirements – social, economic, political – of ‘a livable world’.73 How this long-term project would translate into global policy is not specified but, consistent with his previous work, Herz identified the need for shifts in attitudes to and awareness of global problems and solutions. Only then would it be possible for ‘a turn round that demands leadership to persuade millions to change lifestyles and make the sacrifices needed for survival’. 74 Productive pessimism and temporality In 1976, shortly before he began compiling the ideas that would become Survival Research, Herz wrote: For the first time, we are compelled to take the futuristic view if we want to make sure that there will be future generations at all. Acceleration of developments in the decisive areas (demographic, ecological, strategic) has become so strong that even the egotism of après nous le déluge might not work because the déluge may well overtake ourselves, the living. Of significance here is not the appeal to futurism per se, although this is important, but the suggestion this is ‘the first time’ futurism is necessary to ensuring human survival. This is Herz the realist declaring a break with conventional realism: Herz is not bound to a cyclical vision of political or historical time in which events and processes reoccur over and again. His identification of nuclear weapons as an ‘absolute novum’ in international politics demonstrates this belief in the non-cyclical nature of humankind’s unfolding temporality.76 As Sylvest observes of Herz’s attitude to the nuclear revolution, ‘the horizons of meaning it produced installed a temporal break with the past, and simultaneously carried a promise for the future’. This ‘promise for the future’ was not, however, a simple liberal view of a better future consonant with human progress. His autobiography is clear that his experiences of Nazism and the Holocaust destroyed all remnants of any original belief in ‘inevitable progress’.78 His frustration at scientism, technocratic deception, and the brutal rationality of twentieth-century killing, all but demanded a rejection of the liberal dream and the inevitability of its consummation. If the ‘new age’ ushered in by nuclear weapons, he wrote, is characterized by anything, it is by its ‘indefiniteness of the age and the uncertainties of the future’; it was impossible under these conditions to draw firm conclusions about the future course of international politics.79 Instead, he recognised the contingency, precarity and fragility of international politics, and the ghastly tensions inherent to the structural core of international politics, the security dilemma. 80 Herz was uneasy with both cyclical and linear-progressive ways of perceiving historical time. The former ‘closed’ temporalities are endemic to versions of realist IR, the latter to post-Enlightenment narratives feeding liberal-utopian visions of international relations and those of Marxism.81 In their own ways, each marginalizes and diminishes the contingency of the social world in and through time, and the agency of political actors in effecting change. Simultaneously, each shapes the futures that may be imagined and brought into being. Herz recognised this danger. Whilst drawing attention to his own gloomy disposition, he warns that without care and attention, ‘the assumption may determine the event’.82 As a pessimist, Herz was alert to the hazard of succumbing to negativity, cynicism or resignation. E.H. Carr recognised this also, in the difference between the ‘deterministic pessimism’ of ‘pure’ realism and those realists ‘who have made their mark on history’; the latter may be pessimists but they still believe ‘human affairs can be directed and modified by human action and human thought’.83 Herz would share this anti-deterministic perspective with Carr. Moreover, the possibility of agency is a product of a temporality ‘neither temporally closed nor deterministic, neither cyclical nor linear-progressive; it is rooted in contingency’.
7,411
<h4>Futurist imaginaries to prevent extinction are <u>valuable</u>.</h4><p><strong>Stevens ’18</strong> [Tim; 2018; Senior Lecturer in Global Security at Kings College London; Millennium: Journal of International Studies, “Exeunt Omnes? Survival, Pessimism and Time in the Work of John H. Herz<u>,” p. 283-302]</p><p></u>Herz explicitly combined, therefore, a political realism with an ethical idealism, resulting in what he termed a ‘survival ethic’.65 This was applicable to all humankind and its propagation relied on the generation of what he termed ‘world-consciousness’.66 Herz’s <u>implicit recognition of an open yet linear temporality allowed him to <strong><mark>imagine</mark> possible <mark>futures</strong></mark> aligned <mark>with</mark> the <strong>survival <mark>ethic</strong>, whilst at the <strong>same time</strong> imagining futures in which <strong>humans become extinct</u></strong></mark>. His <u><strong><mark>pessimism</strong></mark> about the latter <strong><mark>did not preclude</strong></mark> working towards the former.</p><p></u>As Herz recognized, <u>it was one thing to develop an ethics of survival but quite another to translate theory into practice. What was required was <mark>a <strong>collective</strong></mark>, transnational and inherently<strong> interdisciplinary <mark>effort</strong> to address <strong>nuclear</mark> and environmental <mark>issues</strong> and</mark> to <mark>problematize</mark> notions of security</u>, sustainability and survival <u>in the context of <strong>nuclear <mark>geopolitics</u></strong></mark> and the technological transformation of society. Herz proposed various practical ways in which young people in particular could become involved in this project. One idea floated in the 1980s, which would alarm many in today’s more cosmopolitan and culturally-sensitive IR, was for a Peace Corps-style ‘peace and development service’, which would ‘crusade’ to provide ‘something beneficial for people living under unspeakably sordid conditions’ in the ‘Third World’.67 He expended most of his energy, however, from the 1980s onwards, in thinking about and formulating ‘a new subdiscipline of the social sciences’, which he called ‘Survival Research’.</p><p>68 Informed by the survival ethic outlined above, and within the overarching framework of his realist liberal internationalism, Survival Research emerged as Herz’s solution to the shortcomings of academic research, public education and policy development in the face of global catastrophe.69 It was also Herz’s plea to scholars to venture beyond the ivory tower and become – excusing the gendered language of the time – ‘homme engagé, if not homme révolté’.70 His proposals for Survival Research were far from systematic but they reiterated his life-long concerns with nuclear and environmental issues, and with the necessity to act in the face of threats to human survival. <u><mark>The</mark> <strong>principal <mark>responsibilities</strong> of</u></mark> survival <u><strong><mark>researchers</strong> were two</mark>-fold. One, <mark>to <strong>raise awareness</strong> of survival</mark> issues <mark>in the minds of <strong>policy-makers</strong> </mark>and the <strong>public</strong>, and to demonstrate the link between <strong>political <mark>inaction now</strong> and</mark> its effect on <strong><mark>subsequent</mark> human <mark>survival</u></strong></mark>. Two, to suggest and shape new attitudes more ‘appropriate to the solution of new and unfamiliar survival problems’, rather than relying on ingrained modes of thought and practice.71 The primary initial purpose, therefore, of Survival Research would be to identify scientific, sociocultural and political problems bearing on the possibilities of survival, and to begin to develop ways of overcoming these. This was, admittedly, non-specific and somewhat vague, but the central thrust of his proposal was clear: <u>‘In our age of global survival concerns, it should be the <strong>primary responsibility of <mark>scholars</strong></mark> to engage in survival issues’</u>.72 Herz considered <u>IR</u> an essential disciplinary contributor to this endeavour, one that should be promiscuous across the social and natural sciences. It <u><mark>should not be afraid to <strong>think the worst</strong></mark>, if the worst is at all possible, <mark>and</mark> to <strong><mark>establish the</mark> various <mark>requirements</u></strong></mark> – social, economic, political – <u><mark>of ‘a <strong>livable world</strong>’</mark>.</u>73 How this long-term project would translate into global policy is not specified but, consistent with his previous work, Herz identified the need for shifts in attitudes to and awareness of global problems and solutions. Only then would it be possible for ‘a turn round that demands leadership to persuade millions to change lifestyles and make the sacrifices needed for survival’.</p><p>74 Productive pessimism and temporality</p><p>In 1976, shortly before he began compiling the ideas that would become Survival Research, Herz wrote: </p><p>For the first time, we are compelled to take the futuristic view if we want to make sure that there will be future generations at all. Acceleration of developments in the decisive areas (demographic, ecological, strategic) has become so strong that even the egotism of après nous le déluge might not work because the déluge may well overtake ourselves, the living.</p><p> <u>Of significance here is not the appeal to futurism per se</u>, although this is important, <u>but the suggestion this is ‘the first time’ <mark>futurism is <strong>necessary to</mark> ensuring human <mark>survival</u></strong></mark>. This is Herz the realist declaring a break with conventional realism: Herz is not bound to a cyclical vision of political or historical time in which events and processes reoccur over and again. His identification of nuclear weapons as an ‘absolute novum’ in international politics demonstrates this belief in the non-cyclical nature of humankind’s unfolding temporality.76 As Sylvest observes of Herz’s attitude to the nuclear revolution, ‘the horizons of meaning it produced installed a temporal break with the past, and simultaneously carried a promise for the future’.</p><p> <u><mark>This</mark> ‘promise for the <mark>future’ was <strong>not</strong></mark>, however, <mark>a</mark> <strong>simple <mark>liberal view</strong> of</mark> a better future consonant with human progress</u>. His autobiography is clear that his <u>experiences of Nazism and the Holocaust destroyed all remnants of any original belief in ‘<strong>inevitable <mark>progress</u></strong></mark>’.<u>78 </u>His frustration at scientism, technocratic deception, and the brutal rationality of twentieth-century killing, all but demanded a rejection of the liberal dream and the inevitability of its consummation. If<u> </u>the ‘new age’ ushered in by nuclear weapons, he wrote, is characterized by anything, it is by its ‘indefiniteness of the age and the uncertainties of the future’; it was impossible under these con<u>ditions to draw fir</u>m conclusions about the future course<u> of international politics</u>.79 Instead, he recognised the contingency, precarity and fragility of international politics, and the ghastly tensions inherent to the structural core of international politics, the security dilemma.</p><p>80 Herz was uneasy with <u>both <strong><mark>cyclical</strong></mark> and <strong>linear-progressive <mark>ways</strong> of perceiving</mark> historical <mark>time</u></mark>. The former ‘closed’ temporalities are endemic to versions of realist IR, the latter to post-Enlightenment narratives feeding liberal-utopian visions of international relations and those of Marxism.81 In their own ways, <u>each <strong><mark>marginalizes</strong> and <strong>diminishes</strong></mark> the <mark>contingency</mark> of the social world in and through time, <mark>and the <strong>agency of</mark> political <mark>actors</strong> in <strong></mark>effecting <mark>change</u></strong></mark>. Simultaneously, each shapes the futures that may be imagined and brought into being. Herz recognised this danger. Whilst drawing attention to his own gloomy disposition, he warns that without care and attention, ‘the assumption may determine the event’.82 As a pessimist, Herz was alert to the hazard of succumbing to negativity, cynicism or resignation. E.H. Carr recognised this also, in the difference between the ‘deterministic pessimism’ of ‘pure’ realism and those realists ‘who have made their mark on history’; the latter may be pessimists but they still believe ‘human affairs can be directed and modified by human action and human thought’.83 Herz would share this anti-deterministic perspective with Carr. Moreover, <u>the <strong>possibility of agency</strong> is a product of a temporality ‘neither <strong>temporally closed</strong> nor <strong>deterministic</strong>, neither cyclical nor linear-progressive; it is <strong>rooted in contingency</strong>’</u>.</p>
1NC TOC Round 3
Case
Advantage
1,650
459
167,408
./documents/hsld22/SanMateo/YeRa/SanMateo-YeRa-Neg-Tournament-of-Champions-Round-3.docx
994,993
N
Tournament of Champions
3
Charlotte Latin EL
Zachary Siegel
1ac - undocuqueer 1nc - t framework, adv cp, da, standard text 1ar - all 2nr - standard text, da, case 2ar - case, t framework
hsld22/SanMateo/YeRa/SanMateo-YeRa-Neg-Tournament-of-Champions-Round-3.docx
2023-04-15 21:46:30
80,665
YeRa
San Mateo YeRa
null
Ye.....
Ra.....
null
null
27,080
SanMateo
San Mateo
CA
null
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
3,815,566
Warming is real, anthropogenic, and threatens extinction --- prefer new evidence that represents consensus
Griffin 15 )
Griffin 15 (David, Claremont philosophy professor, “The climate is ruined. So can civilization even survive?”, 4-14, http://www.cnn.com/2015/01/14/opinion/co2-crisis-griffin/)
climate scientists have become increasingly worried about the survival of civilization. For virtually all climatologists "are now convinced that global warming poses a clear and present danger to civilization." The climate crisis "threatens the survival of our civilization," said Pulitzer Prize-winner Ross Gelbspan. Mark Hertsgaard agrees saying that the continuation of global warming "would create planetary conditions all but certain to end civilization as we know it." The threat to civilization comes primarily from the increase of the level of carbon dioxide (CO2) in the atmosphere Because of the CO2 increase, the planet's average temperature has increased 0.85 degrees Celsius (1.5 degrees Fahrenheit). Although this increase may not seem much, it has already brought about serious changes. The burning of coal, oil, and natural gas has made the planet warmer than it had been since the rise of civilization 10,000 years ago. Civilization was made possible by the emergence about 12,000 years ago of the "Holocene" epoch, which turned out to be the Goldilocks zone - not too hot, not too cold. This catapult is dangerous, because we have no evidence civilization can long survive with significantly higher temperatures What would "a 4C world" be like? According to Kevin Anderson of the Tyndall Centre for Climate Change Research (at the University of East Anglia), "during New York's summer heat waves the warmest days would be around 10-12C (18-21.6F) hotter [than today's]." Moreover, he has said, above an increase of 4C only about 10% of the human population will survive. some scientists consider Anderson overly optimistic The main reason for pessimism is the fear that the planet's temperature may be close to a tipping point that would initiate a "low-end runaway greenhouse," involving "out-of-control amplifying feedbacks." This This result "would make most of the planet uninhabitable by humans." Moreover, many scientists believe that runaway global warming could occur much more quickly, because the rising temperature caused by CO2 could release massive amounts of methane (CH4), which is, during its first 20 years, 86 times more powerful than CO2 The resulting threat of runaway global warming may not be merely theoretical. Scientists have long been convinced that methane was central to the fastest period of global warming in geological history, which occurred 55 million years ago. Now a group of scientists have accumulated evidence that methane was also central to the greatest extinction of life thus far: the end-Permian extinction about 252 million years ago. What can be done then? Given the failure of political leaders to deal with the CO2 problem, it is now too late to prevent terrible developments. But it may -- just may -- be possible to keep global warming from bringing about the destruction of civilization. To have a chance, we must, as Hansen says, do everything possible to "keep climate close to the Holocene range" -- which means, mobilize the whole world to replace dirty energy with clean as soon as possible.
virtually all climatologists "are convinced warming poses a clear and present danger continuation "would create planetary conditions all but certain to end civilization This catapult is dangerous above an increase of 4C only about 10% of the human population will survive. some scientists consider Anderson overly optimistic "out-of-control amplifying feedbacks." make the planet uninhabitable rising temperature caused by CO2 could release methane which is, 86 times more powerful But it may be possible to keep warming from bringing about destruction we must do everything to "keep climate close to the Holocene range"
Although most of us worry about other things, climate scientists have become increasingly worried about the survival of civilization. For example, Lonnie Thompson, who received the U.S. National Medal of Science in 2010, said that virtually all climatologists "are now convinced that global warming poses a clear and present danger to civilization." Informed journalists share this concern. The climate crisis "threatens the survival of our civilization," said Pulitzer Prize-winner Ross Gelbspan. Mark Hertsgaard agrees, saying that the continuation of global warming "would create planetary conditions all but certain to end civilization as we know it." These scientists and journalists, moreover, are worried not only about the distant future but about the condition of the planet for their own children and grandchildren. James Hansen, often considered the world's leading climate scientist, entitled his book "Storms of My Grandchildren." The threat to civilization comes primarily from the increase of the level of carbon dioxide (CO2) in the atmosphere, due largely to the burning of fossil fuels. Before the rise of the industrial age, CO2 constituted only 275 ppm (parts per million) of the atmosphere. But it is now above 400 and rising about 2.5 ppm per year. Because of the CO2 increase, the planet's average temperature has increased 0.85 degrees Celsius (1.5 degrees Fahrenheit). Although this increase may not seem much, it has already brought about serious changes. The idea that we will be safe from "dangerous climate change" if we do not exceed a temperature rise of 2C (3.6F) has been widely accepted. But many informed people have rejected this assumption. In the opinion of journalist-turned-activist Bill McKibben, "the one degree we've raised the temperature already has melted the Arctic, so we're fools to find out what two will do." His warning is supported by James Hansen, who declared that "a target of two degrees (Celsius) is actually a prescription for long-term disaster." The burning of coal, oil, and natural gas has made the planet warmer than it had been since the rise of civilization 10,000 years ago. Civilization was made possible by the emergence about 12,000 years ago of the "Holocene" epoch, which turned out to be the Goldilocks zone - not too hot, not too cold. But now, says physicist Stefan Rahmstorf, "We are catapulting ourselves way out of the Holocene." This catapult is dangerous, because we have no evidence civilization can long survive with significantly higher temperatures. And yet, the world is on a trajectory that would lead to an increase of 4C (7F) in this century. In the opinion of many scientists and the World Bank, this could happen as early as the 2060s. What would "a 4C world" be like? According to Kevin Anderson of the Tyndall Centre for Climate Change Research (at the University of East Anglia), "during New York's summer heat waves the warmest days would be around 10-12C (18-21.6F) hotter [than today's]." Moreover, he has said, above an increase of 4C only about 10% of the human population will survive. Believe it or not, some scientists consider Anderson overly optimistic. The main reason for pessimism is the fear that the planet's temperature may be close to a tipping point that would initiate a "low-end runaway greenhouse," involving "out-of-control amplifying feedbacks." This condition would result, says Hansen, if all fossil fuels are burned (which is the intention of all fossil-fuel corporations and many governments). This result "would make most of the planet uninhabitable by humans." Moreover, many scientists believe that runaway global warming could occur much more quickly, because the rising temperature caused by CO2 could release massive amounts of methane (CH4), which is, during its first 20 years, 86 times more powerful than CO2. Warmer weather induces this release from carbon that has been stored in methane hydrates, in which enormous amounts of carbon -- four times as much as that emitted from fossil fuels since 1850 -- has been frozen in the Arctic's permafrost. And yet now the Arctic's temperature is warmer than it had been for 120,000 years -- in other words, more than 10 times longer than civilization has existed. According to Joe Romm, a physicist who created the Climate Progress website, methane release from thawing permafrost in the Arctic "is the most dangerous amplifying feedback in the entire carbon cycle." The amplifying feedback works like this: The warmer temperature releases millions of tons of methane, which then further raise the temperature, which in turn releases more methane. The resulting threat of runaway global warming may not be merely theoretical. Scientists have long been convinced that methane was central to the fastest period of global warming in geological history, which occurred 55 million years ago. Now a group of scientists have accumulated evidence that methane was also central to the greatest extinction of life thus far: the end-Permian extinction about 252 million years ago. Worse yet, whereas it was previously thought that significant amounts of permafrost would not melt, releasing its methane, until the planet's temperature has risen several degrees Celsius, recent studies indicate that a rise of 1.5 degrees would be enough to start the melting. What can be done then? Given the failure of political leaders to deal with the CO2 problem, it is now too late to prevent terrible developments. But it may -- just may -- be possible to keep global warming from bringing about the destruction of civilization. To have a chance, we must, as Hansen says, do everything possible to "keep climate close to the Holocene range" -- which means, mobilize the whole world to replace dirty energy with clean as soon as possible.
5,788
<h4>Warming is real, anthropogenic, and threatens extinction --- prefer <u>new evidence</u> that represents <u><strong>consensus</h4><p></u>Griffin 15 </strong>(David, Claremont philosophy professor, “The climate is ruined. So can civilization even survive?”, 4-14, http://www.cnn.com/2015/01/14/opinion/co2-crisis-griffin/<u><strong>)</p><p></u></strong>Although most of us worry about other things, <u>climate scientists have become increasingly worried about the survival of civilization. For</u> example, Lonnie Thompson, who received the U.S. National Medal of Science in 2010, said that <u><strong><mark>virtually all climatologists "are</mark> now <mark>convinced</mark> that global <mark>warming poses a clear and present danger </mark>to civilization." </u></strong>Informed journalists share this concern. <u>The climate crisis "threatens the survival of our civilization," said Pulitzer Prize-winner Ross Gelbspan. Mark Hertsgaard agrees</u>, <u><strong>saying that the <mark>continuation</mark> of global warming <mark>"would create planetary conditions all but certain to end civilization</mark> as we know it." </u></strong>These scientists and journalists, moreover, are worried not only about the distant future but about the condition of the planet for their own children and grandchildren. James Hansen, often considered the world's leading climate scientist, entitled his book "Storms of My Grandchildren." <u>The threat to civilization comes primarily from the increase of the level of carbon dioxide (CO2) in the atmosphere</u>, due largely to the burning of fossil fuels. Before the rise of the industrial age, CO2 constituted only 275 ppm (parts per million) of the atmosphere. But it is now above 400 and rising about 2.5 ppm per year. <u>Because of the CO2 increase, the planet's average temperature has increased 0.85 degrees Celsius (1.5 degrees Fahrenheit). Although this increase may not seem much, it has already brought about serious changes. </u>The idea that we will be safe from "dangerous climate change" if we do not exceed a temperature rise of 2C (3.6F) has been widely accepted. But many informed people have rejected this assumption. In the opinion of journalist-turned-activist Bill McKibben, "the one degree we've raised the temperature already has melted the Arctic, so we're fools to find out what two will do." His warning is supported by James Hansen, who declared that "a target of two degrees (Celsius) is actually a prescription for long-term disaster." <u>The burning of coal, oil, and natural gas has made the planet warmer than it had been since the rise of civilization 10,000 years ago. Civilization was made possible by the emergence about 12,000 years ago of the "Holocene" epoch, which turned out to be the Goldilocks zone - not too hot, not too cold. </u>But now, says physicist Stefan Rahmstorf, "We are catapulting ourselves way out of the Holocene." <u><strong><mark>This catapult is dangerous</mark>, because we have no evidence civilization can long survive with significantly higher temperatures</u></strong>. And yet, the world is on a trajectory that would lead to an increase of 4C (7F) in this century. In the opinion of many scientists and the World Bank, this could happen as early as the 2060s. <u>What would "a 4C world" be like? According to Kevin Anderson of the Tyndall Centre for Climate Change Research (at the University of East Anglia), "during New York's summer heat waves the warmest days would be around 10-12C (18-21.6F) hotter [than today's]." Moreover, he has said, <mark>above an increase of 4C only <strong>about 10% of the human population will survive.</mark> </u></strong>Believe it or not, <u><mark>some scientists consider Anderson overly optimistic</u></mark>. <u>The main reason for pessimism is the fear that the planet's temperature may be close to a tipping point that would initiate a "low-end runaway greenhouse," involving <mark>"out-of-control amplifying feedbacks." </mark>This</u> condition would result, says Hansen, if all fossil fuels are burned (which is the intention of all fossil-fuel corporations and many governments). <u><strong>This result "would <mark>make </mark>most of <mark>the planet uninhabitable </mark>by humans."</u></strong> <u>Moreover, many scientists believe that runaway global warming could occur much more quickly, because the <mark>rising temperature caused by CO2 could release </mark>massive amounts of <mark>methane </mark>(CH4), <mark>which is, </mark>during its first 20 years, <mark>86 times more powerful </mark>than CO2</u>. Warmer weather induces this release from carbon that has been stored in methane hydrates, in which enormous amounts of carbon -- four times as much as that emitted from fossil fuels since 1850 -- has been frozen in the Arctic's permafrost. And yet now the Arctic's temperature is warmer than it had been for 120,000 years -- in other words, more than 10 times longer than civilization has existed. According to Joe Romm, a physicist who created the Climate Progress website, methane release from thawing permafrost in the Arctic "is the most dangerous amplifying feedback in the entire carbon cycle." The amplifying feedback works like this: The warmer temperature releases millions of tons of methane, which then further raise the temperature, which in turn releases more methane. <u>The resulting threat of runaway global warming may not be merely theoretical. Scientists have long been convinced that methane was central to the fastest period of global warming in geological history, which occurred 55 million years ago. Now a group of scientists have accumulated evidence that methane was also central to the greatest extinction of life thus far: the end-Permian extinction about 252 million years ago. </u>Worse yet, whereas it was previously thought that significant amounts of permafrost would not melt, releasing its methane, until the planet's temperature has risen several degrees Celsius, recent studies indicate that a rise of 1.5 degrees would be enough to start the melting. <u>What can be done then? Given the failure of political leaders to deal with the CO2 problem, it is now too late to prevent terrible developments. <strong><mark>But it may</mark> -- just may -- <mark>be possible to keep</mark> global <mark>warming from bringing about</mark> the <mark>destruction</mark> of civilization. To have a chance, <mark>we must</mark>, as Hansen says, <mark>do everything</mark> possible <mark>to "keep climate close to the Holocene range"</mark> -- which means, mobilize the whole world to replace dirty energy with clean as soon as possible.</p></u></strong>
null
1AC
Relations
76,292
262
126,882
./documents/hspolicy16/MontgomeryBellAcademy/BrHa/Montgomery%20Bell%20Academy-Bradford-Harrington-Aff-Westminster-Round1.docx
662,867
A
Westminster
1
Carrollton AT
Bill Batterman
1AC MES 2NR Union QPQ CP
hspolicy16/MontgomeryBellAcademy/BrHa/Montgomery%20Bell%20Academy-Bradford-Harrington-Aff-Westminster-Round1.docx
null
56,190
BrHa
Montgomery Bell Academy BrHa
null
Wi.....
Br.....
Ja.....
Ha.....
20,211
MontgomeryBellAcademy
Montgomery Bell Academy
null
null
1,015
hspolicy16
HS Policy 2016-17
2,016
cx
hs
2
2,797,004
Trump’s blurred the offense-defense line, which is historically unprecedented.
Lee 19, Hudson Institute senior fellow, 4-3-2019, “Why a US Sale of Fighter Jets to Taiwan Matters,” Diplomat, https://thediplomat.com/2019/04/why-a-us-sale-of-fighter-jets-to-taiwan-matters/
John Lee 19, Hudson Institute senior fellow, 4-3-2019, “Why a US Sale of Fighter Jets to Taiwan Matters,” Diplomat, https://thediplomat.com/2019/04/why-a-us-sale-of-fighter-jets-to-taiwan-matters/
In late March, Bloomberg reported that U.S. President Donald Trump’s advisers had encouraged Taiwan to submit a formal request to buy up to 60 advanced F-16V fighter planes Even if the F-16V sale goes ahead, Taiwan’s new planes will not alter the military balance between China and Taiwan, nor dissuade the mainland from further provocations such as the median line flyover Since the Bill Clinton era, administrations have denied Taiwan’s request to purchase new fighter planes on the basis that the grey line from “defense” to “offense” might be crossed Under the Barack Obama administration, the decision to only offer Taipei upgrades to its aging F-16 A/B planes suggested to Beijing that de-escalating tensions arising from differences over Taiwan was the predominant mindset. the Trump administration has shown unprecedented willingness to escalate tensions with China over political, strategic, and economic differences If the sale of F-16V planes goes through, then, it is evidence that the mindset in Washington with respect to Taiwan has also changed and is less accepting of mainland sensibilities and demands. Such a sale would be an indication that preserving de facto Taiwanese independence is once more considered critical to U.S. and allied strategy when it comes to keeping the PLA confined to inside the so-called First Island Chain. That would be a significant blow to Xi Jinping’s plans Xi implied that “reunification” with Taiwan was a “historic task” he wanted to achieve during his tenure U.S. sale of F-16Vs to Taiwan — and all it implies — makes fulfillment of that task less likely took a great risk in abandoning the rhetoric and diplomacy of China’s “peaceful rise Xi is now being criticized domestically for overreach and miscalculation. It is speculated that the legitimacy of the Communist Party would not survive the “loss” of Taiwan. If the United States goes ahead with the sale of F-16Vs to Taiwan, then the pressure on a president will be immense.
Taiwan’s new planes will not alter the military balance the grey line from “defense” to “offense” might be crossed Trump has shown unprecedented willingness to escalate tensions with China the sale of F-16V planes would be an indication that Taiwanese independence is critical to U.S. strategy keeping the PLA confined to inside the First Island Chain. That would be a significant blow to Xi ’s plans Xi implied that “reunification” was a “historic task” Xi is being criticized the legitimacy of the Party would not survive the “loss” of Taiwan. the pressure will be immense.
In late March, Bloomberg reported that U.S. President Donald Trump’s advisers had encouraged Taiwan to submit a formal request to buy up to 60 advanced F-16V fighter planes. Any sale must still be approved by Congress and would be the first major aircraft purchase from the United States by Taiwan since 1992. During her visit to Hawaii last week, Taiwanese President Tsai Ing-wen confirmed that Taiwan had requested a purchase of new fighter jets from the United States. Days later, two Chinese fighter planes crossed the median line in the Taiwan Strait that divides China and Taiwan – the first time this has occurred for 20 years. Even if the F-16V sale goes ahead, Taiwan’s new planes will not alter the military balance between China and Taiwan, nor dissuade the mainland from further provocations such as the median line flyover. That is not Beijing’s primary concern, however. The most important calculation China must make is not the relative capabilities of the Taiwanese armed forces but how the United States will respond in the event of a crisis or conflict in the Taiwan Strait. Every clue with respect to uncovering U.S. intention is vital because U.S. intervention could tip the military balance against China in any such conflict. In any event, it guarantees the end of any “acceptable cost” outcome in the event of conflict for China. Under the United States’ 1979 Taiwan Relations Act, any attempt to forcibly determine Taiwan’s future is considered “a threat to peace and security of the Western Pacific and of grave concern to the United States.” To prevent that, Washington is obligated to sell “arms of a defensive character” to Taipei to allow the latter to defend itself and dissuade China from launching any military action. Since the Bill Clinton era, administrations have denied Taiwan’s request to purchase new fighter planes on the basis that the grey line from “defense” to “offense” might be crossed. Speaking from Hawaii, Tsai let the cat out of the bag when she said the purchase of advanced fourth generation fighters would “greatly enhance our land and air capabilities, strengthen military moral and show to the world the U.S. commitment to Taiwan’s defense.” It is the last line which sends shivers down the spine of mainland leaders. Since the Taiwan Relations Act came into force, the United States has deliberately embarked on a policy of “strategic ambiguity” with respect to its military commitments to Taiwan in the event the latter is attacked. Whether the United States intervenes is a matter of political judgment and strategic assessment. Under the Barack Obama administration, the decision to only offer Taipei upgrades to its aging F-16 A/B planes suggested to Beijing that de-escalating tensions arising from differences over Taiwan was the predominant mindset. In contrast, the Trump administration has shown unprecedented willingness to escalate tensions with China over political, strategic, and economic differences. The speech by Vice President Mike Pence last October at the Hudson Institute and the 2017 National Security Strategy pulled no punches in identifying China as a comprehensive rival to the United States. If the sale of F-16V planes goes through, then, it is evidence that the mindset in Washington with respect to Taiwan has also changed and is less accepting of mainland sensibilities and demands. Such a sale would be an indication that preserving de facto Taiwanese independence is once more considered critical to U.S. and allied strategy when it comes to keeping the PLA confined to inside the so-called First Island Chain. That would be a significant blow to Chinese President Xi Jinping’s plans. In a wide-ranging speech on Taiwan in January to mark the 40th anniversary of the “Message to Compatriots in Taiwan” delivered to the 1978 National People’s Congress, Xi implied that “reunification” with Taiwan was a “historic task” he wanted to achieve during his tenure. A U.S. sale of F-16Vs to Taiwan — and all it implies — makes fulfillment of that task less likely. Finally, the strength of American support for Taiwan will influence how other nations respond to persistent Chinese attempts to reduce international space within which Taiwan can act as a de facto sovereign entity. The most important regional relationship for Taiwan is with Japan, which has emerged under Shinzo Abe as the political, strategic, and economic leader among democratic Asian nations. On issues such as the Trans-Pacific Partnership, Tokyo has shown initiative when Washington has been found wanting. The Japanese leader has emerged as one of the few regional countries to have established a strong personal relationship with Taiwan’s Tsai and is widely seen as the most pro-Taiwan leaders amongst U.S. allies in the region. Even then, Abe’s room to move is dependent on the extent to which the United States is willing to defend Taipei’s desire to behave as a de facto sovereign entity. If it is confirmed that Washington is moving to a more robust approach with respect to cross-strait relations, Japan, Australia and others will follow. Xi is already under internal pressure from the global pushback against his flagship policies such as the Belt and Road Initiative and “Made in China 2025.” China has lost goodwill with neighboring states over its actions in the East and South China Seas and along the disputed border with India. It is in the middle of an economic war with the United States while the European Union and Japan are openly criticizing China for violations of economic rules and norms, including the systematic theft of intellectual property by Chinese state-owned firms and “national champions.” Xi took a great risk in abandoning the rhetoric and diplomacy of China’s “peaceful rise,” which was promulgated by his predecessor Hu Jintao. Previously admired for his iron determination to achieve China’s great “rejuvenation,” Xi is now being criticized domestically for overreach and miscalculation. It is speculated that the legitimacy of the Communist Party would not survive the “loss” of Taiwan. If the United States goes ahead with the sale of F-16Vs to Taiwan, then the pressure on a president who has embarked on an unprecedented “anti-corruption campaign” to silence political enemies and doubters will be immense.
6,301
<h4>Trump’s blurred the offense-defense line, which is historically unprecedented.</h4><p>John <strong>Lee 19<u>, Hudson Institute senior fellow, 4-3-2019, “Why a US Sale of Fighter Jets to Taiwan Matters,” Diplomat, https://thediplomat.com/2019/04/why-a-us-sale-of-fighter-jets-to-taiwan-matters/</p><p></strong>In late March, Bloomberg reported that U.S. President Donald Trump’s advisers had encouraged Taiwan to submit a formal request to buy up to 60 advanced F-16V fighter planes</u>. Any sale must still be approved by Congress and would be the first major aircraft purchase from the United States by Taiwan since 1992. During her visit to Hawaii last week, Taiwanese President Tsai Ing-wen confirmed that Taiwan had requested a purchase of new fighter jets from the United States. Days later, two Chinese fighter planes crossed the median line in the Taiwan Strait that divides China and Taiwan – the first time this has occurred for 20 years. <u>Even if the F-16V sale goes ahead, <mark>Taiwan’s new planes will not alter the military balance</mark> between China and Taiwan, nor dissuade the mainland from further provocations such as the median line flyover</u>. That is not Beijing’s primary concern, however. The most important calculation China must make is not the relative capabilities of the Taiwanese armed forces but how the United States will respond in the event of a crisis or conflict in the Taiwan Strait. Every clue with respect to uncovering U.S. intention is vital because U.S. intervention could tip the military balance against China in any such conflict. In any event, it guarantees the end of any “acceptable cost” outcome in the event of conflict for China. Under the United States’ 1979 Taiwan Relations Act, any attempt to forcibly determine Taiwan’s future is considered “a threat to peace and security of the Western Pacific and of grave concern to the United States.” To prevent that, Washington is obligated to sell “arms of a defensive character” to Taipei to allow the latter to defend itself and dissuade China from launching any military action. <u>Since the Bill Clinton era, administrations have denied Taiwan’s request to purchase new fighter planes on the basis that <mark>the grey line from “defense” to “offense” might be crossed</u></mark>. Speaking from Hawaii, Tsai let the cat out of the bag when she said the purchase of advanced fourth generation fighters would “greatly enhance our land and air capabilities, strengthen military moral and show to the world the U.S. commitment to Taiwan’s defense.” It is the last line which sends shivers down the spine of mainland leaders. Since the Taiwan Relations Act came into force, the United States has deliberately embarked on a policy of “strategic ambiguity” with respect to its military commitments to Taiwan in the event the latter is attacked. Whether the United States intervenes is a matter of political judgment and strategic assessment. <u>Under the Barack Obama administration, the decision to only offer Taipei upgrades to its aging F-16 A/B planes suggested to Beijing <strong>that de-escalating tensions</strong> arising from differences over Taiwan was the predominant mindset. </u>In contrast, <u>the <mark>Trump</mark> administration <mark>has shown <strong>unprecedented willingness</strong> <strong>to escalate tensions</strong> with China</mark> over political, strategic, and economic</u> <u>differences</u>. The speech by Vice President Mike Pence last October at the Hudson Institute and the 2017 National Security Strategy pulled no punches in identifying China as a comprehensive rival to the United States. <u>If <mark>the sale of F-16V planes</mark> goes through, then, it is evidence that the mindset in Washington with respect to Taiwan has also changed and is</u> <u>less accepting of mainland sensibilities and demands.</u> <u><strong>Such a sale <mark>would be an indication that</mark> preserving de facto <mark>Taiwanese independence is</mark> once more considered <mark>critical to U.S.</mark> and allied <mark>strategy</u></strong></mark> <u>when it comes to <mark>keeping the PLA <strong>confined to inside the</mark> so-called <mark>First Island Chain</strong>. <strong>That would be a significant blow to</mark> </u></strong>Chinese President <u><strong><mark>Xi</mark> Jinping<mark>’s plans</u></strong></mark>. In a wide-ranging speech on Taiwan in January to mark the 40th anniversary of the “Message to Compatriots in Taiwan” delivered to the 1978 National People’s Congress, <u><mark>Xi implied that “reunification”</mark> with Taiwan <mark>was a “historic task”</mark> he wanted to achieve during his tenure</u>. A <u>U.S. sale of F-16Vs to Taiwan — and all it implies — makes fulfillment <strong>of that task less likely</u></strong>. Finally, the strength of American support for Taiwan will influence how other nations respond to persistent Chinese attempts to reduce international space within which Taiwan can act as a de facto sovereign entity. The most important regional relationship for Taiwan is with Japan, which has emerged under Shinzo Abe as the political, strategic, and economic leader among democratic Asian nations. On issues such as the Trans-Pacific Partnership, Tokyo has shown initiative when Washington has been found wanting. The Japanese leader has emerged as one of the few regional countries to have established a strong personal relationship with Taiwan’s Tsai and is widely seen as the most pro-Taiwan leaders amongst U.S. allies in the region. Even then, Abe’s room to move is dependent on the extent to which the United States is willing to defend Taipei’s desire to behave as a de facto sovereign entity. If it is confirmed that Washington is moving to a more robust approach with respect to cross-strait relations, Japan, Australia and others will follow. Xi is already under internal pressure from the global pushback against his flagship policies such as the Belt and Road Initiative and “Made in China 2025.” China has lost goodwill with neighboring states over its actions in the East and South China Seas and along the disputed border with India. It is in the middle of an economic war with the United States while the European Union and Japan are openly criticizing China for violations of economic rules and norms, including the systematic theft of intellectual property by Chinese state-owned firms and “national champions.” Xi <u>took a great risk in abandoning the rhetoric and diplomacy of China’s “peaceful rise</u>,” which was promulgated by his predecessor Hu Jintao. Previously admired for his iron determination to achieve China’s great “rejuvenation,” <u><mark>Xi is </mark>now <mark>being criticized</mark> domestically for overreach and miscalculation. It is speculated that <mark>the legitimacy of the</mark> Communist <mark>Party would not survive the “loss” of Taiwan.</mark> If the<strong> United States goes ahead with the sale of F-16Vs to Taiwan, then <mark>the pressure</mark> on a president </u></strong>who has embarked on an unprecedented “anti-corruption campaign” to silence political enemies and doubters <u><strong><mark>will be immense.</p></u></strong></mark>
1AC – Taiwan
1AC – Taiwan War
null
68,015
403
88,536
./documents/hspolicy19/RowlandHall/DoGu/Rowland%20Hall-Doctorman-Gushin-Aff-7%20-%20Copper%20Classic-Round6.docx
719,965
A
7 - Copper Classic
6
Meadows NY
Michael, Joshua
1AC - Taiwan 1NC - - Cap K 2NR - - Cap K
hspolicy19/RowlandHall/DoGu/Rowland%20Hall-Doctorman-Gushin-Aff-7%20-%20Copper%20Classic-Round6.docx
null
61,448
DoGu
Rowland Hall DoGu
null
St.....
Do.....
Ad.....
Gu.....
21,405
RowlandHall
Rowland Hall
UT
null
1,018
hspolicy19
HS Policy 2019-20
2,019
cx
hs
2
2,765,849
Absent accommodation, spirals escalate into military conflict.
Swaine 19
Michael D. Swaine 19, senior fellow at the Carnegie Endowment for International Peace and one of the most prominent American analysts in Chinese security studies., 2-21-2019, "The Deepening U.S.-China Crisis: Origins and Solutions," Carnegie Endowment for International Peace, https://carnegieendowment.org/2019/02/21/deepening-u.s.-china-crisis-origins-and-solutions-pub-78429
The ugly dynamic of growing suspicion and worst-case assumptions is increasing the likelihood of future U.S.-China political or military crises in Asia The deepening suspicion and hostility in the relationship is occurring during, and (in part) as a result of, a shifting balance of This negative turn also reflects a general failure to resolve several contentious issues in the region, including Taiwan I believe that China’s continued growth in military and economic power and resulting relative decline in U.S. maritime predominance will eventually create an unstable rough parity This could cause China to overestimate its leverage on contentious issues such as Taiwan it could cause the United States to overreact partly to disabuse China and others of the notion that the United States is losing its dominant position. Without adequate communication and a clear sense of each other’s red lines, and without reassuring understandings on limits and intentions, such miscalculations could easily escalate into tests of relative resolve Although Beijing and Washington could perhaps avoid letting such a crisis devolve into actual military conflict, even a major nonviolent confrontation could severely, and perhaps irreparably, damage U.S.-China relations well beyond anything seen thus far, producing untold shocks to the global economy and both regional and global security Needless to say, if such views became policy, the U.S. One China policy would collapse, along with the original basis for normalized relations with Beijing. The result could be a military conflict this should lead the two countries to accept the need for a stable (and real) balance in Asia and a defusing of the most likely sources of conflict through mutual accommodation Such a mentality should take the place of what currently appear to be U.S. efforts to deepen strategic competition through a largely futile attempt to stay well ahead of China in the region while isolating Beijing economically.
suspicion is increasing the likelihood of U.S.-China crises as a result of failure to resolve Taiwan China’s continued growth in military and economic power and decline in U.S. maritime predominance, will eventually create an unstable rough parity This could cause China to overestimate its leverage on Taiwan it could cause the U S to overreact without reassuring understandings on intentions miscalc escalate to tests of relative resolve result could be a military conflict this should lead to stable balance in Asia and a defusing of conflict through mutual accommodation
The ugly dynamic of growing suspicion and worst-case assumptions is increasing the likelihood of future U.S.-China political or military crises in Asia, crises that could in turn eventually propel the two sides into a Cold War or worse. The deepening suspicion and hostility in the relationship is occurring during, and (in part) as a result of, a shifting balance of power in Asia within the First Island Chain. This negative turn also reflects a general failure to resolve several contentious issues in the region, including the Korean Peninsula; Taiwan; maritime disputes; and military-related intelligence, surveillance, and reconnaissance activities. I believe that China’s continued growth in military and economic power and influence in Asia, and the resulting relative decline in U.S. maritime predominance, will eventually create an unstable rough parity between China and U.S./allied states within the First Island Chain along China’s maritime periphery (within approximately 1,500 kilometers of the country’s coast). This could cause China to overestimate its leverage and ability to advance its interests on contentious and provocative issues such as Taiwan and maritime sovereignty disputes. At the same time, it could also cause the United States and Japan to overreact to such behavior, partly to disabuse China and others of the notion that the United States is losing its dominant position. Without adequate communication and a clear sense of each other’s red lines, and without reassuring understandings on limits and intentions, such miscalculations could easily escalate into tests of relative resolve, with neither side willing to make accommodations to reach a middle ground. Although Beijing and Washington could perhaps avoid letting such a crisis devolve into actual military conflict, even a major nonviolent confrontation could severely, and perhaps irreparably, damage U.S.-China relations well beyond anything seen thus far, producing untold shocks to the global economy and both regional and global security. Under present conditions, the issue of Taiwan is particularly concerning. Given the current and worsening U.S. trend toward a zero-sum strategic competition with Beijing in virtually all areas, it is quite possible that anti-China zealots in or around the U.S. government could successfully argue that Washington should start regarding Taiwan as a strategic asset that it should deny China. These sentiments are already found among defense analysts in the United States and Japan. Needless to say, if such views became policy, the U.S. One China policy would collapse, along with the original basis for normalized relations with Beijing. The result could be a military conflict. I am certainly not predicting such an outcome. But I am less confident today than I was a few years ago that it can be avoided. HOW TO SALVAGE CONSTRUCTIVE U.S.-CHINA TIES What should policymakers do about this troubling state of affairs? First, serious, influential individuals in both countries (and not just experts on U.S.-China relations) need to speak out more forcefully. They need to call for an end to reckless rhetoric, soothing propagandistic utterances about win-win outcomes, and mild, half measures for dealing with the serious sources of discontent and suspicion in the relationship. For its part, in the near term, China needs to focus like a laser on dealing with the sources of Western businesses’ discontent and cyber espionage, while indicating a clear willingness, through actions and not just words, to involve Western capitals and business interests in Chinese economic enterprises such as the Belt and Road Initiative. Such actions, along with the efforts of U.S. state and local officials to strengthen close economic ties with China, could contribute greatly to reestablishing the U.S. business community as a major pillar of the U.S.-China relationship. Meanwhile, the U.S. Congress should hold hearings on the future strategic balance in Asia and its implications for U.S. policy. This exercise should involve a full assessment of how medium- and long-term changes in the military, economic, political/diplomatic, and soft-power resources that the United States, China, and other Asian states possess will likely affect regional stability, especially in terms of changing levels of risk tolerance and regional threat perceptions. The point of this assessment would be to confirm and define more clearly the power shift occurring in Asia and to determine the most feasible and effective policy options. In my view, this should lead the two countries to accept the need for a stable (and real) balance in Asia and a defusing of the most likely sources of conflict through mutual accommodation, alongside genuine efforts to integrate the region economically. Such a mentality should take the place of what currently appear to be U.S. efforts to deepen strategic competition through a largely futile attempt to stay well ahead of China in the region while isolating Beijing economically.
5,029
<h4>Absent accommodation, spirals escalate into military conflict. </h4><p>Michael D. <strong>Swaine 19<u></strong>, senior fellow at the Carnegie Endowment for International Peace and one of the most prominent American analysts in Chinese security studies., 2-21-2019, "The Deepening U.S.-China Crisis: Origins and Solutions," Carnegie Endowment for International Peace, https://carnegieendowment.org/2019/02/21/deepening-u.s.-china-crisis-origins-and-solutions-pub-78429</p><p>The ugly dynamic of growing <mark>suspicion</mark> and worst-case assumptions <mark>is increasing the likelihood of</mark> future <mark>U.S.-China</mark> political or military <mark>crises</mark> in Asia</u>, crises that could in turn eventually propel the two sides into a Cold War or worse. <u>The deepening suspicion and hostility in the relationship is occurring during, and (in part) <mark>as a result of</mark>, a shifting balance of</u> power in Asia within the First Island Chain. <u>This negative turn also reflects a general <mark>failure to resolve</mark> several contentious issues in the region, including </u>the Korean Peninsula; <u><mark>Taiwan</u></mark>; maritime disputes; and military-related intelligence, surveillance, and reconnaissance activities. <u>I believe that <mark>China’s continued growth in military and economic power</u></mark> and influence in Asia, <u><mark>and</u></mark> the <u>resulting relative <mark>decline in U.S. maritime predominance</u>, <u><strong>will eventually create an unstable rough parity</mark> </u></strong>between China and U.S./allied states within the First Island Chain along China’s maritime periphery (within approximately 1,500 kilometers of the country’s coast). <u><mark>This could cause China to overestimate its leverage</u></mark> and ability to advance its interests <u><mark>on</mark> contentious</u> and provocative <u>issues</u> <u>such as <mark>Taiwan</u></mark> and maritime sovereignty disputes. At the same time, <u><mark>it could</u></mark> also <u><mark>cause the U</mark>nited <mark>S</mark>tates</u> and Japan <u><strong><mark>to overreact</u></strong></mark> to such behavior, <u>partly to disabuse China and others of the notion that the United States is losing its dominant position. Without adequate communication and a clear sense of each other’s red lines, <strong>and <mark>without reassuring understandings on</mark> limits and <mark>intentions</mark>, such <mark>miscalc</mark>ulations could easily <mark>escalate </mark>in<mark>to tests of relative resolve</u></strong></mark>, with neither side willing to make accommodations to reach a middle ground. <u>Although Beijing and Washington could perhaps avoid letting such a crisis devolve into <strong>actual military conflict</strong>, even a major nonviolent confrontation could severely, and perhaps irreparably, <strong>damage U.S.-China relations well beyond anything seen thus far, producing untold shocks to the global economy and both regional and global security</u></strong>. Under present conditions, the issue of Taiwan is particularly concerning. Given the current and worsening U.S. trend toward a zero-sum strategic competition with Beijing in virtually all areas, it is quite possible that anti-China zealots in or around the U.S. government could successfully argue that Washington should start regarding Taiwan as a strategic asset that it should deny China. These sentiments are already found among defense analysts in the United States and Japan. <u>Needless to say, if such views became policy, the U.S. One China policy would collapse, along with the original basis for normalized relations with Beijing. <strong>The <mark>result could be a military conflict</u></strong></mark>. I am certainly not predicting such an outcome. But I am less confident today than I was a few years ago that it can be avoided. HOW TO SALVAGE CONSTRUCTIVE U.S.-CHINA TIES What should policymakers do about this troubling state of affairs? First, serious, influential individuals in both countries (and not just experts on U.S.-China relations) need to speak out more forcefully. They need to call for an end to reckless rhetoric, soothing propagandistic utterances about win-win outcomes, and mild, half measures for dealing with the serious sources of discontent and suspicion in the relationship. For its part, in the near term, China needs to focus like a laser on dealing with the sources of Western businesses’ discontent and cyber espionage, while indicating a clear willingness, through actions and not just words, to involve Western capitals and business interests in Chinese economic enterprises such as the Belt and Road Initiative. Such actions, along with the efforts of U.S. state and local officials to strengthen close economic ties with China, could contribute greatly to reestablishing the U.S. business community as a major pillar of the U.S.-China relationship. Meanwhile, the U.S. Congress should hold hearings on the future strategic balance in Asia and its implications for U.S. policy. This exercise should involve a full assessment of how medium- and long-term changes in the military, economic, political/diplomatic, and soft-power resources that the United States, China, and other Asian states possess will likely affect regional stability, especially in terms of changing levels of risk tolerance and regional threat perceptions. The point of this assessment would be to confirm and define more clearly the power shift occurring in Asia and to determine the most feasible and effective policy options. In my view, <u><mark>this should lead</mark> the two countries <mark>to</mark> accept the need for a <mark>stable</mark> (and real) <mark>balance in Asia and a defusing of</mark> the most likely sources of <mark>conflict through <strong>mutual accommodation</u></strong></mark>, alongside genuine efforts to integrate the region economically. <u>Such a mentality should take the place of what currently appear to be U.S. efforts to deepen strategic competition through a largely futile attempt to stay well ahead of China in the region while isolating Beijing economically.</p></u>
1ac – Samford – Flash
Taiwan War
null
401,886
264
87,698
./documents/hspolicy19/MontgomeryBell/BoYo/Montgomery%20Bell-Bozza-Young-Aff-Samford-Round3.docx
717,489
A
Samford
3
Riverwood JP
Pandey
1ac - taiwan v3 1nc - psychoanalysis mba cannons r racist k 2nr - psychoanalysis
hspolicy19/MontgomeryBell/BoYo/Montgomery%20Bell-Bozza-Young-Aff-Samford-Round3.docx
null
61,148
BoYo
Montgomery Bell BoYo
null
Be.....
Bo.....
Ja.....
Yo.....
21,322
MontgomeryBell
Montgomery Bell
TN
null
1,018
hspolicy19
HS Policy 2019-20
2,019
cx
hs
2
2,377,424
Psychoanalysis is both falsifiable and accurate – studies prove.
Grant & Harari 5
Grant & Harari 5 (Don and Edwin, psychiatrists, “Psychoanalysis, science and the seductive theory of Karl Popper,” Australian and New Zealand Journal of Psychiatry)
Attacks on psychoanalysis and the long-term therapies derived from it, have enjoyed a long history and much publicity [1-4]. Yet, the justification for such attacks has been challenged on many grounds, including their methodology [5] and the empirically demonstrable validity of core psychoanalytic concepts neuroscience research indicates likely neurological correlates for many key clinically derived psychoanalytic concepts such as self-coherence [8], repression [9] and projective identification [10]. the effectiveness of psychoanalysis and its derivative therapies has been supported by empirical research for DSM axis II pathology what exactly is being attacked is often unclear
Attacks on psychoanalysis has been challenged on methodology and empirical validity of psychoanalytic concepts neuroscience research indicates psychoanalytic concepts self-coherence repression and projective identification psychoanalysis has been supported by empirical research for DSM axis II pathology
Attacks on psychoanalysis and the long-term therapies derived from it, have enjoyed a long history and much publicity [1-4]. Yet, the justification for such attacks has been challenged on many grounds, including their methodology [5] and the empirically demonstrable validity of core psychoanalytic concepts [6,7]. Also, burgeoning neuroscience research, some of which is summarized below, indicates likely neurological correlates for many key clinically derived psychoanalytic concepts such as self-coherence [8], repression [9] and projective identification [10]. Furthermore, the effectiveness of psychoanalysis and its derivative therapies has been supported by empirical research [11,12], particularly for patients with DSM axis II pathology. Despite this evidence, the attacks on psychoanalysis continue unabated, not only from some psychiatrists [13,14] but also from the highest levels of politics and health bureaucrats [15], although what exactly is being attacked is often unclear.
992
<h4>Psychoanalysis is both falsifiable and accurate – studies prove.</h4><p><strong>Grant & Harari 5</strong> (Don and Edwin, psychiatrists, “Psychoanalysis, science and the seductive theory of Karl Popper,” Australian and New Zealand Journal of Psychiatry)</p><p><u><strong><mark>Attacks on psychoanalysis</mark> and the long-term therapies derived from it, have enjoyed a long history and much publicity [1-4]. Yet, the justification for such attacks <mark>has been challenged on</mark> many grounds, including their <mark>methodology</mark> [5] <mark>and</mark> the <mark>empirical</mark>ly demonstrable <mark>validity of</mark> core <mark>psychoanalytic concepts</u></strong></mark> [6,7]. Also, burgeoning <u><strong><mark>neuroscience</u></strong> <u><strong>research</u></strong></mark>, some of which is summarized below, <u><strong><mark>indicates</mark> likely neurological correlates for many key clinically derived <mark>psychoanalytic concepts </mark>such as <mark>self-coherence</mark> [8], <mark>repression</mark> [9] <mark>and projective identification</mark> [10].</u></strong> Furthermore, <u><strong>the effectiveness of <mark>psychoanalysis</mark> and its derivative therapies <mark>has been supported by empirical research</u></strong></mark> [11,12], particularly <u><strong><mark>for</u></strong></mark> patients with <u><strong><mark>DSM axis II pathology</u></strong></mark>. Despite this evidence, the attacks on psychoanalysis continue unabated, not only from some psychiatrists [13,14] but also from the highest levels of politics and health bureaucrats [15], although <u><strong>what exactly is being attacked is often unclear</u></strong>.</p>
1NC R1 St. Mark’s 2021
1
null
12,240
210
75,899
./documents/hsld20/StrakeJesuit/Ge/Strake%20Jesuit-Georges-Neg-Heart%20of%20Texas-Round1.docx
874,331
N
Heart of Texas
1
Greenhill RM
Claudia Ribera
1AC - LAWs v2 1NC - Disability K AC 1AR - AC K 2NR - AC 2AR - AC
hsld20/StrakeJesuit/Ge/Strake%20Jesuit-Georges-Neg-Heart%20of%20Texas-Round1.docx
null
73,798
JoGe
Strake Jesuit JoGe
null
Jo.....
Ge.....
null
null
24,736
StrakeJesuit
Strake Jesuit
TX
null
1,028
hsld20
HS LD 2020-21
2,020
ld
hs
1
2,374,403
Only a universal prohibition solves – stigma would independently solve circumvention
Goose 15 Stephen Goose (Executive Director, Arms Division, Human Rights Watch) The Case for Banning Killer Robots, 11/24/2015, https://www.hrw.org/news/2015/11/24/case-banning-killer-robots#
Goose 15 Stephen Goose (Executive Director, Arms Division, Human Rights Watch) The Case for Banning Killer Robots, 11/24/2015, https://www.hrw.org/news/2015/11/24/case-banning-killer-robots#
Some oppose a preemptive and comprehensive prohibition, saying it is too early and we should "wait and see" where the technology takes us The point of a preemptive treaty is to prevent future harm and with all the dangers and concerns associated with fully autonomous weapons, it would be irresponsible to take a "wait and see" approach and only try to deal with the issue after the harm has already occurred. Once developed, they will be irreversible; it will not be possible to put the genie back in the bottle as the weapons spread rapidly around the world. While some rightly point out that there is no "proof" there cannot be a technological fix to the problems of fully autonomous weapons, it is equally true there is no proof there can be. The principle suggests the international community need not wait for scientific certainty, but could and should take action now. A specific treaty banning a weapon is also the best way to stigmatize the weapon. Experience has shown that stigmatization has a powerful effect even on those who have not yet formally joined the treaty, inducing them to comply with the key provisions, lest they risk international condemnation. A regulatory approach restricting use to certain locations or to specific purposes would be prone to longer-term failure as countries would likely be tempted to use them in other, possibly inappropriate, ways during the heat of battle or in dire circumstances. Once legitimized, the weapons would no doubt be mass produced and proliferate worldwide; only a preemptive international treaty will prevent that. Research and development activities should be banned if they are directed at technology that can only be used for fully autonomous weapons or that is explicitly intended for use in such weapons.
fully autonomous weapons Once developed it will not be possible to put the genie back in the bottle A specific treaty banning a weapon stigmatize the weapon has a powerful effect even on those who have joined the treaty lest they risk international condemnation. A regulatory approach would fail as countries would use them in inappropriate, ways during the heat of battle or in dire circumstances Once legitimized, the weapons would proliferate only a preemptive treaty will prevent that.
Some oppose a preemptive and comprehensive prohibition, saying it is too early and we should "wait and see" where the technology takes us. Others believe restrictions would be more appropriate than a ban, limiting their use to specific situations and missions. Some say existing international humanitarian law will be sufficient to address the challenges posed. The point of a preemptive treaty is to prevent future harm and with all the dangers and concerns associated with fully autonomous weapons, it would be irresponsible to take a "wait and see" approach and only try to deal with the issue after the harm has already occurred. Once developed, they will be irreversible; it will not be possible to put the genie back in the bottle as the weapons spread rapidly around the world. The notion of a preemptive treaty has been done before. The best example is the 1995 CCW protocol that bans blinding laser weapons. After initial opposition from the U.S. and others, states came to agree the weapons would pose unacceptable dangers to soldiers and civilians. The weapons were seen as counter to the dictates of public conscience and nations came to recognize their militaries would be better off if no one had the weapons than if everyone had them. These same rationales apply to fully autonomous weapons. While some rightly point out that there is no "proof" there cannot be a technological fix to the problems of fully autonomous weapons, it is equally true there is no proof there can be. Given the scientific uncertainty that exists, and given the potential benefits of a new legally binding instrument, the precautionary principle in international law is directly applicable. The principle suggests the international community need not wait for scientific certainty, but could and should take action now. Fully autonomous weapons represent a new category of weapons that could change the way wars are fought and pose serious risks to civilians. As such, they demand new, specific law that clarifies and strengthens existing international humanitarian law. A specific treaty banning a weapon is also the best way to stigmatize the weapon. Experience has shown that stigmatization has a powerful effect even on those who have not yet formally joined the treaty, inducing them to comply with the key provisions, lest they risk international condemnation. A regulatory approach restricting use to certain locations or to specific purposes would be prone to longer-term failure as countries would likely be tempted to use them in other, possibly inappropriate, ways during the heat of battle or in dire circumstances. Once legitimized, the weapons would no doubt be mass produced and proliferate worldwide; only a preemptive international treaty will prevent that. The call for a ban on development of fully autonomous weapons is not aimed at impeding broader research into military robotics or weapons autonomy or full autonomy in the civilian sphere. It is not intended to curtail basic AI research in any way. Research and development activities should be banned if they are directed at technology that can only be used for fully autonomous weapons or that is explicitly intended for use in such weapons.
3,208
<h4>Only a universal prohibition solves – stigma would independently solve circumvention</h4><p><strong>Goose 15</strong> <u><strong>Stephen Goose (Executive Director, Arms Division, Human Rights Watch) The Case for Banning Killer Robots, 11/24/2015, https://www.hrw.org/news/2015/11/24/case-banning-killer-robots#</p><p>Some oppose a preemptive and comprehensive prohibition, saying it is too early and we should "wait and see" where the technology takes us</u></strong>. Others believe restrictions would be more appropriate than a ban, limiting their use to specific situations and missions. Some say existing international humanitarian law will be sufficient to address the challenges posed. <u><strong>The point of a preemptive treaty is to prevent future harm and with all the dangers and concerns associated with <mark>fully autonomous weapons</mark>, it would be irresponsible to take a "wait and see" approach and only try to deal with the issue after the harm has already occurred. <mark>Once developed</mark>, they will be irreversible; <mark>it will not be possible to put the genie back in the bottle </mark>as the weapons spread rapidly around the world. </u></strong>The notion of a preemptive treaty has been done before. The best example is the 1995 CCW protocol that bans blinding laser weapons. After initial opposition from the U.S. and others, states came to agree the weapons would pose unacceptable dangers to soldiers and civilians. The weapons were seen as counter to the dictates of public conscience and nations came to recognize their militaries would be better off if no one had the weapons than if everyone had them. These same rationales apply to fully autonomous weapons. <u><strong>While some rightly point out that there is no "proof" there cannot be a technological fix to the problems of fully autonomous weapons, it is equally true there is no proof there can be. </u></strong>Given the scientific uncertainty that exists, and given the potential benefits of a new legally binding instrument, the precautionary principle in international law is directly applicable. <u><strong>The principle suggests the international community need not wait for scientific certainty, but could and should take action now. </u></strong>Fully autonomous weapons represent a new category of weapons that could change the way wars are fought and pose serious risks to civilians. As such, they demand new, specific law that clarifies and strengthens existing international humanitarian law. <u><strong><mark>A specific treaty banning a weapon </mark>is also the best way to <mark>stigmatize the weapon</mark>. Experience has shown that stigmatization <mark>has a powerful effect even on those who have</mark> not yet formally <mark>joined the treaty</mark>, inducing them to comply with the key provisions, <mark>lest they risk international condemnation. A regulatory approach</mark> restricting use to certain locations or to specific purposes <mark>would </mark>be prone to longer-term <mark>fail</mark>ure <mark>as countries would</mark> likely be tempted to <mark>use them in</mark> other, possibly <mark>inappropriate, ways</mark> <mark>during the heat of battle or in dire circumstances</mark>. <mark>Once legitimized, the weapons would</mark> no doubt be mass produced and <mark>proliferate </mark>worldwide; <mark>only a preemptive</mark> international <mark>treaty will prevent that.</u></strong></mark> The call for a ban on development of fully autonomous weapons is not aimed at impeding broader research into military robotics or weapons autonomy or full autonomy in the civilian sphere. It is not intended to curtail basic AI research in any way. <u><strong>Research and development activities should be banned if they are directed at technology that can only be used for fully autonomous weapons or that is explicitly intended for use in such weapons. </p></u></strong>
1ac
Solvency
null
349,360
321
75,764
./documents/hsld20/StrakeJesuit/Zh/Strake%20Jesuit-Zhu-Aff-Golden%20Desert-Round1.docx
875,646
A
Golden Desert
1
Max Norman
Grace Nelson
AC - Stock AC NC - Nukes CP Util LAWs CP Innovation DA Nigeria CP 1AR - Stock AC Multiple Condo Bad NR - Nigeria CP Innovation DA 2AR - Stock AC
hsld20/StrakeJesuit/Zh/Strake%20Jesuit-Zhu-Aff-Golden%20Desert-Round1.docx
null
73,814
HaZh
Strake Jesuit HaZh
null
Ha.....
Zh.....
null
null
24,736
StrakeJesuit
Strake Jesuit
TX
null
1,028
hsld20
HS LD 2020-21
2,020
ld
hs
1
4,710,901
Pain and pleasure are intrinsically valuable – they are reasons for actions in and of themselves
Nagel 86
Nagel 86 - Thomas Nagel, The View From Nowhere, HUP, 1986: 156-168.
Physical pleasure and pain are just sensory experiences toward which we feel involuntary desire or aversion. Almost everyone takes the avoidance of his own pain as subjective reasons for action there is no plausibility in th position that pleasure and pain have no value you couldn't say that someone had a reason not to put [her] hand on a hot stove, just because of the pain. see whether you can withhold that judgment. If the idea of reason makes any sense at all, it does not seem possible. someone who was never motivated to do anything would still have involuntary avoidance reactions, And he would be motivated to reduce pain because interfered with some activity that was important to him. even an irrational hatred makes its object very unpleasant we cannot from an objective standpoint withhold endorsement of the most direct subjective value judgments we make We regard ourselves as too close to those things to be mistaken in our immediate, nonideological evaluative impressions. No objective view we can attain could possibly overrule our subjective authority in such cases.
everyone takes the avoidance of pain as reasons for action pleasure and pain have no value you couldn't say that someone had a reason not to put [her] hand on a hot stove If reason makes any sense it does not seem possible. someone who was never motivated would be motivated to reduce pain we cannot from an objective standpoint withhold endorsement of the most direct subjective value judgments No objective view could overrule our subjective authority
I shall defend the unsurprising claim that sensory [P]leasure is good and pain bad, no matter whose they are. The point of the exercise is to see how the pressures of objectification operate in a simple case. Physical pleasure and pain do not usually depend on activities or desires which themselves raise questions of justification and value. They are just sensory experiences in relation to which we are fairly passive, but toward which we feel involuntary desire or aversion. Almost everyone takes the avoidance of his own pain and the promotion of his own pleasure as subjective reasons for action in a fairly simple way; they are not back[ed] up by any further reasons. On the other hand if someone pursues pain or avoids pleasure [it is a means to their end], either it as a means to some end or it is backed up by dark reasons like guilt or sexual masochism. What sort of general value, if any, ought to be assigned to pleasure and pain when we consider these facts from an objective standpoint? What kind of judgment can we reasonably make about these things when we view them in abstraction from who we are? We can begin by asking why there is no plausibility in the zero position, that pleasure and pain have no value of any kind that can be objectively recognized. That would mean that I have no reason to take aspirin for a severe headache, however I may in fact be motivated; and that looking at it from outside, you couldn't even say that someone had a reason not to put his [her] hand on a hot stove, just because of the pain. Try looking at it from the outside and see whether you can manage to withhold that judgment. If the idea of objective practical reason makes any sense at all, so that there is some judgment to withhold, it does not seem possible. If the general arguments against the reality of objective reasons are no good, then it is at least possible that I have a reason, and not just an inclination, to refrain from putting my hand on a hot stove. But given the possibility, it seems meaningless to deny that this is so. Oddly enough, however, we can think of a story that would go with such a denial. It might be suggested that the aversion to pain is a useful phobia—having nothing to do with the intrinsic undesirability of pain itself—which helps us avoid or escape the injuries that are signaled by pain. (The same type of purely instrumental value might be ascribed to sensory pleasure: the pleasures of food, drink, and sex might be regarded as having no value in themselves, though our natural attraction to them assists survival and reproduction.) There would then be nothing wrong with pain in itself, and someone who was never motivated deliberately to do anything just because he knew it would reduce or avoid pain would have nothing the matter with him. He would still have involuntary avoidance reactions, otherwise it would be hard to say that he felt pain at all. And he would be motivated to reduce pain for other reasons—because it was an effective way to avoid the danger being signaled, or because interfered with some physical or mental activity that was important to him. He just wouldn't regard the pain as itself something he had any reason to avoid, even though he hated the feeling just as much as the rest of us. (And of course he wouldn't be able to justify the avoidance of pain in the way that we customarily justify avoiding what we hate without reason—that is, on the ground that even an irrational hatred makes its object very unpleasant!) There is nothing self-contradictory in this proposal, but it seems nevertheless insane. Without some positive reason to think there is nothing in itself good or bad about having an experience you intensely like or dislike, we can't seriously regard the common impression to the contrary as a collective illusion. Such things are at least good or bad for us, if anything is. What seems to be going on here is that we cannot from an objective standpoint withhold a certain kind of endorsement of the most direct and immediate subjective value judgments we make concerning the contents of our own consciousness. We regard ourselves as too close to those things to be mistaken in our immediate, nonideological evaluative impressions. No objective view we can attain could possibly overrule our subjective authority in such cases. There can be no reason to reject the appearances here.
4,384
<h4>Pain and pleasure are intrinsically valuable – they are reasons for actions in and of themselves </h4><p><strong>Nagel 86 </strong>- Thomas Nagel, The View From Nowhere, HUP, 1986: 156-168.</p><p>I shall defend the unsurprising claim that sensory [P]leasure is good and pain bad, no matter whose they are. The point of the exercise is to see how the pressures of objectification operate in a simple case.<u><strong> Physical pleasure and pain </u></strong>do not usually depend on activities or desires which themselves raise questions of justification and value. They <u><strong>are just sensory experiences </u></strong>in relation to which we are fairly passive, but<u><strong> toward which we feel involuntary desire or aversion. Almost <mark>everyone takes the avoidance of </mark>his own <mark>pain </u></strong></mark>and the promotion of his own pleasure<u><strong> <mark>as </mark>subjective <mark>reasons for action </u></strong></mark>in a fairly simple way; they are not back[ed] up by any further reasons.<u><strong> </u></strong>On the other hand if someone pursues pain or avoids pleasure [it is a means to their end], either it as a means to some end or it is backed up by dark reasons like guilt or sexual masochism.<u><strong> </u></strong>What sort of general value, if any, ought to be assigned to pleasure and pain when we consider these facts from an objective standpoint? What kind of judgment can we reasonably make about these things when we view them in abstraction from who we are? We can begin by asking why <u><strong>there is no plausibility in th</u></strong>e zero <u><strong>position</u></strong>, <u><strong>that <mark>pleasure and pain have no value </u></strong></mark>of any kind that can be objectively recognized. That would mean that I have no reason to take aspirin for a severe headache, however I may in fact be motivated; and that looking at it from outside, <u><strong><mark>you couldn't </u></strong></mark>even <u><strong><mark>say that someone had a reason not to put </u></strong></mark>his<u><strong><mark> [her] hand on a hot stove</mark>, just because of the pain. </u></strong>Try looking at it from the outside and <u><strong>see whether you can </u></strong>manage to <u><strong>withhold that judgment. <mark>If </mark>the idea of</u></strong> objective practical <u><strong><mark>reason makes any sense </mark>at all,</u></strong> so that there is some judgment to withhold, <u><strong><mark>it does not seem possible.</u></strong> </mark>If the general arguments against the reality of objective reasons are no good, then it is at least possible that I have a reason, and not just an inclination, to refrain from putting my hand on a hot stove. But given the possibility, it seems meaningless to deny that this is so. Oddly enough, however, we can think of a story that would go with such a denial. It might be suggested that the aversion to pain is a useful phobia—having nothing to do with the intrinsic undesirability of pain itself—which helps us avoid or escape the injuries that are signaled by pain. (The same type of purely instrumental value might be ascribed to sensory pleasure: the pleasures of food, drink, and sex might be regarded as having no value in themselves, though our natural attraction to them assists survival and reproduction.) There would then be nothing wrong with pain in itself, and<u><strong> <mark>someone who was never motivated </u></strong></mark>deliberately<u><strong> to do anything </u></strong>just because<u><strong> </u></strong>he knew it would reduce or avoid pain would have nothing the matter with him. He<u><strong> would still have involuntary avoidance reactions, </u></strong>otherwise it would be hard to say that he felt pain at all.<u><strong> And he <mark>would be motivated to reduce pain </u></strong></mark>for other reasons—because it was an effective way to avoid the danger being signaled, or<u><strong> because interfered with some </u></strong>physical or mental<u><strong> activity that was important to him. </u></strong>He just wouldn't regard the pain as itself something he had any reason to avoid, even though he hated the feeling just as much as the rest of us. (And of course he wouldn't be able to justify the avoidance of pain in the way that we customarily justify avoiding what we hate without reason—that is, on the ground that <u><strong>even an irrational hatred makes its object very unpleasant</u></strong>!) There is nothing self-contradictory in this proposal, but it seems nevertheless insane. Without some positive reason to think there is nothing in itself good or bad about having an experience you intensely like or dislike, we can't seriously regard the common impression to the contrary as a collective illusion. Such things are at least good or bad for us, if anything is. What seems to be going on here is that <u><strong><mark>we cannot from an objective standpoint withhold </u></strong></mark>a certain kind of <u><strong><mark>endorsement of the most direct </u></strong></mark>and immediate<u><strong> <mark>subjective value judgments </mark>we make </u></strong>concerning the contents of our own consciousness.<u><strong> We regard ourselves as too close to those things to be mistaken in our immediate, nonideological evaluative impressions. <mark>No objective view </mark>we can attain <mark>could </mark>possibly <mark>overrule our subjective authority </mark>in such cases. </u></strong>There can be no reason to reject the appearances here.</p>
null
1AC
Framing
355,140
682
164,136
./documents/hsld22/ImmaculateHeart/MiFl/ImmaculateHeart-MiFl-Aff-California-Invitational-Berkeley-Debate-Round-1.docx
979,269
A
California Invitational Berkeley Debate
1
Bellarmine AK
Meza
1AC - US-Mexico AC 1NC - Set Col K ICJ CP Populism DA Case 1AR - Case K Da Cp 2NR - CP Case 2AR - Case CP
hsld22/ImmaculateHeart/MiFl/ImmaculateHeart-MiFl-Aff-California-Invitational-Berkeley-Debate-Round-1.docx
2023-02-18 23:12:46
80,476
MiFl
Immaculate Heart MiFl
null
Mi.....
Fl.....
null
null
26,574
ImmaculateHeart
Immaculate Heart
CA
null
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
621,425
Extinction
Sandberg, 8
Sandberg, 8 -- Oxford University Future of Humanity Institute research fellow
Advances in synthetic biology make it possible to engineer pathogens capable of extinction-level pandemics unlike other weapons, pathogens are self-replicating, allowing a small arsenal to become exponentially destructive. Pathogens have been implicated in the extinctions of many species Although most pandemics "fade out" by reducing the density of susceptible populations, pathogens with wide host ranges in multiple species can reach even isolated individuals. engineered pathogens with high transmissibility, latency, and lethality might be capable of causing human extinction
Advances in synthetic biology make pathogens capable of extinction-level pandemics unlike other weapons, pathogens are self-replicating, allowing a small arsenal to become exponentially destructive Although most pandemics "fade out" pathogens with wide host ranges can reach even isolated individuals. T engineered pathogens with high transmissibility, latency, and lethality might be capable of causing human extinction
[Anders, PhD in computation neuroscience, and Milan Cirkovic, senior research associate at the Astronomical Observatory of Belgrade, "How can we reduce the risk of human extinction?" Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists, 9-9-2008, thebulletin.org/how-can-we-reduce-risk-human-extinction, accessed 8-13-14] The risks from anthropogenic hazards appear at present larger than those from natural ones. Although great progress has been made in reducing the number of nuclear weapons in the world, humanity is still threatened by the possibility of a global thermonuclear war and a resulting nuclear winter. We may face even greater risks from emerging technologies. Advances in synthetic biology might make it possible to engineer pathogens capable of extinction-level pandemics. The knowledge, equipment, and materials needed to engineer pathogens are more accessible than those needed to build nuclear weapons. And unlike other weapons, pathogens are self-replicating, allowing a small arsenal to become exponentially destructive. Pathogens have been implicated in the extinctions of many wild species. Although most pandemics "fade out" by reducing the density of susceptible populations, pathogens with wide host ranges in multiple species can reach even isolated individuals. The intentional or unintentional release of engineered pathogens with high transmissibility, latency, and lethality might be capable of causing human extinction. While such an event seems unlikely today, the likelihood may increase as biotechnologies continue to improve at a rate rivaling Moore's Law.
1,575
<h4>Extinction</h4><p><strong>Sandberg, 8</strong> -- Oxford University Future of Humanity Institute research fellow </p><p>[Anders, PhD in computation neuroscience, and Milan Cirkovic, senior research associate at the Astronomical Observatory of Belgrade, "How can we reduce the risk of human extinction?" Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists, 9-9-2008, thebulletin.org/how-can-we-reduce-risk-human-extinction, accessed 8-13-14]</p><p>The risks from anthropogenic hazards appear at present larger than those from natural ones. Although great progress has been made in reducing the number of nuclear weapons in the world, humanity is still threatened by the possibility of a global thermonuclear war and a resulting nuclear winter. We may face even greater risks from emerging technologies. <u><mark>Advances in synthetic biology</u> </mark>might <u><mark>make<strong> </strong></mark>it possible to engineer<strong> </strong><mark>pathogens capable of<strong> extinction-level </strong>pandemics</u></mark>. The knowledge, equipment, and materials needed to engineer pathogens are more accessible than those needed to build nuclear weapons. And <u><strong><mark>unlike other weapons</strong>, pathogens are <strong>self-replicating</strong>, allowing a small arsenal to become <strong>exponentially destructive</strong></mark>.</u> <u>Pathogens have been implicated in the extinctions of many</u> wild <u>species</u>. <u><mark>Although most pandemics "fade out" </mark>by reducing the density of susceptible populations,</u> <u><mark>pathogens with wide host ranges </mark>in multiple species <mark>can reach even isolated individuals.</u> T</mark>he intentional or unintentional release of <u><strong><mark>engineered pathogens</strong> with high transmissibility, latency, and lethality might be capable of causing <strong>human extinction</u></strong></mark>. While such an event seems unlikely today, the likelihood may increase as biotechnologies continue to improve at a rate rivaling Moore's Law.</p>
1NC R4
Offs
DA
21,354
917
11,367
./documents/hsld19/Harker/Sh1/Harker-Sheth-Neg-CPS-Round4.docx
838,429
N
CPS
4
Carmel EP
Whit Jackson
1AC - Cult of Personality (NoKo) 1NC - DA-CBW CP-Peace Talks DA-Conv War 2NR - CBW
hsld19/Harker/Sh1/Harker-Sheth-Neg-CPS-Round4.docx
null
71,625
AnSh
Harker AnSh
null
An.....
Sh.....
null
null
24,119
Harker
Harker
CA
null
1,027
hsld19
HS LD 2019-20
2,019
ld
hs
1
2,226,669
“A” is an indefinite article that indicates the “democracy” is non-specific.
CCC No Date. ahsBC
CCC No Date. (“Articles, Determiners, and Quantifiers”, http://grammar.ccc.commnet.edu/grammar/determiners/determiners.htm#articles, Capital Community College Foundation, a nonprofit 501 c-3 organization that supports scholarships, faculty development, and curriculum innovation) ahsBC
The article a are a kind of adjective The is called the definite article a and an are indefinite articles they are used to refer to something in a less specific manner We refer to something in a generic way by using any of the articles We can do the same thing by omitting the article altogether A beagle makes a great hunting dog and family companion The indefinite pronoun refers to all members of that class.
a and an are indefinite articles they are used to refer to something in a less specific manner We refer to something in a generic way by using the article A beagle makes a great hunting dog The indefinite pronoun refers to all members of that class
The three articles — a, an, the — are a kind of adjective. The is called the definite article because it usually precedes a specific or previously mentioned noun; a and an are called indefinite articles because they are used to refer to something in a less specific manner (an unspecified count noun). These words are also listed among the noun markers or determiners because they are almost invariably followed by a noun (or something else acting as a noun). caution CAUTION! Even after you learn all the principles behind the use of these articles, you will find an abundance of situations where choosing the correct article or choosing whether to use one or not will prove chancy. Icy highways are dangerous. The icy highways are dangerous. And both are correct. The is used with specific nouns. The is required when the noun it refers to represents something that is one of a kind: The moon circles the earth. The is required when the noun it refers to represents something in the abstract: The United States has encouraged the use of the private automobile as opposed to the use of public transit. The is required when the noun it refers to represents something named earlier in the text. (See below..) If you would like help with the distinction between count and non-count nouns, please refer to Count and Non-Count Nouns. We use a before singular count-nouns that begin with consonants (a cow, a barn, a sheep); we use an before singular count-nouns that begin with vowels or vowel-like sounds (an apple, an urban blight, an open door). Words that begin with an h sound often require an a (as in a horse, a history book, a hotel), but if an h-word begins with an actual vowel sound, use an an (as in an hour, an honor). We would say a useful device and a union matter because the u of those words actually sounds like yoo (as opposed, say, to the u of an ugly incident). The same is true of a European and a Euro (because of that consonantal "Yoo" sound). We would say a once-in-a-lifetime experience or a one-time hero because the words once and one begin with a w sound (as if they were spelled wuntz and won). Merriam-Webster's Dictionary says that we can use an before an h- word that begins with an unstressed syllable. Thus, we might say an hisTORical moment, but we would say a HIStory book. Many writers would call that an affectation and prefer that we say a historical, but apparently, this choice is a matter of personal taste. For help on using articles with abbreviations and acronyms (a or an FBI agent?), see the section on Abbreviations. First and subsequent reference: When we first refer to something in written text, we often use an indefinite article to modify it. A newspaper has an obligation to seek out and tell the truth. In a subsequent reference to this newspaper, however, we will use the definite article: There are situations, however, when the newspaper must determine whether the public's safety is jeopardized by knowing the truth. Another example: "I'd like a glass of orange juice, please," John said. "I put the glass of juice on the counter already," Sheila replied. Exception: When a modifier appears between the article and the noun, the subsequent article will continue to be indefinite: "I'd like a big glass of orange juice, please," John said. "I put a big glass of juice on the counter already," Sheila replied. Generic reference: We can refer to something in a generic way by using any of the three articles. We can do the same thing by omitting the article altogether. A beagle makes a great hunting dog and family companion. An airedale is sometimes a rather skittish animal. The golden retriever is a marvelous pet for children. Irish setters are not the highly intelligent animals they used to be. The difference between the generic indefinite pronoun and the normal indefinite pronoun is that the latter refers to any of that class ("I want to buy a beagle, and any old beagle will do.") whereas the former (see beagle sentence) refers to all members of that class.
4,023
<h4>“A” is an indefinite article that indicates the “democracy” is non-specific.</h4><p><strong>CCC No Date. </strong>(“Articles, Determiners, and Quantifiers”, http://grammar.ccc.commnet.edu/grammar/determiners/determiners.htm#articles, Capital Community College Foundation, a nonprofit 501 c-3 organization that supports scholarships, faculty development, and curriculum innovation) <u><strong>ahsBC</p><p></strong>The</u> three <u>article</u>s — <u>a</u>, an, the — <u>are a kind of adjective</u>. <u>The is called the definite article</u> because it usually precedes a specific or previously mentioned noun; <u><mark>a and an are</u></mark> called <u><mark>indefinite articles</u></mark> because <u><mark>they are used to refer to something in a less specific manner</u></mark> (an unspecified count noun). These words are also listed among the noun markers or determiners because they are almost invariably followed by a noun (or something else acting as a noun). caution CAUTION! Even after you learn all the principles behind the use of these articles, you will find an abundance of situations where choosing the correct article or choosing whether to use one or not will prove chancy. Icy highways are dangerous. The icy highways are dangerous. And both are correct. The is used with specific nouns. The is required when the noun it refers to represents something that is one of a kind: The moon circles the earth. The is required when the noun it refers to represents something in the abstract: The United States has encouraged the use of the private automobile as opposed to the use of public transit. The is required when the noun it refers to represents something named earlier in the text. (See below..) If you would like help with the distinction between count and non-count nouns, please refer to Count and Non-Count Nouns. We use a before singular count-nouns that begin with consonants (a cow, a barn, a sheep); we use an before singular count-nouns that begin with vowels or vowel-like sounds (an apple, an urban blight, an open door). Words that begin with an h sound often require an a (as in a horse, a history book, a hotel), but if an h-word begins with an actual vowel sound, use an an (as in an hour, an honor). We would say a useful device and a union matter because the u of those words actually sounds like yoo (as opposed, say, to the u of an ugly incident). The same is true of a European and a Euro (because of that consonantal "Yoo" sound). We would say a once-in-a-lifetime experience or a one-time hero because the words once and one begin with a w sound (as if they were spelled wuntz and won). Merriam-Webster's Dictionary says that we can use an before an h- word that begins with an unstressed syllable. Thus, we might say an hisTORical moment, but we would say a HIStory book. Many writers would call that an affectation and prefer that we say a historical, but apparently, this choice is a matter of personal taste. For help on using articles with abbreviations and acronyms (a or an FBI agent?), see the section on Abbreviations. First and subsequent reference: When we first refer to something in written text, we often use an indefinite article to modify it. A newspaper has an obligation to seek out and tell the truth. In a subsequent reference to this newspaper, however, we will use the definite article: There are situations, however, when the newspaper must determine whether the public's safety is jeopardized by knowing the truth. Another example: "I'd like a glass of orange juice, please," John said. "I put the glass of juice on the counter already," Sheila replied. Exception: When a modifier appears between the article and the noun, the subsequent article will continue to be indefinite: "I'd like a big glass of orange juice, please," John said. "I put a big glass of juice on the counter already," Sheila replied. Generic reference: <u><mark>We</u></mark> can <u><mark>refer to something in a generic way</u> <u>by</u> <u>using</mark> any of <mark>the</u></mark> three <u><mark>article</mark>s</u>. <u>We can do the same thing by omitting the article altogether</u>. <u><strong><mark>A beagle</strong> makes a great hunting dog</mark> and family companion</u>. An airedale is sometimes a rather skittish animal. The golden retriever is a marvelous pet for children. Irish setters are not the highly intelligent animals they used to be. <u><mark>The</u></mark> difference between the generic indefinite pronoun and the normal <u><mark>indefinite pronoun</u></mark> is that the latter refers to any of that class ("I want to buy a beagle, and any old beagle will do.") whereas the former (see beagle sentence) <u><strong><mark>refers to all members of that class</mark>.</p></u></strong>
null
null
1
327,722
698
69,064
./documents/hsld20/IndependentRubenSAyala/Mi/Independent%20Ruben%20S%20Ayala-Mimou-Neg-Nano%20Nagle-Round4.docx
863,046
N
Nano Nagle
4
Ben Cortez
Asher Towner
1AC - Advantage 1NC - T Shell DA CP 1AR - All 2NR - Shell 2AR - Shell
hsld20/IndependentRubenSAyala/Mi/Independent%20Ruben%20S%20Ayala-Mimou-Neg-Nano%20Nagle-Round4.docx
null
73,195
AdMi
Independent Ruben S Ayala AdMi
null
Ad.....
Mi.....
null
null
24,556
IndependentRubenSAyala
Independent Ruben S Ayala
CA
null
1,028
hsld20
HS LD 2020-21
2,020
ld
hs
1
1,906,243
Extinction first equates to Pascal’s Wager — infinite scenarios cause policy failure
Munthe 15
Munthe 15 – Christian Munthe, PhD, Practical Philosophy Professor Associate Head of Department for Research at the University of Gothenburg. [Why Aren't Existential Risk / Ultimate Harm Argument Advocates All Attending Mass? Philosophical Comment, 2-1-15, http://philosophicalcomment.blogspot.com/2015/02/why-arent-existential-risk-ultimate.html]//BPS
"existential risks" or "ultimate harms" is a case of the emperor's new clothes existential risk genre strikes me as philosophically shallow this is well-known to anyone with a philosophical education, since it seems to share the basic form of the philosophical classic known as Pascal's Wager it is rational to bet on God, no matter what theoretical or other evidence exists and no matter the probability of this truth. It seems to me the typical existential risk argument advocacy subscribes to a very similar logic the existential risk argument seems to ignore there seems to be an innumerable amount of (merely) possible existential risk scenarios, as well as innumerable (merely) possibly workable technologies that might help to prevent or mitigate these, and it is unlikely (to say the least) we have resources to bet substantially on them all, unless we spread them so thin that this action becomes meaningless the argument above ignores completely the (rather high) likelihood the mobilised resources will be mostly wasted, and there are substantial opportunity costs attached to not using these resources to use better proven strategies with better identified threats and problems albeit maybe not as massive as the outcomes in the existential risk scenarios None of that is worth any consideration in light of the massive stakes of the existential risk / religious belief or non-belief scenarios If you're impressed by the existential risk argument, you should be equally impressed by Pascal's Wager I very much doubt that you do or even accept you should
"ex risks" strikes me as shallow this is known as Pascal's Wager it is rational to bet on God, no matter probability ex risk subscribes to similar logic arg ignore there seems to be innumerable scenarios innumerable work that mitigate these, and it is unlikely we have resources to bet on them all, unless we spread them so thin this becomes meaningless arg ignores likelihood resources will be wasted, and costs to not using better strategies None worth any consideration in light of stakes If you're impressed by the ex risk you should be impressed by Pascal's Wager
An increasingly popular genre in the sort of applied philosophy and ethics of technology, which does not so much engage with actual technological development as more or less wild phantasies about possibly forthcoming ones is the notions of "existential risks" or "ultimate harms", or similar expressions. The theme is currently inspiring several research environments at world-leading universities, such as this one and this one (where you can find many links to other sources, articles, blog posts, and so on), and given quite a bit of space in recent scholarly literature on a topic often referred to as the ethics of emerging technology. Now, personally and academically, as it has actually proceeded, I have found much of this development being to a large extent a case of the emperor's new clothes. The fact that there are possible threats to human civilizations, the existence of humanity, life on earth or, at least, extended human well-being, is not exactly news, is it? Neither is there any kind of new insight that some of these are created by humans themselves. Also, it is not any sort of recent revelation that established moral ideas, or theories of rational decision making, may provide reason for avoiding or mitigating such threats. Rather, both these theses follow rather trivially from a great many well-established ethical and philosophical theories, and are well-known to do so since hundreds of years. Still, piece after piece is being produced in the existential risk genre making this out as some sort of recent finding, and exposing grand gestures at proving the point against more or less clearly defined straw-men. At the same time, quite a bit of what is currently written on the topic strikes me as philosophically shallow. For instance, the notion that the eradication of the human species has to be a bad thing seems to be far from obvious from a philosophical point of view - this would depend on such things as the source of the value of specifically human existence, the manner of the imagined extinction (it certainly does not have to involve any sort of carnage or catastrophe), and what might possibly come instead of humanity or currently known life when extinct and how that is to be valued. Similarly, it is a very common step in the typical existential risk line to jump rather immediately from the proposition of such a risk to the suggestion that substantial (indeed, massive) resources should be spent on its prevention, mitigation or management. This goes for everything from imagined large scale geo-engineering solutions to environmental problems, dreams of outer space migration, to so-called human enhancement to adapt people to be able to handle otherwise massive threats in a better way. At the same time, the advocates of the existential risk line of thought also urges caution in the application of new hitherto unexplored technology, such as synthetic biology or (if it ever comes to appear) "real" A.I. and android technology. However, also there, the angle of analysis is often restricted to this very call, typically ignoring the already since long ongoing debates in the ethics of technology, bioethics, environmental ethics, et cetera, where the issue of how much of and what sort of such caution may be warranted in light of various good aspects of different the technologies considered. And, to be frank, this simplification seems to be the only thing that is special with the existential risk argument advocacy: the idea that the mere possibility of a catastrophic scenario justifies substantial sacrifices, without having to complicate things by pondering alternative uses of resources. Now, this kind of argument, is (or should be) well-known to anyone with a philosophical education, since it seems to share the basic form of the philosophical classic known as Pascal's Wager. In this argument, French enlightenment philosopher and mathematician, Blaise Pascal offered a "proof" of the rationality of believing in God (the sort of God found in abrahamitic monotheistic religion, that is), based on the possible consequences of belief or non-belief, given the truth or falsity of the belief. You can explore the details of Pascal's argument, but the basic idea is that in the face of the immense consequences of belief and non-belief if God exists (eternal salvation vs. eternal damnation), it is rational to bet on the existence of God, no matter what theoretical or other evidence for the truth of this belief exists and no matter the probability of this truth. It seems to me that the typical existential risk argument advocacy subscribes to a very similar logic. For instance, the standard line to defend that resources should be spent on probing and (maybe) facilitating), e.g., possible extraterrestial migration for humanity, seems to have the following form: 1) Technology T might possibly prevent/mitigate existential risk, E 2) It would be really, really, very, very bad if E was to be actualised 3) Therefore: If E was otherwise to be actualised, it would be really, really, very, very good if E was prevented 4) Therefore: If E was otherwise to be actualised, it would be really, really, very, very good if we had access to a workable T 5) Therefore: there are good reasons to spend substantial resources on probing and (maybe, if that turns out to be possible) facilitating a workable T That is, what drives the argument is the (mere) possibility of a massively significant outcome, and the (mere) possibility of a way to prevent that particular outcome, thus doing masses of good. Now, I'm sure that everyone can see that this argument is far from obviously valid, even if we ignore the question of whether or not premise 2 is true, and this goes for Pascal's Wager too in parallel ways. For instance, the existential risk argument above seems to ignore that there seems to be an innumerable amount of thus (merely) possible existential risk scenarios, as well as innumerable (merely) possibly workable technologies that might help to prevent or mitigate each of these, and it is unlikely (to say the least) that we have resources to bet substantially on them all, unless we spread them so thin that this action becomes meaningless. Similarly, there are innumerable possible versions of the god that lures you with threats and promises of damnation and salvation, and what that particular god may demand in return, often implying a ban on meeting a competing deity's demands, so the wager doesn't seem to tell you to try to start believing in any particular of all these (merely) possible gods. Likewise, the argument above ignores completely the (rather high) likelihood that the mobilised resources will be mostly wasted, and that, therefore, there are substantial opportunity costs attached to not using these resources to use better proven strategies with better identified threats and problems (say, preventing global poverty) - albeit maybe not as massive as the outcomes in the existential risk scenarios. Similarly, Pascal's Wager completely ignores all the good things one needs to give up to meet the demands of the god promising eternal salvation in return (for instance, spending your Sundays working for the allieviation of global poverty). None of that is worth any consideration, the idea seems to be, in light of the massive stakes of the existential risk / religious belief or non-belief scenarios. Now, I will not pick any quarrel with the existential risk argument as such on these grounds, although I do think that more developed ways to analyse risk-scenarios and the ethical implications of these already in existence and used in the fields I referred above will mean lots of troubles for the simplistic aspects already mentioned. What I do want to point to, however, is this: If you're impressed by the existential risk argument, you should be equally impressed by Pascal's Wager. Thus, in accordance with Pascal's recommendation that authentic religious belief can be gradually installed via the practice of rituals, you should – as should indeed the existential risk argument advocates themselves – spend your Sundays celebrating mass (or any other sort ritual demanded by the God you bet on). I very much doubt, however, that you (or they) in fact do that, or even accept the conclusion that you (or they) should be doing that.
8,331
<h4>Extinction first equates to <u>Pascal’s Wager</u> — infinite scenarios cause policy failure<u> </h4><p></u><strong>Munthe 15</strong> – Christian Munthe, PhD, Practical Philosophy Professor Associate Head of Department for Research at the University of Gothenburg. [Why Aren't Existential Risk / Ultimate Harm Argument Advocates All Attending Mass? Philosophical Comment, 2-1-15, http://philosophicalcomment.blogspot.com/2015/02/why-arent-existential-risk-ultimate.html]//BPS</p><p>An increasingly popular genre in the sort of applied philosophy and ethics of technology, which does not so much engage with actual technological development as more or less wild phantasies about possibly forthcoming ones is the notions of <u><mark>"ex</mark>istential <mark>risks"</mark> or "ultimate harms"</u>, or similar expressions. The theme <u>is</u> currently inspiring several research environments at world-leading universities, such as this one and this one (where you can find many links to other sources, articles, blog posts, and so on), and given quite a bit of space in recent scholarly literature on a topic often referred to as the ethics of emerging technology. Now, personally and academically, as it has actually proceeded, I have found much of this development being to a large extent <u>a case of the emperor's new clothes</u>. The fact that there are possible threats to human civilizations, the existence of humanity, life on earth or, at least, extended human well-being, is not exactly news, is it? Neither is there any kind of new insight that some of these are created by humans themselves. Also, it is not any sort of recent revelation that established moral ideas, or theories of rational decision making, may provide reason for avoiding or mitigating such threats. Rather, both these theses follow rather trivially from a great many well-established ethical and philosophical theories, and are well-known to do so since hundreds of years. Still, piece after piece is being produced in the <u>existential risk genre</u> making this out as some sort of recent finding, and exposing grand gestures at proving the point against more or less clearly defined straw-men.</p><p>At the same time, quite a bit of what is currently written on the topic <u><mark>strikes me as</mark> <strong>philosophically <mark>shallow</u></strong></mark>. For instance, the notion that the eradication of the human species has to be a bad thing seems to be far from obvious from a philosophical point of view - this would depend on such things as the source of the value of specifically human existence, the manner of the imagined extinction (it certainly does not have to involve any sort of carnage or catastrophe), and what might possibly come instead of humanity or currently known life when extinct and how that is to be valued. Similarly, it is a very common step in the typical existential risk line to jump rather immediately from the proposition of such a risk to the suggestion that substantial (indeed, massive) resources should be spent on its prevention, mitigation or management. This goes for everything from imagined large scale geo-engineering solutions to environmental problems, dreams of outer space migration, to so-called human enhancement to adapt people to be able to handle otherwise massive threats in a better way. At the same time, the advocates of the existential risk line of thought also urges caution in the application of new hitherto unexplored technology, such as synthetic biology or (if it ever comes to appear) "real" A.I. and android technology. However, also there, the angle of analysis is often restricted to this very call, typically ignoring the already since long ongoing debates in the ethics of technology, bioethics, environmental ethics, et cetera, where the issue of how much of and what sort of such caution may be warranted in light of various good aspects of different the technologies considered. And, to be frank, this simplification seems to be the only thing that is special with the existential risk argument advocacy: the idea that the mere possibility of a catastrophic scenario justifies substantial sacrifices, without having to complicate things by pondering alternative uses of resources.</p><p>Now, <u><mark>this</u></mark> kind of argument, <u><mark>is</u></mark> (or should be) <u><strong>well-<mark>known</strong></mark> to anyone with a philosophical education, since it seems to share the basic form of the <strong>philosophical classic known <mark>as Pascal's Wager</u></strong></mark>. In this argument, French enlightenment philosopher and mathematician, Blaise Pascal offered a "proof" of the rationality of believing in God (the sort of God found in abrahamitic monotheistic religion, that is), based on the possible consequences of belief or non-belief, given the truth or falsity of the belief. You can explore the details of Pascal's argument, but the basic idea is that in the face of the immense consequences of belief and non-belief if God exists (eternal salvation vs. eternal damnation), <u><mark>it is rational to bet on</u></mark> the existence of <u><mark>God, no matter</mark> what theoretical or other evidence</u> for the truth of this belief <u>exists and no matter the <mark>probability</mark> of this truth. It seems to me</u> that <u>the <strong>typical <mark>ex</mark>istential <mark>risk</mark> argument advocacy</strong> <mark>subscribes to</mark> a <strong>very <mark>similar logic</u></strong></mark>. For instance, the standard line to defend that resources should be spent on probing and (maybe) facilitating), e.g., possible extraterrestial migration for humanity, seems to have the following form:</p><p>1) Technology T might possibly prevent/mitigate existential risk, E</p><p>2) It would be really, really, very, very bad if E was to be actualised</p><p>3) Therefore: If E was otherwise to be actualised, it would be really, really, very, very good if E was prevented</p><p>4) Therefore: If E was otherwise to be actualised, it would be really, really, very, very good if we had access to a workable T</p><p>5) Therefore: there are good reasons to spend substantial resources on probing and (maybe, if that turns out to be possible) facilitating a workable T</p><p>That is, what drives the argument is the (mere) possibility of a massively significant outcome, and the (mere) possibility of a way to prevent that particular outcome, thus doing masses of good. Now, I'm sure that everyone can see that this argument is far from obviously valid, even if we ignore the question of whether or not premise 2 is true, and this goes for Pascal's Wager too in parallel ways. For instance, <u>the existential risk <mark>arg</mark>ument</u> above <u>seems to <strong><mark>ignore</u></strong></mark> that <u><mark>there seems to be</mark> an <strong><mark>innumerable</mark> amount</strong> of</u> thus <u><strong>(merely) possible existential risk <mark>scenarios</strong></mark>, as well as <strong><mark>innumerable</mark> (merely) possibly <mark>work</mark>able technologies</strong> <mark>that</mark> might help to prevent or <mark>mitigate</u></mark> each of <u><mark>these, and it is <strong>unlikely</mark> (to say the least)</u></strong> that <u><mark>we have resources to <strong>bet</mark> substantially</strong> <mark>on them <strong>all</strong>, unless we spread them <strong>so thin</strong></mark> that <strong><mark>this</mark> action</strong> <mark>becomes <strong>meaningless</u></strong></mark>. Similarly, there are innumerable possible versions of the god that lures you with threats and promises of damnation and salvation, and what that particular god may demand in return, often implying a ban on meeting a competing deity's demands, so the wager doesn't seem to tell you to try to start believing in any particular of all these (merely) possible gods. Likewise, <u>the <mark>arg</mark>ument above <strong><mark>ignores</mark> completely</strong> the <strong>(rather high) <mark>likelihood</u></strong></mark> that <u>the mobilised <mark>resources will be</mark> <strong>mostly <mark>wasted</strong>, and</u></mark> that, therefore, <u>there are <strong>substantial opportunity <mark>costs</strong></mark> attached <mark>to not using</mark> these resources to use <strong><mark>better</mark> proven <mark>strategies</strong></mark> with better identified threats and problems</u> (say, preventing global poverty) - <u>albeit maybe not as <strong>massive</strong> as the outcomes in the <strong>existential risk scenarios</u></strong>. Similarly, Pascal's Wager completely ignores all the good things one needs to give up to meet the demands of the god promising eternal salvation in return (for instance, spending your Sundays working for the allieviation of global poverty). <u><mark>None</mark> of that is <mark>worth <strong>any consideration</u></strong></mark>, the idea seems to be, <u><mark>in light of</mark> the <strong>massive <mark>stakes</strong></mark> of the <strong>existential risk</strong> / <strong>religious belief</strong> or <strong>non-belief scenarios</u></strong>. </p><p>Now, I will not pick any quarrel with the existential risk argument as such on these grounds, although I do think that more developed ways to analyse risk-scenarios and the ethical implications of these already in existence and used in the fields I referred above will mean lots of troubles for the simplistic aspects already mentioned. What I do want to point to, however, is this: <u><mark>If you're impressed by the ex</mark>istential <mark>risk</mark> argument, <mark>you should be</mark> <strong>equally <mark>impressed</strong> by Pascal's Wager</u></mark>. Thus, in accordance with Pascal's recommendation that authentic religious belief can be gradually installed via the practice of rituals, you should – as should indeed the existential risk argument advocates themselves – spend your Sundays celebrating mass (or any other sort ritual demanded by the God you bet on). <u>I <strong>very much doubt</u></strong>, however, <u>that you</u> (or they) in fact <u>do</u> that, <u>or even accept</u> the conclusion that <u>you</u> (or they) <u>should</u> be doing that.</p>
1AC
1AC — LFS RM
1AC — Framing
10,125
307
56,299
./documents/hspolicy20/LawrenceFreeState/RuMa/Lawrence%20Free%20State-Rupp-Marshall-Aff-DCI-Finals.docx
732,209
A
DCI
Finals
Washburn Rural PR
Brian Box, Azja Butler, Niko Helixon
1AC - Death Penalty 1NC - T-Enact T-CJR Subsets Congress Advantage CP Native CJR PIC Distinguish CP Stare Decisis DA ACA DA 2NR - T-Enact
hspolicy20/LawrenceFreeState/RuMa/Lawrence%20Free%20State-Rupp-Marshall-Aff-DCI-Finals.docx
null
62,529
RuMa
Lawrence Free State RuMa
null
Se.....
Ru.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
21,684
LawrenceFreeState
Lawrence Free State
KS
null
1,019
hspolicy20
HS Policy 2020-21
2,020
cx
hs
2
955,886
Unpredictable legal shifts wreck business confidence.
Cambon 21
Sarah Chaney Cambon 21, Reporter on The Wall Street Journal's Economics Team, BA in Business Journalism from the University of North Carolina-Chapel Hill, “Capital-Spending Surge Further Lifts Economic Recovery”, Wall Street Journal, 6/27/2021, https://www.wsj.com/articles/capital-spending-surge-further-lifts-economic-recovery-11624798800
Business investment is emerging as a powerful source of U.S. economic growth that will likely help sustain the recovery Companies are ramping up orders for computers, machinery and software as they grow more confident in the outlook business spending, rose Business investment has really been an important engine powering the U.S. economic recovery In our outlook for the economy, it’s certainly one of the bright spots Robust capital investment will be key to ensuring that the recovery maintains strength after the spending boost from fiscal stimulus and business reopenings eventually fades Rising business investment helps fuel economic output. It lifts worker productivity Company executives are increasingly confident in the economy’s trajectory less uncertainty should underpin business confidence At the very least, businesses will understand the strategy that the Biden is trying to follow and will be able to plan around that
Business investment is a powerful source of growth that will sustain recovery Companies ramp up as they grow confident Business has been an important engine powering recovery Robust investment will be key after stimulus and reopenings fade executives are increasingly confident less uncertainty underpin bus con businesses understand the strategy Biden follow and plan around that
Business investment is emerging as a powerful source of U.S. economic growth that will likely help sustain the recovery. Companies are ramping up orders for computers, machinery and software as they grow more confident in the outlook. Nonresidential fixed investment, a proxy for business spending, rose at a seasonally adjusted annual rate of 11.7% in the first quarter, led by growth in software and tech-equipment spending, according to the Commerce Department. Business investment also logged double-digit gains in the third and fourth quarters last year after falling during pandemic-related shutdowns. It is now higher than its pre-pandemic peak. Orders for nondefense capital goods excluding aircraft, another measure for business investment, are near the highest levels for records tracing back to the 1990s, separate Commerce Department figures show. “Business investment has really been an important engine powering the U.S. economic recovery,” said Robert Rosener, senior U.S. economist at Morgan Stanley. “In our outlook for the economy, it’s certainly one of the bright spots.” Consumer spending, which accounts for about two-thirds of economic output, is driving the early stages of the recovery. Americans, flush with savings and government stimulus checks, are spending more on goods and services, which they shunned for much of the pandemic. Robust capital investment will be key to ensuring that the recovery maintains strength after the spending boost from fiscal stimulus and business reopenings eventually fades, according to some economists. Rising business investment helps fuel economic output. It also lifts worker productivity, or output per hour. That metric grew at a sluggish pace throughout the last economic expansion but is now showing signs of resurgence. The recovery in business investment is shaping up to be much stronger than in the years following the 2007-09 recession. “The events especially in late ’08, early ’09 put a lot of businesses really close to the edge,” said Phil Suttle, founder of Suttle Economics. “I think a lot of them said, ‘We’ve just got to be really cautious for a long while.’” Businesses appear to be less risk-averse now, he said. After the financial crisis, businesses grew by adding workers, rather than investing in capital. Hiring was more attractive than capital spending because labor was abundant and relatively cheap. Now the supply of workers is tight. Companies are raising pay to lure employees. As a result, many firms have more incentive to grow by investing in capital. Economists at Morgan Stanley predict that U.S. capital spending will rise to 116% of prerecession levels after three years. By comparison, investment took 10 years to reach those levels once the 2007-09 recession hit. Company executives are increasingly confident in the economy’s trajectory. The Business Roundtable’s economic-outlook index—a composite of large companies’ plans for hiring and spending, as well as sales projections—increased by nine points in the second quarter to 116, just below 2018’s record high, according to a survey conducted between May 25 and June 9. In the second quarter, the share of companies planning to boost capital investment increased to 59% from 57% in the first. “We’re seeing really strong reopening demand, and a lot of times capital investment follows that,” said Joe Song, senior U.S. economist at BofA Securities. Mr. Song added that less uncertainty regarding trade tensions between the U.S. and China should further underpin business confidence and investment. “At the very least, businesses will understand the strategy that the Biden administration is trying to follow and will be able to plan around that,” he said.
3,713
<h4>Unpredictable legal shifts <u>wreck</u> business confidence.</h4><p>Sarah Chaney <strong>Cambon 21</strong>, Reporter on The Wall Street Journal's Economics Team, BA in Business Journalism from the University of North Carolina-Chapel Hill, “Capital-Spending Surge Further Lifts Economic Recovery”, Wall Street Journal, 6/27/2021, https://www.wsj.com/articles/capital-spending-surge-further-lifts-economic-recovery-11624798800</p><p><u><mark>Business investment is</mark> emerging as <mark>a <strong>powerful source</strong> of</mark> U.S. economic <mark>growth that will</mark> likely help <strong><mark>sustain</mark> the <mark>recovery</u></strong></mark>.</p><p><u><mark>Companies</mark> are <strong><mark>ramp</mark>ing <mark>up</strong></mark> orders for computers, machinery and software <mark>as they <strong>grow</mark> more <mark>confident</strong></mark> in the outlook</u>.</p><p>Nonresidential fixed investment, a proxy for <u>business spending, rose</u> at a seasonally adjusted annual rate of 11.7% in the first quarter, led by growth in software and tech-equipment spending, according to the Commerce Department. Business investment also logged double-digit gains in the third and fourth quarters last year after falling during pandemic-related shutdowns. It is now higher than its pre-pandemic peak.</p><p>Orders for nondefense capital goods excluding aircraft, another measure for business investment, are near the highest levels for records tracing back to the 1990s, separate Commerce Department figures show.</p><p>“<u><mark>Business</mark> investment <mark>has</mark> really <mark>been an <strong>important engine</strong> powering</mark> the U.S. economic <mark>recovery</u></mark>,” said Robert Rosener, senior U.S. economist at Morgan Stanley. “<u>In our outlook for the economy, it’s certainly one of the <strong>bright spots</u></strong>.”</p><p>Consumer spending, which accounts for about two-thirds of economic output, is driving the early stages of the recovery. Americans, flush with savings and government stimulus checks, are spending more on goods and services, which they shunned for much of the pandemic.</p><p><u><mark>Robust</mark> capital <mark>investment will be <strong>key</strong></mark> to ensuring that the recovery maintains strength <strong><mark>after</strong></mark> the spending boost from fiscal <strong><mark>stimulus</strong> and</mark> <strong>business <mark>reopenings</strong></mark> eventually <strong><mark>fade</strong></mark>s</u>, according to some economists.</p><p><u>Rising business investment helps fuel <strong>economic output</strong>. It</u> also <u>lifts <strong>worker productivity</u></strong>, or output per hour. That metric grew at a sluggish pace throughout the last economic expansion but is now showing signs of resurgence.</p><p>The recovery in business investment is shaping up to be much stronger than in the years following the 2007-09 recession. “The events especially in late ’08, early ’09 put a lot of businesses really close to the edge,” said Phil Suttle, founder of Suttle Economics. “I think a lot of them said, ‘We’ve just got to be really cautious for a long while.’”</p><p>Businesses appear to be less risk-averse now, he said.</p><p>After the financial crisis, businesses grew by adding workers, rather than investing in capital. Hiring was more attractive than capital spending because labor was abundant and relatively cheap. Now the supply of workers is tight. Companies are raising pay to lure employees. As a result, many firms have more incentive to grow by investing in capital.</p><p>Economists at Morgan Stanley predict that U.S. capital spending will rise to 116% of prerecession levels after three years. By comparison, investment took 10 years to reach those levels once the 2007-09 recession hit.</p><p><u>Company <mark>executives are <strong>increasingly confident</strong></mark> in the economy’s trajectory</u>. The Business Roundtable’s economic-outlook index—a composite of large companies’ plans for hiring and spending, as well as sales projections—increased by nine points in the second quarter to 116, just below 2018’s record high, according to a survey conducted between May 25 and June 9. In the second quarter, the share of companies planning to boost capital investment increased to 59% from 57% in the first.</p><p>“We’re seeing really strong reopening demand, and a lot of times capital investment follows that,” said Joe Song, senior U.S. economist at BofA Securities.</p><p>Mr. Song added that <u><mark>less <strong>uncertainty</u></strong></mark> regarding trade tensions between the U.S. and China <u>should</u> further <u><strong><mark>underpin</strong></mark> <strong><mark>bus</strong></mark>iness <strong><mark>con</strong></mark>fidence</u> and investment. “<u>At the <strong>very least</strong>, <mark>businesses</mark> will <strong><mark>understand</strong> the <strong>strategy</strong></mark> that the <mark>Biden</u></mark> administration <u>is trying to <mark>follow and</mark> will be <strong>able to <mark>plan</strong> around that</u></mark>,” he said.</p>
1NC vs Minnesota FP
Off
BizCon DA --- 1NC
18,377
461
23,218
./documents/ndtceda21/EmoryUniversity/BeWa/Emory%20University-Bedi-Wallen-Neg-4%20-%20Wake%20Forest-Round4.docx
623,538
N
4 - Wake Forest
4
Minnesota FP
Amar Adam
1AC - Co-Ops Ag 1NC - T Prohibit Disclosure Cap K Reg CP Forecasting CP FTC DA Trade DA BizCon DA 2NR - Trade DA 2AR - Condo
ndtceda21/EmoryUniversity/BeWa/Emory%20University-Bedi-Wallen-Neg-4%20-%20Wake%20Forest-Round4.docx
null
52,631
BeWa
Emory University BeWa
null
Am.....
Be.....
Kr.....
Wa.....
19,378
EmoryUniversity
Emory University
null
null
1,011
ndtceda21
NDT/CEDA 2021-22
2,021
cx
college
2
1,016,456
The competitive nature of debate makes change impossible
Ritter 13.
Ritter 13. JD from U Texas Law (Michael J., “Overcoming The Fiction of “Social Change Through Debate”: What’s To Learn from 2pac’s Changes?,” National Journal of Speech and Debate, Vol. 2, Issue 1
The structure of competitive interscholastic debate renders any message communicated in a debate round virtually incapable of creating any social change, either in the debate community or in general society to the extent that the fiction of social change through debate can be proven or disproven through empirical studies or surveys, academics instead have analyzed debate with nonapplicable rhetorical theory that fails to account for the unique aspects of competitive interscholastic debate. The position that competitive interscholastic debate can create social change is more properly characterize5d as a fiction than an argument. A fiction is an invented or fabricated idea purporting to be factual but is not provable by any human senses or rational thinking capability or is unproven by valid statistical studies. An argument, most basically, consists of a claim and some support for why the claim is true. If the support for the claim is false or its relation to the claim is illogical, then we can deduce that the particular argument does not help in ascertaining whether the claim is true. Interscholastic competitive debate is premised upon the assumption that debate is argumentation. Because fictions are necessarily not true or cannot be proven true by any means of argumentation, the competitive interscholastic debate community should be incredibly critical of those fictions and adopt them only if they promote the activity and its purposes only be read as a manifestation of “the West’s” ongoing will to colonize and impose its will on others.
competitive debate renders any message incapable of social change in the community or society academics analyz with theory that fails to account for competitive debate that competitive debate can create change is a fiction unproven by valid statistical studies competitive debate is premised upon the assumption that debate is argumentation the community should be incredibly critical only be read as the West’s” ongoing will to colonize and impose its will on others.
The structure of competitive interscholastic debate renders any message communicated in a debate round virtually incapable of creating any social change, either in the debate community or in general society. And to the extent that the fiction of social change through debate can be proven or disproven through empirical studies or surveys, academics instead have analyzed debate with nonapplicable rhetorical theory that fails to account for the unique aspects of competitive interscholastic debate. Rather, the current debate relating to activism and competitive interscholastic debate concerns the following: “What is the best model to promote social change?” But a more fundamental question that must be addressed first is: “Can debate cause social change?” Despite over two decades of opportunity to conduct and publish empirical studies or surveys, academic proponents of the fiction that debate can create social change have chosen not to prove this fundamental assumption, which—as this article argues—is merely a fiction that is harmful in most, if not all, respects. The position that competitive interscholastic debate can create social change is more properly characterize5d as a fiction than an argument. A fiction is an invented or fabricated idea purporting to be factual but is not provable by any human senses or rational thinking capability or is unproven by valid statistical studies. An argument, most basically, consists of a claim and some support for why the claim is true. If the support for the claim is false or its relation to the claim is illogical, then we can deduce that the particular argument does not help in ascertaining whether the claim is true. Interscholastic competitive debate is premised upon the assumption that debate is argumentation. Because fictions are necessarily not true or cannot be proven true by any means of argumentation, the competitive interscholastic debate community should be incredibly critical of those fictions and adopt them only if they promote the activity and its purposes only be read as a manifestation of “the West’s” ongoing will to colonize and impose its will on others.
2,143
<h4><strong>The competitive nature of debate makes change impossible </h4><p>Ritter 13. </strong>JD from U Texas Law (Michael J., “Overcoming The Fiction of “Social Change Through Debate”: What’s To Learn from 2pac’s Changes?,” National Journal of Spe<u>ech and Debate, Vol. 2, Issue 1</p><p>The structure of <mark>competitive </mark>interscholastic <mark>debate renders any message </mark>communicated in a debate round virtually <mark>incapable of </mark>creating any <mark>social change</mark>, either <mark>in the </mark>debate <mark>community or </mark>in general <mark>society</u></mark>. And <u>to the extent that the fiction of social change through debate can be proven or disproven through empirical studies or surveys, <mark>academics</mark> instead have <mark>analyz</mark>ed debate <mark>with </mark>nonapplicable rhetorical <mark>theory that fails to account for </mark>the unique aspects of <mark>competitive </mark>interscholastic <mark>debate</mark>.</u> Rather, the current debate relating to activism and competitive interscholastic debate concerns the following: “What is the best model to promote social change?” But a more fundamental question that must be addressed first is: “Can debate cause social change?” Despite over two decades of opportunity to conduct and publish empirical studies or surveys, academic proponents of the fiction that debate can create social change have chosen not to prove this fundamental assumption, which—as this article argues—is merely a fiction that is harmful in most, if not all, respects.<u> The position <mark>that competitive </mark>interscholastic <mark>debate can create </mark>social <mark>change is </mark>more properly characterize5d as <mark>a fiction </mark>than an argument. A fiction is an invented or fabricated idea purporting to be factual but is not provable by any human senses or rational thinking capability or is <mark>unproven by valid statistical studies</mark>. An argument, most basically, consists of a claim and some support for why the claim is true. If the support for the claim is false or its relation to the claim is illogical, then we can deduce that the particular argument does not help in ascertaining whether the claim is true. Interscholastic <mark>competitive debate is premised upon the assumption that debate is argumentation</mark>. Because fictions are necessarily not true or cannot be proven true by any means of argumentation, <mark>the </mark>competitive interscholastic debate <mark>community should be incredibly critical </mark>of those fictions and adopt them only if they promote the activity and its purposes</p><p><strong><mark>only be read</strong> as</mark> a manifestation of “<mark>the West’s” <strong>ongoing will</strong> to <strong>colonize</strong> and <strong>impose its will on others</strong>.</p></u></mark>
1NC v Iowa CN – UMinn R3
null
Case
130,826
531
24,469
./documents/ndtceda21/Pittsburgh/ReSh/Pittsburgh-Reznik-Shah-Neg-Minnesota-Round3.docx
626,954
N
Minnesota
3
Iowa CN
Jackie Poapst
1AC - break the white monopoly 1NC - cap k fw case 2NR - fw case
ndtceda21/Pittsburgh/ReSh/Pittsburgh-Reznik-Shah-Neg-Minnesota-Round3.docx
null
52,874
ReSh
Pittsburgh ReSh
null
Al.....
Re.....
Pa.....
Sh.....
19,412
Pittsburgh
Pittsburgh
null
null
1,011
ndtceda21
NDT/CEDA 2021-22
2,021
cx
college
2
4,376,489
Africa war escalates---great power war
Heath 20
Heath 20 [Nathanael C. Heath, Fares Center Senior Research Associate and Political Risk Analyst, 02-04-2020, A Red Sea Geopolitics Primer – Fares Center, https://sites.tufts.edu/farescenter/a-red-sea-geopolitics-primer/ HKR-MK]
One of the world’s oldest waterways is becoming increasingly relevant in geopolitics. The Red Sea is positioned between two continents, bordering six countries in Africa and four in the Middle East, and approximately 10% of all global trade passes through its waters. It also serves as a strategic zone for both regional and Great Powers projecting their military might or openly engaging in conflict. There is the potential for either reward or disaster in the Red Sea, as increasing economic and military competition in its waters raises the possibility of intense economic growth while simultaneously foreshadowing potential conflicts between rival powers. High levels of trade, energy production, and innovation forecast significant economic opportunity in the Red Sea, but this prosperity is threatened by regional rivalries and the ongoing Great Power competition between the U.S. and China. Moreover, the construction of new ports and military bases to protect trade and investment interests will lead to even higher levels of trade throughout the Red Sea. visions for sustainable innovation to be completed in the next decade. In short, this crucial waterway may soon be home to innovation driving regional prosperity forward even faster. These terrific opportunities for prosperity rooted in trade, energy, and innovation face risks posed by complex economic and military comp among both regional and global owners African rivalries stretching from Egypt to Djibouti are adding to the Red Sea region’s volatility. Egyptian and Ethiopian relations And Djibouti remains caught in a tug of war between an ever-growing number of regional and global powers. The formation of Middle East-African alliances has added a further risk of conflict to the region. In addition to its relationship with Sudan (where Saudi Arabia and Iran have competed with Eritrea), Turkey has poured significant aid and investment into Somalia, and Istanbul now owns all of the country’s major ports. Saudi Arabia and the UAE have sparred with Ethiopia over influence in Eritrea. Additionally, Qatar’s alignment with the Turks, Saudis, and Emiratis at different times has increased Doha’s influence in nations along the Horn of Africa. It is in Djibouti, however, that the greatest risk to the Red Sea itself lies, as the city-state has drawn the attention of the great powers. is symptomatic of the larger continental rivalry between two Great Powers, as both Washington and Beijing continue to vie for influence in Africa with rival political ideologies and systems of economic development. Djibouti is thus a true powder key, not merely for regional rivalries but also for the larger Great Power game between the U.S. and China. An economic and military conflict between Washington and Beijing would impact Djibouti, threatening to disrupt trade routes passing through the Red Sea. In the near future we can expect to see increasing economic competition in the Red Sea as both traditional fossil fuels and renewable energy sources bolster already-significant levels of trade and innovative projects such as Neom and the GERD. The With shifting alliances and economic competition, however, comes increased risk of conflict in a region already home to numerous zones of instability. To minimize risk to the global supply chain, powers with military, economic, or political interests in the Red Sea region will have to work together to ensure that conflicts are contained or prevented altogether in the interest of stabilizing both regional and global markets.
increasingly relevant in geopolitics Africa 10% of trade passes a strategic zone for Great Powers projecting might or engaging in conflict. potential for disaster competition foreshadowing conflicts between U.S. and China. new ports military bases protect trade and investment These face risks posed by complex military comp African rivalries adding to volatility caught in tug of war between global powers symptomatic of continental rivalry Washington and Beijing vie for influence in Africa with rival ideologies and systems key, for the Great Power game expect conflict
One of the world’s oldest waterways is becoming increasingly relevant in geopolitics. The Red Sea is positioned between two continents, bordering six countries in Africa and four in the Middle East, and approximately 10% of all global trade passes through its waters. It also serves as a strategic zone for both regional and Great Powers projecting their military might or openly engaging in conflict. There is the potential for either reward or disaster in the Red Sea, as increasing economic and military competition in its waters raises the possibility of intense economic growth while simultaneously foreshadowing potential conflicts between rival powers. High levels of trade, energy production, and innovation forecast significant economic opportunity in the Red Sea, but this prosperity is threatened by regional rivalries and the ongoing Great Power competition between the U.S. and China. The Red Sea’s global importance is rooted largely in its role as a key waterway for trade. By 2050, Red Sea GDP is projected to more than triple, increasing from $1.8 trillion to $6.1 trillion, and trade is expected to grow more than five times, from $881 billion to $4.7 trillion. This enormous wealth will be driven by trade agreements encouraging countries with substantial Red Sea interests to increase exports, particularly in key sectors such as energy, infrastructure, and technology. Moreover, the construction of new ports and military bases to protect trade and investment interests will lead to even higher levels of trade throughout the Red Sea. The geographical positioning of the Red Sea, proximate to numerous top energy producers, both explains the area’s current wealth and forecasts continuing economic growth. On the African side, Egypt and Sudan alone produce a combined 500,000+ barrels per day (bpd) of oil. On the Middle East side, Saudi Arabia and Oman produce more than 12 million bpd of oil. In total, more than 50 million bpd of oil from producers as diverse as the U.S., Russia, China, Libya, and Iran pass through the Red Sea on a daily basis, along with approximately 3.5 billion cubic feet per day in liquid natural gas. In the future, renewable energy will add even more value to this waterway, given the current interest in hydro, wind, and solar initiatives in numerous bordering states. In addition to serving as a leading trade route and home to multiple leading energy producers, the Red Sea is also becoming relevant as a hub of innovation. Saudi Arabia’s megacity projects such as Neom, The Red Sea Project, and the Amalaa Project present an opportunity for the region to participate in sustainable urbanization through massive, renewables-focused initiatives integrating robotics and smart services into new economies designed to thrive on innovation and tourism alike. Saudi Arabia’s megacities are projected to bring in hundreds of billions of dollars by 2050, but more importantly, Neom and its sister cities highlight the tremendous opportunity for innovation and economic diversification in a region where many countries have historically been dependent on homogenous or semi-homogenous revenue streams such as fossil fuels. The UAE, Bahrain, and Qatar, all of which heavily traffic their goods in the Red Sea, have unveiled similar visions for sustainable innovation to be completed in the next decade. In short, this crucial waterway may soon be home to innovation driving regional prosperity forward even faster. These terrific opportunities for prosperity rooted in trade, energy, and innovation face risks posed by complex economic and military competition among both regional and global owners. For one, African rivalries stretching from Egypt to Djibouti are adding to the Red Sea region’s volatility. Egyptian and Ethiopian relations, although somewhat improved since the transitions to the al-Sisi and Abiy regimes, respectively, remain tense over the Grand Ethiopian Renaissance Dam (GERD). Ethiopia views the dam as a strategic necessity, while Egypt fears the dam will deplete its water resources. Although Ethiopia’s relations with Somalia and Eritrea have improved from Addis’s historically hostile positions towards Asmara and Mogadishu, Ethiopia’s access to the Red Sea ports remains a point of negotiation between the three countries. Sudan has also become increasingly problematic for its neighbors, as its resources, access to the sea, and ongoing political violence have attracted the attention of Turkey and the Gulf Nations, frustrating Egypt given Cairo and Khartoum’s historically close relationship. And Djibouti remains caught in a tug of war between an ever-growing number of regional and global powers. The Middle East is home to its own set of conflicts fueling military and economic competition in the Red Sea. The primary regional rivalry continues to be between Iran and Saudi Arabia, who are each vying for regional supremacy via either direct or proxy engagement in conflicts. Iran’s allies are Syria, Lebanon, and the Houthi rebels in Yemen (and also Qatar to a limited extent). Saudi Arabi is allied with the UAE, Bahrain, and Egypt, and the Qataris have historically been Saudi allies but have in recent years struck a more independent foreign policy that resulted in their blockade by Saudi Arabia, Egypt, Bahrain, and the UAE. The conflict between Riyadh and Tehran presents the most probable risk of a regional conflagration that could threaten the political and economic stability of the Red Sea region. At the moment, the risk of a tanker war or all-out military conflict between the U.S. and Iran is quite high, and the closure of the Strait of Hormuz or even the disruption of trade through the Gulf of Oman is a troubling and possible outcome of such an event. The formation of Middle East-African alliances has added a further risk of conflict to the region. In addition to its relationship with Sudan (where Saudi Arabia and Iran have competed with Eritrea), Turkey has poured significant aid and investment into Somalia, and Istanbul now owns all of the country’s major ports. Saudi Arabia and the UAE have sparred with Ethiopia over influence in Eritrea. Additionally, Qatar’s alignment with the Turks, Saudis, and Emiratis at different times has increased Doha’s influence in nations along the Horn of Africa. It is in Djibouti, however, that the greatest risk to the Red Sea itself lies, as the city-state has drawn the attention of the great powers. In addition to a slew of Middle Eastern and African powers including Qatar, the UAE, Saudi Arabia, Turkey, Ethiopia, Somalia, Eritrea, and Egypt, a number of global powers have set their sights on Djibouti as a strategic asset. The U.S., China, Russia, Japan, France, and Italy have all secured or pursued military bases in Djibouti, which is situated close to the critical Strait of Bab-el-Mandeb. China’s first overseas military base, positioned in Djibouti, is situated just miles from Camp Lemonnier, the only significant U.S. military base in Africa. Russia failed to secure a base in Djibouti and has looked further inland for African military partnerships; France, Italy, and Japan maintain smaller operations. The U.S.-China base rivalry in Djibouti (if it could be thought of as such), is symptomatic of the larger continental rivalry between two Great Powers, as both Washington and Beijing continue to vie for influence in Africa with rival political ideologies and systems of economic development. Djibouti is thus a true powder key, not merely for regional rivalries but also for the larger Great Power game between the U.S. and China. An economic and military conflict between Washington and Beijing would impact Djibouti, threatening to disrupt trade routes passing through the Red Sea. In the near future we can expect to see increasing economic competition in the Red Sea as both traditional fossil fuels and renewable energy sources bolster already-significant levels of trade and innovative projects such as Neom and the GERD. The struggle for economic power will fuel increased investment by developed or middle-income regional powers such as Egypt, Turkey, or Saudi Arabia, Qatar, or the UAE into developing countries such as Sudan, Somalia, and Eritrea. Furthermore, global powers such as the U.S., China, EU, and Japan will be increasingly drawn to key Djibouti and other key ports to protect access to key trade routes. With shifting alliances and economic competition, however, comes increased risk of conflict in a region already home to numerous zones of instability. To minimize risk to the global supply chain, powers with military, economic, or political interests in the Red Sea region will have to work together to ensure that conflicts are contained or prevented altogether in the interest of stabilizing both regional and global markets.
8,816
<h4>Africa war escalates---great power war</h4><p><strong>Heath 20</strong> [Nathanael C. Heath, Fares Center Senior Research Associate and Political Risk Analyst<u>, 02-04-2020, A Red Sea Geopolitics Primer – Fares Center, https://sites.tufts.edu/farescenter/a-red-sea-geopolitics-primer/ HKR-MK]</p><p>One of the world’s oldest waterways is becoming <strong><mark>increasingly relevant</strong> in <strong>geopolitics</strong></mark>. The Red Sea is positioned between two continents, bordering six countries in <strong><mark>Africa</strong></mark> and four in the Middle East, and approximately <strong><mark>10% </strong>of</mark> all <strong>global <mark>trade</strong> passes</mark> through its waters. It also serves as <mark>a <strong>strategic zone</strong> for</mark> both regional and <strong><mark>Great Powers</strong> <strong>projecting</strong></mark> their <strong>military <mark>might</strong> or</mark> <strong>openly <mark>engaging</strong> in <strong>conflict</strong>. </mark>There is the <strong><mark>potential</strong> for</mark> either reward or <strong><mark>disaster</strong></mark> in the Red Sea, as increasing <strong>economic</strong> and <strong>military <mark>competition</strong></mark> in its waters raises the possibility of intense economic growth while simultaneously <strong><mark>foreshadowing</strong></mark> <strong>potential <mark>conflicts</strong></mark> between <strong>rival powers</strong>. High levels of trade, energy production, and innovation forecast significant economic opportunity in the Red Sea, but this prosperity is <strong>threatened</strong> by <strong>regional rivalries</strong> and the <strong>ongoing Great Power competition</strong> <mark>between </mark>the <strong><mark>U.S. and China.</p><p></u></strong></mark>The Red Sea’s global importance is rooted largely in its role as a key waterway for trade. By 2050, Red Sea GDP is projected to more than triple, increasing from $1.8 trillion to $6.1 trillion, and trade is expected to grow more than five times, from $881 billion to $4.7 trillion. This enormous wealth will be driven by trade agreements encouraging countries with substantial Red Sea interests to increase exports, particularly in key sectors such as energy, infrastructure, and technology. <u>Moreover, the construction of <strong><mark>new ports</strong></mark> and <strong><mark>military bases</strong></mark> to <strong><mark>protect trade</strong> and <strong>investment</mark> interests</strong> will lead to even higher levels of trade throughout the Red Sea.</p><p></u>The geographical positioning of the Red Sea, proximate to numerous top energy producers, both explains the area’s current wealth and forecasts continuing economic growth. On the African side, Egypt and Sudan alone produce a combined 500,000+ barrels per day (bpd) of oil. On the Middle East side, Saudi Arabia and Oman produce more than 12 million bpd of oil. In total, more than 50 million bpd of oil from producers as diverse as the U.S., Russia, China, Libya, and Iran pass through the Red Sea on a daily basis, along with approximately 3.5 billion cubic feet per day in liquid natural gas. In the future, renewable energy will add even more value to this waterway, given the current interest in hydro, wind, and solar initiatives in numerous bordering states.</p><p>In addition to serving as a leading trade route and home to multiple leading energy producers, the Red Sea is also becoming relevant as a hub of innovation. Saudi Arabia’s megacity projects such as Neom, The Red Sea Project, and the Amalaa Project present an opportunity for the region to participate in sustainable urbanization through massive, renewables-focused initiatives integrating robotics and smart services into new economies designed to thrive on innovation and tourism alike. Saudi Arabia’s megacities are projected to bring in hundreds of billions of dollars by 2050, but more importantly, Neom and its sister cities highlight the tremendous opportunity for innovation and economic diversification in a region where many countries have historically been dependent on homogenous or semi-homogenous revenue streams such as fossil fuels. The UAE, Bahrain, and Qatar, all of which heavily traffic their goods in the Red Sea, have unveiled similar <u><strong>visions for sustainable innovation to be completed in the next decade. In short, this crucial waterway may soon be home to innovation driving regional prosperity forward even faster.</p><p></strong><mark>These</mark> <strong>terrific opportunities</strong> for prosperity rooted in trade, energy, and innovation <mark>face <strong>risks</strong> posed by</mark> <strong><mark>complex</strong></mark> <strong>economic</strong> and <strong><mark>military comp</u></strong></mark>etition<u> among both regional and <strong>global owners</u></strong>. For one, <u><mark>African <strong>rivalries</strong></mark> stretching from Egypt to Djibouti are <mark>adding to</mark> the Red Sea region’s <strong><mark>volatility</strong></mark>. Egyptian and Ethiopian relations</u>, although somewhat improved since the transitions to the al-Sisi and Abiy regimes, respectively, remain tense over the Grand Ethiopian Renaissance Dam (GERD). Ethiopia views the dam as a strategic necessity, while Egypt fears the dam will deplete its water resources. Although Ethiopia’s relations with Somalia and Eritrea have improved from Addis’s historically hostile positions towards Asmara and Mogadishu, Ethiopia’s access to the Red Sea ports remains a point of negotiation between the three countries. Sudan has also become increasingly problematic for its neighbors, as its resources, access to the sea, and ongoing political violence have attracted the attention of Turkey and the Gulf Nations, frustrating Egypt given Cairo and Khartoum’s historically close relationship. <u>And Djibouti remains <mark>caught in</mark> a <strong><mark>tug of war</strong> between</mark> an <strong>ever-growing</strong> number of regional and <strong><mark>global powers</mark>.</p><p></u></strong>The Middle East is home to its own set of conflicts fueling military and economic competition in the Red Sea. The primary regional rivalry continues to be between Iran and Saudi Arabia, who are each vying for regional supremacy via either direct or proxy engagement in conflicts. Iran’s allies are Syria, Lebanon, and the Houthi rebels in Yemen (and also Qatar to a limited extent). Saudi Arabi is allied with the UAE, Bahrain, and Egypt, and the Qataris have historically been Saudi allies but have in recent years struck a more independent foreign policy that resulted in their blockade by Saudi Arabia, Egypt, Bahrain, and the UAE. The conflict between Riyadh and Tehran presents the most probable risk of a regional conflagration that could threaten the political and economic stability of the Red Sea region. At the moment, the risk of a tanker war or all-out military conflict between the U.S. and Iran is quite high, and the closure of the Strait of Hormuz or even the disruption of trade through the Gulf of Oman is a troubling and possible outcome of such an event. </p><p><u>The formation of Middle East-African alliances has added a further risk of conflict to the region. In addition to its relationship with Sudan (where Saudi Arabia and Iran have competed with Eritrea), Turkey has poured significant aid and investment into Somalia, and Istanbul now owns all of the country’s major ports. Saudi Arabia and the UAE have sparred with Ethiopia over influence in Eritrea. Additionally, Qatar’s alignment with the Turks, Saudis, and Emiratis at different times has increased Doha’s influence in nations along the Horn of Africa. It is in Djibouti, however, that the greatest risk to the Red Sea itself lies, as the city-state has drawn the attention of the great powers.</p><p></u>In addition to a slew of Middle Eastern and African powers including Qatar, the UAE, Saudi Arabia, Turkey, Ethiopia, Somalia, Eritrea, and Egypt, a number of global powers have set their sights on Djibouti as a strategic asset. The U.S., China, Russia, Japan, France, and Italy have all secured or pursued military bases in Djibouti, which is situated close to the critical Strait of Bab-el-Mandeb. China’s first overseas military base, positioned in Djibouti, is situated just miles from Camp Lemonnier, the only significant U.S. military base in Africa. Russia failed to secure a base in Djibouti and has looked further inland for African military partnerships; France, Italy, and Japan maintain smaller operations. The U.S.-China base rivalry in Djibouti (if it could be thought of as such), <u>is <strong><mark>symptomatic</strong> of </mark>the <strong>larger <mark>continental rivalry</strong></mark> between <strong>two Great Powers</strong>, as both <strong><mark>Washington</strong> and <strong>Beijing</strong> </mark>continue to <strong><mark>vie for influence</strong> in Africa</mark> <mark>with <strong>rival</strong></mark> political <strong><mark>ideologies</strong> and <strong>systems</strong></mark> of economic development. Djibouti is thus <strong>a true powder <mark>key</strong>,</mark> not merely for regional rivalries but also <mark>for the</mark> larger <strong><mark>Great Power game</strong></mark> between the U.S. and China. An economic and <strong>military conflict</strong> between Washington and Beijing would impact Djibouti, threatening to <strong>disrupt trade</strong> routes passing through the Red Sea. </p><p>In the near future we can <mark>expect</mark> to see <strong>increasing</strong> economic <strong>competition</strong> in the Red Sea as both traditional fossil fuels and renewable energy sources bolster already-significant levels of <strong>trade</strong> and <strong>innovative</strong> <strong>projects</strong> such as Neom and the GERD. The</u> struggle for economic power will fuel increased investment by developed or middle-income regional powers such as Egypt, Turkey, or Saudi Arabia, Qatar, or the UAE into developing countries such as Sudan, Somalia, and Eritrea. Furthermore, global powers such as the U.S., China, EU, and Japan will be increasingly drawn to key Djibouti and other key ports to protect access to key trade routes. <u>With <strong>shifting alliances</strong> and <strong>economic competition</strong>, however, comes <strong>increased</strong> <strong>risk of <mark>conflict</strong></mark> in a region <strong>already home</strong> to <strong>numerous zones</strong> of <strong>instability</strong>. To <strong>minimize risk</strong> to the global supply chain, powers with <strong>military</strong>, <strong>economic</strong>, or <strong>political interests</strong> in the Red Sea region will have to work together to ensure that <strong>conflicts</strong> are contained or <strong>prevented</strong> altogether in the interest of <strong>stabilizing</strong> both regional and <strong>global markets.</strong> </p></u>
1AC---Africa v2---Harker VL
null
1AC ---Development
21,557
265
149,257
./documents/hsld22/Harker/VaLi/Harker-VaLi-Aff-Harvard-Westlake-Debates-Round-1.docx
963,438
A
Harvard Westlake Debates
1
Greenhill SL
Flores
1ac - africa aff v2 1nc - psycho cap k, fwk 1ar - all 2nr - same 2ar- same
hsld22/Harker/VaLi/Harker-VaLi-Aff-Harvard-Westlake-Debates-Round-1.docx
2023-01-14 18:15:32
80,923
VaLi
Harker VaLi
null
Va.....
Li.....
null
null
26,565
Harker
Harker
CA
null
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
3,180,395
Blackouts collapse deterrence which incentivizes war
Andres and Breetz 2011
Andres and Breetz 2011
critical security issues have proven resistant to existing solutions: bases’ vulnerability to civilian power outages, and the need to transport large quantities of fuel via convoys DOD is unable to provide its bases with electricity when the civilian electrical grid is offline for an extended period of time domestic military installations receive 99 percent of their electricity from the civilian power grid critical missions, such as national strategic awareness and national command authorities, are entirely dependent on the national transmission grid [which] is fragile, vulnerable, near its capacity limit, and outside of DOD control neither the grid nor on-base backup power provides sufficient reliability to ensure continuity of critical national priority functions and oversight of strategic missions in the face of a long term (several months) outage The grid’s fragility was demonstrated during the 2003 Northeast blackout that the grid is vulnerable to purposive attacks terrorist groups might be able to develop the capability to conduct this type of attack that some nation-states either have or are working on developing the ability to take down the U.S. grid it is possible, if not likely, that parts of the civilian grid would cease to function, taking with them military bases located in affected regions organizations are currently working to secure the grid against attacks it is not clear that they will be successful military assets taken offline by the crisis would not be available to help with disaster relief during an extended blackout, global military operations could be seriously compromised; this disruption would be particularly serious if the blackout was induced during major combat operations blinding an opponent with a grid blackout could escalate to nuclear war America’s current opponents may not share this fear or be deterred by this possibility DOD should mitigate the electrical grid’s vulnerabilities by turning military installations into “islands The department has made efforts to do so by promoting efficiency programs constructing renewable power generation facilities Unfortunately, these programs will not come close to reaching the goal of islanding the vast majority of bases Even with massive investment in efficiency and renewables, most bases would not be able to function for more than a few days Unlike other alternative sources of energy, small reactors have the potential to solve DOD’s vulnerability to grid outages Small reactors could easily support bases’ power demands separate from the civilian grid during crises the reactors could be designed to produce enough power not only to supply the base, but also to provide critical services in surrounding towns during long-term outages One of the main reasons an enemy might be willing to risk reprisals by taking down the U.S. grid during a period of military hostilities would be to affect ongoing military operations. Without the lifeline of U.S. domestic bases, American military operations would be compromised in almost any conceivable contingency. Making bases more resilient to civilian power outages would reduce the incentive for an opponent to attack the grid the powerful incentive to do so in order to win an ongoing battle or war would be greatly reduced
DOD is unable to provide bases with electricity when the grid is offline critical strategic awareness and command authorities, are dependent on the grid [which] is vulnerable global military operations could be seriously compromised blinding an opponent could escalate to nuclear war renewable facilities will not come close to military operations would be compromised in any conceivable contingency
Richard, Hanna. Professor of National Security Strategy at the National War College and a Senior Fellow and Energy and Environmental Security and Policy Chair in the Center for Strategic Research, Institute for National Strategic Studies, at the National Defense University, doctoral candidate in the Department of Political Science at The Massachusetts Institute of Technology. “Small Nuclear Reactors for Military Installations: Capabilities, Costs, and Technological Implications”, www.ndu.edu/press/lib/pdf/StrForum/SF-262.pdf The DOD interest in small reactors derives largely from problems with base and logistics vulnerability. Over the last few years, the Services have begun to reexamine virtually every aspect of how they generate and use energy with an eye toward cutting costs, decreasing carbon emissions, and reducing energy-related vulnerabilities. These actions have resulted in programs that have significantly reduced DOD energy consumption and greenhouse gas emissions at domestic bases. Despite strong efforts, however, two critical security issues have thus far proven resistant to existing solutions: bases’ vulnerability to civilian power outages, and the need to transport large quantities of fuel via convoys through hostile territory to forward locations. Each of these is explored below. Grid Vulnerability. DOD is unable to provide its bases with electricity when the civilian electrical grid is offline for an extended period of time. Currently, domestic military installations receive 99 percent of their electricity from the civilian power grid. As explained in a recent study from the Defense Science Board: DOD’s key problem with electricity is that critical missions, such as national strategic awareness and national command authorities, are almost entirely dependent on the national transmission grid . . . [which] is fragile, vulnerable, near its capacity limit, and outside of DOD control. In most cases, neither the grid nor on-base backup power provides sufficient reliability to ensure continuity of critical national priority functions and oversight of strategic missions in the face of a long term (several months) outage.7 The grid’s fragility was demonstrated during the 2003 Northeast blackout in which 50 million people in the United States and Canada lost power, some for up to a week, when one Ohio utility failed to properly trim trees. The blackout created cascading disruptions in sewage systems, gas station pumping, cellular communications, border check systems, and so forth, and demonstrated the interdependence of modern infrastructural systems.8 More recently, awareness has been growing that the grid is also vulnerable to purposive attacks. A report sponsored by the Department of Homeland Security suggests that a coordinated cyberattack on the grid could result in a third of the country losing power for a period of weeks or months.9 Cyberattacks on critical infrastructure are not well understood. It is not clear, for instance, whether existing terrorist groups might be able to develop the capability to conduct this type of attack. It is likely, however, that some nation-states either have or are working on developing the ability to take down the U.S. grid. In the event of a war with one of these states, it is possible, if not likely, that parts of the civilian grid would cease to function, taking with them military bases located in affected regions. Government and private organizations are currently working to secure the grid against attacks; however, it is not clear that they will be successful. Most military bases currently have backup power that allows them to function for a period of hours or, at most, a few days on their own. If power were not restored after this amount of time, the results could be disastrous. First, military assets taken offline by the crisis would not be available to help with disaster relief. Second, during an extended blackout, global military operations could be seriously compromised; this disruption would be particularly serious if the blackout was induced during major combat operations. During the Cold War, this type of event was far less likely because the United States and Soviet Union shared the common understanding that blinding an opponent with a grid blackout could escalate to nuclear war. America’s current opponents, however, may not share this fear or be deterred by this possibility. In 2008, the Defense Science Board stressed that DOD should mitigate the electrical grid’s vulnerabilities by turning military installations into “islands” of energy self-sufficiency. The department has made efforts to do so by promoting efficiency programs that lower power consumption on bases and by constructing renewable power generation facilities on selected bases. Unfortunately, these programs will not come close to reaching the goal of islanding the vast majority of bases. Even with massive investment in efficiency and renewables, most bases would not be able to function for more than a few days after the civilian grid went offline Unlike other alternative sources of energy, small reactors have the potential to solve DOD’s vulnerability to grid outages. Most bases have relatively light power demands when compared to civilian towns or cities. Small reactors could easily support bases’ power demands separate from the civilian grid during crises. In some cases, the reactors could be designed to produce enough power not only to supply the base, but also to provide critical services in surrounding towns during long-term outages. Strategically, islanding bases with small reactors has another benefit. One of the main reasons an enemy might be willing to risk reprisals by taking down the U.S. grid during a period of military hostilities would be to affect ongoing military operations. Without the lifeline of intelligence, communication, and logistics provided by U.S. domestic bases, American military operations would be compromised in almost any conceivable contingency. Making bases more resilient to civilian power outages would reduce the incentive for an opponent to attack the grid. An opponent might still attempt to take down the grid for the sake of disrupting civilian systems, but the powerful incentive to do so in order to win an ongoing battle or war would be greatly reduced.
6,328
<h4>Blackouts <strong>collapse deterrence which incentivizes war </h4><p>Andres and</strong> <strong>Breetz</strong> <strong>2011</p><p></strong>Richard, Hanna. Professor of National Security Strategy at the National War College and a Senior Fellow and Energy and Environmental Security and Policy Chair in the Center for Strategic Research, Institute for National Strategic Studies, at the National Defense University, doctoral candidate in the Department of Political Science at The Massachusetts Institute of Technology. “Small Nuclear Reactors for Military Installations: Capabilities, Costs, and Technological Implications”, www.ndu.edu/press/lib/pdf/StrForum/SF-262.pdf</p><p>The DOD interest in small reactors derives largely from problems with base and logistics vulnerability. Over the last few years, the Services have begun to reexamine virtually every aspect of how they generate and use energy with an eye toward cutting costs, decreasing carbon emissions, and reducing energy-related vulnerabilities. These actions have resulted in programs that have significantly reduced DOD energy consumption and greenhouse gas emissions at domestic bases. Despite strong efforts, however, two <u>critical security issues have</u> thus far <u>proven resistant to existing solutions: bases’ vulnerability to civilian power outages, and the need to transport large quantities of fuel via convoys</u> through hostile territory to forward locations. Each of these is explored below. Grid Vulnerability. <u><mark>DOD is unable to provide</mark> its <mark>bases with electricity when the</mark> civilian electrical <mark>grid is offline</mark> for an extended period of time</u>. Currently, <u>domestic military installations receive 99 percent of their electricity from the civilian power grid</u>. As explained in a recent study from the Defense Science Board: DOD’s key problem with electricity is that <u><mark>critical</mark> missions, such as national <mark>strategic awareness and</mark> national <mark>command authorities, are</u></mark> almost<u> entirely <mark>dependent on the</mark> national transmission <mark>grid</u></mark> . . . <u><mark>[which] is</mark> fragile, <mark>vulnerable</mark>, near its capacity limit, and outside of DOD control</u>. In most cases, <u>neither the grid nor on-base backup power provides sufficient reliability to ensure continuity of critical national priority functions and oversight of strategic missions in the face of a long term (several months) outage</u>.7 <u>The grid’s fragility was demonstrated during the 2003 Northeast blackout</u> in which 50 million people in the United States and Canada lost power, some for up to a week, when one Ohio utility failed to properly trim trees. The blackout created cascading disruptions in sewage systems, gas station pumping, cellular communications, border check systems, and so forth, and demonstrated the interdependence of modern infrastructural systems.8 More recently, awareness has been growing <u>that the grid is</u> also <u>vulnerable to purposive attacks</u>. A report sponsored by the Department of Homeland Security suggests that a coordinated cyberattack on the grid could result in a third of the country losing power for a period of weeks or months.9 Cyberattacks on critical infrastructure are not well understood. It is not clear, for instance, whether existing <u>terrorist groups might be able to develop the capability to conduct this type of attack</u>. It is likely, however, <u>that some nation-states either have or are working on developing the ability to take down the U.S. grid</u>. In the event of a war with one of these states, <u>it is possible, if not likely, that parts of the civilian grid would cease to function, taking with them military bases located in affected regions</u>. Government and private <u>organizations are currently working to secure the grid against</u> <u>attacks</u>; however, <u>it is not clear that they will be successful</u>. Most military bases currently have backup power that allows them to function for a period of hours or, at most, a few days on their own. If power were not restored after this amount of time, the results could be disastrous. First, <u>military assets taken offline by the crisis would not be available to help with disaster relief</u>. Second, <u>during an extended blackout, <mark>global military operations could be seriously compromised</mark>; this disruption would be particularly serious if the blackout was induced during major combat operations</u>. During the Cold War, this type of event was far less likely because the United States and Soviet Union shared the common understanding that <u><mark>blinding an opponent</mark> with a grid blackout <mark>could escalate to nuclear war</u></mark>. <u>America’s current opponents</u>, however, <u>may not share this fear or be deterred by this possibility</u>. In 2008, the Defense Science Board stressed that <u>DOD should mitigate the electrical grid’s vulnerabilities by turning military installations into “islands</u>” of energy self-sufficiency.<u> The department has made efforts to do so by promoting efficiency programs</u> that lower power consumption on bases and by <u>constructing <mark>renewable</mark> power generation <mark>facilities</u></mark> on selected bases. <u>Unfortunately, these programs <mark>will not come close to</mark> reaching the goal of islanding the vast majority of bases</u>. <u>Even with massive investment in efficiency and renewables, most bases would not be able to function for more than a few days</u> after the civilian grid went offline <u>Unlike other alternative sources of energy, small reactors have the potential to solve DOD’s vulnerability to grid outages</u>. Most bases have relatively light power demands when compared to civilian towns or cities. <u>Small reactors could easily support bases’ power demands separate from the civilian grid during crises</u>. In some cases, <u>the reactors could be designed to produce enough power not only to supply the base, but also to provide critical services in surrounding towns during long-term outages</u>. Strategically, islanding bases with small reactors has another benefit. <u>One of the main reasons an enemy might be willing to risk reprisals by taking down the U.S. grid during a period of military hostilities would be to affect ongoing military operations. Without the lifeline of</u> intelligence, communication, and logistics provided by <u>U.S. domestic bases, American <mark>military operations would be compromised in</mark> almost <mark>any conceivable contingency</mark>. Making bases more resilient to civilian power outages would reduce the incentive for an opponent to attack the grid</u>. An opponent might still attempt to take down the grid for the sake of disrupting civilian systems, but <u>the powerful incentive to do so in order to win an ongoing battle or war would be greatly reduced</u>.</p>
null
null
3
1,662
430
102,973
./documents/ndtceda18/Texas-Dallas/SaWa/Texas-Dallas-Sanchez-Watson-Neg-Kentucky-Round4.docx
608,210
N
Kentucky
4
Cornell CD
Lowe
2nr - Dedev 1nc - ESR - MT w warming - NAFTA DA- T- restrictions
ndtceda18/Texas-Dallas/SaWa/Texas-Dallas-Sanchez-Watson-Neg-Kentucky-Round4.docx
null
51,570
SaWa
Texas-Dallas SaWa
null
Ra.....
Sa.....
So.....
Wa.....
19,218
Texas-Dallas
Texas-Dallas
null
null
1,008
ndtceda18
NDT/CEDA 2018-19
2,018
cx
college
2
1,101,660
1AC Ord concludes that there is no risk of extinction from Warming AND it’s not inevitable
1AC Ord 20
Dr. Toby 1AC Ord 20, Senior Research Fellow in Philosophy at Oxford University, DPhil in Philosophy from the University of Oxford, The Precipice: Existential Risk and the Future of Humanity, Hachette Books, Kindle Edition, p. 110-112
the purpose of this chapter is finding and assessing threats that pose a direct existential risk to humanity Even at extreme levels it is difficult to see exactly how climate change could do so effects include reduced ag yields, sea level rises, water scarcity, increased diseases, ocean acidification and collapse of the Gulf Stream none threaten extinction Crops are less sensitive to increases we would still have food Even if sea levels rose hundreds of meters most of the Earth’s land area would remain More may become susceptible to tropical diseases, but look to the tropics to see civilization flourish a concern is that the high temperatures might cause a large loss of biodiversity and subsequent ecosystem collapse Yet the evidence is mixed. For when we look at many of the past cases of extremely high global temperatures or extremely rapid warming we don’t see a corresponding loss of biodiversity We don’t see such biodiversity loss in the 12°C warmer climate of the early Eocene, nor the rapid global change of the PETM, nor in rapid regional changes of climate the rates and magnitude of climate change are similar to those predicted for the future and therefore potentially relevant to understanding future biotic response. What emerges from these past records is evidence for rapid community turnover, migrations, development of novel ecosystems and thresholds from one stable ecosystem state to another, but there is very little evidence for broad-scale extinctions due to a warming world.” There are similar conclusions in Botkin Dawson Hof and Willis & MacDonald the most important known effect of climate change from the perspective of direct existential risk is heat stress However, substantial regions would also remain below this threshold. Even with an extreme 20°C of warming there would be many coastal areas (and some elevated regions) that would have no days above the temperature/humidity threshold So there would remain large areas in which humanity and civilization could continue it is hard to see how any realistic level of heat stress could pose such a risk direct existential risk from climate change appears very small
Even at extreme levels none threaten extinction Crops are less sensitive we would have food Even if sea levels rose hundreds of meters most land remain past cases of high temp s don’t see a loss of biod of the Eocene, nor PETM there is very little ev for broad extinctions due to warming most important is heat stress However, substantial regions remain below Even with 20°C warming many coastal areas (and elevated regions remain civ could continue existential risk from climate appears very small
But the purpose of this chapter is finding and assessing threats that pose a direct existential risk to humanity. Even at such extreme levels of warming, it is difficult to see exactly how climate change could do so. Major effects of climate change include reduced agricultural yields, sea level rises, water scarcity, increased tropical diseases, ocean acidification and the collapse of the Gulf Stream. While extremely important when assessing the overall risks of climate change, none of these threaten extinction or irrevocable collapse. Crops are very sensitive to reductions in temperature (due to frosts), but less sensitive to increases. By all appearances we would still have food to support civilization.85 Even if sea levels rose hundreds of meters (over centuries), most of the Earth’s land area would remain. Similarly, while some areas might conceivably become uninhabitable due to water scarcity, other areas will have increased rainfall. More areas may become susceptible to tropical diseases, but we need only look to the tropics to see civilization flourish despite this. The main effect of a collapse of the system of Atlantic Ocean currents that includes the Gulf Stream is a 2°C cooling of Europe—something that poses no permanent threat to global civilization. From an existential risk perspective, a more serious concern is that the high temperatures (and the rapidity of their change) might cause a large loss of biodiversity and subsequent ecosystem collapse. While the pathway is not entirely clear, a large enough collapse of ecosystems across the globe could perhaps threaten human extinction. The idea that climate change could cause widespread extinctions has some good theoretical support.86 Yet the evidence is mixed. For when we look at many of the past cases of extremely high global temperatures or extremely rapid warming we don’t see a corresponding loss of biodiversity.87 [FOOTNOTE] We don’t see such biodiversity loss in the 12°C warmer climate of the early Eocene, nor the rapid global change of the PETM, nor in rapid regional changes of climate. Willis et al. (2010) state: “We argue that although the underlying mechanisms responsible for these past changes in climate were very different (i.e. natural processes rather than anthropogenic), the rates and magnitude of climate change are similar to those predicted for the future and therefore potentially relevant to understanding future biotic response. What emerges from these past records is evidence for rapid community turnover, migrations, development of novel ecosystems and thresholds from one stable ecosystem state to another, but there is very little evidence for broad-scale extinctions due to a warming world.” There are similar conclusions in Botkin et al. (2007), Dawson et al. (2011), Hof et al. (2011) and Willis & MacDonald (2011). The best evidence of warming causing extinction may be from the end-Permian mass extinction, which may have been associated with large-scale warming (see note 91 to this chapter). [END FOOTNOTE] So the most important known effect of climate change from the perspective of direct existential risk is probably the most obvious: heat stress. We need an environment cooler than our body temperature to be able to rid ourselves of waste heat and stay alive. More precisely, we need to be able to lose heat by sweating, which depends on the humidity as well as the temperature. A landmark paper by Steven Sherwood and Matthew Huber showed that with sufficient warming there would be parts of the world whose temperature and humidity combine to exceed the level where humans could survive without air conditioning.88 With 12°C of warming, a very large land area—where more than half of all people currently live and where much of our food is grown—would exceed this level at some point during a typical year. Sherwood and Huber suggest that such areas would be uninhabitable. This may not quite be true (particularly if air conditioning is possible during the hottest months), but their habitability is at least in question. However, substantial regions would also remain below this threshold. Even with an extreme 20°C of warming there would be many coastal areas (and some elevated regions) that would have no days above the temperature/humidity threshold.89 So there would remain large areas in which humanity and civilization could continue. A world with 20°C of warming would be an unparalleled human and environmental tragedy, forcing mass migration and perhaps starvation too. This is reason enough to do our utmost to prevent anything like that from ever happening. However, our present task is identifying existential risks to humanity and it is hard to see how any realistic level of heat stress could pose such a risk. So the runaway and moist greenhouse effects remain the only known mechanisms through which climate change could directly cause our extinction or irrevocable collapse. This doesn’t rule out unknown mechanisms. We are considering large changes to the Earth that may even be unprecedented in size or speed. It wouldn’t be astonishing if that directly led to our permanent ruin. The best argument against such unknown mechanisms is probably that the PETM did not lead to a mass extinction, despite temperatures rapidly rising about 5°C, to reach a level 14°C above pre-industrial temperatures.90 But this is tempered by the imprecision of paleoclimate data, the sparsity of the fossil record, the smaller size of mammals at the time (making them more heat-tolerant), and a reluctance to rely on a single example. Most importantly, anthropogenic warming could be over a hundred times faster than warming during the PETM, and rapid warming has been suggested as a contributing factor in the end-Permian mass extinction, in which 96 percent of species went extinct.91 In the end, we can say little more than that direct existential risk from climate change appears very small, but cannot yet be ruled out.
5,965
<h4>1AC Ord concludes that there is <u>no risk</u> of extinction from Warming AND it’s not inevitable</h4><p>Dr. Toby <strong>1AC Ord 20</strong>, Senior Research Fellow in Philosophy at Oxford University, DPhil in Philosophy from the University of Oxford, The Precipice: Existential Risk and the Future of Humanity, Hachette Books, Kindle Edition, p. 110-112</p><p>But <u><strong>the purpose of this chapter is finding and assessing threats that pose a direct existential risk to humanity</u></strong>. <u><mark>Even at</u></mark> such <u><strong><mark>extreme levels</u></strong></mark> of warming, <u>it is difficult to see exactly how climate change could do so</u>. Major <u>effects</u> of climate change <u>include reduced <strong>ag</u></strong>ricultural <u>yields, sea level rises, water scarcity, increased</u> tropical <u>diseases, ocean acidification and</u> the <u>collapse of the Gulf Stream</u>. While extremely important when assessing the overall risks of climate change, <u><strong><mark>none</u></strong></mark> of these <u><strong><mark>threaten extinction</u></strong></mark> or irrevocable collapse.</p><p><u><mark>Crops are</u></mark> very sensitive to reductions in temperature (due to frosts), but <u><mark>less sensitive</mark> to increases</u>. By all appearances <u><mark>we would</mark> <strong>still <mark>have food</u></strong></mark> to support civilization.85 <u><mark>Even if sea levels rose <strong>hundreds of meters</u></strong></mark> (over centuries), <u><strong><mark>most</strong></mark> of the Earth’s <mark>land</mark> area would <mark>remain</u></mark>. Similarly, while some areas might conceivably become uninhabitable due to water scarcity, other areas will have increased rainfall. <u>More</u> areas <u>may become susceptible to tropical diseases, but</u> we need only <u>look to the tropics to see civilization <strong>flourish</u></strong> despite this. The main effect of a collapse of the system of Atlantic Ocean currents that includes the Gulf Stream is a 2°C cooling of Europe—something that poses no permanent threat to global civilization. </p><p>From an existential risk perspective, <u>a</u> more serious <u>concern is that the high temperatures</u> (and the rapidity of their change) <u>might cause a large loss of biodiversity and subsequent ecosystem collapse</u>. While the pathway is not entirely clear, a large enough collapse of ecosystems across the globe could perhaps threaten human extinction. The idea that climate change could cause widespread extinctions has some good theoretical support.86 <u>Yet the evidence is <strong>mixed</strong>. For when we look at many of the <strong><mark>past cases</strong> of</mark> extremely <mark>high</mark> global <strong><mark>temp</strong></mark>erature<strong><mark>s</strong></mark> or extremely rapid warming we <strong><mark>don’t see</strong> a</mark> corresponding <mark>loss of <strong>biod</strong></mark>iversity</u>.87 </p><p>[FOOTNOTE]</p><p><u>We don’t see such biodiversity loss in the <strong>12°C warmer climate</strong> <mark>of the</mark> <strong>early <mark>Eocene</strong>, nor</mark> the rapid global change of the <strong><mark>PETM</strong></mark>, nor in rapid <strong>regional</strong> changes of climate</u>. Willis et al. (2010) state: “We argue that although the underlying mechanisms responsible for these past changes in climate were very different (i.e. natural processes rather than anthropogenic), <u>the rates and magnitude of climate change are similar to those predicted for the future and therefore potentially <strong>relevant</strong> to understanding future biotic response. What emerges from these past records is evidence for <strong>rapid community turnover</strong>, <strong>migrations</strong>, <strong>development</strong> of novel ecosystems and thresholds from one stable ecosystem state to another, but <mark>there is <strong>very little ev</mark>idence</strong> <mark>for <strong>broad</mark>-scale <mark>extinctions</strong> due to</mark> a <mark>warming</mark> world.” There are similar conclusions in <strong>Botkin</u></strong> et al. (2007), <u><strong>Dawson</u></strong> et al. (2011), <u><strong>Hof</u></strong> et al. (2011) <u>and <strong>Willis & MacDonald</u></strong> (2011). The best evidence of warming causing extinction may be from the end-Permian mass extinction, which may have been associated with large-scale warming (see note 91 to this chapter).</p><p>[END FOOTNOTE]</p><p>So <u>the <mark>most important</mark> known effect of climate change from the perspective of direct existential risk <mark>is</u></mark> probably the most obvious: <u><strong><mark>heat stress</u></strong></mark>. We need an environment cooler than our body temperature to be able to rid ourselves of waste heat and stay alive. More precisely, we need to be able to lose heat by sweating, which depends on the humidity as well as the temperature. </p><p>A landmark paper by Steven Sherwood and Matthew Huber showed that with sufficient warming there would be parts of the world whose temperature and humidity combine to exceed the level where humans could survive without air conditioning.88 With 12°C of warming, a very large land area—where more than half of all people currently live and where much of our food is grown—would exceed this level at some point during a typical year. Sherwood and Huber suggest that such areas would be uninhabitable. This may not quite be true (particularly if air conditioning is possible during the hottest months), but their habitability is at least in question. </p><p><u><mark>However, <strong>substantial regions</strong></mark> would also <strong><mark>remain below</strong></mark> this threshold. <strong><mark>Even with</mark> an extreme <mark>20°C</mark> of <mark>warming</strong></mark> there would be <strong><mark>many</strong> coastal areas (and</mark> some <strong><mark>elevated regions</strong></mark>) that would have no days above the temperature/humidity threshold</u>.89 <u>So there would <mark>remain</mark> <strong>large areas</strong> in which humanity and <strong><mark>civ</strong></mark>ilization <mark>could <strong>continue</u></strong></mark>. A world with 20°C of warming would be an unparalleled human and environmental tragedy, forcing mass migration and perhaps starvation too. This is reason enough to do our utmost to prevent anything like that from ever happening. However, our present task is identifying existential risks to humanity and <u>it is hard to see how any realistic level of heat stress could pose such a risk</u>. So the runaway and moist greenhouse effects remain the only known mechanisms through which climate change could directly cause our extinction or irrevocable collapse.</p><p>This doesn’t rule out unknown mechanisms. We are considering large changes to the Earth that may even be unprecedented in size or speed. It wouldn’t be astonishing if that directly led to our permanent ruin. The best argument against such unknown mechanisms is probably that the PETM did not lead to a mass extinction, despite temperatures rapidly rising about 5°C, to reach a level 14°C above pre-industrial temperatures.90 But this is tempered by the imprecision of paleoclimate data, the sparsity of the fossil record, the smaller size of mammals at the time (making them more heat-tolerant), and a reluctance to rely on a single example. Most importantly, anthropogenic warming could be over a hundred times faster than warming during the PETM, and rapid warming has been suggested as a contributing factor in the end-Permian mass extinction, in which 96 percent of species went extinct.91 In the end, we can say little more than that <u>direct <mark>existential risk from climate</mark> change <mark>appears <strong>very small</u></strong></mark>, but cannot yet be ruled out.</p>
1NC vs MBA AB
Adv 1
1NC --- AT: Adaptation
17,606
401
26,277
./documents/hspolicy21/Decatur/LaKo/Decatur-Lam-Kochel-Neg-Samford-Round3.docx
746,034
N
Samford
3
MBA AB
Riley Talamantes
1AC - SDGs 1NC - T Permitting ADV CP States CP MENA DA BBB DA EPA Trade off DA Litigation DA Case 2NC - T ADV CP Case 1NR - MENA DA EPA DA 2NR - T EPA ADV CP Case
hspolicy21/Decatur/LaKo/Decatur-Lam-Kochel-Neg-Samford-Round3.docx
null
63,612
LaKo
Decatur LaKo
null
Aa.....
La.....
Wi.....
Ko.....
21,941
Decatur
Decatur
GA
null
1,020
hspolicy21
HS Policy 2021-22
2,021
cx
hs
2
1,085,809
That’s key to clash — procedures are necessary and sufficient to facilitate argumentation—exploding limits wrecks argumentative processes which turns the case.
Dascal and Knoll ’11
Dascal and Knoll ’11 [Marcelo and Amnon; May 18th; former Professor of Philosophy at Tel Aviv University, B.A. in Philosophy from the University of Sao Paulo; former Professor of Philosophy at Tel Aviv University; Argumentation: Cognition and Community, "'Cognitive systemic dichotomization' in public argumentation and controversies," p. 20-25]
in the present critical discussion is far from being successfully applied debates are monologues calculated only to win the audience’s consent to one’s own views”, rather than ‘genuine discussions’ intellectual exchange This can be achieved only by following “the dialectical rules for argumentative discourse Are there structural, obstacles in idealized critical discussion that prevents even its approximate use ? these doubts require parameters : The preconditions for initiating critical discussion: The argumentative process context and agents argumentation is a voluntary endeavor Argumentation consists in putting forth a position by one of the parties for critical examination of the other critical discussion can only be realized if preconditions are satisfied. The most important are a clear-cut identification of the standpoint that provokes the disagreement and commitment to procedural rules This precondition assumes it is possible to isolate rigorously the subject matter to conduct focused discussion This precondition stresses the ‘contractual’ character of a critical discussion, which requires explicit mutual commitments by the discussants. without commitments the aim of critical discussion will not be achieved, which makes engaging pointless ‘first order’ preconditions are conditions that candidates to participate must fulfill a requirement is anticipated identification of the starting point in order to ensure satisfactory closure
debates are monologues calculated only to win consent to one’s views”, rather than ‘genuine exchange This can be achieved only by following rules for argument Are there structural obstacles in idealized discussion that prevents its approximate use ? these doubts require parameters : preconditions for initiating discussion argumentative process context and agents argumentation is voluntary Argument consists putting forth a position by one of the parties for examination of the other discussion can only be realized if preconditions are satisfied clear identification of the standpoint that provokes disagreement and rules This precondition assumes it is possible to isolate the subject to conduct discussion This precondition requires mutual commitments by discussants without commitments the aim of discussion will not be achieved, which makes engaging pointless preconditions are conditions that candidates must fulfill a requirement is identification of the start
He opposes positions whose ‘exclusionist’ outlook rejects the normative approach to the political sphere on the grounds that “normative statements can never be subjected to a reasonable discussion” (ibid.: 2), because—he argues—the discussion of politics “is an area of vital interest to all of us and should clearly not be excluded from argumentative reasonableness” (ibid.: 3)—a view with which we are prone to agree. Nevertheless, he admits that in the present situation critical discussion is far from being systematically and successfully applied to that vital area: “In representative democracies, however, the out-comes of the political process tend to be predominantly the product of negotiations be-tween political leaders rather than the result of a universal and mutual process of deliberative disputation” (ibid.). Political debates, therefore, are ‘quasi-discussions’, i.e., “monologues calculated only to win the audience’s consent to one’s own views”, rather than ‘genuine discussions’, i.e., serious attempts to have an intellectual exchange, which is typical of critical discussions (ibid.). In order to overcome this situation, “democracy should always have promoted such a critical discussion of standpoints as a central aim. Only if this is the case can stimulating participation in political discourse enhance the quality of democracy" (ibid.). This can be achieved, however, only by following “the dialectical rules for argumentative discourse that make up a code of conduct for political discourse [and] are therefore of crucial importance to giving substance to the ideal of participatory democracy” (ibid.: 4); thereby fully acknowledging that “education in processing argumentation in a critical discussion is indispensable for a democratic society (van Eemeren 1995: 145-146). The reasons provided for the failure of the adoption of the critical discussion model in reality ranges from a general allusion to human nature (“in real-life contexts, it has to be taken into account that human interaction is not always automatically 'naturally' and fully oriented toward the ideal of dialectical reasonableness "; van Eemeren 2010: 4) to specific political sphere argumentation handicaps (unwillingness of people “to subject their thinking to critical scrutiny”; “vested interest in particular outcome”; “inequality in power and resources; “different levels of critical skills”; and “a practical demand for an immediate settlement”; van Eemeren 2010: 4). Although these causes may have some explanatory value in some cases, in our opinion their modus operandi is not accounted for and, what is more important, they do not cover the full spectrum of challenges that the successful use of critical discussion in the public and political spheres must face, as we have seen (cf. sections 2 and 3). No wonder that van Eemeren himself raises the question “whether maintaining the dialectical ideal of critical discussion in political and other real-life contexts is not utopian” (ibid.), to which he replies by admitting that "[t]he ideal of a critical discussion is by definition not a description of any kind of reality but sets a theoretical standard that can be used for heuristic, analytic and evaluative purpose” (ibid.). This ideal seems to be so inspiring that it remains valid as a pure theoretical ideal, “even if the argumentative discourse falls short of the dialectical ideal” (ibid.). In the light of the substantial gap between the normative ideal and the actual practices of public and political argumentation that PD’s description and explanation provides, a number of doubts arise: Are there structural, rather than merely contingent obstacles in idealized critical discussion that prevents even its approximate use in the public sphere? Can a theory that claims to be a praxis based normative system fulfill its promise if it sets up a threshold that no one who tries to apply it to the public sphere can reach? Doesn’t the very fact that argumentation is excessively idealized in the model PD proposes cause the gap by distancing people concerned by public issues from argumentation at all? All these doubts suggest that a powerful structural phenomenon like the existence of CSDs in the public sphere is perhaps overlooked by PD and requires, for its overcoming, a radically different approach. 4.2 Discrepancies between the PD approach and reasonable argumentation in the public sphere The discrepancies in question have to do with basic parameters relevant to every argumentative process, namely: (A) The discussants’ goals and targets: what do they expect to achieve through the argumentation process and what is it capable of providing. (B) The preconditions for initiating a critical discussion: what are the discussants presumed to know and accept of these preconditions. (C) The argumentative process that is supposed to lead to the achievement of the discussants’ goals. (D) The influence of context and agents on the argumentative process. 4.2.1 Goals Assuming that argumentation is a voluntary endeavor, the parties are presumed to engage in it if and only if: (i) the process will serve their goals; (ii) these goals cannot be achieved by different, better means. PD describes as follows the aim of engaging in an argumentative process: Argumentation is basically aimed at resolving a difference of opinion about the acceptability of a standpoint by making an appeal to the other party's reasonableness. (van Eemeren 2010: 1, with reference to van Eemeren & Grootendorst 2004: 11-18) The difference of opinion is resolved when the antagonist accepts the protagonist's viewpoint on the basis of the arguments advanced or when the protagonist abandons his viewpoint as a result of the critical responses of the antagonist. (van Eemeren 2010: 33) Simply put, the basic assumption is that a critical discussion’s aim consists in putting forth a certain position by one of the parties for the critical examination of the other, who calls it into question. The latter undertakes to refute the former’s position, while its proponent is committed to defend it. Four stages (see below) are supposed to ensure a valid performance of the refutation and defense tasks. The essential point is that at the end of the four stages the parties clearly agree whether the proponent’s position has been refuted or not and, accordingly, change their position (either retracting it or withdrawing from his questioning). In ‘mixed’ disagreements, in which the antagonist not only questions but also puts forth an opposed position, the same process takes place sequentially, i.e., at first one side (A) attacks trying to refute the other’s (B) position, and after this stage is concluded, they switch roles and the second side (B) proceeds to attack the first (A) in the same fashion. Regardless of whether the described process is indeed capable to yield a conclusive decision about the refutation of a position, and of whether the linearity of the refutation process makes sense, it is obvious that debates in the public sphere are for the most part ‘mixed’. Furthermore, in so far as these debates involve dichotomous positions (rather than just opposed ones), it is necessary that at the end of the PD process one of the parties accept the position of the other. It is also worth noticing that, contrary to deliberative democracy approaches, which in some cases approve the attempt to reach agreement in a (public) debate as a form of justification of political systems, PD claims that it is not a consensus theory at all. Instead, it conceives itself as a theory based on Popper’s critical rationality, i.e., as having as its principal goal to provide each party with the means—i.e., refutation attempts—to test critically its position: [T]he conception of reasonableness upheld in pragma-dialectics insights from critical rationalist epistemology and utilitarian ethics conjoin … The intersubjective acceptability we attribute to the procedure, which is eventually expected to lend conventional validity to the procedure, is primarily based on its instrumentality in doing the job it is intended to do: re-solving a difference of opinion. … This means that, philosophically speaking, the rationale for accepting the pragma-dialectical procedure is pragmatic—more precisely, utilitarian [italics in quoted text]. … However, based on Popper's falsification idea, this is a ‘negative’ and not ‘positive’, utilitarianism. … Rather than maximization of agreement, minimization of disagreement is to be aimed for. (van Eemeren 2010: 34) The distinction between maximization of agreement and minimization of disagreement purports to stress that PD doesn’t view agreement as the suitable end of the process, but just as “an intermediate step on the way to new, and more advanced, disagreements” (van Eemeren 2010: 26n). Nevertheless, no explanation is given of how these “more advanced disagreements” are engendered as a part of the dynamics of the critical process, nor what is the role or value of such disagreements in the public sphere or elsewhere. This may be due to the fact that PD’s ‘critical discussion’ is not tuned to the generation of new positions or ideas but only to the testing of extant ones, thus echoing once again Popper, now in his focus on the justification rather than on the discovery of theories (see sections 4.2.4 and 5). In any case, it is quite clear that the only practical result of the critical discussion à la PD of opposed positions on a public issue is to determine whether one discussant succeeded in refuting the other’s position, thus obtaining the adversary’s agreement, who will then share his/her position, at least for some time. In this respect, PD’s critical discussion is close to Habermas’s ‘reasonable argumentation’, whose aim is to reach consensus.15 In spite of the apparent difference between a critical examination of a position aiming at its refutation or at its acceptance, even van Eemeren admits, to some extent, their similarity. He points out that “the pragma-dialectical procedure deals only with ‘first order’ conditions for resolving differences of opinion on the merits by means of critical discussion” (van Eemeren 2010: 34), and stresses that there are ‘higher order’ conditions, ‘internal’ and ‘external’, that are “beyond the agent’s control”, conditions that are similar to Habermas’s “ideal speech conditions” (van Eemeren 2010: 35n). Anyhow, whether according to PD the main goal of the critical discussion process in the public alliance is to create the opportunity for refutation or for agreement (meaning that one of the discussants acknowledges that his position is wrong), the essential assumption of this process is that the participants in it in the public sphere (or elsewhere) must be aware that one of them holds a wrong position and will have to explicitly acknowledge this. Is such a goal, especially when conceived as the ultimate aim of the proposed argumentative process, feasible and acceptable in the public sphere? In our opinion, there are at least four reasons for arguing that it is a utopian, hence unacceptable goal, if one takes seriously what should be expected from argumentative practice and theory in the public sphere. First, because PD deserves a critique similar to the one leveled against the Popperian version of critical rationalism it espouses,16 which defends a theory of knowledge “without a knowing subject” (Popper 1972); obviously, such a-contextual position becomes even more problematic if applied to the public and political spheres, where it must operate in a context essentially involved with practical rationality. Second, due to its analogy with theories such as Habermas’s that were discussed in this section as well as in 2.2—an analogy that deserves additional criticism because, unlike Habermasianism, PD overlooks the relationship between the political and public context and argumentative practice. Third, because of PD’s total overlooking of the role of CSDs in public argumentation (cf. 4.2.2). And fourth, due to unilateral value judgments of positions in the public sphere, which lead to simplistic criteria of refutation or acceptance in a domain where complexity is the rule (cf. 2.1.1 and 4.2.3). (ii) Let us admit, for the sake of argument, that the refutation goal as claimed by PD is central, feasible, acceptable, and useful in public argumentation. Aren’t there better ways to achieve this goal? The refutation and defense moves stipulated by the PD critical discussion model include, on the one side, the antagonist’s critical remarks or demands and on the other, the proponent’s replies. We believe that it must be assumed that neither the critique nor the replies are previously known to the contenders, which is why they have an interest in engage in the argumentation process: presumably, the expression of both, counter-arguments and defensive-arguments, is good to both sides. In spite of its usefulness in certain situations, this kind of exchange does not amount to the full manifestation of the dialectical critical process, wherein the context and co-text of the dialectical exchange, as well as the cognitive interaction that takes place and evolves throughout the exchange, play a decisive role in the design and ‘inner’ justification of each of the participants’ moves. Argumentation strategies that take into account these resources and make full use of their potential are no doubt setting up another, broader span of goals for the argumentative process, and are more likely to achieve these goals more effectively than they certainly would achieve their PD more limited counterparts (cf. 4.2.4 and 5). 4.2.2 Preconditions The ideal PD critical discussion can only be realized if some preconditions are satisfied. The most important ones are a) a clear-cut identification of the standpoint that provokes the disagreement, b) the decision of the parties to engage in a discussion, and c) the participants’ commitment to obey the procedural rules. As we shall see, these preconditions share a common assumption, which calls into question the feasibility of using critical discussion in the public sphere. (A) This precondition assumes that it is possible to isolate rigorously the subject matter of a critical discussion, so as to conduct a focused discussion that makes use only of relevant arguments. This precondition is quite strict, for whenever both discussants defend contrary standpoints, their disagreement should be treated as two separate fully fledged discussions: “… if another discussion begins, it must go through the same stages again—from confrontation stage to concluding stage” (van Eemeren 2010: 10n). (B) This precondition subordinates the decision to engage in the discussion to the evaluation that the discussants share enough common ground to pursue it adequately: “After the parties have decided that there is enough common ground to conduct a discussion …” (van Eemeren 2010: 33). (C) This precondition stresses the ‘contractual’ character of a critical discussion, which requires explicit mutual commitments by the discussants. Its rationale is that without such commitments the aim of the critical discussion, i.e., the resolution of the difference of opinions, will not be achieved, which makes engaging in the discussion pointless: “There is no point in venturing to resolve a difference … if there is no mutual commitment to a common starting point, which may include procedural commitments as well as substantive agreement” (van Eemeren and Grootendorst 2004: 60). These ‘first order’ preconditions, as they are labeled in PD (cf. van Eemeren 2010: 33), are the conditions that candidates to participate in a critical discussion must fulfill if they intend to do so and can afford it personally (a ‘second order’ condition) and politically (a ‘third order’ condition).17 In addition, the first order conditions demand from the prospective discussants a clear, distinct, and detailed picture of the scope of the discussion that they are about to engage in. This means not mixing up the various differences of opinion that the discussion may involve, and being able to separate them properly as the subject matter for independent discussions; a further requirement is the anticipated identification of the pieces of the ‘substantive agreement’ forming the starting point in order to ensure that they are sufficient for conducting the discussion up to a satisfactory closure.
16,476
<h4>That’s key to <u>clash</u> — <u>procedures</u> are necessary and sufficient to <u>facilitate argumentation</u>—exploding limits wrecks argumentative processes which turns the case.</h4><p><strong>Dascal and Knoll ’11</strong> [Marcelo and Amnon; May 18th; former Professor of Philosophy at Tel Aviv University, B.A. in Philosophy from the University of Sao Paulo; former Professor of Philosophy at Tel Aviv University; Argumentation: Cognition and Community, "'Cognitive systemic dichotomization' in public argumentation and controversies," p. 20-25]</p><p>He opposes positions whose ‘exclusionist’ outlook rejects the normative approach to the political sphere on the grounds that “normative statements can never be subjected to a reasonable discussion” (ibid.: 2), because—he argues—the discussion of politics “is an area of vital interest to all of us and should clearly not be excluded from argumentative reasonableness” (ibid.: 3)—a view with which we are prone to agree. Nevertheless, he admits that <u>in the <strong>present</u></strong> situation <u>critical discussion is far from being </u>systematically and <u>successfully applied</u> to that vital area: “In representative democracies, however, the out-comes of the political process tend to be predominantly the product of negotiations be-tween political leaders rather than the result of a universal and mutual process of deliberative disputation” (ibid.). Political <u><strong><mark>debates</u></strong></mark>, therefore, <u><mark>are</u></mark> ‘quasi-discussions’, i.e., “<u><strong><mark>monologues calculated</strong> only to <strong>win</strong></mark> the <strong>audience’s <mark>consent</strong> to one’s <strong></mark>own <mark>views</strong>”, rather than ‘<strong>genuine</strong></mark> discussions’</u>, i.e., serious attempts to have an <u><strong>intellectual <mark>exchange</u></strong></mark>, which is typical of critical discussions (ibid.). In order to overcome this situation, “democracy should always have promoted such a critical discussion of standpoints as a central aim. Only if this is the case can stimulating participation in political discourse enhance the quality of democracy" (ibid.). <u><mark>This can be achieved</u></mark>, however, <u><strong><mark>only</strong> by following</mark> “the dialectical <strong><mark>rules for argument</mark>ative discourse</u></strong> that make up a code of conduct for political discourse [and] are therefore of crucial importance to giving substance to the ideal of participatory democracy” (ibid.: 4); thereby fully acknowledging that “education in processing argumentation in a critical discussion is indispensable for a democratic society (van Eemeren 1995: 145-146). </p><p>The reasons provided for the failure of the adoption of the critical discussion model in reality ranges from a general allusion to human nature (“in real-life contexts, it has to be taken into account that human interaction is not always automatically 'naturally' and fully oriented toward the ideal of dialectical reasonableness "; van Eemeren 2010: 4) to specific political sphere argumentation handicaps (unwillingness of people “to subject their thinking to critical scrutiny”; “vested interest in particular outcome”; “inequality in power and resources; “different levels of critical skills”; and “a practical demand for an immediate settlement”; van Eemeren 2010: 4). Although these causes may have some explanatory value in some cases, in our opinion their modus operandi is not accounted for and, what is more important, they do not cover the full spectrum of challenges that the successful use of critical discussion in the public and political spheres must face, as we have seen (cf. sections 2 and 3).</p><p>No wonder that van Eemeren himself raises the question “whether maintaining the dialectical ideal of critical discussion in political and other real-life contexts is not utopian” (ibid.), to which he replies by admitting that "[t]he ideal of a critical discussion is by definition not a description of any kind of reality but sets a theoretical standard that can be used for heuristic, analytic and evaluative purpose” (ibid.). This ideal seems to be so inspiring that it remains valid as a pure theoretical ideal, “even if the argumentative discourse falls short of the dialectical ideal” (ibid.). </p><p>In the light of the substantial gap between the normative ideal and the actual practices of public and political argumentation that PD’s description and explanation provides, a number of doubts arise: <u><mark>Are there <strong>structural</strong></mark>,</u> rather than merely contingent <u><mark>obstacles in idealized <strong></mark>critical <mark>discussion</strong> that prevents</mark> even <mark>its <strong>approximate use</u></strong></mark> in the public sphere<u><strong><mark>?</u></strong></mark> Can a theory that claims to be a praxis based normative system fulfill its promise if it sets up a threshold that no one who tries to apply it to the public sphere can reach? Doesn’t the very fact that argumentation is excessively idealized in the model PD proposes cause the gap by distancing people concerned by public issues from argumentation at all? All <u><mark>these doubts</u></mark> suggest that a powerful structural phenomenon like the existence of CSDs in the public sphere is perhaps overlooked by PD and <u><strong><mark>require</u></strong></mark>s, for its overcoming, a radically different approach. </p><p>4.2 Discrepancies between the PD approach and reasonable argumentation in the public sphere </p><p>The discrepancies in question have to do with basic <u><strong><mark>parameters</u></strong></mark> relevant to every argumentative process, namely<u><mark>:</p><p></u></mark>(A) The discussants’ goals and targets: what do they expect to achieve through the argumentation process and what is it capable of providing. </p><p>(B) <u>The <strong><mark>preconditions</strong> for initiating</u></mark> a <u><strong>critical <mark>discussion</strong></mark>:</u> what are the discussants presumed to know and accept of these preconditions. </p><p>(C) <u>The <strong><mark>argumentative process</u></strong></mark> that is supposed to lead to the achievement of the discussants’ goals. </p><p>(D) The influence of <u><strong><mark>context and agents</u></strong></mark> on the argumentative process. </p><p>4.2.1 Goals </p><p>Assuming that <u><mark>argumentation is</mark> a <strong><mark>voluntary</mark> endeavor</u></strong>, the parties are presumed to engage in it if and only if: (i) the process will serve their goals; (ii) these goals cannot be achieved by different, better means.</p><p>PD describes as follows the aim of engaging in an argumentative process: </p><p><u><strong><mark>Argument</mark>ation</u></strong> is basically aimed at resolving a difference of opinion about the acceptability of a standpoint by making an appeal to the other party's reasonableness. (van Eemeren 2010: 1, with reference to van Eemeren & Grootendorst 2004: 11-18) </p><p>The difference of opinion is resolved when the antagonist accepts the protagonist's viewpoint on the basis of the arguments advanced or when the protagonist abandons his viewpoint as a result of the critical responses of the antagonist. (van Eemeren 2010: 33)</p><p>Simply put, the basic assumption is that a critical discussion’s aim <u><mark>consists</mark> in <mark>putting forth a</u></mark> certain <u><strong><mark>position</strong> by one of the parties for</u></mark> the <u><strong>critical <mark>examination</strong> of the other</u></mark>, who calls it into question. The latter undertakes to refute the former’s position, while its proponent is committed to defend it. Four stages (see below) are supposed to ensure a valid performance of the refutation and defense tasks. The essential point is that at the end of the four stages the parties clearly agree whether the proponent’s position has been refuted or not and, accordingly, change their position (either retracting it or withdrawing from his questioning). In ‘mixed’ disagreements, in which the antagonist not only questions but also puts forth an opposed position, the same process takes place sequentially, i.e., at first one side (A) attacks trying to refute the other’s (B) position, and after this stage is concluded, they switch roles and the second side (B) proceeds to attack the first (A) in the same fashion.</p><p>Regardless of whether the described process is indeed capable to yield a conclusive decision about the refutation of a position, and of whether the linearity of the refutation process makes sense, it is obvious that debates in the public sphere are for the most part ‘mixed’. Furthermore, in so far as these debates involve dichotomous positions (rather than just opposed ones), it is necessary that at the end of the PD process one of the parties accept the position of the other.</p><p>It is also worth noticing that, contrary to deliberative democracy approaches, which in some cases approve the attempt to reach agreement in a (public) debate as a form of justification of political systems, PD claims that it is not a consensus theory at all. Instead, it conceives itself as a theory based on Popper’s critical rationality, i.e., as having as its principal goal to provide each party with the means—i.e., refutation attempts—to test critically its position: </p><p>[T]he conception of reasonableness upheld in pragma-dialectics insights from critical rationalist epistemology and utilitarian ethics conjoin … The intersubjective acceptability we attribute to the procedure, which is eventually expected to lend conventional validity to the procedure, is primarily based on its instrumentality in doing the job it is intended to do: re-solving a difference of opinion. … This means that, philosophically speaking, the rationale for accepting the pragma-dialectical procedure is pragmatic—more precisely, utilitarian [italics in quoted text]. … However, based on Popper's falsification idea, this is a ‘negative’ and not ‘positive’, utilitarianism. … Rather than maximization of agreement, minimization of disagreement is to be aimed for. (van Eemeren 2010: 34) </p><p>The distinction between maximization of agreement and minimization of disagreement purports to stress that PD doesn’t view agreement as the suitable end of the process, but just as “an intermediate step on the way to new, and more advanced, disagreements” (van Eemeren 2010: 26n). Nevertheless, no explanation is given of how these “more advanced disagreements” are engendered as a part of the dynamics of the critical process, nor what is the role or value of such disagreements in the public sphere or elsewhere. This may be due to the fact that PD’s ‘critical discussion’ is not tuned to the generation of new positions or ideas but only to the testing of extant ones, thus echoing once again Popper, now in his focus on the justification rather than on the discovery of theories (see sections 4.2.4 and 5). </p><p>In any case, it is quite clear that the only practical result of the critical discussion à la PD of opposed positions on a public issue is to determine whether one discussant succeeded in refuting the other’s position, thus obtaining the adversary’s agreement, who will then share his/her position, at least for some time. In this respect, PD’s critical discussion is close to Habermas’s ‘reasonable argumentation’, whose aim is to reach consensus.15 In spite of the apparent difference between a critical examination of a position aiming at its refutation or at its acceptance, even van Eemeren admits, to some extent, their similarity. He points out that “the pragma-dialectical procedure deals only with ‘first order’ conditions for resolving differences of opinion on the merits by means of critical discussion” (van Eemeren 2010: 34), and stresses that there are ‘higher order’ conditions, ‘internal’ and ‘external’, that are “beyond the agent’s control”, conditions that are similar to Habermas’s “ideal speech conditions” (van Eemeren 2010: 35n). Anyhow, whether according to PD the main goal of the critical discussion process in the public alliance is to create the opportunity for refutation or for agreement (meaning that one of the discussants acknowledges that his position is wrong), the essential assumption of this process is that the participants in it in the public sphere (or elsewhere) must be aware that one of them holds a wrong position and will have to explicitly acknowledge this.</p><p>Is such a goal, especially when conceived as the ultimate aim of the proposed argumentative process, feasible and acceptable in the public sphere? </p><p>In our opinion, there are at least four reasons for arguing that it is a utopian, hence unacceptable goal, if one takes seriously what should be expected from argumentative practice and theory in the public sphere. First, because PD deserves a critique similar to the one leveled against the Popperian version of critical rationalism it espouses,16 which defends a theory of knowledge “without a knowing subject” (Popper 1972); obviously, such a-contextual position becomes even more problematic if applied to the public and political spheres, where it must operate in a context essentially involved with practical rationality. Second, due to its analogy with theories such as Habermas’s that were discussed in this section as well as in 2.2—an analogy that deserves additional criticism because, unlike Habermasianism, PD overlooks the relationship between the political and public context and argumentative practice. Third, because of PD’s total overlooking of the role of CSDs in public argumentation (cf. 4.2.2). And fourth, due to unilateral value judgments of positions in the public sphere, which lead to simplistic criteria of refutation or acceptance in a domain where complexity is the rule (cf. 2.1.1 and 4.2.3). </p><p>(ii) Let us admit, for the sake of argument, that the refutation goal as claimed by PD is central, feasible, acceptable, and useful in public argumentation. Aren’t there better ways to achieve this goal? </p><p>The refutation and defense moves stipulated by the PD critical discussion model include, on the one side, the antagonist’s critical remarks or demands and on the other, the proponent’s replies. We believe that it must be assumed that neither the critique nor the replies are previously known to the contenders, which is why they have an interest in engage in the argumentation process: presumably, the expression of both, counter-arguments and defensive-arguments, is good to both sides. In spite of its usefulness in certain situations, this kind of exchange does not amount to the full manifestation of the dialectical critical process, wherein the context and co-text of the dialectical exchange, as well as the cognitive interaction that takes place and evolves throughout the exchange, play a decisive role in the design and ‘inner’ justification of each of the participants’ moves. Argumentation strategies that take into account these resources and make full use of their potential are no doubt setting up another, broader span of goals for the argumentative process, and are more likely to achieve these goals more effectively than they certainly would achieve their PD more limited counterparts (cf. 4.2.4 and 5). </p><p>4.2.2 Preconditions </p><p>The ideal PD <u><strong>critical <mark>discussion</strong> can <strong>only</strong> be realized if</u></mark> some <u><strong><mark>preconditions</strong> are <strong>satisfied</strong></mark>. The most important</u> ones <u>are</u> a) <u>a <strong><mark>clear</mark>-cut</strong><mark> identification of the <strong>standpoint</strong> that provokes</mark> the <strong><mark>disagreement</u></strong></mark>, b) the decision of the parties to engage in a discussion, <u><mark>and</u></mark> c) the participants’ <u>commitment to</u> obey the <u><strong>procedural <mark>rules</u></strong></mark>. As we shall see, these preconditions share a common assumption, which calls into question the feasibility of using critical discussion in the public sphere.</p><p>(A) <u><mark>This <strong>precondition</strong> assumes</u></mark> that <u><mark>it is possible to <strong>isolate</mark> rigorously</strong><mark> the <strong>subject</mark> matter</u></strong> of a critical discussion, so as <u><mark>to conduct</u></mark> a <u><strong>focused <mark>discussion</u></strong></mark> that makes use only of relevant arguments. This precondition is quite strict, for whenever both discussants defend contrary standpoints, their disagreement should be treated as two separate fully fledged discussions: “… if another discussion begins, it must go through the same stages again—from confrontation stage to concluding stage” (van Eemeren 2010: 10n). </p><p>(B) This precondition subordinates the decision to engage in the discussion to the evaluation that the discussants share enough common ground to pursue it adequately: “After the parties have decided that there is enough common ground to conduct a discussion …” (van Eemeren 2010: 33). </p><p>(C) <u><mark>This <strong>precondition</strong></mark> stresses the ‘contractual’ character of a critical discussion, which <mark>requires</mark> <strong>explicit <mark>mutual commitments</strong> by</mark> the <mark>discussants</mark>.</u> Its rationale is that <u><mark>without</u></mark> such <u><strong><mark>commitments</strong> the aim of</u></mark> the <u><strong>critical <mark>discussion</u></strong></mark>, i.e., the resolution of the difference of opinions, <u><mark>will <strong>not be achieved</strong>, which makes engaging</u></mark> in the discussion <u><strong><mark>pointless</u></strong></mark>: “There is no point in venturing to resolve a difference … if there is no mutual commitment to a common starting point, which may include procedural commitments as well as substantive agreement” (van Eemeren and Grootendorst 2004: 60). </p><p>These <u><strong>‘first order’ <mark>preconditions</u></strong></mark>, as they are labeled in PD (cf. van Eemeren 2010: 33), <u><mark>are</u></mark> the <u><mark>conditions that candidates</mark> to participate</u> in a critical discussion <u><strong><mark>must fulfill</u></strong></mark> if they intend to do so and can afford it personally (a ‘second order’ condition) and politically (a ‘third order’ condition).17 In addition, the first order conditions demand from the prospective discussants a clear, distinct, and detailed picture of the scope of the discussion that they are about to engage in. This means not mixing up the various differences of opinion that the discussion may involve, and being able to separate them properly as the subject matter for independent discussions; <u><mark>a</u></mark> further <u><strong><mark>requirement</strong> is</u></mark> the <u><strong>anticipated <mark>identification</strong> of</u></mark> the pieces of the ‘substantive agreement’ forming <u><mark>the <strong>start</mark>ing point</strong> in order to ensure</u> that they are sufficient for conducting the discussion up to a <u><strong>satisfactory closure</u></strong>.</p>
1NC — Valley — Round 3
OFF
1NC — T-USFG — v1
13,494
382
25,778
./documents/hspolicy21/BlueValleyNorthwest/MoSc/Blue%20Valley%20Northwest-Mojica-Schiffman-Neg-2%20-%20Mid%20America%20Cup-Round3.docx
744,375
N
2 - Mid America Cup
3
Maine East BV
Jared Burke
1AC - Epistemicide 1NC - T - USFG CP - PTD 2NR - T
hspolicy21/BlueValleyNorthwest/MoSc/Blue%20Valley%20Northwest-Mojica-Schiffman-Neg-2%20-%20Mid%20America%20Cup-Round3.docx
null
63,396
MoSc
Blue Valley Northwest MoSc
null
Al.....
Mo.....
St.....
Sc.....
21,891
BlueValleyNorthwest
Blue Valley Northwest
KS
null
1,020
hspolicy21
HS Policy 2021-22
2,021
cx
hs
2
4,773,980
Studies affirm—enlargement boosts growth, reduces crime, and increases trust.
Hafner et al. 16
Hafner et al. 16 [Marco*; CEMFI Madrid, Certificate, Economics, Barcelona Graduate School of Economics, Certificate, Personnel Economics; & Jirka Taylor**, Martin Stepanek**, Stijn Hoorens**, Sarah Grand-Clement**, Martin Sacher**, Elma Dujso**, Matteo Barberi**; RAND; “The Cost of Non-Europe: Schengen,” https://www.rand.org/randeurope/research/projects/cost-of-non-europe-schengen.html] brett
The border-free Schengen Area guarantees free movement to more than 400 million EU citizens as well as many non-EU nationals, businessmen, tourists or other persons with legal access to EU territory the functioning of Schengen has been placed under considerable strain, with several member states reintroducing controls on parts of their internal borders evidence suggests that suspensions of Schengen are associated with, among other factors, economic costs related to barriers to trade and traffic delays at border crossing points Are there potential benefits of more concerted action at the EU level within the current Schengen governance framework or by external factors? Methodology To calculate the social and political costs of the reintroduction of border controls, the team used econometric modelling techniques to investigate the association between Schengen and different types of crime, including acquisitive and violent crime, as well as illicit drug trade including interpersonal trust and trust in national and transnational institutions. For both potential social and political costs the team examined both cross-country trends and changes within countries by comparing border and non-border regions. Findings Re-establishing border controls cost around €2–3 bn in annual operating costs also fixed one-off costs 19 bn depending on the timeframe for establishing border controls. The permanent establishment of border controls would result in a higher one-off cost Following Schengen enlargement in 2007 there has been a decrease in levels of crime within the Schengen Area, such as burglary, car theft, theft and robberies particularly strong association between the 2007 enlargement and the volume of seized drugs, such as cocaine and heroin, within the Schengen Area There has been an upward trend in European citizens’ trust in national and European institutions following the Schengen enlargement in 2007. Trust is seen as an important factor in making the Schengen Agreement work for countries in the
borders are associated with economic costs econometric modelling techniques examined cross-country trends border controls cost 3 bn also fixed one-off costs 19 bn Following enlargement there has been a decrease in crime upward trend in trust in European institutions
The border-free Schengen Area guarantees free movement to more than 400 million EU citizens, as well as many non-EU nationals, businessmen, tourists or other persons with legal access to EU territory. Amid recent unprecedented influx of migrants into the European Union, the functioning of Schengen has been placed under considerable strain, with several member states reintroducing controls on parts of their internal borders. Recent evidence suggests that suspensions of Schengen are associated with, among other factors, economic costs related to barriers to trade and traffic delays at border crossing points. Goals RAND Europe was commissioned by the European Parliament to investigate the economic, social and political costs of 'non-Schengen'— that is, reintroducing border controls. The researchers placed a special emphasis on aspects dealing with civil liberties and home affairs. Key questions included: What are the economic, social and political costs of the reintroduction of border controls regarding aspects of justice and home affairs? What are the budgetary costs of reallocating public sources towards border control? What are the empirical associations between Schengen, crime and security? What is the empirical association between Schengen and various modalities and levels of trust? Are there potential benefits of more concerted action at the EU level within the current Schengen governance framework or by external factors? Methodology To calculate the social and political costs of the reintroduction of border controls, the team used econometric modelling techniques to investigate the association between Schengen and different types of crime, including acquisitive and violent crime, as well as illicit drug trade. In addition, the team explored associations between Schengen and different measures of trust, including interpersonal trust and trust in national and transnational institutions. For both potential social and political costs the team examined both cross-country trends and changes within countries by comparing border and non-border regions. Findings Re-establishing border controls in Europe would cost around €2–3 bn in annual operating costs. There would also be fixed one-off costs of €0.1–19 bn, depending on the timeframe for establishing border controls. The permanent establishment of border controls would result in a higher one-off cost. Following the Schengen enlargement in 2007, there has been a decrease in levels of crime within the Schengen Area, such as burglary, car theft, theft and robberies. There was a particularly strong association between the 2007 enlargement and the volume of seized drugs, such as cocaine and heroin, within the Schengen Area. There has been an upward trend in European citizens’ trust in national and European institutions following the Schengen enlargement in 2007. Trust is seen as an important factor in making the Schengen Agreement work for countries in the area.
2,957
<h4><u>Studies</u> affirm—enlargement <u>boosts growth</u>, <u>reduces crime</u>, and <u>increases trust</u>.</h4><p><strong>Hafner et al. 16</strong> [Marco*; CEMFI Madrid, Certificate, Economics, Barcelona Graduate School of Economics, Certificate, Personnel Economics; & Jirka Taylor**, Martin Stepanek**, Stijn Hoorens**, Sarah Grand-Clement**, Martin Sacher**, Elma Dujso**, Matteo Barberi**; RAND; “The Cost of Non-Europe: Schengen,” https://www.rand.org/randeurope/research/projects/cost-of-non-europe-schengen.html] brett</p><p><u>The border-free Schengen Area guarantees free movement</u> <u>to more than <strong>400 million EU citizens</u></strong>, <u>as well as many non-EU nationals, businessmen, tourists or other persons with legal access to EU territory</u>. Amid recent unprecedented influx of migrants into the European Union, <u>the functioning of Schengen has been placed under considerable strain, with several member states reintroducing controls on parts of their <strong>internal <mark>borders</u></strong></mark>. Recent <u><strong>evidence</u></strong> <u>suggests that suspensions of Schengen <mark>are associated with</mark>, among other factors, <strong><mark>economic costs</strong></mark> related to <strong>barriers to trade</strong> and <strong>traffic delays</strong> at border crossing points</u>.</p><p>Goals</p><p>RAND Europe was commissioned by the European Parliament to investigate the economic, social and political costs of 'non-Schengen'— that is, reintroducing border controls. The researchers placed a special emphasis on aspects dealing with civil liberties and home affairs. Key questions included:</p><p>What are the economic, social and political costs of the reintroduction of border controls regarding aspects of justice and home affairs?</p><p>What are the budgetary costs of reallocating public sources towards border control?</p><p>What are the empirical associations between Schengen, crime and security?</p><p>What is the empirical association between Schengen and various modalities and levels of trust?</p><p><u><strong>Are there potential benefits of more concerted action at the EU level within the current Schengen governance framework or by external factors?</p><p>Methodology</p><p></strong>To calculate the social and political costs of the reintroduction of border controls, the team used <strong><mark>econometric modelling techniques</strong></mark> to investigate the association between <strong>Schengen</strong> and different types of crime, including acquisitive and violent crime, as well as illicit drug trade</u>. In addition, the team explored associations between Schengen and different measures of trust, <u><strong>including interpersonal trust and trust in national and transnational institutions. For both potential social and political costs the team <mark>examined</mark> both <mark>cross-country trends</mark> and changes within countries by comparing border and non-border regions.</p><p>Findings</p><p>Re-establishing <mark>border controls</u></strong></mark> in Europe would <u><mark>cost</mark> around €2–<strong><mark>3 bn</strong></mark> in <strong>annual operating costs</u></strong>. There would <u><mark>also</u></mark> be <u><mark>fixed one-off costs</u></mark> of €0.1–<u><strong><mark>19 bn</u></strong></mark>, <u>depending on the timeframe for establishing border controls. The permanent establishment of border controls would result in a higher one-off cost</u>.</p><p><u><mark>Following</u></mark> the <u><strong>Schengen <mark>enlargement</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>in 2007</u></strong>, <u><mark>there has been a decrease in</mark> levels of <strong><mark>crime</strong></mark> within the Schengen Area, such as burglary, car theft, theft and robberies</u>. There was a <u>particularly strong association between the 2007 enlargement and the volume of seized <strong>drugs</strong>, such as cocaine and heroin, within the Schengen Area</u>.</p><p><u>There has been an <strong><mark>upward trend</strong> in</mark> European citizens’ <mark>trust in</mark> national and <strong><mark>European institutions</strong></mark> following the Schengen enlargement in 2007. Trust is seen as an important factor in making the Schengen Agreement work for countries in the</u> area.</p>
null
null
1AC—Plan
1,705,355
172
167,301
./documents/hsld22/Sammamish/LyWa/Sammamish-LyWa-Aff-Harvard-Round-6.docx
980,904
A
Harvard
6
Midtown FB
Curtis Chang
1AC - Schengen 1NC - K biopower, case 1AR - all 2NR - all 2AR - all
hsld22/Sammamish/LyWa/Sammamish-LyWa-Aff-Harvard-Round-6.docx
2023-02-19 19:43:18
80,369
LyWa
Sammamish LyWa
*ghill update * the wiki won't let me disclose round 2 for some reason it crashes everytime i try so just dm me if you want docs for that round Feel free to contact me before round for disclosure or if you want me to meet any accommodation! Number - 4252409655 Email - [email protected] Messenger - Lydia Wang
Ly.....
Wa.....
null
null
26,999
Sammamish
Sammamish
WA
75,775
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
2,392,992
They destroy the possibility for politics, ethics, and the value of life.
Ruti ‘14
Ruti ‘14 (mari, English, Toronto, Psychoanalysis, Culture & Society (2014) 19, 297–314) SJBE, recut from Harvard BoSu
On the other hand, Lacan – again like Marcuse – recognizes that the symbolic order is repressive beyond the demands of subject formation, that it includes forms of violence that exceed the ubiquitous violence of the signifier. Indeed, even the violence of the signifier is not equally distributed, so that some of us are much more vulnerable to its injurious effects than others (consider, for instance, hate speech). Lacan And both acknowledge that the model citizen of this symbolic is a subject who shows up at work reliably every morning, performs its duties with a degree of diligence, does not let its desires get the better of its productivity, and seeks satisfaction (“enjoys”) in moderate, socially sanctioned ways. Lacan’s point is by no means, as critics such as Butler have suggested, that a different kind of symbolic is intrinsically impossible but rather that the configuration of subjectivity that Western modernity has produced – a subjectivity that has been subjected to a particular form of surplus-repression (the performance principle, the service of goods) – makes it virtually impossible for us to entertain the idea that the symbolic could be organized differently, that it could be centered around a different version of the reality principle individuals who were so out of touch with the truth of their desire that they were willing to sacrifice this desire for the sake of social conformity and that they were, furthermore, willing to do so to the point of self-betrayal Such a betrayal invariably results in the reassertion of the status quo, sending the subject back to the service of goods, what Lacan in this context calls “the common path” This society of the spectacle – of technology, image, and speed – shares many parallels with Adorno’s “culture industry”: a flattened surface of the life world, a constriction of psychic space, a death of critical thought, the worship of efficiency over intellectual curiosity, and the incapacity to revolt But as I have already suggested, the lifting of surplus-repression renders the imprint of primary repression more clearly discernable, for when surplus-repression is removed, what remains are the always highly singular outlines of primary repression. And if Lacan – like Marcuse – sought to remove surplus-repression, it was because he understood that it was on the level of primary repression (fundamental fantasies) that one could find the most basic building blocks of the subject’s psychic destiny; primary repression was the layer of psychic life that expressed something essential about the distinctive ways in which the pleasure principle, in the subject’s life, had become bound up with the repetition compulsion
the symbolic order is repressive beyond subject formation it includes violence that exceed the signifier the configuration of subjectivity makes it impossible for us to entertain the idea that the symbolic could be organized differently individuals sacrifice desire for social conformity to the point of self-betrayal results in the reassertion of the status quo This society a flattened surface of the life world, a constriction of psychic space
On the other hand, Lacan – again like Marcuse – recognizes that the symbolic order is repressive beyond the demands of subject formation, that it includes forms of violence that exceed the ubiquitous violence of the signifier. Indeed, even the violence of the signifier is not equally distributed, so that some of us are much more vulnerable to its injurious effects than others (consider, for instance, hate speech). Lacan does not necessarily talk about the unequal distribution of resources in the manner Marcuse does, but there is no doubt that his analysis of symbolic law as the Law of the Father elucidates a historically specific, deeply heteropatriarchal and hierarchical organization of social life. In point of fact, one reason I have taken a detour through Marcuse is to illustrate the obvious ways in which Lacan’s portraiture of the symbolic mirrors that of Marcuse’s explicitly historical account: what Marcuse calls “the performance principle,” Lacan calls the “service of goods.” Both thinkers identify the underpinnings of a social order dominated by the ideal of productivity – an ideal that is, moreover, placed in direct opposition to the pleasure principle. Both emphasize that the dominant morality of this symbolic – what Lacan calls “the morality of the master” – measures the merit of lives based on largely pragmatic criteria. And both acknowledge that the model citizen of this symbolic is a subject who shows up at work reliably every morning, performs its duties with a degree of diligence, does not let its desires get the better of its productivity, and seeks satisfaction (“enjoys”) in moderate, socially sanctioned ways. “Part of the world has resolutely turned in the directions of the service of goods,” Lacan writes, “thereby rejecting everything that has to do with the relationship of man to desire” (318). This, he adds, “is what is known as the postrevolutionary perspective” (318). In other words, the service of goods reflects the mindset of the levelheaded utilitarian subject who has deemed revolutionary change to be unrealistic. Lacan is here referring to the kind of depoliticization that is arguably the hallmark of Western subjectivity under capitalism. Lacan’s point is by no means, as critics such as Butler have suggested, that a different kind of symbolic is intrinsically impossible but rather that the configuration of subjectivity that Western modernity has produced – a subjectivity that has been subjected to a particular form of surplus-repression (the performance principle, the service of goods) – makes it virtually impossible for us to entertain the idea that the symbolic could be organized differently, that it could be centered around a different version of the reality principle. As Marcuse remarks, one reason the performance principle is so powerful is that it has managed to convince us that all alternatives to it are either utopian or otherwise unpalatable. Yet, for Marcuse, the fact that this principle has been so successful also points to the possibility of transcending it. As he states, “The very progress of civilization under the performance principle has attained a level of productivity at which the social demands upon instinctual energy to be spent in alienated labor could be considerably reduced. Consequently, the continued repressive organization of the instincts seems to be necessitated less by the ‘struggle for existence’ than by the interest in prolonging this struggle – by the interest in domination” (pp. 129–130). This is to say that there is really nothing besides social power that keeps us invested in the notion that our welfare demands relentless toil. The performance principle has outlived its usefulness in the sense that our collective productivity these days surpasses what is necessary for the provision of food, clothing, housing, and other basic amenities. The fact that these amenities have not yet reached all corners of the world, or even all corners of our own society (the homeless, innercity dwellers, etc.), is a function of domination (the unequal distribution of resources) rather than of any deficiencies of productivity. As a result, in Marcuse’s view, all we would need to do to bring about a more “non-repressive civilization” (p. 134) would be to refuse the parameters of the current symbolic; even something as simple as reducing the length of the working day would immediately realign our priorities, perhaps even impacting the very organization of our psychic lives. Our standard of living might drop somewhat, but we might also learn to assess the value of our lives according to other, less performance-oriented, measurements. Psychoanalysis, particularly Lacanian analysis, does not have a normative goal; it does not seek to tell us how we should desire but merely to explore the idiosyncratic contours of our desire. But this does not change the fact that Lacan, at least as a theorist, was exasperated by people’s inability to make their way out of the maze of the master’s morality, including its performance principle; he was frustrated by individuals who were so out of touch with the truth of their desire that they were willing to sacrifice this desire for the sake of social conformity and that they were, furthermore, willing to do so to the point of self-betrayal. As he explains, “What I call ‘giving ground relative to one’s desire’ is always accompanied in the destiny of the subject by some betrayal – you will observe it in every case and should note its importance. Either the subject betrays his own way, betrays himself, and the result is significant for him, or, more simply, he tolerates the fact that someone with whom he has more or less vowed to do something betrays his hope and doesn’t do for him what their pact entailed” (p. 321). Such a betrayal invariably results in the reassertion of the status quo, sending the subject back to the service of goods, what Lacan in this context calls “the common path” (p. 321). And given that desire, for Lacan, is “the metonymy of our being” (p. 321), betraying it in this way leads to the kind of psychic death that extinguishes the subject’s sense of agency. To use Lacan’s wording, “Doing things in the name of the good, and even more in the name of the good of the other, is something that is far from protecting us not only from guilt but also from all kinds of inner catastrophes” (p. 319). It is precisely such inner catastrophes that Lacanian clinical practice was designed to counter, though it may be Julia Kristeva – rather than Lacan himself – who has most clearly developed this interpretation of analytic work. Kristeva depicts psychoanalysis as a means of restoring the subject’s psychic aliveness, as an explicit revolt against the numbing impact of what she calls “the society of the spectacle” (2002, p. 4). This society of the spectacle – of technology, image, and speed – shares many parallels with Adorno’s “culture industry”: a flattened surface of the life world, a constriction of psychic space, a death of critical thought, the worship of efficiency over intellectual curiosity, and the incapacity to revolt. Against this backdrop, psychoanalysis – along with art, writing, and some forms of religious experience – offers, for Kristeva, a gateway to revolt, a way of resurrecting “the life of the mind” (a phrase Kristeva borrows from Hannah Arendt) through ongoing questioning, interrogation, and psychic recreation. “Freud founded psychoanalysis as an invitation to anamnesis in the goal of a rebirth, that is, a psychical restructuring,” Kristeva writes: “Through a narrative of free association and in the regenerative revolt against the old law (familial taboos, superego, ideals, oedipal or narcissistic limits, etc.) comes the singular autonomy of each, as well as a renewed link with the other” (2002, p. 8). In the context of my overall argument in this essay, it is worth stressing that it is “the desire of the subject” that, in Kristeva’s view, reserves a place “for initiative, autonomy” (2002, p. 11). This is in part because the “Freudian journey into the night of desire was followed by attention to the capacity to think: never one without the other” (2010, p. 41). In other words, the exploration of desire, in psychoanalysis, is akin to the critical (or at least curious) movement of thought – the very movement that Arendt also saw as vital to the life of the mind. This is why psychoanalysis has, Kristeva asserts, “the (unique?) privilege today of accompanying the emergence of new capacities of thinking/representing/thinking, beyond the frequent and increasingly noticeable disasters of psychosomatic space – capacities that are so many new bodies and new lives” (2010, pp. 41–42). Kristeva therefore draws the same link between desire and autonomy (in this instance, the capacity for critical thought) as Lacan does. Furthermore, to translate Kristeva’s point into Marcuse’s terminology, one might say that psychoanalysis, at least the kind of analysis that refuses to uphold social adaptation as a therapeutic goal, presents the possibility of sidestepping, or at the very least diminishing, the effects of surplus-repression. This, in turn, creates space for the truth of the subject’s desire in the Lacanian sense. This does not mean that repression as such is defeated. Quite the contrary, as we will see shortly, the truth of the subject’s desire is inextricable from the primary (constitutive) repression that accompanies subject formation. But as I have already suggested, the lifting of surplus-repression renders the imprint of primary repression more clearly discernable, for when surplus-repression is removed, what remains are the always highly singular outlines of primary repression. And if Lacan – like Marcuse – sought to remove surplus-repression, it was because he understood that it was on the level of primary repression (fundamental fantasies) that one could find the most basic building blocks of the subject’s psychic destiny; primary repression was the layer of psychic life that expressed something essential about the distinctive ways in which the pleasure principle, in the subject’s life, had become bound up with the repetition compulsion. This is why Lacan states, “If analysis has a meaning, desire is nothing other than that which supports an unconscious theme, the very articulation of that which roots us in a particular destiny, and that destiny demands insistently that the debt be paid, and desire keeps coming back, keeps returning, and situates us once again in a given track, the track of something that is specifically our business” (p. 319).According to Lacan, analysis aims to enable us to understand something about the eccentric specificity (or truth) of our most fundamental desire as well as about the track of destiny that this desire carves out for us (and that is therefore “specifically our business”). If it is indeed the case, as I have conceded, that most of us tend to be alienated from our desire, Lacanian analysis strives to undo this alienation by familiarizing us with the truth of this desire. This process entails, among other things, recognizing that the destiny we owe to this desire can never be definitively overcome, that the debt of desire can never be fully redeemed (for how are we to compensate the signifier for having brought us into being as subjects of desire?). Our destiny – which might initially coincide quite seamlessly with our repetition compulsion – consists of recurring efforts to pay off this debt, which is why it keeps ushering us to the same track of desire, the same nexus of psychic conundrums, our unconscious hope being that if we wear out the track of our desire by incessant reiteration, one day we might be able to absolve ourselves of our debt. But since we cannot, the only thing to be done is to “own” our destiny even as we might seek to mitigate its more painful dimensions. That is, the only way to arrive at the kind of psychic rebirth Kristeva is talking about is to take full responsibility for our (unconsciously generated) destiny. In the ethical act, our impulse is to embrace this destiny wholesale regardless of consequences (this is one way to understand what it means to plunge into the jouissance of the real). In analysis, the exploration of our destiny is more gradual, more self-reflexive. But in both cases, the point is not to obliterate our foundational destiny (or fundamental fantasies) but merely to elaborate it in more satisfying directions, away from the incapacitating effects of the repetition compulsion and toward the rewards of subjective autonomy. And, if we are to achieve this goal, nothing is more important than staying faithful to the truth of desire that, on the most elementary level, determines our destiny.
12,793
<h4>They destroy the possibility for politics, ethics, and the value of life.</h4><p><strong>Ruti ‘14</strong> (mari, English, Toronto, Psychoanalysis, Culture & Society (2014) 19, 297–314) SJBE, recut from Harvard BoSu</p><p><u><strong>On the other hand, Lacan – again like Marcuse – recognizes that <mark>the symbolic order is repressive</mark> <mark>beyond</mark> the demands of <mark>subject formation</mark>, that <mark>it includes</mark> forms of <mark>violence that exceed</mark> <mark>the</mark> ubiquitous violence of the <mark>signifier</mark>. Indeed, even the violence of the signifier is not equally distributed, so that some of us are much more vulnerable to its injurious effects than others (consider, for instance, hate speech). Lacan</u></strong> does not necessarily talk about the unequal distribution of resources in the manner Marcuse does, but there is no doubt that his analysis of symbolic law as the Law of the Father elucidates a historically specific, deeply heteropatriarchal and hierarchical organization of social life. In point of fact, one reason I have taken a detour through Marcuse is to illustrate the obvious ways in which Lacan’s portraiture of the symbolic mirrors that of Marcuse’s explicitly historical account: what Marcuse calls “the performance principle,” Lacan calls the “service of goods.” Both thinkers identify the underpinnings of a social order dominated by the ideal of productivity – an ideal that is, moreover, placed in direct opposition to the pleasure principle. Both emphasize that the dominant morality of this symbolic – what Lacan calls “the morality of the master” – measures the merit of lives based on largely pragmatic criteria. <u><strong>And both acknowledge that the model citizen of this symbolic is a subject who shows up at work reliably every morning, performs its duties with a degree of diligence, does not let its desires get the better of its productivity, and seeks satisfaction (“enjoys”) in moderate, socially sanctioned ways. </u></strong>“Part of the world has resolutely turned in the directions of the service of goods,” Lacan writes, “thereby rejecting everything that has to do with the relationship of man to desire” (318). This, he adds, “is what is known as the postrevolutionary perspective” (318). In other words, the service of goods reflects the mindset of the levelheaded utilitarian subject who has deemed revolutionary change to be unrealistic. Lacan is here referring to the kind of depoliticization that is arguably the hallmark of Western subjectivity under capitalism. <u><strong>Lacan’s point is by no means, as critics such as Butler have suggested, that a different kind of symbolic is intrinsically impossible but rather that <mark>the configuration of subjectivity</mark> that Western modernity has produced – a subjectivity that has been subjected to a particular form of surplus-repression (the performance principle, the service of goods) – <mark>makes it </mark>virtually <mark>impossible for us to entertain the idea</mark> <mark>that the symbolic could be organized differently</mark>, that it could be centered around a different version of the reality principle</u></strong>. As Marcuse remarks, one reason the performance principle is so powerful is that it has managed to convince us that all alternatives to it are either utopian or otherwise unpalatable. Yet, for Marcuse, the fact that this principle has been so successful also points to the possibility of transcending it. As he states, “The very progress of civilization under the performance principle has attained a level of productivity at which the social demands upon instinctual energy to be spent in alienated labor could be considerably reduced. Consequently, the continued repressive organization of the instincts seems to be necessitated less by the ‘struggle for existence’ than by the interest in prolonging this struggle – by the interest in domination” (pp. 129–130). This is to say that there is really nothing besides social power that keeps us invested in the notion that our welfare demands relentless toil. The performance principle has outlived its usefulness in the sense that our collective productivity these days surpasses what is necessary for the provision of food, clothing, housing, and other basic amenities. The fact that these amenities have not yet reached all corners of the world, or even all corners of our own society (the homeless, innercity dwellers, etc.), is a function of domination (the unequal distribution of resources) rather than of any deficiencies of productivity. As a result, in Marcuse’s view, all we would need to do to bring about a more “non-repressive civilization” (p. 134) would be to refuse the parameters of the current symbolic; even something as simple as reducing the length of the working day would immediately realign our priorities, perhaps even impacting the very organization of our psychic lives. Our standard of living might drop somewhat, but we might also learn to assess the value of our lives according to other, less performance-oriented, measurements. Psychoanalysis, particularly Lacanian analysis, does not have a normative goal; it does not seek to tell us how we should desire but merely to explore the idiosyncratic contours of our desire. But this does not change the fact that Lacan, at least as a theorist, was exasperated by people’s inability to make their way out of the maze of the master’s morality, including its performance principle; he was frustrated by <u><strong><mark>individuals</mark> who were so out of touch with the truth of their desire that they were willing to <mark>sacrifice</mark> this <mark>desire</mark> <mark>for</mark> the sake of <mark>social conformity</mark> and that they were, furthermore, willing to do so <mark>to the point of self-betrayal</u></strong></mark>. As he explains, “What I call ‘giving ground relative to one’s desire’ is always accompanied in the destiny of the subject by some betrayal – you will observe it in every case and should note its importance. Either the subject betrays his own way, betrays himself, and the result is significant for him, or, more simply, he tolerates the fact that someone with whom he has more or less vowed to do something betrays his hope and doesn’t do for him what their pact entailed” (p. 321). <u><strong>Such a betrayal invariably <mark>results in the reassertion of the status quo</mark>, sending the subject back to the service of goods, what Lacan in this context calls “the common path”</u></strong> (p. 321). And given that desire, for Lacan, is “the metonymy of our being” (p. 321), betraying it in this way leads to the kind of psychic death that extinguishes the subject’s sense of agency. To use Lacan’s wording, “Doing things in the name of the good, and even more in the name of the good of the other, is something that is far from protecting us not only from guilt but also from all kinds of inner catastrophes” (p. 319). It is precisely such inner catastrophes that Lacanian clinical practice was designed to counter, though it may be Julia Kristeva – rather than Lacan himself – who has most clearly developed this interpretation of analytic work. Kristeva depicts psychoanalysis as a means of restoring the subject’s psychic aliveness, as an explicit revolt against the numbing impact of what she calls “the society of the spectacle” (2002, p. 4). <u><strong><mark>This society</mark> of the spectacle – of technology, image, and speed – shares many parallels with Adorno’s “culture industry”: <mark>a flattened surface of the life world, a constriction of psychic space</mark>, a death of critical thought, the worship of efficiency over intellectual curiosity, and the incapacity to revolt</u></strong>. Against this backdrop, psychoanalysis – along with art, writing, and some forms of religious experience – offers, for Kristeva, a gateway to revolt, a way of resurrecting “the life of the mind” (a phrase Kristeva borrows from Hannah Arendt) through ongoing questioning, interrogation, and psychic recreation. “Freud founded psychoanalysis as an invitation to anamnesis in the goal of a rebirth, that is, a psychical restructuring,” Kristeva writes: “Through a narrative of free association and in the regenerative revolt against the old law (familial taboos, superego, ideals, oedipal or narcissistic limits, etc.) comes the singular autonomy of each, as well as a renewed link with the other” (2002, p. 8). In the context of my overall argument in this essay, it is worth stressing that it is “the desire of the subject” that, in Kristeva’s view, reserves a place “for initiative, autonomy” (2002, p. 11). This is in part because the “Freudian journey into the night of desire was followed by attention to the capacity to think: never one without the other” (2010, p. 41). In other words, the exploration of desire, in psychoanalysis, is akin to the critical (or at least curious) movement of thought – the very movement that Arendt also saw as vital to the life of the mind. This is why psychoanalysis has, Kristeva asserts, “the (unique?) privilege today of accompanying the emergence of new capacities of thinking/representing/thinking, beyond the frequent and increasingly noticeable disasters of psychosomatic space – capacities that are so many new bodies and new lives” (2010, pp. 41–42). Kristeva therefore draws the same link between desire and autonomy (in this instance, the capacity for critical thought) as Lacan does. Furthermore, to translate Kristeva’s point into Marcuse’s terminology, one might say that psychoanalysis, at least the kind of analysis that refuses to uphold social adaptation as a therapeutic goal, presents the possibility of sidestepping, or at the very least diminishing, the effects of surplus-repression. This, in turn, creates space for the truth of the subject’s desire in the Lacanian sense. This does not mean that repression as such is defeated. Quite the contrary, as we will see shortly, the truth of the subject’s desire is inextricable from the primary (constitutive) repression that accompanies subject formation. <u><strong>But as I have already suggested, the lifting of surplus-repression renders the imprint of primary repression more clearly discernable, for when surplus-repression is removed, what remains are the always highly singular outlines of primary repression. And if Lacan – like Marcuse – sought to remove surplus-repression, it was because he understood that it was on the level of primary repression (fundamental fantasies) that one could find the most basic building blocks of the subject’s psychic destiny; primary repression was the layer of psychic life that expressed something essential about the distinctive ways in which the pleasure principle, in the subject’s life, had become bound up with the repetition compulsion</u></strong>. This is why Lacan states, “If analysis has a meaning, desire is nothing other than that which supports an unconscious theme, the very articulation of that which roots us in a particular destiny, and that destiny demands insistently that the debt be paid, and desire keeps coming back, keeps returning, and situates us once again in a given track, the track of something that is specifically our business” (p. 319).According to Lacan, analysis aims to enable us to understand something about the eccentric specificity (or truth) of our most fundamental desire as well as about the track of destiny that this desire carves out for us (and that is therefore “specifically our business”). If it is indeed the case, as I have conceded, that most of us tend to be alienated from our desire, Lacanian analysis strives to undo this alienation by familiarizing us with the truth of this desire. This process entails, among other things, recognizing that the destiny we owe to this desire can never be definitively overcome, that the debt of desire can never be fully redeemed (for how are we to compensate the signifier for having brought us into being as subjects of desire?). Our destiny – which might initially coincide quite seamlessly with our repetition compulsion – consists of recurring efforts to pay off this debt, which is why it keeps ushering us to the same track of desire, the same nexus of psychic conundrums, our unconscious hope being that if we wear out the track of our desire by incessant reiteration, one day we might be able to absolve ourselves of our debt. But since we cannot, the only thing to be done is to “own” our destiny even as we might seek to mitigate its more painful dimensions. That is, the only way to arrive at the kind of psychic rebirth Kristeva is talking about is to take full responsibility for our (unconsciously generated) destiny. In the ethical act, our impulse is to embrace this destiny wholesale regardless of consequences (this is one way to understand what it means to plunge into the jouissance of the real). In analysis, the exploration of our destiny is more gradual, more self-reflexive. <strong>But in both cases, the point is not to obliterate our foundational destiny (or fundamental fantasies) but merely to elaborate it in more satisfying directions, away from the incapacitating effects of the repetition compulsion and toward the rewards of subjective autonomy. And, if we are to achieve this goal, nothing is more important than staying faithful to the truth of desire that, on the most elementary level, determines our destiny.</p></strong>
null
1
null
41,714
181
76,559
./documents/hsld20/StrakeJesuit/Ma/Strake%20Jesuit-Mankidy-Neg-Jack%20Howe-Doubles.docx
875,326
N
Jack Howe
Doubles
Loyola SN
Joseph Barquin, Taman Kanchanapalli, Nikhita Vasan
1AC - US Populism 1NC - Psychoanalysis v2 - T "a" v2 - Case 1AR - Same 2NR - K 2AR - Same
hsld20/StrakeJesuit/Ma/Strake%20Jesuit-Mankidy-Neg-Jack%20Howe-Doubles.docx
null
73,808
VrMa
Strake Jesuit VrMa
null
Vr.....
Ma.....
null
null
24,736
StrakeJesuit
Strake Jesuit
TX
null
1,028
hsld20
HS LD 2020-21
2,020
ld
hs
1
2,074,197
Industrial civilization wouldn’t recover.
Dartnell 15
Lewis Dartnell 15. UK Space Agency research fellow at the University of Leicester, working in astrobiology and the search for microbial life on Mars. His latest book is The Knowledge: How to Rebuild Our World from Scratch. 04-13-15. "Could we reboot a modern civilisation without fossil fuels? – Lewis Dartnell." Aeon. https://aeon.co/essays/could-we-reboot-a-modern-civilisation-without-fossil-fuels
Imagine that the world as we know it ends tomorrow. There’s a global catastrophe perhaps a nuclear holocaust The vast majority of the human race perishes. Our civilisation collapses. The post-apocalyptic survivors find themselves in a devastated world of decaying, deserted cities Bad as things sound, that’s not the end for humanity We bounce back peace and order emerge again, just as they have time and again through history. Stable communities take shape They begin rebuilding But here’s the question: how far could such a society rebuild? Is there any chance that a post-apocalyptic society could reboot a technological civilisation? we have already consumed the most easily drainable crude oil and most readily mined deposits of coal Fossil fuels are central to the organisation of modern industrial society, just as they were central to its development Those are distinct roles even if we could somehow do without fossil fuels now (which we can’t, quite), it’s a different question whether we could have got to where we are without ever having had them. It’s easy to underestimate our current dependence on fossil fuels You can’t smelt metal, make glass, roast the ingredients of concrete, or synthesise artificial fertiliser without a lot of heat. It is fossil fuels – coal, gas and oil – that provide most of this thermal energy. n fact, the problem is even worse than that. Many of the chemicals required in bulk to run the modern world, from pesticides to plastics, derive from the diverse organic compounds in crude oil Is the emergence of a technologically advanced civilisation necessarily contingent on the easy availability of ancient energy? Why couldn’t our civilisation 2.0 just start with renewables? Well, it could, in a very limited way. If you find yourself among the survivors in a post-apocalyptic world, you could scavenge working solar panels Then what? New ones would be fiendishly difficult Solar panels are extremely complex These techniques took a long time to develop, and would presumably take a long time to recover. So photovoltaic solar power would not be within the capability of a society early in the industrialisation process. In a world without fossil fuels, one might envisage an electrified civilisation that largely bypasses combustion I say ‘largely’. We couldn’t get round it all together. When it comes to generating the white heat demanded by modern industry, there are few good options but to burn stuff Could our rebooting society run on wood Maybe so, if the population was fairly small But here’s the catch. These options all presuppose that our survivors are able to construct efficient steam turbines, CHP stations and internal
Is there any chance a post-apocalyptic society could reboot a technological civilisation? we have already consumed the most easily drainable crude oil Fossil fuels are central to organisation of modern society You can’t smelt metal, make glass, roast the ingredients of concrete, or synthesise artificial fertiliser without fossil fuels that provide thermal energy In a world without fossil fuels, one might envisage an electrified civilisation that largely bypasses combustion options presuppose that our survivors are able to
Imagine that the world as we know it ends tomorrow. There’s a global catastrophe: a pandemic virus, an asteroid strike, or perhaps a nuclear holocaust. The vast majority of the human race perishes. Our civilisation collapses. The post-apocalyptic survivors find themselves in a devastated world of decaying, deserted cities and roving gangs of bandits looting and taking by force. Bad as things sound, that’s not the end for humanity. We bounce back. Sooner or later, peace and order emerge again, just as they have time and again through history. Stable communities take shape. They begin the agonising process of rebuilding their technological base from scratch. But here’s the question: how far could such a society rebuild? Is there any chance, for instance, that a post-apocalyptic society could reboot a technological civilisation? Let’s make the basis of this thought experiment a little more specific. Today, we have already consumed the most easily drainable crude oil and, particularly in Britain, much of the shallowest, most readily mined deposits of coal. Fossil fuels are central to the organisation of modern industrial society, just as they were central to its development. Those, by the way, are distinct roles: even if we could somehow do without fossil fuels now (which we can’t, quite), it’s a different question whether we could have got to where we are without ever having had them. So, would a society starting over on a planet stripped of its fossil fuel deposits have the chance to progress through its own Industrial Revolution? Or to phrase it another way, what might have happened if, for whatever reason, the Earth had never acquired its extensive underground deposits of coal and oil in the first place? Would our progress necessarily have halted in the 18th century, in a pre-industrial state? It’s easy to underestimate our current dependence on fossil fuels. In everyday life, their most visible use is the petrol or diesel pumped into the vehicles that fill our roads, and the coal and natural gas which fire the power stations that electrify our modern lives. But we also rely on a range of different industrial materials, and in most cases, high temperatures are required to transform the stuff we dig out of the ground or harvest from the landscape into something useful. You can’t smelt metal, make glass, roast the ingredients of concrete, or synthesise artificial fertiliser without a lot of heat. It is fossil fuels – coal, gas and oil – that provide most of this thermal energy. In fact, the problem is even worse than that. Many of the chemicals required in bulk to run the modern world, from pesticides to plastics, derive from the diverse organic compounds in crude oil. Given the dwindling reserves of crude oil left in the world, it could be argued that the most wasteful use for this limited resource is to simply burn it. We should be carefully preserving what’s left for the vital repertoire of valuable organic compounds it offers. But my topic here is not what we should do now. Presumably everybody knows that we must transition to a low-carbon economy one way or another. No, I want to answer a question whose interest is (let’s hope) more theoretical. Is the emergence of a technologically advanced civilisation necessarily contingent on the easy availability of ancient energy? Is it possible to build an industrialised civilisation without fossil fuels? And the answer to that question is: maybe – but it would be extremely difficult. Let’s see how. We’ll start with a natural thought. Many of our alternative energy technologies are already highly developed. Solar panels, for example, represent a good option today, and are appearing more and more on the roofs of houses and businesses. It’s tempting to think that a rebooted society could simply pick up where we leave off. Why couldn’t our civilisation 2.0 just start with renewables? Well, it could, in a very limited way. If you find yourself among the survivors in a post-apocalyptic world, you could scavenge enough working solar panels to keep your lifestyle electrified for a good long while. Without moving parts, photovoltaic cells require little maintenance and are remarkably resilient. They do deteriorate over time, though, from moisture penetrating the casing and from sunlight itself degrading the high-purity silicon layers. The electricity generated by a solar panel declines by about 1 per cent every year so, after a few generations, all our hand-me-down solar panels will have degraded to the point of uselessness. Then what? New ones would be fiendishly difficult to create from scratch. Solar panels are made from thin slices of extremely pure silicon, and although the raw material is common sand, it must be processed and refined using complex and precise techniques – the same technological capabilities, more or less, that we need for modern semiconductor electronics components. These techniques took a long time to develop, and would presumably take a long time to recover. So photovoltaic solar power would not be within the capability of a society early in the industrialisation process. Perhaps, though, we were on the right track by starting with electrical power. Most of our renewable-energy technologies produce electricity. In our own historical development, it so happens that the core phenomena of electricity were discovered in the first half of the 1800s, well after the early development of steam engines. Heavy industry was already committed to combustion-based machinery, and electricity has largely assumed a subsidiary role in the organisation of our economies ever since. But could that sequence have run the other way? Is there some developmental requirement that thermal energy must come first? On the face of it, it’s not beyond the bounds of possibility that a progressing society could construct electrical generators and couple them to simple windmills and waterwheels, later progressing to wind turbines and hydroelectric dams. In a world without fossil fuels, one might envisage an electrified civilisation that largely bypasses combustion engines, building its transport infrastructure around electric trains and trams for long-distance and urban transport. I say ‘largely’. We couldn’t get round it all together. When it comes to generating the white heat demanded by modern industry, there are few good options but to burn stuff While the electric motor could perhaps replace the coal-burning steam engine for mechanical applications, society, as we’ve already seen, also relies upon thermal energy to drive the essential chemical and physical transformations it needs. How could an industrialising society produce crucial building materials such as iron and steel, brick, mortar, cement and glass without resorting to deposits of coal? You can of course create heat from electricity. We already use electric ovens and kilns. Modern arc furnaces are used for producing cast iron or recycling steel. The problem isn’t so much that electricity can’t be used to heat things, but that for meaningful industrial activity you’ve got to generate prodigious amounts of it, which is challenging using only renewable energy sources such as wind and water. An alternative is to generate high temperatures using solar power directly. Rather than relying on photovoltaic panels, concentrated solar thermal farms use giant mirrors to focus the sun’s rays onto a small spot. The heat concentrated in this way can be exploited to drive certain chemical or industrial processes, or else to raise steam and drive a generator. Even so, it is difficult (for example) to produce the very high temperatures inside an iron-smelting blast furnace using such a system. What’s more, it goes without saying that the effectiveness of concentrated solar power depends strongly on the local climate. No, when it comes to generating the white heat demanded by modern industry, there are few good options but to burn stuff. But that doesn’t mean the stuff we burn necessarily has to be fossil fuels. Let’s take a quick detour into the pre-history of modern industry. Long before the adoption of coal, charcoal was widely used for smelting metals. In many respects it is superior: charcoal burns hotter than coal and contains far fewer impurities. In fact, coal’s impurities were a major delaying factor on the Industrial Revolution. Released during combustion, they can taint the product being heated. During smelting, sulphur contaminants can soak into the molten iron, making the metal brittle and unsafe to use. It took a long time to work out how to treat coal to make it useful for many industrial applications. And, in the meantime, charcoal worked perfectly well. And then, well, we stopped using it. In retrospect, that’s a pity. When it comes from a sustainable source, charcoal burning is essentially carbon-neutral, because it doesn’t release any new carbon into the atmosphere – not that this would have been a consideration for the early industrialists. But charcoal-based industry didn’t die out altogether. In fact, it survived to flourish in Brazil. Because it has substantial iron deposits but few coalmines, Brazil is the largest charcoal producer in the world and the ninth biggest steel producer. We aren’t talking about a cottage industry here, and this makes Brazil a very encouraging example for our thought experiment. The trees used in Brazil’s charcoal industry are mainly fast-growing eucalyptus, cultivated specifically for the purpose. The traditional method for creating charcoal is to pile chopped staves of air-dried timber into a great dome-shaped mound and then cover it with turf or soil to restrict airflow as the wood smoulders. The Brazilian enterprise has scaled up this traditional craft to an industrial operation. Dried timber is stacked into squat, cylindrical kilns, built of brick or masonry and arranged in long lines so that they can be easily filled and unloaded in sequence. The largest sites can sport hundreds of such kilns. Once filled, their entrances are sealed and a fire is lit from the top. The skill in charcoal production is to allow just enough air into the interior of the kiln. There must be enough combustion heat to drive out moisture and volatiles and to pyrolyse the wood, but not so much that you are left with nothing but a pile of ashes. The kiln attendant monitors the state of the burn by carefully watching the smoke seeping out of the top, opening air holes or sealing with clay as necessary to regulate the process. Brazil shows how the raw materials of modern civilisation can be supplied without reliance on fossil fuels Good things come to those who wait, and this wood pyrolysis process can take up to a week of carefully controlled smouldering. The same basic method has been used for millennia. However, the ends to which the fuel is put are distinctly modern. Brazilian charcoal is trucked out of the forests to the country’s blast furnaces where it is used to transform ore into pig iron. This pig iron is the basic ingredient of modern mass-produced steel. The Brazilian product is exported to countries such as China and the US where it becomes cars and trucks, sinks, bathtubs, and kitchen appliances. Around two-thirds of Brazilian charcoal comes from sustainable plantations, and so this modern-day practice has been dubbed ‘green steel’. Sadly, the final third is supplied by the non-sustainable felling of primary forest. Even so, the Brazilian case does provide an example of how the raw materials of modern civilisation can be supplied without reliance on fossil fuels. Another, related option might be wood gasification. The use of wood to provide heat is as old as mankind, and yet simply burning timber only uses about a third of its energy. The rest is lost when gases and vapours released by the burning process blow away in the wind. Under the right conditions, even smoke is combustible. We don’t want to waste it. Better than simple burning, then, is to drive the thermal breakdown of the wood and collect the gases. You can see the basic principle at work for yourself just by lighting a match. The luminous flame isn’t actually touching the matchwood: it dances above, with a clear gap in between. The flame actually feeds on the hot gases given off as the wood breaks down in the heat, and the gases combust only once they mix with oxygen from the air. Matches are fascinating when you look at them closely. Wartime gasifier cars could achieve about 1.5 miles per kilogram. Today’s designs improve upon this To release these gases in a controlled way, bake some timber in a closed container. Oxygen is restricted so that the wood doesn’t simply catch fire. Its complex molecules decompose through a process known as pyrolysis, and then the hot carbonised lumps of charcoal at the bottom of the container react with the breakdown products to produce flammable gases such as hydrogen and carbon monoxide. The resultant ‘producer gas’ is a versatile fuel: it can be stored or piped for use in heating or street lights, and is also suitable for use in complex machinery such as the internal combustion engine. More than a million gasifier-powered cars across the world kept civilian transport running during the oil shortages of the Second World War. In occupied Denmark, 95 per cent of all tractors, trucks and fishing boats were powered by wood-gas generators. The energy content of about 3 kg of wood (depending on its dryness and density) is equivalent to a litre of petrol, and the fuel consumption of a gasifier-powered car is given in miles per kilogram of wood rather than miles per gallon. Wartime gasifier cars could achieve about 1.5 miles per kilogram. Today’s designs improve upon this. But you can do a lot more with wood gases than just keep your vehicle on the road. It turns out to be suitable for any of the manufacturing processes needing heat that we looked at before, such as kilns for lime, cement or bricks. Wood gas generator units could easily power agricultural or industrial equipment, or pumps. Sweden and Denmark are world leaders in their use of sustainable forests and agricultural waste for turning the steam turbines in power stations. And once the steam has been used in their ‘Combined Heat and Power’ (CHP) electricity plants, it is piped to the surrounding towns and industries to heat them, allowing such CHP stations to approach 90 per cent energy efficiency. Such plants suggest a marvellous vision of industry wholly weaned from its dependency on fossil fuel. Is that our solution, then? Could our rebooting society run on wood, supplemented with electricity from renewable sources? Maybe so, if the population was fairly small. But here’s the catch. These options all presuppose that our survivors are able to construct efficient steam turbines, CHP stations and internal
14,846
<h4>Industrial civilization wouldn’t recover. </h4><p>Lewis <strong>Dartnell 15</strong>. UK Space Agency research fellow at the University of Leicester, working in astrobiology and the search for microbial life on Mars. His latest book is The Knowledge: How to Rebuild Our World from Scratch. 04-13-15. "Could we reboot a modern civilisation without fossil fuels? – Lewis Dartnell<u>." Aeon. https://aeon.co/essays/could-we-reboot-a-modern-civilisation-without-fossil-fuels</p><p><strong>Imagine that the world as we know it ends tomorrow</strong>. There’s a <strong>global catastrophe</u></strong>: a pandemic virus, an asteroid strike, or <u>perhaps a <strong>nuclear holocaust</u></strong>. <u>The <strong>vast majority</strong> of the human race <strong>perishes</strong>. Our civilisation collapses. The post-apocalyptic survivors find themselves in a devastated world of decaying, deserted cities</u> and roving gangs of bandits looting and taking by force. <u><strong>Bad as things sound, that’s not the end for humanity</u></strong>. <u>We</u> <u><strong>bounce back</u></strong>. Sooner or later, <u><strong>peace and order</u></strong> <u>emerge again, just as they have time and again through history. <strong>Stable communities</strong> take shape</u>. <u>They</u> <u>begin</u> the agonising process of <u><strong>rebuilding</u></strong> their technological base from scratch. <u>But here’s the question: how far could such a society rebuild? <mark>Is there <strong>any chance</u></strong></mark>, for instance, <u>that <mark>a post-apocalyptic society could <strong>reboot a technological civilisation?</mark> </u></strong>Let’s make the basis of this thought experiment a little more specific. Today, <u><mark>we have already consumed the <strong>most</strong> easily drainable <strong>crude oil</strong></mark> and</u>, particularly in Britain, much of the shallowest, <u><strong>most</strong> readily mined deposits of <strong>coal</u></strong>. <u><strong><mark>Fossil fuels are central</u></strong> <u>to</mark> the <mark>organisation of modern</mark> industrial <mark>society</mark>, just as they were central to its <strong>development</u></strong>. <u>Those</u>, by the way, <u>are</u> <u><strong>distinct roles</u></strong>: <u>even if we could somehow do without fossil fuels now (which we can’t, quite), it’s a different question whether we <strong>could have got to where we are without ever having had them</strong>. </u>So, would a society starting over on a planet stripped of its fossil fuel deposits have the chance to progress through its own Industrial Revolution? Or to phrase it another way, what might have happened if, for whatever reason, the Earth had never acquired its extensive underground deposits of coal and oil in the first place? Would our progress necessarily have halted in the 18th century, in a pre-industrial state? <u>It’s easy to <strong>underestimate</strong> our current dependence on fossil fuels</u>. In everyday life, their most visible use is the petrol or diesel pumped into the vehicles that fill our roads, and the coal and natural gas which fire the power stations that electrify our modern lives. But we also rely on a range of different industrial materials, and in most cases, high temperatures are required to transform the stuff we dig out of the ground or harvest from the landscape into something useful. <u><mark>You can’t smelt metal, make glass, roast the ingredients of concrete, or synthesise artificial fertiliser without</mark> a lot of heat. It is <strong><mark>fossil fuels</strong></mark> – coal, gas and oil – <mark>that provide</mark> most of this <strong><mark>thermal</strong> energy</mark>. </u>I<u>n fact, the problem is <strong>even worse</strong> than that. Many of the <strong>chemicals</strong> required in bulk to run the modern world, from pesticides to plastics, derive from the <strong>diverse organic compounds in crude oil</u></strong>. Given the dwindling reserves of crude oil left in the world, it could be argued that the most wasteful use for this limited resource is to simply burn it. We should be carefully preserving what’s left for the vital repertoire of valuable organic compounds it offers. But my topic here is not what we should do now. Presumably everybody knows that we must transition to a low-carbon economy one way or another. No, I want to answer a question whose interest is (let’s hope) more theoretical. <u>Is the emergence of a technologically advanced civilisation necessarily contingent on the easy availability of ancient energy?</u> Is it possible to build an industrialised civilisation without fossil fuels? And the answer to that question is: maybe – but it would be extremely difficult. Let’s see how. We’ll start with a natural thought. Many of our alternative energy technologies are already highly developed. Solar panels, for example, represent a good option today, and are appearing more and more on the roofs of houses and businesses. It’s tempting to think that a rebooted society could simply pick up where we leave off. <u>Why couldn’t our civilisation 2.0 just start with renewables? Well, it could, in a very limited way. If you find yourself among the survivors in a post-apocalyptic world, you could <strong>scavenge</u></strong> enough <u><strong>working solar panels</u></strong> to keep your lifestyle electrified for a good long while. Without moving parts, photovoltaic cells require little maintenance and are remarkably resilient. They do deteriorate over time, though, from moisture penetrating the casing and from sunlight itself degrading the high-purity silicon layers. The electricity generated by a solar panel declines by about 1 per cent every year so, after a few generations, all our hand-me-down solar panels will have degraded to the point of uselessness. <u><strong>Then what? New ones</u></strong> <u>would be <strong>fiendishly difficult</u></strong> to create from scratch. <u>Solar panels are</u> made from thin slices of <u><strong>extremely</u></strong> pure silicon, and although the raw material is common sand, it must be processed and refined using <u><strong>complex</u></strong> and precise techniques – the same technological capabilities, more or less, that we need for modern semiconductor electronics components. <u>These techniques took a long time to develop, and would presumably take a long time to recover. So photovoltaic solar power would not be within the capability of a society early in the industrialisation process. </u>Perhaps, though, we were on the right track by starting with electrical power. Most of our renewable-energy technologies produce electricity. In our own historical development, it so happens that the core phenomena of electricity were discovered in the first half of the 1800s, well after the early development of steam engines. Heavy industry was already committed to combustion-based machinery, and electricity has largely assumed a subsidiary role in the organisation of our economies ever since. But could that sequence have run the other way? Is there some developmental requirement that thermal energy must come first? On the face of it, it’s not beyond the bounds of possibility that a progressing society could construct electrical generators and couple them to simple windmills and waterwheels, later progressing to wind turbines and hydroelectric dams. <u><mark>In a world without fossil fuels, one might envisage an electrified civilisation that largely <strong>bypasses combustion</u></strong></mark> engines, building its transport infrastructure around electric trains and trams for long-distance and urban transport. <u>I say ‘largely’. We couldn’t get round it all together. When it comes to generating the white heat demanded by modern industry, there are <strong>few good options but to burn stuff </u></strong>While the electric motor could perhaps replace the coal-burning steam engine for mechanical applications, society, as we’ve already seen, also relies upon thermal energy to drive the essential chemical and physical transformations it needs. How could an industrialising society produce crucial building materials such as iron and steel, brick, mortar, cement and glass without resorting to deposits of coal? You can of course create heat from electricity. We already use electric ovens and kilns. Modern arc furnaces are used for producing cast iron or recycling steel. The problem isn’t so much that electricity can’t be used to heat things, but that for meaningful industrial activity you’ve got to generate prodigious amounts of it, which is challenging using only renewable energy sources such as wind and water. An alternative is to generate high temperatures using solar power directly. Rather than relying on photovoltaic panels, concentrated solar thermal farms use giant mirrors to focus the sun’s rays onto a small spot. The heat concentrated in this way can be exploited to drive certain chemical or industrial processes, or else to raise steam and drive a generator. Even so, it is difficult (for example) to produce the very high temperatures inside an iron-smelting blast furnace using such a system. What’s more, it goes without saying that the effectiveness of concentrated solar power depends strongly on the local climate. No, when it comes to generating the white heat demanded by modern industry, there are few good options but to burn stuff. But that doesn’t mean the stuff we burn necessarily has to be fossil fuels. Let’s take a quick detour into the pre-history of modern industry. Long before the adoption of coal, charcoal was widely used for smelting metals. In many respects it is superior: charcoal burns hotter than coal and contains far fewer impurities. In fact, coal’s impurities were a major delaying factor on the Industrial Revolution. Released during combustion, they can taint the product being heated. During smelting, sulphur contaminants can soak into the molten iron, making the metal brittle and unsafe to use. It took a long time to work out how to treat coal to make it useful for many industrial applications. And, in the meantime, charcoal worked perfectly well. And then, well, we stopped using it. In retrospect, that’s a pity. When it comes from a sustainable source, charcoal burning is essentially carbon-neutral, because it doesn’t release any new carbon into the atmosphere – not that this would have been a consideration for the early industrialists. But charcoal-based industry didn’t die out altogether. In fact, it survived to flourish in Brazil. Because it has substantial iron deposits but few coalmines, Brazil is the largest charcoal producer in the world and the ninth biggest steel producer. We aren’t talking about a cottage industry here, and this makes Brazil a very encouraging example for our thought experiment. The trees used in Brazil’s charcoal industry are mainly fast-growing eucalyptus, cultivated specifically for the purpose. The traditional method for creating charcoal is to pile chopped staves of air-dried timber into a great dome-shaped mound and then cover it with turf or soil to restrict airflow as the wood smoulders. The Brazilian enterprise has scaled up this traditional craft to an industrial operation. Dried timber is stacked into squat, cylindrical kilns, built of brick or masonry and arranged in long lines so that they can be easily filled and unloaded in sequence. The largest sites can sport hundreds of such kilns. Once filled, their entrances are sealed and a fire is lit from the top. The skill in charcoal production is to allow just enough air into the interior of the kiln. There must be enough combustion heat to drive out moisture and volatiles and to pyrolyse the wood, but not so much that you are left with nothing but a pile of ashes. The kiln attendant monitors the state of the burn by carefully watching the smoke seeping out of the top, opening air holes or sealing with clay as necessary to regulate the process. Brazil shows how the raw materials of modern civilisation can be supplied without reliance on fossil fuels Good things come to those who wait, and this wood pyrolysis process can take up to a week of carefully controlled smouldering. The same basic method has been used for millennia. However, the ends to which the fuel is put are distinctly modern. Brazilian charcoal is trucked out of the forests to the country’s blast furnaces where it is used to transform ore into pig iron. This pig iron is the basic ingredient of modern mass-produced steel. The Brazilian product is exported to countries such as China and the US where it becomes cars and trucks, sinks, bathtubs, and kitchen appliances. Around two-thirds of Brazilian charcoal comes from sustainable plantations, and so this modern-day practice has been dubbed ‘green steel’. Sadly, the final third is supplied by the non-sustainable felling of primary forest. Even so, the Brazilian case does provide an example of how the raw materials of modern civilisation can be supplied without reliance on fossil fuels. Another, related option might be wood gasification. The use of wood to provide heat is as old as mankind, and yet simply burning timber only uses about a third of its energy. The rest is lost when gases and vapours released by the burning process blow away in the wind. Under the right conditions, even smoke is combustible. We don’t want to waste it. Better than simple burning, then, is to drive the thermal breakdown of the wood and collect the gases. You can see the basic principle at work for yourself just by lighting a match. The luminous flame isn’t actually touching the matchwood: it dances above, with a clear gap in between. The flame actually feeds on the hot gases given off as the wood breaks down in the heat, and the gases combust only once they mix with oxygen from the air. Matches are fascinating when you look at them closely. Wartime gasifier cars could achieve about 1.5 miles per kilogram. Today’s designs improve upon this To release these gases in a controlled way, bake some timber in a closed container. Oxygen is restricted so that the wood doesn’t simply catch fire. Its complex molecules decompose through a process known as pyrolysis, and then the hot carbonised lumps of charcoal at the bottom of the container react with the breakdown products to produce flammable gases such as hydrogen and carbon monoxide. The resultant ‘producer gas’ is a versatile fuel: it can be stored or piped for use in heating or street lights, and is also suitable for use in complex machinery such as the internal combustion engine. More than a million gasifier-powered cars across the world kept civilian transport running during the oil shortages of the Second World War. In occupied Denmark, 95 per cent of all tractors, trucks and fishing boats were powered by wood-gas generators. The energy content of about 3 kg of wood (depending on its dryness and density) is equivalent to a litre of petrol, and the fuel consumption of a gasifier-powered car is given in miles per kilogram of wood rather than miles per gallon. Wartime gasifier cars could achieve about 1.5 miles per kilogram. Today’s designs improve upon this. But you can do a lot more with wood gases than just keep your vehicle on the road. It turns out to be suitable for any of the manufacturing processes needing heat that we looked at before, such as kilns for lime, cement or bricks. Wood gas generator units could easily power agricultural or industrial equipment, or pumps. Sweden and Denmark are world leaders in their use of sustainable forests and agricultural waste for turning the steam turbines in power stations. And once the steam has been used in their ‘Combined Heat and Power’ (CHP) electricity plants, it is piped to the surrounding towns and industries to heat them, allowing such CHP stations to approach 90 per cent energy efficiency. Such plants suggest a marvellous vision of industry wholly weaned from its dependency on fossil fuel. Is that our solution, then? <u>Could our rebooting society run on <strong>wood</u></strong>, supplemented with electricity from renewable sources? <u>Maybe so, if the <strong>population</strong> was <strong>fairly small</u></strong>. <u>But <strong>here’s the catch</strong>. These <mark>options</mark> all <mark>presuppose that our survivors are able to </mark>construct efficient steam turbines, CHP stations and internal </p></u>
4th Off
null
null
11,479
261
61,682
./documents/hsld20/AmericanHeritagePlantation/Ch/American%20Heritage%20Plantation-Cheng-Neg-Stanford-Round6.docx
852,662
N
Stanford
6
Sequoia AS
Eric Deng
1ac- nuclear LAWs 1n- must read a ROB ought implies can util k bunkers cp case 1ar- condo bad all 2n- ought implies can truth testing condo bad 2ar- aff ought implies can
hsld20/AmericanHeritagePlantation/Ch/American%20Heritage%20Plantation-Cheng-Neg-Stanford-Round6.docx
null
72,657
MaCh
American Heritage Plantation MaCh
null
Ma.....
Ch.....
null
null
24,407
AmericanHeritagePlantation
American Heritage Plantation
FL
null
1,028
hsld20
HS LD 2020-21
2,020
ld
hs
1
2,385,655
Lethal autonomous weapons are
CRS 20
CRS 20 Congressional Research Service, last updated 12/1/2020, “Defense Primer: U.S. Policy on Lethal Autonomous Weapon Systems,” https://fas.org/sgp/crs/natsec/IF11150.pdf, SJBE
“weapon system[s] that, once activated, can select and engage targets without further intervention by a human operator This contrasts LAWS with “human on the loop,” systems The directive does not cover munitions manually guided by the operator
weapon system[s] that can select and engage targets without further intervention by a human This contrasts LAWS with human on the loop systems
DODD 3000.09 defines LAWS as “weapon system[s] that, once activated, can select and engage targets without further intervention by a human operator.” This concept of autonomy is also known as “human out of the loop” or “full autonomy.” The directive contrasts LAWS with humansupervised, or “human on the loop,” autonomous weapon systems, in which operators have the ability to monitor and halt a weapon’s target engagement. Another category is semi-autonomous, or “human in the loop,” weapon systems that “only engage individual targets or specific target groups that have been selected by a human operator.” Semiautonomous weapons include so-called “fire and forget” weapons, such as certain types of guided missiles, that deliver effects to human-identified targets using autonomous functions. The directive does not cover “autonomous or semiautonomous cyberspace systems for cyberspace operations; unarmed, unmanned platforms; unguided munitions; munitions manually guided by the operator (e.g., laser- or wire-guided munitions); mines; [and] unexploded explosive ordnance,” nor subject them to its guidelines.
1,113
<h4>Lethal autonomous weapons are</h4><p><strong>CRS 20</strong> Congressional Research Service, last updated 12/1/2020, “Defense Primer: U.S. Policy on Lethal Autonomous Weapon Systems,” https://fas.org/sgp/crs/natsec/IF11150.pdf, SJBE</p><p>DODD 3000.09 defines LAWS as <u><strong>“<mark>weapon system[s] that</mark>, once activated, <mark>can select and engage targets without further intervention by a human</mark> operator</u></strong>.” <u><strong><mark>This</u></strong></mark> concept of autonomy is also known as “human out of the loop” or “full autonomy.” The directive <u><strong><mark>contrasts LAWS with</u></strong></mark> humansupervised, or <u><strong>“<mark>human on the loop</mark>,”</u></strong> autonomous weapon <u><strong><mark>systems</u></strong></mark>, in which operators have the ability to monitor and halt a weapon’s target engagement. Another category is semi-autonomous, or “human in the loop,” weapon systems that “only engage individual targets or specific target groups that have been selected by a human operator.” Semiautonomous weapons include so-called “fire and forget” weapons, such as certain types of guided missiles, that deliver effects to human-identified targets using autonomous functions. <u><strong>The directive does not cover</u></strong> “autonomous or semiautonomous cyberspace systems for cyberspace operations; unarmed, unmanned platforms; unguided munitions; <u><strong>munitions manually guided by the operator</u></strong> (e.g., laser- or wire-guided munitions); mines; [and] unexploded explosive ordnance,” nor subject them to its guidelines. </p>
null
1AC
Advocacy
7,523
1,183
76,245
./documents/hsld20/StrakeJesuit/Sh/Strake%20Jesuit-Shah-Aff-Churchill-Round2.docx
875,177
A
Churchill
2
Lincoln JR
Misra, Parth
1AC-Stock 1NC-SoKo PIC MAD DA Case 1AR-All 2NR-All 2AR-All
hsld20/StrakeJesuit/Sh/Strake%20Jesuit-Shah-Aff-Churchill-Round2.docx
null
73,807
KaSh
Strake Jesuit KaSh
null
Ka.....
Sh.....
null
null
24,736
StrakeJesuit
Strake Jesuit
TX
null
1,028
hsld20
HS LD 2020-21
2,020
ld
hs
1
4,669,304
Nuke war causes extinction.
Trevithick and Rogoway ’19
Trevithick and Rogoway ’19 [Joseph and Tyler; February 27; Military Analyst, M.A. in Conflict Resolution from Georgetown University, B.A. in the History and Policy of International Relations at Carnegie-Mellon University; Defense Journalist; The Drive, “Yes, India And Pakistan Could End The World As We Know It Through A Nuclear Exchange,” https://www.thedrive.com/the-war-zone/26674/yes-india-and-pakistan-could-end-the-world-as-we-know-it-through-a-nuclear-exchange] brett
India and Pakistan's nuclear arsenals are tiny United States and Russia but that does not mean they're purely regional threats nuclear weapons create lasting and far-reaching effects that could upend life on Earth if parties use them in sufficient numbers. In 2012 it might not take a large amount of nuclear weapons to create "Nuclear Winter." this occurs when soot from nuclear explosions block sunlight from earth's surface, leading to a drop in temperatures that results in crop failure and widespread famine writing "Even a 'small' nuclear war between India and Pakistan, with each country detonating 50 Hiroshima-size bombs – only about 0.03 percent of the global arsenal's power could produce smoke that temperatures would fall below the Little Ice Age threatening the global food supply there would be massive ozone depletion Little Boy results from Indian and Pakistani nuclear testing indicate both countries meet this threshold and weapons programs matured in decades at least 20 million people second order impacts would be even worse This study concluded detonation of 100 bombs in a purely regional conflict would result in "multi-decadal global cooling" and "would trigger a global nuclear famine." critics have questioned the impacts could be more severe if India and Pakistan use a larger number weapons or higher yields, which both belligerents readily have Nuclear Winter is just one of the things that might happen following a nuclear exchange A detonation of dozens of nuclear weapons, even small ones, would throw fallout into the air that could carry material far and wide ground zeroes a nuclear exchange could cut off water and food supplies melted down and exploded exclusion zone There would be major second-order "spillover" effects, as individuals fled areas, putting economic and political strains on neighboring regions. This could inflame existing tensions not directly related to conflict between India or Pakistan or lead to all new violent competition for limited resources. India already threatened to weaponize water access in its spat with the Pakistanis Any impacts on food and water or economic upheavals would have cascading impact across South Asia some negative reactions markets would certainly collapse after nuclear exchange We can only hope the two countries find a diplomatic solution and avoid any escalation. If things spiral out of control and lead to nuclear weapons, it would threaten all of humanity
nuclear weapons create Winter explosions block sunlight results in famine Ice Age ozone depletion global cooling effects inflame tensions cascading impact threaten humanity
A global threat India and Pakistan's nuclear arsenals are tiny compared to those of the United States and Russia, and these weapons are focused primarily on deterring each other, but that does not mean they're purely regional threats. Unlike conventional weapons, nuclear weapons create lasting and far-reaching effects that scientists have posited could upend life on Earth if warring parties were to use them in sufficient numbers. In 2012, Alan Robock, a distinguished professor in the Department of Environmental  Sciences and Associate Director of the Center for Environmental Prediction at Rutgers University, and Owen Brian Toon, a professor in the Department of Atmospheric and Oceanic Sciences and a research associate at  the Laboratory for Atmospheric and Space Physics at the University of Colorado, Boulder, argued that it might not take a large amount of nuclear weapons to create a scenario commonly known as "Nuclear Winter." In general, this hypothesized event occurs when smoke and soot from nuclear explosions block significant amounts of sunlight from reaching the earth's surface, leading to a precipitous drop in temperatures that results in mass crop failure and widespread famine. Robcock and Toon summarized their findings, which were based in part on their previous work, in an article in the Bulletin of The Atomic Scientists, writing: "Even a 'small' nuclear war between India and Pakistan, with each country detonating 50 Hiroshima-size atom bombs – only about 0.03 percent of the global nuclear arsenal's explosive power – as airbursts in urban areas, could produce so much smoke that temperatures would fall below those of the Little Ice Age of the fourteenth to nineteenth centuries, shortening the growing season around the world and threatening the global food supply. Furthermore, there would be massive ozone depletion, allowing more ultraviolet radiation to reach Earth's surface. Recent studies predict that agricultural production in parts of the United States and China would decline by about 20 percent for four years, and by 10 percent for a decade. The bomb the United States dropped on Hiroshima Japan, known as Little Boy, was an inefficient and essentially experimental design with a yield of around 15 kilotons. The reported results from Indian and Pakistani nuclear testing indicate that both countries can meet this threshold and both countries' weapons programs have almost certainly matured in the decades since. In previous studies, Robcock, working with others, postulated that temperature changes could begin within 10 days of a limited nuclear exchange and the effects from the detonations of 100 nuclear weapons in the 15-kiloton class would directly result in the deaths of at least 20 million people. The second order impacts would be even worse in the years that followed. In 2014, Michael Mills and Julia Lee-Taylor, both then working at the federally-funded National Center for Atmospheric Research's (NCAR) Earth System Laboratory, authored another paper with Robcock and Toon. This study concluded again that detonation of 100 15-kiloton yield bombs in a purely regional conflict would result in "multi-decadal global cooling" and "would put significant pressures on global food supplies and could trigger a global nuclear famine." It is important to note that critics have questioned whether the Nuclear Winter concept relies on too many assumptions and would ever actually occur. At the center of many of these rebuttals are debates about whether the nuclear explosions would truly create the amount of smoke and soot necessary for major climate change, as well as the specific conditions for those particles to remain in the atmosphere for a prolonged period of time. The studies here do indicate significant impacts based on a relatively limited number of nuclear detonations of smaller yield devices, though. But even if the impacts are less pronounced than projected in this particular scenario, they could be far more severe if India and Pakistan were to use a larger number weapons and/or ones of higher yields, which both belligerents readily have. In addition, Nuclear Winter is just one of the potential things that might happen following a nuclear exchange between the longtime foes. A detonation of dozens of nuclear weapons, even small ones, would throw hazardous nuclear fallout into the air that, depending on the weather pattern, could carry that material far and wide, causing both near- and short-term health impacts. The various ground zeroes themselves would be irritated and potentially hazardous for many years to come. Depending on where the detonations occur, a nuclear exchange could potentially cut people off from critical water and food supplies, putting increased and potentially unsustainable strains on uncontaminated areas.  After the Chernobyl nuclear power plant, situated in Ukraine, melted down and exploded in 1986, authorities established a 1,000 square mile restricted access "exclusion zone" that remains in place today. There would also be a major danger of second-order "spillover" effects, as individuals fled affected areas, putting economic and political strains on neighboring regions. This could inflame existing tensions not directly related to the inter-state conflict between India or Pakistan or lead to all new and potentially violent competition for what might already be limited resources. India has already threatened to weaponize water access in its latest spat with the Pakistanis. Any serious impacts on food and water supplies, or other economic upheavals as a direct or indirect result of the conflict, would have cascading impact across South Asia and beyond, as well. The very threat of a potential India-Pakistan war of any kind already caused some negative reactions in regional financial markets. Those markets would certainly collapse after an unprecedented nuclear exchange actually occurred, and that is before the long-term physical impacts of such an event would even manifest themselves. Overall, we are talking about a sudden and dramatic geopolitical, financial, and environmental shift that would change our reality in a matter of hours. Even then, the darkness, both figuratively and literally, that could propagate over the weeks, months, and years would be far more damaging. How great is the risk? So far, India and Pakistan have not made any clear indications that the fighting is close to crossing their nuclear thresholds. Pakistan's warnings about the risks of escalation seem more calculated to try and prompt India to back down. India itself has a so-called "no first use" policy, which means it has publicly pledged to use its nuclear weapons only in retaliation to a nuclear strike. However, experts have increasingly called into question whether this is truly the case and whether India might be developing delivery systems more suited to a first strike should there be a need to shift policies. Pakistan, however, does not have a no first use policy and has insisted on its right to employ nuclear weapons to defend itself even in the face of purely conventional threat. Pakistani officials have, in the past, specifically cited this policy as way of deterring India, which has a much larger and in some cases more advanced conventional force, and preventing larger wars. The concern, then, is that this policy appears to have failed, at least to some degree, with India's strike on undisputed Pakistani territory on Feb. 26, 2019. India, however, did not target Pakistani forces in that instance and exchanges between the two countries have been limited, at least so far, to the disputed Jammu and Kashmir region, where violent skirmishes occur semi-regularly without precipitating a larger confrontation. We can only hope that the two countries will find a diplomatic solution to this latest conflict and avoid any further escalation. If things were to spiral out of control and lead to the use of nuclear weapons, it would be something that would threaten all of humanity.
8,027
<h4>Nuke war causes <u>extinction</u>.</h4><p><strong>Trevithick and Rogoway ’19 </strong>[Joseph and Tyler; February 27; Military Analyst, M.A. in Conflict Resolution from Georgetown University, B.A. in the History and Policy of International Relations at Carnegie-Mellon University; Defense Journalist; The Drive, “Yes, India And Pakistan Could End The World As We Know It Through A Nuclear Exchange,” https://www.thedrive.com/the-war-zone/26674/yes-india-and-pakistan-could-end-the-world-as-we-know-it-through-a-nuclear-exchange] brett</p><p>A global threat</p><p><u>India and Pakistan's nuclear arsenals are tiny</u> compared to those of the <u>United States and Russia</u>, and these weapons are focused primarily on deterring each other, <u>but that does <strong>not mean</strong> they're <strong>purely regional</strong> threats</u>. Unlike conventional weapons, <u><mark>nuclear weapons</mark> create <strong>lasting</strong> and <strong>far-reaching</strong> effects that</u> scientists have posited <u>could <strong>upend life on Earth</strong> if</u> warring <u>parties</u> were to <u>use them in sufficient numbers.</p><p>In 2012</u>, Alan Robock, a distinguished professor in the Department of Environmental  Sciences and Associate Director of the Center for Environmental Prediction at Rutgers University, and Owen Brian Toon, a professor in the Department of Atmospheric and Oceanic Sciences and a research associate at  the Laboratory for Atmospheric and Space Physics at the University of Colorado, Boulder, argued that <u>it might not take a <strong>large amount</strong> of nuclear weapons to <mark>create</u></mark> a scenario commonly known as <u>"<strong>Nuclear <mark>Winter</strong></mark>."</u> </p><p>In general, <u>this</u> hypothesized event <u>occurs when</u> smoke and <u>soot from nuclear <mark>explosions block</u></mark> significant amounts of <u><mark>sunlight</mark> from</u> reaching the <u>earth's surface, leading to a</u> precipitous <u>drop in temperatures that <mark>results in</u></mark> mass <u><strong>crop failure</strong> and <strong>widespread <mark>famine</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>Robcock and Toon summarized their findings, which were based in part on their previous work, in an article in the Bulletin of The Atomic Scientists, <u>writing</u>:</p><p><u>"Even a '<strong>small</strong>' nuclear war between <strong>India</strong> and <strong>Pakistan</strong>, with each country detonating <strong>50 Hiroshima-size</u></strong> atom <u>bombs – only about <strong>0.03 percent</strong> of the global</u> nuclear <u>arsenal's</u> explosive <u>power</u> – as airbursts in urban areas, <u>could produce</u> so much <u>smoke that temperatures would fall below </u>those of <u>the</u> <u>Little <strong><mark>Ice Age</u></strong></mark> of the fourteenth to nineteenth centuries, shortening the growing season around the world and <u>threatening the global food supply</u>. Furthermore, <u>there would be massive <strong><mark>ozone depletion</u></strong></mark>, allowing more ultraviolet radiation to reach Earth's surface. Recent studies predict that agricultural production in parts of the United States and China would decline by about 20 percent for four years, and by 10 percent for a decade.</p><p>The bomb the United States dropped on Hiroshima Japan, known as <u>Little Boy</u>, was an inefficient and essentially experimental design with a yield of around 15 kilotons. The reported <u>results from Indian and Pakistani <strong>nuclear testing</strong> indicate</u> that <u>both countries</u> can <u><strong>meet this threshold</strong> and</u> both countries' <u>weapons programs</u> have almost certainly <u>matured in</u> the <u>decades</u> since.</p><p>In previous studies, Robcock, working with others, postulated that temperature changes could begin within 10 days of a limited nuclear exchange and the effects from the detonations of 100 nuclear weapons in the 15-kiloton class would directly result in the deaths of <u>at least 20 million people</u>. The <u><strong>second order</strong> impacts would be even worse</u> in the years that followed. </p><p>In 2014, Michael Mills and Julia Lee-Taylor, both then working at the federally-funded National Center for Atmospheric Research's (NCAR) Earth System Laboratory, authored another paper with Robcock and Toon. <u>This study concluded</u> again that <u>detonation of 100</u> 15-kiloton yield <u>bombs in a <strong>purely regional</strong> conflict would result in "multi-decadal <strong><mark>global cooling</strong></mark>" and "would</u> put significant pressures on global food supplies and could <u>trigger a global <strong>nuclear famine</strong>."</p><p></u>It is important to note that<u> critics have questioned</u> whether the Nuclear Winter concept relies on too many assumptions and would ever actually occur. At the center of many of these rebuttals are debates about whether the nuclear explosions would truly create the amount of smoke and soot necessary for major climate change, as well as the specific conditions for those particles to remain in the atmosphere for a prolonged period of time. </p><p>The studies here do indicate significant impacts based on a relatively limited number of nuclear detonations of smaller yield devices, though. But even if <u>the impacts</u> are less pronounced than projected in this particular scenario, they <u>could be</u> far <u>more severe if India and Pakistan</u> were to <u>use a larger number weapons</u> and/<u>or</u> ones of <u><strong>higher yields</strong>, which both belligerents readily have</u>. </p><p>In addition, <u>Nuclear Winter is just <strong>one</strong> of the</u> potential <u>things that might happen following a nuclear exchange</u> between the longtime foes. <u>A detonation of <strong>dozens</strong> of nuclear weapons, <strong>even small ones</strong>, would throw</u> hazardous nuclear <u>fallout <strong>into the air</strong> that</u>, depending on the weather pattern, <u>could <strong>carry</u></strong> that <u><strong>material</u></strong> <u>far and wide</u>, causing both near- and short-term health impacts. The various <u>ground zeroes</u> themselves would be irritated and potentially hazardous for many years to come.</p><p>Depending on where the detonations occur, <u>a nuclear exchange could</u> potentially <u>cut</u> people <u>off</u> from critical <u><strong>water</strong> and <strong>food</strong> supplies</u>, putting increased and potentially unsustainable strains on uncontaminated areas.  After the Chernobyl nuclear power plant, situated in Ukraine, <u>melted down and exploded</u> in 1986, authorities established a 1,000 square mile restricted access "<u>exclusion zone</u>" that remains in place today. </p><p><u>There would</u> also <u>be</u> a <u>major</u> danger of <u><strong>second-order</strong> "spillover" <strong><mark>effects</strong></mark>, as individuals fled</u> affected <u>areas, putting <strong>economic</strong> and <strong>political strains</strong> on neighboring regions. This could <strong><mark>inflame</strong></mark> existing <mark>tensions</mark> <strong>not directly related</strong> to</u> the inter-state <u>conflict between India or Pakistan or lead to all new</u> and potentially <u><strong>violent competition</strong> for</u> what might already be <u><strong>limited resources</strong>. India</u> has <u>already threatened to <strong>weaponize water</strong> access in its</u> latest <u>spat with the Pakistanis</u>.</p><p><u>Any</u> serious <u>impacts on food and water</u> supplies,<u> or</u> other <u>economic upheavals</u> as a direct or indirect result of the conflict, <u>would have <strong><mark>cascading impact</strong></mark> across <strong>South Asia</u></strong> and beyond, as well. The very threat of a potential India-Pakistan war of any kind already caused <u>some negative reactions</u> in regional financial markets. Those <u>markets would <strong>certainly collapse</strong> after</u> an unprecedented <u>nuclear exchange</u> actually occurred, and that is before the long-term physical impacts of such an event would even manifest themselves. </p><p>Overall, we are talking about a sudden and dramatic geopolitical, financial, and environmental shift that would change our reality in a matter of hours. Even then, the darkness, both figuratively and literally, that could propagate over the weeks, months, and years would be far more damaging. </p><p>How great is the risk?</p><p>So far, India and Pakistan have not made any clear indications that the fighting is close to crossing their nuclear thresholds. Pakistan's warnings about the risks of escalation seem more calculated to try and prompt India to back down.</p><p>India itself has a so-called "no first use" policy, which means it has publicly pledged to use its nuclear weapons only in retaliation to a nuclear strike. However, experts have increasingly called into question whether this is truly the case and whether India might be developing delivery systems more suited to a first strike should there be a need to shift policies.</p><p>Pakistan, however, does not have a no first use policy and has insisted on its right to employ nuclear weapons to defend itself even in the face of purely conventional threat. Pakistani officials have, in the past, specifically cited this policy as way of deterring India, which has a much larger and in some cases more advanced conventional force, and preventing larger wars.</p><p>The concern, then, is that this policy appears to have failed, at least to some degree, with India's strike on undisputed Pakistani territory on Feb. 26, 2019. India, however, did not target Pakistani forces in that instance and exchanges between the two countries have been limited, at least so far, to the disputed Jammu and Kashmir region, where violent skirmishes occur semi-regularly without precipitating a larger confrontation.</p><p><u>We can only hope</u> that <u>the two countries</u> will <u>find a diplomatic solution</u> to this latest conflict <u>and avoid any</u> further <u>escalation. If things</u> were to <u><strong>spiral out of control</strong> and lead to</u> the use of <u><strong>nuclear weapons</strong>, it would</u> be something that would <u><mark>threaten</mark> <strong>all of <mark>humanity</u></strong></mark>.</p>
null
null
1AC—ADV—Unity
13,882
675
161,967
./documents/hsld22/CarnegieVanguard/LaHu/CarnegieVanguard-LaHu-Aff-Seattle-University-High-School-Speech-and-Debate-Tournament-Octas.docx
970,362
A
Seattle University High School Speech and Debate Tournament
Octas
MouVer Taite Kirkpatrick
Talamantes,Clinger-Mobley,Rereddy
1ac - schengenlargement v7 1nc - no borders cp, populism da, case 1ar - all 2nr - all 2ar - all
hsld22/CarnegieVanguard/LaHu/CarnegieVanguard-LaHu-Aff-Seattle-University-High-School-Speech-and-Debate-Tournament-Octas.docx
2023-01-29 22:56:59
80,518
LaHu
Carnegie Vanguard LaHu
null
La.....
Hu.....
null
null
27,038
CarnegieVanguard
Carnegie Vanguard
TX
null
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
2,536,791
Undoing squo power relations requires analyzing and attacking power structures through agonistic struggle---normative appeals alone are ineffective.
Zack 17
Naomi Zack 17. Professor of philosophy at the University of Oregon. 02/2017. “Ideal, Nonideal, and Empirical Theories of Social Justice: The Need for Applicative Justice in Addressing Injustice.” The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Race, Oxford University Press.
Ideals of justice may do little toward the correction of injustice in real life Rawls has led some philosophers of race to focus on “nonideal theory” as a way to bring conditions in unjust societies closer to conditions of justice described by ideal theory However, a more direct approach to injustice may be needed to address unfair public policy and existing conditions for minorities in racist societies ideal theory is too abstract to correct injustice or provide justice for victims of injustice in reality, because it is based on a thought experiment and the assumption of a “well-ordered” society in which there already is compliance with law What people care about in reality concerning justice is not what ideal justice is or would be but how immediate injustice can be corrected Injustice is always specific in concrete events that are recognizable as certain types for example, theft, murder, or police racial profiling. Injustice can be corrected by punishing those responsible in specific cases and instituting social changes that prevent or reduce future occurrences of the same type nonideal theories of justice rely on ideal theory as a standard for just institutional structures Nonideal theory asks how this long-term goal might be achieved, or worked toward, usually in gradual steps However, injured or indignant parties may not care about the long-term goal of justice that could lead to balance or compensation for their situations the best theory of justice in the world does not tell us what to do about the injustices we are faced with in the here and now especially “the more pressing problems” of race-related injustices Such questions cannot be answered with reference to ideal theory or some application of ideal or nonideal theory to their concrete situations, because the a priori nature of both of these does not provide a fit with specific contingencies ideal and nonideal theories do not generate practical bridge principles As theories, they posit ideal entities but without connections to observable entities or events The correction of injustice or injustice theory requires a philosophical foundation for itself. Models of justice have often been naïvely utopian because they are based on an assumption of compliance, as though the right words or pictures by themselves have the power to transform reality, or as though agreement with those right words or pictures will automatically result in action that will automatically make the world instantiate those words or pictures When they are not fantastically and ineffectively utopian in this way such models have been used to justify the already-existing dominance of some groups over others The extension of existing practices of justice to members of new groups is applicative justice Applicative justice takes a comparative approach, comparing how young black males are treated by police officers in contemporary US society, to how young white males are treated Applicative justice rests on a pragmatic approach to social ills which includes the premise that government is much more than the apparatus of state and written laws and court decisions Government is an extended, dynamic process, an ongoing contention among interest groups in society Rawls’s insistence that “the rights secured by justice are not subject to political bargaining should be understood as “the rights secured by justice should not be subject to political bargaining In reality the rights secured by justice” are constantly subject to political bargaining and the living calculus of social interests One consequence of this empirical perspective is that moral outrage, critiques of white supremacy, or analyses of white privilege, along with other forms of blame, cannot be assumed to have the power to change anything, by themselves By contrast, changing relationships between police officers and their local communities, or changing the rules of engagement might have some causal power It is important to realize that such changes in practice would not be specific applications of a theory of justice, but ways of changing social reality into a different political mix. Unjust laws or laws with gaps are compatible with just practice Thus, applicative justice is pragmatic in taking the whole political mix as its subject for a specific injustice the applicative justice approach brooks little faith that reality can be changed by a special conceptual space or mode of critical moral discourse that is undertaken apart from reality. Reality cannot be changed by normative pronouncements, by or on behalf of the oppressed but only by shifts in existing interests of groups of real people To base hopes for change on normative content alone may [eliminate] the means for taking action that could result in change because such content proceeds as though matters of justice were only matters of argument Those who have opposed social racial justice have understood this well enough, because instead of mainly arguing against new just law they have taken action to block progress. The contrast between blueprints and maps is important to consider Political philosophers often proceed as though their writings about justice are blueprints, when they should instead begin by constructing maps. Present politics or a political party in power may present obstacles and challenges to applicative justice in any specific case Those who aim for applicative justice must struggle against such obstacles and challenges as well as the ignorance, prejudice, and ill will of large parts of voting publics under democratic government, and in addition, media misrepresentations, business interests in a status quo, and lack of understanding of oppression by those who are treated unjustly the complexity of causes and background factors associated with the disproportionate number of African American male prison inmates can be understood through a number of approaches The normative approach of applicative justice would be to address those causes or factors, distinctly and individually, through specific changes in concrete practice, as well as changes in law, as relevant
a direct approach to injustice may be needed to address unfair policy and conditions for minorities in racist societies What people care about is not ideal justice but how immediate injustice in concrete events can be corrected in the here and now Models of justice assum words by themselves have power to transform reality, or as though agreement with words will automatically result in action fantastically and ineffectively utopian Applicative justice takes a comparative pragmatic approach Government is an ongoing contention among interest groups rights secured by justice” are constantly subject to political bargaining and the calculus of social interests outrage, critiques of white supremacy, or analyses of white privilege cannot change anything, by themselves By contrast changing the rules might have causal power Reality cannot be changed by normative pronouncements but only by shifts in interests of groups of real people To base hopes for change on normative content alone may [eliminate] means for taking action that could result in change Political philosophers should construct maps politics or a party in power may challenge justice Those who aim for justice must struggle against such obstacles through specific changes in concrete practice, as well as changes in law
Ideals of justice may do little toward the correction of injustice in real life. The influence of John Rawls’s A Theory of Justice has led some philosophers of race to focus on “nonideal theory” as a way to bring conditions in unjust societies closer to conditions of justice described by ideal theory. However, a more direct approach to injustice may be needed to address unfair public policy and existing conditions for minorities in racist societies. Applicative justice describes the applications of principles of justice that are now “good enough” for whites to nonwhites (based on prior comparisons of how whites and nonwhites are treated). Social information just dribbles in, bit by bit, and we simply get used to it. A single story about a person really hits home at once, but the grinding injustices of daily life are endured. It is easy to ignore them and we do. Judith Shklar, The Faces of Injustice (Shklar 1990, 110) IDEAL theory about justice extends from Plato’s Republic to John Rawls’s A Theory of Justice, including many careers devoted to analyses and criticism about such texts in political philosophy. Rawls offers a picture of the basic institutional structures of a just society, on the premise that in order to correct injustice, we must first know what justice is. According to Rawls, while “partial compliance theory” studies the principles that govern how we are to deal with injustice, full compliance theory, or ideal theory, studies the institutional principles of justice in a stable society where citizens obey the law. Rawls began A Theory of Justice with the claim: “The reason for beginning with ideal theory is that it provides, I believe, the only basis for the systematic grasp of these more pressing problems” (Rawls 1971, 8). Rawls’s ideal theory is too abstract to correct injustice or provide justice for victims of injustice in reality, because it is based on a thought experiment and the assumption of a “well-ordered” society in which there already is compliance with law (Zack 2016, 1–64). What people care about in reality concerning justice is not what ideal justice is or would be, but how immediate injustice can be corrected. Injustice is always specific in concrete events that are recognizable as certain types, for example, theft, murder, or police racial profiling. Injustice can be corrected by punishing those responsible for it in specific cases and instituting social changes that prevent or reduce future occurrences of the same type. Rawlsian nonideal theories of justice, constructed for societies where people do not comply with just laws, rely on ideal theory as a standard for just institutional structures. The main question driving nonideal theory is how to construct a model or picture of justice that will result in the future correction or avoidance of present injustices. John Simmons quotes John Rawls from Law of Peoples, on this matter. Nonideal theory asks how this long-term goal might be achieved, or worked toward, usually in gradual steps. It looks for courses of action that are morally permissible and politically possible as well as likely to be effective [LOP p. 89]. (Simmons 2010, 7) However, injured or indignant parties may not care about the long-term goal of justice that could lead to balance or compensation for their situations. Not only are what P. F. Strawson (1962) called “reactive attitudes,” such as moral indignation, blame, and a desire for deserved punishment, strong in their focus on injustice, but the best theory of justice in the world does not tell us what to do about the injustices we are faced with in the here and now, especially “the more pressing problems” of race-related injustices. Such questions cannot be answered with reference to ideal theory or some application of ideal or nonideal theory to their concrete situations, because the a priori nature of both of these does not provide a fit with specific contingencies—ideal and nonideal theories do not generate practical bridge principles. As theories, they posit ideal entities, but without the apparatus of scientific theories which provides connections to observable entities or events. (Moulines 1985). The correction of injustice or injustice theory requires a philosophical foundation for itself. Models of justice have often been naïvely utopian throughout the history of philosophy, because they are based on an assumption of automatic total compliance, as though the right words or pictures by themselves have the power to transform reality, or as though agreement with those right words or pictures will automatically result in action that will automatically make the world instantiate those words or pictures. When they are not fantastically and ineffectively utopian in this way, such models have been used to justify the already-existing dominance of some groups over others. (A prime example is John Locke’s Second Treatise of Government, written decades before 1688 Glorious Revolution, to express the interests of the new rising class of landed gentry, which were eventually fulfilled by a Protestant king on the throne and a strong representative parliament after that revolution [Laslett 1988].) Models of justice have legitimately served to inspire law in modern societies with government constitutions and national and local law. But, sometimes, as in US founding documents, although universal and absolute justice is proclaimed, subsequent events make it clear that this language was intended to legitimize just treatment for members of selected groups only, that is, white male property owners, at first. As a result of just law and its selective application, over time, there comes to be justice for an expanding group, but still not everyone in society. However, what is written, together with descriptions of real justice for some, can be a powerful lever for obtaining justice for at least some of the excluded. To understand how that works, it is necessary to develop an approach to justice that begins with injustice, in real situations where there is already some degree of justice in a larger whole. The extension of existing practices of justice to members of new groups is applicative justice, a concept with substantial historical and intellectual precedent, although not by that name. In what follows, more will be said about the idea of applicative justice and then its history will be considered. Voting rights and housing rights are examples of candidates for applicative justice in our time. Finally, content in the form of narrative may be motivational for social change. The Idea of Applicative Justice Applicative justice is an approach to justice with the goal of making the unjust treatment of some comparable to those who already receive just treatment. Applicative justice takes a comparative approach, for example, comparing how young black males are treated by police officers in contemporary US society, to how young white males are treated (Jones 2013; Zack 2013, 2015). Applicative justice rests on a pragmatic approach to social ills, which includes the premise, based on Arthur Bentley’s 1908 insights in The Process of Government, that government is much more than the apparatus of state and written laws and court decisions. Government is an extended, dynamic process, an ongoing contention among interest groups in society. This full-bodied, empirical and pragmatic view of government process entails, for example, that we consider as parts of the same political mix/phenomenon/raw material all of the foregoing: the Fourth and Fourteenth Amendments, the 1960s Civil Rights Legislation, doctrines of probable cause, the disproportionate incarceration of African Americans, racial profiling, and police homicide with impunity. Thus, Rawls’s insistence that “the rights secured by justice are not subject to political bargaining or to the calculus of social interests” (Rawls 1971, 4), should be understood as “the rights secured by justice should not be subject to political bargaining or to the calculus of social interests.” In reality, “the rights secured by justice” are constantly subject to political bargaining and the living calculus of social interests. One consequence of this empirical perspective is that moral outrage, critiques of white supremacy, or analyses of white privilege, along with other forms of blame, cannot be assumed to have the power to change anything, by themselves. By contrast, changing relationships between police officers and their local communities, or changing the rules of engagement when police stop or attempt to stop suspects, might on this view have some causal power (Ayres and Markovits 2014). It is important to realize that such changes in practice would not be specific applications of a theory of justice, but ways of changing social reality into a different political mix. However, a better theory of justice, even a more racially egalitarian one and even a theory of applicative justice that was widely accepted, would still be no more than a change in what Bentley calls “political content.” Any theory of justice or any set of just laws is compatible with widespread racially unequal and unjust practice. And the converse also holds. Unjust laws or laws with gaps for unjust practice are compatible with just practice. Thus, applicative justice is pragmatic in taking the whole political mix/ phenomenon/raw material as its subject for a specific injustice. Unlike ideal or nonideal justice theory, the applicative justice approach brooks little faith that reality can be changed by a special conceptual space or mode of critical moral discourse that is undertaken apart from reality. Reality cannot be changed by normative pronouncements, by or on behalf of the oppressed, but only by shifts in existing interests of groups of real people. To base hopes for change on normative content alone may paralyze [eliminate] the means for taking action that could result in change, because such content proceeds as though matters of justice were only matters of argument. Those who have opposed social racial justice have understood this well enough, because instead of mainly arguing against new just law over the twentieth century, they have taken action to block progress. Race and Justice Consideration of race and injustice together, within political philosophy, focuses on the need for specific groups to not be treated unjustly. For a group to be treated justly, a large number of its members need to be treated justly. But for a group to be treated unjustly, it is sufficient if a smaller number or lower proportion than required to meet the standard of just treatment be treated unjustly. One reason for this asymmetry is that just treatment is easily normalized within communities, whereas unjust treatment of only a few is disruptive and considered abnormal among other members of the group to which victims belong (although not necessarily by members of groups who are generally treated justly). The unjust treatment of a small number ripples from their friends and relations to other members of the same group, who realize that they are subject to similar unjust treatment from their membership in that group alone. More broadly, if the group treated justly and the group treated unjustly belong to the same larger collective, such as whites and blacks in the United States, then the unjust treatment of even a very small number of that total collective of residents or citizens should be disruptive to the whole collective, given promulgated principles of “justice for all.” But that does not always happen, at least not in ways that result in real change. Apathy and self-absorption of those not treated unjustly is part of the reason, although another significant part is that the group treated justly already knows that the national collective rhetoric of justice is intended to apply primarily to them. It is that kind of disparate treatment, which does not disrupt everyone, even though it should, which calls for a theory of applicative justice, on the abstract level where people call for justice. But applicative justice is not only an abstract theory. Applicative justice requires comparisons of group treatment. If minorities are treated unjustly, a description of that injustice does not require an ideal or nonideal theory or model of justice, but simply a comparison with how the majority is treated. (The term “minorities” refers to those disadvantaged or oppressed, because sometimes minorities are greater in number than “majorities,” e.g., blacks under apartheid in South Africa, American slaves in some Southern states, or black Americans in some twenty-first-century cities.) The principles and mechanics of justice that work well enough for most white Americans need to be applied to nonwhite Americans. For rhetorical purposes, it might be evocative to talk about black lives or black rights, but strictly speaking the subject is a racial framework that is color-blind in an important part of law—constitutional amendments and federal legislation—but not in reality. This gap between written law and social reality can be viewed as hypocrisy, racial bias, or white supremacy, only if one assumes that written law is an accurate description of, or blueprint for, social reality. But a perspective that takes in the whole process of government reveals that the gap and what is permissible within it, are parts of the same whole process. The contrast between blueprints and maps is important to consider. Political philosophers often proceed as though their writings about justice are blueprints, when they should instead begin by constructing maps. Present politics or a political party in power may present obstacles and challenges to applicative justice in any specific case. Those who aim for applicative justice must struggle against such obstacles and challenges, as well as the ignorance, prejudice, and ill will of large parts of voting publics under democratic government, and in addition, media misrepresentations, business interests in a status quo, and lack of understanding of oppression by those who are treated unjustly. For example, the injustice in the disproportionately large number of African Americans in the US criminal justice system has been supported by law-and-order politics, the War on Drugs, belief in racial gender myths (e.g., the larger-than-life black rapist), explicit racism, media sensationalism of crime committed by black men, profits made by for-profit prison corporations, and embrace of self-destructive subcultures by some black men who become incarcerated. At the same time, as an efficient cause or precipitating factor, ongoing racial profiling by police helps feed the system with new suspects, about 90 percent of whom plead guilty in preference to the risks and costs of a trial (Kerby 2013; Rakoff et al. 2014). Intergenerational poverty, unemployment, and undereducation contain people within this system, and the high rates of nonwhites in the prison population are used as official justification for racial profiling (Zack 2015, chap 2). Thus, the complexity of causes and background factors associated with the disproportionate number of African American male prison inmates can be understood through a number of approaches. The normative approach of applicative justice would be to address those causes or factors, distinctly and individually, through specific changes in concrete practice, as well as changes in law, as relevant.
15,487
<h4>Undoing squo power relations requires analyzing and attacking power structures through agonistic struggle---normative appeals alone are ineffective. </h4><p>Naomi <strong>Zack 17</strong>. Professor of philosophy at the University of Oregon. 02/2017. “Ideal, Nonideal, and Empirical Theories of Social Justice: The Need for Applicative Justice in Addressing Injustice.” The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Race, Oxford University Press.</p><p><u><strong>Ideals</u></strong> <u>of justice may do <strong>little toward the correction of injustice in real life</u></strong>. The influence of John <u>Rawls</u>’s A Theory of Justice <u>has led some philosophers of race to focus on “nonideal theory” as a way to bring conditions in unjust societies closer to conditions of justice described by ideal theory</u>. <u>However, <mark>a</mark> <strong>more <mark>direct approach to injustice</u></strong> <u>may be needed to <strong>address unfair</mark> public <mark>policy</u></strong> <u>and</u></mark> <u><strong>existing <mark>conditions for minorities in racist societies</u></strong></mark>. Applicative justice describes the applications of principles of justice that are now “good enough” for whites to nonwhites (based on prior comparisons of how whites and nonwhites are treated). Social information just dribbles in, bit by bit, and we simply get used to it. A single story about a person really hits home at once, but the grinding injustices of daily life are endured. It is easy to ignore them and we do. Judith Shklar, The Faces of Injustice (Shklar 1990, 110) IDEAL theory about justice extends from Plato’s Republic to John Rawls’s A Theory of Justice, including many careers devoted to analyses and criticism about such texts in political philosophy. Rawls offers a picture of the basic institutional structures of a just society, on the premise that in order to correct injustice, we must first know what justice is. According to Rawls, while “partial compliance theory” studies the principles that govern how we are to deal with injustice, full compliance theory, or ideal theory, studies the institutional principles of justice in a stable society where citizens obey the law. Rawls began A Theory of Justice with the claim: “The reason for beginning with ideal theory is that it provides, I believe, the only basis for the systematic grasp of these more pressing problems” (Rawls 1971, 8). Rawls’s <u>ideal theory is too abstract to correct injustice or provide justice for victims of injustice in reality, because it is based on a <strong>thought experiment</u></strong> <u>and the <strong>assumption of a “well-ordered” society</u></strong> <u>in which there already is compliance with law</u> (Zack 2016, 1–64). <u><mark>What people care about</mark> in reality concerning justice <mark>is <strong>not</mark> what <mark>ideal justice</mark> is or would be</u></strong>, <u><mark>but how <strong>immediate injustice</mark> can be corrected</u></strong>. <u>Injustice is always <strong>specific <mark>in concrete events</u></strong></mark> <u>that are recognizable as <strong>certain types</u></strong>, <u>for example, theft, murder, or police racial profiling. Injustice <mark>can be corrected</mark> by <strong>punishing those responsible</u></strong> for it <u>in specific cases and <strong>instituting social changes that prevent or reduce future occurrences of the same type</u></strong>. Rawlsian <u>nonideal theories of justice</u>, constructed for societies where people do not comply with just laws, <u>rely on ideal theory as a standard for just institutional structures</u>. The main question driving nonideal theory is how to construct a model or picture of justice that will result in the future correction or avoidance of present injustices. John Simmons quotes John Rawls from Law of Peoples, on this matter. <u>Nonideal theory asks how this long-term goal might be achieved, or worked toward, usually in gradual steps</u>. It looks for courses of action that are morally permissible and politically possible as well as likely to be effective [LOP p. 89]. (Simmons 2010, 7) <u>However, injured or indignant parties <strong>may not care about the long-term goal of justice</u></strong> <u>that could lead to balance or compensation for their situations</u>. Not only are what P. F. Strawson (1962) called “reactive attitudes,” such as moral indignation, blame, and a desire for deserved punishment, strong in their focus on injustice, but <u>the <strong>best theory of justice in the world</u></strong> <u>does not tell us what to do about the injustices we are faced with <mark>in the <strong>here and now</u></strong></mark>, <u>especially “the <strong>more pressing problems” of race-related injustices</u></strong>. <u>Such questions cannot be answered with reference to ideal theory or some application of ideal or nonideal theory to their concrete situations, because the a priori nature of both of these <strong>does not provide a fit with specific contingencies</u></strong>—<u>ideal and nonideal theories do not generate <strong>practical bridge principles</u></strong>. <u>As theories, they posit <strong>ideal entities</u></strong>, <u>but without</u> the apparatus of scientific theories which provides <u>connections to <strong>observable entities or events</u></strong>. (Moulines 1985). <u>The correction of injustice or injustice theory requires a philosophical foundation for itself. <mark>Models of justice</mark> have often been <strong>naïvely utopian</u></strong> throughout the history of philosophy, <u>because they are based on an <mark>assum</mark>ption of</u> automatic total <u>compliance, as though the <strong>right <mark>words</mark> or pictures <mark>by themselves</u></strong> <u>have</mark> the <mark>power to <strong>transform reality</strong>,</u> <u>or as though agreement with</mark> those right <mark>words</mark> or pictures <mark>will <strong>automatically result in action</mark> that will automatically make the world instantiate those words or pictures</u></strong>. <u>When they are not <strong><mark>fantastically and ineffectively utopian</strong></mark> in this way</u>, <u>such models have been used to justify the already-existing dominance of some groups over others</u>. (A prime example is John Locke’s Second Treatise of Government, written decades before 1688 Glorious Revolution, to express the interests of the new rising class of landed gentry, which were eventually fulfilled by a Protestant king on the throne and a strong representative parliament after that revolution [Laslett 1988].) Models of justice have legitimately served to inspire law in modern societies with government constitutions and national and local law. But, sometimes, as in US founding documents, although universal and absolute justice is proclaimed, subsequent events make it clear that this language was intended to legitimize just treatment for members of selected groups only, that is, white male property owners, at first. As a result of just law and its selective application, over time, there comes to be justice for an expanding group, but still not everyone in society. However, what is written, together with descriptions of real justice for some, can be a powerful lever for obtaining justice for at least some of the excluded. To understand how that works, it is necessary to develop an approach to justice that begins with injustice, in real situations where there is already some degree of justice in a larger whole. <u>The extension of existing practices of justice to members of new groups is <strong>applicative justice</u></strong>, a concept with substantial historical and intellectual precedent, although not by that name. In what follows, more will be said about the idea of applicative justice and then its history will be considered. Voting rights and housing rights are examples of candidates for applicative justice in our time. Finally, content in the form of narrative may be motivational for social change. The Idea of Applicative Justice Applicative justice is an approach to justice with the goal of making the unjust treatment of some comparable to those who already receive just treatment. <u><mark>Applicative justice takes a <strong>comparative</mark> approach</strong>,</u> for example, <u>comparing how young <strong>black</strong> males are treated by police officers in contemporary US society, to how young <strong>white</strong> males are treated</u> (Jones 2013; Zack 2013, 2015). <u>Applicative justice rests on a <strong><mark>pragmatic approach</mark> to social ills</u></strong>, <u>which includes the premise</u>, based on Arthur Bentley’s 1908 insights in The Process of Government, <u>that government is much more than the apparatus of state and written laws and court decisions</u>. <u><mark>Government is an</mark> extended, dynamic process, an <mark>ongoing <strong>contention among interest groups</mark> in society</u></strong>. This full-bodied, empirical and pragmatic view of government process entails, for example, that we consider as parts of the same political mix/phenomenon/raw material all of the foregoing: the Fourth and Fourteenth Amendments, the 1960s Civil Rights Legislation, doctrines of probable cause, the disproportionate incarceration of African Americans, racial profiling, and police homicide with impunity. Thus, <u>Rawls’s insistence that “the rights secured by justice are not subject to political bargaining</u> or to the calculus of social interests” (Rawls 1971, 4), <u>should be understood as “the rights secured by justice <strong>should</strong> not be subject to political bargaining</u> or to the calculus of social interests.” <u>In</u> <u><strong>reality</u></strong>, “<u>the <mark>rights secured by justice” are <strong>constantly subject to political bargaining</u></strong> <u>and the</mark> <strong>living <mark>calculus of social interests</u></strong></mark>. <u>One consequence of this empirical perspective is that <strong>moral <mark>outrage</strong>, <strong>critiques of white supremacy</strong>, or <strong>analyses of white privilege</strong></mark>, along with other forms of <strong>blame</strong>, <strong><mark>cannot</mark> be assumed to have the power to <mark>change anything, by themselves</u></strong></mark>. <u><mark>By contrast</mark>, changing relationships between police officers and their local communities, or <mark>changing the <strong>rules</mark> of engagement</u></strong> when police stop or attempt to stop suspects, <u><strong><mark>might</u></strong></mark> on this view <u><mark>have</mark> some <strong><mark>causal power</u></strong></mark> (Ayres and Markovits 2014). <u>It is important to realize that such changes in practice would not be specific applications of a theory of justice, but ways of changing social reality into a different political mix. </u>However, a better theory of justice, even a more racially egalitarian one and even a theory of applicative justice that was widely accepted, would still be no more than a change in what Bentley calls “political content.” Any theory of justice or any set of just laws is compatible with widespread racially unequal and unjust practice. And the converse also holds. <u>Unjust laws or laws with gaps</u> for unjust practice <u>are</u> <u><strong>compatible with just practice</u></strong>. <u>Thus, applicative justice is <strong>pragmatic</u></strong> <u>in taking the <strong>whole political mix</u></strong>/ phenomenon/raw material <u>as its subject for a specific injustice</u>. Unlike ideal or nonideal justice theory, <u>the applicative justice approach brooks <strong>little faith</u></strong> <u>that <strong>reality can be changed by a special conceptual space or mode of critical moral discourse</u></strong> <u>that is undertaken apart from reality. <mark>Reality <strong>cannot be changed by normative pronouncements</mark>, by or on behalf of the oppressed</u></strong>, <u><mark>but <strong>only by shifts in</mark> existing <mark>interests of groups of real people</u></strong></mark>. <u><mark>To base <strong>hopes for change on normative content alone may</u></strong></mark> paralyze <u><strong><mark>[eliminate]</mark> the <mark>means for taking action that could result in change</u></strong></mark>, <u>because such content proceeds as though matters of justice were <strong>only matters of argument</u></strong>. <u>Those who have opposed social racial justice have understood this well enough, because instead of mainly arguing against new just law</u> over the twentieth century, <u>they have taken action to block progress. </u>Race and Justice Consideration of race and injustice together, within political philosophy, focuses on the need for specific groups to not be treated unjustly. For a group to be treated justly, a large number of its members need to be treated justly. But for a group to be treated unjustly, it is sufficient if a smaller number or lower proportion than required to meet the standard of just treatment be treated unjustly. One reason for this asymmetry is that just treatment is easily normalized within communities, whereas unjust treatment of only a few is disruptive and considered abnormal among other members of the group to which victims belong (although not necessarily by members of groups who are generally treated justly). The unjust treatment of a small number ripples from their friends and relations to other members of the same group, who realize that they are subject to similar unjust treatment from their membership in that group alone. More broadly, if the group treated justly and the group treated unjustly belong to the same larger collective, such as whites and blacks in the United States, then the unjust treatment of even a very small number of that total collective of residents or citizens should be disruptive to the whole collective, given promulgated principles of “justice for all.” But that does not always happen, at least not in ways that result in real change. Apathy and self-absorption of those not treated unjustly is part of the reason, although another significant part is that the group treated justly already knows that the national collective rhetoric of justice is intended to apply primarily to them. It is that kind of disparate treatment, which does not disrupt everyone, even though it should, which calls for a theory of applicative justice, on the abstract level where people call for justice. But applicative justice is not only an abstract theory. Applicative justice requires comparisons of group treatment. If minorities are treated unjustly, a description of that injustice does not require an ideal or nonideal theory or model of justice, but simply a comparison with how the majority is treated. (The term “minorities” refers to those disadvantaged or oppressed, because sometimes minorities are greater in number than “majorities,” e.g., blacks under apartheid in South Africa, American slaves in some Southern states, or black Americans in some twenty-first-century cities.) The principles and mechanics of justice that work well enough for most white Americans need to be applied to nonwhite Americans. For rhetorical purposes, it might be evocative to talk about black lives or black rights, but strictly speaking the subject is a racial framework that is color-blind in an important part of law—constitutional amendments and federal legislation—but not in reality. This gap between written law and social reality can be viewed as hypocrisy, racial bias, or white supremacy, only if one assumes that written law is an accurate description of, or blueprint for, social reality. But a perspective that takes in the whole process of government reveals that the gap and what is permissible within it, are parts of the same whole process. <u>The contrast between <strong>blueprints</strong> and <strong>maps</strong> is important to consider</u>. <u><mark>Political philosophers</mark> often proceed as though their writings about justice are blueprints, when <strong>they <mark>should</mark> instead begin by <mark>construct</mark>ing <mark>maps</strong></mark>. Present <strong><mark>politics</strong> or a</mark> <strong>political <mark>party</u></strong> <u>in power may</mark> present obstacles and <mark>challenge</mark>s to applicative <mark>justice</mark> in any specific case</u>. <u><mark>Those who aim for</mark> applicative <mark>justice must <strong>struggle against such obstacles</mark> and challenges</u></strong>, <u>as well as the ignorance, prejudice, and ill will of large parts of voting publics under democratic government, and in addition, media misrepresentations, business interests in a status quo, and lack of understanding of oppression by those who are treated unjustly</u>. For example, the injustice in the disproportionately large number of African Americans in the US criminal justice system has been supported by law-and-order politics, the War on Drugs, belief in racial gender myths (e.g., the larger-than-life black rapist), explicit racism, media sensationalism of crime committed by black men, profits made by for-profit prison corporations, and embrace of self-destructive subcultures by some black men who become incarcerated. At the same time, as an efficient cause or precipitating factor, ongoing racial profiling by police helps feed the system with new suspects, about 90 percent of whom plead guilty in preference to the risks and costs of a trial (Kerby 2013; Rakoff et al. 2014). Intergenerational poverty, unemployment, and undereducation contain people within this system, and the high rates of nonwhites in the prison population are used as official justification for racial profiling (Zack 2015, chap 2). Thus, <u>the complexity of causes and background factors associated with the disproportionate number of African American male prison inmates can be understood through a <strong>number of approaches</u></strong>. <u>The</u> <u><strong>normative approach of applicative justice</u></strong> <u>would be to address those causes or factors, <strong>distinctly and individually, <mark>through specific changes in concrete practice, as well as changes in law</mark>, as relevant</u></strong>.</p>
1NC
Case
1NC
9,336
337
81,830
./documents/ndtceda19/Kentucky/SaJa/Kentucky-Sanchez-Jamal-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
612,651
N
Navy
4
GMU ST
Ryan Wardak
1ac - frontier stc 1nc - t hege da 2nr - hege da
ndtceda19/Kentucky/SaJa/Kentucky-Sanchez-Jamal-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
null
51,906
SaJa
Kentucky SaJa
null
Ma.....
Sa.....
Su.....
Ja.....
19,265
Kentucky
Kentucky
null
null
1,009
ndtceda19
NDT/CEDA 2019-20
2,019
cx
college
2
3,488,397
Scientific consensus and empirics prove no impact to zoonosis- their ev is fear mongering
Orent 15
Orent 15 – Wendy Orent, anthropologist and freelance science writer whose work has appeared in The Washington Post, The LA Times, The New Republic, Discover, and The American Prospect, instructor in science journalism @ Emory, Ignore predictions of lethal pandemics and pay attention to what really matters, LA Times, 1/3/15, http://www.latimes.com/opinion/op-ed/la-oe-orent-pandemic-hysteria-20150104-story.html
Prophets of doom have been telling us for decades that a deadly new pandemic is on its way. Why are we still listening? Nature ran a special section titled — “Avian flu: Are we ready?” that began detailing catastrophic civil breakdown. hysteria still goes on: Whether it's over the MERS coronavirus flu viruses, a real but not very deadly influenza pandemic in 2009, or in 2012 over a scientist-crafted ferret flu that also was supposed to be a pandemic threat. Quammen warned in his gripping “Spillover” that some new animal plague could arise and sweep across the world. The scientific world has changed since 2005. Now, most scientists understand that there are significant physical and evolutionary barriers to a blood- and fluid-borne virus developing airborne transmission There probably will always be significant barriers preventing the easy adaptation of an animal disease to the human species. there are no recorded instances of viruses that have adapted to humans, changing the way they are spread. So we need to stop listening to the doomsayers, and we need to do it now. Predictions of lethal pandemics have since the swine flu fiasco of 1976 always been wrong. Fear-mongering wastes our time and our emotions and diverts resources from where they should be directed
Prophets of doom have been telling us for decades that a pandemic is on its way. hysteria goes on over MERS flu in 2009, or in 2012 over ferret flu Quammen warned some plague could arise most scientists understand there are significant physical and evolutionary barriers to a virus developing airborne transmission There will always be significant barriers preventing adaptation to human s there are no recorded instances of viruses that have adapted to humans Predictions of lethal pandemics have always been wrong.
Prophets of doom have been telling us for decades that a deadly new pandemic — of bird flu, of SARS or MERS coronavirus, and now of Ebola — is on its way. Why are we still listening? If you look back at the furor raised at many distinguished publications — Nature, Science, Scientific American, National Geographic — back in, say, 2005, about a potential bird flu (H5N1) pandemic, you wonder what planet they were on. Nature ran a special section titled — “Avian flu: Are we ready?” — that began, ominously, with the words “Trouble is brewing in the East” and went on to present a mock aftermath report detailing catastrophic civil breakdown. Robert Webster, a famous influenza virologist, told ABC News in 2006 that “society just can't accept the idea that 50% of the population could die. And I think we have to face that possibility.” Public health expert Michael T. Osterholm of the University of Minnesota, at a meeting in Washington of scientists brought together by the Institute of Medicine, warned in 2005 that a post-pandemic commission, like the post-9/11 commission, could hold “many scientists … accountable to that commission for what we did or didn't do to prevent a pandemic.” He also predicted that we could be facing “three years of a given hell” as the world struggled to right itself after the deadly pandemic. And Laurie Garrett, author of what must be the urtext for pandemic predictions, her 1994 book “The Coming Plague,” intoned in Foreign Affairs that “in short, doom may loom.” Although she followed that with “But note the may,” the article went on to paint a terrifying picture of the avian flu threat nonetheless. And such hysteria still goes on: Whether it's over the MERS coronavirus, a whole alphabet of chicken flu viruses, a real but not very deadly influenza pandemic in 2009, or a kerfuffle like the one in 2012 over a scientist-crafted ferret flu that also was supposed to be a pandemic threat. Along the way, virologist Nathan Wolfe published “The Viral Storm: the Dawn of a New Pandemic Age,” and David Quammen warned in his gripping “Spillover” that some new animal plague could arise from the jungle and sweep across the world. And now there's Ebola. Osterholm, in a widely read op-ed in the New York Times in September, wrote about the possibility that scientists were afraid to mention publicly the danger they discuss privately: that Ebola “could mutate to become transmissible through the air.” “The Ebola epidemic in West Africa has the potential to alter history as much as any plague has ever done,” he wrote. And Garrett wrote in Foreign Policy, “Attention, World: You just don't get it.” She went on to say, “Wake up, fools,” because we should be more frightened of a potential scenario like the one in the movie “Contagion,” in which a lethal, fictitious pandemic scours the world, nearly destroying civilization. But there were fewer takers this time. Osterholm's claims about Ebola going airborne were discounted by serious scientists, and Garrett seemingly retracted her earlier hysteria about Ebola by claiming that, after all, evolution made such spread unlikely. The scientific world has changed since 2005. Now, most scientists understand that there are significant physical and evolutionary barriers to a blood- and fluid-borne virus developing airborne transmission, as Garrett has acknowledged. Though Ebola virus has been detected in human alveolar cells, as Vincent Racaniello, virologist at Columbia University, explained to me, that doesn't mean it can replicate in the airways enough to allow transmission. “Maybe … the virus can get in, but can't get out. Like a roach motel,” wrote Racaniello in an email. H5N1, we understand now, never went airborne because it attached only to cell receptors located deep in human lungs, and could not, therefore, be coughed or sneezed out. SARS, or severe acute respiratory syndrome, caused local outbreaks after multiple introductions via air travel but spread only sluggishly and mostly in hospitals. Breaking its chains of transmission ended the outbreak globally. There probably will always be significant barriers preventing the easy adaptation of an animal disease to the human species. Furthermore, Racaniello insists that there are no recorded instances of viruses that have adapted to humans, changing the way they are spread. So we need to stop listening to the doomsayers, and we need to do it now. Predictions of lethal pandemics have — since the swine flu fiasco of 1976, when President Ford vowed to vaccinate “every man, woman and child in the United States” — always been wrong. Fear-mongering wastes our time and our emotions and diverts resources from where they should be directed — in the case of Ebola, to the ongoing tragedy in West Africa. Americans have all but forgotten about Ebola now, because most people realize it isn't coming to a school or a shopping mall near you. But Sierra Leoneans and Liberians go on dying.
4,949
<h4>Scientific consensus and empirics prove no impact to zoonosis- their ev is fear mongering</h4><p><strong>Orent 15</strong> – Wendy Orent, anthropologist and freelance science writer whose work has appeared in The Washington Post, The LA Times, The New Republic, Discover, and The American Prospect, instructor in science journalism @ Emory, Ignore predictions of lethal pandemics and pay attention to what really matters, LA Times, 1/3/15, http://www.latimes.com/opinion/op-ed/la-oe-orent-pandemic-hysteria-20150104-story.html</p><p><u><mark>Prophets of doom have been telling us for decades that a </mark>deadly new <mark>pandemic</u></mark> — of bird flu, of SARS or MERS coronavirus, and now of Ebola — <u><mark>is on its way. </mark>Why are we still listening?</u> If you look back at the furor raised at many distinguished publications — Nature, Science, Scientific American, National Geographic — back in, say, 2005, about a potential bird flu (H5N1) pandemic, you wonder what planet they were on. <u>Nature ran a</u> <u>special</u> <u>section titled — “Avian flu: Are we ready?”</u> — <u>that began</u>, ominously, with the words “Trouble is brewing in the East” and went on to present a mock aftermath report <u>detailing catastrophic civil breakdown.</u> Robert Webster, a famous influenza virologist, told ABC News in 2006 that “society just can't accept the idea that 50% of the population could die. And I think we have to face that possibility.” Public health expert Michael T. Osterholm of the University of Minnesota, at a meeting in Washington of scientists brought together by the Institute of Medicine, warned in 2005 that a post-pandemic commission, like the post-9/11 commission, could hold “many scientists … accountable to that commission for what we did or didn't do to prevent a pandemic.” He also predicted that we could be facing “three years of a given hell” as the world struggled to right itself after the deadly pandemic. And Laurie Garrett, author of what must be the urtext for pandemic predictions, her 1994 book “The Coming Plague,” intoned in Foreign Affairs that “in short, doom may loom.” Although she followed that with “But note the may,” the article went on to paint a terrifying picture of the avian flu threat nonetheless. And such <u><mark>hysteria</mark> still <mark>goes on</mark>: Whether it's <mark>over</mark> the <mark>MERS</mark> coronavirus</u>, a whole alphabet of chicken <u>flu viruses, a real but not very deadly in<mark>flu</mark>enza pandemic <mark>in 2009, or</u></mark> a kerfuffle like the one <u><mark>in 2012 over</mark> a scientist-crafted <mark>ferret flu</mark> that also was supposed to be a pandemic threat.</u> Along the way, virologist Nathan Wolfe published “The Viral Storm: the Dawn of a New Pandemic Age,” and David <u><strong><mark>Quammen warned</strong></mark> in his gripping “Spillover” that <mark>some</mark> new animal <mark>plague could arise</u></mark> from the jungle <u>and sweep across the world.</u> And now there's Ebola. Osterholm, in a widely read op-ed in the New York Times in September, wrote about the possibility that scientists were afraid to mention publicly the danger they discuss privately: that Ebola “could mutate to become transmissible through the air.” “The Ebola epidemic in West Africa has the potential to alter history as much as any plague has ever done,” he wrote. And Garrett wrote in Foreign Policy, “Attention, World: You just don't get it.” She went on to say, “Wake up, fools,” because we should be more frightened of a potential scenario like the one in the movie “Contagion,” in which a lethal, fictitious pandemic scours the world, nearly destroying civilization. But there were fewer takers this time. Osterholm's claims about Ebola going airborne were discounted by serious scientists, and Garrett seemingly retracted her earlier hysteria about Ebola by claiming that, after all, evolution made such spread unlikely. <u>The scientific world has changed since 2005. Now, <mark>most scientists understand</mark> that <mark>there are significant physical and evolutionary barriers to a</mark> blood- and fluid-borne <mark>virus developing airborne transmission</u></mark>, as Garrett has acknowledged. Though Ebola virus has been detected in human alveolar cells, as Vincent Racaniello, virologist at Columbia University, explained to me, that doesn't mean it can replicate in the airways enough to allow transmission. “Maybe … the virus can get in, but can't get out. Like a roach motel,” wrote Racaniello in an email. H5N1, we understand now, never went airborne because it attached only to cell receptors located deep in human lungs, and could not, therefore, be coughed or sneezed out. SARS, or severe acute respiratory syndrome, caused local outbreaks after multiple introductions via air travel but spread only sluggishly and mostly in hospitals. Breaking its chains of transmission ended the outbreak globally. <u><mark>There</mark> probably <mark>will always be significant barriers preventing</mark> the easy <mark>adaptation</mark> of an animal disease <mark>to </mark>the <mark>human s</mark>pecies.</u> Furthermore, Racaniello insists that <u><mark>there are no recorded instances of viruses that have adapted to humans</mark>, changing the way they are spread. So we need to stop listening to the doomsayers, and we need to do it now. <mark>Predictions of lethal pandemics have</u></mark> — <u>since the swine flu fiasco of 1976</u>, when President Ford vowed to vaccinate “every man, woman and child in the United States” — <u><mark>always been wrong.</u></mark> <u>Fear-mongering wastes our time and our emotions and diverts resources from where they should be directed </u>— in the case of Ebola, to the ongoing tragedy in West Africa. Americans have all but forgotten about Ebola now, because most people realize it isn't coming to a school or a shopping mall near you. But Sierra Leoneans and Liberians go on dying.</p>
Wake R6
disease
Zoonosis
138
304
115,908
./documents/ndtceda17/MichiganState/JoSe/Michigan%20State-Jones-Serrins-Neg-Wake-Round6.docx
598,803
N
Wake
6
Georgetown AL
Jacob Thompson
1AC - Telehealth 2NR - States and Elections
ndtceda17/MichiganState/JoSe/Michigan%20State-Jones-Serrins-Neg-Wake-Round6.docx
null
50,971
JoSe
Michigan State JoSe
null
Ev.....
Jo.....
Ez.....
Se.....
19,127
MichiganState
Michigan State
null
null
1,007
ndtceda17
NDT/CEDA 2017-18
2,017
cx
college
2
1,662,349
IR is reflexive and effective---its track record of prediction proves.
Reiter 15
Dan Reiter 15. Professor of Political Science at Emory University. “Scholars Help Policymakers Know Their Tools.” War on the Rocks. 8-27-2015. https://warontherocks.com/2015/08/scholars-help-policymakers-know-their-tools/
Context is important, but foreign policy choices are not sui generis, there are patterns across space and time that inform decision-making broader scholarship can improve foreign policy performance, as evidenced by the ability of IR academics to build on their own work to predict outcomes, including for example forecasting the lengths of the conventional and insurgency phases of the U.S.–Iraq conflict in the 2000s there is a danger in not appreciating the importance of rigorous research design, including sophisticated quantitative techniques, for crafting effective policy Sophisticated research design is not the enemy of effective policy, it is critically necessary for it the current academic focus on building research designs that permit causal inference speaks exactly to what policymakers care about the most: if implementing a certain policy will cause the desired outcome bad research designs make for bad public policy A classic example is school busing In the 60s and 70s some cities adopted voluntary integration programs for public schools Policymakers used the favorable results for the voluntary programs to make the improper inference that mandatory busing policies would also work The result was bad public policy and violence Sophisticated technical methods can improve our ability to make causal inferences, and solve empirical problems Assessing whether certain policies do win public support requires collecting opinion data Methodologists have crafted sophisticated techniques for addressing this issue, improving our ability to measure public support for the government in these areas Going forward, we will continue to need advanced methodologies to address pressing policy questions Certainly, other areas of public policy understand the importance of rigorous research design Economic and development policy communities read the work of and employ economics Ph.D.s. Policymakers incorporate the findings of sophisticated studies on policy areas such as microfinance, gender empowerment, and foreign aid, knowing the best policy decisions must incorporate these studies’ findings Lives are literally on the line as decision-makers must make decisions about issues such as vaccinations, nutritional recommendations, and air quality Policymakers know they must use sophisticated technical studies executed by epidemiologists and other public health academics to craft the best policies the technical components of the work need to be there Stripping them out directly undermines the ability of the research to give the right kinds of policy recommendations IR academics have the potential to make real contributions to big picture debates The nature of the IR subfield and its integration of political economy and security, and its ability to think about structure as well as units, make it especially well positioned to consider these broad questions political science should retain IR and resist the temptation to replace the traditional empirical subfields with new subfields of conflict, political economy, behavior, and institutions foreign policymakers need to know their tools Rigorous IR research is the only way to evaluate them effectively
choices are not sui generis patterns inform decision-making broader scholarship improve policy performance evidenced by the ability of academics to build on work to predict outcomes forecasting lengths of insurgency there is danger in not appreciating the importance of rigorous research design quantitative techniques, for crafting policy is critically necessary bad research make for bad policy technical methods improve causal inferences, and solve empirical problems Policymakers incorporate findings of microfinance, gender empowerment, and foreign aid Lives are on the line decisions about vaccinations, nutritional recommendations, and air quality technical components need to be there Stripping them out directly undermines right recommendations academics have potential to make real contributions to debates IR research is the only way to evaluate effectively
This critique is both narrowly true and narrow in perspective. Context is of course important, but foreign policy choices are not sui generis, there are patterns across space and time that inform decision-making. Policymakers recognize this and routinely draw lessons from history when making foreign policy decisions. As noted below, policymakers in other areas such as development and public health routinely rely on broader, more general studies to craft policy. And, broader scholarship can improve foreign policy performance, as evidenced by the ability of IR academics to build on their own work to predict outcomes, including for example forecasting the lengths of the conventional and insurgency phases of the U.S.–Iraq conflict in the 2000s. But, even if one were to accept the limits of general work, there is a growing body of academic work that evaluates foreign policy tools as applied to a specific country or region. These studies ask questions such as whether: Development projects reduced insurgent violence in Afghanistan; Drone strikes reduced insurgent violence in Pakistan; Development programs increased civic participation and social capital in Sudan; Building cell phone towers in Iraq reduced insurgent violence; Attempts to reintegrate combatants into society in Burundi succeeded; Security sector reform in Liberia increased the legitimacy of the government there; Road projects in India reduced insurgent violence; We can understand peacekeeping’s failure in Congo; Israel’s targeted assassinations reduced violent attacks from militants. This is not by any means a dismissal of professional intelligence work. Academics are not intelligence analysts: They do not have access to contemporary intelligence data, nor are they generally trained to do things like examine the latest satellite photos of North Korean nuclear activities and make judgments about North Korea’s current plutonium production. And certainly, academic IR work can never replace professional intelligence work. But the best policy decisions marry timely, specific intelligence with academic work that has a more general perspective. A third critique is that much of this academic work on foreign policy tools is unusable by policymakers because it is too quantitative and technically complex. Here, echoing a point made by Erik Voeten, there is a danger in not appreciating the importance of rigorous research design, including sophisticated quantitative techniques, for crafting effective policy. Sophisticated research design is not the enemy of effective policy, it is critically necessary for it. Certainly, the current academic focus on building research designs that permit causal inference speaks exactly to what policymakers care about the most: if implementing a certain policy will cause the desired outcome. Or, put differently, bad research designs make for bad public policy. A classic example is school busing. In the 1960s and early 1970s, some cities adopted voluntary integration programs for public schools, in which families could volunteer to bus their children to schools in neighborhoods with different racial majorities. Policymakers used the favorable results for the voluntary programs to make the improper inference that mandatory busing policies would also work. The result was bad public policy and violence in the streets. Sophisticated technical methods can improve our ability to make causal inferences, and can help solve other empirical problems. Consider that the heart of successful counterinsurgency is, according to U.S. military doctrine, winning the support of the population. Assessing whether certain policies do win public support requires collecting opinion data. A conventional method for measuring popular opinion is the survey, but of course, individuals in insurgency-stricken areas may be unwilling to reveal their true opinions to a survey-taker out of fear for their personal safety. Methodologists have crafted sophisticated techniques for addressing this issue, improving our ability to measure public support for the government in these areas. These techniques have been used to assess better the determinants of public support in insurgency-affected countries such as Pakistan, Afghanistan, and India. Going forward, we will continue to need advanced methodologies to address pressing policy questions. Consider the U.S. military’s commitment to gender integration. The implementation of this commitment will be best informed if it rests on rigorous social science that address outstanding questions. Is there a Sacagawea effect, in which mixed gender units engaged in counterinsurgency are more effective than male-only units? How might mixed gender affect small unit cohesion in combat? How might mixed gender units reduce the incidence of sexual assault, both within the military and of assault committed by troops against civilians? Certainly, other areas of public policy understand the importance of rigorous research design. Economic and development policy communities read the work of and employ economics Ph.D.s. Policymakers incorporate the findings of sophisticated studies on policy areas such as microfinance, gender empowerment, and foreign aid, knowing the best policy decisions must incorporate these studies’ findings. Or consider public health policy. Lives are literally on the line as decision-makers must make decisions about issues such as vaccinations, nutritional recommendations, and air quality. Policymakers know they must use sophisticated technical studies executed by epidemiologists and other public health academics to craft the best policies. Critics will argue that some U.S. policymakers remain alienated from contemporary academic IR work, with the suggestion that if IR academics let go of an obsession with technique, they will then be better able to connect with policymakers and help them craft better policy. I agree that IR academics need to find ways to communicate their results in clear, non-technical language. But the technical components of the work need to be there. Stripping them out directly undermines the ability of the research to give the right kinds of policy recommendations. Let me conclude by noting that I am sympathetic to the concern that IR academics should think about the big picture as well as smaller questions, the forest of grand strategy as well as the trees of foreign policy tools. IR academics have the potential to make real contributions to big picture debates, to think hard about the essence of grand strategy by assembling a framework that effectively integrates foreign policy means and ends. The nature of the IR subfield and its integration of political economy and security, and its ability to think about structure as well as units, make it especially well positioned to consider these broad questions. The ability of IR academics to contribute to contemporary foreign policy debates is one of many reasons why political science should retain the subfield of IR and resist the temptation to replace the traditional empirical subfields of IR, comparative, and American with new subfields of conflict, political economy, behavior, and institutions. Like good carpenters, foreign policymakers need to know their tools. Rigorous IR research is the only way to evaluate them effectively.
7,319
<h4>IR is <u>reflexive</u> and <u>effective</u>---its <u>track record</u> of <u>prediction</u> proves.</h4><p>Dan<strong> Reiter 15</strong>. Professor of Political Science at Emory University. “Scholars Help Policymakers Know Their Tools.” War on the Rocks. 8-27-2015. https://warontherocks.com/2015/08/scholars-help-policymakers-know-their-tools/</p><p>This critique is both narrowly true and narrow in perspective. <u>Context is</u> of course <u>important, but foreign <strong>policy <mark>choices</strong> are <strong>not sui generis</strong></mark>, there are <mark>patterns</mark> across space and time that <strong><mark>inform decision-making</u></strong></mark>. Policymakers recognize this and routinely draw lessons from history when making foreign policy decisions. As noted below, policymakers in other areas such as development and public health routinely rely on broader, more general studies to craft policy. And, <u><strong><mark>broader scholarship</strong></mark> can <strong><mark>improve</strong></mark> foreign <mark>policy performance</mark>, as <mark>evidenced by the ability of</mark> <strong>IR <mark>academics</strong> to build on</mark> their own <mark>work to <strong>predict outcomes</strong></mark>, including for example <strong><mark>forecasting</strong></mark> the <mark>lengths of</mark> the conventional and <mark>insurgency</mark> phases of the U.S.–Iraq conflict in the 2000s</u>.</p><p>But, even if one were to accept the limits of general work, there is a growing body of academic work that evaluates foreign policy tools as applied to a specific country or region. These studies ask questions such as whether:</p><p>Development projects reduced insurgent violence in Afghanistan; Drone strikes reduced insurgent violence in Pakistan; Development programs increased civic participation and social capital in Sudan; Building cell phone towers in Iraq reduced insurgent violence; Attempts to reintegrate combatants into society in Burundi succeeded; Security sector reform in Liberia increased the legitimacy of the government there; Road projects in India reduced insurgent violence; We can understand peacekeeping’s failure in Congo; Israel’s targeted assassinations reduced violent attacks from militants.</p><p>This is not by any means a dismissal of professional intelligence work. Academics are not intelligence analysts: They do not have access to contemporary intelligence data, nor are they generally trained to do things like examine the latest satellite photos of North Korean nuclear activities and make judgments about North Korea’s current plutonium production. And certainly, academic IR work can never replace professional intelligence work. But the best policy decisions marry timely, specific intelligence with academic work that has a more general perspective.</p><p>A third critique is that much of this academic work on foreign policy tools is unusable by policymakers because it is too quantitative and technically complex. Here, echoing a point made by Erik Voeten, <u><mark>there is</mark> a <strong><mark>danger</strong> in <strong>not appreciating</strong> the <strong>importance</strong> of <strong>rigorous research design</strong></mark>, including sophisticated <strong><mark>quantitative techniques</strong>, for <strong>crafting</mark> effective <mark>policy</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong>Sophisticated research design</strong> is not the enemy of effective policy, it <mark>is <strong>critically necessary</strong></mark> for it</u>. Certainly, <u>the current academic focus on building research designs that permit causal inference speaks exactly to what policymakers care about the most: if implementing a certain policy will cause the desired outcome</u>.</p><p>Or, put differently, <u><strong><mark>bad research</strong></mark> designs <mark>make for <strong>bad</mark> public <mark>policy</u></strong></mark>. <u>A classic example is school busing</u>. <u>In the</u> 19<u>60s</u> <u>and</u> early 19<u>70s</u>, <u>some cities adopted voluntary integration programs for public schools</u>, in which families could volunteer to bus their children to schools in neighborhoods with different racial majorities. <u>Policymakers used the favorable results for the voluntary programs to make the improper inference that mandatory busing policies would also work</u>. <u>The result was bad public policy and violence</u> in the streets.</p><p><u>Sophisticated <strong><mark>technical methods</strong></mark> can <mark>improve</mark> our ability to make <strong><mark>causal inferences</strong>, and</u></mark> can help <u><mark>solve</u></mark> other <u><strong><mark>empirical problems</u></strong></mark>. Consider that the heart of successful counterinsurgency is, according to U.S. military doctrine, winning the support of the population. <u>Assessing whether certain policies do win public support requires collecting opinion data</u>. A conventional method for measuring popular opinion is the survey, but of course, individuals in insurgency-stricken areas may be unwilling to reveal their true opinions to a survey-taker out of fear for their personal safety. <u>Methodologists have crafted sophisticated techniques for addressing this issue, improving our ability to measure public support for the government in these areas</u>. These techniques have been used to assess better the determinants of public support in insurgency-affected countries such as Pakistan, Afghanistan, and India.</p><p><u>Going forward, we will continue to need advanced methodologies to address pressing policy questions</u>. Consider the U.S. military’s commitment to gender integration. The implementation of this commitment will be best informed if it rests on rigorous social science that address outstanding questions. Is there a Sacagawea effect, in which mixed gender units engaged in counterinsurgency are more effective than male-only units? How might mixed gender affect small unit cohesion in combat? How might mixed gender units reduce the incidence of sexual assault, both within the military and of assault committed by troops against civilians?</p><p><u>Certainly, <strong>other areas</strong> of public policy understand the importance of rigorous research design</u>. <u>Economic and development policy communities read the work of and employ economics Ph.D.s.</u> <u><mark>Policymakers incorporate</mark> the <mark>findings of</mark> sophisticated studies on policy areas such as <strong><mark>microfinance</strong>, <strong>gender empowerment</strong>, and <strong>foreign aid</strong></mark>, knowing the best policy decisions must incorporate these studies’ findings</u>.</p><p>Or consider public health policy. <u><strong><mark>Lives are</mark> literally <mark>on the line</strong></mark> as decision-makers must make <mark>decisions about</mark> issues such as <strong><mark>vaccinations</strong>, <strong>nutritional recommendations</strong>, and <strong>air quality</u></strong></mark>. <u>Policymakers know they must use sophisticated technical studies executed by epidemiologists and other public health academics to craft the best policies</u>.</p><p>Critics will argue that some U.S. policymakers remain alienated from contemporary academic IR work, with the suggestion that if IR academics let go of an obsession with technique, they will then be better able to connect with policymakers and help them craft better policy. I agree that IR academics need to find ways to communicate their results in clear, non-technical language. But <u>the <strong><mark>technical components</strong></mark> of the work <strong><mark>need to be there</u></strong></mark>. <u><mark>Stripping them out <strong>directly undermines</strong></mark> the ability of the research to give the <strong><mark>right</strong></mark> kinds of policy <strong><mark>recommendations</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>Let me conclude by noting that I am sympathetic to the concern that IR academics should think about the big picture as well as smaller questions, the forest of grand strategy as well as the trees of foreign policy tools. <u><strong>IR <mark>academics</strong> have</mark> the <mark>potential to <strong>make real contributions</strong> to</mark> big picture <strong><mark>debates</u></strong></mark>, to think hard about the essence of grand strategy by assembling a framework that effectively integrates foreign policy means and ends. <u>The nature of the IR subfield and its integration of political economy and security, and its ability to think about structure as well as units, make it especially well positioned to consider these broad questions</u>. The ability of IR academics to contribute to contemporary foreign policy debates is one of many reasons why <u>political science should retain</u> the subfield of <u>IR and resist the temptation to replace the traditional empirical subfields</u> of IR, comparative, and American <u>with new subfields of conflict, political economy, behavior, and institutions</u>.</p><p>Like good carpenters, <u>foreign policymakers need to know their tools</u>. <u><strong>Rigorous <mark>IR research</strong> is the <strong>only way to evaluate</mark> them <mark>effectively</u></strong></mark>.</p>
2AC
K
AT: Matsuoka 18---2AC
2,170
431
49,612
./documents/ndtceda20/Emory/PaRa/Emory-Pak-Rajagopal-Aff-5%20-%20Fullerton-Georgetown-Round6.docx
617,289
A
5 - Fullerton-Georgetown
6
NYU ST
Brent Lamb
1AC - Heg 1NC - T Russia DA K 2NR - Russia DA
ndtceda20/Emory/PaRa/Emory-Pak-Rajagopal-Aff-5%20-%20Fullerton-Georgetown-Round6.docx
null
52,225
PaRa
Emory PaRa
null
An.....
Pa.....
Sh.....
Ra.....
19,313
Emory
Emory
null
null
1,010
ndtceda20
NDT/CEDA 2020-21
2,020
cx
college
2
1,518,357
Japan will develop offensive strike---nuclear war
Wadsworth 19
Kelly C. Wadsworth 19, Non-Resident Kelly Fellow at Pacific Forum at the Center for Strategic & International Studies, PhD Student in International Security Studies at the University of Pittsburgh, MBA and MA in International Studies (Korea Studies) at the University of Washington, Former Visiting Fellow at the Japan Institute of International Affairs, BA in International Relations and East Asia from the University of California, Davis, “Should Japan Adopt Conventional Missile Strike Capabilities?”, Asia Policy, Volume 14, Number 2, April 2019, p. 83-87
the long-term interests in maintaining regional stability should be considered. In addition to the negative reactions of Beijing and Seoul, a Japanese offensive strike capability could decrease regional confidence in the credibility of U.S. power in Asia if Japan strengthens its offensive capability, such a move might be interpreted by neighbors reliant on the U.S. nuclear umbrella as a sign that Tokyo is losing confidence in the U S credibility This could start a chain reaction that causes more U.S. allies to hedge with China or to develop their own strike capabilities, further increasing instability in Asia China would offer harsh actions that could further decrease regional stability in an already tense security environment the regional environment is even more tense as a result of North Korea’s acquisition of nuclear weapons and China’s island reclamation efforts in the E and S C S Tokyo’s armament would likely end any chance of dialogue between Washington and Beijing on facilitating peaceful resolutions to regional territorial disputes the ensuing heightened mistrust between the alliance partners and China may increase the likelihood of a gray-zone conflict escalating into war if Japan had a conventional missile strike capability Beijing would in turn be more likely to consider preemption of Japanese strike abilities, causing a premature escalation of the crisis that would undoubtedly draw in the United States Japan-ROK military relations remain increasingly tense, a situation that could easily spiral out of control if Japan adopted an offensive capability If Tokyo were to push forward South Korean public opinion would become even more unfavorable At a time when enhanced trilateral cooperation is important to deter the evolving threats in the region, Japan advancing legislation to allow for conventional missile strike capabilities would likely derail those efforts Such a move could even push Seoul to hedge with Beijing Countries in Southeast Asia are watching Trump closely and hedging accordingly Vietnam and the Philippines are increasing their own arsenal as a result of Washington’s “slow erosion of credibility” if Japan were to pursue an offensive defense strategy, the Southeast Asian countries could see this as a sign of Tokyo’s loss of faith in the U S willingness to uphold its defense commitments Declining credibility and corresponding hedging—through either growing armament or alignment with China—could not only further increase tensions and heighten the risk of a gray-zone escalation but also lead to greater Chinese military assertiveness and dominance in the region Japan’s development of an independent conventional missile strike capability could undermine regional stability and U.S. credibility A strike-capable Japan might not only escalate an already tense regional standoff with China but also elicit a harsh response from other countries against Tokyo and Washington. It could erode the credibility of the U.S. nuclear umbrella, potentially leading to increased militarization throughout Asia If the environment surrounding any of these three arguments changes—for example, if the U S actions discredit its reliability to protect Japan under the alliance Japan would have a strong argument to move forward with conventional missile strike capabilities even the discussion of Tokyo acquiring conventional missile strike capabilities could ultimately worsen the regional security environment rather than improve it
Japanese strike could decrease confidence in U.S. power interpreted as a sign Tokyo is losing confidence This start a chain reaction increasing instability the environment is tense as a result of Korea’s nuclear weapons and island reclamation in E and S C S armament would end dialogue on territorial disputes heightened mistrust increase gray-zone conflict escalating into war Beijing would preempt Japan causing escalation that draw in the U S Japan-ROK relations spiral trilateral coop is important Japan strike derail efforts countries see this as a loss of faith Declining cred and hedging increase tensions heighten risk of escalation also lead to Chinese assertiveness If the environment changes if U S actions discredit its reliability under the alliance Japan would move forward with conventional strike even discussion worsen security
American proponents of Japan obtaining a conventional missile strike capability interviewed for this research argued that the United States could use a more capable ally in the region to address the threat posed by heightened Chinese naval activity. While that prospect might be a tempting short-term fix to offset the U.S. Department of Defense budget cuts over the last decade, the long-term interests of the United States in maintaining regional stability should also be considered. In addition to the negative reactions of Beijing and Seoul, a Japanese offensive strike capability could decrease regional confidence in the credibility of U.S. power in Asia. As noted above, some experts argue that if Japan strengthens its offensive capability, such a move might be interpreted by neighbors reliant on the U.S. nuclear umbrella as a sign that Tokyo is losing confidence in the United States’ credibility.71 This could start a chain reaction that causes more U.S. allies to hedge with China or to develop their own strike capabilities, further increasing instability in Asia. China. China would likely be the most vocal in its disapproval of a Japanese conventional missile strike capability, potentially offering not just harsh words but also harsh actions that could further decrease regional stability in an already tense security environment. China expressed dissent when Japan considered a preemptive strike option against the North Korean threat in 2006, arguing that the move was “extremely irresponsible” and would severely interfere with international diplomatic efforts, aggravating tensions in Northeast Asia.72 Over ten years later, the regional environment is even more tense as a result of North Korea’s acquisition of nuclear weapons and China’s island reclamation efforts in the East and South China Seas. Support from Washington for Tokyo’s armament would likely fuel Beijing’s narrative that an aggressive and hegemonic United States is fixated on containing China and would be used to justify China’s own increased militarization. It would likely also end any chance of dialogue between Washington and Beijing on facilitating peaceful resolutions to regional territorial disputes. Brad Roberts points out that adopting strike capability would assist Japan in cases where its interests do not align with those of the United States, as in potential gray-zone conflicts. 73 However, the ensuing heightened mistrust between the alliance partners and China may work to increase the likelihood of a gray-zone conflict—such as the 2010 collision of Japanese and Chinese boats in disputed territory—possibly escalating into war. In addition, if Japan had a conventional missile strike capability that could be used to “preempt” a perceived imminent attack from China, Beijing would in turn be more likely to consider preemption of Japanese strike abilities, causing a premature escalation of the crisis that would undoubtedly draw in the United States. South Korea. Despite significant progress on U.S.-ROK-Japan trilateral security cooperation in recent years, Japan-ROK military relations remain increasingly tense, a situation that could easily spiral out of control if Japan adopted an offensive capability.74 When Japan, sparked by North Korea’s provocations in 2006, publicly debated the legality of a “preemptive strike” option, South Korean officials bluntly expressed their negative opinion of Japan’s intentions. A spokesperson for the Blue House secretariat, for example, remarked, “We have been alerted by this display of Japan’s inclination to aggression,” and that Japan was using the crisis “as an excuse to beef up their military.”75 South Koreans demonstrated a similar sentiment after Tokyo’s 2014 CSD proposal, with a 2015 poll showing that the majority of the public (56.9%) perceived Japan as “militaristic,” up 3.8 percentage points from the previous year.76 If Tokyo were to push forward with the discussion of adopting a conventional missile strike capability, South Korean public opinion would likely become even more unfavorable toward Japan. At a time when enhanced trilateral cooperation is important to deter the evolving threats in the region, Japan advancing legislation to allow for conventional missile strike capabilities would likely derail those efforts, especially if labeled “preemptive.” Such a move could even push Seoul to hedge with Beijing, as the ROK is increasingly reluctant to join any initiative perceived to be aimed at containing China.77 With China as South Korea’s largest trading partner and the United States as its greatest security ally, the ROK is not eager to choose between the two sides. Southeast Asia. Countries in Southeast Asia are watching the Trump administration closely to see where Washington will draw the line on China’s military rise and growing regional assertiveness, and many are already hedging accordingly. For example, countries such as Vietnam and the Philippines are increasing their own conventional arsenal and naval capabilities as a result of Washington’s “slow erosion of credibility” in the region during the Obama administration.78 Defense of Japan 2018 seems to have confidence in the Trump administration’s commitment to maintaining a powerful presence in Asia.79 However, as discussed earlier, if Japan were to pursue an offensive defense strategy, the Southeast Asian countries could see this as a sign of Tokyo’s loss of faith in the United States’ willingness to uphold its defense commitments. China’s seizure of the Scarborough Shoal from the Philippines in 2012 has already eroded these countries’ confidence in the U.S. security guarantee to some extent.80 Declining credibility and corresponding hedging—through either growing armament or alignment with China—could not only further increase tensions and heighten the risk of a gray-zone escalation but also lead to greater Chinese military assertiveness and dominance in the region. Summary Despite the seemingly unbalanced nature of the U.S.-Japan alliance, the argument for “balancing” the alliance with Japan’s development of an independent conventional missile strike capability does not take into account important repercussions that could undermine both regional stability and U.S. credibility. In addition, updated Japanese defense guidelines, such as CSD, already give Japan a “greater role” in global security. Unless future U.S. administrations drastically reduce the U.S. military presence in Asia, the benefit of a more equal alliance would not outweigh the potential costs of Japan’s adoption of a conventional missile strike capability. CONCLUSION The arguments supporting Japan’s acquisition of a conventional missile strike capability do not hold weight in the current regional, economic, and alliance environments. The development of such a capability is not a practical solution for Japan to abate the threat from the DPRK, and the move could be perceived by China and South Korea as facilitating a U.S. strategy of containment. Traditional restrictions on the Japanese defense budget would not practically allow the buildup of the military capabilities required for a conventional missile strike force, a restriction that cannot be changed without support from a military-wary public. At first glance, a “normal” Japan that is capable of contributing to U.S. deterrence efforts might seem appealing from an alliance perspective, especially after the 2010 U.S. defense budget cuts, and an increasingly threatening regional security environment. Yet, though the U.S.-Japan alliance may be unbalanced in terms of capabilities, the United States has broader interests in regional stability that will be better promoted if Japan maintains a purely defensive force. A strike-capable Japan might not only escalate an already tense regional standoff with China but also elicit a harsh response from other countries against Tokyo and Washington. It could also erode the credibility of the U.S. nuclear umbrella, potentially leading to increased militarization throughout Asia. If the environment surrounding any of these three arguments changes—for example, if the United States’ actions discredit its reliability to protect Japan under the alliance, if Japanese public support allows an increase in the JSDF’s budget, or if the United States can no longer maintain a credible military deterrence in Asia—Japan would have a strong argument to move forward with conventional missile strike capabilities. In that case, both parties should exercise prudence in their public communications of planned alliance cooperation on the matter and about how or why the alliance would choose to employ such abilities. Hawkish suggestions of the potential to increase U.S. dominance in the region should be avoided.81 China is rightfully wary of any reference to conventional prompt global strike. Such rhetoric coming from Japan or the United States combined with the decision to move forward on conventional missile strike capabilities could be considered a threatening signal by Beijing.82 Without calculated prudence in regional dialogues, even the discussion of Tokyo acquiring conventional missile strike capabilities could ultimately worsen the regional security environment rather than improve it.
9,264
<h4>Japan will develop <u>offensive strike</u>---nuclear war</h4><p>Kelly C. <strong>Wadsworth 19</strong>, Non-Resident Kelly Fellow at Pacific Forum at the Center for Strategic & International Studies, PhD Student in International Security Studies at the University of Pittsburgh, MBA and MA in International Studies (Korea Studies) at the University of Washington, Former Visiting Fellow at the Japan Institute of International Affairs, BA in International Relations and East Asia from the University of California, Davis, “Should Japan Adopt Conventional Missile Strike Capabilities?”, Asia Policy, Volume 14, Number 2, April 2019, p. 83-87</p><p>American proponents of Japan obtaining a conventional missile strike capability interviewed for this research argued that the United States could use a more capable ally in the region to address the threat posed by heightened Chinese naval activity. While that prospect might be a tempting short-term fix to offset the U.S. Department of Defense budget cuts over the last decade, <u>the long-term interests</u> of the United States <u>in maintaining regional stability should</u> also <u>be considered. In addition to the negative reactions of Beijing and Seoul, a <mark>Japanese</mark> offensive <mark>strike</mark> capability <mark>could <strong>decrease</mark> regional <mark>confidence</strong> in</mark> the <strong>credibility of <mark>U.S. power</strong></mark> in Asia</u>. As noted above, some experts argue that <u>if Japan strengthens its offensive capability, such a move might be <strong><mark>interpreted</strong></mark> by neighbors reliant on the U.S. nuclear umbrella <mark>as a <strong>sign</strong></mark> that <mark>Tokyo is <strong>losing confidence</strong></mark> in the <strong>U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates’ <u>credibility</u>.71 <u><mark>This</mark> could <strong><mark>start a chain reaction</strong></mark> that causes more U.S. allies to <strong>hedge</strong> with China or to <strong>develop their own strike capabilities</strong>, further <strong><mark>increasing instability</strong></mark> in Asia</u>. China. <u>China would</u> likely be the most vocal in its disapproval of a Japanese conventional missile strike capability, potentially <u>offer</u>ing not just harsh words but also <u>harsh actions that could further <strong>decrease regional stability</strong> in an <strong>already tense</strong> security environment</u>. China expressed dissent when Japan considered a preemptive strike option against the North Korean threat in 2006, arguing that the move was “extremely irresponsible” and would severely interfere with international diplomatic efforts, aggravating tensions in Northeast Asia.72 Over ten years later, <u><mark>the</mark> regional <mark>environment is</mark> <strong>even more <mark>tense</strong> as a result of</mark> North <mark>Korea’s</mark> acquisition of <strong><mark>nuclear weapons</strong> and</mark> China’s <strong><mark>island reclamation</strong></mark> efforts <mark>in</mark> the <strong><mark>E</u></strong></mark>ast <u><mark>and <strong>S</u></strong></mark>outh <u><strong><mark>C</u></strong></mark>hina <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>eas. Support from Washington for <u>Tokyo’s <mark>armament</u></mark> would likely fuel Beijing’s narrative that an aggressive and hegemonic United States is fixated on containing China and would be used to justify China’s own increased militarization. It <u><mark>would</mark> likely</u> also <u><mark>end</mark> any chance of <mark>dialogue</mark> between Washington and Beijing <mark>on</mark> facilitating peaceful resolutions to regional <strong><mark>territorial disputes</u></strong></mark>. Brad Roberts points out that adopting strike capability would assist Japan in cases where its interests do not align with those of the United States, as in potential gray-zone conflicts. 73 However, <u>the ensuing <mark>heightened mistrust</mark> between the alliance partners and China may</u> work to <u><mark>increase</mark> the likelihood of a <strong><mark>gray-zone conflict</u></strong></mark>—such as the 2010 collision of Japanese and Chinese boats in disputed territory—possibly <u><strong><mark>escalating</strong> into <strong>war</u></strong></mark>. In addition, <u>if Japan had a conventional missile strike capability</u> that could be used to “preempt” a perceived imminent attack from China, <u><mark>Beijing would</mark> in turn be more likely to consider <mark>preempt</mark>ion of <mark>Japan</mark>ese strike abilities, <mark>causing</mark> a <strong>premature <mark>escalation</strong></mark> of the crisis <mark>that</mark> would undoubtedly <strong><mark>draw in the U</mark>nited <mark>S</mark>tates</u></strong>. South Korea. Despite significant progress on U.S.-ROK-Japan trilateral security cooperation in recent years, <u><mark>Japan-ROK</mark> military <mark>relations</mark> remain increasingly tense, a situation that could <strong>easily <mark>spiral</mark> out of control</strong> if Japan adopted an offensive capability</u>.74 When Japan, sparked by North Korea’s provocations in 2006, publicly debated the legality of a “preemptive strike” option, South Korean officials bluntly expressed their negative opinion of Japan’s intentions. A spokesperson for the Blue House secretariat, for example, remarked, “We have been alerted by this display of Japan’s inclination to aggression,” and that Japan was using the crisis “as an excuse to beef up their military.”75 South Koreans demonstrated a similar sentiment after Tokyo’s 2014 CSD proposal, with a 2015 poll showing that the majority of the public (56.9%) perceived Japan as “militaristic,” up 3.8 percentage points from the previous year.76 <u>If Tokyo were to push forward</u> with the discussion of adopting a conventional missile strike capability, <u>South Korean public opinion would</u> likely <u>become even more unfavorable</u> toward Japan. <u>At a time when enhanced <mark>trilateral <strong>coop</strong></mark>eration <mark>is <strong>important</mark> to deter the evolving threats</strong> in the region, <mark>Japan</mark> advancing legislation to allow for conventional missile <mark>strike</mark> capabilities would likely <strong><mark>derail</mark> those <mark>efforts</u></strong></mark>, especially if labeled “preemptive.” <u>Such a move could even push Seoul to <strong>hedge</strong> with Beijing</u>, as the ROK is increasingly reluctant to join any initiative perceived to be aimed at containing China.77 With China as South Korea’s largest trading partner and the United States as its greatest security ally, the ROK is not eager to choose between the two sides. Southeast Asia. <u>Countries in Southeast Asia are watching</u> the <u>Trump</u> administration <u>closely</u> to see where Washington will draw the line on China’s military rise and growing regional assertiveness, <u>and</u> many are already <u>hedging accordingly</u>. For example, countries such as <u>Vietnam and the Philippines are increasing their own</u> conventional <u>arsenal</u> and naval capabilities <u>as a result of Washington’s “slow erosion of credibility”</u> in the region during the Obama administration.78 Defense of Japan 2018 seems to have confidence in the Trump administration’s commitment to maintaining a powerful presence in Asia.79 However, as discussed earlier, <u>if Japan were to pursue an offensive defense strategy, the Southeast Asian <mark>countries</mark> could <mark>see this as a</mark> sign of Tokyo’s <mark>loss of faith</mark> in the <strong>U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates’ <u>willingness to uphold its defense commitments</u>. China’s seizure of the Scarborough Shoal from the Philippines in 2012 has already eroded these countries’ confidence in the U.S. security guarantee to some extent.80 <u><mark>Declining cred</mark>ibility <mark>and</mark> corresponding <mark>hedging</mark>—through either growing armament or alignment with China—could not only further <strong><mark>increase tensions</strong></mark> and <strong><mark>heighten</mark> the <mark>risk of</mark> a gray-zone <mark>escalation</strong></mark> but <mark>also <strong>lead to</mark> greater <mark>Chinese</mark> military <mark>assertiveness</mark> and dominance</strong> in the region</u>. Summary Despite the seemingly unbalanced nature of the U.S.-Japan alliance, the argument for “balancing” the alliance with <u>Japan’s development of an independent conventional missile strike capability</u> does not take into account important repercussions that <u>could <strong>undermine</u></strong> both <u><strong>regional stability and U.S. credibility</u></strong>. In addition, updated Japanese defense guidelines, such as CSD, already give Japan a “greater role” in global security. Unless future U.S. administrations drastically reduce the U.S. military presence in Asia, the benefit of a more equal alliance would not outweigh the potential costs of Japan’s adoption of a conventional missile strike capability. CONCLUSION The arguments supporting Japan’s acquisition of a conventional missile strike capability do not hold weight in the current regional, economic, and alliance environments. The development of such a capability is not a practical solution for Japan to abate the threat from the DPRK, and the move could be perceived by China and South Korea as facilitating a U.S. strategy of containment. Traditional restrictions on the Japanese defense budget would not practically allow the buildup of the military capabilities required for a conventional missile strike force, a restriction that cannot be changed without support from a military-wary public. At first glance, a “normal” Japan that is capable of contributing to U.S. deterrence efforts might seem appealing from an alliance perspective, especially after the 2010 U.S. defense budget cuts, and an increasingly threatening regional security environment. Yet, though the U.S.-Japan alliance may be unbalanced in terms of capabilities, the United States has broader interests in regional stability that will be better promoted if Japan maintains a purely defensive force. <u>A strike-capable Japan might not only escalate an already tense regional standoff with China but also elicit a harsh response from other countries against Tokyo and Washington. It could</u> also <u>erode the credibility of the U.S. nuclear umbrella, potentially leading to <strong>increased militarization throughout Asia</u></strong>. <u><mark>If the <strong>environment</strong></mark> surrounding any of these three arguments <strong><mark>changes</strong></mark>—for example, <mark>if</mark> the <strong><mark>U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates’ <u><mark>actions <strong>discredit its reliability</strong></mark> to protect Japan <mark>under the alliance</u></mark>, if Japanese public support allows an increase in the JSDF’s budget, or if the United States can no longer maintain a credible military deterrence in Asia—<u><strong><mark>Japan would</mark> have a strong argument to <mark>move forward</strong> with conventional</mark> missile <mark>strike</mark> capabilities</u>. In that case, both parties should exercise prudence in their public communications of planned alliance cooperation on the matter and about how or why the alliance would choose to employ such abilities. Hawkish suggestions of the potential to increase U.S. dominance in the region should be avoided.81 China is rightfully wary of any reference to conventional prompt global strike. Such rhetoric coming from Japan or the United States combined with the decision to move forward on conventional missile strike capabilities could be considered a threatening signal by Beijing.82 Without calculated prudence in regional dialogues, <u><strong><mark>even </mark>the <mark>discussion</strong></mark> of Tokyo acquiring conventional missile strike capabilities could ultimately <strong><mark>worsen</mark> the regional <mark>security</mark> environment</strong> rather than improve it</u>.</p>
1NC
5 – DA
null
25,903
772
43,128
./documents/hsld21/ParkCity/Le/Park%20City-Levinsky-Neg-ASU-Semis.docx
896,351
N
ASU
Semis
Ayala AM
Panel
1AC - Public Trust Doctrine 1NC - T plans bad DA climate DA india DA escape DA japan case 1AR - all 2NR - DA escape case 2AR - case
hsld21/ParkCity/Le/Park%20City-Levinsky-Neg-ASU-Semis.docx
null
75,219
NoLe
Park City NoLe
null
No.....
Le.....
null
null
25,123
ParkCity
Park City
UT
null
1,029
hsld21
HS LD 2021-22
2,021
ld
hs
1
1,969,312
2. The public image will be compliance and cooperation, not strong defiance
Gardner 18
James A. Gardner 18, Bridget and Thomas Black SUNY Distinguished Professor at the University at Buffalo School of Law, State University of New York, JD from the University of Chicago Law School, BA in Economics and Political Science from Yale University, “The Theory and Practice of Contestatory Federalism”, William & Mary Law Review, 60 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 507, Lexis
Defiance is the refusal of subnational governments to accept exercises of power by the central government. Defiance can take many forms, but it is useful to distinguish between strong and weak forms strong defiance consists of open refusal to accede to some policy of the national government. A subnational government may defy by taking more elaborate, affirmative steps to undermine national policy Weak defiance refers to actions which do not rise to the level of open refusal The tactic can be invoked by cultivating a public appearance of compliance and cooperation with a disliked national policy
Defiance is refusal to accept power by central government it is useful to distinguish between strong and weak forms strong consists of open refusal by taking elaborate, affirmative steps Weak do not rise to open refusal by cultivating public appearance of compliance and cooperation with disliked policy
3. Defiance Defiance, as I use the term here, is the nonviolent refusal of subnational governments to accept specific exercises of power by the central government. Defiance can take many forms, but it is useful to distinguish between strong and weak forms of defiance. [*535] a. Strong Defiance What I will call strong defiance consists of the open, nonviolent refusal by a subnational government to accede to some policy or action of the national government. A subnational government may defy national power by passive refusal to comply with disliked national policies, or by taking more elaborate, affirmative steps to undermine the operation or success of the national policy or action at issue within its borders. The states under study furnish many examples of strong defiance. In the United States, southern states engaged in a lengthy period of open defiance of national enforcement of the political rights of African-Americans, including outright disregard of the Fifteenth Amendment, which prohibits states from denying the right to vote on account of race. Some U.S. states repeatedly defy national constitutional protection of the right to abortion by enacting highly restrictive laws. In Argentina during the 1990s, the government of Santa Cruz province refused repeatedly to comply with orders of the Argentine Supreme Court requiring reinstatement of a provincial Attorney General who had been removed from office after embarking on investigations into the activities of provincial government officials. In another incident, provincial courts in San [*536] Luis province refused to enforce a national law regulating methods of determining the surnames of newborns. In 2017, the Catalan government defied a series of court orders designed to prevent a referendum on independence from Spain. Subnational units engage from time to time in strong defiance even in states, such as Germany and Switzerland, that have a reputation for amicable intergovernmental relations, and in which, my interlocutors assured me, such tactics would never be used. For example, the German Land of Bavaria in 1983 enacted a law requiring the display of a crucifix in every public school classroom. Upon challenge, the Constitutional Court ruled the law unconstitutional, but Bavaria has since refused to comply with the order. In Switzerland, the canton of Appenzell refused for nearly two decades to implement a 1971 national law mandating female suffrage until forced to do so by the federal courts. Similarly, the canton of Nidwalden has refused repeatedly to comply with a national law requiring cantons to share in the storage of nuclear waste. b. Weak Defiance Weak defiance, as I use the term here, refers to actions intended to thwart, undermine, or diminish the force or success of national policies to which the subnational unit objects, but which do not rise [*537] to the level of open refusal. Use of the tactic exploits the margin of discretion afforded to subnational units in the implementation of national policies. The tactic can be invoked by cultivating a public appearance of compliance and cooperation with a disliked national policy, but then implementing or following it so half-heartedly, or even downright uncooperatively, as to undermine the policy's force and effect within the jurisdiction.
3,315
<h4>2. The <u>public image</u> will be <u>compliance</u> and <u>cooperation</u>, not <u>strong defiance</h4><p></u>James A. <strong>Gardner 18</strong>, Bridget and Thomas Black SUNY Distinguished Professor at the University at Buffalo School of Law, State University of New York, JD from the University of Chicago Law School, BA in Economics and Political Science from Yale University, “The Theory and Practice of Contestatory Federalism”, William & Mary Law Review, 60 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 507, Lexis</p><p>3. Defiance</p><p><u><mark>Defiance</u></mark>, as I use the term here, <u><mark>is</mark> the</u> nonviolent <u><strong><mark>refusal</strong></mark> of subnational governments <mark>to accept</u></mark> specific <u>exercises of <mark>power by</mark> the <mark>central government</mark>. Defiance can take many forms, but <mark>it is useful to <strong>distinguish</strong> between <strong>strong</strong> and <strong>weak</strong> forms</u></mark> of defiance.</p><p> [*535] a. Strong Defiance</p><p>What I will call <u><strong><mark>strong</strong></mark> defiance <mark>consists of</u></mark> the <u><strong><mark>open</u></strong></mark>, nonviolent <u><strong><mark>refusal</u></strong></mark> by a subnational government <u>to accede to some policy</u> or action <u>of the national government. A subnational government may defy</u> national power by passive refusal to comply with disliked national policies, or <u><mark>by taking</mark> more <strong><mark>elaborate, affirmative steps</strong></mark> to undermine</u> the operation or success of the <u>national policy</u> or action at issue within its borders.</p><p>The states under study furnish many examples of strong defiance. In the United States, southern states engaged in a lengthy period of open defiance of national enforcement of the political rights of African-Americans, including outright disregard of the Fifteenth Amendment, which prohibits states from denying the right to vote on account of race. Some U.S. states repeatedly defy national constitutional protection of the right to abortion by enacting highly restrictive laws. In Argentina during the 1990s, the government of Santa Cruz province refused repeatedly to comply with orders of the Argentine Supreme Court requiring reinstatement of a provincial Attorney General who had been removed from office after embarking on investigations into the activities of provincial government officials. In another incident, provincial courts in San [*536] Luis province refused to enforce a national law regulating methods of determining the surnames of newborns. In 2017, the Catalan government defied a series of court orders designed to prevent a referendum on independence from Spain.</p><p>Subnational units engage from time to time in strong defiance even in states, such as Germany and Switzerland, that have a reputation for amicable intergovernmental relations, and in which, my interlocutors assured me, such tactics would never be used. For example, the German Land of Bavaria in 1983 enacted a law requiring the display of a crucifix in every public school classroom. Upon challenge, the Constitutional Court ruled the law unconstitutional, but Bavaria has since refused to comply with the order. In Switzerland, the canton of Appenzell refused for nearly two decades to implement a 1971 national law mandating female suffrage until forced to do so by the federal courts. Similarly, the canton of Nidwalden has refused repeatedly to comply with a national law requiring cantons to share in the storage of nuclear waste.</p><p>b. Weak Defiance</p><p><u><strong><mark>Weak</strong></mark> defiance</u>, as I use the term here, <u>refers to actions</u> intended to thwart, undermine, or diminish the force or success of national policies to which the subnational unit objects, but <u>which <mark>do <strong>not</strong> rise</u></mark> [*537] <u><mark>to</mark> the level of <strong><mark>open refusal</u></strong></mark>. Use of the tactic exploits the margin of discretion afforded to subnational units in the implementation of national policies. <u>The tactic can be invoked <mark>by cultivating</mark> a <strong><mark>public appearance of compliance and cooperation</strong> with</mark> a <mark>disliked</mark> national <mark>policy</u></mark>, but then implementing or following it so half-heartedly, or even downright uncooperatively, as to undermine the policy's force and effect within the jurisdiction.</p>
2NC Round 6
Uncoop
Perm: Do Both---2NC
37,986
235
58,092
./documents/hspolicy20/MontgomeryBell/GrYo/Montgomery%20Bell-Green-Young-Neg-Notre%20Dame-Round6.docx
735,248
N
Notre Dame
6
CKM BG
Michael Wimsatt
1AC - Collateral Consequences 2NR - NGA CP
hspolicy20/MontgomeryBell/GrYo/Montgomery%20Bell-Green-Young-Neg-Notre%20Dame-Round6.docx
null
62,697
GrYo
Montgomery Bell GrYo
null
Ma.....
Gr.....
Ja.....
Yo.....
21,723
MontgomeryBell
Montgomery Bell
TN
null
1,019
hspolicy20
HS Policy 2020-21
2,020
cx
hs
2
1,266,303
Interpretation: “medicines” is a generic bare plural. The aff may not defend that member nations of the World Trade Organization ought to reduce intellectual property protections for a medicine or subset of medicines.
Nebel 19
Nebel 19. [Jake Nebel is an assistant professor of philosophy at the University of Southern California and executive director of Victory Briefs. He writes a lot of this stuff lol – duh.] “Genericity on the Standardized Tests Resolution.” Vbriefly. August 12, 2019. https://www.vbriefly.com/2019/08/12/genericity-on-the-standardized-tests-resolution/?fbclid=IwAR0hUkKdDzHWrNeqEVI7m59pwsnmqLl490n4uRLQTe7bWmWDO_avWCNzi14 TG
Generic resolutions can’t be affirmed by specifying particular instances. “Colleges and universities” is a generic bare plural Second, “colleges and universities” fails the upward-entailment test for existential uses of bare plurals Colleges and universities ought not consider the SAT.” This sentence does not entail the more general statement that educational institutions ought not consider the SAT. This shows that “colleges and universities” is generic, because it fails the upward-entailment test for existential bare plurals. Third, “colleges and universities” fails the adverb of quantification test for existential bare plurals. Consider the sentence, “Dogs are barking outside my window.” This sentence expresses an existential statement that is true just in case there are some dogs barking outside my window. One test of this appeals to the drastic change of meaning caused by inserting any adverb of quantification (e.g., always, sometimes, generally, often, seldom, never, ever). You cannot add any such adverb into the sentence without drastically changing its meaning. To apply this test to the resolution, let’s again isolate the bare plural subject: “Colleges and universities ought not consider the SAT.” Adding generally (“Colleges and universitiesz generally ought not consider the SAT”) or ever (“Colleges and universities ought not ever consider the SAT”) result in comparatively minor changes of meaning. “colleges and universities” is generic rather than existential in the resolution.
Generic can’t be affirmed by particular instances “colleges fails the upward-entailment test for existential bare plurals Colleges ought not consider the SAT.” does not entail the more general statement that educational institutions ought not consider the SAT. “colleges fails the adverb of quantification test for existential bare plurals Dogs are barking outside my window expresses an existential true just in case there are some dogs barking inserting any adverb of quantification cannot add meaning
Both distinctions are important. Generic resolutions can’t be affirmed by specifying particular instances. But, since generics tolerate exceptions, plan-inclusive counterplans (PICs) do not negate generic resolutions. Bare plurals are typically used to express generic generalizations. But there are two important things to keep in mind. First, generic generalizations are also often expressed via other means (e.g., definite singulars, indefinite singulars, and bare singulars). Second, and more importantly for present purposes, bare plurals can also be used to express existential generalizations. For example, “Birds are singing outside my window” is true just in case there are some birds singing outside my window; it doesn’t require birds in general to be singing outside my window. So, what about “colleges and universities,” “standardized tests,” and “undergraduate admissions decisions”? Are they generic or existential bare plurals? On other topics I have taken great pains to point out that their bare plurals are generic—because, well, they are. On this topic, though, I think the answer is a bit more nuanced. Let’s see why. “Colleges and universities” is a generic bare plural. I don’t think this claim should require any argument, when you think about it, but here are a few reasons. First, ask yourself, honestly, whether the following speech sounds good to you: “Eight colleges and universities—namely, those in the Ivy League—ought not consider standardized tests in undergraduate admissions decisions. Maybe other colleges and universities ought to consider them, but not the Ivies. Therefore, in the United States, colleges and universities ought not consider standardized tests in undergraduate admissions decisions.” That is obviously not a valid argument: the conclusion does not follow. Anyone who sincerely believes that it is valid argument is, to be charitable, deeply confused. But the inference above would be good if “colleges and universities” in the resolution were existential. By way of contrast: “Eight birds are singing outside my window. Maybe lots of birds aren’t singing outside my window, but eight birds are. Therefore, birds are singing outside my window.” Since the bare plural “birds” in the conclusion gets an existential reading, the conclusion follows from the premise that eight birds are singing outside my window: “eight” entails “some.” If the resolution were existential with respect to “colleges and universities,” then the Ivy League argument above would be a valid inference. Since it’s not a valid inference, “colleges and universities” must be a generic bare plural. Second, “colleges and universities” fails the upward-entailment test for existential uses of bare plurals. Consider the sentence, “Lima beans are on my plate.” This sentence expresses an existential statement that is true just in case there are some lima beans on my plate. One test of this is that it entails the more general sentence, “Beans are on my plate.” Now consider the sentence, “Colleges and universities ought not consider the SAT.” (To isolate “colleges and universities,” I’ve eliminated the other bare plurals in the resolution; it cannot plausibly be generic in the isolated case but existential in the resolution.) This sentence does not entail the more general statement that educational institutions ought not consider the SAT. This shows that “colleges and universities” is generic, because it fails the upward-entailment test for existential bare plurals. Third, “colleges and universities” fails the adverb of quantification test for existential bare plurals. Consider the sentence, “Dogs are barking outside my window.” This sentence expresses an existential statement that is true just in case there are some dogs barking outside my window. One test of this appeals to the drastic change of meaning caused by inserting any adverb of quantification (e.g., always, sometimes, generally, often, seldom, never, ever). You cannot add any such adverb into the sentence without drastically changing its meaning. To apply this test to the resolution, let’s again isolate the bare plural subject: “Colleges and universities ought not consider the SAT.” Adding generally (“Colleges and universitiesz generally ought not consider the SAT”) or ever (“Colleges and universities ought not ever consider the SAT”) result in comparatively minor changes of meaning. (Note that this test doesn’t require there to be no change of meaning and doesn’t have to work for every adverb of quantification.) This strongly suggests what we already know: that “colleges and universities” is generic rather than existential in the resolution.
4,661
<h4>Interpretation: “medicines” is a generic bare plural. The aff may not defend that member nations of the World Trade Organization ought to reduce intellectual property protections for a medicine or subset of medicines. </h4><p><strong>Nebel 19</strong>. [Jake Nebel is an assistant professor of philosophy at the University of Southern California and executive director of Victory Briefs. He writes a lot of this stuff lol – duh.] “Genericity on the Standardized Tests Resolution.” Vbriefly. August 12, 2019. https://www.vbriefly.com/2019/08/12/genericity-on-the-standardized-tests-resolution/?fbclid=IwAR0hUkKdDzHWrNeqEVI7m59pwsnmqLl490n4uRLQTe7bWmWDO_avWCNzi14<u> TG</p><p></u>Both distinctions are important. <u><mark>Generic</mark> resolutions <mark>can’t be affirmed by</mark> specifying <mark>particular instances</mark>.</u> But, since generics tolerate exceptions, plan-inclusive counterplans (PICs) do not negate generic resolutions. Bare plurals are typically used to express generic generalizations. But there are two important things to keep in mind. First, generic generalizations are also often expressed via other means (e.g., definite singulars, indefinite singulars, and bare singulars). Second, and more importantly for present purposes, bare plurals can also be used to express existential generalizations. For example, “Birds are singing outside my window” is true just in case there are some birds singing outside my window; it doesn’t require birds in general to be singing outside my window. So, what about “colleges and universities,” “standardized tests,” and “undergraduate admissions decisions”? Are they generic or existential bare plurals? On other topics I have taken great pains to point out that their bare plurals are generic—because, well, they are. On this topic, though, I think the answer is a bit more nuanced. Let’s see why. <u>“Colleges and universities” is a generic bare plural</u>. I don’t think this claim should require any argument, when you think about it, but here are a few reasons. First, ask yourself, honestly, whether the following speech sounds good to you: “Eight colleges and universities—namely, those in the Ivy League—ought not consider standardized tests in undergraduate admissions decisions. Maybe other colleges and universities ought to consider them, but not the Ivies. Therefore, in the United States, colleges and universities ought not consider standardized tests in undergraduate admissions decisions.” That is obviously not a valid argument: the conclusion does not follow. Anyone who sincerely believes that it is valid argument is, to be charitable, deeply confused. But the inference above would be good if “colleges and universities” in the resolution were existential. By way of contrast: “Eight birds are singing outside my window. Maybe lots of birds aren’t singing outside my window, but eight birds are. Therefore, birds are singing outside my window.” Since the bare plural “birds” in the conclusion gets an existential reading, the conclusion follows from the premise that eight birds are singing outside my window: “eight” entails “some.” If the resolution were existential with respect to “colleges and universities,” then the Ivy League argument above would be a valid inference. Since it’s not a valid inference, “colleges and universities” must be a generic bare plural. <u>Second, <mark>“colleges</mark> and universities” <mark>fails the upward-entailment test for existential</mark> uses of <mark>bare plurals</u></mark>. Consider the sentence, “Lima beans are on my plate.” This sentence expresses an existential statement that is true just in case there are some lima beans on my plate. One test of this is that it entails the more general sentence, “Beans are on my plate.” Now consider the sentence, “<u><mark>Colleges </mark>and universities <mark>ought not consider the SAT.”</u></mark> (To isolate “colleges and universities,” I’ve eliminated the other bare plurals in the resolution; it cannot plausibly be generic in the isolated case but existential in the resolution.) <u>This sentence <mark>does not entail the more general statement that educational institutions ought not consider the SAT.</mark> This shows that “colleges and universities” is generic, because it fails the upward-entailment test for existential bare plurals. Third, <mark>“colleges </mark>and universities” <mark>fails the adverb of quantification test for existential bare plurals</mark>. Consider the sentence, “<mark>Dogs are barking outside my window</mark>.” This sentence <mark>expresses an existential</mark> statement that is <mark>true just in case there are some dogs barking</mark> outside my window. One test of this appeals to the drastic change of meaning caused by <mark>inserting any adverb of quantification</mark> (e.g., always, sometimes, generally, often, seldom, never, ever). You <mark>cannot add</mark> any such adverb into the sentence without drastically changing its <mark>meaning</mark>. To apply this test to the resolution, let’s again isolate the bare plural subject: “Colleges and universities ought not consider the SAT.” Adding generally (“Colleges and universitiesz generally ought not consider the SAT”) or ever (“Colleges and universities ought not ever consider the SAT”) result in comparatively minor changes of meaning. </u>(Note that this test doesn’t require there to be no change of meaning and doesn’t have to work for every adverb of quantification.) This strongly suggests what we already know: that <u>“colleges and universities” is generic rather than existential in the resolution. </p></u>
1NC
Shell
null
336,758
586
31,447
./documents/hsld21/AmericanHeritageBroward/Gu/American%20Heritage%20Broward-Gupta-Neg-Mid%20America%20Cup-Round3.docx
882,805
N
Mid America Cup
3
Lake Highland Prep Arjun Verma
Rohit Lakshman
1AC - Kant AC 1NC - Parametrics bad Can't read consistency the categorical imperative Case 1AR - Aff 2NR - Parametrics bad 2AR - Aff
hsld21/AmericanHeritageBroward/Gu/American%20Heritage%20Broward-Gupta-Neg-Mid%20America%20Cup-Round3.docx
null
74,341
PrGu
American Heritage Broward PrGu
null
Pr.....
Gu.....
null
null
24,899
AmericanHeritageBroward
American Heritage Broward
FL
null
1,029
hsld21
HS LD 2021-22
2,021
ld
hs
1
1,746,603
Prolif escalates.
Kroenig 15
Kroenig 15—(Associate Professor and International Relations Field Chair in the Department of Government and School of Foreign Service at Georgetown University). Matthew Kroenig. 2015. “The History of Proliferation Optimism: Does It Have a Future?” Journal of Strategic Studies, Volume 38, Issue 1-2, 2015.
The spread of nuclear weapons poses at least six severe threats to international peace and security including: nuclear war, nuclear terrorism, global and regional instability, constrained US freedom of action, weakened alliances, and further nuclear proliferation. The more states in possession of nuclear weapons, the greater the probability that somewhere, someday, there will be a catastrophic nuclear war. Before reaching a state of MAD, new states go through a transition period in which they lack a secure-second strike capability. one or both s might believe that it has an incentive to use nuclear weapons first. if Iran acquires nuclear weapons, neither Iran, nor its nuclear-armed rival, Israel, will have a secure, second-strike capability. Israel might not be confident that it could absorb a nuclear strike and respond with a devastating counterstrike. In these pre-MAD situations, there are at least three ways that nuclear war could occur. First, the state with the nuclear advantage might believe it has a splendid first strike capability. In a crisis, Israel might, therefore, decide to launch a preventive nuclear strike to disarm Iran’s nuclear capabilities. Indeed, this incentive might be further increased by Israel’s aggressive strategic culture that emphasizes preemptive action. Second, the state with a small and vulnerable nuclear arsenal, in this case Iran, might feel use them or lose them pressures. Third nuclear war could result due to the reciprocal fear of surprise attack. it would be better to go first than to go second. Even in a world of MAD, however, when both sides have secure, second-strike capabilities, there is still a risk of nuclear war. deterrence theory assumes nuclear-armed states are governed by rational leaders who would not intentionally launch a suicidal nuclear This applie to current nuclear powers, but there is no guarantee that it will continue to hold in the future. Iran’s theocratic government contains leaders who hold millenarian religious worldviews and could one day ascend to power. some leader somewhere will choose to launch a nuclear war, knowing full well that it could result in self-destruction. One does not need to resort to irrationality, however, to imagine nuclear war under MAD. Leaders might, therefore, choose to launch limited nuclear war. This strategy might be especially attractive to states in a position of conventional inferiority that might have an incentive to escalate a crisis quickly to the nuclear level. leaders can make a ‘threat that leaves something to chance’. They can initiate a nuclear crisis. By playing these risky games of nuclear brink ship, states can increase the risk of nuclear war in an attempt to force a less resolved adversary to back down. scholars have documented historical incidents when accidents nearly led to war. Nuclear Terrorism spread of nuclear weapons also increases the risk of nuclear terrorism. Unlike states, which can be more easily deterred, there is little doubt that if terrorists acquired nuclear weapons, they would use them. Regional Instability The spread of nuclear weapons also emboldens nuclear powers, contributing to regional instability states with nuclear weapons can be confident they can deter an intentional military attack, giving them an incentive to be more aggressive . nuclear weapons provide a shield under which states can feel free to engage in lower-level aggression. Recent scholarly analyses have demonstrated that, after controlling for other relevant factors, nuclear-weapon states are more likely to engage in conflict than nonnuclear-weapon states and this is more pronounced in new states that have less experience with nuclear diplomacy any one of those crises could result in a catastrophic nuclear exchange
The spread of nuc s poses nuclear war terrorism, and further prolif Before MAD new states lack second strike . one or both s might believe it has incentive to use first. Even in MAD deterrence assumes rational leaders . but there is no guarantee . games of brink ship, can increase risk . scholars have documented historical accidents . spread also increases nuc terror . new states have less experience with nuclear diplomacy any crises result in catastrophic exchange
The spread of nuclear weapons poses at least six severe threats to international peace and security including: nuclear war, nuclear terrorism, global and regional instability, constrained US freedom of action, weakened alliances, and further nuclear proliferation. Each of these threats has received extensive treatment elsewhere and this review is not intended to replicate or even necessarily to improve upon these previous efforts. Rather the goals of this section are more modest: to usefully bring together and recap the many reasons why we should be pessimistic about the likely consequences of nuclear proliferation. Many of these threats will be illuminated with a discussion of a case of much contemporary concern: Iran’s advanced nuclear program. Nuclear War The greatest threat posed by the spread of nuclear weapons is nuclear war. The more states in possession of nuclear weapons, the greater the probability that somewhere, someday, there will be a catastrophic nuclear war. To date, nuclear weapons have only been used in warfare once. In 1945, the United States used nuclear weapons on Hiroshima and Nagasaki, bringing World War II to a close. Many analysts point to the 65-plus-year tradition of nuclear non-use as evidence that nuclear weapons are unusable, but it would be naïve to think that nuclear weapons will never be used again simply because they have not been used for some time. After all, analysts in the 1990s argued that worldwide economic downturns like the Great Depression were a thing of the past, only to be surprised by the dot-com bubble bursting later in the decade and the Great Recession of the late 2000s.48 This author, for one, would be surprised if nuclear weapons are not used again sometime in his lifetime. Before reaching a state of MAD, new nuclear states go through a transition period in which they lack a secure-second strike capability. In this context, one or both states might believe that it has an incentive to use nuclear weapons first. For example, if Iran acquires nuclear weapons, neither Iran, nor its nuclear-armed rival, Israel, will have a secure, second-strike capability. Even though it is believed to have a large arsenal, given its small size and lack of strategic depth, Israel might not be confident that it could absorb a nuclear strike and respond with a devastating counterstrike. Similarly, Iran might eventually be able to build a large and survivable nuclear arsenal, but, when it first crosses the nuclear threshold, Tehran will have a small and vulnerable nuclear force. In these pre-MAD situations, there are at least three ways that nuclear war could occur. First, the state with the nuclear advantage might believe it has a splendid first strike capability. In a crisis, Israel might, therefore, decide to launch a preventive nuclear strike to disarm Iran’s nuclear capabilities. Indeed, this incentive might be further increased by Israel’s aggressive strategic culture that emphasizes preemptive action. Second, the state with a small and vulnerable nuclear arsenal, in this case Iran, might feel use them or lose them pressures. That is, in a crisis, Iran might decide to strike first rather than risk having its entire nuclear arsenal destroyed. Third, as Thomas Schelling has argued, nuclear war could result due to the reciprocal fear of surprise attack.49 If there are advantages to striking first, one state might start a nuclear war in the belief that war is inevitable and that it would be better to go first than to go second. Fortunately, there is no historic evidence of this dynamic occurring in a nuclear context, but it is still possible. In an Israeli–Iranian crisis, for example, Israel and Iran might both prefer to avoid a nuclear war, but decide to strike first rather than suffer a devastating first attack from an opponent. Even in a world of MAD, however, when both sides have secure, second-strike capabilities, there is still a risk of nuclear war. Rational deterrence theory assumes nuclear-armed states are governed by rational leaders who would not intentionally launch a suicidal nuclear war. This assumption appears to have applied to past and current nuclear powers, but there is no guarantee that it will continue to hold in the future. Iran’s theocratic government, despite its inflammatory rhetoric, has followed a fairly pragmatic foreign policy since 1979, but it contains leaders who hold millenarian religious worldviews and could one day ascend to power. We cannot rule out the possibility that, as nuclear weapons continue to spread, some leader somewhere will choose to launch a nuclear war, knowing full well that it could result in self-destruction. One does not need to resort to irrationality, however, to imagine nuclear war under MAD. Nuclear weapons may deter leaders from intentionally launching full-scale wars, but they do not mean the end of international politics. As was discussed above, nuclear-armed states still have conflicts of interest and leaders still seek to coerce nuclear-armed adversaries. Leaders might, therefore, choose to launch a limited nuclear war.50 This strategy might be especially attractive to states in a position of conventional inferiority that might have an incentive to escalate a crisis quickly to the nuclear level. During the Cold War, the United States planned to use nuclear weapons first to stop a Soviet invasion of Western Europe given NATO’s conventional inferiority.51 As Russia’s conventional power has deteriorated since the end of the Cold War, Moscow has come to rely more heavily on nuclear weapons in its military doctrine. Indeed, Russian strategy calls for the use of nuclear weapons early in a conflict (something that most Western strategists would consider to be escalatory) as a way to de-escalate a crisis. Similarly, Pakistan’s military plans for nuclear use in the event of an invasion from conventionally stronger India. And finally, Chinese generals openly talk about the possibility of nuclear use against a US superpower in a possible East Asia contingency. Second, as was also discussed above, leaders can make a ‘threat that leaves something to chance’.52 They can initiate a nuclear crisis. By playing these risky games of nuclear brinkmanship, states can increase the risk of nuclear war in an attempt to force a less resolved adversary to back down. Historical crises have not resulted in nuclear war, but many of them, including the 1962 Cuban Missile Crisis, have come close. And scholars have documented historical incidents when accidents nearly led to war.53 When we think about future nuclear crisis dyads, such as Iran and Israel, with fewer sources of stability than existed during the Cold War, we can see that there is a real risk that a future crisis could result in a devastating nuclear exchange. Nuclear Terrorism The spread of nuclear weapons also increases the risk of nuclear terrorism.54 While September 11th was one of the greatest tragedies in American history, it would have been much worse had Osama Bin Laden possessed nuclear weapons. Bin Laden declared it a ‘religious duty’ for Al- Qa’eda to acquire nuclear weapons and radical clerics have issued fatwas declaring it permissible to use nuclear weapons in Jihad against the West.55 Unlike states, which can be more easily deterred, there is little doubt that if terrorists acquired nuclear weapons, they would use them.56 Indeed, in recent years, many US politicians and security analysts have argued that nuclear terrorism poses the greatest threat to US national security.57 Analysts have pointed out the tremendous hurdles that terrorists would have to overcome in order to acquire nuclear weapons.58 Nevertheless, as nuclear weapons spread, the possibility that they will eventually fall into terrorist hands increases. States could intentionally transfer nuclear weapons, or the fissile material required to build them, to terrorist groups. There are good reasons why a state might be reluctant to transfer nuclear weapons to terrorists, but, as nuclear weapons spread, the probability that a leader might someday purposely arm a terrorist group increases. Some fear, for example, that Iran, with its close ties to Hamas and Hizballah, might be at a heightened risk of transferring nuclear weapons to terrorists. Moreover, even if no state would ever intentionally transfer nuclear capabilities to terrorists, a new nuclear state, with underdeveloped security procedures, might be vulnerable to theft, allowing terrorist groups or corrupt or ideologically-motivated insiders to transfer dangerous material to terrorists. There is evidence, for example, that representatives from Pakistan’s atomic energy establishment met with Al-Qa’eda members to discuss a possible nuclear deal.59 Finally, a nuclear-armed state could collapse, resulting in a breakdown of law and order and a loose nukes problem. US officials are currently very concerned about what would happen to Pakistan’s nuclear weapons if the government were to fall. As nuclear weapons spread, this problem is only further amplified. Iran is a country with a history of revolutions and a government with a tenuous hold on power. The regime change that Washington has long dreamed about in Tehran could actually become a nightmare if a nuclear-armed Iran suffered a breakdown in authority, forcing us to worry about the fate of Iran’s nuclear arsenal. Regional Instability The spread of nuclear weapons also emboldens nuclear powers, contributing to regional instability. States that lack nuclear weapons need to fear direct military attack from other states, but states with nuclear weapons can be confident that they can deter an intentional military attack, giving them an incentive to be more aggressive in the conduct of their foreign policy. In this way, nuclear weapons provide a shield under which states can feel free to engage in lower-level aggression. Indeed, international relations theories about the ‘stability-instability paradox’ maintain that stability at the nuclear level contributes to conventional instability.60 Historically, we have seen that the spread of nuclear weapons has emboldened their possessors and contributed to regional instability. Recent scholarly analyses have demonstrated that, after controlling for other relevant factors, nuclear-weapon states are more likely to engage in conflict than nonnuclear-weapon states and that this aggressiveness is more pronounced in new nuclear states that have less experience with nuclear diplomacy.61 Similarly, research on internal decision-making in Pakistan reveals that Pakistani foreign policymakers may have been emboldened by the acquisition of nuclear weapons, which encouraged them to initiate militarized disputes against India.62 Currently, Iran restrains its foreign policy because it fears major military retaliation from the United States or Israel, but with nuclear weapons it could feel free to push harder. A nuclear-armed Iran would likely step up support to terrorist and proxy groups and engage in more aggressive coercive diplomacy. With a nuclear-armed Iran increasingly throwing its weight around in the region, we could witness an even more crisis prone Middle East. And in a poly-nuclear Middle East with Israel, Iran, and, in the future, possibly other states, armed with nuclear weapons, any one of those crises could result in a catastrophic nuclear exchange.
11,405
<h4>Prolif escalates.</h4><p><u><strong>Kroenig 15</u></strong>—(Associate Professor and International Relations Field Chair in the Department of Government and School of Foreign Service at Georgetown University). Matthew Kroenig. 2015. “The History of Proliferation Optimism: Does It Have a Future?” Journal of Strategic Studies, Volume 38, Issue 1-2, 2015.</p><p><u><strong><mark>The spread of nuc</mark>lear weapon<mark>s poses</mark> at least six severe threats to international peace and security including: <mark>nuclear war</mark>, nuclear <mark>terrorism, </mark>global and</u></strong> <u><strong>regional instability, constrained US freedom of action, weakened alliances, <mark>and further</mark> nuclear <mark>prolif</mark>eration.</u></strong> Each of these threats has received extensive treatment elsewhere and this review is not intended to replicate or even necessarily to improve upon these previous efforts. Rather the goals of this section are more modest: to usefully bring together and recap the many reasons why we should be pessimistic about the likely consequences of nuclear proliferation. Many of these threats will be illuminated with a discussion of a case of much contemporary concern: Iran’s advanced nuclear program. Nuclear War The greatest threat posed by the spread of nuclear weapons is nuclear war. <u><strong>The more states in possession of nuclear weapons, the greater the probability that somewhere, someday, there will be a catastrophic nuclear war.</u></strong> To date, nuclear weapons have only been used in warfare once. In 1945, the United States used nuclear weapons on Hiroshima and Nagasaki, bringing World War II to a close. Many analysts point to the 65-plus-year tradition of nuclear non-use as evidence that nuclear weapons are unusable, but it would be naïve to think that nuclear weapons will never be used again simply because they have not been used for some time. After all, analysts in the 1990s argued that worldwide economic downturns like the Great Depression were a thing of the past, only to be surprised by the dot-com bubble bursting later in the decade and the Great Recession of the late 2000s.48 This author, for one, would be surprised if nuclear weapons are not used again sometime in his lifetime. <u><strong><mark>Before </mark>reaching a state of <mark>MAD</mark>, <mark>new </u></strong></mark>nuclear <u><strong><mark>states </mark>go through a transition period in which they <mark>lack </mark>a secure-<mark>second strike </mark>capability<mark>.</u></strong></mark> In this context, <u><strong><mark>one or both s</u></strong></mark>tates <u><strong><mark>might believe</mark> that <mark>it has</mark> an <mark>incentive to use </mark>nuclear weapons <mark>first.</u></strong></mark> For example, <u><strong>if Iran acquires nuclear weapons, neither Iran, nor its nuclear-armed rival, Israel, will have a secure, second-strike capability.</u></strong> Even though it is believed to have a large arsenal, given its small size and lack of strategic depth, <u><strong>Israel might not be confident that it could absorb a nuclear strike and respond with a devastating counterstrike.</u></strong> Similarly, Iran might eventually be able to build a large and survivable nuclear arsenal, but, when it first crosses the nuclear threshold, Tehran will have a small and vulnerable nuclear force. <u><strong>In these pre-MAD situations, there are at least three ways that nuclear war could occur. First, the state with the nuclear advantage might believe it has a splendid first strike capability. In a crisis, Israel might, therefore, decide to launch a preventive nuclear strike to disarm Iran’s nuclear capabilities. Indeed, this incentive might be further increased by Israel’s aggressive strategic culture that emphasizes preemptive action. Second, the state with a small and vulnerable nuclear arsenal, in this case Iran, might feel use them or lose them pressures.</u></strong> That is, in a crisis, Iran might decide to strike first rather than risk having its entire nuclear arsenal destroyed. <u><strong>Third</u></strong>, as Thomas Schelling has argued, <u><strong>nuclear war could result due to the reciprocal fear of surprise attack.</u></strong>49 If there are advantages to striking first, one state might start a nuclear war in the belief that war is inevitable and that <u><strong>it would be better to go first than to go second.</u></strong> Fortunately, there is no historic evidence of this dynamic occurring in a nuclear context, but it is still possible. In an Israeli–Iranian crisis, for example, Israel and Iran might both prefer to avoid a nuclear war, but decide to strike first rather than suffer a devastating first attack from an opponent. <u><strong><mark>Even in </mark>a world of <mark>MAD</mark>, however, when both sides have secure, second-strike capabilities, there is still a risk of nuclear war.</u></strong> Rational <u><strong><mark>deterrence </mark>theory</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>assumes</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>nuclear-armed states are governed by <mark>rational leaders </mark>who would not intentionally launch a suicidal nuclear </u></strong>war<mark>.<u><strong> </mark>This</u></strong> assumption appears to have <u><strong>applie</u></strong>d <u><strong>to</u></strong> past and <u><strong>current nuclear powers, <mark>but there is no guarantee</mark> that it will continue to hold in the future<mark>. </mark>Iran’s theocratic government</u></strong>, despite its inflammatory rhetoric, has followed a fairly pragmatic foreign policy since 1979, but it <u><strong>contains leaders who hold millenarian religious worldviews and could one day ascend to power.</u></strong> We cannot rule out the possibility that, as nuclear weapons continue to spread, <u><strong>some leader somewhere will choose to launch a nuclear war, knowing full well that it could result in self-destruction. One does not need to resort to irrationality, however, to imagine nuclear war under MAD.</u></strong> Nuclear weapons may deter leaders from intentionally launching full-scale wars, but they do not mean the end of international politics. As was discussed above, nuclear-armed states still have conflicts of interest and leaders still seek to coerce nuclear-armed adversaries. <u><strong>Leaders might, therefore, choose to launch </u></strong>a<u><strong> limited nuclear war.</u></strong>50 <u><strong>This strategy might be especially attractive to states in a position of conventional inferiority that might have an incentive to escalate a crisis quickly to the nuclear level.</u></strong> During the Cold War, the United States planned to use nuclear weapons first to stop a Soviet invasion of Western Europe given NATO’s conventional inferiority.51 As Russia’s conventional power has deteriorated since the end of the Cold War, Moscow has come to rely more heavily on nuclear weapons in its military doctrine. Indeed, Russian strategy calls for the use of nuclear weapons early in a conflict (something that most Western strategists would consider to be escalatory) as a way to de-escalate a crisis. Similarly, Pakistan’s military plans for nuclear use in the event of an invasion from conventionally stronger India. And finally, Chinese generals openly talk about the possibility of nuclear use against a US superpower in a possible East Asia contingency. Second, as was also discussed above, <u><strong>leaders can make a ‘threat that leaves something to chance’.</u></strong>52 <u><strong>They can initiate a nuclear crisis. By playing these risky <mark>games of</mark> nuclear <mark>brink</u></strong></mark>man<u><strong><mark>ship, </mark>states <mark>can increase </mark>the <mark>risk </mark>of nuclear war in an attempt to force a less resolved adversary to back down<mark>.</u></strong></mark> Historical crises have not resulted in nuclear war, but many of them, including the 1962 Cuban Missile Crisis, have come close. And <u><strong><mark>scholars have documented historical </mark>incidents when <mark>accidents </mark>nearly led to war<mark>.</u></strong></mark>53 When we think about future nuclear crisis dyads, such as Iran and Israel, with fewer sources of stability than existed during the Cold War, we can see that there is a real risk that a future crisis could result in a devastating nuclear exchange. <u><strong>Nuclear Terrorism </u></strong>The <u><strong><mark>spread</mark> of nuclear weapons <mark>also increases</mark> the risk of <mark>nuc</mark>lear <mark>terror</mark>ism<mark>.</u></strong></mark>54 While September 11th was one of the greatest tragedies in American history, it would have been much worse had Osama Bin Laden possessed nuclear weapons. Bin Laden declared it a ‘religious duty’ for Al- Qa’eda to acquire nuclear weapons and radical clerics have issued fatwas declaring it permissible to use nuclear weapons in Jihad against the West.55 <u><strong>Unlike states, which can be more easily deterred, there is little doubt that if terrorists acquired nuclear weapons, they would use them.</u></strong>56 Indeed, in recent years, many US politicians and security analysts have argued that nuclear terrorism poses the greatest threat to US national security.57 Analysts have pointed out the tremendous hurdles that terrorists would have to overcome in order to acquire nuclear weapons.58 Nevertheless, as nuclear weapons spread, the possibility that they will eventually fall into terrorist hands increases. States could intentionally transfer nuclear weapons, or the fissile material required to build them, to terrorist groups. There are good reasons why a state might be reluctant to transfer nuclear weapons to terrorists, but, as nuclear weapons spread, the probability that a leader might someday purposely arm a terrorist group increases. Some fear, for example, that Iran, with its close ties to Hamas and Hizballah, might be at a heightened risk of transferring nuclear weapons to terrorists. Moreover, even if no state would ever intentionally transfer nuclear capabilities to terrorists, a new nuclear state, with underdeveloped security procedures, might be vulnerable to theft, allowing terrorist groups or corrupt or ideologically-motivated insiders to transfer dangerous material to terrorists. There is evidence, for example, that representatives from Pakistan’s atomic energy establishment met with Al-Qa’eda members to discuss a possible nuclear deal.59 Finally, a nuclear-armed state could collapse, resulting in a breakdown of law and order and a loose nukes problem. US officials are currently very concerned about what would happen to Pakistan’s nuclear weapons if the government were to fall. As nuclear weapons spread, this problem is only further amplified. Iran is a country with a history of revolutions and a government with a tenuous hold on power. The regime change that Washington has long dreamed about in Tehran could actually become a nightmare if a nuclear-armed Iran suffered a breakdown in authority, forcing us to worry about the fate of Iran’s nuclear arsenal. <u><strong>Regional Instability The spread of nuclear weapons also emboldens nuclear powers, contributing to regional instability</u></strong>. States that lack nuclear weapons need to fear direct military attack from other states, but <u><strong>states with nuclear weapons can be confident</u></strong> that <u><strong>they can deter an intentional military attack, giving them an incentive to be more aggressive</u></strong> in the conduct of their foreign policy<u><strong>.</u></strong> In this way, <u><strong>nuclear weapons provide a shield under which states can feel free to engage in lower-level aggression. </u></strong>Indeed, international relations theories about the ‘stability-instability paradox’ maintain that stability at the nuclear level contributes to conventional instability.60 Historically, we have seen that the spread of nuclear weapons has emboldened their possessors and contributed to regional instability. <u><strong>Recent scholarly analyses have demonstrated that, after controlling for other relevant factors, nuclear-weapon states are more likely to engage in conflict than nonnuclear-weapon states and </u></strong>that<u><strong> this </u></strong>aggressiveness<u><strong> is more pronounced in <mark>new </u></strong></mark>nuclear <u><strong><mark>states </mark>that <mark>have less experience with nuclear diplomacy</u></strong></mark>.61 Similarly, research on internal decision-making in Pakistan reveals that Pakistani foreign policymakers may have been emboldened by the acquisition of nuclear weapons, which encouraged them to initiate militarized disputes against India.62 Currently, Iran restrains its foreign policy because it fears major military retaliation from the United States or Israel, but with nuclear weapons it could feel free to push harder. A nuclear-armed Iran would likely step up support to terrorist and proxy groups and engage in more aggressive coercive diplomacy. With a nuclear-armed Iran increasingly throwing its weight around in the region, we could witness an even more crisis prone Middle East. And in a poly-nuclear Middle East with Israel, Iran, and, in the future, possibly other states, armed with nuclear weapons, <u><strong><mark>any </mark>one of those <mark>crises </mark>could <mark>result in </mark>a <mark>catastrophic</mark> nuclear <mark>exchange</u></strong></mark>. </p>
null
Ukraine/Georgia: 1AC—2.1 (Send)
AC: 1AC
6,955
2,098
51,647
./documents/ndtceda20/Minnesota/FeRa/Minnesota-Ferguson-Rao-Aff-Gtown-Fullerton-Round3.docx
620,205
A
Gtown-Fullerton
3
Dartmouth LW
Louvis, Ezra
1AC - Exp Ukr AC Regime 1NC - T activate T reduce QPQ CP Newtonian Cosmology K MDT PIC German Prolif NPT Turn Det Turn Block - K T activate Prolif NPT turn Det Turn 2nr - K
ndtceda20/Minnesota/FeRa/Minnesota-Ferguson-Rao-Aff-Gtown-Fullerton-Round3.docx
null
52,396
FeRa
Minnesota FeRa
null
Jo.....
Fe.....
Br.....
Ra.....
19,336
Minnesota
Minnesota
null
null
1,010
ndtceda20
NDT/CEDA 2020-21
2,020
cx
college
2
1,131,723
Widespread grid collapse causes extinction.
Benjamin Monarch 20
Benjamin Monarch 20, University of Kentucky College of Law, J.D. May 2015, LLM in Energy, Natural Resources, and Environmental Law and Policy from the University of Denver Sturm College of Law, Deputy District Attorney at Colorado Judicial Branch, and Term Member at the Council on Foreign Relations, “Black Start: The Risk of Grid Failure from a Cyber Attack and the Policies Needed to Prepare for It,” Journal of Energy & Natural Resources Law, vol. 38, no. 2, Routledge, 04/02/2020, pp. 131–160
even in prolonged power outages, we expect that electricity will be restored and, consequently, life will return to normal Perhaps we need ask, however, what if power cannot be restored in a timely manner? how did we reach a point where something so critical to routine life now presents an existential threat, and what can we do to mitigate the risk of a catastrophic grid attack? grid attacks pose existential risk If an electric disruption occurs at a household level, some homes may be equipped with a modest gasoline generator to temporarily restore power. If a hospital loses power, it will almost invariably be resupplied by automatic, industrial-scale generators. These micro considerations hardly give anyone pause . But what happens, at a macro level, when an electric grid supplying power to large portions of the United States goes black, or worse, what happens if all of the United States’ electric grids go down simultaneously? the more ominous question is not how, but whether or not we can survive the vastness of the grid makes the opportunities for intrusion seemingly infinite. By any measure, grid failure will unleash a parade of horrors. Stores would close, food scarcity would follow, communication would cease, garbage would pile up, planes would be grounded, clean water would become a luxury, service stations would yield no fuel, hospitals would eventually go dark, financial transactions would stop, and this is only the tip of the iceberg – in a prolonged grid failure social chaos would reign, once-eradicated diseases would re-emerge and, increasingly, hope of returning to a normal life would fade.9 The notion of complete grid failure, once relegated to science fiction comics or James Bond movies, is now not only possible but also one of the most pressing national security threats today.10
if power cannot be restored presents an existential threat the question is not how, but whether we survive grid failure unleash a parade of horrors food scarcity communication cease, garbage pile up water become a luxury hospitals go dark transactions stop social chaos would reign diseases would re-emerge
In the industrial world, when a switch is flipped, we take for granted that it will produce light, boot a computer, illuminate a stadium or activate a power plant. We know, of course, that power losses can and do occur. Many of us have lit candles during a thunderstorm or brought out extra blankets when a blizzard takes down transmission lines. As of this writing, the most populated state in the United States, California, is experiencing rolling blackouts.1 Yet even in prolonged power outages, we expect that electricity will be restored and, consequently, life will return to normal. Perhaps we need ask, however, what if power cannot be restored in a timely manner? Concern is growing that in the not-too-distant future our electricity supply could be irreparably compromised by a cyber attack. The issue when considering a systemic grid failure of this nature is twofold: how did we reach a point where something so critical to routine life now presents an existential threat, and what can we do to mitigate the risk of a catastrophic grid attack? This article posits that the emergence of cyber attacks on industrial control systems, as a means of war or criminal menace, have reached a level of sophistication capable of crippling those systems. This article argues that a new grid security policy paradigm is required to thwart catastrophic grid failure – a paradigm that recognises the inextricable link between commercial power generation and national security. In section 5, seven policy recommendations are outlined that may, in part, mitigate a future where grid attacks pose existential risk to nations and their citizenry. Those recommendations are: first, develop a comprehensive insurance programme to minimise the financial risk of grid disruption; second, train more cybersecurity professionals with particular expertise in industrial control systems; third, institute a federally mandated information-sharing programme that is centralised under United States Cyber Command; fourth, subsidise and/or incentivise cybersecurity protections for small to mid-size utilities; fifth, provide university grants for grid security research; sixth, integrate new technologies with an eye towards securing the grid; and, lastly, formulate clear rules of engagement for a military response to grid disruption. The purpose of this article is to provide the reader with an introduction to this complex topic. It is the aim of the author to give orientation to this issue and its many branches in the hope that better understanding will animate further curiosity and, ultimately, positive action on the part of the reader. Although many skilled and earnest people work tirelessly to prevent a grid failure scenario, it is essential that more be added to their ranks each day. Advisors, engineers, regulators, private counsel to power generators, and many others who play roles in electric power production are crucial to this subject. So, while this article provides entrée to the topic of grid security, its long-term objective is to spur action by the entire energy-related community. In the end, no one is immune to consequences of grid failure and, therefore, everyone is responsible, in part, for promoting grid integrity.2 In this regard, lawyers who represent various actors in the energy sector are going to be faced with questions and potential legal risks of a magnitude that they have never experienced before. 1.2. Turning the power back on in a powerless world ‘Black start’, not to be confused with the term ‘blackout’, is the name given to the process of restoring an electric grid to operation without relying on the external electric power transmission network to recover from a total or partial shutdown.3 At first glance, this description is unremarkable, but it implies a disturbing catch-22 – how might one restore power if the entire external transmission network is compromised? If an electric disruption occurs at a household level, some homes may be equipped with a modest gasoline generator to temporarily restore power. If a hospital loses power, it will almost invariably be resupplied by automatic, industrial-scale generators. These micro considerations hardly give anyone pause; they are hiccups on a stormy night or a snowy day. In other words, their ‘black start’ is a quick and effective process for restoring power. But what happens, at a macro level, when an electric grid supplying power to large portions of the United States goes black, or worse, what happens if all of the United States’ electric grids go down simultaneously?4 In that scenario, how might enough non-grid power be harnessed and transmitted to turn the United States’ lights back on? Moreover, how might such a catastrophe occur in the first place? Perhaps the more ominous question is not how, but whether or not we can survive such circumstances if they persist in the long term. The United States electric grid (‘the grid’) is the ‘largest interconnected machine’ in the world.5 It consists of more than 7000 power plants, 55,000 substations, 160,000 miles of high-voltage transmission lines and millions of low-voltage distribution lines.6 The scale and complexity of the grid in the context of the modern digital world are beyond comprehension because within it are innumerable industrial control systems; incalculable connections to digital networks; millions, if not billions, of analogue or digital sensors; many thousands of human actors; and trillions of lines of programming code.7 Further complexifying the grid is that it is comprised of generations of technologies, stitched together in ways that are not inherently secure in a world of cyber threats.8 The vastness of the grid makes security of it challenging. Likewise, the vastness of the grid makes the opportunities for intrusion seemingly infinite. By any measure, grid failure will unleash a parade of horrors. Stores would close, food scarcity would follow, communication would cease, garbage would pile up, planes would be grounded, clean water would become a luxury, service stations would yield no fuel, hospitals would eventually go dark, financial transactions would stop, and this is only the tip of the iceberg – in a prolonged grid failure social chaos would reign, once-eradicated diseases would re-emerge and, increasingly, hope of returning to a normal life would fade.9 The notion of complete grid failure, once relegated to science fiction comics or James Bond movies, is now not only possible but also one of the most pressing national security threats today.10
6,560
<h4>Widespread grid collapse causes extinction.</h4><p><strong>Benjamin Monarch 20</strong>, University of Kentucky College of Law, J.D. May 2015, LLM in Energy, Natural Resources, and Environmental Law and Policy from the University of Denver Sturm College of Law, Deputy District Attorney at Colorado Judicial Branch, and Term Member at the Council on Foreign Relations, “Black Start: The Risk of Grid Failure from a Cyber Attack and the Policies Needed to Prepare for It,” Journal of Energy & Natural Resources Law, vol. 38, no. 2, Routledge, 04/02/2020, pp. 131–160 </p><p>In the industrial world, when a switch is flipped, we take for granted that it will produce light, boot a computer, illuminate a stadium or activate a power plant. We know, of course, that power losses can and do occur. Many of us have lit candles during a thunderstorm or brought out extra blankets when a blizzard takes down transmission lines. As of this writing, the most populated state in the United States, California, is experiencing rolling blackouts.1 Yet <u><strong>even in prolonged power outages, we expect that electricity will be restored and, consequently, life will return to normal</u></strong>. <u>Perhaps we need ask,</u> <u><strong>however, what <mark>if power cannot be restored</mark> in a timely manner?</u></strong> Concern is growing that in the not-too-distant future our electricity supply could be irreparably compromised by a cyber attack. The issue when considering a systemic grid failure of this nature is twofold: <u><strong>how did we reach a point where something so critical to routine life now <mark>presents an existential threat</mark>, and what can we do to mitigate the risk of a catastrophic grid attack? </u></strong>This article posits that the emergence of cyber attacks on industrial control systems, as a means of war or criminal menace, have reached a level of sophistication capable of crippling those systems. This article argues that a new grid security policy paradigm is required to thwart catastrophic grid failure – a paradigm that recognises the inextricable link between commercial power generation and national security. In section 5, seven policy recommendations are outlined that may, in part, mitigate a future where <u><strong>grid attacks pose existential risk</u></strong> to nations and their citizenry. Those recommendations are: first, develop a comprehensive insurance programme to minimise the financial risk of grid disruption; second, train more cybersecurity professionals with particular expertise in industrial control systems; third, institute a federally mandated information-sharing programme that is centralised under United States Cyber Command; fourth, subsidise and/or incentivise cybersecurity protections for small to mid-size utilities; fifth, provide university grants for grid security research; sixth, integrate new technologies with an eye towards securing the grid; and, lastly, formulate clear rules of engagement for a military response to grid disruption. The purpose of this article is to provide the reader with an introduction to this complex topic. It is the aim of the author to give orientation to this issue and its many branches in the hope that better understanding will animate further curiosity and, ultimately, positive action on the part of the reader. Although many skilled and earnest people work tirelessly to prevent a grid failure scenario, it is essential that more be added to their ranks each day. Advisors, engineers, regulators, private counsel to power generators, and many others who play roles in electric power production are crucial to this subject. So, while this article provides entrée to the topic of grid security, its long-term objective is to spur action by the entire energy-related community. In the end, no one is immune to consequences of grid failure and, therefore, everyone is responsible, in part, for promoting grid integrity.2 In this regard, lawyers who represent various actors in the energy sector are going to be faced with questions and potential legal risks of a magnitude that they have never experienced before. 1.2. Turning the power back on in a powerless world ‘Black start’, not to be confused with the term ‘blackout’, is the name given to the process of restoring an electric grid to operation without relying on the external electric power transmission network to recover from a total or partial shutdown.3 At first glance, this description is unremarkable, but it implies a disturbing catch-22 – how might one restore power if the entire external transmission network is compromised? <u><strong>If an electric disruption occurs at a household level, some homes may be equipped with a modest gasoline generator to temporarily restore power. If a hospital loses power, it will almost invariably be resupplied by automatic, industrial-scale generators. These micro considerations hardly give anyone pause</u></strong>; they are hiccups on a stormy night or a snowy day. In other words, their ‘black start’ is a quick and effective process for restoring power<u><strong>. But what happens, at a macro level, when an electric grid supplying power to large portions of the United States goes black, or worse, what happens if all of the United States’ electric grids go down simultaneously?</u></strong>4 In that scenario, how might enough non-grid power be harnessed and transmitted to turn the United States’ lights back on? Moreover, how might such a catastrophe occur in the first place? Perhaps <u><strong><mark>the</mark> more ominous <mark>question is not how, but whether</mark> or not <mark>we</mark> can <mark>survive</u></strong></mark> such circumstances if they persist in the long term. The United States electric grid (‘the grid’) is the ‘largest interconnected machine’ in the world.5 It consists of more than 7000 power plants, 55,000 substations, 160,000 miles of high-voltage transmission lines and millions of low-voltage distribution lines.6 The scale and complexity of the grid in the context of the modern digital world are beyond comprehension because within it are innumerable industrial control systems; incalculable connections to digital networks; millions, if not billions, of analogue or digital sensors; many thousands of human actors; and trillions of lines of programming code.7 Further complexifying the grid is that it is comprised of generations of technologies, stitched together in ways that are not inherently secure in a world of cyber threats.8 The vastness of the grid makes security of it challenging. Likewise, <u><strong>the vastness of the grid makes the opportunities for intrusion seemingly infinite. By any measure, <mark>grid failure</mark> will <mark>unleash a parade of horrors</mark>. Stores would close, <mark>food scarcity</mark> would follow, <mark>communication</mark> would <mark>cease, garbage</mark> would <mark>pile up</mark>, planes would be grounded, clean <mark>water</mark> would <mark>become a luxury</mark>, service stations would yield no fuel, <mark>hospitals</mark> would eventually <mark>go dark</mark>, financial <mark>transactions</mark> would <mark>stop</mark>, and this is only the tip of the iceberg – in a prolonged grid failure <mark>social chaos would reign</mark>, once-eradicated <mark>diseases would re-emerge</mark> and, increasingly, hope of returning to a normal life would fade</strong>.9 The notion of complete grid failure, once relegated to science fiction comics or James Bond movies, is now not only possible but also one of the most pressing national security threats today.10</p></u>
null
1AC---FloMo R4
1AC---Scarcity Advantage
1,589
308
27,847
./documents/hspolicy21/Lovejoy/ZaRa/Lovejoy-Zanzuri-Ramirez-Aff-10%20-%20Flower%20Mound-Round4.docx
750,298
A
10 - Flower Mound
4
Timber Creek WC
Steele Musgrove
1AC - Toilet Water V3 1NC - DA Fizm Bad CP SDWA Advantage 2NR - Conceded 2AR - oh Win
hspolicy21/Lovejoy/ZaRa/Lovejoy-Zanzuri-Ramirez-Aff-10%20-%20Flower%20Mound-Round4.docx
null
64,015
ZaRa
Lovejoy ZaRa
null
Jo.....
Za.....
Se.....
Ra.....
22,038
Lovejoy
Lovejoy
TX
null
1,020
hspolicy21
HS Policy 2021-22
2,021
cx
hs
2
4,610,681
A] Dogmatism Paradox – disregard the 1NC
Sorensen
Sorensen Sorensen, Roy, Professor of Philosophy at Washington University in St. Louis. "Epistemic Paradoxes.” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 21 June 2006. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/epistemic-paradoxes/. PeteZ
If I know h is true, I know that any evidence against h is evidence against something that is true; I should disregard evidence that I know is misleading. So, once I know that h is true, I am in a position to disregard any future evidence that seems to tell against h.
If I know h evidence against h is evidence against something true; I should disregard evidence that is misleading. once h is true, I disregard any future evidence against h.
Saul Kripke’s ruminations on the surprise test paradox led him to a paradox about dogmatism. He lectured on both paradoxes at Cambridge University to the Moral Sciences Club in 1972. (A descendent of this lecture now appears as Kripke 2011). Gilbert Harman transmitted Kripke’s new paradox as follows: If I know that h is true, I know that any evidence against h is evidence against something that is true; I know that such evidence is misleading. But I should disregard evidence that I know is misleading. So, once I know that h is true, I am in a position to disregard any future evidence that seems to tell against h. (1973, 148)
632
<h4>A] Dogmatism Paradox – disregard the 1NC</h4><p><strong>Sorensen</strong> Sorensen, Roy, Professor of Philosophy at Washington University in St. Louis. "Epistemic Paradoxes.” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 21 June 2006. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/epistemic-paradoxes/. PeteZ</p><p>Saul Kripke’s ruminations on the surprise test paradox led him to a paradox about dogmatism. He lectured on both paradoxes at Cambridge University to the Moral Sciences Club in 1972. (A descendent of this lecture now appears as Kripke 2011). Gilbert Harman transmitted Kripke’s new paradox as follows:</p><p><u><mark>If I know</mark> </u>that<u> <mark>h</mark> is true, I know that any <mark>evidence against h is evidence against something </mark>that is<mark> true; </u></mark>I know that such evidence is misleading. But <u><mark>I should disregard evidence that </mark>I know <mark>is misleading.</mark> So, <mark>once </mark>I know that<mark> h is true, I</mark> am in a position to <mark>disregard any future evidence </mark>that seems to tell <mark>against h.</u></mark> (1973, 148)</p>
null
1AC
FW
327,419
166
152,859
./documents/hsld22/StrakeJesuitCollegePreparatory/KaSh/StrakeJesuitCollegePreparatory-KaSh-Aff-Lexington-Winter-Invitational-Round-2.docx
963,332
A
Lexington Winter Invitational
2
Harrison CZ
Roy
1AC- Kant w/ASean 1NC - Spanish/Latin K, Case 1AR, 2NR, 2AR - All
hsld22/StrakeJesuitCollegePreparatory/KaSh/StrakeJesuitCollegePreparatory-KaSh-Aff-Lexington-Winter-Invitational-Round-2.docx
2023-01-14 17:18:51
80,549
KaSh
Strake Jesuit College Preparatory KaSh
Pronouns: He/Him Contact Info: Phone- 8323962580 Preface with name, round and etc DONT CALL UNLESS NECESSARY Facebook Messenger- Karan Shah Email: [email protected] or [email protected] Messenger and Text are the best bets If there is any way you would like me to accommodate your needs in any way before and during the round, just contact me! I'm happy to do so. Please tell me if there are any specific interps you would like me to meet before round (spikes on top, rob spec, etc.) Feel free to hmu if my wiki is acting up and there are some docs you can't access - I'll send them to you directly. Let me know any trigger warnings or pronouns before the round so we can make the debate as comfortable as possible for both of us. Good luck!
Ka.....
Sh.....
null
null
27,049
StrakeJesuitCollegePreparatory
Strake Jesuit College Preparatory
TX
36,501
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
4,465,190
Efficient court review underpins patent-led innovation---that stops nuclear war and a range of existential threats
Rando 16
Robert J. Rando 16, Founder and Lead Counsel of The Rando Law Firm P.C., Fellow of the Academy of Court-Appointed Masters, Treasurer for the New York Intellectual Property Law Association, Chair of the Federal Bar Association Intellectual Property Law Section, “America’s Need For Strong, Stable and Sound Intellectual Property Protection and Policies: Why It Really Matters”, IP Insight, June 2016, p. 12-14 [language modified] [abbreviations in brackets]
greater global unity, cooperation and communication could be, achieved by advances in technology technological advancement, societal needs, globalization, existential threats, economic realities, and political imperatives have combined to create the “interesting times” for the United States [IP] intellectual property laws. Many of the existential threats remain the same (nuclear war and proliferation, [genocides] and natural disease) and some are new ([hu]manmade disease, greater awareness of environmental changes and possibly human interrelationship factors, and the unintended consequences of genetic manipulation and robotic technologies). The danger and uncertainty that pervades changes in intellectual property laws, though not an existential threat of the same manner and kind, correlates with the threat and remains “more open to the creative energy of man than any other time in history.” there is a non-coincidental congruence and convergence of activity across and among the three branches of government, occurring almost simultaneously with the congruence and convergence of the rapid developments of technological innovation across various scientific disciplines and the information age, reflected in the transformation of the [IP] intellectual property laws in the United States The passage of the AIA brought monumental changes in patent law in the way that patents are procured (first inventor to file instead of first to invent) and how they are enforced (quasi-judicial challenges to patent validity through inter-party reviews at the Patent Trial and Appeals Board (PTAB)). patent law include district court litigation concerning patent validity. to the perceived Federal Circuit’s pro-patent and bright line decisions, it can just as assuredly be viewed as decisions rendered by a Court of final resort which does not function in a vacuum devoid of the social, economic and political winds of the times. In recognition of the effect new technologies have on the patent law, the politicization of intellectual property law matters, especially patent law (through factious governing principles of the political branches of the government), and the maturation of the Federal Circuit patent law jurisprudence, the SCOTUS has rendered opinions in cases that impact, and perhaps are/were intended to mitigate the concerns regarding, some of the vexing issues confronting the patent community today (e.g., non-practicing entities or in the politicized parlance “patent trolls,” the intersection of patent and antitrust laws in Hatch-Waxman so called “pay-for-delay” settlements between Branded and Generic pharma companies, and the fundamental tenets that comprise the very heart of what is patent eligible subject matter). Copyrights there is an overlap of patent rights and copyrights for software driven by the ebb and flow of the strength of each respective intellectual property protection For example, none other than the famous Crooner, Bing Crosby, benefited from both protections. Well-known as a prolific and popular recording artist he also benefited from his investments in the, then innovative, recording technologies. Similarly, the Beatles, Beach Boys, as well as many other rock and roll artists, experimental efforts in music performance, recording and production, helped to transform the music industry in both copyrightable artistic expression and patentable inventions. Similarly, film, literary and digital arts reap benefits at the crossroads of both copyright and patent protections. Trademarks from nations that have a less than stellar respect for intellectual property rights, and international trade agreements. More recently, politicization (or perhaps political correctness) has creeped into the trademark law arena pitting branding rights and protections against first amendment rights. Trade Secrets the strengthening of trade secret protection in conjunction with the perceived weakening of patent protection may very-well have the unintended consequence of contravening the purpose behind the Patent and Copyright Clause: It is increasingly more difficult to function “off the grid.” The invasive and non-invasive attributes of the internet, the reliance upon the multitude of devices, social media, and information age technologies, and access to big data, all contribute to the decrease in and dilution of the right to privacy. Wittingly or otherwise, the strong libertarian roots of the republic have been replaced by dependence upon these modes of an information-age life. Commentary on the benefits and deficits of this reality are beyond the subject and purpose of this writing. Suffice to acknowledge that the right to privacy has been significantly reduced. The laws that protect these rights are in a constant struggle to maintain those rights while yielding to the demands of the lifestyle and security concerns. Laws that relate to cybersecurity in the global and domestic space create interplay with privacy rights. Legislation, trade agreements and jurisprudence all impact this area of intellectual property. Cross-border theft of trade secrets, competitor espionage, and loss of control over personal data are all implicated in the intellectual property law arena. America’s Need For Strong Intellectual Property Protection The need for strong protection of intellectual property rights is greater now than it was at the dawn of our republic the U.S. Constitution recognizes the need for: uniformity of the protection of IP rights, securing rights for the individual and, incentivizing innovation and creative aspirations To be sure, some change is inevitable, and both beneficial and necessary in an environment of rapidly changing technology where the law needs to evolve or conform to new realities the social, political and economic impact of strong protections for intellectual property cannot be overstated. In the social context, the incentive for disclosure and innovation is critical. Solutions for sustainability and climate change rely upon this premise. Likewise, as we are on the precipice of the ultimate convergence in technologies from the hi-tech digital world and life sciences space, capturing the ability to cure many diseases this incentive must be preserved advancements in technologies related to the global economy and communications will enhance the possibilities for solutions to political and cultural conflicts that arise around the globe. Likewise, the U S economy has always benefited when it is at the forefront of innovation and achieves prosperity from its leadership role in technological advancements to solve the many problems facing our country and the broader global community depends upon the strong, stable and sound protection of intellectual property rights
greater global cooperation could be, achieved by advances in tech tech advancement globalization, existential threats combine to create “interesting times” for [IP] existential threats remain nuclear war [genocides] disease environmental changes genetic manipulation and robotic tech there is a congruence of activity with rapid innovation across disciplines reflected in [IP] laws patent law include district court litigation concerning validity the perceived weakening of patent protection may have unintended consequence the impact of strong i p cannot be overstated innovation is critical. Solutions for sustainability and climate change rely upon this Likewise to cure diseases tech will enhance solutions to conflicts around the globe U S economy has benefited from leadership in advancements to solve problems facing the global community depends upon strong, stable i p rights
Robert F. Kennedy’s speech, which includes his reference to the oft-quoted “interesting times” curse, applies throughout history in many contexts and, indeed, with both negative and positive connotation. While he focused on the struggles for freedom and social justice, the requisite ascendancy of the individual over the state, and the institution and integration of those ideals for the greater good, he also promoted the goals of greater global unity, cooperation and communication, which were, and could be, achieved by advances in technology. And, as noted in the excerpt, he championed “the creative energy of men.” Intellectual Property in “Interesting Times” It is beyond question that starting with the last decade of the twentieth century and throughout the first two decades of the twenty-first century, when it comes to matters relating to intellectual property, we have been living in “interesting times.” Some may interpret these interesting times as defined by the curse and others may view it by the ordinary meaning of “interesting.” In either case, those of us that toil in the fields of patents, copyrights, trademarks, trade secrets, and privacy rights have experienced an unprecedented sea change in the way those rights are procured, protected and enforced. Likewise, and perhaps more importantly, even those of us that do not practice in these areas of law, as well as the general public, have been, and continue to be, impacted by the consequences of these changes (both positive and negative). The Changes In Intellectual Property Law Examples of some of the changes in intellectual property law are: the sweeping 2011 legislative changes to the patent laws under the America Invents Act (AIA), which impact is only beginning to be fully appreciated; the various proposals for patent law reform, on the heels of the AIA, beginning with the 113th and 114th Congress; the copyright laws Digital Millennium Copyright Act (DMCA) and numerous 114th Congressional proposed copyright law changes; the recently enacted federal trade secret law (Defend Trade Secrets Act of 2016 (DTSA))2; the impact of the internet, domain names and globalization on Trademark law; the intellectual property law harmonization requirements included in various global/regional trade agreements; and the proliferation of devices (both invasive and non-invasive) that defy any rational basis for believing we can still adhere to the republic’s libertarian understanding of the right to privacy. Without engaging in “chicken and egg” analysis, it is sufficient to observe that technological advancement, societal needs, globalization, existential threats, economic realities, and political imperatives (or what James Madison referred to in the Federalist Papers No. 10 as factious governance), have combined to create the “interesting times” for the United States [IP] intellectual property laws. What was said by Bobby Kennedy in 1966 remains true today. We live in dangerous and uncertain times. Many of the existential threats remain the same (nuclear war and proliferation, [genocides] genocidal maniacs and natural disease) and some are new ([hu]manmade disease, greater awareness of environmental changes and possibly human interrelationship factors, and the unintended consequences of genetic manipulation and robotic technologies). The danger and uncertainty that pervades changes in intellectual property laws, though not an existential threat of the same manner and kind, correlates with the threat and remains “more open to the creative energy of man than any other time in history.” Apropos the creative energy of man, there is a non-coincidental congruence and convergence of activity across and among the three branches of government, occurring almost simultaneously with the congruence and convergence of the rapid developments of technological innovation across various scientific disciplines and the information age, reflected in the transformation of the [IP] intellectual property laws in the United States. Patents The passage of the AIA was a culmination of efforts spanning several years of Congressional efforts; and the product of a push by the companies at the forefront of the twenty-first century new technology business titans. The legislation brought about monumental changes in the patent law in the way that patents are procured (first inventor to file instead of first to invent) and how they are enforced (quasi-judicial challenges to patent validity through inter-party reviews at the Patent Trial and Appeals Board (PTAB)). The 113th and 114th Congress grappled with newly proposed patent law reforms that, if enacted, may present additional tectonic shifts in the patent law. Major provisions of the proposals include: fee-shifting measures (requiring loser pays legal fees - counter to the American rule); strict detailed pleadings requirements, promulgated without the traditional Rules Enabling Act procedure, that exceed those of the Twombly/Iqbal standard applied to all other civil matters in federal courts, and the different standards applicable to patent claim interpretation in PTAB proceedings and district court litigation concerning patent validity. The Executive and administrative branch has also been active in the patent law arena. President Obama was a strong supporter of the AIA3 and in his 2014 State Of The Union Address, essentially stated that, with respect to the proposed patent law reforms aimed at patent troll issues, we must innovate rather than litigate.4 Additionally, the USPTO has embarked upon an energetic overhaul of its operations in terms of patent quality and PTO performance in granting patents, and the PTAB has expanded to almost 250 Administrative Law Judges in concert with the AIA post-grant proceedings’ strict timetable requirements. The Supreme Court, not to be outdone by the Articles I and II branches of the U.S. government, has raised the profile of patent cases to historical heights. From 1996 to the 2014-15 term there has been a steady increase in the number of patent cases decided by the SCOTUS5. The 2014-15 term occupied almost ten percent of the Court’s docket. Prior to the last two decades, the Supreme Court would rarely include more than one or two patent cases in a docket that was much larger than those we have become accustomed to from the Roberts’ Court6. While the SCOTUS activity in patent cases is viewed by some as a counter-balance to the perceived Federal Circuit’s pro-patent and bright line decisions, it can just as assuredly be viewed as decisions rendered by a Court of final resort which does not function in a vacuum devoid of the social, economic and political winds of the times. In recognition of the effect new technologies have on the patent law, the politicization of intellectual property law matters, especially patent law (through factious governing principles of the political branches of the government), and the maturation of the Federal Circuit patent law jurisprudence, the SCOTUS has rendered opinions in cases that impact, and perhaps are/were intended to mitigate the concerns regarding, some of the vexing issues confronting the patent community today (e.g., non-practicing entities or in the politicized parlance “patent trolls,” the intersection of patent and antitrust laws in Hatch-Waxman so called “pay-for-delay” settlements between Branded and Generic pharma companies, and the fundamental tenets that comprise the very heart of what is patent eligible subject matter). Copyrights The advent and ubiquity of the internet, social media and digital technologies (MP3s, Napster, Facebook, YouTube, and Twitter) represents the impetus for changes in the Copyright laws. The DMCA addressed the issues presented by these advances or changes in the differing media and forms of artistic impressions. The proliferation of digital photos, graphic designs and publishing alternatives, as well as adherence to globalization harmonization have given rise to changes in the statutory law and jurisprudence in this area of intellectual property law. Additionally, there is an overlap of patent rights and copyrights for software driven by the ebb and flow of the strength of each respective intellectual property protection. Notably, the Patent and Copyright Clause7, in addition to Author’s writings, has been viewed as discretely applying to two different types of creativity or innovation. When drafted the “sciences” referred not only to fields of modern scienctific inquiry but rather to all knowledge. And the “useful arts” does not refer to artistic endeavors, but rather to the work of artisans or people skilled in a manufacturing craft. Rather than result in ambiguity or confusion, perhaps the Framers were either quite prescient or, just coincidentally, these aspects of the Patent and Copyright Clause have converged. For example, none other than the famous Crooner, Bing Crosby, benefited from both protections. Well-known as a prolific and popular recording artist he also benefited from his investments in the, then innovative, recording technologies. Similarly, the Beatles, Beach Boys, as well as many other rock and roll artists, experimental efforts in music performance, recording and production, helped to transform the music industry in both copyrightable artistic expression and patentable inventions. Similarly, film, literary and digital arts reap benefits at the crossroads of both copyright and patent protections. Trademarks Trademark laws have been impacted by numerous changes in the business landscape. They include the internet, Domain names, international rights in a global economy, different venues and avenues for branding, marketing and merchandising, global knock-offs from nations that have a less than stellar respect for intellectual property rights, and international trade agreements. More recently, politicization (or perhaps political correctness) has creeped into the trademark law arena pitting branding rights and protections against first amendment rights. Trade Secrets As with Copyright and Trademark law, trade secrets law includes some of the same issues related to trade agreements. TRIPS required members to have trade secret protection in place. Initially, the United States compliance with this requirement has relied upon the trade secret law of the individual states. That compliance may be supplanted by the recently enacted DTSA. Similarly, the Trans Pacific Partnership (TPP) trade agreement contains intellectual property rights provisions that will trigger required changes to United States statutory Intellectual Property Laws. The proposed trade secret legislation also gives rise to several concerns. For instance, there is an absence of a specific definition for trade secret, as well as potential issues of federalism, conflict with state law precedent (despite no preemption), remedies, and the impact on employer/employee relations. There is also a real concern that the strengthening of trade secret protection in conjunction with the perceived weakening of patent protection (e.g., high rate of invalidating patents in post-grant proceedings before the PTAB and strict limitations on what is patent eligible subject matter) may very-well have the unintended consequence of contravening the purpose behind the Patent and Copyright Clause: “to promote the progress of the sciences and the useful arts.” Moreover, the incentive to innovate may very well be usurped by the advantage of withholding patent law disclosure of highly beneficial scientific advancements that directly affect the human condition, alter life expectancies and the evolution of the human species (rather than by mere “natural selection”), and what is the very essence of a human being (for better or worse). Thus, crippling innovation and the progress of the sciences and useful arts. Privacy Rights It is increasingly more difficult to function “off the grid.” The invasive and non-invasive attributes of the internet, the reliance upon the multitude of devices, social media, and information age technologies, and access to big data, all contribute to the decrease in and dilution of the right to privacy. Wittingly or otherwise, the strong libertarian roots of the republic have been replaced by dependence upon these modes of an information-age life. Commentary on the benefits and deficits of this reality are beyond the subject and purpose of this writing. Suffice to acknowledge that the right to privacy has been significantly reduced. The laws that protect these rights are in a constant struggle to maintain those rights while yielding to the demands of the lifestyle and security concerns. Laws that relate to cybersecurity in the global and domestic space create interplay with privacy rights. Legislation, trade agreements and jurisprudence all impact this area of intellectual property. Cross-border theft of trade secrets, competitor espionage, and loss of control over personal data are all implicated in the intellectual property law arena. America’s Need For Strong Intellectual Property Protection The need for strong protection of intellectual property rights is greater now than it was at the dawn of our republic. Our Forefathers and the Framers of the U.S. Constitution recognized the need to secure those rights in Article 1, Section 8, Clause 8. James Madison provides insight for its significance in the Federalist Papers No. 43 (the only reference to the clause). It is contained in the first Article section dedicated to the enumerated powers of Congress. The clause recognizes the need for: uniformity of the protection of IP rights, securing those rights for the individual rather than the state; and, incentivizing innovation and creative aspirations. Underlying this particular enumerated power of Congress is the same struggle that the Framers grappled with throughout the document for the new republic: how to promote a unified republic while protecting individual liberty. The fear of tyranny and protection of the “natural law” individual liberty is a driving theme for the Constitution and throughout the Federalist Papers. For example, in Federalist No. 10, James Madison articulated the important recognition of the “faction” impact on a democracy and a republic. In Federalist No. 51, Madison emphasized the importance of the separation of powers among the three branches of the republic. And in Federalist No. 78, Alexander Hamilton, provided his most significant essay, which described the judiciary as the weakest branch of government and sought the protection of its independence providing the underpinnings for judicial review as recognized thereafter in Marbury v. Madison. All of these related themes are relevant to the Patent and Copyright Clause and at the center of the intellectual property protections then and now. The Federalist Papers No. 10 recognition that a faction may influence the law has been playing itself out in the halls of congress in the period of time leading up to the AIA and in connection with the current patent law reform debate. The large tech companies of the past, new tech, new patent-based financial business model entities, and pharma factions have been the drivers, proponents and opponents of certain of these efforts. To be sure, some change is inevitable, and both beneficial and necessary in an environment of rapidly changing technology where the law needs to evolve or conform to new realities. However, changes not premised upon the founding principles of the Constitution and the Patent and Copyright Clause (i.e., uniformity, secured rights for the individual, incentivizing innovation and protecting individual liberty) run afoul of the intended purpose of the constitutional guarantee. Although the Sovereign does not benefit directly from the fruits of the innovator, enacting laws that empower the King, and enables the King to remain so, has the same effect as deprivation and diminishment of the individual’s rights and effectively confiscates them from him/her. Specifically, with respect to intellectual property rights, effecting change to the laws that do not adhere to these underlying principles, in favor of the faction that lobbies the most and the best in the quid pro quo of political gain to the governing body threatens to undermine the individual’s intellectual property rights and hinder the greatest economic driver and source of prosperity in the country. It is also important to recognize that the social, political and economic impact of strong protections for intellectual property cannot be overstated. In the social context, the incentive for disclosure and innovation is critical. Solutions for sustainability and climate change (whether natural, man-made or mutually/marginally intertwined) rely upon this premise. Likewise, as we are on the precipice of the ultimate convergence in technologies from the hi-tech digital world and life sciences space, capturing the ability to cure many diseases and fatal illnesses and providing the true promise of extended longevity in good health and well-being, that is meaningful, productive, and purposeful; this incentive must be preserved. In similar fashion, advancements in technologies related to the global economy and communications will enhance the possibilities for solutions to political and cultural conflicts that arise around the globe. Likewise, the United States economy has always benefited when it is at the forefront of innovation and achieves prosperity from its leadership role in technological advancements. Conclusion As was the case in 1966, how we move forward today, to solve the many problems facing our country and the broader global community in these “interesting times,” both within and without the laws affecting intellectual property rights, depends upon the “creative energy of man” which must prevail. An achievable goal, dependent on the strong, stable and sound protection of intellectual property rights.
17,971
<h4>Efficient court review underpins <u>patent-led innovation</u>---that stops <u>nuclear war</u> and a <u>range</u> of <u>existential threats</h4><p></u>Robert J. <strong>Rando 16</strong>, Founder and Lead Counsel of The Rando Law Firm P.C., Fellow of the Academy of Court-Appointed Masters, Treasurer for the New York Intellectual Property Law Association, Chair of the Federal Bar Association Intellectual Property Law Section, “America’s Need For Strong, Stable and Sound Intellectual Property Protection and Policies: Why It Really Matters”, IP Insight, June 2016, p. 12-14 [language modified] [abbreviations in brackets]</p><p>Robert F. Kennedy’s speech, which includes his reference to the oft-quoted “interesting times” curse, applies throughout history in many contexts and, indeed, with both negative and positive connotation. While he focused on the struggles for freedom and social justice, the requisite ascendancy of the individual over the state, and the institution and integration of those ideals for the greater good, he also promoted the goals of <u><strong><mark>greater global</mark> unity, <mark>cooperation</mark> and communication</u></strong>, which were, and <u><mark>could be, achieved by advances in <strong>tech</strong></mark>nology</u>. And, as noted in the excerpt, he championed “the creative energy of men.”</p><p>Intellectual Property in “Interesting Times”</p><p>It is beyond question that starting with the last decade of the twentieth century and throughout the first two decades of the twenty-first century, when it comes to matters relating to intellectual property, we have been living in “interesting times.” Some may interpret these interesting times as defined by the curse and others may view it by the ordinary meaning of “interesting.” In either case, those of us that toil in the fields of patents, copyrights, trademarks, trade secrets, and privacy rights have experienced an unprecedented sea change in the way those rights are procured, protected and enforced. Likewise, and perhaps more importantly, even those of us that do not practice in these areas of law, as well as the general public, have been, and continue to be, impacted by the consequences of these changes (both positive and negative).</p><p>The Changes In Intellectual Property Law</p><p>Examples of some of the changes in intellectual property law are: the sweeping 2011 legislative changes to the patent laws under the America Invents Act (AIA), which impact is only beginning to be fully appreciated; the various proposals for patent law reform, on the heels of the AIA, beginning with the 113th and 114th Congress; the copyright laws Digital Millennium Copyright Act (DMCA) and numerous 114th Congressional proposed copyright law changes; the recently enacted federal trade secret law (Defend Trade Secrets Act of 2016 (DTSA))2; the impact of the internet, domain names and globalization on Trademark law; the intellectual property law harmonization requirements included in various global/regional trade agreements; and the proliferation of devices (both invasive and non-invasive) that defy any rational basis for believing we can still adhere to the republic’s libertarian understanding of the right to privacy.</p><p>Without engaging in “chicken and egg” analysis, it is sufficient to observe that <u><strong><mark>tech</mark>nological <mark>advancement</strong></mark>, <strong>societal needs</strong>, <strong><mark>globalization</strong>, <strong>existential threats</strong></mark>, <strong>economic realities</strong>, and <strong>political imperatives</u></strong> (or what James Madison referred to in the Federalist Papers No. 10 as factious governance), <u>have <strong><mark>combine</strong></mark>d <mark>to create</mark> the <mark>“interesting times” for</mark> the United States <mark>[IP]</mark> intellectual property laws.</p><p></u>What was said by Bobby Kennedy in 1966 remains true today. We live in dangerous and uncertain times. <u>Many of the <mark>existential threats <strong>remain</strong></mark> the same (<strong><mark>nuclear war</strong></mark> and proliferation, <strong><mark>[genocides]</u></strong></mark> genocidal maniacs <u>and <strong>natural <mark>disease</strong></mark>) and some are new ([hu]manmade disease, greater awareness of <strong><mark>environmental changes</strong></mark> and possibly human interrelationship factors, and the unintended consequences of <strong><mark>genetic manipulation</strong> and <strong>robotic tech</mark>nologies</strong>). The danger and uncertainty that pervades changes in intellectual property laws, though not an existential threat of the same manner and kind, correlates with the threat and remains “more open to the creative energy of man than any other time in history.”</p><p></u>Apropos the creative energy of man, <u><mark>there is a</mark> non-coincidental <mark>congruence</mark> and convergence <mark>of activity</mark> across and among the three branches of government, occurring almost simultaneously <mark>with</mark> the congruence and convergence of the <mark>rapid</mark> developments of technological <mark>innovation across</mark> various scientific <mark>disciplines</mark> and the information age, <mark>reflected in</mark> the transformation of the <mark>[IP]</mark> intellectual property <mark>laws</mark> in the United States</u>.</p><p>Patents</p><p><u>The passage of the AIA</u> was a culmination of efforts spanning several years of Congressional efforts; and the product of a push by the companies at the forefront of the twenty-first century new technology business titans. The legislation <u>brought</u> about <u>monumental changes in</u> the <u>patent law in the way that patents are procured (first inventor to file instead of first to invent) and how they are enforced (quasi-judicial challenges to patent validity through inter-party reviews at the Patent Trial and Appeals Board (PTAB)).</p><p></u>The 113th and 114th Congress grappled with newly proposed <u><mark>patent law</u></mark> reforms that, if enacted, may present additional tectonic shifts in the patent law. Major provisions of the proposals <u><mark>include</u></mark>: fee-shifting measures (requiring loser pays legal fees - counter to the American rule); strict detailed pleadings requirements, promulgated without the traditional Rules Enabling Act procedure, that exceed those of the Twombly/Iqbal standard applied to all other civil matters in federal courts, and the different standards applicable to patent claim interpretation in PTAB proceedings and <u><strong><mark>district court litigation</strong> concerning</mark> patent <strong><mark>validity</strong></mark>.</p><p></u>The Executive and administrative branch has also been active in the patent law arena. President Obama was a strong supporter of the AIA3 and in his 2014 State Of The Union Address, essentially stated that, with respect to the proposed patent law reforms aimed at patent troll issues, we must innovate rather than litigate.4 Additionally, the USPTO has embarked upon an energetic overhaul of its operations in terms of patent quality and PTO performance in granting patents, and the PTAB has expanded to almost 250 Administrative Law Judges in concert with the AIA post-grant proceedings’ strict timetable requirements.</p><p>The Supreme Court, not to be outdone by the Articles I and II branches of the U.S. government, has raised the profile of patent cases to historical heights. From 1996 to the 2014-15 term there has been a steady increase in the number of patent cases decided by the SCOTUS5. The 2014-15 term occupied almost ten percent of the Court’s docket. Prior to the last two decades, the Supreme Court would rarely include more than one or two patent cases in a docket that was much larger than those we have become accustomed to from the Roberts’ Court6.</p><p>While the SCOTUS activity in patent cases is viewed by some as a counter-balance<u> to the perceived Federal Circuit’s pro-patent and bright line decisions, it can just as assuredly be viewed as decisions rendered by a Court of final resort which does not function in a vacuum devoid of the social, economic and political winds of the times. In recognition of the effect new technologies have on the patent law, the politicization of intellectual property law matters, especially patent law (through factious governing principles of the political branches of the government), and the maturation of the Federal Circuit patent law jurisprudence, the SCOTUS has rendered opinions in cases that impact, and perhaps are/were intended to mitigate the concerns regarding, some of the vexing issues confronting the patent community today (e.g., non-practicing entities or in the politicized parlance “patent trolls,” the intersection of patent and antitrust laws in Hatch-Waxman so called “pay-for-delay” settlements between Branded and Generic pharma companies, and the fundamental tenets that comprise the very heart of what is patent eligible subject matter).</p><p>Copyrights</p><p></u>The advent and ubiquity of the internet, social media and digital technologies (MP3s, Napster, Facebook, YouTube, and Twitter) represents the impetus for changes in the Copyright laws. The DMCA addressed the issues presented by these advances or changes in the differing media and forms of artistic impressions. The proliferation of digital photos, graphic designs and publishing alternatives, as well as adherence to globalization harmonization have given rise to changes in the statutory law and jurisprudence in this area of intellectual property law. Additionally, <u>there is an overlap of patent rights and copyrights for software driven by the ebb and flow of the strength of each respective intellectual property protection</u>.</p><p>Notably, the Patent and Copyright Clause7, in addition to Author’s writings, has been viewed as discretely applying to two different types of creativity or innovation. When drafted the “sciences” referred not only to fields of modern scienctific inquiry but rather to all knowledge. And the “useful arts” does not refer to artistic endeavors, but rather to the work of artisans or people skilled in a manufacturing craft. Rather than result in ambiguity or confusion, perhaps the Framers were either quite prescient or, just coincidentally, these aspects of the Patent and Copyright Clause have converged.</p><p><u>For example, none other than the famous Crooner, Bing Crosby, benefited from both protections. Well-known as a prolific and popular recording artist he also benefited from his investments in the, then innovative, recording technologies. Similarly, the Beatles, Beach Boys, as well as many other rock and roll artists, experimental efforts in music performance, recording and production, helped to transform the music industry in both copyrightable artistic expression and patentable inventions. Similarly, film, literary and digital arts reap benefits at the crossroads of both copyright and patent protections.</p><p>Trademarks</p><p></u>Trademark laws have been impacted by numerous changes in the business landscape. They include the internet, Domain names, international rights in a global economy, different venues and avenues for branding, marketing and merchandising, global knock-offs<u> from nations that have a less than stellar respect for intellectual property rights, and international trade agreements. More recently, politicization (or perhaps political correctness) has creeped into the trademark law arena pitting branding rights and protections against first amendment rights.</p><p>Trade Secrets</p><p></u>As with Copyright and Trademark law, trade secrets law includes some of the same issues related to trade agreements. TRIPS required members to have trade secret protection in place. Initially, the United States compliance with this requirement has relied upon the trade secret law of the individual states. That compliance may be supplanted by the recently enacted DTSA. Similarly, the Trans Pacific Partnership (TPP) trade agreement contains intellectual property rights provisions that will trigger required changes to United States statutory Intellectual Property Laws.</p><p>The proposed trade secret legislation also gives rise to several concerns. For instance, there is an absence of a specific definition for trade secret, as well as potential issues of federalism, conflict with state law precedent (despite no preemption), remedies, and the impact on employer/employee relations.</p><p>There is also a real concern that <u>the strengthening of trade secret protection <strong>in conjunction with <mark>the perceived weakening of patent protection</u></strong></mark> (e.g., high rate of invalidating patents in post-grant proceedings before the PTAB and strict limitations on what is patent eligible subject matter) <u><mark>may</mark> very-well <mark>have</mark> the <mark>unintended consequence</mark> of contravening the purpose behind the Patent and Copyright Clause:</u> “to promote the progress of the sciences and the useful arts.” Moreover, the incentive to innovate may very well be usurped by the advantage of withholding patent law disclosure of highly beneficial scientific advancements that directly affect the human condition, alter life expectancies and the evolution of the human species (rather than by mere “natural selection”), and what is the very essence of a human being (for better or worse). Thus, crippling innovation and the progress of the sciences and useful arts.</p><p>Privacy Rights</p><p><u>It is increasingly more difficult to function “off the grid.” The invasive and non-invasive attributes of the internet, the reliance upon the multitude of devices, social media, and information age technologies, and access to big data, all contribute to the decrease in and dilution of the right to privacy. Wittingly or otherwise, the strong libertarian roots of the republic have been replaced by dependence upon these modes of an information-age life. Commentary on the benefits and deficits of this reality are beyond the subject and purpose of this writing. Suffice to acknowledge that the right to privacy has been significantly reduced. The laws that protect these rights are in a constant struggle to maintain those rights while yielding to the demands of the lifestyle and security concerns. Laws that relate to cybersecurity in the global and domestic space create interplay with privacy rights. Legislation, trade agreements and jurisprudence all impact this area of intellectual property. Cross-border theft of trade secrets, competitor espionage, and loss of control over personal data are all implicated in the intellectual property law arena.</p><p>America’s Need For Strong Intellectual Property Protection</p><p>The need for strong protection of intellectual property rights is greater now than it was at the dawn of our republic</u>. Our Forefathers and the Framers of <u>the U.S. Constitution</u> recognized the need to secure those rights in Article 1, Section 8, Clause 8. James Madison provides insight for its significance in the Federalist Papers No. 43 (the only reference to the clause). It is contained in the first Article section dedicated to the enumerated powers of Congress. The clause <u>recognizes the need for: uniformity of the protection of IP rights, securing</u> those <u>rights for the individual</u> rather than the state; <u>and, incentivizing innovation and creative aspirations</u>.</p><p>Underlying this particular enumerated power of Congress is the same struggle that the Framers grappled with throughout the document for the new republic: how to promote a unified republic while protecting individual liberty. The fear of tyranny and protection of the “natural law” individual liberty is a driving theme for the Constitution and throughout the Federalist Papers. For example, in Federalist No. 10, James Madison articulated the important recognition of the “faction” impact on a democracy and a republic. In Federalist No. 51, Madison emphasized the importance of the separation of powers among the three branches of the republic. And in Federalist No. 78, Alexander Hamilton, provided his most significant essay, which described the judiciary as the weakest branch of government and sought the protection of its independence providing the underpinnings for judicial review as recognized thereafter in Marbury v. Madison.</p><p>All of these related themes are relevant to the Patent and Copyright Clause and at the center of the intellectual property protections then and now. The Federalist Papers No. 10 recognition that a faction may influence the law has been playing itself out in the halls of congress in the period of time leading up to the AIA and in connection with the current patent law reform debate. The large tech companies of the past, new tech, new patent-based financial business model entities, and pharma factions have been the drivers, proponents and opponents of certain of these efforts. <u>To be sure, some change is inevitable, and both beneficial and necessary in an environment of rapidly changing technology where the law needs to evolve or conform to new realities</u>. However, changes not premised upon the founding principles of the Constitution and the Patent and Copyright Clause (i.e., uniformity, secured rights for the individual, incentivizing innovation and protecting individual liberty) run afoul of the intended purpose of the constitutional guarantee.</p><p>Although the Sovereign does not benefit directly from the fruits of the innovator, enacting laws that empower the King, and enables the King to remain so, has the same effect as deprivation and diminishment of the individual’s rights and effectively confiscates them from him/her. Specifically, with respect to intellectual property rights, effecting change to the laws that do not adhere to these underlying principles, in favor of the faction that lobbies the most and the best in the quid pro quo of political gain to the governing body threatens to undermine the individual’s intellectual property rights and hinder the greatest economic driver and source of prosperity in the country.</p><p>It is also important to recognize that <u><mark>the</mark> social, political and economic <mark>impact of strong</mark> protections for <strong><mark>i</strong></mark>ntellectual <strong><mark>p</strong></mark>roperty <strong><mark>cannot be overstated</strong></mark>. In the social context, the incentive for disclosure and <strong><mark>innovation is critical</strong>. Solutions for <strong>sustainability</strong> and <strong>climate change</u></strong></mark> (whether natural, man-made or mutually/marginally intertwined) <u><mark>rely upon this</mark> premise. <mark>Likewise</mark>, as we are on the precipice of the ultimate convergence in technologies from the hi-tech digital world and life sciences space, capturing the ability <mark>to <strong>cure</mark> many <mark>diseases</u></strong></mark> and fatal illnesses and providing the true promise of extended longevity in good health and well-being, that is meaningful, productive, and purposeful; <u>this incentive <strong>must be preserved</u></strong>.</p><p>In similar fashion, <u>advancements in <strong><mark>tech</strong></mark>nologies related to the global economy and communications <mark>will enhance</mark> the possibilities for <strong><mark>solutions to</mark> political and cultural <mark>conflicts</mark> that arise <mark>around the globe</strong></mark>. Likewise, the <strong><mark>U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates <u><mark>economy has</mark> always <mark>benefited</mark> when it is at the forefront of innovation and achieves prosperity <mark>from</mark> its <strong><mark>leadership</mark> role <mark>in</mark> technological <mark>advancements</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>Conclusion</p><p>As was the case in 1966, how we move forward today, <u><strong><mark>to solve</mark> the many <mark>problems facing</mark> our country and <mark>the</mark> broader <mark>global community</u></strong></mark> in these “interesting times,” both within and without the laws affecting intellectual property rights, <u><strong><mark>depends upon</u></strong></mark> the “creative energy of man” which must prevail. An achievable goal, dependent on <u><strong>the <mark>strong, stable</mark> and sound protection of <mark>i</mark>ntellectual <mark>p</mark>roperty <mark>rights</u></strong></mark>.</p>
1NC
Off
2
4,329
489
146,525
./documents/ndtceda22/Liberty/BeHo/Liberty-BeHo-Neg-ADA-Fall-Championship-Octas.docx
964,964
N
ADA Fall Championship
Octas
Houston FL - ONL
Gannon,Gates,Nelson - ONL
1AC - NHP 1NC - DA AI spillover, DA Clog, CP executive 2NR - CP
ndtceda22/Liberty/BeHo/Liberty-BeHo-Neg-ADA-Fall-Championship-Octas.docx
2023-01-16 13:44:51
82,663
BeHo
Liberty BeHo
null
Ca.....
Be.....
Ka.....
Ho.....
26,918
Liberty
Liberty
null
null
2,001
ndtceda22
NDT/CEDA College 2022-23
2,022
cx
college
2
1,889,147
A) They’ll compartmentalize — Kavanaugh proves.
Pergram 18
Pergram 18 (Chad Pergram, Congressional reporter. “Amid Kavanaugh cacophony, Congress forges bipartisan agreements on key issues”. October 13, 2018. https://www.foxnews.com/politics/amid-kavanaugh-cacophony-congress-forges-bipartisan-agreements-on-key-issues)
Step back from Kavanaugh Examine what lawmakers from both parties in both chambers accomplished in September and early October, Amid turmoil Congress approved the first revamp of national aviation policy Congress approved a sweeping, bipartisan measure to combat opioid abuse. Democrats praised Republicans for keeping conservative “poison pill” riders out of the appropriations The Senate approved a bipartisan water and infrastructure package. McConnell hailed bipartisanship -- - - even as the senators fought over Kavanaugh in the same breath Schumer also extracted a concession from McConnell lawmakers can find themselves in an imbroglio over a major issue yet forge major bipartisan accords on other Successful lawmakers know they should compartmentalize their disputes
Amid turmoil Congress approved aviation policy measure to combat opioid abuse bipartisan water and infrastructure package McConnell hailed even as senators fought over Kavanaugh in the same breath lawmakers can find themselves in an imbroglio over a major issue yet forge major bipartisan accords on other lawmakers compartmentalize their disputes
Step back from the Kavanaugh cacophony. Examine what lawmakers from both parties in both chambers accomplished in September and early October, with virtually zero fanfare. Amid the turmoil, Congress approved the first revamp of national aviation policy in years. The Senate approved the final version of the legislation 93-6. This came after a staggering six extensions due to bickering and disagreement. Then, Congress approved a sweeping, bipartisan measure to combat opioid abuse. The House okayed the package 393-8. The Senate adopted the measure 98-1. And, there was no government shutdown. The House and Senate came to terms on two bipartisan bills which funded five of the 12 annual spending bills which operate the government. The sides agreed to latch an additional measure to one of the spending plans to fund the remaining seven areas of federal spending through December 7. President Trump briefly threatened to force a government shutdown if lawmakers didn’t include money for his border wall in the plan. But the President ultimately punted that battle until December. Democrats praised Republicans for keeping conservative “poison pill” riders out of the appropriations bills. That decision drew Democratic support for the measures. The Senate approved a bipartisan water and infrastructure package. McConnell hailed the bipartisanship -- - - which descended upon the Senate – even as the senators fought over Kavanaugh. Nearly in the same breath, McConnell derided boisterous, anti-Kavanaugh protesters outside the Capitol as a “mob.” McConnell insisted this week he needed the Senate to clear a slate of 15 conservative judges to lower courts before he could cut senators loose for the midterm elections. McConnell and Schumer appeared at loggerheads. McConnell’s goal was clear: extract the confirmation of these nominees – or tether to Washington vulnerable Democratic senators from battleground states to keep them off the campaign trail. Schumer knew McConnell would ultimately prevail on the nominees after the midterms. So the New York Democrat accepted McConnell’s ransom, permitting the Senate vote on a slate of nominees on Thursday night. Schumer also extracted a concession from McConnell: send senators home until November 13th. One may wonder how lawmakers can find themselves in an imbroglio over a major issue like Kavanaugh – yet forge major bipartisan accords on other. Frankly, that’s just politics. Politics always elicits strange bedfellows. Successful lawmakers know they should compartmentalize their disputes. The enemy today may be your best ally tomorrow
2,596
<h4>A) They’ll compartmentalize — Kavanaugh proves.</h4><p><strong>Pergram 18</strong> (Chad Pergram, Congressional reporter. “Amid Kavanaugh cacophony, Congress forges bipartisan agreements on key issues”. October 13, 2018. https://www.foxnews.com/politics/amid-kavanaugh-cacophony-congress-forges-bipartisan-agreements-on-key-issues<u>)</p><p>Step back from</u> the <u>Kavanaugh</u> cacophony. <u>Examine what lawmakers from both parties in both chambers accomplished</u> <u>in September and early October,</u> with virtually zero fanfare. <u><strong><mark>Amid</u></strong></mark> the <u><strong><mark>turmoil</u></strong></mark>, <u><mark>Congress approved</mark> the first revamp of national <mark>aviation policy</u></mark> in years. The Senate approved the final version of the legislation 93-6. This came after a staggering six extensions due to bickering and disagreement. Then, <u>Congress approved a sweeping, bipartisan <mark>measure to combat opioid abuse</mark>.</u> The House okayed the package 393-8. The Senate adopted the measure 98-1. And, there was no government shutdown. The House and Senate came to terms on two bipartisan bills which funded five of the 12 annual spending bills which operate the government. The sides agreed to latch an additional measure to one of the spending plans to fund the remaining seven areas of federal spending through December 7. President Trump briefly threatened to force a government shutdown if lawmakers didn’t include money for his border wall in the plan. But the President ultimately punted that battle until December. <u>Democrats praised Republicans for keeping conservative “poison pill” riders out of the appropriations</u> bills. That decision drew Democratic support for the measures. <u>The Senate approved a <mark>bipartisan water and infrastructure package</mark>. <mark>McConnell hailed</u></mark> the <u>bipartisanship</p><p>--</p><p>-</p><p>-</p><p></u> which descended upon the Senate – <u><strong><mark>even as</mark> the <mark>senators</mark> <mark>fought over Kavanaugh</u></strong></mark>. Nearly <u><strong><mark>in the same breath</u></strong></mark>, McConnell derided boisterous, anti-Kavanaugh protesters outside the Capitol as a “mob.” McConnell insisted this week he needed the Senate to clear a slate of 15 conservative judges to lower courts before he could cut senators loose for the midterm elections. McConnell and Schumer appeared at loggerheads. McConnell’s goal was clear: extract the confirmation of these nominees – or tether to Washington vulnerable Democratic senators from battleground states to keep them off the campaign trail. Schumer knew McConnell would ultimately prevail on the nominees after the midterms. So the New York Democrat accepted McConnell’s ransom, permitting the Senate vote on a slate of nominees on Thursday night. <u>Schumer also extracted a concession from McConnell</u>: send senators home until November 13th. One may wonder how <u><mark>lawmakers can find themselves in an <strong>imbroglio</strong></mark> <mark>over a major issue</u></mark> like Kavanaugh – <u><strong><mark>yet forge major bipartisan accords on other</u></strong></mark>. Frankly, that’s just politics. Politics always elicits strange bedfellows. <u>Successful <mark>lawmakers </mark>know they should <strong><mark>compartmentalize their disputes</u></strong></mark>. The enemy today may be your best ally tomorrow</p>
2AC
AT – DA
2AC Omnibus DA – T/L
7,626
363
55,628
./documents/hspolicy20/Interlake/GaQi/Interlake-Ganesh-Qian-Aff-Alta-Quarters.docx
730,607
A
Alta
Quarters
New Trier RW
Anthony Wintchell, Josh Lamet, Maddie Pieropan
1AC - 13th 1NC - K-Settlerism CP-Courts PIC-Domestic Terrorists DA-Shutdown Case 2NC - K-Settlerism Case 1NR - PIC-Domestic Terrorists 2NR - PIC-Domestic Terrorists Case
hspolicy20/Interlake/GaQi/Interlake-Ganesh-Qian-Aff-Alta-Quarters.docx
null
62,395
GaQi
Interlake GaQi
null
Ha.....
Ga.....
Je.....
Qi.....
21,651
Interlake
Interlake
WA
null
1,019
hspolicy20
HS Policy 2020-21
2,020
cx
hs
2
2,041,183
US has been the cause of anti-imperialism globally – four waves of empire building, and dismantlement are intrinsically US driven.
Deudney & Ikenberry 15. Daniel Deudney, Johns Hopkins University G. John Ikenberry, Princeton University “America’s Impact: The End of Empire and the Globalization of the Westphalian System”, August 2015, http://scholar.princeton.edu/sites/default/files/gji3/files/am-impact-dd-gji-final-1-august-2015.pdf) **two charts from the article
Daniel Deudney & John Ikenberry 15. Daniel Deudney, Johns Hopkins University G. John Ikenberry, Princeton University “America’s Impact: The End of Empire and the Globalization of the Westphalian System”, August 2015, http://scholar.princeton.edu/sites/default/files/gji3/files/am-impact-dd-gji-final-1-august-2015.pdf) **two charts from the article
, this argument undercuts, modifies, and qualifies characterizations held by so many of the U S as essentially imperial the U S is the first anti-imperial and post-imperial great power in the global system. Against the four waves of empire building and dismantlement it becomes possible to see the many ways in which the U S played important anti-imperial, anti-colonial, and pro-Westphalian roles In each of the four waves of empire building and dismantlement the U S had an impact The U S was the first “new nation” to emerge from a rebellion against European imperial The U S supported independence of other European settler colonies throughout the Americas and with the Monroe Doctrine helped sustain their independence against European efforts to recolonize parts of the Americas the U S despite its great relative power did not establish an empire of its own of any significance or duration during the 20th century, the U S pushed European decolonization, facilitating the breakup of second wave empires In the world wars the U S played an important role in thwarting Germany, Japan, and Italy In the second half of the 20th century the U S played decisive roles, both ideological and military in thwarting the fourth wave of empire building, the expansion of the communist great power, the Soviet Union as well as communist coups and revolutions in many weak and small independent states. The U S played a variety of important roles in building and strengthening Westphalian institutions moderating inter-state anarchy and facilitating the ability of states to survive as independent members of international society From its inception the U S was precocious in its support for the law of nations institutions of the society of states the laws of war neutrality and international law a means of restraining war and aggression In the 19th and 20th centuries the U S inspired and helped legitimate anti-colonial and anti-imperial independence movements and national liberation struggles among peoples struggling against empires all over the world the U S led the efforts to institutionalize Westphalian norms of non-aggression and sovereign independence the American-led liberal international order institutionalized free trade and multilateral cooperation providing infrastructure for a global economic system enabling smaller and weaker states to sustain their sovereign the American system of military alliances contributed to the dampening of violent conflicts among allied states protecting the Westphalian system from the return of violent conflict and empire-building. these varied American activities in the world clearly provide strong preliminary evidence for our claim that the U S has significantly contributed to the dismantlement of empires, the thwarting of further empire-building, and to the universalization, institutionalization, and stabilization of the Westphalian state-system.
the U S is the first anti-imperial great power Against the four waves of empire dismantlement, it becomes possible to see the ways in which the U S played anti-imperial anti-colonial roles The U S supported independence of other colonies and with the Monroe Doctrine helped sustain independence against European efforts the U S did not establish an empire of its own the U S pushed European decolonization facilitating the breakup of second wave empires thwarting Germany, Japan, and Italy played decisive roles in thwarting the Soviet Union as well as communist coups and revolutions moderating inter-state anarchy, and facilitating ability of states to survive as independent members of in support for international law a means of restraining war and aggression inspired legitimate anti-colonial independence movements against empires all over the world providing infrastructure for a global economic system enabling smaller states to sustain their sovereign the system of alliances contributed to the dampening of violent conflicts protecting the system from the return of violent conflict and empire-building. significantly contributed to dismantlement of empires, thwarting further building and universalization institutionalization and stabilization of Westphalian state-system.
In contemporary debates, this argument undercuts, modifies, and qualifies characterizations held by so many of the United States as essentially imperial, and the American order as an empire. In our rendering, the United State is not the last Western empire, but the first anti-imperial and post-imperial great power in the global system. Our argument is thus focused on the consequences of American foreign policy for the evolution of the international system, and we do not in this confined treatment offer an explanation for the origins of U.S. foreign policy. In short, we offer an argument about impacts rather than the sources of America’s antiimperial and pro-Westphalian role. Against the backdrop of this evolution of the international system and the four waves of empire building and dismantlement, it becomes possible to see more clearly the many ways in which the United States played important anti-imperial, anti-colonial, and pro-Westphalian roles. 16 The Pattern of American Anti-Imperial, Anti-Colonial, and Pro-Westphalian Impacts In each of the four waves of empire building and dismantlement, the United States had an impact. The United States was the first “new nation” to emerge from a rebellion against European imperial rule during the first wave of modern empire. The United States also supported the independence of other European settler colonies throughout the Americas and, with the Monroe Doctrine, helped sustain their independence against European efforts to recolonize parts of the Americas. In the second wave of late 19th century empire-building, the United States, despite its great relative power, did not establish an empire of its own of any significance or duration. And during the latter part of the 20th century, the United States pushed European decolonization, thus facilitating the breakup of second wave empires. In the great world wars in the 20th century, the United States played an important role in thwarting a third wave of imperial projects of Germany, Japan, and Italy. In the second half of the 20th century, the United States played decisive roles, both ideological and military, in thwarting the fourth wave of empire building, the expansion of the communist great power, the Soviet Union, as well as communist coups and revolutions in many weak and small independent states. The United States also played a variety of important roles in building and strengthening Westphalian institutions, moderating inter-state anarchy, and facilitating the ability of states to survive as independent members of international society . From its inception, the United States was precocious in its support for the law of nations, the institutions of the society of states, particularly the laws of war and neutrality, and public international law, as a means of restraining war and aggression. In both the 19th and 20th centuries, the United States, first regionally and then globally, inspired and helped legitimate anti-colonial and anti-imperial independence movements and national liberation struggles among peoples struggling against empires all over the world. In the 20th century, the United States led the efforts to institutionalize Westphalian norms of non-aggression and sovereign independence, first with the League of Nations and then with the United Nations Charter. In the second half of the 20th century, the American-led liberal international order institutionalized free trade and multilateral cooperation, thus providing the infrastructure for a global economic system, thus enabling smaller and weaker states to sustain their sovereign. Also in the second half of the 20th century, the American system of military alliances contributed to the dampening of violent conflicts among allied states, particularly in Europe and East Asia, thus protecting the Westphalian system from the return of violent conflict and empire-building. Taken together, these varied American activities in the world clearly provide strong preliminary evidence for our claim that the United States has significantly contributed to the dismantlement of empires, the thwarting of further empire-building, and to the universalization, institutionalization, and stabilization of the Westphalian state-system.
4,241
<h4>US has been the cause of <u>anti-imperialism</u> globally – four waves of empire building, and dismantlement are intrinsically US driven.</h4><p>Daniel<strong> Deudney & </strong>John<strong> Ikenberry 15. <u>Daniel Deudney, Johns Hopkins University G. John Ikenberry, Princeton University “America’s Impact: The End of Empire and the Globalization of the Westphalian System”, August 2015, http://scholar.princeton.edu/sites/default/files/gji3/files/am-impact-dd-gji-final-1-august-2015.pdf) **two charts from the article</p><p></u></strong>In contemporary debates<u>, this argument undercuts, modifies, and qualifies characterizations held by so many of the <strong>U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates<u> as <strong>essentially imperial</u></strong>, and the American order as an empire. In our rendering, <u><mark>the</u> <u><strong>U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tate <u><mark>is</u></mark> not the last Western empire, but <u><strong><mark>the first anti-imperial</mark> and post-imperial <mark>great power</mark> in the global system.</u></strong> Our argument is thus focused on the consequences of American foreign policy for the evolution of the international system, and we do not in this confined treatment offer an explanation for the origins of U.S. foreign policy. In short, we offer an argument about impacts rather than the sources of America’s antiimperial and pro-Westphalian role. <u><mark>Against</u></mark> the backdrop of this evolution of the international system and <u><mark>the four waves of empire </mark>building and <mark>dismantlement</u>, <u>it becomes possible to see</u></mark> more clearly <u><mark>the</mark> many <mark>ways in which the</u></mark> <u><strong><mark>U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates <u><mark>played</mark> important <strong><mark>anti-imperial</mark>, <mark>anti-colonial</mark>, and pro-Westphalian <mark>roles</u></strong></mark>. 16 The Pattern of American Anti-Imperial, Anti-Colonial, and Pro-Westphalian Impacts <u>In each of the four waves of empire building and dismantlement</u>, <u>the</u> <u><strong>U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates <u>had an impact</u>. <u>The</u> <u><strong>U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates <u>was the first “new nation” to emerge from a rebellion against European imperial</u> rule during the first wave of modern empire. <u><mark>The</u> <u><strong>U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates also <u><mark>supported</u></mark> the <u><mark>independence of other </mark>European settler <mark>colonies</u></mark> <u>throughout the Americas <mark>and</u></mark>, <u><mark>with the Monroe Doctrine</u></mark>, <u><mark>helped sustain</mark> their <mark>independence against European efforts</mark> to recolonize parts of the Americas</u>. In the second wave of late 19th century empire-building, <u><mark>the</u></mark> <u><strong><mark>U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates, <u>despite its great relative power</u>, <u><strong><mark>did not establish an empire of its own</mark> of any significance or duration</u></strong>. And <u>during the</u> latter part of the <u>20th century, <mark>the</u></mark> <u><strong><mark>U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates <u><mark>pushed European decolonization</mark>,</u> thus <u><strong><mark>facilitating the breakup of second wave empires</u></strong></mark>. <u>In the </u>great<u> world wars</u> in the 20th century, <u>the</u> <u><strong>U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates <u>played an important role in <mark>thwarting</u></mark> a third wave of imperial projects of <u><strong><mark>Germany, Japan, and Italy</u></strong></mark>. <u>In the second half of the 20th century</u>, <u>the</u> <u><strong>U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates <u><mark>played</u> <u><strong>decisive roles</mark>, both ideological and military</u></strong>, <u><mark>in thwarting</mark> the fourth wave of empire building, the expansion of the communist great power, <mark>the Soviet Union</u></mark>, <u><strong><mark>as well as communist coups and revolutions</mark> in many weak and small independent states. </u></strong> <u>The</u> <u><strong>U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates also <u>played a variety of important roles in <strong>building and strengthening Westphalian institutions</u></strong>, <u><strong><mark>moderating inter-state anarchy</u></strong>, <u>and</u> <u><strong>facilitating</u></strong></mark> <u>the <mark>ability of states to survive <strong>as independent members of</mark> international </strong>society</p><p></u>. <u>From its inception</u>, <u>the</u> <u><strong>U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates <u>was precocious <mark>in</mark> its <mark>support for</mark> the <strong>law of nations</u></strong>, the <u><strong>institutions of the society of states</u></strong>, particularly <u><strong>the laws of war</u></strong> and <u>neutrality</u>, <u>and</u> public <u><strong><mark>international law</u></strong></mark>, as <u><mark>a means of <strong>restraining war and aggression</u></strong></mark>. <u>In</u> both <u>the 19th and 20th centuries</u>, <u>the</u> <u><strong>U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates, first regionally and then globally, <u><mark>inspired</mark> and helped <strong><mark>legitimate anti-colonial</mark> and anti-imperial <mark>independence movements</u></strong></mark> <u>and national liberation struggles among peoples struggling <strong><mark>against empires all over the world</u></strong></mark>. In the 20th century, <u>the</u> <u><strong>U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates <u>led the efforts to institutionalize Westphalian norms of non-aggression and sovereign independence</u>, first with the League of Nations and then with the United Nations Charter. In the second half of the 20th century, <u>the American-led liberal international order institutionalized free trade and multilateral cooperation</u>, thus <u><mark>providing</u></mark> the <u><strong><mark>infrastructure for a global economic system</u></strong></mark>, thus <u><mark>enabling smaller</mark> and weaker <mark>states to <strong>sustain their sovereign</u></strong></mark>. Also in the second half of the 20th century, <u><mark>the</mark> American <mark>system of</mark> military <mark>alliances contribute<strong>d to the dampening of violent</mark> <mark>conflicts</mark> among allied states</u></strong>, particularly in Europe and East Asia, thus <u><strong><mark>protecting</mark> <mark>the</mark> Westphalian <mark>system from the return of violent conflict and empire-building.</mark> </u></strong> Taken together, <u>these varied American activities in the world clearly provide strong preliminary evidence for our claim that the U</u>nited <u>S</u>tates<u> has <strong><mark>significantly contributed to</mark> the <mark>dismantlement of empires</strong>,</mark> the <strong><mark>thwarting</mark> of <mark>further</mark> empire-<mark>building</mark>, <mark>and</mark> to the <mark>universalization</mark>, <mark>institutionalization</mark>, <mark>and</mark> <mark>stabilization</mark> <mark>of</mark> the <mark>Westphalian state-system.</strong></mark> </p></u>
2AC – Round 5 – Michigan
Case
1AC---Advantage
1,240,506
311
60,508
./documents/hspolicy20/Westminster/YuLi/Westminster-Yu-Li-Aff-Michigan-Round5.docx
741,952
A
Michigan
5
North Broward DR
David Kilpatrick
1ac FRT 1nc Onticide K 2nr K
hspolicy20/Westminster/YuLi/Westminster-Yu-Li-Aff-Michigan-Round5.docx
null
63,213
YuLi
Westminster YuLi
null
Aa.....
Yu.....
Co.....
Li.....
21,854
Westminster
Westminster
GA
null
1,019
hspolicy20
HS Policy 2020-21
2,020
cx
hs
2
2,094,096
Political parties in the United States have grown farther apart, locking in partisanship and political gridlock.
Jones 19 ]
Jones 19 [Brad Jones, A research associate at Pew Research Center, involved in all stages of the research process at the center, doctorate in political science from the University of Wisconsin, Madison, “Republicans and Democrats have grown further apart on what the nation’s top priorities should be, https://www.pewresearch.org/fact-tank/2019/02/05/republicans-and-democrats-have-grown-further-apart-on-what-the-nations-top-priorities-should-be/] JJ
Republicans and Democrats have long held differing views about policy solutions, but throughout most of the recent past there was rough partisan agreement about the set of issues Republicans and Democrats have been moving further apart not just in their political values and approaches to addressing the issues facing the country but also on issues they identify as top priorities our most recent survey. there is virtually no common ground in the priorities for Democrats and Republicans. Among Democrats health care costs, education, the environment Medicare and assistance for poor and needy people top the list of priorities ( None of these is among the five leading top priorities for Republicans and Republican-leaning independents Conversely, the two priorities named by more than seven-in-ten Republicans – terrorism and the economy – are cited by far smaller shares of Democrats. The partisan gap is particularly wide for a handful of issues For instance, two-thirds of Democrats and Democratic leaners identify global climate change as a top priority, while just 21% of Republicans and Republican leaners say the same. 1999 Ten years later
Republicans and Democrats have been moving further apart in political values there is no common ground Among Democrats health care costs, education, the environment top priorities ( None of these is among the five leading priorities for Republicans The partisan gap is wide for handful of issues two-thirds of Democrats identify climate change as top priority, while just 21% of Republicans
Republicans and Democrats have long held differing views about policy solutions, but throughout most of the recent past there was rough partisan agreement about the set of issues that were the top priorities for the nation. However, that is less and less the case. Republicans and Democrats have been moving further apart not just in their political values and approaches to addressing the issues facing the country, but also on the issues they identify as top priorities for the president and Congress to address. For more than two decades, Pew Research Center has tracked the public’s priorities, including in our most recent survey. While many issues are considered high priorities by majorities in both parties today, there is virtually no common ground in the priorities that rise to the top of the lists for Democrats and Republicans. Among Democrats and Democratic-leaning independents, health care costs, education, the environment, Medicare and assistance for poor and needy people top the list of priorities (all are named as top priorities by seven-in-ten or more Democrats). None of these is among the five leading top priorities for Republicans and Republican-leaning independents (Medicare and health care costs rank sixth and seventh, respectively). Conversely, the two priorities named by more than seven-in-ten Republicans – terrorism and the economy – are cited by far smaller shares of Democrats. The partisan gap is particularly wide for a handful of issues. For instance, two-thirds of Democrats and Democratic leaners identify global climate change as a top priority, while just 21% of Republicans and Republican leaners say the same. Similarly, although only 31% of Democrats say that strengthening the military should be a top priority, 65% of Republicans hold this view. Republicans were much more aligned than they are today. In 1999, improving the educational system topped the list of priorities for both Republicans and Democrats, and four of the top five issues for Republicans were listed among the Democrats’ top five issues as well. Ten years later, in the wake of the financial crisis, three issues (economy, jobs and terrorism) topped the list among both Republicans and Democrats (although they ranked them slightly differently). Five years ago, the economy, the job situation and Social Security all ranked among the top five issues in both parties.
2,386
<h4>Political parties in the United States have grown farther apart, locking in partisanship and political gridlock. </h4><p><u><strong>Jones 19</u></strong> [Brad Jones, A research associate at Pew Research Center, involved in all stages of the research process at the center, doctorate in political science from the University of Wisconsin, Madison, “Republicans and Democrats have grown further apart on what the nation’s top priorities should be, <u>https://www.pewresearch.org/fact-tank/2019/02/05/republicans-and-democrats-have-grown-further-apart-on-what-the-nations-top-priorities-should-be/</u><strong>] </strong>JJ</p><p><u><strong>Republicans and Democrats have long held differing views about policy solutions, but throughout most of the recent past there was rough partisan agreement about the set of issues </u></strong>that were the top priorities for the nation.</p><p>However, that is less and less the case. <u><strong><mark>Republicans and Democrats have been moving further apart </mark>not just <mark>in</mark> their <mark>political values</mark> and approaches to addressing the issues facing the country</u></strong>, <u><strong>but also on </u></strong>the <u><strong>issues they identify as top priorities</u></strong> for the president and Congress to address.</p><p>For more than two decades, Pew Research Center has tracked the public’s priorities, including in <u>our most recent survey<strong>.</p><p></u></strong>While many issues are considered high priorities by majorities in both parties today, <u><strong><mark>there is</mark> virtually <mark>no common ground</mark> in the priorities</u></strong> that rise to the top of the lists <u><strong>for Democrats and Republicans.</p><p><mark>Among Democrats</u></strong></mark> and Democratic-leaning independents, <u><strong><mark>health care costs, education, the environment</u></strong></mark>, <u><strong>Medicare and assistance for poor and needy people <mark>top</mark> the list of <mark>priorities (</u></strong></mark>all are named as top priorities by seven-in-ten or more Democrats). <u><strong><mark>None of these is among the five leading</mark> top <mark>priorities for Republicans</mark> and Republican-leaning independents</u></strong> (Medicare and health care costs rank sixth and seventh, respectively). <u><strong>Conversely, the two priorities named by more than seven-in-ten Republicans – terrorism and the economy – are cited by far smaller shares of Democrats.</p><p><mark>The partisan gap is</mark> particularly <mark>wide for</mark> a <mark>handful of issues</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong>For instance, <mark>two-thirds of Democrats</mark> and Democratic leaners <mark>identify</mark> global <mark>climate change as</mark> a <mark>top priority, while just 21% of Republicans</mark> and Republican leaners say the same.</u></strong> Similarly, although only 31% of Democrats say that strengthening the military should be a top priority, 65% of Republicans hold this view.</p><p>Republicans were much more aligned than they are today. In<u> 1999</u>, improving the educational system topped the list of priorities for both Republicans and Democrats, and four of the top five issues for Republicans were listed among the Democrats’ top five issues as well. <u>Ten years later</u>, in the wake of the financial crisis, three issues (economy, jobs and terrorism) topped the list among both Republicans and Democrats (although they ranked them slightly differently). Five years ago, the economy, the job situation and Social Security all ranked among the top five issues in both parties.</p>
1AC
null
1AC—Advantage: Partisanship
905,265
178
62,538
./documents/hsld20/Bishops/Ch/Bishops-Chandra-Aff-Arthur-Round4.docx
854,184
A
Arthur
4
Lake Highland Prep MS
Jharick Shields
1AC - US Aff 1NC - Abortion PIC Indigenous PIC Uninformed Voter DA Case 1AR - Case Uninformed Voter DA Abortion PIC Indigenous PIC 2NR - Abortion PIC PIC's Indigenous PIC Condo Case 2AR - Case Abortion PIC PIC's Indigenous PIC
hsld20/Bishops/Ch/Bishops-Chandra-Aff-Arthur-Round4.docx
null
72,727
AdCh
Bishops AdCh
null
Ad.....
Ch.....
null
null
24,431
Bishops
Bishops
CA
null
1,028
hsld20
HS LD 2020-21
2,020
ld
hs
1
2,179,981
Only a total ban solves – preserving a shred of doubt that capability exists causes crisis instability.
Johnson 20
Johnson and Krabill 1/31/20 — (James Johnson, Postdoctoral Research Fellow at the James Martin Center for Nonproliferation Studies at the Middlebury Institute of International Studies (MIIS), Monterey. His latest book project is entitled, Artificial Intelligence & the Future of Warfare: USA, China, and Strategic Stability, Eleanor Krabill, Master of Arts in Nonproliferation and Terrorism candidate at Middlebury Institute of International Studies (MIIS), Monterey, “AI, CYBERSPACE, AND NUCLEAR WEAPONS”, War on the Rocks, 1-31-20, Available Online at https://warontherocks.com/2020/01/ai-cyberspace-and-nuclear-weapons/, accessed 1-31-20, HKR-AM) ***NC3 = nuclear command, control, and communication systems
The blurring of cyber offense-defense will likely compound an adversary’s fear of a preemptive strike and increase first-mover incentives. In extremis, strategic ambiguity caused by this issue may trigger use-them-or-lose-them situations Chinese analysts view the vulnerability of China’s NC3 to cyber infiltrations — even if an attacker’s objective was limited to cyber espionage — as a highly escalatory national security threat even a modicum of uncertainty about the effectiveness of AI-augmented cyber capabilities during a crisis or conflict would, therefore, reduce both sides’ risk tolerance, increasing the incentive to strike preemptively. Against the backdrop of a competitive strategic environment in which states are inclined to assume the worst of others’ intentions, one state’s efforts to enhance the survivability of its strategic forces may be viewed by others as a threat to their nuclear retaliatory capability or second-strike capacity. During crisis conditions, for example, an offensive AI cyber tool that succeeds in compromising an adversary’s nuclear weapon systems — resulting in an “asymmetric information” situation — could cause either or both sides to overstate (or understate) their retaliatory capabilities, and in turn, be more inclined to act in a risky and escalatory manner. It is now thought possible that a cyber attack (i.e., spoofing, hacking, manipulation, and digital jamming) could infiltrate a nuclear weapons system, threaten the integrity of its communications, and ultimately (and possibly unbeknown to its target) gain control of both its nuclear and non-nuclear command and control systems. recent reports of successful cyber attacks against dual-use, early-warning systems suggests that cyber intrusions against NC3 is fast becoming a reality. the perception alone that this capability exists would be inherently destabilizing several states, including the United States, have already shifted their strategic force postures and doctrine to reflect these emergent threat perceptions. Even if nuclear early-warning systems might eventually detect the subversion, heightened levels of uncertainty and tension caused by an alert may impel the respective militaries to put their nuclear weapons on high alert status. This skewed assessment in the context of nuclear weapons, ready to launch at a moment’s notice, would likely precipitate worst-case scenario thinking that may spark inadvertent escalation. , AI-augmented cyber intelligence gathering tools (or espionage) used during a crisis could easily be misinterpreted by an adversary as a prelude for a preemptive attack on its nuclear force.
blurring cyber offense-defense will compound fear of preemptive strike and increase first-mover incentives trigger use-them-or-lose-them situations Chinese analysts view NC3 cyber infiltrations as a highly escalatory threat a modicum of uncertainty about the effectiveness of AI-augmented cyber capabilities during a crisis would increa the incentive to strike preemptively states are inclined to assume the worst a cyber attack could infiltrate a nuclear system threaten communications gain control of command and control cyber intrusions against NC3 is becoming reality the perception alone this capability exists would be inherently destabilizing This would likely precipitate worst-case thinking that spark escalation cyber intelligence gathering used could easily be misinterpreted as a prelude for a preemptive attack on its nuclear force.
During the early stages of a cyber operation, it is generally unclear whether an adversary intends to collect intelligence or prepare for an offensive attack. The blurring of cyber offense-defense will likely compound an adversary’s fear of a preemptive strike and increase first-mover incentives. In extremis, strategic ambiguity caused by this issue may trigger use-them-or-lose-them situations. Open-source research suggests, for example, that Chinese analysts view the vulnerability of China’s NC3 to cyber infiltrations — even if an attacker’s objective was limited to cyber espionage — as a highly escalatory national security threat. By contrast, Russian analysts tend to view Russia’s nuclear command, control, communications, and intelligence (C3I) network as more isolated, and thus, relatively insulated from cyber attacks. To be sure, even a modicum of uncertainty about the effectiveness of AI-augmented cyber capabilities during a crisis or conflict would, therefore, reduce both sides’ risk tolerance, increasing the incentive to strike preemptively. Furthermore, any potential advantages from enhanced reassurances premised on comprehensive intelligence would require equal access to intelligence and analysis systems between great and rising powers. Shared confidence in the accuracy and credibility of these systems would also be needed. Most optimistically, the intentions of all rival states would need to be genuinely benign. In a world of “revisionist” rising powers, the prospects of such a rosy outcome seems improbable. Against the backdrop of a competitive strategic environment in which states are inclined to assume the worst of others’ intentions, one state’s efforts to enhance the survivability of its strategic forces may be viewed by others as a threat to their nuclear retaliatory capability or second-strike capacity. During crisis conditions, for example, an offensive AI cyber tool that succeeds in compromising an adversary’s nuclear weapon systems — resulting in an “asymmetric information” situation — could cause either or both sides to overstate (or understate) their retaliatory capabilities, and in turn, be more inclined to act in a risky and escalatory manner. It is now thought possible that a cyber attack (i.e., spoofing, hacking, manipulation, and digital jamming) could infiltrate a nuclear weapons system, threaten the integrity of its communications, and ultimately (and possibly unbeknown to its target) gain control of both its nuclear and non-nuclear command and control systems. AI has not yet evolved to a point where it could credibly threaten the survivability of a state’s nuclear second-strike capability. However, recent reports of successful cyber attacks against dual-use, early-warning systems suggests that cyber intrusions against NC3 is fast becoming a reality. Irrespective of the technical feasibility of “left of launch” operations (i.e., a preemptive operation to prevent an adversary launching its missiles) against NC3 systems, the perception alone that this capability exists would be inherently destabilizing. Moreover, while the veracity of these counterforce capabilities remains highly contested, several states, including the United States, have already shifted their strategic force postures and doctrine to reflect these emergent threat perceptions. Somewhat paradoxically, AI applications designed to enhance cyber security for nuclear forces could simultaneously make cyber-dependent nuclear weapon systems (e.g., communications, data processing, or early-warning sensors) more vulnerable to cyber attacks. Pathways to Escalation AI-enhanced cyber attacks against nuclear systems would be almost impossible to detect and authenticate, let alone attribute, within the short timeframe for initiating a nuclear strike. According to open sources, operators at the North American Aerospace Defense Command have less than three minutes to assess and confirm initial indications from early-warning systems of an incoming attack. This compressed decision-making timeframe could put political leaders under intense pressure to make a decision to escalate during a crisis, with incomplete (and possibly false) information about a situation. Ironically, new technologies designed to enhance information, such as 5G networks, machine learning, big-data analytics, and quantum computing, can also undermine its clear and reliable flow and communication, which is critical for effective deterrence. Advances in AI could also exacerbate this cyber security challenge by enabling improvements to cyber offense. Machine learning and AI, by automating advanced persistent threat (or “hunting for weaknesses”) operations, might dramatically reduce the extensive manpower resources and high levels of technical skill required to execute advanced persistent threat operations, especially against hardened nuclear targets. Information Warfare Could Lead to Escalation Machine learning, big data analytics, and sensing technologies, supported by 5G networks, could alert commanders of incoming threats with increased speed and precision. This could result in fewer accidents in the sensitive command and control environment. However, this technological coalescence will also amplify risks of escalation in two ways: First, AI machine learning used as a force multiplier for cyber offense — e.g., data poisoning spoofing, deepfakes, manipulation, hacking, and digital jamming — would be considerably more difficult to detect, especially if an attacker used advanced persistent threat tools in the spectrum-contested environment. Second, in the unlikely event that an attack was successfully detected, threat identification (or attribution) at machine speed would be virtually impossible. In short, the key security challenge lies not in making more convincing fakes, but in detecting the spread of false information. AI machine learning techniques might also exacerbate the escalation risks by manipulating the digital information landscape, where decisions about the use of nuclear weapons are made. Given current tensions between the United States and other nuclear powers — China, Russia, and North Korea — it is possible to imagine unprovoked escalation caused by a malicious third-party (or state-proxy) clandestine action. During a crisis, the inability of a state to determine an attacker’s intent may lead an actor to conclude that an attack (threatened or actual) was intended to undermine its nuclear deterrent. For example, an AI-enabled, third-party-generated deepfake, coupled with data-poisoning cyber attacks, could spark an escalatory crisis between two (or more) nuclear states. As demonstrated at a recent workshop hosted by the International Institute for Strategic Studies, malign manipulation of input data received by early-warning systems might not only subvert the output of AI systems in a specific situation, but also undermine the reliability of an entire algorithm network environment if executed during the program’s training phase. Consider the following fictional scenarios, in which the use of deepfakes and spoofing by nefarious third-party, non-state, or state-proxy actors triggers unintentional and unprovoked escalation. Fictional Example #1: Deepfakes To incite conflict between two rival states, State A uses proxy hackers to launch deepfake video or audio material, which depicts senior military commanders of State B conspiring to launch a preemptive strike on State C. Then, this deepfake footage is deliberately leaked into State C’s AI-augmented intelligence collection and analysis systems, provoking State C to escalate the situation with strategic consequences. State B responds to the threat of preemption with a retaliatory strike. Escalation in this case would, of course, be deliberate. Thus, increased escalation risk as a result of technology is not always inadvertent or accidental. For example, escalation risks caused by the aggressive U.S.-Soviet expansion of counterforce technology during the Cold War reflected shifting nuclear doctrines on both sides (i.e., away from assured mutual destruction), not the pursuit of these technologies themselves. Moreover, AI technology could enable an adversary to pursue a predetermined escalatory path. In fact, AI may be developed precisely for this purpose. Fictional Example #2: Spoofing State A launches a malicious AI-enhanced cyber attack to spoof State B’s AI-enabled autonomous sensor platforms and automated target recognition systems, in such a way that the weapon system (a human-supervised automated target recognition system) is fooled into interpreting a civilian object (a commercial airliner, for example) as a military target. State B, based on subverted information and the inability of human supervisors to detect the spoofed imagery in time to take corrective action, accidentally (and unintentionally) escalates the situation. In this example, the spoofing attack on the weapon systems’ algorithm is executed in such a way that the imagery appears to the recognition system as indistinguishable from a valid military target, escalating the situation based on a false premise that would be unlikely to fool the human eye. AI experts have proven that even when data appears accurate to AI image recognition software, these systems often hallucinate objects that do not exist. The explainability (or “black box”) problem associated with AI applications may further compound these dynamics. Insufficient understanding of how and why AI algorithms reach a particular judgment or decision would complicate the task of determining if datasets had been deliberately compromised to manufacture false outcomes — such as attacking incorrect targets or misdirecting allies during combat. Furthermore, as humans and AI team up to accomplish particular missions, the opacity associated with how AI systems reach a decision may cause an operator to have either too much or too little confidence in a system’s performance. Consequently, unless the system’s machine learn­ing algorithm is terminated, once deployed at the end of the training phase it could potentially learn something it was not intended to, or even perform a task or mission that its human designers do not expect it to do. This issue is one of the main reasons why the use of AI machine learning in the context of weapon systems is, for now, confined to mostly experimental research. Even if nuclear early-warning systems might eventually detect the subversion, heightened levels of uncertainty and tension caused by an alert may impel the respective militaries to put their nuclear weapons on high alert status. This skewed assessment in the context of nuclear weapons, ready to launch at a moment’s notice, would likely precipitate worst-case scenario thinking that may spark inadvertent escalation. Therefore, AI-augmented cyber intelligence gathering tools (or espionage) used during a crisis could easily be misinterpreted by an adversary as a prelude for a preemptive attack on its nuclear force.
11,034
<h4>Only a <u>total ban</u> solves – preserving a <u>shred of doubt</u> that capability exists causes <u>crisis instability</u>. </h4><p><strong>Johnson</strong> and Krabill 1/31/<strong>20</strong> — (James Johnson, Postdoctoral Research Fellow at the James Martin Center for Nonproliferation Studies at the Middlebury Institute of International Studies (MIIS), Monterey. His latest book project is entitled, Artificial Intelligence & the Future of Warfare: USA, China, and Strategic Stability, Eleanor Krabill, Master of Arts in Nonproliferation and Terrorism candidate at Middlebury Institute of International Studies (MIIS), Monterey, “AI, CYBERSPACE, AND NUCLEAR WEAPONS”, War on the Rocks, 1-31-20, Available Online at https://warontherocks.com/2020/01/ai-cyberspace-and-nuclear-weapons/<u>, accessed 1-31-20, HKR-AM) ***NC3 = nuclear command, control, and communication systems</p><p></u>During the early stages of a cyber operation, it is generally unclear whether an adversary intends to collect intelligence or prepare for an offensive attack.<u> The <mark>blurring </mark>of <mark>cyber offense-defense</mark> <mark>will</mark> likely <mark>compound</mark> an adversary’s <mark>fear</mark> <mark>of</mark> a <strong><mark>preemptive strike</strong></mark> <mark>and increase <strong>first-mover incentives</strong></mark>. In extremis, strategic ambiguity caused by this issue may <mark>trigger use<strong>-them-or-lose</strong>-them situations</u></mark>. Open-source research suggests, for example, that <u><mark>Chinese analysts view</mark> the vulnerability of China’s <strong><mark>NC3</strong></mark> to <mark>cyber infiltrations</mark> — even if an attacker’s objective was limited to cyber espionage — <mark>as a <strong>highly escalatory</strong></mark> national security <mark>threat</u></mark>. By contrast, Russian analysts tend to view Russia’s nuclear command, control, communications, and intelligence (C3I) network as more isolated, and thus, relatively insulated from cyber attacks. To be sure, <u>even <mark>a <strong>modicum of uncertainty</strong></mark> <mark>about the effectiveness of <strong>AI-augmented cyber capabilities</mark> </strong><mark>during a crisis</mark> or conflict <mark>would</mark>, therefore, reduce both sides’ risk tolerance, <mark>increa</mark>sing <mark>the incentive to <strong>strike preemptively</strong></mark>.</u> Furthermore, any potential advantages from enhanced reassurances premised on comprehensive intelligence would require equal access to intelligence and analysis systems between great and rising powers. Shared confidence in the accuracy and credibility of these systems would also be needed. Most optimistically, the intentions of all rival states would need to be genuinely benign. In a world of “revisionist” rising powers, the prospects of such a rosy outcome seems improbable. <u>Against the backdrop of a competitive strategic environment in which <mark>states are inclined to <strong>assume the worst</strong></mark> of others’ intentions, one state’s efforts to enhance the survivability of its strategic forces may be viewed by others as a threat to their nuclear retaliatory capability or second-strike capacity. During crisis conditions, for example, an offensive AI cyber tool that succeeds in compromising an adversary’s nuclear weapon systems — resulting in an “asymmetric information” situation — could cause either or both sides to overstate (or understate) their retaliatory capabilities, and in turn, be more inclined to act in a risky and escalatory manner. It is now thought possible that <mark>a cyber attack</mark> (i.e., spoofing, hacking, manipulation, and digital jamming) <mark>could infiltrate a nuclear</mark> weapons <mark>system</mark>, <mark>threaten</mark> the integrity of its <mark>communications</mark>, and ultimately (and possibly unbeknown to its target) <strong><mark>gain control</strong> of</mark> both its nuclear and non-nuclear <strong><mark>command and control</strong></mark> systems. </u>AI has not yet evolved to a point where it could credibly threaten the survivability of a state’s nuclear second-strike capability. However, <u>recent reports of successful cyber attacks against dual-use, early-warning systems suggests that <mark>cyber intrusions against NC3 is</mark> fast <mark>becoming</mark> a <mark>reality</mark>.</u> Irrespective of the technical feasibility of “left of launch” operations (i.e., a preemptive operation to prevent an adversary launching its missiles) against NC3 systems, <u><mark>the <strong>perception alone</strong></mark> that <mark>this capability exists would</mark> <mark>be <strong>inherently destabilizing</u></strong></mark>. Moreover, while the veracity of these counterforce capabilities remains highly contested, <u>several states, including the United States, have already shifted their strategic force postures and doctrine to reflect these emergent threat perceptions.</u> Somewhat paradoxically, AI applications designed to enhance cyber security for nuclear forces could simultaneously make cyber-dependent nuclear weapon systems (e.g., communications, data processing, or early-warning sensors) more vulnerable to cyber attacks. Pathways to Escalation AI-enhanced cyber attacks against nuclear systems would be almost impossible to detect and authenticate, let alone attribute, within the short timeframe for initiating a nuclear strike. According to open sources, operators at the North American Aerospace Defense Command have less than three minutes to assess and confirm initial indications from early-warning systems of an incoming attack. This compressed decision-making timeframe could put political leaders under intense pressure to make a decision to escalate during a crisis, with incomplete (and possibly false) information about a situation. Ironically, new technologies designed to enhance information, such as 5G networks, machine learning, big-data analytics, and quantum computing, can also undermine its clear and reliable flow and communication, which is critical for effective deterrence. Advances in AI could also exacerbate this cyber security challenge by enabling improvements to cyber offense. Machine learning and AI, by automating advanced persistent threat (or “hunting for weaknesses”) operations, might dramatically reduce the extensive manpower resources and high levels of technical skill required to execute advanced persistent threat operations, especially against hardened nuclear targets. Information Warfare Could Lead to Escalation Machine learning, big data analytics, and sensing technologies, supported by 5G networks, could alert commanders of incoming threats with increased speed and precision. This could result in fewer accidents in the sensitive command and control environment. However, this technological coalescence will also amplify risks of escalation in two ways: First, AI machine learning used as a force multiplier for cyber offense — e.g., data poisoning spoofing, deepfakes, manipulation, hacking, and digital jamming — would be considerably more difficult to detect, especially if an attacker used advanced persistent threat tools in the spectrum-contested environment. Second, in the unlikely event that an attack was successfully detected, threat identification (or attribution) at machine speed would be virtually impossible. In short, the key security challenge lies not in making more convincing fakes, but in detecting the spread of false information. AI machine learning techniques might also exacerbate the escalation risks by manipulating the digital information landscape, where decisions about the use of nuclear weapons are made. Given current tensions between the United States and other nuclear powers — China, Russia, and North Korea — it is possible to imagine unprovoked escalation caused by a malicious third-party (or state-proxy) clandestine action. During a crisis, the inability of a state to determine an attacker’s intent may lead an actor to conclude that an attack (threatened or actual) was intended to undermine its nuclear deterrent. For example, an AI-enabled, third-party-generated deepfake, coupled with data-poisoning cyber attacks, could spark an escalatory crisis between two (or more) nuclear states. As demonstrated at a recent workshop hosted by the International Institute for Strategic Studies, malign manipulation of input data received by early-warning systems might not only subvert the output of AI systems in a specific situation, but also undermine the reliability of an entire algorithm network environment if executed during the program’s training phase. Consider the following fictional scenarios, in which the use of deepfakes and spoofing by nefarious third-party, non-state, or state-proxy actors triggers unintentional and unprovoked escalation. Fictional Example #1: Deepfakes To incite conflict between two rival states, State A uses proxy hackers to launch deepfake video or audio material, which depicts senior military commanders of State B conspiring to launch a preemptive strike on State C. Then, this deepfake footage is deliberately leaked into State C’s AI-augmented intelligence collection and analysis systems, provoking State C to escalate the situation with strategic consequences. State B responds to the threat of preemption with a retaliatory strike. Escalation in this case would, of course, be deliberate. Thus, increased escalation risk as a result of technology is not always inadvertent or accidental. For example, escalation risks caused by the aggressive U.S.-Soviet expansion of counterforce technology during the Cold War reflected shifting nuclear doctrines on both sides (i.e., away from assured mutual destruction), not the pursuit of these technologies themselves. Moreover, AI technology could enable an adversary to pursue a predetermined escalatory path. In fact, AI may be developed precisely for this purpose. Fictional Example #2: Spoofing State A launches a malicious AI-enhanced cyber attack to spoof State B’s AI-enabled autonomous sensor platforms and automated target recognition systems, in such a way that the weapon system (a human-supervised automated target recognition system) is fooled into interpreting a civilian object (a commercial airliner, for example) as a military target. State B, based on subverted information and the inability of human supervisors to detect the spoofed imagery in time to take corrective action, accidentally (and unintentionally) escalates the situation. In this example, the spoofing attack on the weapon systems’ algorithm is executed in such a way that the imagery appears to the recognition system as indistinguishable from a valid military target, escalating the situation based on a false premise that would be unlikely to fool the human eye. AI experts have proven that even when data appears accurate to AI image recognition software, these systems often hallucinate objects that do not exist. The explainability (or “black box”) problem associated with AI applications may further compound these dynamics. Insufficient understanding of how and why AI algorithms reach a particular judgment or decision would complicate the task of determining if datasets had been deliberately compromised to manufacture false outcomes — such as attacking incorrect targets or misdirecting allies during combat. Furthermore, as humans and AI team up to accomplish particular missions, the opacity associated with how AI systems reach a decision may cause an operator to have either too much or too little confidence in a system’s performance. Consequently, unless the system’s machine learn­ing algorithm is terminated, once deployed at the end of the training phase it could potentially learn something it was not intended to, or even perform a task or mission that its human designers do not expect it to do. This issue is one of the main reasons why the use of AI machine learning in the context of weapon systems is, for now, confined to mostly experimental research. <u>Even if nuclear early-warning systems might eventually detect the subversion, heightened levels of uncertainty and tension caused by an alert may impel the respective militaries to put their nuclear weapons on high alert status. <mark>This</mark> skewed assessment in the context of nuclear weapons, ready to launch at a moment’s notice, <mark>would likely precipitate <strong>worst-case</strong> </mark>scenario <strong><mark>thinking</strong></mark> <mark>that</mark> may <mark>spark </mark>inadvertent <strong><mark>escalation</strong></mark>. </u>Therefore<u>, AI-augmented <mark>cyber intelligence gathering</mark> tools (or espionage) <mark>used</mark> during a crisis <mark>could easily be misinterpreted</mark> by an adversary <mark>as a prelude for a <strong>preemptive attack</strong></mark> <mark>on its nuclear force.</p></u></mark>
Cyber
null
1AC
1,240,848
802
66,707
./documents/hsld20/Harker/Kh/Harker-Khan-Aff-Cal-Round5.docx
860,366
A
Cal
5
Lynbrook AG
Arya Goel
1ac - Nukes 1nc - T Ban T Lethal ICJ CP Hobbes NC 2nr - CP 2ar - Case CP
hsld20/Harker/Kh/Harker-Khan-Aff-Cal-Round5.docx
null
73,092
MuKh
Harker MuKh
null
Mu.....
Kh.....
null
null
24,534
Harker
Harker
CA
null
1,028
hsld20
HS LD 2020-21
2,020
ld
hs
1
1,153,045
American economic strength prevents US-China-Russia war, baby-proofs emerging tech, and makes international cooperation great again.
Burrows 16
Matthew Burrows 16, Director of the Atlantic Council’s Strategic Foresight Initiative, PhD in European History from the University of Cambridge, September 2016, “The Difficult Transition to a Post-Western Order,” Chapter 8 of Global Risks 2035, https://espas.secure.europarl.europa.eu/orbis/sites/default/files/generated/document/en/Global_Risks_2035_web_0922.pdf
The multilateralist global system was premised on an economically strong U S there will be less capacity for defense and military spending. The U S is the biggest military spender China is increasing its portion of worldwide military spending, while the worldwide share of European NATO members is diminishing China’s military will not rival the U S power-projection capabilities even by 2035, but it will have greater anti-access and denial powers China may never deliver a knockout blow, but it could tarnish the US image of military invincibility a confrontation could trigger a domestic legitimacy crisis for the Communist Party leadership lower growth rates mak it harder to continue trade-liberalization efforts US and Western power rested on a Western-dominated financial system plan for a world that will not have the West as its big economic powerhouse Handovers have been historically difficult and fraught decided by bloody contests envisage military contests between the U S and China and Russia contests would pit West against East, creating a new Cold War War is not inevitable As emerging technologies come online, the lack of a truly global institutional framework could be dangerous the U S is the world’s most vocal champion of a rules-based international order No country has the networks and connections the U S does The U S needs to guid he international system as a “first among equals,” there is no vibrant global-governance system without US and Western leadership The speed with which new technologies com online carries big risks geoengineering, drones, synthetic biology, and nanotechnology. Without rules risk catastrophes there is little alternative to increased global cooperation if one does not want to see higher risks of conflict and economic degradation
The multilateral system premised on a strong U S China may never deliver a knockout but it could tarnish US invincibility trigger a legitimacy crisis for the Party lower growth mak harder liberalization plan for a world that will not have the West as its powerhouse Handovers have been contests envisage the U S China and Russia a new Cold War War is not inevitable As emerging tech come online, the lack of a global framework could be dangerous there is no governance without US leadership geoengineering, drones, synthetic bio and nano Without rules risk catastrophes
The multilateralist global system that the United States and the West built after the end of the Second World War was premised on an economically strong United States and West. In 1945, the United States was the only victor that was not completely devastated. World War II had brought the country out of the Great Depression, and the US GDP constituted more than 50 percent of the world’s total. Into the twenty-first century, the members of the Group of Seven (G7) were the world’s political and economic heavyweights. It has only been in the past several years that the collective GDP of the developing world—led by China—has surpassed the developed world’s. Even as non-Western powers grow, it is psychologically hard for the West to think about relinquishing its reins. Demographically, the West has, for a long time, been in the minority. What’s more recent is the aging of the Western population (analyzed in chapter 2), which is already occurring in Japan and Europe, beginning to squeeze the availability of resources for anything but health, social security, and interest payments on debt. Unless healthcare becomes far more efficient, the US economy will be overburdened with healthcare and pension costs as the “baby boomer” generation ages. Healthcare constitutes a whopping 18 percent of the US GDP—significantly more than is the case for other industrialized countries—without necessarily providing better results. With more going to health and pensions, there will be less capacity for defense and military spending. The United States is the biggest military spender, but China is increasing its portion of worldwide military spending, while the worldwide share of European NATO members is diminishing. China’s military probably will not rival the United States’ power-projection capabilities even by 2035, but it will have greater anti-access and denial powers. In a military contest, China may never be able to deliver a knockout blow, but it could tarnish the US image of military invincibility in a conventional state-on-state contest held in its region. Equally, a confrontation that results in a Chinese humiliation could set back China’s aspirations for regional leadership, if not trigger a domestic legitimacy crisis for the Communist Party leadership. Biggest Problem Is Domestic The biggest psychological blow to ordinary Western citizens has been their sagging standard of living (more analysis in chapter 1). Despite a much better record of overall growth in the United States since the 2008 financial crisis, those with median incomes have taken a hit. Worrisome for future US growth potential has been the drop in the labor-participation rate, from the 67 percent range before the 2008 financial crisis to 62-63 percent in the years since. The labor-participation rate was destined to drop due to a growing numbers of retirees, but much of the current sharp decrease comes from unskilled males in their prime working years—forties and early fifties—dropping out. Additionally, many younger women are not entering or staying in the job market. Global Trends 2030 looked at two scenarios for future US growth—one in which the United States maintained or slightly increased its average 2.5 percent pre-2008 growth rate, or one in which growth would slow to an average of 1.5 percent a year. In the first, there would still be the global economic shift to China. On the other hand, the 2.5 percent average growth would help boost average living standards, engendering a “feel-good” factor, which would make more Americans interested in reengaging with world issues.91 Given the record of slower growth and labor-force decline since the 2008 financial crisis, the likelihood of the second scenario is increasing. That scenario anticipated lower growth rates—which accelerated declines in average living standards—making it harder to continue trade-liberalization efforts. Indeed, the IMF warned in June 2016 that the United States faces potentially significant longer-term challenges to strong and sustained growth, saying, “concerted policy actions are warranted, sooner rather than later… focusing on the causes and consequences of falling labor force participation, an increasingly polarized income distribution, high levels of poverty, and weak productivity.”92 Moreover, it is not as if traditional US partners—Europe and Japan—are doing much better. Japan and many European countries are aging faster than the United States, eliminating labor-force growth as a driver of future economic growth. Europe’s and Japan’s economic performances have been declining since the 1990s. In Europe, the public discontent with high unemployment and declining incomes has helped to spur the rise of antiestablishment far-right and populist parties that want to weaken the EU and transatlantic ties. Even in richer European countries, such as Germany, a backlash has been growing against the Transatlantic Trade and Investment Partnership (TTIP), out of fear that Europe’s rewards would be meager and European standards would be diluted. McKinsey Global Institute, for example, believes a “return to sustained growth of 2-to-3 percent” is possible for Europe, but would require many politically difficult reforms.93 These include: reducing dependence on imports (much coming from Russia) for crude oil and natural gas; fostering a more vibrant digital economy; increasing workforce participation by the elderly, women, and migrants; and promoting flexibility in labor markets. China now spends a greater share of its GDP on research and development than does Europe. The latest OECD figures show that Europe now spends even less than the rest of the OECD.94 In both the United States and Europe, there is increasing anti-immigrant sentiment despite documented economic benefits from immigration. According to EU Commission Employment Analyst Dr. Jorg Peschner, productivity, by itself, will not be enough to reverse the negative employment trend absent more immigration: “EU’s productivity growth would have to double in order to keep the EU’s economy growing at the same pace as it did before the crisis started.” For employment growth to remain positive as long as possible, improving the labor participation of women, low-educated people, and migrants will also have to be a priority. In the United States, many of the new businesses started every year are started by first- or second-generation immigrants.95 Politically, there has been a large rise in support for right-wing and populist parties in the United States and Europe, undermining traditional parties. The gaps, for example, between the leadership and supporters in the US Republican and UK Tory and Labor Parties have been particularly evident in the selection of Donald Trump as presidential candidate and the June 2016 victory of the “Leave” vote in Britain. Unfortunately, there is no end of economic disruption. The job churn will continue as more and more skills and professions are automated, also increasing the potential for more “losers” from globalization, greater political polarization, and inequality. The increased competitiveness of the developing world with the West is a particular morale buster for Western middle classes who got used to ever-increasing prosperity for themselves and succeeding generations. Adapting to a new norm of economic turbulence—more prevalent in other eras—may be one of the biggest mental hurdles for Westerners. The West is used to thinking of the “Third World,” not home, as the place where economic turmoil happens. And a Multipolar Financial Architecture, Too Historically, US and Western power has rested on having a monopoly on reserve currencies and a Western-dominated financial system. In 2035, the dollar will be the biggest reserve currency, but its share of global financial transactions is expected to drop from 60 percent today to 45 percent. The euro will probably remain the second reserve currency, while the Chinese yuan or RMB—which became a part of the IMF benchmark-currency basket in 2015—will become a third reserve currency, accounting for 10 to 15 percent of global finance in two decades’ time.96 The financial architecture will also become more regionalized. The central role played by the financial centers of New York and London will also diminish, and a multitiered financial architecture will develop. Following the UK Brexit, those centers’ share in financial intermediation will decrease, as a second pole of global finance forms in the Eurozone. A third pole will develop in East Asia and Southeast Asia. Gradually, a growing share of global financial resources will be concentrated in those regional clusters. As with the growth of regional trade, the regional clusters will be more self-encapsulated, spurred by rising domestic demand in China and other developing countries with growing middle classes. With the role of electronic money likely to grow, the traditional banking system will probably also undergo major revision, with potential impacts on governmental powers. A more multipolar reserve system and regionalized financial architecture should lessen risks and contribute to greater stability. But the large-scale technological innovations—some of which contributed to the 2008 breakdown—will continue, making global finance still volatile. Emerging-market countries with fragmentary regulatory regimes will be particularly prone to suffering financial crises. The aging-population factor also increases risks to public finances. This report anticipates modestly increased volatility, lower than what occurred in the global economy during the 1890s through the 1940s, but higher than in the 1950s and 1960s—more of a continuation of what has been the trend line since the mid-1980s. Are There Alternative Visions to Western Order? Four years ago, when Global Trends 2030 was published, the answer was largely no.97 Increasingly, the facts on the ground would suggest otherwise. They do not add up to a cohesive plan to substitute wholesale all Western institutions and practices. However, they clearly indicate that there are some no-go areas, particularly those connected to regime change, democracy promotion, state control over NGOs, and maintaining sovereignty. Russia and China, in particular, see themselves as great powers and, as such, believe they have special rights to dominance in their regions. However, as other powers like India develop, it is likely that they will see themselves as regional powers with inherent prerogatives. It is worth recalling the United States’ expansive Manifest Destiny and nineteenth-century Monroe Doctrine, claiming special rights to determine the future of the Western Hemisphere. The Mercator Institute for China Studies (MERICS) has been closely following Beijing’s efforts to build a network of parallel structures to existing international organizations. It has concluded that China “is not seeking to demolish or exit from current international organizations…It is constructing supplementary— in part complementary, in part competitive—channels for shaping the international order beyond Western claims to leadership.”98 As the accompanying chart indicates, China’s shadow network of alternative international structures encompasses everything from financial and economic partnerships (the Silk Road Economic Belt and the Asian Infrastructure Investment Bank) to full-blown political groupings like the Shanghai Cooperation Organization, Conference on Interaction and Confidence Building Measures in Asia (CICA), and the BRICS association of Brazil, Russia, India, China, and South Africa.99 Moreover, there is increasing cooperation among many of the emerging powers—beyond just authoritarians—to not just limit what they see as Western meddling in domestic affairs, but to go on the attack globally. According to a recent academic study, the “Big Five” authoritarian states of China, Russia, Iran, Saudi Arabia, and Venezuela “have taken more coordinated and decisive action to contain democracy on the global level.” They have sought to “alter the democracy and human-rights mechanisms of key rulesbased institutions, including the Organization of American States, the Council of Europe, the Organization for Security and Cooperation in Europe, and international bodies concerned with the governance of the Internet.”100 How durable are these preferences for nondemocracy and state control? By 2035, if not sooner (in the case of Venezuela), some of the now-authoritarian states could be liberalized, and the perceived threat posed by Western civil-society NGOs may ease. However, China and Russia are more likely than not to want to dominate their regions. Nationalism and democracy have been shown to be highly compatible. It is not clear that an even more powerful China or India would defer to Western leadership of the global order, even if both sides’ values in other areas begin to converge. What Kind of Post-Western World? Clearly, there is a need to plan for a world that will not have the West as its big economic powerhouse—a prospect hard for Western elites and publics to conceive of, despite a decade or more of publicity about the “rise of the rest.” According to a recent survey, Europeans and Americans are more comfortable with each other than they are with anybody else. Although a majority of Europeans said, in the most recent German Marshall Fund transatlantic-trends polling, that they would like to see their country take an approach more independent from the United States, both Americans and Europeans still prefer each other over more Russian or Chinese leadership in the world. The Obama administration—considered among the most multilateralist of recent administrations— campaigned hard in 2015 to convince Europeans not to join China’s proposed Asian Infrastructure and Investment Bank (AIIB). It was as if the United States was against any governance structure not “made in the USA,” even when those running the AIIB have made clear their intentions of operating with the World Bank and the Asian Development Bank. More and more, the talk among Western elites is about locking in as much as possible the status quo, which favors the West, so that it will be harder for the newcomers to overcome. The TPP was sold as a way to set the rules before China gains much more power. A former Obama administration official advised that now might be the best time to undertake UN Security Council reform, before China and other uncooperative powers become more powerful. “A new US administration may be able to advance a proposal to address the Security Council’s anachronistic makeup while perpetuating a council that Washington can work with.”101 For Westerners, the challenge will be to plan for a future that will not be solely run by them, but which they can live with. Handovers have been historically difficult and fraught—more often than not, decided by bloody contests. One could envisage different scenarios, some already described in the earlier chapter on conflict, of military contests between the United States and China, or the United States and China with Russia, or the United States with NATO against Russia. Without delivering a knockout blow by one side or the other, these contests would most likely pit West against East, creating something akin to a new Cold War. Even if there were a knockout blow by the United States against China, it is hard to imagine a defeated China deferring permanently to the West. Its population has been imbued with such a narrative about the injustices by the West against China that any defeat or setback would be confirmation that the United States and West are dead set against a rising China. Perhaps the most harmful effect of such a contest would be to convince both sides that neither is trustworthy. For the non-West, it would confirm the suspicion that the West does not want to relinquish its leadership position. For the West, it would make it harder to ever reach out and help establish a truly global system. Need for a Second-Generation US and Western Leadership Model War is not, and should not be, inevitable as the West struggles with the growing clout of China and other developing states on the world stage. Unlike during other transitions, the tools exist for ensuring more peaceful outcomes. They will require Western acquiescence to greater roles for the developing world to set and implement new rules of the road for the international order. A key feature of the post-1945 US design for the world order is its multilateralist structures. Many of these operate below most people’s radar. This plumbing of the international system has enabled the daily functioning of globalization. To keep it viable, China, as well as other developing countries, must be accorded more representation. There are too many long-term risks involved, for example, in China having only the equivalent of France’s voting rights in the IMF, when it is the first or second economic power in the world. This is how resentments are nurtured—all the more dangerous in China’s case because of its underlying “century of humiliation” mental complex. As emerging technologies come online, the lack of a truly global institutional framework could be particularly dangerous. Assuring the future security of the Internet is particularly important in this regard, because all the new emerging technologies—bio, 3D printing, robotics, big data—take for granted a secure, global Internet. Everyone loses if cyber crime and cyber terrorism undermine the Internet. In the worstcase scenarios, in which cyber crime proliferates or strong national borders fragment the Internet, an Atlantic Council study, as mentioned, found that the economic costs could be as much as $90 trillion out to 2030, in addition to the risk of open conflict.102 Besides bringing the emerging powers into leadership roles in the panoply of multilateral institutions, the United States will need to temper its often “exemptionalist” stance to ensure the survival of the multilateralist order. According to the Council on Foreign Relations’ Patrick Stewart, a prominent scholar of global governance, one of the persistent paradoxes of the post-1945 decades has been that the “United States is at once the world’s most vocal champion of a rules-based international order and the power most insistent on opting out of the constraints that it hopes to see binding on others.”103 No country has the networks and connections that the United States does, but the system is now polycentric, rather than unipolar, and others resent the “exceptional” privileges that the United States claims. The Global Trends works have talked about the need for a new model of US global leadership. The United States needs to be guiding the international system as a “first among equals,” and willing to play by its own rules. Paradoxically, there is likely to be no vibrant global-governance system without US and Western leadership, but too much domineering behavior could doom it. Even if the United States adapted its global role, this is not to say that the tensions and differences with many emerging powers would all disappear, or that the governance system would function seamlessly. In addition to the growing number of new state actors, the increasing importance of nonstate actors adds a new complexity to the functioning of global institutions. Moreover, there are clear-cut differences between the West and emerging powers on values-based issues, such as democracy promotion and the responsibility to protect. Many developing-country publics still resent Western colonialism and equate any intrusion with past historical wrong. They point to the 2011 humanitarian intervention in Libya, for example, as cover for the Western goal of regime change. Hence, the UN Security Council failure to stop the fighting in Syria, with more than two hundred thousand killed and 7.6 million displaced. Russia and China want to make a stand against the United States and the West getting their way and ousting the Assad regime. On the other hand, the lack of a solution smacks more of anarchy than global governance. Certainly, it shows one of the gaps that remains, and likely will remain, limiting global governance because of differences in values. The speed with which new technologies are coming online and becoming an important political, military, and economic tool—for both good and bad—carries big risks for global governance. Stewart Patrick lists four potential new technologies that “cry out for regulation”: geoengineering, drones, synthetic biology, and nanotechnology. Without some setting of rules for their operation, there is the risk of major disruptions, if not catastrophes, stemming from their abuse. The recent advances in synthetic biology lower the bar to abuse by amateurs and terrorists alike, forever affecting human DNA. Geoengineering involves planetary-scale interventions that could interfere with complex climatic systems. However cumbersome, politically unpopular, and ineffective at times, there is little alternative to increased global cooperation if one does not want to see higher risks of conflict and economic degradation. Without some sort of bolstered global governance, the West would end up with less sovereignty in a “dog-eat-dog” world, in which it was increasingly in the minority. But can the United States and the West rise to the challenge of investing in a global-governance system that will not always favor their interests on every issue? Historically, the United States could be especially generous because it was on top of the world in about everything after the Second World War. Europeans came to truly believe in pooling sovereignty and joint governance after centuries of internecine conflict. The tough economic times at home have seen US and European publics become distrustful of overarching multilateral institutions, believing the will of the United States or individual European countries will not be served. It is oftentimes easier for political leaders to fall in with the public mood rather than display leadership that might appear to work against it.
22,155
<h4>American economic strength <u>prevents</u> US-China-Russia war, <u>baby-proofs</u> emerging tech, and <u>makes</u> international cooperation <u>great again</u>.</h4><p>Matthew <strong>Burrows 16</strong>, Director of the Atlantic Council’s Strategic Foresight Initiative, PhD in European History from the University of Cambridge, September 2016, “The Difficult Transition to a Post-Western Order,” Chapter 8 of Global Risks 2035, https://espas.secure.europarl.europa.eu/orbis/sites/default/files/generated/document/en/Global_Risks_2035_web_0922.pdf</p><p><u><strong><mark>The multilateral</mark>ist global <mark>system</u></strong></mark> that the United States and the West built after the end of the Second World War <u>was <mark>premised on <strong>a</mark>n economically <mark>strong</strong> U</u></mark>nited <u><mark>S</u></mark>tates and West. In 1945, the United States was the only victor that was not completely devastated. World War II had brought the country out of the Great Depression, and the US GDP constituted more than 50 percent of the world’s total. Into the twenty-first century, the members of the Group of Seven (G7) were the world’s political and economic heavyweights. It has only been in the past several years that the collective GDP of the developing world—led by China—has surpassed the developed world’s. Even as non-Western powers grow, it is psychologically hard for the West to think about relinquishing its reins.</p><p>Demographically, the West has, for a long time, been in the minority. What’s more recent is the aging of the Western population (analyzed in chapter 2), which is already occurring in Japan and Europe, beginning to squeeze the availability of resources for anything but health, social security, and interest payments on debt. Unless healthcare becomes far more efficient, the US economy will be overburdened with healthcare and pension costs as the “baby boomer” generation ages. Healthcare constitutes a whopping 18 percent of the US GDP—significantly more than is the case for other industrialized countries—without necessarily providing better results.</p><p>With more going to health and pensions, <u>there will be <strong>less capacity</strong> for <strong>defense and military spending</strong>. The U</u>nited <u>S</u>tates <u>is <strong>the biggest military spender</u></strong>, but <u>China is increasing its portion of <strong>worldwide military spending</strong>, while <strong>the worldwide share</strong> of <strong>European NATO members</strong> is <strong>diminishing</u></strong>.</p><p><u>China’s military</u> probably <u>will <strong>not</strong> rival the U</u>nited <u>S</u>tates’ <u><strong>power-projection capabilities</strong> even by 2035, but it will have greater <strong>anti-access and denial powers</u></strong>. In a military contest, <u><mark>China may never</u></mark> be able to <u><mark>deliver a <strong>knockout</mark> blow</strong>, <mark>but it could tarnish</mark> <strong>the <mark>US </mark>image</strong> of <strong>military <mark>invincibility</u></strong></mark> in a conventional state-on-state contest held in its region. Equally, <u><strong>a confrontation</u></strong> that results in a Chinese humiliation <u>could</u> set back China’s aspirations for regional leadership, if not <u><mark>trigger <strong>a</mark> domestic <mark>legitimacy crisis</strong> for <strong>the</mark> Communist <mark>Party</mark> leadership</u></strong>.</p><p>Biggest Problem Is Domestic </p><p>The biggest psychological blow to ordinary Western citizens has been their sagging standard of living (more analysis in chapter 1). Despite a much better record of overall growth in the United States since the 2008 financial crisis, those with median incomes have taken a hit.</p><p>Worrisome for future US growth potential has been the drop in the labor-participation rate, from the 67 percent range before the 2008 financial crisis to 62-63 percent in the years since. The labor-participation rate was destined to drop due to a growing numbers of retirees, but much of the current sharp decrease comes from unskilled males in their prime working years—forties and early fifties—dropping out. Additionally, many younger women are not entering or staying in the job market. Global Trends 2030 looked at two scenarios for future US growth—one in which the United States maintained or slightly increased its average 2.5 percent pre-2008 growth rate, or one in which growth would slow to an average of 1.5 percent a year. In the first, there would still be the global economic shift to China. On the other hand, the 2.5 percent average growth would help boost average living standards, engendering a “feel-good” factor, which would make more Americans interested in reengaging with world issues.91</p><p>Given the record of slower growth and labor-force decline since the 2008 financial crisis, the likelihood of the second scenario is increasing. That scenario anticipated <u><mark>lower growth</mark> rates</u>—which accelerated declines in average living standards—<u><strong><mark>mak</u></strong></mark>ing <u>it <mark>harder</mark> to continue <strong>trade-<mark>liberalization</mark> efforts</u></strong>. Indeed, the IMF warned in June 2016 that the United States faces potentially significant longer-term challenges to strong and sustained growth, saying, “concerted policy actions are warranted, sooner rather than later… focusing on the causes and consequences of falling labor force participation, an increasingly polarized income distribution, high levels of poverty, and weak productivity.”92 </p><p>Moreover, it is not as if traditional US partners—Europe and Japan—are doing much better. Japan and many European countries are aging faster than the United States, eliminating labor-force growth as a driver of future economic growth. Europe’s and Japan’s economic performances have been declining since the 1990s. </p><p>In Europe, the public discontent with high unemployment and declining incomes has helped to spur the rise of antiestablishment far-right and populist parties that want to weaken the EU and transatlantic ties. Even in richer European countries, such as Germany, a backlash has been growing against the Transatlantic Trade and Investment Partnership (TTIP), out of fear that Europe’s rewards would be meager and European standards would be diluted. McKinsey Global Institute, for example, believes a “return to sustained growth of 2-to-3 percent” is possible for Europe, but would require many politically difficult reforms.93 These include: reducing dependence on imports (much coming from Russia) for crude oil and natural gas; fostering a more vibrant digital economy; increasing workforce participation by the elderly, women, and migrants; and promoting flexibility in labor markets. China now spends a greater share of its GDP on research and development than does Europe. The latest OECD figures show that Europe now spends even less than the rest of the OECD.94</p><p>In both the United States and Europe, there is increasing anti-immigrant sentiment despite documented economic benefits from immigration. According to EU Commission Employment Analyst Dr. Jorg Peschner, productivity, by itself, will not be enough to reverse the negative employment trend absent more immigration: “EU’s productivity growth would have to double in order to keep the EU’s economy growing at the same pace as it did before the crisis started.” For employment growth to remain positive as long as possible, improving the labor participation of women, low-educated people, and migrants will also have to be a priority. In the United States, many of the new businesses started every year are started by first- or second-generation immigrants.95</p><p>Politically, there has been a large rise in support for right-wing and populist parties in the United States and Europe, undermining traditional parties. The gaps, for example, between the leadership and supporters in the US Republican and UK Tory and Labor Parties have been particularly evident in the selection of Donald Trump as presidential candidate and the June 2016 victory of the “Leave” vote in Britain. Unfortunately, there is no end of economic disruption. The job churn will continue as more and more skills and professions are automated, also increasing the potential for more “losers” from globalization, greater political polarization, and inequality. The increased competitiveness of the developing world with the West is a particular morale buster for Western middle classes who got used to ever-increasing prosperity for themselves and succeeding generations. Adapting to a new norm of economic turbulence—more prevalent in other eras—may be one of the biggest mental hurdles for Westerners. The West is used to thinking of the “Third World,” not home, as the place where economic turmoil happens. </p><p>And a Multipolar Financial Architecture, Too</p><p>Historically, <u><strong>US and Western power</u></strong> has <u>rested on</u> having a monopoly on reserve currencies and <u><strong>a Western-dominated financial system</u></strong>. In 2035, the dollar will be the biggest reserve currency, but its share of global financial transactions is expected to drop from 60 percent today to 45 percent. The euro will probably remain the second reserve currency, while the Chinese yuan or RMB—which became a part of the IMF benchmark-currency basket in 2015—will become a third reserve currency, accounting for 10 to 15 percent of global finance in two decades’ time.96</p><p>The financial architecture will also become more regionalized. The central role played by the financial centers of New York and London will also diminish, and a multitiered financial architecture will develop. Following the UK Brexit, those centers’ share in financial intermediation will decrease, as a second pole of global finance forms in the Eurozone. A third pole will develop in East Asia and Southeast Asia. </p><p>Gradually, a growing share of global financial resources will be concentrated in those regional clusters. As with the growth of regional trade, the regional clusters will be more self-encapsulated, spurred by rising domestic demand in China and other developing countries with growing middle classes. With the role of electronic money likely to grow, the traditional banking system will probably also undergo major revision, with potential impacts on governmental powers. </p><p>A more multipolar reserve system and regionalized financial architecture should lessen risks and contribute to greater stability. But the large-scale technological innovations—some of which contributed to the 2008 breakdown—will continue, making global finance still volatile. Emerging-market countries with fragmentary regulatory regimes will be particularly prone to suffering financial crises. The aging-population factor also increases risks to public finances. This report anticipates modestly increased volatility, lower than what occurred in the global economy during the 1890s through the 1940s, but higher than in the 1950s and 1960s—more of a continuation of what has been the trend line since the mid-1980s.</p><p>Are There Alternative Visions to Western Order?</p><p>Four years ago, when Global Trends 2030 was published, the answer was largely no.97 Increasingly, the facts on the ground would suggest otherwise. They do not add up to a cohesive plan to substitute wholesale all Western institutions and practices. However, they clearly indicate that there are some no-go areas, particularly those connected to regime change, democracy promotion, state control over NGOs, and maintaining sovereignty. Russia and China, in particular, see themselves as great powers and, as such, believe they have special rights to dominance in their regions. However, as other powers like India develop, it is likely that they will see themselves as regional powers with inherent prerogatives. It is worth recalling the United States’ expansive Manifest Destiny and nineteenth-century Monroe Doctrine, claiming special rights to determine the future of the Western Hemisphere.</p><p>The Mercator Institute for China Studies (MERICS) has been closely following Beijing’s efforts to build a network of parallel structures to existing international organizations. It has concluded that China “is not seeking to demolish or exit from current international organizations…It is constructing supplementary— in part complementary, in part competitive—channels for shaping the international order beyond Western claims to leadership.”98</p><p>As the accompanying chart indicates, China’s shadow network of alternative international structures encompasses everything from financial and economic partnerships (the Silk Road Economic Belt and the Asian Infrastructure Investment Bank) to full-blown political groupings like the Shanghai Cooperation Organization, Conference on Interaction and Confidence Building Measures in Asia (CICA), and the BRICS association of Brazil, Russia, India, China, and South Africa.99 </p><p>Moreover, there is increasing cooperation among many of the emerging powers—beyond just authoritarians—to not just limit what they see as Western meddling in domestic affairs, but to go on the attack globally. According to a recent academic study, the “Big Five” authoritarian states of China, Russia, Iran, Saudi Arabia, and Venezuela “have taken more coordinated and decisive action to contain democracy on the global level.” They have sought to “alter the democracy and human-rights mechanisms of key rulesbased institutions, including the Organization of American States, the Council of Europe, the Organization for Security and Cooperation in Europe, and international bodies concerned with the governance of the Internet.”100</p><p>How durable are these preferences for nondemocracy and state control? By 2035, if not sooner (in the case of Venezuela), some of the now-authoritarian states could be liberalized, and the perceived threat posed by Western civil-society NGOs may ease. However, China and Russia are more likely than not to want to dominate their regions. Nationalism and democracy have been shown to be highly compatible. It is not clear that an even more powerful China or India would defer to Western leadership of the global order, even if both sides’ values in other areas begin to converge.</p><p>What Kind of Post-Western World? Clearly, there is a need to <u><mark>plan for a world that will not have the West as <strong>its</mark> big economic <mark>powerhouse</u></strong></mark>—a prospect hard for Western elites and publics to conceive of, despite a decade or more of publicity about the “rise of the rest.” According to a recent survey, Europeans and Americans are more comfortable with each other than they are with anybody else. Although a majority of Europeans said, in the most recent German Marshall Fund transatlantic-trends polling, that they would like to see their country take an approach more independent from the United States, both Americans and Europeans still prefer each other over more Russian or Chinese leadership in the world.</p><p>The Obama administration—considered among the most multilateralist of recent administrations— campaigned hard in 2015 to convince Europeans not to join China’s proposed Asian Infrastructure and Investment Bank (AIIB). It was as if the United States was against any governance structure not “made in the USA,” even when those running the AIIB have made clear their intentions of operating with the World Bank and the Asian Development Bank.</p><p>More and more, the talk among Western elites is about locking in as much as possible the status quo, which favors the West, so that it will be harder for the newcomers to overcome. The TPP was sold as a way to set the rules before China gains much more power. A former Obama administration official advised that now might be the best time to undertake UN Security Council reform, before China and other uncooperative powers become more powerful. “A new US administration may be able to advance a proposal to address the Security Council’s anachronistic makeup while perpetuating a council that Washington can work with.”101</p><p>For Westerners, the challenge will be to plan for a future that will not be solely run by them, but which they can live with. <u><mark>Handovers have been</mark> <strong>historically difficult and fraught</u></strong>—more often than not, <u>decided by <strong>bloody <mark>contests</u></strong></mark>. One could <u><mark>envisage</u></mark> different scenarios, some already described in the earlier chapter on conflict, of <u><strong>military contests</strong> between <mark>the U</u></mark>nited <u><mark>S</u></mark>tates <u>and <mark>China</u></mark>, or the United States <u><mark>and</u></mark> China with <u><mark>Russia</u></mark>, or the United States with NATO against Russia. Without delivering a knockout blow by one side or the other, these <u>contests would</u> most likely <u>pit West against East, creating</u> something akin to <u><strong><mark>a new Cold War</u></strong></mark>. Even if there were a knockout blow by the United States against China, it is hard to imagine a defeated China deferring permanently to the West. Its population has been imbued with such a narrative about the injustices by the West against China that any defeat or setback would be confirmation that the United States and West are dead set against a rising China.</p><p>Perhaps the most harmful effect of such a contest would be to convince both sides that neither is trustworthy. For the non-West, it would confirm the suspicion that the West does not want to relinquish its leadership position. For the West, it would make it harder to ever reach out and help establish a truly global system. </p><p>Need for a Second-Generation US and Western Leadership Model </p><p><u><mark>War is <strong>not</u></strong></mark>, and should not be, <u><strong><mark>inevitable</u></strong></mark> as the West struggles with the growing clout of China and other developing states on the world stage. Unlike during other transitions, the tools exist for ensuring more peaceful outcomes. They will require Western acquiescence to greater roles for the developing world to set and implement new rules of the road for the international order. A key feature of the post-1945 US design for the world order is its multilateralist structures. Many of these operate below most people’s radar. This plumbing of the international system has enabled the daily functioning of globalization. To keep it viable, China, as well as other developing countries, must be accorded more representation. There are too many long-term risks involved, for example, in China having only the equivalent of France’s voting rights in the IMF, when it is the first or second economic power in the world. This is how resentments are nurtured—all the more dangerous in China’s case because of its underlying “century of humiliation” mental complex.</p><p><u><mark>As <strong>emerging tech</mark>nologies</strong> <mark>come online, the lack of <strong>a</mark> truly <mark>global</mark> institutional <mark>framework</strong> could be</u></mark> particularly <u><strong><mark>dangerous</u></strong></mark>. Assuring the future security of the Internet is particularly important in this regard, because all the new emerging technologies—bio, 3D printing, robotics, big data—take for granted a secure, global Internet. Everyone loses if cyber crime and cyber terrorism undermine the Internet. In the worstcase scenarios, in which cyber crime proliferates or strong national borders fragment the Internet, an Atlantic Council study, as mentioned, found that the economic costs could be as much as $90 trillion out to 2030, in addition to the risk of open conflict.102</p><p>Besides bringing the emerging powers into leadership roles in the panoply of multilateral institutions, the United States will need to temper its often “exemptionalist” stance to ensure the survival of the multilateralist order. According to the Council on Foreign Relations’ Patrick Stewart, a prominent scholar of global governance, one of the persistent paradoxes of the post-1945 decades has been that <u>the</u> “<u>U</u>nited <u>S</u>tates <u>is</u> at once <u><strong>the world’s most vocal champion</strong> of <strong>a rules-based international order</u></strong> and the power most insistent on opting out of the constraints that it hopes to see binding on others.”103 <u>No country has <strong>the networks and connections</u></strong> that <u>the U</u>nited <u>S</u>tates <u>does</u>, but the system is now polycentric, rather than unipolar, and others resent the “exceptional” privileges that the United States claims. The Global Trends works have talked about the need for a new model of US global leadership. <u>The U</u>nited <u>S</u>tates <u>needs to</u> be <u><strong>guid</u></strong>ing t<u>he international system as a “<strong>first among equals</strong>,”</u> and willing to play by its own rules. Paradoxically, <u><mark>there is</u></mark> likely to be <u><strong><mark>no</mark> vibrant global-<mark>governance</mark> system</strong> <mark>without US</mark> and Western <mark>leadership</u></mark>, but too much domineering behavior could doom it.</p><p>Even if the United States adapted its global role, this is not to say that the tensions and differences with many emerging powers would all disappear, or that the governance system would function seamlessly. In addition to the growing number of new state actors, the increasing importance of nonstate actors adds a new complexity to the functioning of global institutions. Moreover, there are clear-cut differences between the West and emerging powers on values-based issues, such as democracy promotion and the responsibility to protect. Many developing-country publics still resent Western colonialism and equate any intrusion with past historical wrong. They point to the 2011 humanitarian intervention in Libya, for example, as cover for the Western goal of regime change. Hence, the UN Security Council failure to stop the fighting in Syria, with more than two hundred thousand killed and 7.6 million displaced. Russia and China want to make a stand against the United States and the West getting their way and ousting the Assad regime. On the other hand, the lack of a solution smacks more of anarchy than global governance. Certainly, it shows one of the gaps that remains, and likely will remain, limiting global governance because of differences in values. </p><p><u>The speed with which new technologies</u> are <u><strong>com</u></strong>ing <u>online</u> and becoming an important political, military, and economic tool—for both good and bad—<u>carries <strong>big risks</u></strong> for global governance. Stewart Patrick lists four potential new technologies that “cry out for regulation”: <u><strong><mark>geoengineering</strong>, <strong>drones</strong>, <strong>synthetic bio</mark>logy</strong>, <mark>and <strong>nano</mark>technology</strong>. <mark>Without</u></mark> some setting of <u><mark>rules</u></mark> for their operation, there is the <u><mark>risk</u></mark> of major disruptions, if not <u><strong><mark>catastrophes</u></strong></mark>, stemming from their abuse. The recent advances in synthetic biology lower the bar to abuse by amateurs and terrorists alike, forever affecting human DNA. Geoengineering involves planetary-scale interventions that could interfere with complex climatic systems. </p><p>However cumbersome, politically unpopular, and ineffective at times, <u>there is <strong>little alternative</strong> to <strong>increased global cooperation</strong> if one does not want to see <strong>higher risks of conflict</strong> and <strong>economic degradation</u></strong>. Without some sort of bolstered global governance, the West would end up with less sovereignty in a “dog-eat-dog” world, in which it was increasingly in the minority. But can the United States and the West rise to the challenge of investing in a global-governance system that will not always favor their interests on every issue? Historically, the United States could be especially generous because it was on top of the world in about everything after the Second World War. Europeans came to truly believe in pooling sovereignty and joint governance after centuries of internecine conflict. The tough economic times at home have seen US and European publics become distrustful of overarching multilateral institutions, believing the will of the United States or individual European countries will not be served. It is oftentimes easier for political leaders to fall in with the public mood rather than display leadership that might appear to work against it.</p>
OFF
null
1NC---OFF
9,526
421
28,423
./documents/hspolicy21/MontgomeryBell/BaAs/Montgomery%20Bell-Barnard-Asbury-Neg-Marist%20Ivy%20Street%20Invitational-Round4.docx
751,747
N
Marist Ivy Street Invitational
4
GBN PS
Hunter McCullough
1ac- wotus 2nr - states fism
hspolicy21/MontgomeryBell/BaAs/Montgomery%20Bell-Barnard-Asbury-Neg-Marist%20Ivy%20Street%20Invitational-Round4.docx
null
64,107
BaAs
Montgomery Bell BaAs
null
Al.....
Ba.....
Pa.....
As.....
22,058
MontgomeryBell
Montgomery Bell
TN
null
1,020
hspolicy21
HS Policy 2021-22
2,021
cx
hs
2
1,062,557
3. No dead zones impact and alt causes.
Duarte, et al, 15
Duarte, et al, 15—University of Western Australia's Oceans Institute and School of Plant Biology, Department of Global Change Research at the Instituto Mediterráneo de Estudios Avanzados (Carlos, with Robinson W. Fulweiler, Department of Earth and Environment and the Department of Biology at Boston University, Catherine E. Lovelock and John M. Pandolfi both School of Biological Sciences at the University of Queensland, Paulina Martinetto, Laboratorio de Ecología at the Instituto de Investigaciones Marinas y Costeras, Megan I. Saunders, Global Change Institute and the Marine Spatial Ecology Lab at the University of Queensland, Stefan Gelcich, Laboratorio Internacional en Cambio Global (Lincglobal) and with the Centro de Conservacion Marina, in the Departamento de Ecologia, Facultad de Ciencias Biologicas, at the Pontificia Universidad Catolica de Chile, Scott Nixon, Graduate School of Oceanography at the University of Rhode Island, “Reconsidering Ocean Calamities,” BioScience (February 2015) 65 (2): 130-139, dml)
It is tempting to assume that all harmful algal blooms are caused only by human activities such as excess nitrogen and phosphorus Reduced nutrient inputs have proven successful in some cases the connections between anthropogenic eutrophication and HAB proliferation is more uncertain in some cases such as HAB occurrence in association with nutrient limitation rather than excess a complex picture remains, with clear cases of some HAB's being driven solely by human activities; some being driven by larger-scale forcings; and those that cannot be cleanly associated with one cause or another.
It is tempting to assume all algal blooms are caused by human s connections between anthropogenic eutrophication is uncertain in some cases occurrence in association with nutrient limitation complex p remains and those cannot be cleanly associated
It is tempting to assume that all harmful algal blooms (HABs) are caused only by human activities, such as changes to the delivery of both the quantity and the ratio of nutrients available to marine systems (Nixon 1995). In particular, excess nitrogen and phosphorus in reference to silica favors the growth and proliferation of nonsiliceous phytoplankton, most often flagellates (Van Dolah 2000). Reduced nutrient inputs have, therefore, proven successful in reducing HABs in some cases (Okaichi 1997, Bodeanu and Ruta 1998). However, the connections between anthropogenic eutrophication and HAB proliferation is more uncertain in some cases (Anderson et al. 2012), such as HAB occurrence in association with upwelling nutrient supplies (Anderson et al. 2008) or nutrient limitation rather than excess (Smayda 2008). Overall, a complex picture remains, with clear cases of some HAB's being driven solely by human activities; some being driven by larger-scale forcings; and those that, at this point, cannot be cleanly associated with one cause or another.
1,056
<h4>3. No dead zones impact and alt causes.</h4><p><strong>Duarte, et al, 15</strong>—University of Western Australia's Oceans Institute and School of Plant Biology, Department of Global Change Research at the Instituto Mediterráneo de Estudios Avanzados (Carlos, with Robinson W. Fulweiler, Department of Earth and Environment and the Department of Biology at Boston University, Catherine E. Lovelock and John M. Pandolfi both School of Biological Sciences at the University of Queensland, Paulina Martinetto, Laboratorio de Ecología at the Instituto de Investigaciones Marinas y Costeras, Megan I. Saunders, Global Change Institute and the Marine Spatial Ecology Lab at the University of Queensland, Stefan Gelcich, Laboratorio Internacional en Cambio Global (Lincglobal) and with the Centro de Conservacion Marina, in the Departamento de Ecologia, Facultad de Ciencias Biologicas, at the Pontificia Universidad Catolica de Chile, Scott Nixon, Graduate School of Oceanography at the University of Rhode Island, “Reconsidering Ocean Calamities,” BioScience (February 2015) 65 (2): 130-139, dml<u>)</p><p><mark>It is tempting to assume</mark> that <strong><mark>all</strong></mark> harmful <mark>algal blooms</u></mark> (HABs) <u><mark>are caused</mark> <strong>only <mark>by human</mark> activitie<mark>s</u></strong></mark>, <u>such as</u> changes to the delivery of both the quantity and the ratio of nutrients available to marine systems (Nixon 1995). In particular, <u><strong>excess nitrogen</strong> and <strong>phosphorus</u></strong> in reference to silica favors the growth and proliferation of nonsiliceous phytoplankton, most often flagellates (Van Dolah 2000). <u>Reduced nutrient inputs have</u>, therefore, <u>proven successful</u> in reducing HABs <u><strong>in some cases</u></strong> (Okaichi 1997, Bodeanu and Ruta 1998). However, <u>the <mark>connections between</mark> <mark>anthropogenic</mark> <mark>eutrophication</mark> and HAB proliferation <mark>is</mark> <strong>more <mark>uncertain</strong></mark> <mark>in some cases</u></mark> (Anderson et al. 2012), <u>such as HAB <mark>occurrence</mark> <mark>in association with</u></mark> upwelling nutrient supplies (Anderson et al. 2008) or <u><strong><mark>nutrient limitation</mark> rather than excess</u></strong> (Smayda 2008). Overall, <u>a <strong><mark>complex p</mark>icture</strong> <mark>remains</mark>, with clear cases of some HAB's being driven solely by human activities; some being driven by larger-scale forcings; <mark>and those</mark> that</u>, at this point, <u><mark>cannot be cleanly associated</mark> with one cause or another.</p></u>
1NC vs Kent Denver AT
Case
1NC – AT: Runoff
32,792
206
25,662
./documents/hspolicy21/Bellarmine/DiDw/Bellarmine-Dinesh-Dwivedula-Neg-Berkeley-Round6.docx
744,043
N
Berkeley
6
Kent Denver AT
Kevin Sun
null
hspolicy21/Bellarmine/DiDw/Bellarmine-Dinesh-Dwivedula-Neg-Berkeley-Round6.docx
null
63,369
DiDw
Bellarmine DiDw
null
Ri.....
Di.....
Ne.....
Dw.....
21,887
Bellarmine
Bellarmine
CA
null
1,020
hspolicy21
HS Policy 2021-22
2,021
cx
hs
2
4,533,070
Populist backlash risks existential nuclear war
Hymans 22
Dr. Jacques E. C. Hymans 22, PhD in Government from Harvard, Associate Professor of International Relations at the University of Southern California, “Responses to Meier and Vieluf”, The Nonproliferation Review, 28:1-3, 52-54, DOI: 10.1080/10736700.2022.2093513
I have argued that nuclear-armed establishments are dangerous Now I will also argue nuclear-armed populists are dangerous The biggest problem is that populism is a gateway drug to internal political violence revolution and civil war And needless to say serious domestic upheaval in a nuclear power also increases the likelihood of a nuclear incident of some kind. the first-ever populist government in history was led by the Jacobin faction that drove the French Revolution forward The Jacobins expressed a radical populist faith in the power of “redemptive violence” by “the people.” France and the world are lucky that nuclear physics was not very far advanced in the Jacobins’ day. the language of populism is the language of revolution and civil war and pretend revolutionaries can easily be carried along by the tide of social resentments that they have irresponsibly stirred up We need to consider worst-case scenarios. domestic divisions fomented by populists do not have to arrive at their logical end point of revolution and civil war to increase deterrence instability and the chances of a nuclear incident. Below I elaborate three more specific hypotheses on the deterrence consequences of internally divisive populist governments. The hypotheses are speculative, but they logically follow from the definition of populism and should therefore serve as useful points for further discussion of Meier and Vieluf’s core idea. Populists are likely to be insensitive to nuclear threats to the political strongholds of their domestic opponents the question of whether the United States would be willing to trade “Pittsburgh for Paris” has been around for decades The new problem that populism creates is that even homeland deterrence starts to suffer from the same credibility dilemmas as extended deterrence we now also have to ask whether a populist administration in Washington would be willing to trade Pittsburgh for Portland. deterrence theory’s standard assumption that a nuclear threat to any part of the homeland will be treated as a threat to the whole homeland can no longer be taken for granted foreign powers could calculate that they will not be punished for striking at certain targets within the country’s borders the longest-range North Korean missile that is currently operational has enough range for a nuclear attack against Seattle but not Mar-a-Lago Would the same president who formally designated Seattle as an “anarchist jurisdiction” be greatly concerned by a credible threat of a North Korean strike against it? Probably—but is “probably” a good enough answer for homeland deterrence credibility? Populists in power may even be slow to help their political opponents’ regions recover from an actual nuclear attack. There is a lesson for nuclear analysts in the Trump administration’s intentional slow-walking of congressionally mandated emergency aid to the US territory of Puerto Rico after Hurricane Maria in 2017, one of the deadliest natural disasters in US history.26 Having long held a low opinion of Puerto Ricans, Trump reportedly told his chief of staff and budget director that he “did not want a single dollar going to Puerto Rico.” 27 Would Trump have been any more helpful if the island had been hit by a man-made bomb instead of a natural one? Maybe if Puerto Rico could do something for him in return, which leads to the second hypothesis: Populists are likely to exploit their control over homeland deterrence to demand political concessions from their domestic political opponents At the heart of populism is a disrespect for the principle of equal application of the laws governance becomes a pure power game, and populist rulers notably exploit crises as opportunities to bring domestic political opponents to their knees There is every reason to assume that a populist in full command of the nuclear and defense establishment would similarly take advantage of a nuclear crisis to conduct such a shakedown populists in power will charge a high price for adequately responding to nuclear threats against their domestic opponents’ political strongholds. the distractions caused by internal political wrangling could greatly affect the denouement of a time-sensitive nuclear crisis Foreign powers could also be tempted to initiate a nuclear crisis precisely in order to intensify their adversary’s domestic divisions The establishment’s reaction to populism is likely to increase deterrence instability at least as much as the actions of the populists themselves the establishment’s effort to fend off populists could itself dramatically increase deterrence instability by sowing confusion about the chain of command This hypothesis is not mere speculation launch it.” 34 Essentially, Milley was saying that if push came to shove, the military would mutiny. Meier and Vieluf seem to think that Milley did the right thing (pp. 15–16). Maybe so, but he also set an ominous precedent. I would be relieved to discover that I am being overly pessimistic about humanity’s chances of survival with populists in charge of nuclear arsenals But the more I study the issue, the more pessimistic I become
nuclear-armed populists are dangerous populism is a gateway drug to internal violence and civil war serious domestic upheaval in a nuclear power increases likelihood of a nuclear incident We need to consider worst-case scenarios. divisions by populists do not have to arrive at civil war to increase deterrence instability Populists are insensitive to nuclear threats to the political strongholds of domestic opponents homeland deterrence starts to suffer from credibility dilemmas we have to ask whether a populist admin would foreign powers could calculate that they will not be punished for striking certain targets distractions caused by internal wrangling could affect the denouement of a time-sensitive nuclear crisis Foreign powers could initiate a nuclear crisis to intensify their adversary’s domestic divisions The establishment’s reaction to populism increase instability at least as much as the actions of the populists themselves by sowing confusion about chain of command about humanity’s chances of survival with populists the more I study the
Building on Meier and Vieluf’s accounting of the dangers of populism I have argued that nuclear-armed establishments are more dangerous than Meier and Vieluf suggest. Now I will also argue that nuclear-armed populists are dangerous for even more reasons than Meier and Vieluf enumerate. Meier and Vieluf’s article does not do enough with its basic definition of nationalist populism as a black–white oppositional stance toward internal as well as external enemies. If we take that definition seriously, it becomes apparent that the biggest problem stemming from the rise of populists is not that they might ignore the advice of traditional nuclear and defense establishments and behave carelessly toward foreign powers. The biggest problem is that populism is a gateway drug to internal political violence, revolution, and civil war.12 And, perhaps needless to say, serious domestic upheaval in a nuclear power also increases the likelihood of a nuclear incident of some kind. Perhaps the first-ever populist government in history was led by the Jacobin faction that drove the French Revolution forward from 1792 to 1794.13 The Jacobins expressed a radical populist faith in the power of “redemptive violence” by “the people.” 14 They made war both inside and outside France. To quote historian Brian Singer, the Jacobins’ violence was directed neither “at a well-defined enemy” nor “at some limited, short-term end, but to the creation of a new regime, a new humanity.” 15 In short, they wanted to raze the old world to the ground—or die trying. The Jacobins’ favorite metaphor for their violence was lightning, which materializes from out of nowhere to simultaneously destroy and enlighten the dark world it strikes. Their interest in lightning was not only metaphorical; Jacobin ideologues such as Jean-Paul Marat were serious students of the new science of electricity.16 France and the world are lucky that nuclear physics was not very far advanced in the Jacobins’ day. None of the contemporary nuclear-armed populist leaders listed by Meier and Vieluf is a modern-day Jacobin. Most populists are merely unprincipled con artists who prey on atomized and insecure sections of the public, manipulating them to gain personal wealth and power. Even so, the language of populism is the language of revolution and civil war, and pretend revolutionaries can easily be carried along by the tide of social resentments that they have irresponsibly stirred up. Take, for instance, Trump and his followers’ dismal trajectory to January 6, 2021. We need to consider worst-case scenarios. Trump did not actually want a civil war in the United States, but his rhetoric emboldened the not-so-small number of Americans who do. A rigorous time-series analysis found that Trump’s presidential run in 2016 was associated with an abrupt, statistically significant, and durable increase in violent attacks by domestic far-right extremists.17 For instance, the leading ideologist of the neo-Nazi group Atomwaffen Division, James Mason, wrote in July 2017, “I am not ashamed to say that I shed a tear of joy at [Trump’s] win.” 18 Far from standing back and standing by, Mason preached direct action to “accelerate” the onset of a society-purifying race war that he believed would push the Trump administration into embracing full-blown fascism. In May 2017, an Atomwaffen member, National Guard veteran, and onetime physics major named Brandon Russell was arrested for plotting to attack the Turkey Point nuclear power plant, among other targets. Police later also found traces of thorium and americium in Russell’s bedroom.19 The domestic divisions fomented by populists do not have to arrive at their logical end point of revolution and civil war to increase deterrence instability and the chances of a nuclear incident. Below I elaborate three more specific hypotheses on the deterrence consequences of internally divisive populist governments. The hypotheses are speculative, but they logically follow from the definition of populism and should therefore serve as useful points for further discussion of Meier and Vieluf’s core idea. Hypothesis 1. Populists are likely to be insensitive to nuclear threats to the political strongholds of their domestic opponents. Meier and Vieluf observe that the credibility of US extended-deterrence promises to America’s allies suffered massively under the Trump administration. That is certainly true, but the question of whether the United States would be willing to trade “Pittsburgh for Paris” (p. 19) has been around for decades. The new problem that populism creates is that even homeland deterrence starts to suffer from the same credibility dilemmas as extended deterrence. In addition to the “Pittsburgh for Paris” question, we now also have to ask whether a populist administration in Washington would be willing to trade Pittsburgh for Portland. In a country where populist leaders revel in dividing society against itself, deterrence theory’s standard assumption that a nuclear threat to any part of the homeland will be treated as a threat to the whole homeland can no longer be taken for granted.20 Whatever the president’s true intentions, foreign powers could potentially calculate that they will not be punished for striking at certain targets within the country’s borders.21 For instance, the longest-range North Korean missile that is currently operational, the Hwasong-14, has enough range for a nuclear attack against Seattle but not Mar-a-Lago. 22 Would the same president who formally designated Seattle as an “anarchist jurisdiction” in an attempt to starve it of federal dollars be greatly concerned by a credible threat of a North Korean strike against it? 23 Probably—but is “probably” a good enough answer for homeland deterrence credibility? Another dimension of this same hypothesis has to do with the precise locations where populists choose to install military installations that are likely to become nuclear targets. During the Nixon administration, the objections of congressional Democrats to the planned construction of Sentinel anti-ballistic-missile facilities near their political strongholds such as Boston and Seattle led Secretary of Defense Melvin Laird to move the projects to less populated areas.24 President Nixon believed that he needed to work constructively with the Democrats on core national security issues. By contrast, a populist president would love to see his political opponents sweating the targets he put on their backs.25 Populists in power may even be slow to help their political opponents’ regions recover from an actual nuclear attack. There is a lesson for nuclear analysts in the Trump administration’s intentional slow-walking of congressionally mandated emergency aid to the US territory of Puerto Rico after Hurricane Maria in 2017, one of the deadliest natural disasters in US history.26 Having long held a low opinion of Puerto Ricans, Trump reportedly told his chief of staff and budget director that he “did not want a single dollar going to Puerto Rico.” 27 Would Trump have been any more helpful if the island had been hit by a man-made bomb instead of a natural one? Maybe if Puerto Rico could do something for him in return, which leads to the second hypothesis: Hypothesis 2. Populists are likely to exploit their control over homeland deterrence to demand political concessions from their domestic political opponents. At the heart of populism is a disrespect for the principle of equal application of the laws. Instead, governance becomes a pure power game, and populist rulers notably exploit crises as opportunities to bring domestic political opponents to their knees. There is every reason to assume that a populist in full command of the nuclear and defense establishment would similarly take advantage of a nuclear crisis to conduct such a shakedown. In other words, populists in power will charge a high price for adequately responding to nuclear threats against their domestic opponents’ political strongholds. Let us continue with the example of the Trump administration. The mass-destructive COVID-19 pandemic offers a highly relevant analogy for thinking about the internal political dynamics of a potential nuclear crisis under populist rule. Public-administration scholars have labeled Trump’s governing approach as “chaotic transactional federalism,” a cynical power system that “removes any vestige of certainty as decisions are shaped based on a desire to reward or punish other political actors, or left to subnational actors entirely. Expertise matters very little in these political, partisan transactions.” 28 In line with this, Trump responded to the COVID-19 crisis by pitting the 50 states against each other in bidding wars for vital medical supplies and for his political favor.29 The president publicly criticized Vice President Mike Pence for reaching out to all the state governors in his role as the coordinator of the national pandemic response, telling the press that he wanted Pence to deal only with those governors who were sufficiently “appreciative.” 30 Trump administration officials were even blunter in private. Trump’s son-in-law and closest adviser Jared Kushner reportedly said that New York Governor Andrew Cuomo “didn’t pound the phones hard enough to get PPE [personal protective equipment] for his state … . His people are going to suffer and that’s their problem.” 31 Trump’s response to the Democratic governors’ pleas for PPE to defend against the virus was essentially the same as his response to Ukrainian President Volodymyr Zelenskyy’s pleas for weapons to defend against Russia: “I would like you to do us a favor though.” 32 The hypothesis that populists will demand concessions from their domestic political opponents in exchange for issuing nuclear-deterrent threats on their behalf may at first glance appear to be only a matter of internal politics, but the distractions caused by internal political wrangling could greatly affect the denouement of a time-sensitive nuclear crisis. Foreign powers could also be tempted to initiate a nuclear crisis precisely in order to intensify their adversary’s domestic divisions. In addition, when facing the double burden of a nuclear threat and simultaneous shakedown by the president, politicians from disfavored regions would likely appeal to friendly elements of the military for assistance. That possibility tees up the third hypothesis: Hypothesis 3. The establishment’s reaction to populism is likely to increase deterrence instability at least as much as the actions of the populists themselves. Meier and Vieluf’s article implies that the fate of the world hangs on the establishment’s ability to keep populist fingers off the nuclear button. But the establishment’s effort to fend off the populists could itself dramatically increase deterrence instability, for instance by sowing confusion about the chain of command. This hypothesis is not mere speculation. Reacting to widespread fears that Trump might be tempted to launch a nuclear attack against China or another country after his 2020 election loss to Joe Biden, in January 2021, General Mark Milley, the chairman of the Joint Chiefs of Staff, quietly worked the phone lines to reassure key people at home and abroad that he personally would not allow the president to do anything of the sort. The chairman of the Joint Chiefs is legally outside the chain of command for the execution of the president’s military strategy. Indeed, neither he nor anyone else has the legal authority to prevent a determined president from launching a nuclear strike.33 Yet Milley told Pelosi, “The president alone can order the use of nuclear weapons. But he doesn’t make the decision alone. One person can order it, several people have to launch it.” 34 Essentially, Milley was saying that if push came to shove, the military would mutiny. Meier and Vieluf seem to think that Milley did the right thing (pp. 15–16). Maybe so, but he also set an ominous precedent. As I mentioned at the outset, these comments are simply intended to spark further discussion about the important issues raised by Meier and Vieluf’s stimulating article. I would be relieved to discover that I am being overly pessimistic about humanity’s chances of survival with either the establishments or the populists in charge of nuclear arsenals. But the more I study the issue, the more pessimistic I become
12,430
<h4>Populist backlash risks existential nuclear war </h4><p>Dr. Jacques E. C. <strong>Hymans 22</strong>, PhD in Government from Harvard, Associate Professor of International Relations at the University of Southern California, “Responses to Meier and Vieluf”, The Nonproliferation Review, 28:1-3, 52-54, DOI: 10.1080/10736700.2022.2093513</p><p>Building on Meier and Vieluf’s accounting of the dangers of populism </p><p><u>I have argued that nuclear-armed establishments are</u> more <u>dangerous</u> than Meier and Vieluf suggest. <u>Now I will also argue</u> that <u><strong><mark>nuclear-armed populists</u></strong> <u>are</u> <u><strong>dangerous</u></strong></mark> for even more reasons than Meier and Vieluf enumerate.</p><p>Meier and Vieluf’s article does not do enough with its basic definition of nationalist populism as a black–white oppositional stance toward internal as well as external enemies. If we take that definition seriously, it becomes apparent that the biggest problem stemming from the rise of populists is not that they might ignore the advice of traditional nuclear and defense establishments and behave carelessly toward foreign powers. <u><strong>The biggest problem</u></strong> <u>is that <mark>populism is a <strong>gateway drug</strong> to <strong>internal</mark> political <mark>violence</u></strong></mark>, <u><strong>revolution</u></strong>, <u><mark>and</u> <u><strong>civil war</u></strong></mark>.12 <u>And</u>, perhaps <u>needless to say</u>, <u><mark>serious <strong>domestic upheaval</strong> in a <strong>nuclear power</strong></mark> also <mark>increases</mark> the <strong><mark>likelihood of a nuclear incident</mark> of some kind. </p><p></u></strong>Perhaps <u>the first-ever populist government in history was led by the Jacobin faction that drove the French Revolution forward</u> from 1792 to 1794.13 <u>The Jacobins expressed a radical populist faith in the power of “redemptive violence” by “the people.”</u> 14 They made war both inside and outside France. To quote historian Brian Singer, the Jacobins’ violence was directed neither “at a well-defined enemy” nor “at some limited, short-term end, but to the creation of a new regime, a new humanity.” 15 In short, they wanted to raze the old world to the ground—or die trying. The Jacobins’ favorite metaphor for their violence was lightning, which materializes from out of nowhere to simultaneously destroy and enlighten the dark world it strikes. Their interest in lightning was not only metaphorical; Jacobin ideologues such as Jean-Paul Marat were serious students of the new science of electricity.16 <u><strong>France</u></strong> <u>and</u> <u><strong>the world</u></strong> <u>are lucky that <strong>nuclear physics was not very far advanced</u></strong> <u>in the <strong>Jacobins’ day.</p><p></u></strong>None of the contemporary nuclear-armed populist leaders listed by Meier and Vieluf is a modern-day Jacobin. Most populists are merely unprincipled con artists who prey on atomized and insecure sections of the public, manipulating them to gain personal wealth and power. Even so, <u>the</u> <u><strong>language of populism</u></strong> <u>is the <strong>language of revolution</strong> and</u> <u><strong>civil war</u></strong>, <u>and pretend revolutionaries can easily be carried along by the <strong>tide of social resentments</strong> that they have irresponsibly stirred up</u>. Take, for instance, Trump and his followers’ dismal trajectory to January 6, 2021. <u><mark>We need to consider <strong>worst-case scenarios.</p><p></u></strong></mark>Trump did not actually want a civil war in the United States, but his rhetoric emboldened the not-so-small number of Americans who do. A rigorous time-series analysis found that Trump’s presidential run in 2016 was associated with an abrupt, statistically significant, and durable increase in violent attacks by domestic far-right extremists.17 For instance, the leading ideologist of the neo-Nazi group Atomwaffen Division, James Mason, wrote in July 2017, “I am not ashamed to say that I shed a tear of joy at [Trump’s] win.” 18 Far from standing back and standing by, Mason preached direct action to “accelerate” the onset of a society-purifying race war that he believed would push the Trump administration into embracing full-blown fascism. In May 2017, an Atomwaffen member, National Guard veteran, and onetime physics major named Brandon Russell was arrested for plotting to attack the Turkey Point nuclear power plant, among other targets. Police later also found traces of thorium and americium in Russell’s bedroom.19</p><p>The <u>domestic <mark>divisions</mark> fomented <mark>by populists <strong>do not have to arrive at</mark> their logical end point</u></strong> <u>of</u> <u><strong>revolution and <mark>civil war</u></strong> <u>to <strong>increase deterrence instability</u></strong></mark> <u>and the <strong>chances of a nuclear incident. Below I elaborate three more specific hypotheses on the deterrence consequences of internally divisive populist governments. The hypotheses are speculative, but they logically follow from the definition of populism and should therefore serve as useful points for further discussion of Meier and Vieluf’s core idea.</p><p></u></strong>Hypothesis 1. <u><mark>Populists are</mark> likely to be <strong><mark>insensitive to nuclear threats</u></strong> <u>to the political <strong>strongholds</strong> of</mark> their <mark>domestic <strong>opponents</u></strong></mark>. Meier and Vieluf observe that the credibility of US extended-deterrence promises to America’s allies suffered massively under the Trump administration. That is certainly true, but <u>the question of whether the United States would be willing to trade “Pittsburgh for Paris”</u> (p. 19) <u>has been around for decades</u>. <u>The</u> <u><strong>new problem</u></strong> <u>that populism creates is that <strong>even <mark>homeland deterrence</u></strong> <u>starts to <strong>suffer</u></strong> <u>from</mark> the same <strong><mark>credibility dilemmas</u></strong></mark> <u>as <strong>extended deterrence</u></strong>. In addition to the “Pittsburgh for Paris” question, <u><mark>we</mark> now also <mark>have to ask whether a populist admin</mark>istration in <strong>Washington</strong> <mark>would</mark> be <strong>willing to </strong>trade Pittsburgh for Portland.</p><p></u>In a country where populist leaders revel in dividing society against itself, <u>deterrence theory’s <strong>standard assumption</u></strong> <u>that a nuclear threat to any part of the homeland will be treated as a <strong>threat</strong> to the <strong>whole</strong> homeland <strong>can no longer be taken for granted</u></strong>.20 Whatever the president’s true intentions, <u><strong><mark>foreign powers</strong> could</u></mark> potentially <u><strong><mark>calculate</strong> that they <strong>will not be punished</strong> for <strong>striking</mark> at <mark>certain targets</mark> within the country’s borders</u></strong>.21 For instance, <u>the longest-range North Korean missile that is currently operational</u>, the Hwasong-14, <u>has enough range for a nuclear attack against <strong>Seattle</strong> but <strong>not Mar-a-Lago</u></strong>. 22 <u>Would the same president who formally designated Seattle as an “anarchist jurisdiction”</u> in an attempt to starve it of federal dollars <u>be greatly concerned by a credible threat of a North Korean strike against it? </u>23 <u>Probably—but is “probably” a good enough answer for homeland deterrence credibility?</p><p></u>Another dimension of this same hypothesis has to do with the precise locations where populists choose to install military installations that are likely to become nuclear targets. During the Nixon administration, the objections of congressional Democrats to the planned construction of Sentinel anti-ballistic-missile facilities near their political strongholds such as Boston and Seattle led Secretary of Defense Melvin Laird to move the projects to less populated areas.24 President Nixon believed that he needed to work constructively with the Democrats on core national security issues. By contrast, a populist president would love to see his political opponents sweating the targets he put on their backs.25 </p><p><u>Populists in power may even be slow to help their political opponents’ regions recover from an actual nuclear attack. There is a lesson for nuclear analysts in the Trump administration’s intentional slow-walking of congressionally mandated emergency aid to the US territory of Puerto Rico after Hurricane Maria in 2017, one of the deadliest natural disasters in US history.26 Having long held a low opinion of Puerto Ricans, Trump reportedly told his chief of staff and budget director that he “did not want a single dollar going to Puerto Rico.” 27 Would Trump have been any more helpful if the island had been hit by a man-made bomb instead of a natural one? Maybe if Puerto Rico could do something for him in return, which leads to the second hypothesis:</p><p></u>Hypothesis 2. <u>Populists are likely to <strong>exploit their control</strong> over homeland deterrence to <strong>demand political concessions</strong> from their <strong>domestic political opponents</u></strong>. <u>At the heart of populism is a <strong>disrespect</strong> for the principle of <strong>equal application of the laws</u></strong>. Instead, <u>governance becomes a pure power game, and populist rulers notably <strong>exploit crises</strong> as <strong>opportunities</strong> to bring domestic political opponents to their knees</u>. <u>There is every reason to assume that a <strong>populist</strong> in full command of the nuclear and defense establishment would similarly <strong>take advantage</strong> of a <strong>nuclear crisis</strong> to conduct such a shakedown</u>. In other words, <u>populists in power will <strong>charge a high price</strong> for adequately <strong>responding to nuclear threats</strong> against their domestic opponents’ political strongholds.</p><p></u>Let us continue with the example of the Trump administration. The mass-destructive COVID-19 pandemic offers a highly relevant analogy for thinking about the internal political dynamics of a potential nuclear crisis under populist rule. Public-administration scholars have labeled Trump’s governing approach as “chaotic transactional federalism,” a cynical power system that “removes any vestige of certainty as decisions are shaped based on a desire to reward or punish other political actors, or left to subnational actors entirely. Expertise matters very little in these political, partisan transactions.” 28 In line with this, Trump responded to the COVID-19 crisis by pitting the 50 states against each other in bidding wars for vital medical supplies and for his political favor.29 The president publicly criticized Vice President Mike Pence for reaching out to all the state governors in his role as the coordinator of the national pandemic response, telling the press that he wanted Pence to deal only with those governors who were sufficiently “appreciative.” 30 Trump administration officials were even blunter in private. Trump’s son-in-law and closest adviser Jared Kushner reportedly said that New York Governor Andrew Cuomo “didn’t pound the phones hard enough to get PPE [personal protective equipment] for his state … . His people are going to suffer and that’s their problem.” 31 Trump’s response to the Democratic governors’ pleas for PPE to defend against the virus was essentially the same as his response to Ukrainian President Volodymyr Zelenskyy’s pleas for weapons to defend against Russia: “I would like you to do us a favor though.” 32</p><p>The hypothesis that populists will demand concessions from their domestic political opponents in exchange for issuing nuclear-deterrent threats on their behalf may at first glance appear to be only a matter of internal politics, but <u>the <strong><mark>distractions</strong> caused by <strong>internal</mark> political <mark>wrangling</u></strong> <u>could</mark> <strong>greatly <mark>affect the denouement of a time-sensitive nuclear crisis</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong><mark>Foreign powers</strong> could</mark> also be tempted to <strong><mark>initiate a nuclear crisis</u></strong></mark> <u>precisely in order <mark>to <strong>intensify their adversary’s domestic divisions</u></strong></mark>. In addition, when facing the double burden of a nuclear threat and simultaneous shakedown by the president, politicians from disfavored regions would likely appeal to friendly elements of the military for assistance. That possibility tees up the third hypothesis: </p><p>Hypothesis 3. <u><mark>The establishment’s <strong>reaction to populism</u></strong></mark> <u>is likely to <strong><mark>increase</strong></mark> deterrence <mark>instability</u> <u><strong>at least as much as the actions of the populists themselves</u></strong></mark>. Meier and Vieluf’s article implies that the fate of the world hangs on the establishment’s ability to keep populist fingers off the nuclear button. But <u>the establishment’s effort to fend off</u> the <u>populists could <strong>itself dramatically increase deterrence instability</u></strong>, for instance <u><mark>by sowing <strong>confusion</strong> about</mark> the <strong><mark>chain of command</u></strong></mark>. <u>This hypothesis is not <strong>mere speculation</u></strong>. Reacting to widespread fears that Trump might be tempted to launch a nuclear attack against China or another country after his 2020 election loss to Joe Biden, in January 2021, General Mark Milley, the chairman of the Joint Chiefs of Staff, quietly worked the phone lines to reassure key people at home and abroad that he personally would not allow the president to do anything of the sort. The chairman of the Joint Chiefs is legally outside the chain of command for the execution of the president’s military strategy. Indeed, neither he nor anyone else has the legal authority to prevent a determined president from launching a nuclear strike.33 Yet Milley told Pelosi, “The president alone can order the use of nuclear weapons. But he doesn’t make the decision alone. One person can order it, several people have to<u><strong> launch it.” 34 Essentially, Milley was saying that if push came to shove, the military would mutiny. Meier and Vieluf seem to think that Milley did the right thing (pp. 15–16). Maybe so, but he also set an ominous precedent.</p><p></u></strong>As I mentioned at the outset, these comments are simply intended to spark further discussion about the important issues raised by Meier and Vieluf’s stimulating article. <u>I would be relieved to discover that I am being overly pessimistic <mark>about <strong>humanity’s chances of survival</u></strong> <u>with</u></mark> either the establishments or the <u><strong><mark>populists</strong></mark> in charge of <strong>nuclear arsenals</u></strong>. <u>But <strong><mark>the more I study</mark> the issue</strong>, <mark>the <strong></mark>more pessimistic I become</p></u></strong>
1NC v Marlborough PP – CPS R3
Populism DA
null
1,681,254
218
149,140
./documents/hsld22/Harker/SaYi/Harker-SaYi-Neg-CPS-LD-Invitational-Round-3.docx
956,130
N
CPS LD Invitational
3
Marlborough PP
Advay Chandra
1ac - africa 1nc - t open borders, terror da, populism da, adv cp, case 2ar - all, ivi 2nr - populism da, case, ivi 2ar - populism da, case
hsld22/Harker/SaYi/Harker-SaYi-Neg-CPS-LD-Invitational-Round-3.docx
2022-12-17 22:21:52
80,922
SaYi
Harker SaYi
null
Sa.....
Yi.....
null
null
26,565
Harker
Harker
CA
null
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
3,143,997
NFU creates a new regime of nuclear restraint
Tannenwald 18
Nina Tannenwald, Director, International Relations Brown, Watson Institute for International Studies, Brown University, “The Great Unraveling: The Future of the Nuclear Normative Order,” MEETING THE CHALLENGES OF THE NEW NUCLEAR AGE: EMERGING RISKS AND DECLINING NORMS IN THE AGE OF TECHNOLOGICAL INNOVATION AND CHANGING NUCLEAR DOCTRINES, American Academy of Arts and Sciences, 2018, p. 27-29.
Renewing a Regime of Nuclear Restraint . The nuclear-armed states exhibit a striking collective lack of imagination about how to respond to the demands of the humanitarian campaign and the prohibition treaty, even while themselves implementing nuclear doctrines that undermine deterrence, stability, and non-use. a deeper source of normative unraveling is the unequal distribution of the “benefits” of deterrence. As a result of the asymmetrical nature of the nonproliferation regime, some states possess nuclear weapons, others—such as NATO members—are protected by the nuclear deterrence threats of others, while the rest, who exist outside any nuclear umbrella, must put their faith in norms, laws, and morality to protect against nuclear use. this situation is inherently unstable Without a conscious and collective effort to renew the norms of nuclear restraint, they are likely to unravel further, heightening the risk of nuclear war. . A renewed regime of restraint would aim to reduce contradictions and inconsistences in the nuclear normative order through greater effort to balance conflicting norms, which means some attention to principles of equity and fairness The cornerstone of a renewed regime of nuclear restraint would be strengthening the norm of non-use of nuclear weapons through the adoption of a declared no-first-use policy There have been increasing numbers of proposals for the United States to adopt a no-first-use policy in recent years, with compelling analyses. the case can be made more strongly for common declared no-first-use policies as the linchpin of a renewed regime of nuclear restraint among the nuclear powers A no-first-use policy means that nuclear powers would rely on nuclear weapons only to deter nuclear attacks.87 Adoption of no-first-use would not simply be “mere words,” but rather both doctrinal and operational issues would follow from it.88 An operational no-first-use doctrine would eliminate first-strike postures, preemptive capabilities, and other types of destabilizing warfighting strategies. It would induce restraint in targeting, launch-on-warning, alert levels of deployed systems, procurement, and modernization plans it would help shape the physical qualities of nuclear forces in a way that renders them unsuitable for missions other than deterrence of nuclear attacks A no-first-use policy also would reduce the risk of accidental, unauthorized, mistaken, or preemptive use. The removal of threats of a nuclear first strike would strengthen strategic and crisis stability. , no-first-use could be adopted unilaterally or as part of an international agreement It would move Russia and Pakistan away from their high-risk doctrines and reduce a source of Russia-NATO tensions Skeptics will object that the geopolitical preconditions are not ripe for a no-first-use policy at this time. Russia and North Korea are hostile. The Obama administration choked at the last minute on declaring a no-first-use policy, largely because of pushback from allies who are under the U.S. nuclear umbrella. And restraint is not a word normally associated with President Trump, who trades in excess. But the threat to defend allies such as South Korea and Japan with nuclear weapons these days is hardly credible. In Europe, Russia is busy cutting military spending as its oil revenues shrink, with plans to cut the defense budget by 30 percent.93 This is not the sign of a country poised to invade the Baltics. Trump could act on his desire for better relations with Russian President Vladimir Putin to begin rolling back both countries’ nuclear posturing in Europe. Adoption of a no-first-use policy will require close consultation with allies, but the U.S. administration should begin this task. The United States could unilaterally adopt a no-first-use policy, asking other nuclear-armed states to do the same. This would constitute formal adoption of what is already essentially de facto U.S. policy.94 As even card-carrying realists such as the “four horsemen” recognized, given overwhelming U.S. conventional capabilities on the battlefield, there exists no plausible scenario in which nuclear first use would be in the interest of the United States. A U.S. no-first-use policy would create political space for Russia to follow suit. A common no-first-use policy would also help anchor the existing no-first-use policies of China and India and implicitly acknowledge their leadership in this area, a virtue when middle-power states are feeling disenfranchised from the global nuclear order.
the asymmetrical nature of nuclear deterrence is inherently unstable Without conscious effort to renew the norms of nuclear restraint, they are likely to unravel heightening the risk of nuclear war The cornerstone of a renewed regime of nuclear restraint would be no-first-use n -f -u would not be “mere words,” but both doctrinal and operational eliminate first-strike postures, preemptive capabilities, and destabilizing warfighting strategies It would induce restraint in , launch-on-warning n -f -u would reduce the risk of accidental, unauthorized , or preemptive use. The removal of threats of first strike would strengthen strategic and crisis stability n -f -u would move Russia and Pakistan away from high-risk doctrines and reduce Russia-NATO tensions the threat to defend allies such as South Korea and Japan with nuc s is hardly credible Russia is cutting military spending as oil revenues shrink This is not a country poised to invade the Baltics even card-carrying realists recognized, given overwhelming U.S. conventional capabilities , there exists no scenario in which nuclear first use would be in the interest of the U S . n -f u would create political space for Russia to follow n -f -u would help anchor the existing n -f -u policies of China and India
Renewing a Regime of Nuclear Restraint Lawrence Freedman has worried that the disarmament norm is “being used to deride other valuable forms of restraint, including deterrence.”83 This is true. Yet it is debatable whether the humanitarian campaign or the nuclear powers themselves are doing more to undermine deterrence. The nuclear-armed states exhibit a striking collective lack of imagination about how to respond to the demands of the humanitarian campaign and the prohibition treaty, even while themselves implementing nuclear doctrines that undermine deterrence, stability, and non-use. Beyond this, a deeper source of normative unraveling is the unequal distribution of the “benefits” of deterrence. As a result of the asymmetrical nature of the nonproliferation regime, some states possess nuclear weapons, others—such as NATO members—are protected by the nuclear deterrence threats of others, while the rest, who exist outside any nuclear umbrella, must put their faith in norms, laws, and morality to protect against nuclear use. As Angela Kane, UN high representative for disarmament affairs, noted in 2015, this situation is inherently unstable. “The risk of proliferation grows every additional day that states insist the doctrine of nuclear deterrence is essential for their security.”84 The larger problem is one of inequitable access to security globally.85 Restraint is a condition of keeping a situation “under control or within limits.”86 It is associated with notions of self-control, self-discipline, moderation, and prudence. Without a conscious and collective effort to renew the norms of nuclear restraint, they are likely to unravel further, heightening the risk of nuclear war. A renewed regime of nuclear restraint must be based on the fundamental recognition that security in the nuclear age cannot be achieved unilaterally. Rather, it requires the cooperation of others. A renewed regime of restraint would aim to reduce contradictions and inconsistences in the nuclear normative order through greater effort to balance conflicting norms, which means some attention to principles of equity and fairness. A No-First-Use Regime The cornerstone of a renewed regime of nuclear restraint would be strengthening the norm of non-use of nuclear weapons through the adoption of a declared no-first-use policy by all the nuclear powers. There have been increasing numbers of proposals for the United States to adopt a no-first-use policy in recent years, with compelling analyses. However, the case can be made more strongly for common declared no-first-use policies as the linchpin of a renewed regime of nuclear restraint among the nuclear powers. A no-first-use policy means that nuclear powers would rely on nuclear weapons only to deter nuclear attacks.87 Adoption of no-first-use would not simply be “mere words,” but rather both doctrinal and operational issues would follow from it.88 An operational no-first-use doctrine would eliminate first-strike postures, preemptive capabilities, and other types of destabilizing warfighting strategies. It would induce restraint in targeting, launch-on-warning, alert levels of deployed systems, procurement, and modernization plans. In other words, it would help shape the physical qualities of nuclear forces in a way that renders them unsuitable for missions other than deterrence of nuclear attacks.89 A no-first-use policy also would reduce the risk of accidental, unauthorized, mistaken, or preemptive use. The removal of threats of a nuclear first strike would strengthen strategic and crisis stability.90 It would also make absolute the boundary between nuclear and conventional weapons. Finally, by reducing the overall risk of nuclear dangers, no-first-use policies would move toward addressing humanitarian concerns and reducing the salience of nuclear weapons.91 As others have argued, no-first-use could be adopted unilaterally or as part of an international agreement. It would move Russia and Pakistan away from their high-risk doctrines and reduce a source of Russia-NATO tensions. For Russia to consider no-first-use, its concerns about U.S. ballistic missile defenses, imbalances in conventional forces, and issues of NATO enlargement would need to be addressed. The United States would need to address the issue of extended deterrence with its allies and move toward conventional extended deterrence.92 India and Pakistan would need a modus vivendi on Kashmir. The United States and North Korea would need a nonaggression pact. What are the prospects for this? Skeptics will object that the geopolitical preconditions are not ripe for a no-first-use policy at this time. Russia and North Korea are hostile. The Obama administration choked at the last minute on declaring a no-first-use policy, largely because of pushback from allies who are under the U.S. nuclear umbrella. And restraint is not a word normally associated with President Trump, who trades in excess. But the threat to defend allies such as South Korea and Japan with nuclear weapons these days is hardly credible. In Europe, Russia is busy cutting military spending as its oil revenues shrink, with plans to cut the defense budget by 30 percent.93 This is not the sign of a country poised to invade the Baltics. Trump could act on his desire for better relations with Russian President Vladimir Putin to begin rolling back both countries’ nuclear posturing in Europe. Adoption of a no-first-use policy will require close consultation with allies, but the U.S. administration should begin this task. The United States could unilaterally adopt a no-first-use policy, asking other nuclear-armed states to do the same. This would constitute formal adoption of what is already essentially de facto U.S. policy.94 As even card-carrying realists such as the “four horsemen” recognized, given overwhelming U.S. conventional capabilities on the battlefield, there exists no plausible scenario in which nuclear first use would be in the interest of the United States. A U.S. no-first-use policy would create political space for Russia to follow suit. A common no-first-use policy would also help anchor the existing no-first-use policies of China and India and implicitly acknowledge their leadership in this area, a virtue when middle-power states are feeling disenfranchised from the global nuclear order. As an initial step on the way to no-first-use and a regime of nuclear restraint, the U.S. administration should consider the recent proposal by Jeffrey Lewis and Scott Sagan that the United States should declare it will not use nuclear weapons “against any target that could be reliably destroyed by conventional means.”95 This policy would not solve the larger problem of the unhappy entangling of conventional and nuclear deterrence (for example, U.S. hypersonic weapons targeted against China). Nevertheless, it would represent an initial important declaratory statement of nuclear restraint.
6,946
<h4>NFU creates a new regime of nuclear restraint</h4><p>Nina <u><strong>Tannenwald</u></strong>, Director, International Relations Brown, Watson Institute for International Studies, Brown University, “The Great Unraveling: The Future of the Nuclear Normative Order,” MEETING THE CHALLENGES OF THE NEW NUCLEAR AGE: EMERGING RISKS AND DECLINING NORMS IN THE AGE OF TECHNOLOGICAL INNOVATION AND CHANGING NUCLEAR DOCTRINES, American Academy of Arts and Sciences, 20<u><strong>18</u></strong>, p. 27-29.</p><p><u><strong>Renewing a Regime of Nuclear Restraint</p><p></u></strong>Lawrence Freedman has worried that the disarmament norm is “being used to deride other valuable forms of restraint, including deterrence.”83 This is true. Yet it is debatable whether the humanitarian campaign or the nuclear powers themselves are doing more to undermine deterrence<u><strong>. The nuclear-armed states exhibit a striking collective lack of imagination about how to respond to the demands of the humanitarian campaign and the prohibition treaty, even while themselves implementing nuclear doctrines that undermine deterrence, stability, and non-use.</p><p></u></strong>Beyond this, <u><strong>a deeper source of normative unraveling is the unequal distribution of the “benefits” of deterrence. As a result of <mark>the asymmetrical nature of</mark> the nonproliferation regime, some states possess nuclear weapons, others—such as NATO members—are protected by the <mark>nuclear deterrence</mark> threats of others, while the rest, who exist outside any nuclear umbrella, must put their faith in norms, laws, and morality to protect against nuclear use.</u></strong> As Angela Kane, UN high representative for disarmament affairs, noted in 2015, <u><strong>this situation <mark>is inherently unstable</u></strong></mark>. “The risk of proliferation grows every additional day that states insist the doctrine of nuclear deterrence is essential for their security.”84 The larger problem is one of inequitable access to security globally.85 Restraint is a condition of keeping a situation “under control or within limits.”86 It is associated with notions of self-control, self-discipline, moderation, and prudence. <u><strong><mark>Without </mark>a<mark> conscious</mark> and collective <mark>effort to renew the norms of nuclear restraint, they are likely to unravel </mark>further,<mark> heightening the risk of nuclear war</mark>.</u></strong> A renewed regime of nuclear restraint must be based on the fundamental recognition that security in the nuclear age cannot be achieved unilaterally. Rather, it requires the cooperation of others<u><strong>. A renewed regime of restraint would aim to reduce contradictions and inconsistences in the nuclear normative order through greater effort to balance conflicting norms, which means some attention to principles of equity and fairness</u></strong>.</p><p>A No-First-Use Regime</p><p><u><strong><mark>The cornerstone of a renewed regime of nuclear restraint would be</mark> strengthening the norm of non-use of nuclear weapons through the adoption of a declared<mark> no-first-use </mark>policy </u></strong>by all the nuclear powers. <u><strong>There have been increasing numbers of proposals for the United States to adopt a no-first-use policy in recent years, with compelling analyses.</u></strong> However, <u><strong>the case can be made more strongly for common declared no-first-use policies as the linchpin of a renewed regime of nuclear restraint among the nuclear powers</u></strong>.</p><p><u><strong>A no-first-use policy means that nuclear powers would rely on nuclear weapons only to deter nuclear attacks.87 Adoption of <mark>n</mark>o<mark>-f</mark>irst<mark>-u</mark>se <mark>would not </mark>simply <mark>be “mere words,” but </mark>rather<mark> both doctrinal and operational </mark>issues would follow from it.88 An operational no-first-use doctrine would <mark>eliminate first-strike postures, preemptive capabilities, and </mark>other types of <mark>destabilizing warfighting strategies</mark>. <mark>It would induce restraint in </mark>targeting<mark>, launch-on-warning</mark>, alert levels of deployed systems, procurement, and modernization plans</u></strong>. In other words, <u><strong>it would help shape the physical qualities of nuclear forces in a way that renders them unsuitable for missions other than deterrence of nuclear attacks</u></strong>.89 <u><strong>A<mark> n</mark>o<mark>-f</mark>irst<mark>-u</mark>se policy also <mark>would reduce the risk of accidental, unauthorized</mark>, mistaken<mark>, or preemptive use. The removal of threats of </mark>a nuclear <mark>first strike would strengthen strategic and crisis stability</mark>.</u></strong>90 It would also make absolute the boundary between nuclear and conventional weapons. Finally, by reducing the overall risk of nuclear dangers, no-first-use policies would move toward addressing humanitarian concerns and reducing the salience of nuclear weapons.91</p><p>As others have argued<u><strong>, <mark>n</mark>o<mark>-f</mark>irst<mark>-u</mark>se could be adopted unilaterally or as part of an international agreement</u></strong>. <u><strong>It <mark>would move Russia and Pakistan away from </mark>their <mark>high-risk doctrines and reduce </mark>a source of <mark>Russia-NATO tensions</u></strong></mark>. For Russia to consider no-first-use, its concerns about U.S. ballistic missile defenses, imbalances in conventional forces, and issues of NATO enlargement would need to be addressed. The United States would need to address the issue of extended deterrence with its allies and move toward conventional extended deterrence.92 India and Pakistan would need a modus vivendi on Kashmir. The United States and North Korea would need a nonaggression pact.</p><p>What are the prospects for this? <u><strong>Skeptics will object that the geopolitical preconditions are not ripe for a no-first-use policy at this time. Russia and North Korea are hostile. The Obama administration choked at the last minute on declaring a no-first-use policy, largely because of pushback from allies who are under the U.S. nuclear umbrella. And restraint is not a word normally associated with President Trump, who trades in excess. But <mark>the threat to defend allies such as South Korea and Japan with nuc</mark>lear weapon<mark>s </mark>these days <mark>is hardly credible</mark>. In Europe, <mark>Russia is</mark> busy <mark>cutting military spending as </mark>its<mark> oil revenues shrink</mark>, with plans to cut the defense budget by 30 percent.93 <mark>This is not </mark>the sign of <mark>a country poised to invade the Baltics</mark>. Trump could act on his desire for better relations with Russian President Vladimir Putin to begin rolling back both countries’ nuclear posturing in Europe. Adoption of a no-first-use policy will require close consultation with allies, but the U.S. administration should begin this task.</p><p>The United States could unilaterally adopt a no-first-use policy, asking other nuclear-armed states to do the same. This would constitute formal adoption of what is already essentially de facto U.S. policy.94 As <mark>even card-carrying realists</mark> such as the “four horsemen” <mark>recognized, given overwhelming U.S. conventional capabilities </mark>on the battlefield<mark>, there exists no </mark>plausible <mark>scenario in which nuclear first use would be in the interest of the U</mark>nited<mark> S</mark>tates. A U.S<mark>. n</mark>o<mark>-f</mark>irst-<mark>u</mark>se<mark> </mark>policy<mark> would create political space for Russia to follow </mark>suit. A common <mark>n</mark>o<mark>-f</mark>irst<mark>-u</mark>se<mark> </mark>policy<mark> would </mark>also<mark> help</mark> <mark>anchor the existing n</mark>o<mark>-f</mark>irst<mark>-u</mark>se<mark> policies of China and India</mark> and implicitly acknowledge their leadership in this area, a virtue when middle-power states are feeling disenfranchised from the global nuclear order.</p><p></u></strong>As an initial step on the way to no-first-use and a regime of nuclear restraint, the U.S. administration should consider the recent proposal by Jeffrey Lewis and Scott Sagan that the United States should declare it will not use nuclear weapons “against any target that could be reliably destroyed by conventional means.”95 This policy would not solve the larger problem of the unhappy entangling of conventional and nuclear deterrence (for example, U.S. hypersonic weapons targeted against China). Nevertheless, it would represent an initial important declaratory statement of nuclear restraint. </p>
1ac UMN FJ – Mary Washington
null
Norms
372,067
733
102,137
./documents/ndtceda18/Minnesota/JaFe/Minnesota-Jamal-Ferguson-Aff-Mary%20Washington-Round3.docx
606,624
A
Mary Washington
3
Cornell MS
Tom OGorman
1ac war powers crisis norms 1nc Security k T only restrict president esr midterms flex deterrence on case shift on case block esr deterrence shift flex 2nr esr flex shift
ndtceda18/Minnesota/JaFe/Minnesota-Jamal-Ferguson-Aff-Mary%20Washington-Round3.docx
null
51,466
JaFe
Minnesota JaFe
null
Ha.....
Ja.....
Jo.....
Fe.....
19,202
Minnesota
Minnesota
null
null
1,008
ndtceda18
NDT/CEDA 2018-19
2,018
cx
college
2
1,689,534
Containment in east Asia will inevitably fail and alienates allies – Only a shift to a stable balance of power through accommodation prevents security dilemmas
Heer 19,
Paul Heer 19, National Intelligence Officer for East Asia in the Office of the Director of National Intelligence from 2007 to 2015. He has since served as Robert E. Wilhelm Research Fellow at the Massachusetts Institute of Technology’s Center for International Studies and as Adjunct Professor at George Washington University’s Elliott School of International Affairs., 1-8-2019, "Rethinking U.S. Primacy in East Asia," National Interest, https://nationalinterest.org/blog/skeptics/rethinking-us-primacy-east-asia-40972?page=0%2C1
this policy mantra has two fundamental problems: it mischaracterizes China’s strategic intentions in the region, and it is based on a U.S. strategic objective that is probably no longer achievable. China is pursuing hegemony in East Asia, but not an exclusive hostile hegemony It is not trying to extrude the United States from the region or deny American access there. The Chinese have long recognized the utility—and the benefits to China itself—of U.S. engagement with the region, and they have indicated receptivity to peaceful coexistence and overlapping spheres of influence with the United States there. Moreover, China is not trying to impose its political or economic system on its neighbors, and it does not seek to obstruct commercial freedom ). In short, Beijing wants to extend its power and influence within East Asia, but not as part of a “winner-take-all” contest. Of course, China would prefer not to have forward-deployed U.S. military forces in the Western Pacific that could be used against it, but Beijing has long tolerated and arguably could indefinitely tolerate an American military presence in the region—unless that presence is clearly and exclusively aimed at coercing or containing China. The Chinese almost certainly recognize that exclusive control or “domination” of the neighborhood is not achievable at any reasonable cost, and that pursuing it would be counterproductive by inviting pushback and challenges that would negate the objective. So what would Chinese “hegemony” in East Asia mean or look like? Beijing probably thinks in terms of something much like American primacy in the Western Hemisphere: a model in which China is generally recognized as the de facto central or primary power in the region but has little need or incentive for militarily adventurism because the mutual benefits of economic interdependence prevail and the neighbors have no reason to challenge China’s vital interests or security. A standard counterargument to this relatively benign scenario is that Beijing would not be content with it for long because China’s strategic ambitions will expand as its capabilities grow This is a valid hypothesis, but it usually overlooks the greater possibility that China’s external ambitions will expand not because its inherent capabilities have grown, but because Beijing sees the need to be more assertive in response to external challenges Indeed, much of China’s “assertiveness” within East Asia over the past decade has been a reaction to such perceived challenges. Accordingly, Beijing’s willingness to settle for a narrowly-defined, peaceable version of regional preeminence will depend heavily on whether it perceives other countries especially the United States as trying to deny China this option and instead obstruct Chinese interests or security in the region. U.S. primacy in the region itself is not sustainable, and trying to sustain it will probably be counterproductive. American primacy in East Asia—depending on how it is defined—is arguably already a thing of the past. China has a larger share of East Asian regional trade than the United States, and is now the biggest trading partner of most of its neighbors If defined in military terms, most net assessments suggest that the American advantage in power projection forces within the region is eroding relative to Chinese capabilities; and it is not at all clear in the wake of sequestration and competing budgetary priorities that the United States could or will devote the resources necessary to arrest this trend. even U.S. allies do not perceive that China is being deterred in the South and East China Seas. More broadly, it is not clear what other public goods the United States is actually providing in the East Asian commons. For example, commercial shippers in the Western Pacific do not presume or rely on the protection of the U.S. Navy And Washington’s withdrawal from the Trans-Pacific Partnership has undermined the idea of U.S. leadership in the region on behalf of shared economic interests. Indeed, most East Asian countries—including U.S. allies—appear increasingly uncertain about Washington’s attention to their interests and their security Questions and even doubts about the substance and sustainability of the American commitment to the region have grown over the past decade, and most of the countries in the regio have already been adjusting their foreign and security policies to hedge against the potential unreliability of the United States Indeed, such hedging and independent-mindedness by U.S. allies is itself contributing to the erosion of U.S. influence in the region. On balance, it is hard to make the case that the United States retains effective primacy in the Western Pacific when much of the region has doubts about Washington’s ability and willingness to exercise it. It may be possible to regain the confidence of U.S. allies and partners in East Asia, but restoring and retaining American primacy there over the long term is probably no longer achievable Moreover, policies and strategies aimed at upholding U.S. primacy in East Asia are likely to be counterproductive because such an approach, probably more than anything else, would reinforce Beijing’s belief that the United States seeks to contain China by keeping it subordinate within its own region This would increase the chances of Beijing feeling compelled to adopt a more confrontational and aggressive posture Chinese pursuit of a more exclusive hostile hegemony could thus become a self-fulfilling prophecy. Instead, the United States needs to recognize and acknowledge the emerging limits on its power, influence and position in East Asia U.S. primacy in the region is not materially sustainable, it becomes untenable to define it as a vital interest that must be upheld But Washington should not approach this competition on the basis of outdated assumptions—including the belief that U.S. primacy in East Asia can and should be perpetually sustained (an obsolete world view), a misunderstanding or mischaracterization of China’s regional ambitions, or a miscalculation of the United States’ own power and leverage. Washington should accept that strategic competition is unavoidable and absolute security is not possible. It should also recognize that even U.S. allies and partners in the region are already operating within overlapping American and Chinese spheres of influence—and they prefer this to being forced to choose between Washington and Beijing. The United States can and should continue to exercise leadership in East Asia, but will need to share it with China Washington should seek to deescalate the current trend in the regional competition with Beijing—which is now heading toward a destabilizing and futile game of “king of the hill”—and instead pursue opportunities to engage Beijing toward establishing a long-term, stable balance of power in the region
China is pursuing hegemony but not an exclusive hostile hegemony. It is not trying to extrude the U S and indicated receptivity to peaceful coexistence and overlapping s o i China is not trying to impose its system on its neighbors China could indefinitely tolerate an American military presence unless that presence is aimed at containing China Chinese recognize domination is not achievable Beijing thinks in terms of a model in which China is primary power but has little need for militarily adventurism because economic interdependence prevail and the neighbors have no reason to challenge interests China’s external ambitions will expand because Beijing sees the need to be more assertive in response to external challenges assertiveness over the past decade has been a reaction willingness to settle for peace will depend on whether the U S try to obstruct Chinese interests U.S. primacy is not sustainable power projection is eroding relative to Chinese capabilities in the wake of sequestration and competing budgetary priorities allies do not perceive that China is being deterred most East Asian allies appear increasingly uncertain about Washington’s attention to their security adjusting policies to hedge against unreliability the region has doubts about Washington’s ability and willingness upholding primacy reinforce Beijing’s belief that the U S seeks to keep it subordinate This would increase the chances of aggressive posture. hostile hegemony could become a self-fulfilling prophecy Washington should deescalate and pursue a long-term, stable balance of power
American policy in the Western Pacific has long been framed in terms of preventing the emergence of an exclusive, hostile hegemon that could threaten vital U.S. interests and deny American access there. The Trump administration’s National Security Strategy and National Defense Strategy respectively assert that “China seeks to displace the United States” in East Asia and thus achieve “Indo-Pacific regional hegemony.” Avoiding this possibility has required Washington, also as a matter of policy, to maintain its own hegemony in the region (although we prefer to call it “primacy” or “preeminence”) as the best and only guarantee against such a danger. This mantra was central to the Obama administration’s “rebalance” in East Asia, and remains central to the Trump administration’s advocacy of a “Free and Open Indo-Pacific.” But this policy mantra has two fundamental problems: it mischaracterizes China’s strategic intentions in the region, and it is based on a U.S. strategic objective that is probably no longer achievable. First, China is pursuing hegemony in East Asia, but not an exclusive hostile hegemony. It is not trying to extrude the United States from the region or deny American access there. The Chinese have long recognized the utility—and the benefits to China itself—of U.S. engagement with the region, and they have indicated receptivity to peaceful coexistence and overlapping spheres of influence with the United States there. Moreover, China is not trying to impose its political or economic system on its neighbors, and it does not seek to obstruct commercial freedom of navigation in the region (because no country is more dependent on freedom of the seas than China itself). In short, Beijing wants to extend its power and influence within East Asia, but not as part of a “winner-take-all” contest. China does have unsettled and vexing sovereignty claims over Taiwan, most of the islands and other features in the East and South China Seas, and their adjacent waters. Although Beijing has demonstrated a willingness to use force in defense or pursuit of these claims, it is not looking for excuses to do so. Whether these disputes can be managed or resolved in a way that is mutually acceptable to the relevant parties and consistent with U.S. interests in the region is an open, long-term question. But that possibility should not be ruled out on the basis of—or made more difficult by—false assumptions of irreconcilable interests. On the contrary, it should be pursued on the basis of a recognition that all the parties want to avoid conflict—and that the sovereignty disputes in the region ultimately are not military problems requiring military solutions. And since Washington has never been opposed in principle to reunification between China and Taiwan as long as it is peaceful, and similarly takes no position on the ultimate sovereignty of the other disputed features, their long-term disposition need not be the litmus test of either U.S. or Chinese hegemony in the region. Of course, China would prefer not to have forward-deployed U.S. military forces in the Western Pacific that could be used against it, but Beijing has long tolerated and arguably could indefinitely tolerate an American military presence in the region—unless that presence is clearly and exclusively aimed at coercing or containing China. It is also true that Beijing disagrees with American principles of military freedom of navigation in the region; and this constitutes a significant challenge in waters where China claims territorial jurisdiction in violation of the UN Commission on the Law of the Sea. But this should not be conflated with a Chinese desire or intention to exclusively “control” all the waters within the first island chain in the Western Pacific. The Chinese almost certainly recognize that exclusive control or “domination” of the neighborhood is not achievable at any reasonable cost, and that pursuing it would be counterproductive by inviting pushback and challenges that would negate the objective. So what would Chinese “hegemony” in East Asia mean or look like? Beijing probably thinks in terms of something much like American primacy in the Western Hemisphere: a model in which China is generally recognized and acknowledged as the de facto central or primary power in the region, but has little need or incentive for militarily adventurism because the mutual benefits of economic interdependence prevail and the neighbors have no reason—and inherent disincentives—to challenge China’s vital interests or security. And as a parallel to China’s economic and diplomatic engagement in Latin America, Beijing would neither exclude nor be hostile to continued U.S. engagement in East Asia. A standard counterargument to this relatively benign scenario is that Beijing would not be content with it for long because China’s strategic ambitions will expand as its capabilities grow. This is a valid hypothesis, but it usually overlooks the greater possibility that China’s external ambitions will expand not because its inherent capabilities have grown, but because Beijing sees the need to be more assertive in response to external challenges to Chinese interests or security. Indeed, much of China’s “assertiveness” within East Asia over the past decade—when Beijing probably would prefer to focus on domestic priorities—has been a reaction to such perceived challenges. Accordingly, Beijing’s willingness to settle for a narrowly-defined, peaceable version of regional preeminence will depend heavily on whether it perceives other countries—especially the United States—as trying to deny China this option and instead obstruct Chinese interests or security in the region. This leads to the second inherent problem with the mantra that the United States must maintain its primacy in the Western Pacific to prevent a hostile rival hegemon: U.S. primacy in the region itself is not sustainable, and trying to sustain it will probably be counterproductive. For all intents and purposes, American primacy in East Asia—depending on how it is defined—is arguably already a thing of the past. Since about a decade ago, China has a larger share of East Asian regional trade than the United States, and is now the biggest trading partner of most of its neighbors. If defined in military terms, most net assessments suggest that the American advantage in power projection forces within the region is eroding relative to Chinese capabilities; and it is not at all clear in the wake of sequestration and competing budgetary priorities that the United States could or will devote the resources necessary to arrest this trend. American primacy in East Asia has often been characterized in terms of the United States serving as the guarantor of regional security, protecting the “global commons” and providing “public goods” there. The U.S. alliance network in the region certainly extends an umbrella of protection to those countries with which Washington has defense pacts; and its military freedom of navigation operations signal an intention to resist excessive Chinese maritime claims. But even U.S. allies do not perceive that China is being deterred in the South and East China Seas. More broadly, it is not clear what other public goods the United States is actually providing in the East Asian commons. For example, commercial shippers in the Western Pacific do not presume or rely on the protection of the U.S. Navy—which doesn’t have the fleet to provide it. And Washington’s withdrawal from the Trans-Pacific Partnership has undermined the idea of U.S. leadership in the region on behalf of shared economic interests. Indeed, most East Asian countries—including U.S. allies—appear increasingly uncertain about Washington’s attention to their interests and their security. Questions and even doubts about the substance and sustainability of the American commitment to the region have grown over the past decade, and most of the countries in the region—again, including U.S. allies—have already been adjusting their foreign and security policies to hedge against the potential unreliability of the United States. Indeed, such hedging and independent-mindedness by U.S. allies is itself contributing to the erosion of U.S. influence in the region. On balance, it is hard to make the case that the United States retains effective primacy in the Western Pacific when much of the region has doubts about Washington’s ability and willingness to exercise it. So what can and should Washington do to address these new historical circumstances? It may be possible to regain the confidence of U.S. allies and partners in East Asia, but restoring and retaining American primacy there over the long term is probably no longer achievable, given the shifts in the regional balance of power and the constraints on U.S. resources. It’s not 1945 anymore, or even 1991. The United States sought and maintained a preponderance of power during the Cold War, but this almost certainly is not permanently sustainable, either globally or within East Asia. American primacy in the Western Pacific was a historical anomaly, and sooner or later the United States will have to get used to a regional role that is something less than that. Moreover, policies and strategies aimed at upholding U.S. primacy in East Asia are likely to be counterproductive because such an approach, probably more than anything else, would reinforce Beijing’s belief that the United States seeks to contain China by keeping it subordinate within its own region. This would increase the chances of Beijing feeling compelled to adopt a more confrontational and aggressive posture. Chinese pursuit of a more exclusive hostile hegemony could thus become a self-fulfilling prophecy. Instead, the United States needs to recognize and acknowledge the emerging limits on its power, influence and position in East Asia; and accordingly reassess both its definition of its interests in the region and the strategies by which it will pursue and defend those interests. If U.S. primacy in the region is not materially sustainable, it becomes untenable to define it as a vital interest that must be upheld. Indeed, over the long term Washington will have to confront the question of whether there is a version of Chinese primacy in East Asia which—being neither exclusive nor hostile, and akin to U.S. primacy in the Western Hemisphere—would be compatible with American interests and thus acceptable to the United States. None of this means that Washington should withdraw its military forces or commitments in East Asia, downgrade its diplomatic and economic engagement with the region, and surrender the Western Pacific to a Chinese sphere of influence. Quite the contrary. The United States needs to redouble its commitments, and expand and accelerate its engagement, in order to reassure its friends and allies in East Asia and reaffirm its determination to sustain a sphere of influence and a decisive role there. The U.S. alliance network can and should remain central to this effort. It will still be key to balancing, leveraging, guarding and pushing back against China when Beijing overplays its hand in its own pursuit of regional power and influence. But Washington should not approach this competition on the basis of outdated assumptions—including the belief that U.S. primacy in East Asia can and should be perpetually sustained (an obsolete world view), a misunderstanding or mischaracterization of China’s regional ambitions, or a miscalculation of the United States’ own power and leverage. Washington should accept that strategic competition is unavoidable and absolute security is not possible. It should also recognize that even U.S. allies and partners in the region are already operating within overlapping American and Chinese spheres of influence—and they prefer this to being forced to choose between Washington and Beijing. The United States can and should continue to exercise leadership in East Asia, but will need to share it with China. Washington should seek to deescalate the current trend in the regional competition with Beijing—which is now heading toward a destabilizing and futile game of “king of the hill”—and instead pursue opportunities to engage Beijing toward establishing a long-term, stable balance of power in the region. This is a tall order that will challenge the diplomatic and security management skills and finesse of both sides, and will almost certainly remain a work in progress for many years. But it will always be preferable to an arms race or a cold war in East Asia.
12,598
<h4><u>Containment</u> in east Asia will inevitably <u>fail</u> and <u>alienates allies</u> – Only a shift to a stable balance of power through <u>accommodation</u> prevents <u>security dilemmas </h4><p></u>Paul <strong>Heer 19,</strong> National Intelligence Officer for East Asia in the Office of the Director of National Intelligence from 2007 to 2015. He has since served as Robert E. Wilhelm Research Fellow at the Massachusetts Institute of Technology’s Center for International Studies and as Adjunct Professor at George Washington University’s Elliott School of International Affairs., 1-8-2019, "Rethinking U.S. Primacy in East Asia," National Interest, https://nationalinterest.org/blog/skeptics/rethinking-us-primacy-east-asia-40972?page=0%2C1</p><p>American policy in the Western Pacific has long been framed in terms of preventing the emergence of an exclusive, hostile hegemon that could threaten vital U.S. interests and deny American access there. The Trump administration’s National Security Strategy and National Defense Strategy respectively assert that “China seeks to displace the United States” in East Asia and thus achieve “Indo-Pacific regional hegemony.” Avoiding this possibility has required Washington, also as a matter of policy, to maintain its own hegemony in the region (although we prefer to call it “primacy” or “preeminence”) as the best and only guarantee against such a danger. This mantra was central to the Obama administration’s “rebalance” in East Asia, and remains central to the Trump administration’s advocacy of a “Free and Open Indo-Pacific.” But <u>this policy mantra has two fundamental problems: it</u> <u>mischaracterizes China’s strategic intentions in the region, and it is based on a U.S. strategic objective that is probably no longer achievable. </u>First, <u><mark>China is pursuing hegemony</mark> in East Asia, <mark>but not an exclusive hostile hegemony</u>. <u>It is not trying to extrude the U</mark>nited <mark>S</mark>tates from the region or deny American access there. The Chinese have long recognized the utility—and the benefits to China itself—of U.S. engagement with the region, <mark>and</mark> they have <mark>indicated receptivity to peaceful coexistence and overlapping s</mark>pheres <mark>o</mark>f<mark> i</mark>nfluence with the United States there.</u> <u>Moreover, <mark>China is not trying to impose its</mark> political or economic <mark>system on its neighbors</mark>, and it does not seek to obstruct commercial freedom</u> of navigation in the region (because no country is more dependent on freedom of the seas than China itself<u>). In short, Beijing wants to extend its power and influence within East Asia, but not as part of a “winner-take-all” contest. </u>China does have unsettled and vexing sovereignty claims over Taiwan, most of the islands and other features in the East and South China Seas, and their adjacent waters. Although Beijing has demonstrated a willingness to use force in defense or pursuit of these claims, it is not looking for excuses to do so. Whether these disputes can be managed or resolved in a way that is mutually acceptable to the relevant parties and consistent with U.S. interests in the region is an open, long-term question. But that possibility should not be ruled out on the basis of—or made more difficult by—false assumptions of irreconcilable interests. On the contrary, it should be pursued on the basis of a recognition that all the parties want to avoid conflict—and that the sovereignty disputes in the region ultimately are not military problems requiring military solutions. And since Washington has never been opposed in principle to reunification between China and Taiwan as long as it is peaceful, and similarly takes no position on the ultimate sovereignty of the other disputed features, their long-term disposition need not be the litmus test of either U.S. or Chinese hegemony in the region. <u>Of course, <mark>China</mark> would prefer not to have forward-deployed U.S. military forces in the Western Pacific that could be used against it, but Beijing has long tolerated and arguably <mark>could indefinitely tolerate an American military presence</mark> in the region—<mark>unless that presence is</mark> clearly and exclusively <mark>aimed at</mark> coercing or <mark>containing China<strong></mark>.</u></strong> It is also true that Beijing disagrees with American principles of military freedom of navigation in the region; and this constitutes a significant challenge in waters where China claims territorial jurisdiction in violation of the UN Commission on the Law of the Sea. But this should not be conflated with a Chinese desire or intention to exclusively “control” all the waters within the first island chain in the Western Pacific. <u>The <mark>Chinese</mark> almost certainly <mark>recognize</mark> that exclusive control or “<mark>domination</mark>” of the neighborhood <mark>is not achievable</mark> at any reasonable cost, and that pursuing it would be counterproductive by inviting pushback and challenges that would negate the objective. So what would Chinese “hegemony” in East Asia mean or look like? <mark>Beijing</mark> probably <mark>thinks in terms of</mark> something much like American primacy in the Western Hemisphere: <mark>a model in which China is</mark> generally recognized </u>and acknowledged <u>as the de facto central or <mark>primary power</mark> in the region</u>, <u><mark>but has little need</mark> or incentive <mark>for militarily adventurism because</mark> the mutual benefits of <mark>economic interdependence prevail and the neighbors have no reason</u></mark>—and inherent disincentives—<u><mark>to challenge</mark> China’s vital <mark>interests</mark> or security. </u>And as a parallel to China’s economic and diplomatic engagement in Latin America, Beijing would neither exclude nor be hostile to continued U.S. engagement in East Asia. <u>A standard counterargument to this relatively benign scenario is that Beijing would not be content with it for long because China’s strategic ambitions will expand as its capabilities grow</u>. <u>This is a valid hypothesis, but it usually overlooks the greater possibility</u> <u>that <mark>China’s external ambitions</u> <u>will expand</u></mark> <u>not because its inherent capabilities have grown, but <mark>because Beijing sees the need to be more assertive in response to external challenges</u></mark> to Chinese interests or security. <u>Indeed, much of China’s “<mark>assertiveness</mark>” within East Asia <mark>over the past decade</u></mark>—when Beijing probably would prefer to focus on domestic priorities—<u><mark>has been a reaction</mark> to such perceived challenges.<strong> </strong>Accordingly, Beijing’s <mark>willingness to settle for</mark> a narrowly-defined, <mark>peace</mark>able version of regional preeminence <mark>will depend</mark> heavily <mark>on whether</mark> it perceives other countries</u>—<u>especially <mark>the U</mark>nited <mark>S</mark>tates</u>—<u>as <mark>try</mark>ing <mark>to</mark> deny China this option</u> <u>and instead <mark>obstruct Chinese interests</mark> or security in the region. </u>This leads to the second inherent problem with the mantra that the United States must maintain its primacy in the Western Pacific to prevent a hostile rival hegemon: <u><mark>U.S. primacy</mark> in the region itself <mark>is not sustainable</mark>, and trying to sustain it will probably be<strong> </strong>counterproductive<strong>. </u></strong>For all intents and purposes, <u>American primacy in East Asia—depending on how it is defined—is arguably already a thing of the past.</u> Since about a decade ago, <u>China has a larger share of East Asian regional trade than the United States, and is now the biggest trading partner of most of its neighbors</u>. <u>If defined in military terms, most net assessments suggest that the American advantage in <mark>power projection</mark> forces within the region <mark>is eroding relative to Chinese capabilities</mark>; and it is not at all clear <mark>in the wake of sequestration and competing budgetary priorities</mark> that the United States could or will devote the resources necessary<strong> </strong>to arrest this trend.</u> American primacy in East Asia has often been characterized in terms of the United States serving as the guarantor of regional security, protecting the “global commons” and providing “public goods” there. The U.S. alliance network in the region certainly extends an umbrella of protection to those countries with which Washington has defense pacts; and its military freedom of navigation operations signal an intention to resist excessive Chinese maritime claims. But <u>even U.S. <mark>allies do not perceive that China is being deterred</mark> in the South and East China Seas.</u> <u>More broadly, it is not clear what other public goods the United States is actually providing in the East Asian commons. For example, commercial shippers in the Western Pacific do not presume or rely on the protection of the U.S. Navy</u>—which doesn’t have the fleet to provide it. <u>And Washington’s withdrawal from the Trans-Pacific Partnership has undermined the idea of U.S. leadership in the region on behalf of shared economic interests. Indeed, <mark>most East Asian</mark> countries—including U.S. <mark>allies</mark>—<mark>appear increasingly uncertain about Washington’s attention to their</mark> interests and their <mark>security</u></mark>. <u>Questions and even doubts about the substance and sustainability of the American commitment to the region have grown over the past decade, and most of the countries in the regio</u>n—again, including U.S. allies—<u>have already been <mark>adjusting</mark> their foreign and security <mark>policies to hedge against</mark> the potential <mark>unreliability</mark> of the United States</u>. <u>Indeed, such hedging and independent-mindedness by U.S. allies is itself contributing to the erosion of U.S. influence in the region.</u> <u>On balance, it is hard to make the case that the United States retains effective primacy in the Western Pacific when much of <mark>the region has doubts about Washington’s ability and willingness</mark> to exercise it<strong>.</u></strong> So what can and should Washington do to address these new historical circumstances? <u>It may be possible to regain the confidence of U.S. allies and partners in East Asia, but restoring and retaining American primacy there over the long term is probably no longer achievable</u>, given the shifts in the regional balance of power and the constraints on U.S. resources. It’s not 1945 anymore, or even 1991. The United States sought and maintained a preponderance of power during the Cold War, but this almost certainly is not permanently sustainable, either globally or within East Asia. American primacy in the Western Pacific was a historical anomaly, and sooner or later the United States will have to get used to a regional role that is something less than that. <u>Moreover, policies and strategies aimed at <mark>upholding</mark> U.S. <mark>primacy</mark> in East Asia are likely to be counterproductive because such an approach, probably more than anything</u> <u>else, would <mark>reinforce Beijing’s belief that the U</mark>nited <mark>S</mark>tates <mark>seeks to</mark> contain China by <mark>keep</mark>ing <mark>it subordinate</mark> within its own region</u>. <u><mark>This would increase the chances of</mark> Beijing feeling compelled to adopt a more confrontational and <mark>aggressive posture</u>.</mark> <u>Chinese pursuit of a more exclusive <mark>hostile hegemony could</mark> thus <mark>become a self-fulfilling prophecy</mark>. Instead, the United States needs to recognize and acknowledge the emerging limits on its power, influence and position in East Asia</u>; and accordingly reassess both its definition of its interests in the region and the strategies by which it will pursue and defend those interests. If <u>U.S. primacy in the region is not materially sustainable, it becomes untenable to define it as a vital interest that must be upheld</u>. Indeed, over the long term Washington will have to confront the question of whether there is a version of Chinese primacy in East Asia which—being neither exclusive nor hostile, and akin to U.S. primacy in the Western Hemisphere—would be compatible with American interests and thus acceptable to the United States. None of this means that Washington should withdraw its military forces or commitments in East Asia, downgrade its diplomatic and economic engagement with the region, and surrender the Western Pacific to a Chinese sphere of influence. Quite the contrary. The United States needs to redouble its commitments, and expand and accelerate its engagement, in order to reassure its friends and allies in East Asia and reaffirm its determination to sustain a sphere of influence and a decisive role there. The U.S. alliance network can and should remain central to this effort. It will still be key to balancing, leveraging, guarding and pushing back against China when Beijing overplays its hand in its own pursuit of regional power and influence. <u>But Washington should not approach this competition on the basis of outdated assumptions—including the belief that U.S. primacy in East Asia can and should be perpetually sustained (an obsolete world view), a misunderstanding or mischaracterization of China’s regional ambitions, or a miscalculation of the United States’ own power and leverage. Washington should accept that strategic competition is unavoidable and absolute security is not possible. It should also recognize that even U.S. allies and partners in the region are already operating within overlapping American and Chinese spheres of influence—and they prefer this to being forced to choose between Washington and Beijing. The United States can and should continue to exercise leadership in East Asia, but will need to share it with China</u>. <u><mark>Washington should</mark> seek to <mark>deescalate</mark> the current trend in the regional competition with Beijing—which is now heading toward a destabilizing and futile game of “king of the hill”—<mark>and</mark> instead <mark>pursue</mark> opportunities to engage</u> <u>Beijing</u> <u>toward establishing <mark>a long-term, stable balance of power</mark> in the region</u>. This is a tall order that will challenge the diplomatic and security management skills and finesse of both sides, and will almost certainly remain a work in progress for many years. But it will always be preferable to an arms race or a cold war in East Asia.</p>
1AC --- Philippines --- JCCC BB
1AC --- Adv --- S.C.S
null
10,248
609
50,344
./documents/ndtceda20/JCCC/BaBa/JCCC-Babcock-Babcock-Aff-Kentucky-Round6.docx
618,590
A
Kentucky
6
Minnesota PS
Michelle Borbon
1ac- Philippines 1nc- reduce t deterrence cp asean cp deterrence da xi da 2nr- asean cp and xi da
ndtceda20/JCCC/BaBa/JCCC-Babcock-Babcock-Aff-Kentucky-Round6.docx
null
52,317
BaBa
JCCC BaBa
null
Tr.....
Ba.....
Th.....
Ba.....
19,327
JCCC
JCCC
null
null
1,010
ndtceda20
NDT/CEDA 2020-21
2,020
cx
college
2
1,538,182
A] Focus on large scale catastrophes is good and they outweigh – appeals to social costs, moral rules, and securitization play into cognitive biases and flawed risk calculus – 2020 is living proof
Weber 20
Weber 20 (ELKE U. WEBER is Gerhard R. Andlinger Professor in Energy and the Environment and Professor of Psychology and Public Affairs at Princeton University.), November-December 2020 Issue, "Heads in the Sand," Foreign Affairs, https://www.foreignaffairs.com/articles/2020-10-13/heads-sand mvp
We are living in a time of crisis the world is grappling with massive global dangers In any given crisis, the right response is often clear What’s lacking are governments that can translate them into actual policy That means incorporating the full range of scientific knowledge available about the problem at hand. It means embracing uncertainty, rather than willfully ignoring it. And it means thinking in terms of a long time horizon Crises typically require navigating between risks. In the COVID-19 pandemic, policymakers want to save lives and jobs. With climate change, they seek a balance between avoiding extreme weather and allowing economic growth Vested interests attempt to forestall needed action They must accept large amounts of uncertainty. Often, then, the easiest response is to stick with the status quo. But that can be a singularly dangerous response to many new hazards. After all, with the pandemic, business as usual would mean no social distancing. With climate change, it would mean continuing to burn fossil fuels. the explanation for humanity’s woeful response to crises goes beyond politics and incentives. To truly understand the failure to act, one must turn to human psychology. cognitive biases, emotional reactions, and suboptimal shortcuts that hold policymakers back—and the tools to overcome them. People are singularly bad at predicting and preparing for catastrophes. Many of these events are “black swans,” rare and unpredictable occurrences that most people find difficult to imagine, seemingly falling into the realm of science fiction. Others are “gray rhinos,” large and not uncommon threats that are still neglected until they stare you in the face (such as a coronavirus outbreak Not only do humans fail to anticipate crises; they also fail to respond rationally to them. Because humans don’t have enough time, information, or processing power to deliberate rationally, they have evolved easier ways of making decisions. They rely on their emotions, which serve as an early warning system of sorts They also rely on rules they might follow standard operating procedures or abide by some sort of moral code But in times of crisis, emotions and rules are not helpful drivers
We are in a time of crisis with massive global dangers the right response is often clear What’s lacking are actual policy incorporating full range of scientific knowledge embracing uncertainty thinking in a long time horizon require navigating between risks Vested interests forestall action, cognitive biases, emotion and suboptimal shortcuts hold policymakers back People are singularly bad at predicting for catastrophes. Many are “black swans difficult to imagine . Others are not uncommon neglected until they stare you in the face Because humans don’t have time, info , or power to deliberate rationally They rely on emotions or moral code in crisis, emotions and rules are not helpful drivers
We are living in a time of crisis. From the immediate challenge of the COVID-19 pandemic to the looming existential threat of climate change, the world is grappling with massive global dangers—to say nothing of countless problems within countries, such as inequality, cyberattacks, unemployment, systemic racism, and obesity. In any given crisis, the right response is often clear. Wear a mask and keep away from other people. Burn less fossil fuel. Redistribute income. Protect digital infrastructure. The answers are out there. What’s lacking are governments that can translate them into actual policy. As a result, the crises continue. The death toll from the pandemic skyrockets, and the world makes dangerously slow progress on climate change, and so on. It’s no secret how governments should react in times of crisis. First, they need to be nimble. Nimble means moving quickly, because problems often grow at exponential rates: a contagious virus, for example, or greenhouse gas emissions. That makes early action crucial and procrastination disastrous. Nimble also means adaptive. Policymakers need to continuously adjust their responses to crises as they learn from their own experience and from the work of scientists. Second, governments need to act wisely. That means incorporating the full range of scientific knowledge available about the problem at hand. It means embracing uncertainty, rather than willfully ignoring it. And it means thinking in terms of a long time horizon, rather than merely until the next election. But so often, policymakers are anything but nimble and wise. They are slow, inflexible, uninformed, overconfident, and myopic. Why is everyone doing so badly? Part of the explanation lies in the inherent qualities of crises. Crises typically require navigating between risks. In the COVID-19 pandemic, policymakers want to save lives and jobs. With climate change, they seek a balance between avoiding extreme weather and allowing economic growth. Such tradeoffs are hard as it is, and they are further complicated by the fact that costs and benefits are not evenly distributed among stakeholders, making conflict a seemingly unavoidable part of any policy choice. Vested interests attempt to forestall needed action, using their money to influence decision-makers and the media. To make matters worse, policymakers must pay sustained attention to multiple issues and multiple constituencies over time. They must accept large amounts of uncertainty. Often, then, the easiest response is to stick with the status quo. But that can be a singularly dangerous response to many new hazards. After all, with the pandemic, business as usual would mean no social distancing. With climate change, it would mean continuing to burn fossil fuels. But the explanation for humanity’s woeful response to crises goes beyond politics and incentives. To truly understand the failure to act, one must turn to human psychology. It is there that one can grasp the full impediments to proper decision-making—the cognitive biases, emotional reactions, and suboptimal shortcuts that hold policymakers back—and the tools to overcome them. AVOIDING THE UNCOMFORTABLE People are singularly bad at predicting and preparing for catastrophes. Many of these events are “black swans,” rare and unpredictable occurrences that most people find difficult to imagine, seemingly falling into the realm of science fiction. Others are “gray rhinos,” large and not uncommon threats that are still neglected until they stare you in the face (such as a coronavirus outbreak). Then there are “invisible gorillas,” threats in full view that should be noticed but aren’t—so named for a psychological experiment in which subjects watching a clip of a basketball game were so fixated on the players that they missed a person in a gorilla costume walking through the frame. Even professional forecasters, including security analysts, have a poor track record when it comes to accurately anticipating events. The COVID-19 crisis, in which a dystopic science-fiction narrative came to life and took everyone by surprise, serves as a cautionary tale about humans’ inability to foresee important events. Not only do humans fail to anticipate crises; they also fail to respond rationally to them. At best, people display “bounded rationality,” the idea that instead of carefully considering their options and making perfectly rational decisions that optimize their preferences, humans in the real world act quickly and imperfectly, limited as they are by time and cognitive capacity. Add in the stress generated by crises, and their performance gets even worse. Because humans don’t have enough time, information, or processing power to deliberate rationally, they have evolved easier ways of making decisions. They rely on their emotions, which serve as an early warning system of sorts: alerting people that they are in a positive context that can be explored and exploited or in a negative context where fight or flight is the appropriate response. They also rely on rules. To simplify decision-making, they might follow standard operating procedures or abide by some sort of moral code. They might decide to imitate the action taken by other people whom they trust or admire. They might follow what they perceive to be widespread norms. Out of habit, they might continue to do what they have been doing unless there is overwhelming evidence against it. Not only do humans fail to anticipate crises; they also fail to respond rationally to them. Humans evolved these shortcuts because they require little effort and work well in a broad range of situations. Without access to a real-time map of prey in different hunting grounds, for example, a prehistoric hunter might have resorted to a simple rule of thumb: look for animals where his fellow tribesmen found them yesterday. But in times of crisis, emotions and rules are not always helpful drivers of decision-making. High stakes, uncertainty, tradeoffs, and conflict—all elicit negative emotions, which can impede wise responses. Uncertainty is scary, as it signals an inability to predict what will happen, and what cannot be predicted might be deadly. The vast majority of people are already risk averse under normal circumstances. Under stress, they become even more so, and they retreat to the familiar comfort of the status quo. From gun laws to fossil fuel subsidies, once a piece of legislation is in place, it is hard to dislodge it, even when cost-benefit analysis argues for change.
6,531
<h4>A] Focus on large scale catastrophes is good and they outweigh – appeals to social costs, moral rules, and securitization play into cognitive biases and flawed risk calculus – 2020 is living proof</h4><p><strong>Weber 20</strong> (ELKE U. WEBER is Gerhard R. Andlinger Professor in Energy and the Environment and Professor of Psychology and Public Affairs at Princeton University.), November-December 2020 Issue, "Heads in the Sand," Foreign Affairs, https://www.foreignaffairs.com/articles/2020-10-13/heads-sand mvp</p><p><u><strong><mark>We are</mark> living <mark>in a time of crisis</u></strong></mark>. From the immediate challenge of the COVID-19 pandemic to the looming existential threat of climate change, <u><strong>the world is grappling <mark>with massive global dangers</u></strong></mark>—to say nothing of countless problems within countries, such as inequality, cyberattacks, unemployment, systemic racism, and obesity. <u><strong>In any given crisis, <mark>the right response is often clear</u></strong></mark>. Wear a mask and keep away from other people. Burn less fossil fuel. Redistribute income. Protect digital infrastructure. The answers are out there. <u><strong><mark>What’s lacking are</mark> governments that can translate them into <mark>actual policy</u></strong></mark>. As a result, the crises continue. The death toll from the pandemic skyrockets, and the world makes dangerously slow progress on climate change, and so on.</p><p>It’s no secret how governments should react in times of crisis. First, they need to be nimble. Nimble means moving quickly, because problems often grow at exponential rates: a contagious virus, for example, or greenhouse gas emissions. That makes early action crucial and procrastination disastrous. Nimble also means adaptive. Policymakers need to continuously adjust their responses to crises as they learn from their own experience and from the work of scientists. Second, governments need to act wisely. <u><strong>That means <mark>incorporating</mark> the <mark>full range of scientific knowledge</mark> available about the problem at hand. It means <mark>embracing uncertainty</mark>, rather than willfully ignoring it. And it means <mark>thinking in</mark> terms of <mark>a long time horizon</u></strong></mark>, rather than merely until the next election. But so often, policymakers are anything but nimble and wise. They are slow, inflexible, uninformed, overconfident, and myopic.</p><p>Why is everyone doing so badly? Part of the explanation lies in the inherent qualities of crises. <u><strong>Crises typically <mark>require navigating between risks</mark>. In the COVID-19 pandemic, policymakers want to save lives and jobs. With climate change, they seek a balance between avoiding extreme weather and allowing economic growth</u></strong>. Such tradeoffs are hard as it is, and they are further complicated by the fact that costs and benefits are not evenly distributed among stakeholders, making conflict a seemingly unavoidable part of any policy choice. <u><strong><mark>Vested interests</mark> attempt to <mark>forestall</mark> needed <mark>action</u></strong>,</mark> using their money to influence decision-makers and the media. To make matters worse, policymakers must pay sustained attention to multiple issues and multiple constituencies over time. <u><strong>They must accept large amounts of uncertainty. Often, then, the easiest response is to stick with the status quo. But that can be a singularly dangerous response to many new hazards. After all, with the pandemic, business as usual would mean no social distancing. With climate change, it would mean continuing to burn fossil fuels. </p><p></u></strong>But <u><strong>the explanation for humanity’s woeful response to crises goes beyond politics and incentives. To truly understand the failure to act, one must turn to human psychology.</u></strong> It is there that one can grasp the full impediments to proper decision-making—the <u><strong><mark>cognitive biases, emotion</mark>al reactions, <mark>and suboptimal shortcuts</mark> that <mark>hold policymakers back</mark>—and the tools to overcome them. </p><p></u></strong>AVOIDING THE UNCOMFORTABLE</p><p><u><strong><mark>People are singularly bad at predicting</mark> and preparing <mark>for catastrophes. Many</mark> of these events <mark>are “black swans</mark>,” rare and unpredictable occurrences that most people find <mark>difficult to imagine</mark>, seemingly falling into the realm of science fiction<mark>. Others are</mark> “gray rhinos,” large and <mark>not uncommon</mark> threats that are still <mark>neglected until they stare you in the face</mark> (such as a coronavirus outbreak</u></strong>). Then there are “invisible gorillas,” threats in full view that should be noticed but aren’t—so named for a psychological experiment in which subjects watching a clip of a basketball game were so fixated on the players that they missed a person in a gorilla costume walking through the frame. Even professional forecasters, including security analysts, have a poor track record when it comes to accurately anticipating events. The COVID-19 crisis, in which a dystopic science-fiction narrative came to life and took everyone by surprise, serves as a cautionary tale about humans’ inability to foresee important events. </p><p><u><strong>Not only do humans fail to anticipate crises; they also fail to respond rationally to them.</u></strong> At best, people display “bounded rationality,” the idea that instead of carefully considering their options and making perfectly rational decisions that optimize their preferences, humans in the real world act quickly and imperfectly, limited as they are by time and cognitive capacity. Add in the stress generated by crises, and their performance gets even worse.</p><p><u><strong><mark>Because humans don’t have</mark> enough <mark>time, info</mark>rmation<mark>, or</mark> processing <mark>power to deliberate rationally</mark>, they have evolved easier ways of making decisions. <mark>They rely on</mark> their <mark>emotions</mark>, which serve as an early warning system of sorts</u></strong>: alerting people that they are in a positive context that can be explored and exploited or in a negative context where fight or flight is the appropriate response. <u><strong>They also rely on rules</u></strong>. To simplify decision-making, <u><strong>they might follow standard operating procedures <mark>or</mark> abide by some sort of <mark>moral code</u></strong></mark>. They might decide to imitate the action taken by other people whom they trust or admire. They might follow what they perceive to be widespread norms. Out of habit, they might continue to do what they have been doing unless there is overwhelming evidence against it. </p><p>Not only do humans fail to anticipate crises; they also fail to respond rationally to them.</p><p>Humans evolved these shortcuts because they require little effort and work well in a broad range of situations. Without access to a real-time map of prey in different hunting grounds, for example, a prehistoric hunter might have resorted to a simple rule of thumb: look for animals where his fellow tribesmen found them yesterday. <u><strong>But <mark>in</mark> times of <mark>crisis, emotions and rules are not</u></strong></mark> always <u><strong><mark>helpful drivers</mark> </u></strong>of decision-making. High stakes, uncertainty, tradeoffs, and conflict—all elicit negative emotions, which can impede wise responses. Uncertainty is scary, as it signals an inability to predict what will happen, and what cannot be predicted might be deadly. The vast majority of people are already risk averse under normal circumstances. Under stress, they become even more so, and they retreat to the familiar comfort of the status quo. From gun laws to fossil fuel subsidies, once a piece of legislation is in place, it is hard to dislodge it, even when cost-benefit analysis argues for change.</p>
1NC
null
Case
333,124
172
43,956
./documents/hsld21/Sage/Pe/Sage-Perin-Neg-Greenhill-Round4.docx
897,626
N
Greenhill
4
Harrison JP
Varad Agarwala
ac fem nc nebel consult who distribution cp orphan drugs cp innovation da 1ar all theory 2nr orphan drugs cp theory 2ar all
hsld21/Sage/Pe/Sage-Perin-Neg-Greenhill-Round4.docx
null
75,289
MaPe
Sage MaPe
null
Ma.....
Pe.....
null
null
25,149
Sage
Sage
CA
null
1,029
hsld21
HS LD 2021-22
2,021
ld
hs
1
3,507,348
Trying to improve the lives of people while ignoring existential threats is like shuffling the deck-chairs on the titanic – extinction outweighs
Cerutti 14
Cerutti 14 - Professor of Political Philosophy emeritus at the University of Florence and Adjunct Professor at the Scuola superiore Sant’Anna, Pisa. In the last fifteen years, Cerutti has been aVisiting Professor at Harvard, the Universit´e de Paris 8, the Humboldt Universit ¨at zu Berlin, the London School of Economics and Political Science,(China Foreign Affairs University), Beijing, and Stanford University in Florence. Beyond the publications quoted in this article, Cerutti has written widely on the political identity of the Europeans and the legitimacy of the European Union (last publication: Debating Political Identity and Legitimacy in the European Union, ed. with S. Lucarelli and V. Schmidt, Routledge: London 2011). Also, his MOOC ‘Political Philosophy: An Introduction’ is accessible on the platform <iversity.org>.
given the existence of global threats which endanger the life of humankind as a civ- ilized species right to survive should be asserted as its first fundamental right. this is not just philosophical but legal as well nobody seems to take note that the life of all present and future individuals could be annihilated It is like insisting on first debating the rights of a ship’s passengers instead of taking action in the light of the fact that the ship is already taking in seawater from a leak These dangers are philosophically significant because they tell something about human beings challenges like nuclear weapons and climate change can hit everybody on earth and they would destroy human civilization the shifting of Theory to pure normativity has favored an exclusive attention on intersubjectivity as if challenges to politics and civilization caused by systemic imperatives such as the nuclear threat and climate change) were beyond the grasp of critical inquiry the self- centered normative approach should be restructured to address the challenges for humankind’s survival critical theorists seem to be reluctant to address the philosophical issues raised by global challenges, not to mention their complete denial of the meaning of nuclear weapons. It is as if Critical Theory had accepted a tacit division of labor in which its competence is restricted to social justice and the “damaged” subjectivity starting from problems and threats that come up as physical events and are accounted for by hard science has the advantage that philosophy can work on them without first engaging in a complicate and doubt- ful theorizing about how the world should be reshaped The literature on justice and climate change misses the point we have to motivate our interest in existence we should assume responsibility for future generations doing what we can for the survival of humankind can give ourselves reassurance that our individual life is meaningful because doing so helps us shed our isolation as single individuals or single generation and become partners in a wider transgenerational covenant of solidarity acknowledging this right is the pre-condition for making all other rights possible human rights can only apply to a living humankind, but not to a ”republic of insects and grass” The meta-right as a pre-condition has to be un- derstood in the moral sense: no foundation of morality makes sense if it cannot rely on the respect of the fundamental rights of those harmed by our acts and omissions global challenges, which have received so little attention in the mainstream philosophy of the last decades, have indeed philosophical implications capable of undermining the usual attitude in moral and political theory planetary lethal threats such as nuclear war or disastrous climate change have the potential strength to forge all relevant political actors into one community who received the push to unite from the threats to their life and limbs because they are all put in danger, and because they have to act jointly This is a possibility, not an inevitable process all this is enough to use ‘humankind’ in a political sense legal formulations cannot be ignored they create an appropriate and stable environment for what can really bring about a change, that is educational and political struggles, hu)mankind has thus ceased to be just a concept used by philosophers Support from civil society would help Finally, the author’s suggestion as to how to read this proposal: it has a clearly cosmopolitan (or better: cosmopolitical) character, not however in the sense of cosmopolitanism as a general doctrine of government/ governance. It is rather generated by tools coming from realist thought: new threats as source of new rights, and lethal and planetary threats to the survival of hu- mankind’s civilization as drivers towards a new level of legal protection.
given the existence of global threats which endanger humankind right to survive should be asserted as its first fundamental right nobody seems to note that the life of all present and futur could be annihilated the ship is already taking in seawater from a leak nuclear weapons can hit everybody Theory has favored intersubjectivity as if challenges to politics the self- centered approach should be restructured to address challenges for survival critical theorists seem to be reluctant to address philosophical issues raised by global challenges starting from problems and threats that come up as physical events and are accounted for by hard science has the advantage that philosophy can work on them without first engaging in a complicate and doubt- ful theorizing about how the world should be reshaped literature on justice misses the point we have to motivate our interest in existence we should assume responsibility for future generations But doing what we can for the survival can give ourselves reassurance that life is meaningful acknowledging this pre-condition human rights can only apply to a living humankind, but not to a ”republic of insects and grass no morality makes sense if it cannot rely on the respect of the fundamental right planetary threats have the potential strength to forge all relevant political actors into one community to unite from the threats because they are all in danger legal formulations cannot be ignored Support from civil society would help
(Furio “Humankind’s First Fundamental Right: Survival,” Constellations) This article’s main thesis1 is that, given the existence of at least two global threats, nuclear weapons and climate change, which endanger the life of humankind as a civ- ilized species, its right to survive should be asserted as its first human or rather fundamental right. The sense of this assertion is not just philosophical but legal as well.¶ To substantiate this thesis, I shall go through six argumentative steps:¶ 1. Why begin with global threats.¶ 2. Why survival is the leading category in this field, and¶ how it interplays with justice.¶ 3. What interest humankind has in its survival, and why¶ it should be protected as a right.¶ 4. Why regard “humankind” rather than “all indi-¶ viduals” as a possible actor.¶ 5. Why speak of a fundamental rather than human¶ right, and how to constitutionalize this right.¶ 6. How two developments in international law after 1945 can contribute to support the argument I have¶ been sketching.¶ **¶ 1. If philosophical thinking starts with being amazed at something in the world (Plato’s θαυμα ́ζειν), my in- terest in the present matter2 was first stimulated by the pre-philosophical amazement I always felt in seeing that in the now enormous human rights discourse (both in politics and academia) so much care is dedicated to the single individuals, and so wide-ranging designs of a cos- mopolis to come are based on their rights. Yet nobody seems to take note that the life of all present and future individuals could be annihilated by a nuclear war or up- set by catastrophic developments of climate change. It is like insisting on first debating the rights of a ship’s third- class passengers 3 instead of taking action in the light of the fact that the ship is already taking in seawater from a leak (climate change is already happening) and also risks to hit a mine that is floating around and would send it along with all passengers and crew straight to the ocean depths (by thinking and acting timely, leaks can be filled, mines detected and swept away, all ac- tions that would put the care for third-class passengers¶ on a firmer ground). These dangers are philosophically significant because they tell something about human beings, the only ones who have become able to destroy their own race, as well as about modernity: the possibil- ity of self-destruction sets an end to this era, opens a new one, which can only vaguely be termed post-modern,4 and requires an updated rewriting of the Dialectics of the Enlightenment. It is also politically significant as it challenges present politics to restructure itself by ex- tending its attention to the far future, something which is not possible within the boundaries of modern politics because of its narrow time structure.5 In a more precise language, I term challenges like nuclear weapons (con- sidered in themselves, while nuclear proliferation is but a subphenomenon) and climate change global (in a very specific sense) because they are lethal and planet-wide, can hit approximately everybody on earth and can be reasonably addressed only by the near totality of coun- tries and peoples. They would not wipe out biologically humankind, although this cannot be excluded in case of an all-out nuclear war; but they would destroy human civilization:6 not a set of values, but the set of material and cultural tools (agriculture, communications, trans- portation and trade) that allow unspecialized animals like the humans to survive and to thrive.¶ It is clear that my thesis presupposes a revised scale of relevance among the issues requiring and stimulat- ing theoretical investigations: in my philosophical view global threats have a greater relevance and are intellec- tually more challenging than the issues suggested by the media’s headlines (present wars, terrorism, group and minority rights in the US, multiculturalism in Canada or Australia, immigrants in Europe, or, more recently, the crisis of the global economic system). As a reflection upon the deeper longue dure ́e determinants of human- ity’s fate, political philosophy should not necessarily espouse the agenda suggested by current politics and journalism and, instead, seek its own independent as- sessment of the state of the world as part of its business; this is a critical attitude that cannot be implemented without a philosophical view on history (not to be con- fused with a revival of the “grand narratives”). Besides, the shifting of most of Critical Theory to pure normativity has favored the emergence not just of worldviews based on the predominance of Sollen, but also of an exclusive attention on intersubjectivity and its troubles; as if challenges to politics and civilization caused by systemic imperatives (such as the nuclear threat and¶ climate change) were beyond the grasp of critical inquiry. What I am attempting in this article is to address an issue such as human rights that is typical of the self- centered normative approach mentioned and to show how it should be restructured to address the challenges for humankind’s survival.¶ In this attempt I am driven by the intent to debunk the layer of denial (or repression in pshychoanalyti- cal sense) that, more intensely after the end of the Cold War, has removed the nuclear threat from the philosoph- ical reflection on modernity and has later prevented cli- mate change from entering the main agenda of Critical Theory. There is also an epistemological aspect in this: a critical Zeitdiagnose, or an informed assessment of where history has taken us to in our post-modern times is not possible without first taking what hard science has to say about the threats for humankind very seriously.7 With rare exceptions, critical theorists seem to be reluctant to address the philosophical issues raised by global challenges, not to mention their complete denial beginning with Horkheimer and Adorno in the Fifties and Sixties (when Mutual Assured Destruction became a real possibility) of the meaning of nuclear weapons. It is as if Critical Theory, despite its claim to be a gen- eral assessment of our civilization, had accepted a tacit division of labor in which its competence is restricted to social justice (in continuation of its original being rooted in the Marxian critique of political economy) and the “damaged”8 subjectivity. The rest of the real world is left to a purely Hobbesian (and later Luhmannian) reading, or to the perception of side-figures such as Karl Jaspers or Gu ̈nther Anders.¶ A last epistemological remark: starting from problems and threats that, however socially generated, come up as physical events and are accounted for by hard science has the advantage that philosophy can work on them without first engaging in a complicate and doubt- ful theorizing about how the world should be reshaped according to a general normative theory. This ad hoc theorizing shows the ability or inability of a philosoph- ical view to come to terms with problems that are of paramount importance to everybody, not just to the prac- titioners of Schulphilosophie.¶ 2. I have explained elsewhere9why survival rather than justice is the leading category of a philosophy of global threats. The now thriving literature on justice and climate change misses the point that before we look for ways to establish justice between generations, we have to motivate our interest in their existence and wellbeing, or rather in the existence and wellbeing of humankind.10 While survival of humankind is what best defines our problematic situation, when it comes to the normative aspect I believe that we should assume responsibility for future generations rather than do justice to them; talking responsibility I move from its most elementary¶ manifestation, the responsibility parents take on for their children. Justice as fairness comes in when we have to fight back “generational nepotism:” it is wrong for any generation to spoil the environment without regard to the consequences in the future, far that it may be, that is not just out of respect for those that may harm our children and children’s children. Out of elementary fairness, as expressed in the Golden Rule, we cannot deny parents of the, say, twenty-fifth century the chance to bear and educate their children in decent conditions.¶ Now, survival is a Hobbesian category, as such it sounds like an anathema to critical thinking, just as most categories stemming from the tradition of politi- cal realism do. Since under global threats present and future humankind is really endangered in its survival, it is however hard to see the rationale of denying the fact because the name comes from the enemy’s vocabu- lary. More importantly, there is an essential difference: Hobbes’ survival regards the individual and is there- fore self-centered and adversarial (in common parlance, mors tua vita mea), while humankind’s survival as a moral and political goal is by its own definition an uni- versalistic feature. More on this later.¶ A much talked-about issue in this context is the so- called identity problem, which I am however inclined to dismiss. If it means the doubtfulness of any engagement in favor of future generations because we do not know if they will exist (we could decide to stop procreating), the problem is surrounded by an air of futility: there is no imaginable decision process that could effectively lead to a total procreation stop. On the other hand, if only a few humans were alive in the far future, this would be enough of a reason for our engagement. Of course future humanity could never be born because meanwhile the planet may have been burnt out by an asteroid (natural precariousness of human life) or an all-out nuclear war (man-made precariousness). Neither type of precarious- ness can however be a reason not to endorse the interest of future generations in survival, because reducing that precariousness is exactly the engagement’s telos. The other aspect of the identity problem — the non-identity of posterity’s values and preferences with our own, or their indeterminacy — is not relevant to our case, be- cause the goal for whose attainment we are called to save or sacrifice something for their survival has to do with their sheer survival (in an indispensably civilized framework, as explained above) rather than with our own and the posterity’s moral configuration; in other words, there is no paternalistic attitude in it.¶ In a fairly different meaning, closer to social rather than moral (analytical) theory, identity comes up in an- other sense. Assuming responsibility for (or, for that matter, being fair to) future generations is not just an altruistic attitude. Not in the sense that we can do as well do so by acting on egoistic grounds: were this the¶ main reason to take action, we were justified to limit our effort to the less costly adaptation policies instead of funding the restructuring of the economy necessary for mitigation, the only way-out from global warming for generations of the far future. To be true, addressing the limitation of global warming or the neutralization of nuclear weapons requires wide-ranging undertakings that can be justified only on grounds of a moral attitude towards future generations rather than of our enlight- ened self-interest. But doing what we can for the survival of humankind can give ourselves reassurance that our individual life (also seen in the context of our gen- eration’s) is meaningful beyond the limits of our own existence on earth, because doing so helps us shed our isolation as single individuals or single generation and become partners in a wider transgenerational covenant of solidarity.¶ 3. That the interest to live and to raise children in de- cent conditions we attribute to future generations ought to be translated into a right is not self-evident. It is not simply that we should abstain from transforming every reasonable claim into a right, and instead reserve this category for the essentials that make the associated life of individuals in the polity possible and acceptable ac- cording to each evolutionary stage.11 More importantly, doubts may also arise as to whether it is wise to translate any goal of social and political struggles into a right, that is to “juridify” it instead of focusing on the underlying conflict dynamics and the participation of the conflict- ing parties. In general I share this preoccupation, and have misgivings at any inflationary expansion of the hu- man rights catalogue. On the other hand, moral rights that do not translate into legal rights12 are politically pointless or at least much less significant than the rights enshrined in a legal order. Also, our case is different, and the issues we are confronted with are more radi- cal than the worries with ‘juridification;’ this is all the truer, since the establishment of a right to survival for humankind would require a long and fierce political and intellectual battle in the first place.¶ First of all, does the right of humanity to survival qualify as a (basic or human) right? Before we proceed, let us note that humankind’s survival is not a good like civil liberties, which is completely at the disposal of human beings; instead, it can depend on the orbits of asteroids and other NEOs.13 The “right of humankind to survival” should therefore be read as a short for “the right of humankind, including future people, to have all previous generations doing their best to ensure their sur- vival and protect them from man-made threats.” In this version, we are clearly afar from the confusion between rights and goals criticized by Dworkin14 (§3.1 in the chapter on Difficult cases), the causation of the good at stake (survival) being elusive, or not completely nor (in the case of climate change) undoubtedly human; also¶ the content of the right is not a physical state, but rather the behavior influencing it. In a manifest way, this also identifies the right’s indispensable correlate, that is the duty of the relevant actors (individuals and institutions) to refrain from behaviors that are likely to cause harm to that good.¶ Whether or not this claim can translate into a right should be investigated from two points of view, those of its structure (a) and its bearer (b).¶ a. As for structure, three of Feinberg’s15 four crite- ria for being a right are already met (to have a content, a holder and an addressee). The fourth, the ‘source of validation,’ gradually emerges from the argument I am unfolding. Frydman and Haarscher also list four condi- tions, of which three are already present (titulaire, objet, opposabilite ́) – even if more remains to be said about the first one; while the fourth condition (sanction) shall be discussed below in the framework of the constitu- tionalization problem.16 Finally, let us look at the stan- dard distinction of negative and positive rights, which Shue rightly believes to be substantially untenable. This is also true in our case, because the ‘behavior’ of in- dividuals and institutions, which humanity is entitled to expect, according to the new right, can be imple- mented either by abstaining in single cases from using or possessing nuclear weapons and emitting excessive GHGs or by establishing new institutions (a global En- vironmental Protection Agency, say) and strategies (for example, technology transfer from advanced to develop- ing countries to help the latter rein in global warming). What would be acknowledged would be the right, not the policies that according to time and circumstances are devised for its realization.¶ Does this new right share with the other fundamental or human rights the need to be founded in a conception of the human, such as those focused by Donnelly on dignity, by Meyers on moral agency and by Frydman and Haarscher on autonomy?17 Not properly, or not di- rectly. Humanity’s right to survival is a meta-right rather than being the first right and sharing the same founda- tion with the others.18 Therefore, its foundation is for- mal rather than rooted in a substantive view of what is human: acknowledging this right is the pre-condition for making all other rights possible. It is their Bedingung der Mo ̈glichkeit, to put it as Kant might have done. Not only in the trivial but sturdy physical sense that human rights can only apply to a living humankind, but not to a ”republic of insects and grass” (Jonathan Schell on the state of the earth after a large nuclear war19). The meta-right as a pre-condition has rather to be un- derstood in the moral sense: no foundation of morality or legality (except in a totally positivistic view of the latter) makes sense if it cannot rely on the respect of the fundamental rights of those (poor populations al- ready affected by global warming, future generations¶ as victims of nuclear war or extreme climate change) harmed by our acts and omissions. Here I mean moral- ity at large, regardless of its being based on a conception of the right or the good. In other words, the two global challenges, which have received so little attention in the mainstream philosophy of the last decades, have indeed philosophical implications capable of undermining the business-as-usual attitude in moral and political theory; I mean the attitude to think of the foundations of moral- ity and polity as if the man-made (modern) world in which they operate had not been substantially altered by humankind’s newly achieved capability to destroy itself and/or the planet.¶ Let us make a further step on the road that leads to uncouple, as far as it goes, the foundation of a new right of paramount importance from a substantive conception of the human – an effort aimed at protecting it from the uncertain or frail fate of such conceptions. On the one hand, as a meta-right to individual-only human rights, the right to survival does not imply a choice among substantive values; this right does not refer to a partic- ular conception of what is good for future generations, as it only wants to ensure for them existential condi- tions that are an indispensable basis for their members to pursue whatever idea of the good, of liberty and self- realization they may choose. On the other hand, survival is indeed referred not to the mere biological fact, but to the survival of humankind in decent, civilized condi- tions, taking civilization in the meaning explained in §1. Alone, as I explained above, this qualification is not an added axiological component (civilization as a sys- tem of values), as it rather relies on the analytical view that some technical and cultural features of civilization are essential to the life of the human species.¶ There is a last aspect to be examined with regard to the structure or nature of this right: its emergence not from a shift in the doctrine of human rights, but as a response to a new situation in world history, in which survival goods (a livable atmosphere in the first place) that were so far tacitly taken for granted turn out to be no longer guaranteed, but more and more endangered. As such, this new right reconnects to what we know about individual human rights, that is that they come up as a response to “perceived threats” and build an “evolving whole”.20¶ b. Let us now come to the question of the right’s bearer. It is humankind, defined as the generality of the living individuals along with those who will be born. There are three possible objections to this proposition.¶ First, it seems to be self-evident that the notion of a human right for the so defined humankind cannot be subject to the classical liberal objection that bearers of such rights are individuals, not groups.21 Humankind is not an exclusive and self-contained group opposed to others (at least until we do not have our first contact with¶ dwellers of other regions of the universe), nor is it meant here to represent particular sets of values. Between the two meanings of “humanity” — as species (Artbegriff) and as regulative notion of a community cemented by shared values and goals (Zielbegriff)22 — I am referring to the first one; it is now becoming philosophically sig- nificant because not even its biological existence can be taken for granted under man-made threats. Humankind is not a hypostasis detached from the individuals, as in the case of ‘the community’ or ‘das Volk,’ as it rather means the totality of the living individuals of any given generation including (a) their potential to generate fur- ther human beings and generations and (b) their knowl- edge that the latter will exist and probably suffer. This reflexive notion of humankind raises a problem, but remains open to different ethical choices: indifference towards future generations, responsibility for them, and obligations assumed in their favor.¶ 4. A second question is: why should we speak of humankind instead of limiting ourselves to the more sober expression “all present and future individuals?” There is first a lexicological advantage, in as much as we thus use one word instead of connecting two by an “and.” This better conveys the sense that the bond of solidarity based on the responsibility for the elementary living conditions of posterity makes present and future individuals one community – in this sole, thin sense in- deed, which does not try to conceal the deep fractures existing between contemporaries within the present and the successive generations of this community. The very inclusion of future people into humankind is not an act of inclusive kindness towards them, but is rather made compelling by the lethal threats that past and present people have projected into the life of posterity, in an amount unprecedented in history. Lastly, introducing humankind as a bearer of rights highlights that the right of the individuals to be alive and free can be enjoyed only in the middle of a larger community, which makes the claim of human rights possible and helps to im- plement them. In times of economic globalization and global threats, we have come to know that this com- munity is the whole humankind, not just nations. All this however does not alter the truth that who is entitled to vindicate the right to survival is not humanity as a hypostasis, but every individual either living or not yet born – very much like what happens with individual human rights, whose constitutional formulation makes them enjoyable for every citizen who will in the future be born under the same Constitution.¶ Third comes the standard objection: it does not make sense to endorse obligation towards future people, since, if men and women agree to stop reproduction, those people might never be born. I have already dismissed this as a futile mental experiment. It could further be argued, though, that future generations might turn out¶ to have moral standards totally different from ours. Yet, the possibility that posterity will be not amenable to our moral world is not huge enough to release us from any responsibility towards them. We can still under- stand, and to an extent share, the moral problems raised by the Bible or the Greek classical tragedy of millen- nia ago and should not easily assume that our fellow humans of the year 3000, dwellers of a planet spoiled by global warming, will be morally so hugely different from us.¶ Finally, let me anticipate here one of the legal con- siderations that will be developed later on. Any right- establishing text (but I am now referring to the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, UDHR 1948) works with the basic formula “everyone has the right to etc.”23 The validity of the claims is limited only by the spatial ex- tension of the law: a right established by the French Constitution may be thought to be valid universally, but is legally protected only on French territory, while the rights mentioned in the UDHR apply by definition to the entire world where humans live. This can be dubbed spa- tial universalism, while establishing a right of present and future humanity to survive is tantamount to adding a time universalism. In other words, this makes explicit that the right of everyone to a just international order (UDHR 1948, Art. 28; more below) also holds for the ‘everyones’ of the year 3000. This may have always been tacitly intended by the law, the only time limit ly- ing in the possibility that the law is at some point in the future dismissed by another law canceling or expand- ing those rights. In a present like ours, in which it has become known that the future is no longer guaranteed to be essentially homogeneous (with no radical change in the physical and anthropological life conditions) to the present and the past, it has become necessary to openly establish a linkage between our obligations and the rights of future generations, as far as existential issues are concerned; a link that will likewise apply to them as soon as they become the present generation.¶ So far, I have clarified the moral and, to a lesser extent, legal reasons for introducing the notion of hu- mankind as right bearer. I will now stress that the hu- mankind discourse in this article remains political rather than moral.¶ It is not necessary here to rerun the history of the humankind/humanity notion; it is enough to remember that its denial has been a stronghold in the battle of value nihilists (Nietzsche) and realist thinkers (Oswald Spen- gler, who dismissed it as a “zoological notion,” and more extensively Carl Schmitt in Schmitt 1976, particularly §6). As self-contained units (such as the Westphalian system states) were deemed to be the only sustainable and legitimate polities, any reference to humanity was seen as toothless or manipulative, as a noble universalis- tic alibi for particularistic interests.24 Setting aside this¶ sort of criticism, which mistakes the ideological use of the term for its very substance, we know that humanity, as a good-will aspiration of philosophers, poets and re- ligious men, could not be regarded as a political notion because only non-voluntaristic communities can be re- garded as political. They alone allow for binding and effective decisions, whereas any partner can at any time and according to its convenience withdraw from mem- bership in “humanity” or other large associations based on just good will.¶ This can now be expected to change, because planetary lethal threats such as nuclear war or disastrous climate change have the potential strength to forge all relevant political actors into one community, not unlike Hobbes’ individuals, who received the push to unite from the threats to their life and limbs: first because they are all put in danger, and second because they have to act jointly if they really want to fight back those dangers. This is a possibility, not an actual and inevitable process, as there are enough counter-forces that impede those ‘Hobbesian’ threats to fully make hu- mankind one political community: fear, the protecting passion, does no longer work as smoothly as in Hobbes’ model of Leviathan.25 Nor is the potential contained in global challenges supposed to generate a world state as its only outcome: practicing survival policies, who- ever the actors may be, is more important than a uni- fied state-like structure in charge of doing so. Nonethe- less all this is enough to use ‘humankind’ in a political sense, as something that is a potential constituency rather than a fragmented multiplicity of individuals and states.¶ 5. Why a fundamental rather than a human right? The distinction between human and fundamental is not univocally worked out in the literature.26 In the vocab- ulary I am using here, human rights are seen as a philo- sophical concept and a moral (deontological) precept, while fundamental rights are those positively acknowl- edged in a legal order, entrusted to political and institu- tional processes for their implementation, and claimable in courts – this last feature being more problematic. Putting on humankind’s survival the label of a funda- mental right avoids leaving it in a philosophical limbo as a regulative idea,27 and gives it a better defined political and legal nature; this is more adequate to the character- istic of survival as something endangered by political decisions (or the lack thereof) and requesting a political solution by a given deadline (the next few years if we want to try to keep the temperature increase expected by 2100 under two degrees).¶ If humankind’s survival is acknowledged as a funda- mental right, it follows that it should be constitutional- ized, that is inserted in new and old (and aptly modified) Constitutions as well as in a new version of the Univer- sal Declaration of Human Rights; as such, it could be referred to as highest guidance in international treaties aimed at implementing it – rather than being enshrined in a specific ‘survival’ treaty. In constitutional law, a development in this sense is already taking place, in as much as either the rights of future generations to a safe environment or our responsibility towards them in this regard or the imperative to preserve the environ- ment (without mention of the future generations, but implicitly to their benefit) have been affirmed in consti- tutional amendments of the last two decades in countries such as Germany, France, Switzerland, but also Burkina Faso and Burundi. Having rights or being protected by the legally defined responsibility of the previous gener- ations is however not the same thing, and with regard to humankind’s survival I would point at its stronger formulation as a right: it is more binding, while the ob- jections against endowing future generations with rights can be easily argued against. Just because it is conceived in favor of those who cannot yet uphold their interest, this right should be protected against cancellation by a sort of Ewigkeitsklausel as in Art. 79.3 of the German Grundgesetz.28 A right to survival is more specific and more stringent than the right to a safe environment be- cause it derives from lethal and global challenges that affect the very core of the polity, protection, rather than from a generic care for a balanced relationship to na- ture or from a diffuse feeling of benevolence for the posterity.¶ In national or regional Constitutions, the acknowl- edgment of this right could be accompanied by the establishment of corresponding institutions, promoting the implementation of the new right; it could be for example an ombudsman29 for future generation as a (countermajoritarian)30 authority protecting their inter- ests against damages resulting from new legislation, and endowed with the power to send it back to the legislative rather than to veto it straight away.31 Not to be underes- timated are the difficulties that would arise in striking a very delicate balance on two levels: in general between the interests of present and future generations,32 but also between parliaments or executives, which act under the pressure of their constituencies, and the members of the ombudsman authority, who remain nonetheless contem- poraries of the former rather than being appointed by the latter – for all too natural reasons.¶ The same difficulty would affect the national courts in which the new fundamental right, as jus cogens principle, should be made claimable at the initiative of institutions such as the ombudsman or of advocacy groups representing a significative number of citizens in a referendum-like counting procedure. In international courts,33 the interest of future generations should be represented by an ombudsman to be established at the UN as well as at regional associations of states such as the EU or Mercosur. A point however that remains¶ open to further discussion has been raised in the de- bate on socio-economic or solidarity rights, which may have some affinity with the right to survival: theoreti- cally, Frank Michelman has made clear that the status of a norm as constitutional law ought not to be con- flated with the question of its availability for judicial enforcement.34 In practice, conflicts are easily possi- ble between the courts sentencing on the states’ failure to implement those rights and “the vain or overbearing nature of these sentences” on a matter that is political rather than judicial. 35 This is true in our case as well: the attainment of a new international order without national possession of nuclear arms or a carbon-free reordering of the world economy are goals for policy-making, not something that can be attained in courts. In this frame- work, however, courts are not jobless: sentencing the nuclear-armed states for their failure in implementing art.VI of the Nuclear Non-Proliferation Treaty (NPT),36 or the US of the Bush years for withdrawing from the Kyoto Protocol and failing to cut emissions is a typical judicial matter, as the two cases would regard the break of treaty obligations or the failure to cease doing some- thing harmful, not to bring about something good.37¶ Finally, two more fundamental objections could be raised against the idea of a legal protection of the inter- est of future generations. It could be argued that what would be represented (in a time-universalistic mode) is not the interest of future generations, but rather the interest of a particular fraction of the present ones, dis- guising itself as standard bearer of those people to come. On the one hand this should be taken into account as critical point of view in the public debate on those inter- ests. On the other hand, this criticism, strictly speaking, would also delegitimize such an ancient principle of Roman and Western law as the protection of the child. In morality it would affirm a radical skepticism that denies the possibility of slipping into another person’s clothes and acting from a non-egoistic stance. This can be obviously upheld, but at the price of the disappear- ance of morality as well as of the polity, which is – in any case and among other things – a solidaristic association.¶ A second problem, which is more difficult to deal with, is that we do not know as a general piece of knowl- edge what the interest of future generations is; whereas in the case of legal protection of the child we share a generally accepted knowledge of his or her future in- terest (to remain healthy, to get sufficient education, to be free to make the best of him/herself). What the real life conditions and the presumable vital interests of fu- ture generations will be can only be tentatively argued from what the several branches of natural and economic (e.g. demography) science are able to tell us about what is likely to remain constant in physical and cultural anthropology and what is likely to be most endangered.¶ As such, it is important that moral and political theory renew their relationship to the natural sciences after a time of reciprocal disdain between the two. While sci- ence cannot by itself draw an encompassing picture of future life under global threats, philosophy should learn from science what those future problems are likely to be and elaborate on them, instead of reflecting on the future of humanity by just moving from the doctrines of past philosophers or relying on the hearsay about it based on media reports or the philosopher’s personal divinations.¶ 6. My philosophical proposal to fill a hole in human rights discourse and legislation by introducing a first or meta-fundamental right of humankind to survival and positivizing it in national, international and world law38 resonates with two legal developments. The first related to ‘humanity’, the second to ‘human rights.’ The latter resonates with the novelties in constitutional law men- tioned in §5.¶ The first one began in 1970 as the UN General As- sembly adopted Resolution 2749, the Declaration of Principles Governing the Seabed and Ocean Floor, con- taining the notion of a “common heritage of mankind”; it was originally introduced to protect the seabed and ocean floor and later the “moon and other celestial bod- ies” from exploitation by powerful countries against the interest of the developing ones.39 In the 1990s, the competing and “thinner” concept of “common concern of mankind” emerged, as in the Convention on Bio- diversity of 1992; nonetheless it can be said that hu- mankind has become a notion contained in binding in- ternational law and referred to indivisible (climate) and divisible (seabed, ocean floor, moon) objects, and that this has happened as an answer to problems and chances generated by huge technological advancement.¶ In another corner of legal development, it could be argued that the logical structure, so to speak the norma- tive algorithm of the UDHR norms — the aforemen- tioned ‘everyone has the right . . . ’ — implies that hu- mankind, not just single individuals, is to be the bearer of those rights, even if the collective singular is not used. Turning to a more substantive level, we could go as far as to say that the legal protection of humankind’s survival was implicitly enshrined as early as 1948 in the UDHR and later in the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR) as well as the In- ternational Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (ICESCR), both of 1966. Art. 28 UDHR (“ev- eryone has the right to a social and international order in which the rights and freedoms set forth in this Decla- ration can be fully realized”) could be rethought in the direction of institutions bound to implement for every- one, now and in the future, the right to life (Art.3 UDHR, Art. 6 ICCPR), the right to an adequate standard of liv- ing incl. adequate food (Art.11 ICESRC)40 as well as¶ the right of the family to be protected (Art.10 ICESRC), a right that would be denied to families of the posterity bound to live under insufferable environmental condi- tions (cf. above the notion of a transgenerational chain of parents). While the different binding strength of the several legal formulations (treaty, covenant, convention, declaration) cannot be ignored, it remains clear that le- gal documents do not advance by themselves the cause of humankind’s survival, except if they can be effec- tively referred to in a court of justice; but they create an appropriate and stable environment for what can really bring about a change, that is educational and political struggles, the former aiming at a change in the political culture.¶ To sum up, (hu)mankind has thus ceased to be just a concept used by philosophers and theologians, whose presence in international law was merely philo- sophical, if not rhetorical, as in the Preamble to the UN Charter of 1945. Though not explicitly endowed with rights in the documents quoted above, the humankind of the “common heritage” doctrine is an important prece- dent in the direction, suggested by this article, of in- troducing this new legal actor. When looking at the implementation of the rights that can be attributed to it, the other legal novelty of the “common but dif- ferentiated responsibility”41 of individual actors, such as countries, should also be brought to bear. This is important when it comes to distributing the burden of the duties corresponding to those rights – which is in- deed one of the major issues in the debate following the Copenhagen Accord on Climate Change of 2009. In any case, the legal acknowledgment of a “common responsibility” for the global commons is a further step in designing humankind as a juridical notion.¶ This article is policy-oriented in the peculiar sense of a constitutional policy that will require decades, if ever, to become the subject of debate and even longer to be legally implemented. Impulses in this direction are cer- tainly not be expected from the world of politics, but rather from the scientific community (provided a now utopian sounding collaboration of physics, philosophy and legal theory materializes) or from scattered sen- tences of national and international courts, particularly in environmental matter.42 Support from civil society would help.¶ Finally, the author’s suggestion as to how to read this proposal: it has a clearly cosmopolitan (or better: cosmopolitical) character, not however in the sense of cosmopolitanism as a general doctrine of government/ governance. It is rather generated by tools coming from realist thought: new threats as source of new rights, and lethal and planetary threats to the survival of hu- mankind’s civilization as drivers towards a new level of legal protection.
40,522
<h4>Trying to improve the lives of people while <u>ignoring</u> existential threats is like shuffling the deck-chairs on the titanic – extinction outweighs</h4><p><u><strong>Cerutti 14</u></strong> - Professor of Political Philosophy emeritus at the University of Florence and Adjunct Professor at the Scuola superiore Sant’Anna, Pisa. In the last fifteen years, Cerutti has been aVisiting Professor at Harvard, the Universit´e de Paris 8, the Humboldt Universit ¨at zu Berlin, the London School of Economics and Political Science,(China Foreign Affairs University), Beijing, and Stanford University in Florence. Beyond the publications quoted in this article, Cerutti has written widely on the political identity of the Europeans and the legitimacy of the European Union (last publication: Debating Political Identity and Legitimacy in the European Union, ed. with S. Lucarelli and V. Schmidt, Routledge: London 2011). Also, his MOOC ‘Political Philosophy: An Introduction’ is accessible on the platform <iversity.org>.</p><p>(Furio “Humankind’s First Fundamental Right: Survival,” Constellations)</p><p>This article’s main thesis1 is that, <u><strong><mark>given the existence of</u></strong></mark> at least two <u><strong><mark>global threats</u></strong></mark>, nuclear weapons and climate change, <u><strong><mark>which endanger</mark> the life of <mark>humankind</mark> as a civ- ilized species</u></strong>, its <u><strong><mark>right to survive should be asserted as its first</u></strong></mark> human or rather <u><strong><mark>fundamental right</mark>.</u></strong> The sense of <u><strong>this</u></strong> assertion <u><strong>is not just philosophical but legal as</u></strong> <u><strong>well</u></strong>.¶ To substantiate this thesis, I shall go through six argumentative steps:¶ 1. Why begin with global threats.¶ 2. Why survival is the leading category in this field, and¶ how it interplays with justice.¶ 3. What interest humankind has in its survival, and why¶ it should be protected as a right.¶ 4. Why regard “humankind” rather than “all indi-¶ viduals” as a possible actor.¶ 5. Why speak of a fundamental rather than human¶ right, and how to constitutionalize this right.¶ 6. How two developments in international law after 1945 can contribute to support the argument I have¶ been sketching.¶ **¶ 1. If philosophical thinking starts with being amazed at something in the world (Plato’s θαυμα ́ζειν), my in- terest in the present matter2 was first stimulated by the pre-philosophical amazement I always felt in seeing that in the now enormous human rights discourse (both in politics and academia) so much care is dedicated to the single individuals, and so wide-ranging designs of a cos- mopolis to come are based on their rights. Yet <u><strong><mark>nobody seems to</mark> take <mark>note that the life of all present and futur</mark>e individuals <mark>could be annihilated</u></strong></mark> by a nuclear war or up- set by catastrophic developments of climate change. <u><strong>It is like insisting on first debating the rights of a ship’s</u></strong> third- class <u><strong>passengers</u></strong> 3 <u><strong>instead of taking action in the light of the fact that <mark>the ship is already taking in seawater from a leak</u></strong></mark> (climate change is already happening) and also risks to hit a mine that is floating around and would send it along with all passengers and crew straight to the ocean depths (by thinking and acting timely, leaks can be filled, mines detected and swept away, all ac- tions that would put the care for third-class passengers¶ on a firmer ground). <u><strong>These dangers are philosophically significant because they tell something about human beings</u></strong>, the only ones who have become able to destroy their own race, as well as about modernity: the possibil- ity of self-destruction sets an end to this era, opens a new one, which can only vaguely be termed post-modern,4 and requires an updated rewriting of the Dialectics of the Enlightenment. It is also politically significant as it challenges present politics to restructure itself by ex- tending its attention to the far future, something which is not possible within the boundaries of modern politics because of its narrow time structure.5 In a more precise language, I term <u><strong>challenges like <mark>nuclear weapons</u></strong></mark> (con- sidered in themselves, while nuclear proliferation is but a subphenomenon) <u><strong>and climate change</u></strong> global (in a very specific sense) because they are lethal and planet-wide, <u><strong><mark>can hit</u></strong></mark> approximately <u><strong><mark>everybody</mark> on earth and</u></strong> can be reasonably addressed only by the near totality of coun- tries and peoples. They would not wipe out biologically humankind, although this cannot be excluded in case of an all-out nuclear war; but <u><strong>they would destroy human civilization</u></strong>:6 not a set of values, but the set of material and cultural tools (agriculture, communications, trans- portation and trade) that allow unspecialized animals like the humans to survive and to thrive.¶ It is clear that my thesis presupposes a revised scale of relevance among the issues requiring and stimulat- ing theoretical investigations: in my philosophical view global threats have a greater relevance and are intellec- tually more challenging than the issues suggested by the media’s headlines (present wars, terrorism, group and minority rights in the US, multiculturalism in Canada or Australia, immigrants in Europe, or, more recently, the crisis of the global economic system). As a reflection upon the deeper longue dure ́e determinants of human- ity’s fate, political philosophy should not necessarily espouse the agenda suggested by current politics and journalism and, instead, seek its own independent as- sessment of the state of the world as part of its business; this is a critical attitude that cannot be implemented without a philosophical view on history (not to be con- fused with a revival of the “grand narratives”). Besides, <u><strong>the shifting of</u></strong> most of Critical <u><strong><mark>Theory</mark> to pure normativity <mark>has favored</u></strong></mark> the emergence not just of worldviews based on the predominance of Sollen, but also of <u><strong>an exclusive attention on <mark>intersubjectivity</u></strong></mark> and its troubles; <u><strong><mark>as if challenges to politics</mark> and civilization caused by systemic imperatives</u></strong> (<u><strong>such as the nuclear threat and</u></strong>¶ <u><strong>climate change)</u></strong> <u><strong>were beyond the grasp of critical inquiry</u></strong>. What I am attempting in this article is to address an issue such as human rights that is typical of <u><strong><mark>the self- centered</mark> normative <mark>approach</u></strong></mark> mentioned and to show how it <u><strong><mark>should be restructured to address</mark> the <mark>challenges for</mark> humankind’s <mark>survival</u></strong></mark>.¶ In this attempt I am driven by the intent to debunk the layer of denial (or repression in pshychoanalyti- cal sense) that, more intensely after the end of the Cold War, has removed the nuclear threat from the philosoph- ical reflection on modernity and has later prevented cli- mate change from entering the main agenda of Critical Theory. There is also an epistemological aspect in this: a critical Zeitdiagnose, or an informed assessment of where history has taken us to in our post-modern times is not possible without first taking what hard science has to say about the threats for humankind very seriously.7 With rare exceptions, <u><strong><mark>critical theorists seem to be reluctant to address</mark> the <mark>philosophical issues raised by global challenges</mark>, not to mention their</u></strong> <u><strong>complete denial</u></strong> beginning with Horkheimer and Adorno in the Fifties and Sixties (when Mutual Assured Destruction became a real possibility) <u><strong>of the meaning of nuclear weapons. It is as if Critical Theory</u></strong>, despite its claim to be a gen- eral assessment of our civilization, <u><strong>had accepted a tacit division of labor in which its competence is restricted to social justice</u></strong> (in continuation of its original being rooted in the Marxian critique of political economy) <u><strong>and the “damaged”</u></strong>8 <u><strong>subjectivity</u></strong>. The rest of the real world is left to a purely Hobbesian (and later Luhmannian) reading, or to the perception of side-figures such as Karl Jaspers or Gu ̈nther Anders.¶ A last epistemological remark: <u><strong><mark>starting from problems and threats that</u></strong></mark>, however socially generated, <u><strong><mark>come up as physical events and are accounted for by hard science has the advantage that philosophy can work on them without first engaging in a complicate and doubt- ful theorizing about how the world should be reshaped</u></strong> </mark>according to a general normative theory. This ad hoc theorizing shows the ability or inability of a philosoph- ical view to come to terms with problems that are of paramount importance to everybody, not just to the prac- titioners of Schulphilosophie.¶ 2. I have explained elsewhere9why survival rather than justice is the leading category of a philosophy of global threats. <u><strong>The</u></strong> now thriving <u><strong><mark>literature on justice</mark> and climate change <mark>misses the point</u></strong></mark> that before we look for ways to establish justice between generations, <u><strong><mark>we have to motivate our interest in</u></strong></mark> their <u><strong><mark>existence</u></strong></mark> and wellbeing, or rather in the existence and wellbeing of humankind.10 While survival of humankind is what best defines our problematic situation, when it comes to the normative aspect I believe that <u><strong><mark>we should assume responsibility for future generations</u></strong></mark> rather than do justice to them; talking responsibility I move from its most elementary¶ manifestation, the responsibility parents take on for their children. Justice as fairness comes in when we have to fight back “generational nepotism:” it is wrong for any generation to spoil the environment without regard to the consequences in the future, far that it may be, that is not just out of respect for those that may harm our children and children’s children. Out of elementary fairness, as expressed in the Golden Rule, we cannot deny parents of the, say, twenty-fifth century the chance to bear and educate their children in decent conditions.¶ Now, survival is a Hobbesian category, as such it sounds like an anathema to critical thinking, just as most categories stemming from the tradition of politi- cal realism do. Since under global threats present and future humankind is really endangered in its survival, it is however hard to see the rationale of denying the fact because the name comes from the enemy’s vocabu- lary. More importantly, there is an essential difference: Hobbes’ survival regards the individual and is there- fore self-centered and adversarial (in common parlance, mors tua vita mea), while humankind’s survival as a moral and political goal is by its own definition an uni- versalistic feature. More on this later.¶ A much talked-about issue in this context is the so- called identity problem, which I am however inclined to dismiss. If it means the doubtfulness of any engagement in favor of future generations because we do not know if they will exist (we could decide to stop procreating), the problem is surrounded by an air of futility: there is no imaginable decision process that could effectively lead to a total procreation stop. On the other hand, if only a few humans were alive in the far future, this would be enough of a reason for our engagement. Of course future humanity could never be born because meanwhile the planet may have been burnt out by an asteroid (natural precariousness of human life) or an all-out nuclear war (man-made precariousness). Neither type of precarious- ness can however be a reason not to endorse the interest of future generations in survival, because reducing that precariousness is exactly the engagement’s telos. The other aspect of the identity problem — the non-identity of posterity’s values and preferences with our own, or their indeterminacy — is not relevant to our case, be- cause the goal for whose attainment we are called to save or sacrifice something for their survival has to do with their sheer survival (in an indispensably civilized framework, as explained above) rather than with our own and the posterity’s moral configuration; in other words, there is no paternalistic attitude in it.¶ In a fairly different meaning, closer to social rather than moral (analytical) theory, identity comes up in an- other sense. Assuming responsibility for (or, for that matter, being fair to) future generations is not just an altruistic attitude. Not in the sense that we can do as well do so by acting on egoistic grounds: were this the¶ main reason to take action, we were justified to limit our effort to the less costly adaptation policies instead of funding the restructuring of the economy necessary for mitigation, the only way-out from global warming for generations of the far future. To be true, addressing the limitation of global warming or the neutralization of nuclear weapons requires wide-ranging undertakings that can be justified only on grounds of a moral attitude towards future generations rather than of our enlight- ened self-interest. <mark>But <u><strong>doing what we can for the survival</mark> of humankind <mark>can give ourselves reassurance that</mark> our individual <mark>life</u></strong></mark> (also seen in the context of our gen- eration’s) <u><strong><mark>is meaningful</u></strong></mark> beyond the limits of our own existence on earth, <u><strong>because doing so helps us shed our isolation as single individuals or single generation and become partners in a wider transgenerational covenant of solidarity</u></strong>.¶ 3. That the interest to live and to raise children in de- cent conditions we attribute to future generations ought to be translated into a right is not self-evident. It is not simply that we should abstain from transforming every reasonable claim into a right, and instead reserve this category for the essentials that make the associated life of individuals in the polity possible and acceptable ac- cording to each evolutionary stage.11 More importantly, doubts may also arise as to whether it is wise to translate any goal of social and political struggles into a right, that is to “juridify” it instead of focusing on the underlying conflict dynamics and the participation of the conflict- ing parties. In general I share this preoccupation, and have misgivings at any inflationary expansion of the hu- man rights catalogue. On the other hand, moral rights that do not translate into legal rights12 are politically pointless or at least much less significant than the rights enshrined in a legal order. Also, our case is different, and the issues we are confronted with are more radi- cal than the worries with ‘juridification;’ this is all the truer, since the establishment of a right to survival for humankind would require a long and fierce political and intellectual battle in the first place.¶ First of all, does the right of humanity to survival qualify as a (basic or human) right? Before we proceed, let us note that humankind’s survival is not a good like civil liberties, which is completely at the disposal of human beings; instead, it can depend on the orbits of asteroids and other NEOs.13 The “right of humankind to survival” should therefore be read as a short for “the right of humankind, including future people, to have all previous generations doing their best to ensure their sur- vival and protect them from man-made threats.” In this version, we are clearly afar from the confusion between rights and goals criticized by Dworkin14 (§3.1 in the chapter on Difficult cases), the causation of the good at stake (survival) being elusive, or not completely nor (in the case of climate change) undoubtedly human; also¶ the content of the right is not a physical state, but rather the behavior influencing it. In a manifest way, this also identifies the right’s indispensable correlate, that is the duty of the relevant actors (individuals and institutions) to refrain from behaviors that are likely to cause harm to that good.¶ Whether or not this claim can translate into a right should be investigated from two points of view, those of its structure (a) and its bearer (b).¶ a. As for structure, three of Feinberg’s15 four crite- ria for being a right are already met (to have a content, a holder and an addressee). The fourth, the ‘source of validation,’ gradually emerges from the argument I am unfolding. Frydman and Haarscher also list four condi- tions, of which three are already present (titulaire, objet, opposabilite ́) – even if more remains to be said about the first one; while the fourth condition (sanction) shall be discussed below in the framework of the constitu- tionalization problem.16 Finally, let us look at the stan- dard distinction of negative and positive rights, which Shue rightly believes to be substantially untenable. This is also true in our case, because the ‘behavior’ of in- dividuals and institutions, which humanity is entitled to expect, according to the new right, can be imple- mented either by abstaining in single cases from using or possessing nuclear weapons and emitting excessive GHGs or by establishing new institutions (a global En- vironmental Protection Agency, say) and strategies (for example, technology transfer from advanced to develop- ing countries to help the latter rein in global warming). What would be acknowledged would be the right, not the policies that according to time and circumstances are devised for its realization.¶ Does this new right share with the other fundamental or human rights the need to be founded in a conception of the human, such as those focused by Donnelly on dignity, by Meyers on moral agency and by Frydman and Haarscher on autonomy?17 Not properly, or not di- rectly. Humanity’s right to survival is a meta-right rather than being the first right and sharing the same founda- tion with the others.18 Therefore, its foundation is for- mal rather than rooted in a substantive view of what is human: <u><strong><mark>acknowledging this</mark> right is the <mark>pre-condition</mark> for making all other rights possible</u></strong>. It is their Bedingung der Mo ̈glichkeit, to put it as Kant might have done. Not only in the trivial but sturdy physical sense that <u><strong><mark>human rights can only apply to a living humankind, but not to a ”republic of insects and grass</mark>”</u></strong> (Jonathan Schell on the state of the earth after a large nuclear war19). <u><strong>The meta-right as a pre-condition has</u></strong> rather <u><strong>to be un- derstood in the moral sense: <mark>no</mark> foundation of <mark>morality</u></strong> </mark>or legality (except in a totally positivistic view of the latter) <u><strong><mark>makes sense if it cannot rely on the respect of the fundamental right</mark>s of those</u></strong> (poor populations al- ready affected by global warming, future generations¶ as victims of nuclear war or extreme climate change) <u><strong>harmed by our acts and omissions</u></strong>. Here I mean moral- ity at large, regardless of its being based on a conception of the right or the good. In other words, the two <u><strong>global challenges, which have received so little attention in the mainstream philosophy of the last decades, have indeed philosophical implications capable of undermining the</u></strong> business-as-<u><strong>usual attitude in moral and political theory</u></strong>; I mean the attitude to think of the foundations of moral- ity and polity as if the man-made (modern) world in which they operate had not been substantially altered by humankind’s newly achieved capability to destroy itself and/or the planet.¶ Let us make a further step on the road that leads to uncouple, as far as it goes, the foundation of a new right of paramount importance from a substantive conception of the human – an effort aimed at protecting it from the uncertain or frail fate of such conceptions. On the one hand, as a meta-right to individual-only human rights, the right to survival does not imply a choice among substantive values; this right does not refer to a partic- ular conception of what is good for future generations, as it only wants to ensure for them existential condi- tions that are an indispensable basis for their members to pursue whatever idea of the good, of liberty and self- realization they may choose. On the other hand, survival is indeed referred not to the mere biological fact, but to the survival of humankind in decent, civilized condi- tions, taking civilization in the meaning explained in §1. Alone, as I explained above, this qualification is not an added axiological component (civilization as a sys- tem of values), as it rather relies on the analytical view that some technical and cultural features of civilization are essential to the life of the human species.¶ There is a last aspect to be examined with regard to the structure or nature of this right: its emergence not from a shift in the doctrine of human rights, but as a response to a new situation in world history, in which survival goods (a livable atmosphere in the first place) that were so far tacitly taken for granted turn out to be no longer guaranteed, but more and more endangered. As such, this new right reconnects to what we know about individual human rights, that is that they come up as a response to “perceived threats” and build an “evolving whole”.20¶ b. Let us now come to the question of the right’s bearer. It is humankind, defined as the generality of the living individuals along with those who will be born. There are three possible objections to this proposition.¶ First, it seems to be self-evident that the notion of a human right for the so defined humankind cannot be subject to the classical liberal objection that bearers of such rights are individuals, not groups.21 Humankind is not an exclusive and self-contained group opposed to others (at least until we do not have our first contact with¶ dwellers of other regions of the universe), nor is it meant here to represent particular sets of values. Between the two meanings of “humanity” — as species (Artbegriff) and as regulative notion of a community cemented by shared values and goals (Zielbegriff)22 — I am referring to the first one; it is now becoming philosophically sig- nificant because not even its biological existence can be taken for granted under man-made threats. Humankind is not a hypostasis detached from the individuals, as in the case of ‘the community’ or ‘das Volk,’ as it rather means the totality of the living individuals of any given generation including (a) their potential to generate fur- ther human beings and generations and (b) their knowl- edge that the latter will exist and probably suffer. This reflexive notion of humankind raises a problem, but remains open to different ethical choices: indifference towards future generations, responsibility for them, and obligations assumed in their favor.¶ 4. A second question is: why should we speak of humankind instead of limiting ourselves to the more sober expression “all present and future individuals?” There is first a lexicological advantage, in as much as we thus use one word instead of connecting two by an “and.” This better conveys the sense that the bond of solidarity based on the responsibility for the elementary living conditions of posterity makes present and future individuals one community – in this sole, thin sense in- deed, which does not try to conceal the deep fractures existing between contemporaries within the present and the successive generations of this community. The very inclusion of future people into humankind is not an act of inclusive kindness towards them, but is rather made compelling by the lethal threats that past and present people have projected into the life of posterity, in an amount unprecedented in history. Lastly, introducing humankind as a bearer of rights highlights that the right of the individuals to be alive and free can be enjoyed only in the middle of a larger community, which makes the claim of human rights possible and helps to im- plement them. In times of economic globalization and global threats, we have come to know that this com- munity is the whole humankind, not just nations. All this however does not alter the truth that who is entitled to vindicate the right to survival is not humanity as a hypostasis, but every individual either living or not yet born – very much like what happens with individual human rights, whose constitutional formulation makes them enjoyable for every citizen who will in the future be born under the same Constitution.¶ Third comes the standard objection: it does not make sense to endorse obligation towards future people, since, if men and women agree to stop reproduction, those people might never be born. I have already dismissed this as a futile mental experiment. It could further be argued, though, that future generations might turn out¶ to have moral standards totally different from ours. Yet, the possibility that posterity will be not amenable to our moral world is not huge enough to release us from any responsibility towards them. We can still under- stand, and to an extent share, the moral problems raised by the Bible or the Greek classical tragedy of millen- nia ago and should not easily assume that our fellow humans of the year 3000, dwellers of a planet spoiled by global warming, will be morally so hugely different from us.¶ Finally, let me anticipate here one of the legal con- siderations that will be developed later on. Any right- establishing text (but I am now referring to the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, UDHR 1948) works with the basic formula “everyone has the right to etc.”23 The validity of the claims is limited only by the spatial ex- tension of the law: a right established by the French Constitution may be thought to be valid universally, but is legally protected only on French territory, while the rights mentioned in the UDHR apply by definition to the entire world where humans live. This can be dubbed spa- tial universalism, while establishing a right of present and future humanity to survive is tantamount to adding a time universalism. In other words, this makes explicit that the right of everyone to a just international order (UDHR 1948, Art. 28; more below) also holds for the ‘everyones’ of the year 3000. This may have always been tacitly intended by the law, the only time limit ly- ing in the possibility that the law is at some point in the future dismissed by another law canceling or expand- ing those rights. In a present like ours, in which it has become known that the future is no longer guaranteed to be essentially homogeneous (with no radical change in the physical and anthropological life conditions) to the present and the past, it has become necessary to openly establish a linkage between our obligations and the rights of future generations, as far as existential issues are concerned; a link that will likewise apply to them as soon as they become the present generation.¶ So far, I have clarified the moral and, to a lesser extent, legal reasons for introducing the notion of hu- mankind as right bearer. I will now stress that the hu- mankind discourse in this article remains political rather than moral.¶ It is not necessary here to rerun the history of the humankind/humanity notion; it is enough to remember that its denial has been a stronghold in the battle of value nihilists (Nietzsche) and realist thinkers (Oswald Spen- gler, who dismissed it as a “zoological notion,” and more extensively Carl Schmitt in Schmitt 1976, particularly §6). As self-contained units (such as the Westphalian system states) were deemed to be the only sustainable and legitimate polities, any reference to humanity was seen as toothless or manipulative, as a noble universalis- tic alibi for particularistic interests.24 Setting aside this¶ sort of criticism, which mistakes the ideological use of the term for its very substance, we know that humanity, as a good-will aspiration of philosophers, poets and re- ligious men, could not be regarded as a political notion because only non-voluntaristic communities can be re- garded as political. They alone allow for binding and effective decisions, whereas any partner can at any time and according to its convenience withdraw from mem- bership in “humanity” or other large associations based on just good will.¶ This can now be expected to change, because <u><strong><mark>planetary</mark> lethal <mark>threats</mark> such as nuclear war or disastrous climate change <mark>have the potential strength to forge all relevant political actors into one community</u></strong></mark>, not unlike Hobbes’ individuals, <u><strong>who received the push <mark>to unite from the threats</mark> to their life and limbs</u></strong>: first <u><strong><mark>because they are all</mark> put <mark>in danger</mark>, and</u></strong> second <u><strong>because they have to act jointly</u></strong> if they really want to fight back those dangers. <u><strong>This is a possibility, not an</u></strong> actual and <u><strong>inevitable process</u></strong>, as there are enough counter-forces that impede those ‘Hobbesian’ threats to fully make hu- mankind one political community: fear, the protecting passion, does no longer work as smoothly as in Hobbes’ model of Leviathan.25 Nor is the potential contained in global challenges supposed to generate a world state as its only outcome: practicing survival policies, who- ever the actors may be, is more important than a uni- fied state-like structure in charge of doing so. Nonethe- less <u><strong>all this is enough to use ‘humankind’ in a political sense</u></strong>, as something that is a potential constituency rather than a fragmented multiplicity of individuals and states.¶ 5. Why a fundamental rather than a human right? The distinction between human and fundamental is not univocally worked out in the literature.26 In the vocab- ulary I am using here, human rights are seen as a philo- sophical concept and a moral (deontological) precept, while fundamental rights are those positively acknowl- edged in a legal order, entrusted to political and institu- tional processes for their implementation, and claimable in courts – this last feature being more problematic. Putting on humankind’s survival the label of a funda- mental right avoids leaving it in a philosophical limbo as a regulative idea,27 and gives it a better defined political and legal nature; this is more adequate to the character- istic of survival as something endangered by political decisions (or the lack thereof) and requesting a political solution by a given deadline (the next few years if we want to try to keep the temperature increase expected by 2100 under two degrees).¶ If humankind’s survival is acknowledged as a funda- mental right, it follows that it should be constitutional- ized, that is inserted in new and old (and aptly modified) Constitutions as well as in a new version of the Univer- sal Declaration of Human Rights; as such, it could be referred to as highest guidance in international treaties aimed at implementing it – rather than being enshrined in a specific ‘survival’ treaty. In constitutional law, a development in this sense is already taking place, in as much as either the rights of future generations to a safe environment or our responsibility towards them in this regard or the imperative to preserve the environ- ment (without mention of the future generations, but implicitly to their benefit) have been affirmed in consti- tutional amendments of the last two decades in countries such as Germany, France, Switzerland, but also Burkina Faso and Burundi. Having rights or being protected by the legally defined responsibility of the previous gener- ations is however not the same thing, and with regard to humankind’s survival I would point at its stronger formulation as a right: it is more binding, while the ob- jections against endowing future generations with rights can be easily argued against. Just because it is conceived in favor of those who cannot yet uphold their interest, this right should be protected against cancellation by a sort of Ewigkeitsklausel as in Art. 79.3 of the German Grundgesetz.28 A right to survival is more specific and more stringent than the right to a safe environment be- cause it derives from lethal and global challenges that affect the very core of the polity, protection, rather than from a generic care for a balanced relationship to na- ture or from a diffuse feeling of benevolence for the posterity.¶ In national or regional Constitutions, the acknowl- edgment of this right could be accompanied by the establishment of corresponding institutions, promoting the implementation of the new right; it could be for example an ombudsman29 for future generation as a (countermajoritarian)30 authority protecting their inter- ests against damages resulting from new legislation, and endowed with the power to send it back to the legislative rather than to veto it straight away.31 Not to be underes- timated are the difficulties that would arise in striking a very delicate balance on two levels: in general between the interests of present and future generations,32 but also between parliaments or executives, which act under the pressure of their constituencies, and the members of the ombudsman authority, who remain nonetheless contem- poraries of the former rather than being appointed by the latter – for all too natural reasons.¶ The same difficulty would affect the national courts in which the new fundamental right, as jus cogens principle, should be made claimable at the initiative of institutions such as the ombudsman or of advocacy groups representing a significative number of citizens in a referendum-like counting procedure. In international courts,33 the interest of future generations should be represented by an ombudsman to be established at the UN as well as at regional associations of states such as the EU or Mercosur. A point however that remains¶ open to further discussion has been raised in the de- bate on socio-economic or solidarity rights, which may have some affinity with the right to survival: theoreti- cally, Frank Michelman has made clear that the status of a norm as constitutional law ought not to be con- flated with the question of its availability for judicial enforcement.34 In practice, conflicts are easily possi- ble between the courts sentencing on the states’ failure to implement those rights and “the vain or overbearing nature of these sentences” on a matter that is political rather than judicial. 35 This is true in our case as well: the attainment of a new international order without national possession of nuclear arms or a carbon-free reordering of the world economy are goals for policy-making, not something that can be attained in courts. In this frame- work, however, courts are not jobless: sentencing the nuclear-armed states for their failure in implementing art.VI of the Nuclear Non-Proliferation Treaty (NPT),36 or the US of the Bush years for withdrawing from the Kyoto Protocol and failing to cut emissions is a typical judicial matter, as the two cases would regard the break of treaty obligations or the failure to cease doing some- thing harmful, not to bring about something good.37¶ Finally, two more fundamental objections could be raised against the idea of a legal protection of the inter- est of future generations. It could be argued that what would be represented (in a time-universalistic mode) is not the interest of future generations, but rather the interest of a particular fraction of the present ones, dis- guising itself as standard bearer of those people to come. On the one hand this should be taken into account as critical point of view in the public debate on those inter- ests. On the other hand, this criticism, strictly speaking, would also delegitimize such an ancient principle of Roman and Western law as the protection of the child. In morality it would affirm a radical skepticism that denies the possibility of slipping into another person’s clothes and acting from a non-egoistic stance. This can be obviously upheld, but at the price of the disappear- ance of morality as well as of the polity, which is – in any case and among other things – a solidaristic association.¶ A second problem, which is more difficult to deal with, is that we do not know as a general piece of knowl- edge what the interest of future generations is; whereas in the case of legal protection of the child we share a generally accepted knowledge of his or her future in- terest (to remain healthy, to get sufficient education, to be free to make the best of him/herself). What the real life conditions and the presumable vital interests of fu- ture generations will be can only be tentatively argued from what the several branches of natural and economic (e.g. demography) science are able to tell us about what is likely to remain constant in physical and cultural anthropology and what is likely to be most endangered.¶ As such, it is important that moral and political theory renew their relationship to the natural sciences after a time of reciprocal disdain between the two. While sci- ence cannot by itself draw an encompassing picture of future life under global threats, philosophy should learn from science what those future problems are likely to be and elaborate on them, instead of reflecting on the future of humanity by just moving from the doctrines of past philosophers or relying on the hearsay about it based on media reports or the philosopher’s personal divinations.¶ 6. My philosophical proposal to fill a hole in human rights discourse and legislation by introducing a first or meta-fundamental right of humankind to survival and positivizing it in national, international and world law38 resonates with two legal developments. The first related to ‘humanity’, the second to ‘human rights.’ The latter resonates with the novelties in constitutional law men- tioned in §5.¶ The first one began in 1970 as the UN General As- sembly adopted Resolution 2749, the Declaration of Principles Governing the Seabed and Ocean Floor, con- taining the notion of a “common heritage of mankind”; it was originally introduced to protect the seabed and ocean floor and later the “moon and other celestial bod- ies” from exploitation by powerful countries against the interest of the developing ones.39 In the 1990s, the competing and “thinner” concept of “common concern of mankind” emerged, as in the Convention on Bio- diversity of 1992; nonetheless it can be said that hu- mankind has become a notion contained in binding in- ternational law and referred to indivisible (climate) and divisible (seabed, ocean floor, moon) objects, and that this has happened as an answer to problems and chances generated by huge technological advancement.¶ In another corner of legal development, it could be argued that the logical structure, so to speak the norma- tive algorithm of the UDHR norms — the aforemen- tioned ‘everyone has the right . . . ’ — implies that hu- mankind, not just single individuals, is to be the bearer of those rights, even if the collective singular is not used. Turning to a more substantive level, we could go as far as to say that the legal protection of humankind’s survival was implicitly enshrined as early as 1948 in the UDHR and later in the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR) as well as the In- ternational Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (ICESCR), both of 1966. Art. 28 UDHR (“ev- eryone has the right to a social and international order in which the rights and freedoms set forth in this Decla- ration can be fully realized”) could be rethought in the direction of institutions bound to implement for every- one, now and in the future, the right to life (Art.3 UDHR, Art. 6 ICCPR), the right to an adequate standard of liv- ing incl. adequate food (Art.11 ICESRC)40 as well as¶ the right of the family to be protected (Art.10 ICESRC), a right that would be denied to families of the posterity bound to live under insufferable environmental condi- tions (cf. above the notion of a transgenerational chain of parents). While the different binding strength of the several <u><strong><mark>legal formulations</u></strong></mark> (treaty, covenant, convention, declaration) <u><strong><mark>cannot be ignored</u></strong></mark>, it remains clear that le- gal documents do not advance by themselves the cause of humankind’s survival, except if they can be effec- tively referred to in a court of justice; but <u><strong>they create an appropriate and stable environment for what can really bring about a change, that is educational and political struggles,</u></strong> the former aiming at a change in the political culture.¶ To sum up, (<u><strong>hu)mankind has thus ceased to be just a concept used by philosophers</u></strong> and theologians, whose presence in international law was merely philo- sophical, if not rhetorical, as in the Preamble to the UN Charter of 1945. Though not explicitly endowed with rights in the documents quoted above, the humankind of the “common heritage” doctrine is an important prece- dent in the direction, suggested by this article, of in- troducing this new legal actor. When looking at the implementation of the rights that can be attributed to it, the other legal novelty of the “common but dif- ferentiated responsibility”41 of individual actors, such as countries, should also be brought to bear. This is important when it comes to distributing the burden of the duties corresponding to those rights – which is in- deed one of the major issues in the debate following the Copenhagen Accord on Climate Change of 2009. In any case, the legal acknowledgment of a “common responsibility” for the global commons is a further step in designing humankind as a juridical notion.¶ This article is policy-oriented in the peculiar sense of a constitutional policy that will require decades, if ever, to become the subject of debate and even longer to be legally implemented. Impulses in this direction are cer- tainly not be expected from the world of politics, but rather from the scientific community (provided a now utopian sounding collaboration of physics, philosophy and legal theory materializes) or from scattered sen- tences of national and international courts, particularly in environmental matter.42 <u><strong><mark>Support from civil society would help</u></strong></mark>.¶<u><strong> Finally, the author’s suggestion as to how to read this proposal: it has a clearly cosmopolitan (or better: cosmopolitical) character, not however in the sense of cosmopolitanism as a general doctrine of government/ governance. It is rather generated by tools coming from realist thought: new threats as source of new rights, and lethal and planetary threats to the survival of hu- mankind’s civilization as drivers towards a new level of legal protection.</p></u></strong>
Speech 2NC 11-4 6AM
K
null
42,538
633
116,498
./documents/ndtceda17/MissouriState/MoHo/Missouri%20State-Morrison-Hopkins-Neg-Liberty-Round3.docx
599,304
N
Liberty
3
Wake NW
Nathan Buchholz
1AC Anti-black Disease Securitization 1NC FW Cap K 2NR FW
ndtceda17/MissouriState/MoHo/Missouri%20State-Morrison-Hopkins-Neg-Liberty-Round3.docx
null
50,991
MoHo
Missouri State MoHo
null
Ga.....
Mo.....
Pa.....
Ho.....
19,129
MissouriState
Missouri State
null
null
1,007
ndtceda17
NDT/CEDA 2017-18
2,017
cx
college
2
2,897,758
Nukes solve bioweapon acquisition
Horowitz ’14 –
Horowitz ’14 – professor of political science and the associate director of Perry World House at the University of Pennsylvania. NDT Champ (Michael, Neil Narang is Assistant Professor in the Department of Political Science at the University of California, Santa Barbara. In 2015-2016, he served as a Senior Advisor in the Office of the Secretary of Defense for Policy on a Council on Foreign Relations International Affairs Fellow, “Poor Man's Atomic Bomb? Exploring the Relationship between "Weapons of Mass Destruction"” The Journal of Conflict Resolution, Vol. 58, No. 3, Special Issue: Nuclear Posture, Nonproliferation Policy, and the Spread of Nuclear Weapons, http://www.jstor.org/stable/24545650)
we turn to estimating the effect of both nuclear and chemical weapons pur suit and acquisition on the risk of initiating biological weapons pursuit in models 5 and 6. they provide support for the notion that biological weapons can also be appro priately considered a "poor man's nuclear bomb." nuclear weapons possession has a strong negative effect on biological weapons pursuit simply possessing a nuclear weapon appears to decrease the instantaneous risk that a state will pursue biological weapons to virtually zero This is consistent with the understanding of nuclear weapons as so powerful that they make the possession of other types of WMDs less relevant.
we estimat the effect of nuclear weapons on initiating bio weapons biological weapons can be appro priately considered a "poor man's nuclear bomb nuclear possession has a strong negative effect on biological weapons pursuit simply possessing a nuc appears to decrease risk a state will pursue bio weapons to zero consistent with the understanding of nu s as so powerful that they make possession of other WMDs less relevant.
Finally, we turn to estimating the effect of both nuclear and chemical weapons pur suit and acquisition on the risk of initiating biological weapons pursuit in models 5 and 6. These results are equally interesting because they provide support for the notion that biological weapons (in addition to chemical weapons) can also be appro priately considered a "poor man's nuclear bomb." Similar to the impact of posses sing nuclear weapons on the probability a state pursues chemical weapons, nuclear weapons possession has a strong negative effect on biological weapons pursuit in both models 5 and 6. After holding the underlying level of demand constant in model 6, simply possessing a nuclear weapon appears to decrease the instantaneous risk that a state will pursue biological weapons to virtually zero (1.44 χ 10~7). This is consistent with the understanding of nuclear weapons as so powerful that they make the possession of other types of WMDs less relevant. Even before countries such as the United States abandoned their chemical weapons programs, for example, they aban doned their biological weapons program. The United States eliminated its offensive BW program under a Nixon administration order in 1969 and had shut down the pro gram by the time it signed the BWC in 1972. France and Great Britain similarly elim inated their offensive BW programs. Russia stands in stark contrast to this argument, however. Evidence revealed after the cold war demonstrated that the Soviet Union maintained a vibrant offensive BW program at the Biopreparat complex through the end of the cold war. This demonstrates that grouping CBWs into a single category may not accurately represent the way countries actually think about them. Biological weap ons, given their greater theoretical destructive capacity, may be considered somewhat differently. This is a potential path for future research.
1,888
<h4>Nukes solve <u>bioweapon acquisition</u> </h4><p><strong>Horowitz ’14 – </strong>professor of political science and the associate director of Perry World House at the University of Pennsylvania. NDT Champ (Michael, Neil Narang is Assistant Professor in the Department of Political Science at the University of California, Santa Barbara. In 2015-2016, he served as a Senior Advisor in the Office of the Secretary of Defense for Policy on a Council on Foreign Relations International Affairs Fellow, “Poor Man's Atomic Bomb? Exploring the Relationship between "Weapons of Mass Destruction"” The Journal of Conflict Resolution, Vol. 58, No. 3, Special Issue: Nuclear Posture, Nonproliferation Policy, and the Spread of Nuclear Weapons, http://www.jstor.org/stable/24545650)</p><p>Finally, <u><mark>we </mark>turn to <mark>estimat</mark>ing<mark> the effect of</mark> both <mark>nuclear</mark> and chemical <mark>weapons</mark> pur suit and acquisition <mark>on</mark> the risk of <mark>initiating bio</mark>logical <mark>weapons</mark> pursuit in models 5 and 6. </u>These results are equally interesting because <u>they provide support for the notion that <strong><mark>biological weapons</u></strong></mark> (in addition to chemical weapons) <u><strong><mark>can</mark> also <mark>be appro priately considered a "poor man's nuclear bomb</strong></mark>." </u>Similar to the impact of posses sing nuclear weapons on the probability a state pursues chemical weapons, <u><strong><mark>nuclear </mark>weapons <mark>possession has a strong negative effect on biological weapons pursuit</u></strong></mark> in both models 5 and 6. After holding the underlying level of demand constant in model 6, <u><strong><mark>simply possessing a nuc</mark>lear weapon <mark>appears to decrease </mark>the instantaneous <mark>risk </mark>that <mark>a state will pursue bio</mark>logical <mark>weapons to</mark> virtually <mark>zero</u></strong></mark> (1.44 χ 10~7). <u>This is <mark>consistent with the understanding of nu</mark>clear<mark> </mark>weapon<mark>s as so powerful that they make </mark>the <mark>possession of other </mark>types of <mark>WMDs less relevant.</u></mark> Even before countries such as the United States abandoned their chemical weapons programs, for example, they aban doned their biological weapons program. The United States eliminated its offensive BW program under a Nixon administration order in 1969 and had shut down the pro gram by the time it signed the BWC in 1972. France and Great Britain similarly elim inated their offensive BW programs. Russia stands in stark contrast to this argument, however. Evidence revealed after the cold war demonstrated that the Soviet Union maintained a vibrant offensive BW program at the Biopreparat complex through the end of the cold war. This demonstrates that grouping CBWs into a single category may not accurately represent the way countries actually think about them. Biological weap ons, given their greater theoretical destructive capacity, may be considered somewhat differently. This is a potential path for future research.</p>
null
Off
null
74,883
263
92,869
./documents/hsld19/Loyola/Pr/Loyola-Pribe-Neg-Berkeley-Round3.docx
843,321
N
Berkeley
3
Carter KM
Gabriel Gangoso
1AC - Whole Res NC - Deterrence DA Bioweapons V5 US PIC 1AR - Covered 2NR - US PIC 2AR - Covered
hsld19/Loyola/Pr/Loyola-Pribe-Neg-Berkeley-Round3.docx
null
71,961
AnPr
Loyola AnPr
null
An.....
Pr.....
null
null
24,196
Loyola
Loyola
CA
null
1,027
hsld19
HS LD 2019-20
2,019
ld
hs
1
1,774,069
Substantially limiting the defense pact must occur across the board, not in specific environments
Holmen 13
Holmen 13 (Holmen School District, SECTION 504 OF THE REHABILITATION ACT OF 1973, https://www.holmen.k12.wi.us/board/policies_and_admin_rules/300/a342-1%20504%20Rehab%20Act%20of%201973%2012-9-13.pdf)
A substantial limitation is a significant restriction The Supreme Court noted substantially limit definition must occur across the board not only in one environment or one setting
The Supreme Court noted substantially limit must occur across the board not only in one environment or one setting
A substantial limitation is a significant restriction as to the condition, manner, or duration under which an individual can perform a particular major life activity as compared to the condition, or duration under which the average person in the general population can perform that same major life activity. The Supreme Court in “Toyota v. Williams” noted that to meet the “substantially limit” definition, the disability must occur across the board in multiple environments, not only in one environment or one setting. The implication for school related 504 eligibility decisions is that the disability in question must be manifested in all facets of the student’s life, not only in school.
691
<h4><u><strong>Substantially limiting</u> the defense pact must occur <u>across the board</u>, not in specific environments </h4><p>Holmen 13</strong> (Holmen School District, SECTION 504 OF THE REHABILITATION ACT OF 1973, https://www.holmen.k12.wi.us/board/policies_and_admin_rules/300/a342-1%20504%20Rehab%20Act%20of%201973%2012-9-13.pdf)</p><p><u>A substantial limitation is a significant restriction</u> as to the condition, manner, or duration under which an individual can perform a particular major life activity as compared to the condition, or duration under which the average person in the general population can perform that same major life activity. <u><mark>The Supreme Court</mark> </u>in “Toyota v. Williams” <u><mark>noted</u></mark> that to meet the “<u><strong><mark>substantially limit</u></strong></mark>” <u>definition</u>, the disability <u><mark>must occur <strong>across the board </u></strong></mark>in multiple environments, <u><mark>not only in one</mark> <mark>environment or one setting</u><strong></mark>. The implication for school related 504 eligibility decisions is that the disability in question must be manifested in all facets of the student’s life, not only in school.</p></strong>
1NC
null
T
515,897
225
52,187
./documents/ndtceda20/Navy/RoLe/Navy-Rock-Lewis-Neg-UMW-Octas.docx
620,996
N
UMW
Octas
George Mason LM
Tom Pacheco, Ned Gidley, Gabe Morbeck
1AC- NATO Baltics 1NC-Syria Strike CP T-Subsets Afghan Transition DA Baltic Defense CP Deterrence Turns 2NR-Syra Strike CP Deterrence turns
ndtceda20/Navy/RoLe/Navy-Rock-Lewis-Neg-UMW-Octas.docx
null
52,439
RoLe
Navy RoLe
null
Ka.....
Ro.....
Wi.....
Le.....
19,338
Navy
Navy
null
null
1,010
ndtceda20
NDT/CEDA 2020-21
2,020
cx
college
2
1,978,002
Growth ensures resilience to systemic vulnerabilities---imminent extinction.
Kassab 17.
Kassab 17. Hanna Samir Kassab, Visiting Assistant Professor of Political Science at Northern Michigan University, Prioritization Theory and Defensive Foreign Policy. Springer International Publishing, 2017. CrossRef, doi:10.1007/978-3-319-48018-3. pp 222-227.
problems such as global warming, the diffusion of disease and other negative public outcomes Such matters bind the autonomy and sovereignty of peoples together in the universal need for survival When we study International Relations from the point of view of distribution of capabilities, scholars miss other aspects of the discipline A state’s behavior is carried out to survive against systemic vulnerabilities Power, driven by economic development, is the tool for neutralizing these vulnerabilities Power can be considered a laundry list of resources meant to achieve invulnerability from sources of threat. Whether from competitor states or disease and cyber-attacks, the role of power is to enhance the state’s survival ability against the odds Since resources are necessary to increase resilience they are the antidote to vulnerability, and the root of power to achieve invulnerability is the economy: economic development is thus the cure for vulnerability. The stronger the economy, the more resilient to exogenous shock Economic gains can be transformed into power in military terms, but also provide the necessary infrastructure to deal with health cyber environmental and other shocks and destabilization. Since power is tied to economic matters, economic vulnerabilities can significantly impede power The economy, with all its sensitivity and vulnerability, is a source of instability for all actors.
warming disease and other negative outcomes bind peoples together in the universal need for survival Power, driven by economic development, is the tool for neutralizing these power enhance survival against the odds Since resources are necessary to resilience they are the antidote to vulnerability The stronger the economy, the more resilient to exogenous shock Economic gains provide infrastructure to deal with health, cyber, environmental and other shocks and destabilization
Furthermore, this work recognizes the importance of self-determination and economic development. These are not inherently bad things. Self-determination recognizes the right of a state as represented by its people to live out the destiny of their own choosing. Economic development, even from this Western modernist perspective, recognizes the value of human life and seeks to protect it through the proper and efficient allocation of resources. However, if peoples choose to withdraw into a closed community, it is their right to do so. Yet the problem remains: states and peoples are now more interconnected than ever. And so instead of remaining insular, everyone in the world has an interest to ensure the proper functioning of the international system and the tackling of the world’s problems such as global warming, the diffusion of disease and other negative public outcomes. Such matters bind the autonomy and sovereignty of peoples together in the universal need for survival. Final Words When we study International Relations from the point of view of distribution of capabilities, scholars miss other aspects of the discipline. A state’s behavior is carried out to survive against the systemic vulnerabilities described in this book. Power, driven by economic development, is the tool for neutralizing these vulnerabilities, so as to protect individuals living inside the state. Power can be considered a laundry list of resources (Waltz 2010) meant to achieve invulnerability from sources of threat. Whether from competitor states or disease and cyber-attacks, the role of power is to enhance the state’s survival ability against the odds: to decrease vulnerability. Since resources are necessary to increase resilience to threats, they are the antidote to vulnerability, and the root of power to achieve invulnerability is the economy: economic development is thus the cure for vulnerability. The stronger, more advanced the economy, the more resilient it will be to exogenous shock in the ways described. Economic gains can be transformed into power in military terms, but also provide the necessary infrastructure to deal with health, cyber, environmental and other shocks and destabilization. Since power is tied to economic matters, economic vulnerabilities can significantly impede power and a state’s ability to deal with threats. The financial crisis in 2008 damaged the European Union and much of the Caribbean because of their dependence on the USA. The falling price of oil is decreasing global aggregate demand as Russians do not have as much to spend. This has occurred during a period of Russian expansionism and while Eastern Europe is concerned about Russia’s military might, it must recognize the power of the world economy in terms of punishing this sort of action. Waltz focused on the distribution of capabilities as a means toward security. I look at world politics as the struggle to correct vulnerabilities in order to remain secure. Military power cannot solve such vulnerability. Enhancing invulnerability will come through economic development in a modernist perspective but threats will never be truly neutralized until all states in the system are economically developed. The economy, with all its sensitivity and vulnerability, is a source of instability for all actors.
3,311
<h4>Growth ensures resilience to <u>systemic vulnerabilities</u>---imminent <u>extinction</u>. </h4><p><strong><mark>Kassab 17</mark>.</strong> <u>Hanna Samir Kassab, Visiting Assistant Professor of Political Science at Northern Michigan University, Prioritization Theory and Defensive Foreign Policy. Springer International Publishing, 2017. CrossRef, doi:10.1007/978-3-319-48018-3. pp 222-227. </p><p></u>Furthermore, this work recognizes the importance of self-determination and economic development. These are not inherently bad things. Self-determination recognizes the right of a state as represented by its people to live out the destiny of their own choosing. Economic development, even from this Western modernist perspective, recognizes the value of human life and seeks to protect it through the proper and efficient allocation of resources. However, if peoples choose to withdraw into a closed community, it is their right to do so. Yet the problem remains: states and peoples are now more interconnected than ever. And so instead of remaining insular, everyone in the world has an interest to ensure the proper functioning of the international system and the tackling of the world’s <u>problems such as <strong>global <mark>warming</strong></mark>, the diffusion of <strong><mark>disease</strong> and other <strong>negative</mark> public <mark>outcomes</u></strong></mark>. <u>Such matters <strong><mark>bind</strong></mark> the autonomy and sovereignty of <mark>peoples together in the <strong>universal need for survival</u></strong></mark>. Final Words <u>When we study International Relations from the point of view of distribution of capabilities, scholars miss</u> <u><strong>other aspects of the discipline</u></strong>. <u>A state’s behavior is carried out to <strong>survive against</u></strong> the <u><strong>systemic vulnerabilities</strong> </u>described in this book. <u><strong><mark>Power</strong>, driven by</u> <u><strong>economic development</strong>, is the</u> <u><strong>tool for neutralizing these</mark> vulnerabilities</u></strong>, so as to protect individuals living inside the state. <u>Power can be considered a laundry list of resources</u> (Waltz 2010) <u>meant to achieve invulnerability from <strong>sources of threat</strong>. Whether from</u> <u><strong>competitor states</u></strong> <u>or</u> <u><strong>disease and cyber-attacks</strong>, the role of <mark>power</mark> is to <mark>enhance</mark> the state’s</u> <u><strong><mark>survival</mark> ability <mark>against the odds</u></strong></mark>: to decrease vulnerability. <u><mark>Since</u> <u><strong>resources</u></strong> <u>are necessary to</mark> increase <mark>resilience</u></mark> to threats, <u><mark>they are the</u> <u><strong>antidote to vulnerability</strong></mark>, and the root of power to achieve invulnerability is the <strong>economy</strong>: <strong>economic development is thus the cure for vulnerability. </strong><mark>The</u> <u><strong>stronger</u></strong></mark>, more advanced <u><strong><mark>the economy</strong>, the</u> <u><strong>more resilient</u></strong></mark> it will be <u><mark>to exogenous shock</u></mark> in the ways described. <u><mark>Economic gains</mark> can be transformed into power in military terms, but also <mark>provide</mark> the necessary</u> <u><strong><mark>infrastructure</u></strong> <u>to deal with</u> <u><strong>health</u></strong>, <u><strong>cyber</u></strong>, <u><strong>environmental</u></strong> <u>and</u> <u><strong>other shocks</u></strong> <u>and</u> <u><strong>destabilization</strong></mark>. Since power is tied to economic matters, economic vulnerabilities can significantly <strong>impede power</u></strong> and a state’s ability to deal with threats. The financial crisis in 2008 damaged the European Union and much of the Caribbean because of their dependence on the USA. The falling price of oil is decreasing global aggregate demand as Russians do not have as much to spend. This has occurred during a period of Russian expansionism and while Eastern Europe is concerned about Russia’s military might, it must recognize the power of the world economy in terms of punishing this sort of action. Waltz focused on the distribution of capabilities as a means toward security. I look at world politics as the struggle to correct vulnerabilities in order to remain secure. Military power cannot solve such vulnerability. Enhancing invulnerability will come through economic development in a modernist perspective but threats will never be truly neutralized until all states in the system are economically developed. <u>The economy, with all its <strong>sensitivity and vulnerability</strong>, is a source of instability for all actors.</p></u>
null
1AC---Samford
1AC---Taxes
42,250
235
58,296
./documents/hspolicy20/MontgomeryBell/LeHa/Montgomery%20Bell-Leverett-Hastings-Aff-Peninsula-Round2.docx
735,471
A
Peninsula
2
Wooster SW
Jake Melton
1ac taxes
hspolicy20/MontgomeryBell/LeHa/Montgomery%20Bell-Leverett-Hastings-Aff-Peninsula-Round2.docx
null
62,702
LeHa
Montgomery Bell LeHa
null
Le.....
Le.....
Jo.....
Ha.....
21,723
MontgomeryBell
Montgomery Bell
TN
null
1,019
hspolicy20
HS Policy 2020-21
2,020
cx
hs
2
4,548,462
There are infinite worlds, the aff is true in one which affirms.
Vaidman 2
Vaidman 2 Vaidman, Lev, 3-24-2002, "Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)," No Publication, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qm-manyworlds/
-MWI: Multiple Worlds Interpretation The reason for adopting the MWI is that it avoids the collapse of the quantum wave. The collapse postulate is a physical law that differs from all known physics in two aspects: it is genuinely random and it involves some kind of action at a distance quantum experiment is not determined by the initial conditions only the probabilities are governed by the initial state . There is no experimental evidence in favor of collapse and against the MWI.
adopting the MWI avoids the collapse of the quantum wave quantum experiment is not determined by the initial conditions only the probabilities are governed by the initial state . There is no experimental evidence against the MWI.
-MWI: Multiple Worlds Interpretation The reason for adopting the MWI is that it avoids the collapse of the quantum wave. (Other non-collapse theories are not better than MWI for various reasons, e.g., nonlocality of Bohmian mechanics; and the disadvantage of all of them is that they have some additional structure.) The collapse postulate is a physical law that differs from all known physics in two aspects: it is genuinely random and it involves some kind of action at a distance. According to the collapse postulate the outcome of a quantum experiment is not determined by the initial conditions of the Universe prior to the experiment: only the probabilities are governed by the initial state. Moreover, Bell 1964 has shown that there cannot be a compatible local-variables theory that will make deterministic predictions. There is no experimental evidence in favor of collapse and against the MWI.
903
<h4>There are infinite worlds, the aff is true in one which affirms. </h4><p><strong>Vaidman 2</strong> Vaidman, Lev, 3-24-2002, "Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)," No Publication, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qm-manyworlds/</p><p><u><strong>-MWI: Multiple Worlds Interpretation</p><p>The reason for <mark>adopting the MWI </mark>is that it <mark>avoids the collapse of the quantum wave</mark>.</u></strong> (Other non-collapse theories are not better than MWI for various reasons, e.g., nonlocality of Bohmian mechanics; and the disadvantage of all of them is that they have some additional structure.) <u><strong>The collapse postulate is a physical law that differs from all known physics in two aspects: it is genuinely random and it involves some kind of action at a distance</u></strong>. According to the collapse postulate the outcome of a <u><strong><mark>quantum experiment is not determined by the initial conditions</u></strong></mark> of the Universe prior to the experiment: <u><strong><mark>only the probabilities are governed by the initial state</u></strong></mark>. Moreover, Bell 1964 has shown that there cannot be a compatible local-variables theory that will make deterministic predictions<u><strong><mark>. There is no experimental evidence </mark>in favor of collapse and <mark>against the MWI.</p></u></strong></mark>
null
null
Method
327,083
166
149,914
./documents/hsld22/HoustonMemorial/BeDu/HoustonMemorial-BeDu-Aff-Grapevine-Classic-Round-4.docx
922,866
A
Grapevine Classic
4
Greenhill SK
Jack Quisenberry
1AC - Stock 1NC - PTX DA States CP Case 1AR - Condo Bad 50 States Bad Case PTX DA States CP 2NR - Condo Bad 50 States Bad PTX DA States CP 2AR - 50 States Bad States CP
hsld22/HoustonMemorial/BeDu/HoustonMemorial-BeDu-Aff-Grapevine-Classic-Round-4.docx
2022-09-10 21:04:53
79,279
BeDu
Houston Memorial BeDu
null
Be.....
Du.....
null
null
26,529
HoustonMemorial
Houston Memorial
TX
null
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
864,118
Even if decline causes conflicts, leaders won’t use force
Jervis 11
Robert Jervis 11, Professor in the Department of Political Science and School of International and Public Affairs at Columbia University, December 2011, “Force in Our Times,” Survival, Vol. 25, No. 4, p. 403-425
a worsening of current economic difficulties, could produce greater nationalism, undermine democracy and bring back old-fashioned beggar-my-neighbor economic policies While these dangers are real it is hard to believe that the conflicts could be great enough to lead members of the community to contemplate fighting each other. It is not so much that economic interdependence could not be reversed Rather it is that even if the more extreme versions of free trade and economic liberalism become discredited it is hard to see how leaders and mass opinion would come to believe that their countries could prosper by impoverishing or attacking others While a pessimist could note that this argument does not appear as outlandish as it did before the financial crisis an optimist could reply (correctly that the very fact that we have seen such a sharp economic down-turn without anyone suggesting that force is the solution shows that even if bad times bring about greater economic conflict, it will not make war thinkable.
worsening economic difficulties could produce nationalism it is hard to believe that the conflicts could be great enough to lead to fighting even if extreme versions of trade and liberalism become discredited, it is hard to see how leaders would believe their countries could prosper by attacking others the fact that we have seen such a sharp down-turn without anyone suggesting force shows that even if bad times bring economic conflict, it will not make war thinkable
Even if war is still seen as evil, the security community could be dissolved if severe conflicts of interest were to arise. Could the more peaceful world generate new interests that would bring the members of the community into sharp disputes? 45 A zero-sum sense of status would be one example, perhaps linked to a steep rise in nationalism. More likely would be a worsening of the current economic difficulties, which could itself produce greater nationalism, undermine democracy and bring back old-fashioned beggar-my-neighbor economic policies. While these dangers are real, it is hard to believe that the conflicts could be great enough to lead the members of the community to contemplate fighting each other. It is not so much that economic interdependence has proceeded to the point where it could not be reversed – states that were more internally interdependent than anything seen internationally have fought bloody civil wars. Rather it is that even if the more extreme versions of free trade and economic liberalism become discredited, it is hard to see how without building on a preexisting high level of political conflict leaders and mass opinion would come to believe that their countries could prosper by impoverishing or even attacking others. Is it possible that problems will not only become severe, but that people will entertain the thought that they have to be solved by war? While a pessimist could note that this argument does not appear as outlandish as it did before the financial crisis, an optimist could reply (correctly, in my view) that the very fact that we have seen such a sharp economic down-turn without anyone suggesting that force of arms is the solution shows that even if bad times bring about greater economic conflict, it will not make war thinkable.
1,792
<h4>Even if decline causes conflicts, leaders won’t use <u>force</h4><p></u>Robert <strong>Jervis 11<u></strong>, Professor in the Department of Political Science and School of International and Public Affairs at Columbia University, December 2011, “Force in Our Times,” Survival, Vol. 25, No. 4, p. 403-425</p><p></u>Even if war is still seen as evil, the security community could be dissolved if severe conflicts of interest were to arise. Could the more peaceful world generate new interests that would bring the members of the community into sharp disputes? 45 A zero-sum sense of status would be one example, perhaps linked to a steep rise in nationalism. More likely would be <u>a <mark>worsening</mark> of</u> the <u>current <mark>economic difficulties</mark>,</u> which <u><mark>could</u></mark> itself <u><mark>produce</mark> greater <mark>nationalism</mark>, undermine democracy and bring back old-fashioned beggar-my-neighbor economic policies</u>. <u>While these dangers are real</u>, <u><strong><mark>it is hard to believe that the conflicts could be great enough</u></strong> <u>to</mark> <mark>lead</u></mark> the <u>members of the community <mark>to</mark> contemplate <mark>fighting</mark> each other. It is not so much that economic interdependence</u> has proceeded to the point where it <u>could not be reversed</u> – states that were more internally interdependent than anything seen internationally have fought bloody civil wars. <u>Rather it is that</u> <u><strong><mark>even if</mark> the more <mark>extreme versions of</mark> free <mark>trade and</mark> economic <mark>liberalism become discredited</u></strong>, <u>it is</u> <u>hard to see how</u></mark> without building on a preexisting high level of political conflict <u><mark>leaders</mark> and mass opinion <mark>would</mark> come to <mark>believe</mark> that <mark>their countries could prosper by</mark> impoverishing or</u> even <u><mark>attacking others</u></mark>. Is it possible that problems will not only become severe, but that people will entertain the thought that they have to be solved by war? <u>While a pessimist could note that this argument does not appear as outlandish as it did before the financial crisis</u>, <u>an optimist could reply (correctly</u>, in my view) <u>that <mark>the</mark> very <mark>fact that we have seen</u> <u><strong>such a sharp</mark> economic <mark>down-turn</u></strong> <u>without <strong>anyone</strong> suggesting</mark> that <mark>force</u></mark> of arms <u>is the solution</u> <u><mark>shows that</u> <u>even if bad times bring</mark> about greater <strong><mark>economic</strong> conflict, it will not make war thinkable</mark>.</p></u>
1AR
null
Politics DA
3,773
705
20,670
./documents/ndtceda15/Northwestern/McOB/Northwestern-McCarty-OBrien-Aff-Harvard-Round6.docx
584,371
A
Harvard
6
GMU KK
Smelko
New advantage CS21
ndtceda15/Northwestern/McOB/Northwestern-McCarty-OBrien-Aff-Harvard-Round6.docx
null
49,914
McOB
Northwestern McOB
null
Ev.....
Mc.....
Co.....
OB.....
18,975
Northwestern
Northwestern
null
null
1,005
ndtceda15
NDT/CEDA 2015-16
2,015
cx
college
2
4,051,721
No space war and terrestrial conflict turns it
Hall 15
Luke Penn-Hall 15, Analyst at The Cipher Brief, M.A. from the Johns Hopkins School for Advanced International Studies, B.A. in International Relations and Religious Studies from Claremont McKenna College, “5 Reasons “Space War” Isn’t As Scary As It Sounds”, The Cipher Brief, 8/18/2015, https://www.thecipherbrief.com/article/5-reasons-%E2%80%9Cspace-war%E2%80%9D-isn%E2%80%99t-scary-it-sounds
The U.S. depends heavily on military and commercial satellites An ASAT attack would likely be part of a larger, terrestrial attack. An attack on space assets would be no different than an attack on territory or other assets on earth. This means that no space war would stay limited to space. An ASAT campaign would be part of a larger conventional military conflict that would play out on earth. Every country with ASAT capabilities also needs satellites most other countries need satellites to participate in the global economy. All countries that have the technical ability to play in this space – the U.S., Russia, China and India - also have a vested interest in preventing the militarization of space and protecting their own satellites. If any of those countries were to attack U.S. satellites, it would likely hurt them far more than it would hurt the United States. 4. Any country that threatened access to space would threaten the global economy. Even if a full-blown ablation cascade didn’t occur, an ASAT campaign would cause debris, making operating in space more hazardous. The global economy relies on satellites and any disruption of operations would be met with worldwide disapproval and severe economic ramifications. International Prohibits the Use of ASAT Weapons. Several international treaties expressly prohibit signatory nations from attacking other countries’ space assets. It is generally accepted that space should be treated as a global common area, rather than a military domain. space war is highly unlikely All involved parties are incentivized against attacking. However, if a space war did occur, it would be part of a larger conflict on Earth
Every country with ASAT capabilities needs sat s U.S., Russia, China and India have a vested interest preventing militarization to attack would hurt them far more International Prohibits ASAT space war is highly unlikely All parties are incentivized against attacking if did occur, it would be part of a larger conflict on Earth
The U.S. depends heavily on military and commercial satellites. If a less satellite-dependent opponent launched an anti-satellite (ASAT) attack, it would have far greater impact on the U.S. than the attacker. However, it’s not as simple as that – for the following reasons: 1. An ASAT attack would likely be part of a larger, terrestrial attack. An attack on space assets would be no different than an attack on territory or other assets on earth. This means that no space war would stay limited to space. An ASAT campaign would be part of a larger conventional military conflict that would play out on earth. 2. Every country with ASAT capabilities also needs satellites. While the United States is the most dependent on military satellites, most other countries need satellites to participate in the global economy. All countries that have the technical ability to play in this space – the U.S., Russia, China and India - also have a vested interest in preventing the militarization of space and protecting their own satellites. If any of those countries were to attack U.S. satellites, it would likely hurt them far more than it would hurt the United States. 3. Destruction of satellites could create a damaging chain reaction. Scientists warn that the violent destruction of satellites could result in an effect called an ablation cascade. High-velocity debris from a destroyed satellite could crash into other satellites and create more high-velocity debris. If an ablation cascade were to occur, it could render certain orbital levels completely unusable for centuries. 4. Any country that threatened access to space would threaten the global economy. Even if a full-blown ablation cascade didn’t occur, an ASAT campaign would cause debris, making operating in space more hazardous. The global economy relies on satellites and any disruption of operations would be met with worldwide disapproval and severe economic ramifications. 5. International Prohibits the Use of ASAT Weapons. Several international treaties expressly prohibit signatory nations from attacking other countries’ space assets. It is generally accepted that space should be treated as a global common area, rather than a military domain. While it remains necessary for military planners to create contingency plans for a, space war it is a highly unlikely scenario. All involved parties are incentivized against attacking. However, if a space war did occur, it would be part of a larger conflict on Earth. Those concerned about the potential for war in space should be more concerned about the potential for war, period.
2,606
<h4><u><strong>No space war</u> and terrestrial conflict <u>turns it</h4><p></u></strong>Luke Penn-<strong>Hall 15</strong>, Analyst at The Cipher Brief, M.A. from the Johns Hopkins School for Advanced International Studies, B.A. in International Relations and Religious Studies from Claremont McKenna College, “5 Reasons “Space War” Isn’t As Scary As It Sounds”, The Cipher Brief, 8/18/2015, https://www.thecipherbrief.com/article/5-reasons-%E2%80%9Cspace-war%E2%80%9D-isn%E2%80%99t-scary-it-sounds</p><p><u>The U.S. depends heavily on military and commercial satellites</u>. If a less satellite-dependent opponent launched an anti-satellite (ASAT) attack, it would have far greater impact on the U.S. than the attacker. However, it’s not as simple as that – for the following reasons: </p><p>1. <u>An ASAT attack would likely be <strong>part of a larger, terrestrial attack</strong>. An attack on space assets would be no different than an attack on territory or other assets on earth. This means that no space war would stay limited to space. An ASAT campaign would be part of a larger conventional military conflict that would play out on earth.</p><p></u>2. <u><mark>Every country with ASAT capabilities</mark> also <mark>needs <strong>sat</strong></mark>ellite<strong><mark>s</u></strong></mark>. While the United States is the most dependent on military satellites, <u>most other countries need satellites to participate in the global economy. All countries that have the technical ability to play in this space – the <mark>U.S., Russia, China and India</mark> - also <mark>have a <strong>vested interest</strong></mark> in <mark>preventing</mark> the <mark>militarization</mark> of space and protecting their own satellites. If any of those countries were <mark>to attack</mark> U.S. satellites, it <mark>would</mark> likely <strong><mark>hurt them</strong> far more</mark> than it would hurt the United States.</p><p></u>3. Destruction of satellites could create a damaging chain reaction. Scientists warn that the violent destruction of satellites could result in an effect called an ablation cascade. High-velocity debris from a destroyed satellite could crash into other satellites and create more high-velocity debris. If an ablation cascade were to occur, it could render certain orbital levels completely unusable for centuries.</p><p><u>4. Any country that threatened access to space would threaten the global economy. Even if a full-blown ablation cascade didn’t occur, an ASAT campaign would cause debris, making operating in space more hazardous. The global economy relies on satellites and any disruption of operations would be met with worldwide disapproval and severe economic ramifications.</p><p></u>5. <u><mark>International <strong>Prohibits</strong></mark> the Use of <mark>ASAT</mark> Weapons. Several international treaties expressly <strong>prohibit signatory nations</strong> from attacking other countries’ space assets. It is generally accepted that space should be treated as a global common area, rather than a military domain.</p><p></u>While it remains necessary for military planners to create contingency plans for a, <u><mark>space war</u></mark> it <u><mark>is</u></mark> a <u><strong><mark>highly unlikely</u></strong></mark> scenario. <u><mark>All</mark> involved <mark>parties are <strong>incentivized against</strong> attacking</mark>. However, <mark>if</mark> a space war <mark>did occur, it would be <strong>part of</strong> a larger conflict <strong>on Earth</u></strong></mark>. Those concerned about the potential for war in space should be more concerned about the potential for war, period. </p>
K
Adv 2
Alt Cause – Kinetic Weapons
13,352
242
138,437
./documents/hspolicy22/Barstow/LeBa/Barstow-LeBa-Neg-Trevian-Invitational-Round-1.docx
933,460
N
Trevian Invitational
1
Univ Of Chicago Lab ES
Awsare
1AC- Space 1NC- Security K, DoD Tradeoff DA, EU CP, Diplomacy CP 2NR- K and Case Result- Loss
hspolicy22/Barstow/LeBa/Barstow-LeBa-Neg-Trevian-Invitational-Round-1.docx
2022-10-08 19:00:38
82,150
LeBa
Barstow LeBa
Tyler - He/Him - [email protected] Ava - [email protected]
Av.....
Le.....
Ty.....
Ba.....
27,018
Barstow
Barstow
MO
null
2,002
hspolicy22
HS Policy 2022-23
2,022
cx
hs
2
1,959,027
Our authors have self-interest against data inflation.
Ravenal 9
Ravenal 9 – Distinguished Senior Fellow in Foreign Policy Studies at the Cato Institute
The notion of security bureaucracies . . . looking for new enemies is threadbare What is missing from claims of “threat inflation,” is a convincing theory of why national-security roles embody objectivity in the treatment of “threats” and the power and capabilities of other nations behavior tends to be formalized transparent and peer-reviewed defense decision-makers “frame” problems on the basis of the most accurate intelligence They make it their business to know where threats come from threats are not “socially constructed People are fired for presenting skewed analysis because something important is riding on the prediction. “rent-seeking” would present a severe risk of career termination.
The notion of security bureaucracies . . . looking for new enemies is threadbare What is missing from claims of “threat inflation,” is a convincing theory of why national-security roles embody objectivity in the treatment of “threats” and the power and capabilities of other nations behavior tends to be formalized transparent and peer-reviewed defense decision-makers “frame” problems on the basis of the most accurate intelligence They make it their business to know where threats come from threats are not “socially constructed People are fired for presenting skewed analysis because something important is riding on the prediction “rent-seeking” would present a severe risk of career termination
(Earl C., also professor emeritus of the Georgetown University School of Foreign Service, “What's Empire Got to Do with It? The Derivation of America's Foreign Policy.” Critical Review: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Politics and Society 21.1 (2009) 21-75) The underlying notion of “the security bureaucracies . . . looking for new enemies” is a threadbare concept that has somehow taken hold across the political spectrum, from the radical left (viz. Michael Klare [1981], who refers to a “threat bank”), to the liberal center (viz. Robert H. Johnson [1997], who dismisses most alleged “threats” as “improbable dangers”), to libertarians (viz. Ted Galen Carpenter [1992], Vice President for Foreign and Defense Policy of the Cato Institute, who wrote a book entitled A Search for Enemies). What is missing from most analysts’ claims of “threat inflation,” however, is a convincing theory of why, say, the American government significantly (not merely in excusable rhetoric) might magnify and even invent threats (and, more seriously, act on such inflated threat estimates). In a few places, Eland (2004, 185) suggests that such behavior might stem from military or national security bureaucrats’ attempts to enhance their personal status and organizational budgets, or even from the influence and dominance of “the military-industrial complex”; viz.: “Maintaining the empire and retaliating for the blowback from that empire keeps what President Eisenhower called the military-industrial complex fat and happy.” Or, in the same section: In the nation’s capital, vested interests, such as the law enforcement bureaucracies . . . routinely take advantage of “crises”to satisfy parochial desires. Similarly, many corporations use crises to get pet projects— a.k.a. pork—funded by the government. And national security crises, because of people’s fears, are especially ripe opportunities to grab largesse. (Ibid., 182) Thus, “bureaucratic-politics” theory, which once made several reputa- tions (such as those of Richard Neustadt, Morton Halperin, and Graham Allison) in defense-intellectual circles, and spawned an entire sub-industry within the field of international relations,5 is put into the service of dismissing putative security threats as imaginary. So, too, can a surprisingly cognate theory, “public choice,”6 which can be considered the right-wing analog of the “bureaucratic-politics” model, and is a preferred interpretation of governmental decision- making among libertarian observers. As Eland (2004, 203) summarizes: Public-choice theory argues [that] the government itself can develop sepa- rate interests from its citizens. The government reflects the interests of powerful pressure groups and the interests of the bureaucracies and the bureaucrats in them. Although this problem occurs in both foreign and domestic policy, it may be more severe in foreign policy because citizens pay less attention to policies that affect them less directly. There is, in this statement of public-choice theory, a certain ambiguity, and a certain degree of contradiction: Bureaucrats are supposedly, at the same time, subservient to societal interest groups and autonomous from society in general. This journal has pioneered the argument that state autonomy is a likely consequence of the public’s ignorance of most areas of state activity (e.g., Somin 1998; DeCanio 2000a, 2000b, 2006, 2007; Ravenal 2000a). But state autonomy does not necessarily mean that bureaucrats substitute their own interests for those of what could be called the “national society” that they ostensibly serve. I have argued (Ravenal 2000a) that, precisely because of the public-ignorance and elite-expertise factors, and especially because the opportunities—at least for bureaucrats (a few notable post-government lobbyist cases nonwithstanding)—for lucrative self-dealing are stringently fewer in the defense and diplomatic areas of government than they are in some of the contract-dispensing and more under-the-radar-screen agencies of government, the “public-choice” imputation of self-dealing, rather than working toward the national interest (which, however may not be synonymous with the interests, perceived or expressed, of citizens!) is less likely to hold. In short, state autonomy is likely to mean, in the derivation of foreign policy, that “state elites” are using rational judgment, in insulation from self-promoting interest groups—about what strategies, forces, and weapons are required for national defense. Ironically, “public choice”—not even a species of economics, but rather a kind of political interpretation—is not even about “public” choice, since, like the bureaucratic-politics model, it repudiates the very notion that bureaucrats make truly “public” choices; rather, they are held, axiomatically, to exhibit “rent-seeking” behavior, wherein they abuse their public positions in order to amass private gains, or at least to build personal empires within their ostensibly official niches. Such sub- rational models actually explain very little of what they purport to observe. Of course, there is some truth in them, regarding the “behavior” of some people, at some times, in some circumstances, under some conditions of incentive and motivation. But the factors that they posit operate mostly as constraints on the otherwise rational optimization of objectives that, if for no other reason than the playing out of official roles, transcends merely personal or parochial imperatives. My treatment of “role” differs from that of the bureaucratic-politics theorists, whose model of the derivation of foreign policy depends heavily, and acknowledgedly, on a narrow and specific identification of the role- playing of organizationally situated individuals in a partly conflictual “pulling and hauling” process that “results in” some policy outcome. Even here, bureaucratic-politics theorists Graham Allison and Philip Zelikow (1999, 311) allow that “some players are not able to articulate [sic] the governmental politics game because their conception of their job does not legitimate such activity.” This is a crucial admission, and one that points— empirically—to the need for a broader and generic treatment of role. Roles (all theorists state) give rise to “expectations” of performance. My point is that virtually every governmental role, and especially national-security roles, and particularly the roles of the uniformed military, embody expectations of devotion to the “national interest”; rational- ity in the derivation of policy at every functional level; and objectivity in the treatment of parameters, especially external parameters such as “threats” and the power and capabilities of other nations. Sub-rational models (such as “public choice”) fail to take into account even a partial dedication to the “national” interest (or even the possibility that the national interest may be honestly misconceived in more paro- chial terms). In contrast, an official’s role connects the individual to the (state-level) process, and moderates the (perhaps otherwise) self-seeking impulses of the individual. Role-derived behavior tends to be formalized and codified; relatively transparent and at least peer-reviewed, so as to be consistent with expectations; surviving the particular individual and trans- mitted to successors and ancillaries; measured against a standard and thus corrigible; defined in terms of the performed function and therefore derived from the state function; and uncorrrupt, because personal cheating and even egregious aggrandizement are conspicuously discouraged. My own direct observation suggests that defense decision-makers attempt to “frame” the structure of the problems that they try to solve on the basis of the most accurate intelligence. They make it their business to know where the threats come from. Thus, threats are not “socially constructed” (even though, of course, some values are). A major reason for the rationality, and the objectivity, of the process is that much security planning is done, not in vaguely undefined circum- stances that offer scope for idiosyncratic, subjective behavior, but rather in structured and reviewed organizational frameworks. Non-rationalities (which are bad for understanding and prediction) tend to get filtered out. People are fired for presenting skewed analysis and for making bad predictions. This is because something important is riding on the causal analysis and the contingent prediction. For these reasons, “public choice” does not have the “feel” of reality to many critics who have participated in the structure of defense decision-making. In that structure, obvious, and even not-so-obvious,“rent-seeking” would not only be shameful; it would present a severe risk of career termination. And, as mentioned, the defense bureaucracy is hardly a productive place for truly talented rent-seekers to operatecompared to opportunities for personal profit in the commercial world. A bureaucrat’s very self-placement in these reaches of government testi- fies either to a sincere commitment to the national interest or to a lack of sufficient imagination to exploit opportunities for personal profit.
9,189
<h4>Our authors have self-interest <u>against</u> data inflation.</h4><p><strong>Ravenal 9</strong> – Distinguished Senior Fellow in Foreign Policy Studies at the Cato Institute</p><p>(Earl C., also professor emeritus of the Georgetown University School of Foreign Service, “What's Empire Got to Do with It? The Derivation of America's Foreign Policy.” Critical Review: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Politics and Society 21.1 (2009) 21-75)</p><p><u><mark>The</u></mark> underlying <u><mark>notion of</u></mark> “the <u><mark>security bureaucracies . . . looking for new enemies</u></mark>” <u><mark>is</u></mark> a <u><strong><mark>threadbare</u></strong></mark> concept that has somehow taken hold across the political spectrum, from the radical left (viz. Michael Klare [1981], who refers to a “threat bank”), to the liberal center (viz. Robert H. Johnson [1997], who dismisses most alleged “threats” as “improbable dangers”), to libertarians (viz. Ted Galen Carpenter [1992], Vice President for Foreign and Defense Policy of the Cato Institute, who wrote a book entitled A Search for Enemies). <u><mark>What is missing from</u></mark> most analysts’ <u><mark>claims of “threat inflation,”</u></mark> however, <u><mark>is <strong>a convincing theory of why</u></strong></mark>, say, the American government significantly (not merely in excusable rhetoric) might magnify and even invent threats (and, more seriously, act on such inflated threat estimates). In a few places, Eland (2004, 185) suggests that such behavior might stem from military or national security bureaucrats’ attempts to enhance their personal status and organizational budgets, or even from the influence and dominance of “the military-industrial complex”; viz.: “Maintaining the empire and retaliating for the blowback from that empire keeps what President Eisenhower called the military-industrial complex fat and happy.” Or, in the same section: In the nation’s capital, vested interests, such as the law enforcement bureaucracies . . . routinely take advantage of “crises”to satisfy parochial desires. Similarly, many corporations use crises to get pet projects— a.k.a. pork—funded by the government. And national security crises, because of people’s fears, are especially ripe opportunities to grab largesse. (Ibid., 182) Thus, “bureaucratic-politics” theory, which once made several reputa- tions (such as those of Richard Neustadt, Morton Halperin, and Graham Allison) in defense-intellectual circles, and spawned an entire sub-industry within the field of international relations,5 is put into the service of dismissing putative security threats as imaginary. So, too, can a surprisingly cognate theory, “public choice,”6 which can be considered the right-wing analog of the “bureaucratic-politics” model, and is a preferred interpretation of governmental decision- making among libertarian observers. As Eland (2004, 203) summarizes: Public-choice theory argues [that] the government itself can develop sepa- rate interests from its citizens. The government reflects the interests of powerful pressure groups and the interests of the bureaucracies and the bureaucrats in them. Although this problem occurs in both foreign and domestic policy, it may be more severe in foreign policy because citizens pay less attention to policies that affect them less directly. There is, in this statement of public-choice theory, a certain ambiguity, and a certain degree of contradiction: Bureaucrats are supposedly, at the same time, subservient to societal interest groups and autonomous from society in general. This journal has pioneered the argument that state autonomy is a likely consequence of the public’s ignorance of most areas of state activity (e.g., Somin 1998; DeCanio 2000a, 2000b, 2006, 2007; Ravenal 2000a). But state autonomy does not necessarily mean that bureaucrats substitute their own interests for those of what could be called the “national society” that they ostensibly serve. I have argued (Ravenal 2000a) that, precisely because of the public-ignorance and elite-expertise factors, and especially because the opportunities—at least for bureaucrats (a few notable post-government lobbyist cases nonwithstanding)—for lucrative self-dealing are stringently fewer in the defense and diplomatic areas of government than they are in some of the contract-dispensing and more under-the-radar-screen agencies of government, the “public-choice” imputation of self-dealing, rather than working toward the national interest (which, however may not be synonymous with the interests, perceived or expressed, of citizens!) is less likely to hold. In short, state autonomy is likely to mean, in the derivation of foreign policy, that “state elites” are using rational judgment, in insulation from self-promoting interest groups—about what strategies, forces, and weapons are required for national defense. Ironically, “public choice”—not even a species of economics, but rather a kind of political interpretation—is not even about “public” choice, since, like the bureaucratic-politics model, it repudiates the very notion that bureaucrats make truly “public” choices; rather, they are held, axiomatically, to exhibit “rent-seeking” behavior, wherein they abuse their public positions in order to amass private gains, or at least to build personal empires within their ostensibly official niches. Such sub- rational models actually explain very little of what they purport to observe. Of course, there is some truth in them, regarding the “behavior” of some people, at some times, in some circumstances, under some conditions of incentive and motivation. But the factors that they posit operate mostly as constraints on the otherwise rational optimization of objectives that, if for no other reason than the playing out of official roles, transcends merely personal or parochial imperatives. My treatment of “role” differs from that of the bureaucratic-politics theorists, whose model of the derivation of foreign policy depends heavily, and acknowledgedly, on a narrow and specific identification of the role- playing of organizationally situated individuals in a partly conflictual “pulling and hauling” process that “results in” some policy outcome. Even here, bureaucratic-politics theorists Graham Allison and Philip Zelikow (1999, 311) allow that “some players are not able to articulate [sic] the governmental politics game because their conception of their job does not legitimate such activity.” This is a crucial admission, and one that points— empirically—to the need for a broader and generic treatment of role. Roles (all theorists state) give rise to “expectations” of performance. My point is that virtually every governmental role, and especially<u><strong> </strong><mark>national-security roles</u></mark>, and particularly the roles of the uniformed military, <u><mark>embody</u></mark> expectations of devotion to the “national interest”; rational- ity in the derivation of policy at every functional level; and <u><strong><mark>objectivity</strong> in the treatment of</u></mark> parameters, especially external parameters such as <u><mark>“threats” and the power and capabilities of other nations</u></mark>. Sub-rational models (such as “public choice”) fail to take into account even a partial dedication to the “national” interest (or even the possibility that the national interest may be honestly misconceived in more paro- chial terms). In contrast, an official’s role connects the individual to the (state-level) process, and moderates the (perhaps otherwise) self-seeking impulses of the individual. Role-derived <u><mark>behavior tends to be formalized</u></mark> and codified; relatively <u><strong><mark>transparent</strong> and</u></mark> at least <u><strong><mark>peer-reviewed</u></strong></mark>, so as to be consistent with expectations; surviving the particular individual and trans- mitted to successors and ancillaries; measured against a standard and thus corrigible; defined in terms of the performed function and therefore derived from the state function; and uncorrrupt, because personal cheating and even egregious aggrandizement are conspicuously discouraged. My own direct observation suggests that <u><strong><mark>defense decision-makers</u></strong> </mark>attempt to <u><strong><mark>“frame”</u></strong></mark> the structure of the <u><strong><mark>problems</u></strong></mark> that they try to solve <u><strong><mark>on the basis of the most accurate intelligence</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong><mark>They make it their business to know where</u></strong></mark> the <u><strong><mark>threats come from</u></strong></mark>. Thus, <u><strong><mark>threats are not “socially constructed</u></strong></mark>” (even though, of course, some values are). A major reason for the rationality, and the objectivity, of the process is that much security planning is done, not in vaguely undefined circum- stances that offer scope for idiosyncratic, subjective behavior, but rather in structured and reviewed organizational frameworks. Non-rationalities (which are bad for understanding and prediction) tend to get filtered out. <u><strong><mark>People are fired for presenting skewed analysis</u></strong></mark> and for making bad predictions. This is <u><strong><mark>because something important is riding on the</u></strong></mark> causal analysis and the contingent <u><strong><mark>prediction</mark>. </u></strong>For these reasons, “public choice” does not have the “feel” of reality to many critics who have participated in the structure of defense decision-making. In that structure, obvious, and even not-so-obvious,<u><mark>“<strong>rent-seeking” would</u></strong></mark> not only be shameful; it would <u><strong><mark>present a severe risk of career termination</mark>.</u></strong> And, as mentioned, the defense bureaucracy is hardly a productive place for truly talented rent-seekers to operatecompared to opportunities for personal profit in the commercial world. A bureaucrat’s very self-placement in these reaches of government testi- fies either to a sincere commitment to the national interest or to a lack of sufficient imagination to exploit opportunities for personal profit.</p>
null
ADV
Framing
1,602
503
57,866
./documents/hspolicy20/MinneapolisSouth/CoCh/Minneapolis%20South-Conry-ChangDeutsch-Neg-GBX-Round4.docx
734,867
N
GBX
4
LASA GP
Arvind Shankar
1AC - DNA 1NC - ESR CP Senate Elections Abolition CR DA T Immigration T Substantial Courts 2NR -- CR DA (Straight Turned)
hspolicy20/MinneapolisSouth/CoCh/Minneapolis%20South-Conry-ChangDeutsch-Neg-GBX-Round4.docx
null
62,684
CoCh
Minneapolis South CoCh
null
Cl.....
Co.....
Ga.....
Ch.....
21,720
MinneapolisSouth
Minneapolis South
MN
null
1,019
hspolicy20
HS Policy 2020-21
2,020
cx
hs
2
4,549,770
Vote affirmative as an endorsement of dysfluency and the failure of disability to be productive – this 1AC is a performative affective intervention by diverting from what is expected in a space that is meant to purposefully exclude disability in the name of productivity – this 1AC serves as a reminder of the failed ASL movement that the PRL instantly stopped in the name of productivity and efficiency. Only a refusal of this world addresses ableism as the basis of communication—we defend the 1AC’s affective pessimism as an example of a die-in within topic discussions, a refusal to breathe life into the resolution. Pessimistic die-ins break from institutional participation as a starting point for politics in favor of disrupting the circulation of discourses predicated upon optimism and disabled death. This hijacks communicative spheres by purposefully forefronting discussions of disabled killability.
Selck 16
Selck 16 Michael (2016): Crip Pessimism: The Language of Dis/ability and the Culture that Isn't, Southern Illinois University Carbondale, SJCP//JG
The disabled are dying and with them dis/abled culture is being eradicated. In the time between formulating this project and its completion already too many disabled souls have been taken from this world Attached to the grief I feel as a result of the fading disability studies community is the perpetual grief I harbor since my disabled Father’s suicide and in turn the grief concomitant to the claiming of a disabled identity. I choose to start out this project with grief because it communicates the tenor of this research; this is not the disability studies project of inspiration or utopia. My entry point to the disability studies dialogue is riddled with grief, anger, and pain and it is as such that this project plots a course of disability research that attempts to make a space free from the ideological constraints of optimism. Often times, “social organization according to able-bodied norms is just taken as natural, normal, inevitable, necessary, even progress” (Delvin & Pothier, 2006, p. 7). Philosophical pessimism is articulated next as a way to temper the risk of sensationalizing dis/ability I come to pessimism because of my experience with disability. My anxiety disorder comes with an exteriority of anti-social behavior that has branded me pessimistic. The concern for my anxiety in public situations is often commented on as overly critical, negative, narcissistic, and most often pessimistic. I experience an anxious state of becoming different, and after years of failing to rehabilitate my sameness to able-bodied standards, I have come to a comfort with pessimism. Pessimists ask if those improvements are related to a greater set of costs that are not immediately recognizable. (Dienstag, 2006, p. 25) Similar to critical disability theory, pessimism interrogates power and privilege. Pessimists rely on the logic of difference to chart consequences. Consequences go unperceived because they occur across populations with disproportionate access to power, populations that are often culturally unintelligible. The absurdity of existence “is illustrated by the persistent mismatch between human purposes and the means available to achieve them: or again, between our desire for happiness and our capacity to encounter or sustain it” The fourth and final tenet of pessimism that we are to examine asks what we are to do about our dire human condition. The choice to affirm life in its entirety is a pessimistic choice. Embracing life as both miserable and beautiful, fleeting and enduring, validates the perpetually fragmented subject seeking a world that exists beyond good and evil and instead just is.
disability free from ideological constraints of optimism Often times organization to able-bodied taken as inevitable after failing to rehabilitate able-bodied standards come to a comfort with pessimism The choice to affirm life in its entirety is a pessimistic choice Embracing life as miserable and beautiful
The disabled are dying and with them dis/abled culture is being eradicated. In the time between formulating this project and its completion already too many disabled souls have been taken from this world, including pivotal disability studies influences for this research. I barely had enough time to mourn the loss of disability advocate and inspiration porn critic Stella Young before grieving the loss of disability studies exemplar Tobin Siebers. Attached to the grief I feel as a result of the fading disability studies community is the perpetual grief I harbor since my disabled Father’s suicide and in turn the grief concomitant to the claiming of a disabled identity. I choose to start out this project with grief because it communicates the tenor of this research; this is not the disability studies project of inspiration or utopia. My entry point to the disability studies dialogue is riddled with grief, anger, and pain and it is as such that this project plots a course of disability research that attempts to make a space free from the ideological constraints of optimism. The language surrounding dis/ability is highly political. Entire words, phrases, and identities are stretched between, in, and out of the nexus of dis/ability. The choice, for instance, to include a backslash in the word dis/ability represents for Goodley (2014) a desire to delineate and expand each of the categories in the face of global neoliberalism. My initial research inquired about the impact of dis/abled terms and phrases. I went to interrogate rhetoric like “special education”, “handicapable”, and one of the most glaringly overused insults in the American education system “retard”. The scholarship I was coming up with was plentiful but was for the most part located entirely outside of intercultural communication programs like the one I was attending. For the most part the few and far between intercultural communication projects about dis/ability I was able to locate were without modal complexity and didn’t bear semblance to so many of my own experiences. I was beginning to notice a layer of optimism that has been communicatively imprinted upon the negotiation of dis/abled identity. The angst started to manifest as I questioned if I was in the correct field or if dis/ability even was ‘cultural’. I felt a very real cultural erasure of dis/ability in academia and ultimately that glaring lack of consideration is what pushed me to performance studies. I first worked to close the apparent research gap by crafting a collaborative performance titled Under the Mantle (UTM), which put dis/ability, communication scholarship, and pessimist philosophy on stage. The larger purpose of this research report is to antagonize the erasure of dis/ability from communication studies by autoethnographically analyzing the crip-pessimist performance art project Under The Mantle. This research report will first detail the components of the theoretical work that was drawn on to create UTM. Next I offer a literature review to demonstrate the combination of optimism and neglect dis/ability has undergone in intercultural communication models. Following that section I mark my shift to performance methods as I explain how narrative autoethnography can illuminate cultural misconceptions regarding the dis/abled. In the last sections of this report I offer a textual analysis of the performance UTM and analyze three significant arguments of the instillation before concluding. Contextualizing Critical Dis/Ability Theory Often used interchangeably, critical disability theory (CDT) and critical disability studies (CDS) contest dis/ablism (Goodley, 2011, 2014; Devlin & Pothier, 2006; Hosking, 2008). There are several unique additions made to CDS with every new instantiation. Scholars in European countries and Canada attend to the theory, with United States academics often underrepresented. There are three concurrent themes of CDT that I will synthesize in this section with some dis/ability studies authors claiming there are as many as seven themes of CDT (Hosking, 2008). In the introduction to their edited collection of dis/ability essays, Richard Devlin and Dianne Pothier (2006) present three themes of CDT as, first, to highlight the unequal status to which persons with disabilities are confined; second, to destabilize necessitarian assumptions that reinforce the marginalization of persons with disabilities; and third, to help generate the individual and collective practical agency of persons with disabilities in the struggles for recognition and redistribution. (p. 18, emphasis mine) Already the connections between the CDT and the critical communication paradigm are visible as each respectively forefronts notions of power, privilege, identity, and agency. Outlined in more detail, the first theme of CDT argues that there is systemic micro and macro level discrimination against bodies with disabilities. To some critical communication scholars, this theme might be obvious, but it seldom is when “the resulting exclusion of those who do not fit able-bodied norms may not be noticeable or even intelligible” (Delvin & Pothier, 2006, p. 7). As the bumper sticker on my laptop proudly disclaims, “Not all disabilities are visible,” which necessarily adds a level of nuance and complexity to the way that dis/ability studies attend to the prospect of discrimination and violence. Often times, “social organization according to able-bodied norms is just taken as natural, normal, inevitable, necessary, even progress” (Delvin & Pothier, 2006, p. 7). It might be true that the lack of collaborative work between critical communication studies and dis/ability studies is because neoliberalism is supremely effective at rebranding marginalized oppression as a marker of its progress. The implications of this assertion are dire but essential to the basis of crip-pessimism. Theoretical approaches based in pessimism and skepticism are often necessary to distinguish the instruments of self destruction that have been mistaken for those of self betterment. Thus, a key question remains, what is regarded as progress and to whom does it count? The politics of progress call for the second tenet of CDT, which is a destabilization of neoliberal practices that strip power and agency from bodies with disabilities. Devlin and Pothier (2006) use the language of “anti-necessitarian” (p. 2), which refers to the efficacy of social organizations and an unflinching skepticism of liberalism. For Shildrick and Price (1999), “disabled bodies call into question the ‘giveness’ of the ‘natural body’ and, instead, posit a corporeality that is fluid in its investments and meanings” (p. 1). Anti-necessitarian logics ask questions that remain innocuous to the critical communication paradigm. Can the architectural proliferation of stairs and multiple levels on buildings be attributed to neoliberalism and active disablism? If stairs seem to focus too exclusively on physical impairments, then what about the sensitivity of the building’s lighting, acoustics, and spatiality? Finally, if neoliberalism fights to protect its grand narrative of progress then is the social exclusion of bodies with disabilities necessary for the day-to-day operation of our globalized world? As Donaldson (2002) posits: “theories of gendered, raced, sexed, classed, and disabled bodies offer us critical languages for ‘denaturalising’ impairment’” (p. 112) at the level of the subjective and inter-subjective. The third theme of CDT is to attend to the agency of bodies with disabilities in the struggle for recognition. One key element of extending agency to the disabled is the use of social experience. Experience is subjective “but experience remains intimately connected to political and social existence, and therefore individuals and societies are capable of learning from their experiences” (Siebers, 2008, p. 82). Though absolutely necessary, it is not enough to write treatises on the oppression of the disabled over time. Academics, theorists, intercultural trainers, and storytellers alike should be aware of the constant risks of representation. Representation and context are at the core of critical disability studies. The notion of agency is as unstable as the notions of dis/ability. There is no one-size-fits-all human rights based approach that will be suitable to address all disabled experiences, as the theoretical call for crip-pessimism will remind us. Instead of a universal abstract Rawlsian concept of social justice, CDS “attend(s) to the relational components of dis/ablism” (Goodley, 2011, p. 159). By a Rawlsian concept of social justice I mean a model that relies on distributive justice with utopist equality at its core. Where utopist equality projects highlight human sameness to the point of purity. CDT unavoidably invites a discussion about difference into the folds as postmodern and post-structural thinkers position the self as defined constantly in relation to others. Therein lies the difference between an equality model and a justice model of social identity. Often in the attempt to open up spaces for reconsidering self and other, CDS celebrates disability as a positive identity marker. This essay offers a strong argument of caution that the inclusion of CDS in critical communication studies might rely too heavily on celebrations of disabled identity. Nothing better demonstrates that reliance on celebrating identity than the myriad language choices used to describe a disabled identity including: differently-abled, special needs, person with disability, disabled person, temporarily able-bodied, and others. Often, able- bodied audiences have a tendency to sensationalize the presence of disability in a space that has not traditionally welcomed it. Examples of this are highlighted by the increasingly popular discussion of ‘inspiration porn’ (Young, 2014) and Hollywood’s representation of disability. The tendency is to inspirationalize the disabled for achieving tasks that would not be celebrated if they were accomplished by an unimpaired body. Crossing the street, showing up on time, entering a building by oneself are all tasks profoundly routine to the non-disabled and yet simultaneously cherished as markers of progress for the disabled. Philosophical pessimism is articulated next as a way to temper the risk of sensationalizing dis/ability. The theories ultimately fuse together like orchids and wasps to generate the larger theme of crip-pessimism. Philosophical Pessimism Throughout the 19th century pessimism was one of the most popular intellectual and philosophical strains, crossing countries and continents. Authors such as Rousseau, Leopardi, Schopenhauer, and Nietzsche overwhelmingly created and lead the spirit of pessimism. Contemporarily however, the word ‘pessimism’ is pejorative and describes a body’s emotional discontent rather than intellectual engagement with the world. Dienstag (2009) writes, “Since pessimism is perceived more as a disposition than as a theory, pessimists are seen primarily as dissenters from whatever the prevailing consensus of their time happens to be, rather than as constituting a continuous alternative” (p. 3). Power is responsible for ontological shifts, and during shifts some populations benefit while others are harmed. The turn in thinking about pessimism from an intellectual position to an emotional state has been particularly gratuitous for bodies with disabilities. I come to pessimism because of my experience with disability. My anxiety disorder comes with an exteriority of anti-social behavior that has branded me pessimistic. The concern for my anxiety in public situations is often commented on as overly critical, negative, narcissistic, and most often pessimistic. I experience an anxious state of becoming different, and after years of failing to rehabilitate my sameness to able-bodied standards, I have come to a comfort with pessimism. I choose to include pessimism as a theoretical crutch to avoid communication studies’ sensationalism of disability. I imagine that when critical communication studies does bridge the dis/ability research gap that it might, at least initially, extend some neoliberal logics at the expense of CDS. This might manifest by scholars simply asserting disabled personhood where it does not institutionally, culturally, or individually exist. I find that CDT and philosophical pessimism combine in unique and valuable ways, particularly around tensions of personhood, abstract ideal humanism, and neoliberalism. Neoliberalism should be understood as “the superiority of individualized, market-based competition over other modes of organization. This basic principle is the hallmark of neo-liberal thought— one with old roots that lay partly in Anglo economics and partly in German schools of liberalism” (Mudge, 2008, p. 706-707). There are four components of pessimism outlined by Joshua Foa Dienstag (2006) in his book Pessimism: Philosophy, Ethic, Spirit that I wish to explore difference through. They are as following that: (1) time is a burden, (2) history is ironic, (3) human existence is absurd, and finally (4) resignation or affirmation. To write about pessimism necessarily involves questions of time, temporality, and history. The development of philosophical pessimism, specifically, the theories regarding the burden of time-consciousness, begins with difference. For the pessimist, the concept of time begets a differentiation between human and animal. Being a dog-owner myself, I have heard the colloquial aphorism that dogs, as all animals, have no concept of time. Pessimists understand time consciousness as a unique, but ultimately loathsome, trait of the human condition. Even in projects that appear to be geared toward sameness there are always unperceived and neglected populations. For example, even the U.S. constitution alleges persons of color were (and still are often) racially subjugated as property instead of considered to be fully human. The notion of difference is at the center of the pessimist’s position on time-consciousness because the philosophy accepts that the conditions of our existence are subject to relentless unpredictable change. “To the pessimists, however, the human condition is existentially unique— its uniqueness consisting precisely in the capacity for time-consciousness” (Dienstag, 2009, p. 20). For the pessimist nothing is ever the same, everything is always different, and to inhabit linear time means that everything in existence is always rushing off into the past. The advent of human time consciousness is also what leads the pessimist to find the course of history to be ironic. History is ironic for the pessimist because progress is always related to a greater set of unperceived consequences. As suggested above, philosophical pessimism acknowledges that change occurs; technologies develop and improve over time. Pessimists ask if those improvements are related to a greater set of costs that are not immediately recognizable. (Dienstag, 2006, p. 25) Similar to critical disability theory, pessimism interrogates power and privilege. Pessimists rely on the logic of difference to chart consequences. Consequences go unperceived because they occur across populations with disproportionate access to power, populations that are often culturally unintelligible. For instance, the massive boom in mobile technologies like cell phones and laptops has created vast pits of ‘e-waste’ in Africa, surges in child labor, and conflict over rare earth minerals (Vidal, 2013). Pessimists use difference to tease out the distinction between the instruments of suffering and those of betterment. The third philosophical pessimistic position is that human existence is absurd. The absurdity of existence “is illustrated by the persistent mismatch between human purposes and the means available to achieve them: or again, between our desire for happiness and our capacity to encounter or sustain it” (Dienstag, 2006, p. 32). Difference is built upon exanimations of power, which is both fluid and transferable but ultimately permanent. Classical western philosophy has an optimistic pragmatism built into it that posits there must be an answer to our questions. Alternatively, the pessimist embraces uncertainty, ambiguity, and intersubjectivity. Pessimism encourages a sense of comfort around the idea of multiple, coexistent, and perhaps competing histories. Neoliberal optimism is the logic of conflict as materially reconcilable, rather than antagonistically irreconcilable. The fourth and final tenet of pessimism that we are to examine asks what we are to do about our dire human condition. There are multiplicities of rationales that ultimately inform the pessimistic dualism to either resign from life or affirm it entirely. I defer to an existential or Nietzschean pessimism that recognizes suffering is inevitable for two reasons. First, human time-consciousness necessitates an awareness of our impending death. Second, mutually assured value systems will always intersubjectively exist. The choice to affirm life in its entirety is a pessimistic choice. Embracing life as both miserable and beautiful, fleeting and enduring, validates the perpetually fragmented subject seeking a world that exists beyond good and evil and instead just is.
17,358
<h4><strong>Vote affirmative as an endorsement of dysfluency and the failure of disability to be productive – this 1AC is a performative affective intervention by diverting from what is expected in a space that is meant to purposefully exclude disability in the name of productivity – this 1AC serves as a reminder of the failed ASL movement that the PRL instantly stopped in the name of productivity and efficiency. Only a refusal of this world addresses ableism as the basis of communication—we defend the 1AC’s affective pessimism as an example of a die-in within topic discussions, a refusal to breathe life into the resolution. Pessimistic die-ins break from institutional participation as a starting point for politics in favor of disrupting the circulation of discourses predicated upon optimism and disabled death. This hijacks communicative spheres by purposefully forefronting discussions of disabled killability. </h4><p>Selck 16</strong> Michael (2016): Crip Pessimism: The Language of Dis/ability and the Culture that Isn't, Southern Illinois University Carbondale, SJCP//JG</p><p><u>The disabled are dying and with them dis/abled culture is being eradicated. In the time between formulating this project and its completion already too many disabled souls have been taken from this world</u>, including pivotal disability studies influences for this research. I barely had enough time to mourn the loss of disability advocate and inspiration porn critic Stella Young before grieving the loss of disability studies exemplar Tobin Siebers. <u>Attached to the grief I feel as a result of the fading disability studies community is the perpetual grief I harbor since my disabled Father’s suicide and in turn the grief concomitant to the claiming of a disabled identity. I choose to start out this project with grief because it communicates the tenor of this research; this is not the disability studies project of inspiration or utopia. My entry point to the disability studies dialogue is riddled with grief, anger, and pain and it is as such that this project plots a course of <strong><mark>disability</strong></mark> research that attempts to make a space <strong><mark>free from</strong></mark> the <strong><mark>ideological constraints of optimism</strong></mark>. </u>The language surrounding dis/ability is highly political. Entire words, phrases, and identities are stretched between, in, and out of the nexus of dis/ability. The choice, for instance, to include a backslash in the word dis/ability represents for Goodley (2014) a desire to delineate and expand each of the categories in the face of global neoliberalism. My initial research inquired about the impact of dis/abled terms and phrases. I went to interrogate rhetoric like “special education”, “handicapable”, and one of the most glaringly overused insults in the American education system “retard”. The scholarship I was coming up with was plentiful but was for the most part located entirely outside of intercultural communication programs like the one I was attending. For the most part the few and far between intercultural communication projects about dis/ability I was able to locate were without modal complexity and didn’t bear semblance to so many of my own experiences. I was beginning to notice a layer of optimism that has been communicatively imprinted upon the negotiation of dis/abled identity. The angst started to manifest as I questioned if I was in the correct field or if dis/ability even was ‘cultural’. I felt a very real cultural erasure of dis/ability in academia and ultimately that glaring lack of consideration is what pushed me to performance studies. I first worked to close the apparent research gap by crafting a collaborative performance titled Under the Mantle (UTM), which put dis/ability, communication scholarship, and pessimist philosophy on stage. The larger purpose of this research report is to antagonize the erasure of dis/ability from communication studies by autoethnographically analyzing the crip-pessimist performance art project Under The Mantle. This research report will first detail the components of the theoretical work that was drawn on to create UTM. Next I offer a literature review to demonstrate the combination of optimism and neglect dis/ability has undergone in intercultural communication models. Following that section I mark my shift to performance methods as I explain how narrative autoethnography can illuminate cultural misconceptions regarding the dis/abled. In the last sections of this report I offer a textual analysis of the performance UTM and analyze three significant arguments of the instillation before concluding. Contextualizing Critical Dis/Ability Theory Often used interchangeably, critical disability theory (CDT) and critical disability studies (CDS) contest dis/ablism (Goodley, 2011, 2014; Devlin & Pothier, 2006; Hosking, 2008). There are several unique additions made to CDS with every new instantiation. Scholars in European countries and Canada attend to the theory, with United States academics often underrepresented. There are three concurrent themes of CDT that I will synthesize in this section with some dis/ability studies authors claiming there are as many as seven themes of CDT (Hosking, 2008). In the introduction to their edited collection of dis/ability essays, Richard Devlin and Dianne Pothier (2006) present three themes of CDT as, first, to highlight the unequal status to which persons with disabilities are confined; second, to destabilize necessitarian assumptions that reinforce the marginalization of persons with disabilities; and third, to help generate the individual and collective practical agency of persons with disabilities in the struggles for recognition and redistribution. (p. 18, emphasis mine) Already the connections between the CDT and the critical communication paradigm are visible as each respectively forefronts notions of power, privilege, identity, and agency. Outlined in more detail, the first theme of CDT argues that there is systemic micro and macro level discrimination against bodies with disabilities. To some critical communication scholars, this theme might be obvious, but it seldom is when “the resulting exclusion of those who do not fit able-bodied norms may not be noticeable or even intelligible” (Delvin & Pothier, 2006, p. 7). As the bumper sticker on my laptop proudly disclaims, “Not all disabilities are visible,” which necessarily adds a level of nuance and complexity to the way that dis/ability studies attend to the prospect of discrimination and violence. <u><strong><mark>Often times</strong></mark>, “social <strong><mark>organization</strong></mark> according <strong><mark>to</strong></mark> <strong><mark>able-bodied</strong></mark> norms is just <strong><mark>taken as</strong></mark> natural, normal, <strong><mark>inevitable</strong></mark>, necessary, even progress” (Delvin & Pothier, 2006, p. 7).</u> It might be true that the lack of collaborative work between critical communication studies and dis/ability studies is because neoliberalism is supremely effective at rebranding marginalized oppression as a marker of its progress. The implications of this assertion are dire but essential to the basis of crip-pessimism. Theoretical approaches based in pessimism and skepticism are often necessary to distinguish the instruments of self destruction that have been mistaken for those of self betterment. Thus, a key question remains, what is regarded as progress and to whom does it count? The politics of progress call for the second tenet of CDT, which is a destabilization of neoliberal practices that strip power and agency from bodies with disabilities. Devlin and Pothier (2006) use the language of “anti-necessitarian” (p. 2), which refers to the efficacy of social organizations and an unflinching skepticism of liberalism. For Shildrick and Price (1999), “disabled bodies call into question the ‘giveness’ of the ‘natural body’ and, instead, posit a corporeality that is fluid in its investments and meanings” (p. 1). Anti-necessitarian logics ask questions that remain innocuous to the critical communication paradigm. Can the architectural proliferation of stairs and multiple levels on buildings be attributed to neoliberalism and active disablism? If stairs seem to focus too exclusively on physical impairments, then what about the sensitivity of the building’s lighting, acoustics, and spatiality? Finally, if neoliberalism fights to protect its grand narrative of progress then is the social exclusion of bodies with disabilities necessary for the day-to-day operation of our globalized world? As Donaldson (2002) posits: “theories of gendered, raced, sexed, classed, and disabled bodies offer us critical languages for ‘denaturalising’ impairment’” (p. 112) at the level of the subjective and inter-subjective. The third theme of CDT is to attend to the agency of bodies with disabilities in the struggle for recognition. One key element of extending agency to the disabled is the use of social experience. Experience is subjective “but experience remains intimately connected to political and social existence, and therefore individuals and societies are capable of learning from their experiences” (Siebers, 2008, p. 82). Though absolutely necessary, it is not enough to write treatises on the oppression of the disabled over time. Academics, theorists, intercultural trainers, and storytellers alike should be aware of the constant risks of representation. Representation and context are at the core of critical disability studies. The notion of agency is as unstable as the notions of dis/ability. There is no one-size-fits-all human rights based approach that will be suitable to address all disabled experiences, as the theoretical call for crip-pessimism will remind us. Instead of a universal abstract Rawlsian concept of social justice, CDS “attend(s) to the relational components of dis/ablism” (Goodley, 2011, p. 159). By a Rawlsian concept of social justice I mean a model that relies on distributive justice with utopist equality at its core. Where utopist equality projects highlight human sameness to the point of purity. CDT unavoidably invites a discussion about difference into the folds as postmodern and post-structural thinkers position the self as defined constantly in relation to others. Therein lies the difference between an equality model and a justice model of social identity. Often in the attempt to open up spaces for reconsidering self and other, CDS celebrates disability as a positive identity marker. This essay offers a strong argument of caution that the inclusion of CDS in critical communication studies might rely too heavily on celebrations of disabled identity. Nothing better demonstrates that reliance on celebrating identity than the myriad language choices used to describe a disabled identity including: differently-abled, special needs, person with disability, disabled person, temporarily able-bodied, and others. Often, able- bodied audiences have a tendency to sensationalize the presence of disability in a space that has not traditionally welcomed it. Examples of this are highlighted by the increasingly popular discussion of ‘inspiration porn’ (Young, 2014) and Hollywood’s representation of disability. The tendency is to inspirationalize the disabled for achieving tasks that would not be celebrated if they were accomplished by an unimpaired body. Crossing the street, showing up on time, entering a building by oneself are all tasks profoundly routine to the non-disabled and yet simultaneously cherished as markers of progress for the disabled. <u>Philosophical pessimism is articulated next as a way to temper the risk of sensationalizing dis/ability</u>. The theories ultimately fuse together like orchids and wasps to generate the larger theme of crip-pessimism. Philosophical Pessimism Throughout the 19th century pessimism was one of the most popular intellectual and philosophical strains, crossing countries and continents. Authors such as Rousseau, Leopardi, Schopenhauer, and Nietzsche overwhelmingly created and lead the spirit of pessimism. Contemporarily however, the word ‘pessimism’ is pejorative and describes a body’s emotional discontent rather than intellectual engagement with the world. Dienstag (2009) writes, “Since pessimism is perceived more as a disposition than as a theory, pessimists are seen primarily as dissenters from whatever the prevailing consensus of their time happens to be, rather than as constituting a continuous alternative” (p. 3). Power is responsible for ontological shifts, and during shifts some populations benefit while others are harmed. The turn in thinking about pessimism from an intellectual position to an emotional state has been particularly gratuitous for bodies with disabilities. <u>I come to pessimism because of my experience with disability. My anxiety disorder comes with an exteriority of anti-social behavior that has branded me pessimistic. The concern for my anxiety in public situations is often commented on as overly critical, negative, narcissistic, and most often pessimistic. I experience an anxious state of becoming different, and <strong><mark>after</strong></mark> years of <strong><mark>failing to rehabilitate</strong></mark> my sameness to <strong><mark>able-bodied standards</strong></mark>, I have <strong><mark>come to a comfort with pessimism</strong></mark>. </u>I choose to include pessimism as a theoretical crutch to avoid communication studies’ sensationalism of disability. I imagine that when critical communication studies does bridge the dis/ability research gap that it might, at least initially, extend some neoliberal logics at the expense of CDS. This might manifest by scholars simply asserting disabled personhood where it does not institutionally, culturally, or individually exist. I find that CDT and philosophical pessimism combine in unique and valuable ways, particularly around tensions of personhood, abstract ideal humanism, and neoliberalism. Neoliberalism should be understood as “the superiority of individualized, market-based competition over other modes of organization. This basic principle is the hallmark of neo-liberal thought— one with old roots that lay partly in Anglo economics and partly in German schools of liberalism” (Mudge, 2008, p. 706-707). There are four components of pessimism outlined by Joshua Foa Dienstag (2006) in his book Pessimism: Philosophy, Ethic, Spirit that I wish to explore difference through. They are as following that: (1) time is a burden, (2) history is ironic, (3) human existence is absurd, and finally (4) resignation or affirmation. To write about pessimism necessarily involves questions of time, temporality, and history. The development of philosophical pessimism, specifically, the theories regarding the burden of time-consciousness, begins with difference. For the pessimist, the concept of time begets a differentiation between human and animal. Being a dog-owner myself, I have heard the colloquial aphorism that dogs, as all animals, have no concept of time. Pessimists understand time consciousness as a unique, but ultimately loathsome, trait of the human condition. Even in projects that appear to be geared toward sameness there are always unperceived and neglected populations. For example, even the U.S. constitution alleges persons of color were (and still are often) racially subjugated as property instead of considered to be fully human. The notion of difference is at the center of the pessimist’s position on time-consciousness because the philosophy accepts that the conditions of our existence are subject to relentless unpredictable change. “To the pessimists, however, the human condition is existentially unique— its uniqueness consisting precisely in the capacity for time-consciousness” (Dienstag, 2009, p. 20). For the pessimist nothing is ever the same, everything is always different, and to inhabit linear time means that everything in existence is always rushing off into the past. The advent of human time consciousness is also what leads the pessimist to find the course of history to be ironic. History is ironic for the pessimist because progress is always related to a greater set of unperceived consequences. As suggested above, philosophical pessimism acknowledges that change occurs; technologies develop and improve over time. <u>Pessimists ask if those improvements are related to a greater set of costs that are not immediately recognizable. (Dienstag, 2006, p. 25) Similar to critical disability theory, pessimism interrogates power and privilege. Pessimists rely on the logic of difference to chart consequences. Consequences go unperceived because they occur across populations with disproportionate access to power, populations that are often culturally unintelligible.</u> For instance, the massive boom in mobile technologies like cell phones and laptops has created vast pits of ‘e-waste’ in Africa, surges in child labor, and conflict over rare earth minerals (Vidal, 2013). Pessimists use difference to tease out the distinction between the instruments of suffering and those of betterment. The third philosophical pessimistic position is that human existence is absurd. <u>The absurdity of existence “is illustrated by the persistent mismatch between human purposes and the means available to achieve them: or again, between our desire for happiness and our capacity to encounter or sustain it”</u> (Dienstag, 2006, p. 32). Difference is built upon exanimations of power, which is both fluid and transferable but ultimately permanent. Classical western philosophy has an optimistic pragmatism built into it that posits there must be an answer to our questions. Alternatively, the pessimist embraces uncertainty, ambiguity, and intersubjectivity. Pessimism encourages a sense of comfort around the idea of multiple, coexistent, and perhaps competing histories. Neoliberal optimism is the logic of conflict as materially reconcilable, rather than antagonistically irreconcilable. <u>The fourth and final tenet of pessimism that we are to examine asks what we are to do about our dire human condition.</u> There are multiplicities of rationales that ultimately inform the pessimistic dualism to either resign from life or affirm it entirely. I defer to an existential or Nietzschean pessimism that recognizes suffering is inevitable for two reasons. First, human time-consciousness necessitates an awareness of our impending death. Second, mutually assured value systems will always intersubjectively exist. <u><strong><mark>The choice to affirm life in its entirety is a pessimistic choice</strong></mark>. <strong><mark>Embracing life as</strong></mark> both <strong><mark>miserable and</strong></mark> <strong><mark>beautiful</mark>, fleeting and enduring, validates the perpetually fragmented subject seeking a world that exists beyond good and evil and instead just is. </p></u></strong>
null
Shell
null
361,407
354
150,132
./documents/hsld22/JamesBowie/NiWe1/JamesBowie-NiWe1-Aff-Glenbrooks-Speech-and-Debate-Tournament-Round-5.docx
947,837
A
Glenbrooks Speech and Debate Tournament
5
Harker VL
Bukowsky
1AC – Disability 1NC – TFW, CROB, Util, Case 1AR – All 2NR – TFW, Case 2AR – Case, TFW
hsld22/JamesBowie/NiWe1/JamesBowie-NiWe1-Aff-Glenbrooks-Speech-and-Debate-Tournament-Round-5.docx
2022-11-20 16:41:44
80,486
NiWe1
James Bowie NiWe1
you can contact me here 512-817-9346 [email protected] T - Theory Generics K - Kritiks SO - September/October Resolution ND - November/December Resolution JF - January/Feburary Resolution please notify me if you have any specific triggers before the round and or if there any interns you would want me to meet
Ni.....
We.....
null
null
26,980
JamesBowie
James Bowie
TX
null
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
595,883
Plan: The People’s Republic of China ought to ban lethal autonomous weapons.
Freedberg 19 Should We Ban ‘Killer Robots’? Can We?
Freedberg 19 Sydney J. Freedberg Jr. (deputy editor for Breaking Defense).3/11/2019, Should We Ban ‘Killer Robots’? Can We? https://breakingdefense.com/2019/03/should-we-ban-killer-robots-can-we/
Having said that,” Scharre continued, “I think that the kind of arms control that Stuart Russell is advocating for is actually more feasible.” If someone’s building vast swarms of lethal mini-drones, you don’t have to see the code to know they have to be fully autonomous: There’s no practical way, Scharre told me, for humans to review and approve “a million targets.” The best model is probably the Chemical Weapons Convention, which, unlike many other treaties — the Biological Weapons Convention, the landmine ban, and so on — has a robust enforcement mechanism. chlorine phosgene beyond human understanding But there is also a robust monitoring regime, run by the Organisation to Prevent Chemical Weapons, which has about 250 inspectors who can rapidly respond to reported violations. Such “challenge inspections” are a crucial tool, said Irakli Beridze, a Georgian-born veteran of both OPCW and the UNICRI chem, bio, radiological, & nuclear program — with service in Afghanistan, Iraq, Libya, and Syria — who now runs the Centre for AI & Robotics at UNICRI, the United Nations Interregional Crime and Justice Research Institute Mini-drone production would be easier to hide than chemical plants — for one thing, it doesn’t stink like a lot of toxic chemicals — but investigative techniques have advanced since the CWC entered into force in 1997. It might even be possible, Beridze said, to set an AI to catch an AI: use artificial intelligence to crunch big data — social media or parts orders, for example — and correlate subtle clues no human inspector could catch. Countries need not only to sign the treaty but use their own intelligence agencies and domestic law enforcement to watch for violations. Once compliance became a norm in the chemical industry, in large part because of the moral stigma that attached to chemical weapons, it became much harder to produce poison gas in militarily significant amounts. Given widespread anxiety in the tech community about lethal AI, it should be possible to reach a similar consensus among drone manufacturers — eventually small drones
vast swarms of lethal mini-drones you know they have to be fully autonomous The best model is the Chemical Weapons Convention which has a robust enforcement mechanism there is also a monitoring regime which has inspectors who can rapidly respond to reported violations “challenge inspections” are a crucial tool It might be possible to set an AI to catch an AI: Countries need to use their own intelligence agencies to watch for violations Once compliance became a norm it became harder to produce poison gas Given widespread anxiety in the tech community about lethal AI it should be possible to reach a similar consensus
Having said that,” Scharre continued, “I think that the kind of arms control that Stuart Russell is advocating for is actually more feasible.” If someone’s building vast swarms of lethal mini-drones, you don’t have to see the code to know they have to be fully autonomous: There’s no practical way, Scharre told me, for humans to review and approve “a million targets.” Conversely, such mini-drones are only truly threatening in vast numbers. “A country or an individual… might be able to build a few hundred of these,” Scharre said, “but if you’re going to build millions of them, there’s no way to hide that.” So how would you find them? The best model is probably the Chemical Weapons Convention, which, unlike many other treaties — the Biological Weapons Convention, the landmine ban, and so on — has a robust enforcement mechanism. The scope of the problem is similar. Lethal chemicals like chlorine and phosgene are widely used in legitimate industry, so you can’t ban them outright any more than mini-drones; they’re relatively easy to turn into weapons, again like drones; and yet only rogue states like Syria and Iraq have used them since the end of World War I. Much of the reason militaries abandoned poison gas is that a weapon that blows with the wind is hard to control — yet another similarity with AI, since even “narrow” machine-learning algorithms modify themselves in ways beyond human understanding. But there is also a robust monitoring regime, run by the Organisation to Prevent Chemical Weapons, which has about 250 inspectors who can rapidly respond to reported violations. Such “challenge inspections” are a crucial tool, said Irakli Beridze, a Georgian-born veteran of both OPCW and the UNICRI chem, bio, radiological, & nuclear program — with service in Afghanistan, Iraq, Libya, and Syria — who now runs the Centre for AI & Robotics at UNICRI, the United Nations Interregional Crime and Justice Research Institute. (Beridze emphasized he was only expressing his personal opinion as an expert, not as a UN official). Mini-drone production would be easier to hide than chemical plants — for one thing, it doesn’t stink like a lot of toxic chemicals — but investigative techniques have advanced since the CWC entered into force in 1997. It might even be possible, Beridze said, to set an AI to catch an AI: use artificial intelligence to crunch big data — social media or parts orders, for example — and correlate subtle clues no human inspector could catch. Robust inspections, however, are only one part of the solution, he told me. Countries need not only to sign the treaty but use their own intelligence agencies and domestic law enforcement to watch for violations. And, after initial reluctance in the private sector, “buy-in and participation of the chemical industry… was absolutely essential,” he said. “Otherwise this treaty would not work.” Once compliance became a norm in the chemical industry, in large part because of the moral stigma that attached to chemical weapons, it became much harder to produce poison gas in militarily significant amounts. Given widespread anxiety in the tech community about lethal AI, it should be possible to reach a similar consensus among drone manufacturers — eventually. Getting private industry, law enforcement, and national governments on board, even simply making them aware of the problem, would take years. “We don’t have too much time,” Beridze warned. In a few years, “we will have a widespread technology where criminals can use small drones [for] mass terrorist attacks, assassinations, contract killing, you name it.”
3,602
<h4>Plan: The People’s Republic of China ought to ban lethal autonomous weapons.</h4><p><strong>Freedberg 19</strong> Sydney J. Freedberg Jr. (deputy editor for Breaking Defense).3/11/2019, <u><strong>Should We <mark>Ban ‘Killer Robots’?</mark> Can We?</u></strong> https://breakingdefense.com/2019/03/should-we-ban-killer-robots-can-we/</p><p><u><strong>Having said that,” Scharre continued, “I think that the kind of arms control that Stuart Russell is advocating for is actually more feasible.” If someone’s building <mark>vast swarms of lethal mini-drones</mark>, <mark>you</mark> don’t have to see the code to <mark>know they have to be fully autonomous</mark>: There’s no practical way, Scharre told me, for humans to review and approve “a million targets.” </u></strong>Conversely, such mini-drones are only truly threatening in vast numbers. “A country or an individual… might be able to build a few hundred of these,” Scharre said, “but if you’re going to build millions of them, there’s no way to hide that.” So how would you find them? <u><strong><mark>The best model is</mark> probably <mark>the</mark> <mark>Chemical Weapons Convention</mark>, <mark>which</mark>, unlike many other treaties — the Biological Weapons Convention, the landmine ban, and so on — <mark>has a robust enforcement mechanism</mark>. </u></strong>The scope of the problem is similar. Lethal chemicals like <u>chlorine</u> and <u>phosgene</u> are widely used in legitimate industry, so you can’t ban them outright any more than mini-drones; they’re relatively easy to turn into weapons, again like drones; and yet only rogue states like Syria and Iraq have used them since the end of World War I. Much of the reason militaries abandoned poison gas is that a weapon that blows with the wind is hard to control — yet another similarity with AI, since even “narrow” machine-learning algorithms modify themselves in ways <u>beyond human understanding</u>. <u><strong>But <mark>there is also a </mark>robust <mark>monitoring regime</mark>, run by the Organisation to Prevent Chemical Weapons, <mark>which has</mark> about 250 <mark>inspectors who can rapidly respond to reported violations</mark>. Such <mark>“challenge inspections” are a crucial tool</mark>, said Irakli Beridze, a Georgian-born veteran of both OPCW and the UNICRI chem, bio, radiological, & nuclear program — with service in Afghanistan, Iraq, Libya, and Syria — who now runs the Centre for AI & Robotics at UNICRI, the United Nations Interregional Crime and Justice Research Institute</u></strong>. (Beridze emphasized he was only expressing his personal opinion as an expert, not as a UN official). <u><strong>Mini-drone production would be easier to hide than chemical plants — for one thing, it doesn’t stink like a lot of toxic chemicals — but investigative techniques have advanced since the CWC entered into force in 1997. <mark>It might</mark> even <mark>be possible</mark>, Beridze said, <mark>to set an AI to catch an AI:</mark> use artificial intelligence to crunch big data — social media or parts orders, for example — and correlate subtle clues no human inspector could catch. </u></strong>Robust inspections, however, are only one part of the solution, he told me. <u><strong><mark>Countries need</mark> not only <mark>to</mark> sign the treaty but <mark>use their own intelligence agencies</mark> and domestic law enforcement <mark>to watch for violations</mark>.</u></strong> And, after initial reluctance in the private sector, “buy-in and participation of the chemical industry… was absolutely essential,” he said. “Otherwise this treaty would not work.” <u><strong><mark>Once compliance became a norm</mark> in the chemical industry, in large part because of the moral stigma that attached to chemical weapons, <mark>it became</mark> much <mark>harder to produce poison gas</mark> in militarily significant amounts. <mark>Given widespread anxiety in the tech community about lethal AI</mark>, <mark>it should be possible to reach a similar consensus</mark> among drone manufacturers — eventually</u></strong>. Getting private industry, law enforcement, and national governments on board, even simply making them aware of the problem, would take years. “We don’t have too much time,” Beridze warned. In a few years, “we will have a widespread technology where criminals can use <u>small drones</u> [for] mass terrorist attacks, assassinations, contract killing, you name it.”</p>
1AC – China
1AC
1AC – Plan
5,169
274
10,048
./documents/hsld20/Peninsula/Yu/Peninsula-Yu-Aff-NDCA-Round1.docx
870,768
A
NDCA
1
Harker RM
Long, Annabelle
1ac arms race adv navy adv 1nc T plural Sea Iguana PIC Nigeria CP CCP instability DA 2nr Nigeria CP LAWs ban cause preemptive strike CT
hsld20/Peninsula/Yu/Peninsula-Yu-Aff-NDCA-Round1.docx
null
73,635
StYu
Peninsula StYu
null
St.....
Yu.....
null
null
24,672
Peninsula
Peninsula
CA
null
1,028
hsld20
HS LD 2020-21
2,020
ld
hs
1
1,740,939
Arms racing causes miscalc.
Wolfsthal 18
Wolfsthal 18—(Director of the Nuclear Crisis Group and Senior Advisor to Global Zero, former senior director for arms control and nonproliferation at the National Security Council). Jon Wolfsthal. 1/17/18. “America and Russia May Find Themselves in a Nuclear Arms Race Once Again.” https://nationalinterest.org/feature/america-russia-may-find-themselves-nuclear-arms-race-once-24100?page=0%2C1
Threats to the INF are only the tip of the iceberg . Russia is rebuilding much of the Soviet Union’s strategic nuclear arsenal intercontinental-range ballistic missiles and a new fleet of missile-armed submarines. The United States is in a trillion-dollar plus modernization program of its own . This arms competition fuel a new dangerous dynamic that could threaten security of Russia and the United States . Russia and America may be locked into a cycle of “arms race instability.” As each deploys new systems, they perceive the worst in the military capabilities and intentions of the other . The result is an action-reaction cycle of new nuclear deployments. leaving them both vulnerable to nuclear use by accident or through miscalculation. Russia and the United States are undermining “crisis stability” . deployment of short flight-time missiles squeezed time the Kremlin or White House had to make prudent decisions in a crisis. thirty years of stability in Europe is now at risk. a new generation of INF missiles risk recreating the same dangers .
arms competition fuel a Russia America cycle of “ instability.” As each deploys new systems, they perceive the worst in intentions of the other . result is an action-reaction cycle leaving both vulnerable to accident or miscalc . short flight-time missiles squeezed time the Kremlin or White House had to make decisions in a crisis years of stability is now at risk. new missiles recreat the same dangers
Threats to the survival of the INF Treaty are only the tip of the iceberg, however. Russia is now in the process of rebuilding much of the Soviet Union’s strategic nuclear arsenal, including mobile, intercontinental-range ballistic missiles and a new fleet of missile-armed submarines. The United States is in an early stage of a trillion-dollar plus modernization program of its own, including new submarine and land-based missiles and a new stealth bomber armed with a new stealthy, long-range cruise missile. The NPR endorses the Obama program of modernization, and even hints that this program may be increased even beyond the call for new submarine launched warheads and SLCMs. This ongoing arms competition is fueling a new dangerous dynamic that could threaten the security of Russia and the United States in two important ways. The first threat is that Russia and America may soon be locked into what analysts call a cycle of “arms race instability.” As each side deploys new systems, they both perceive the worst in the military capabilities and intentions of the other and each seeks, through additional deployments, to restore the overall balance. The result is an action-reaction cycle of new nuclear deployments. Exhibit A is that Russia’s pursuit of an illegal new ground-launched cruise missile is now driving the United States to consider a new SLCM in response. It was a similar dynamic from the 1960s through the 1980s that led the two sides to deploy tens of thousands of nuclear weapons, leaving them both vulnerable to the ever-present threats of nuclear use by accident or through miscalculation. The second threat, however, is even more dangerous. Russia and the United States are increasingly undermining “crisis stability” as they pursue nuclear modernization. The INF Treaty was negotiated because neither Ronald Reagan nor Mikhail Gorbachev felt secure, in the midst of a deep Soviet-American crisis, in having less than ten minutes to decide whether or not unleash their huge nuclear arsenals. But the deployment of short flight-time INF missiles in range of Moscow and major European capitals significantly squeezed the time that the Kremlin or the White House had to make prudent decisions in a crisis. But the thirty years of stability in Europe purchased by the INF Treaty is now at risk. Russia’s apparent decision to deploy a new generation of INF missiles, together with the NPR’s call to consider new nuclear-armed sea-launched cruise missiles and Congressional funding of a ground launched variant that would also be contrary to the Treaty’s terms, all risk recreating the same dangers that made the INF Treaty necessary in the first place. This, combined with America’s increasingly capable missile-defense capabilities in Europe, Asia and at home, have led a growing number of Russians to believe that the United States may soon have a clear nuclear advantage that leaves Moscow vulnerable to nuclear-first strike.
2,953
<h4>Arms racing causes <u>miscalc</u>.</h4><p><u><strong>Wolfsthal 18</u></strong>—(Director of the Nuclear Crisis Group and Senior Advisor to Global Zero, former senior director for arms control and nonproliferation at the National Security Council). Jon Wolfsthal. 1/17/18. “America and Russia May Find Themselves in a Nuclear Arms Race Once Again.” <u>https://nationalinterest.org/feature/america-russia-may-find-themselves-nuclear-arms-race-once-24100?page=0%2C1</p><p><strong>Threats to the</u></strong> survival of the <u><strong>INF</u></strong> Treaty <u><strong>are only the tip of the iceberg</u></strong>, however<u><strong>. Russia is</u></strong> now in the process of <u><strong>rebuilding much of the Soviet Union’s strategic nuclear arsenal</u></strong>, including mobile, <u><strong>intercontinental-range ballistic missiles and a new fleet of missile-armed submarines. The United States is in a</u></strong>n early stage of a <u><strong>trillion-dollar plus modernization program of its own</u></strong>, including new submarine and land-based missiles and a new stealth bomber armed with a new stealthy, long-range cruise missile<u><strong>. </u></strong>The NPR endorses the Obama program of modernization, and even hints that this program may be increased even beyond the call for new submarine launched warheads and SLCMs. <u><strong>This </u></strong>ongoing<u><strong> <mark>arms competition </u></strong></mark>is<u><strong><mark> fuel</u></strong></mark>ing <u><strong><mark>a </mark>new dangerous dynamic that could threaten </u></strong>the<u><strong> security of Russia and the United States </u></strong>in two important ways<u><strong>. </u></strong>The first threat is that<u><strong> <mark>Russia </mark>and <mark>America </mark>may </u></strong>soon<u><strong> be locked into </u></strong>what analysts call<u><strong> a <mark>cycle of “</mark>arms race <mark>instability.” As each </u></strong></mark>side<u><strong><mark> deploys new systems, they</u></strong></mark> both <u><strong><mark>perceive the worst in</mark> the military capabilities and <mark>intentions of the other</u></strong></mark> and each seeks, through additional deployments, to restore the overall balance<u><strong><mark>. </mark>The <mark>result is an action-reaction cycle</mark> of new nuclear deployments.</u></strong> Exhibit A is that Russia’s pursuit of an illegal new ground-launched cruise missile is now driving the United States to consider a new SLCM in response. It was a similar dynamic from the 1960s through the 1980s that led the two sides to deploy tens of thousands of nuclear weapons, <u><strong><mark>leaving</mark> them <mark>both vulnerable to</mark> </u></strong>the ever-present threats of<u><strong> nuclear use by <mark>accident or</mark> through <mark>miscalc</mark>ulation<mark>.</mark> </u></strong>The second threat, however, is even more dangerous. <u><strong>Russia and the United States are</u></strong> increasingly <u><strong>undermining “crisis stability”</u></strong> as they pursue nuclear modernization<u><strong>.</u></strong> The INF Treaty was negotiated because neither Ronald Reagan nor Mikhail Gorbachev felt secure, in the midst of a deep Soviet-American crisis, in having less than ten minutes to decide whether or not unleash their huge nuclear arsenals. But the <u><strong>deployment of <mark>short flight-time</u></strong></mark> INF <u><strong><mark>missiles</u></strong></mark> in range of Moscow and major European capitals significantly <u><strong><mark>squeezed</u></strong></mark> the <u><strong><mark>time </u></strong></mark>that<u><strong><mark> the Kremlin or </u></strong></mark>the<u><strong><mark> White House had to make </mark>prudent <mark>decisions in a crisis</mark>.</u></strong> But the <u><strong>thirty <mark>years of stability</mark> in Europe</u></strong> purchased by the INF Treaty <u><strong><mark>is now at risk.</mark> </u></strong>Russia’s apparent decision to deploy <u><strong>a <mark>new</mark> generation of INF <mark>missiles</u></strong></mark>, together with the NPR’s call to consider new nuclear-armed sea-launched cruise missiles and Congressional funding of a ground launched variant that would also be contrary to the Treaty’s terms, all <u><strong>risk <mark>recreat</mark>ing <mark>the same dangers</mark> </u></strong>that made the INF Treaty necessary in the first place<u><strong>.</u></strong> This, combined with America’s increasingly capable missile-defense capabilities in Europe, Asia and at home, have led a growing number of Russians to believe that the United States may soon have a clear nuclear advantage that leaves Moscow vulnerable to nuclear-first strike.</p>
1AC
Ukraine/Georgia: 1AC—1.1
AC: 1AC
122,479
327
51,528
./documents/ndtceda20/Minnesota/FeRa/Minnesota-Ferguson-Rao-Aff-Wake%20Forest-Round3.docx
620,201
A
Wake Forest
3
George Mason DH
Brandon Kelley
1AC - GU Exp Ukr AC Elites 1NC - NAC CP T Daska Liberal Subject K Adv CP Det on case Block- NAC CP T Det on case 2NR - NAC CP
ndtceda20/Minnesota/FeRa/Minnesota-Ferguson-Rao-Aff-Wake%20Forest-Round3.docx
null
52,396
FeRa
Minnesota FeRa
null
Jo.....
Fe.....
Br.....
Ra.....
19,336
Minnesota
Minnesota
null
null
1,010
ndtceda20
NDT/CEDA 2020-21
2,020
cx
college
2
1,975,756
It’s a highly probable existential threat from direct effects and multiplying related risk of conflict---global tipping points are possible
Torres 16
Phil Torres 16, Affiliate Scholar at the Institute for Ethics and Emerging Technologies, Founder of the X-Risks Institute, Writer Appearing in Skeptic, Free Inquiry, Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists, Salon, Truthout, Erkenntnis, Metaphilosophy, “Biodiversity Loss: An Existential Risk Comparable To Climate Change”, Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists, 4/11/2016, https://thebulletin.org/2016/04/biodiversity-loss-an-existential-risk-comparable-to-climate-change/
The consequences of rapid pruning of the evolutionary tree of life extend beyond the obvious localized ecosystems can undergo abrupt and irreversible shifts when they reach a tipping point we may be approaching a tipping point in the global ecosystem, beyond which the consequences could be catastrophic for civilization a planetary-scale transition could precipitate “substantial losses of ecosystem services required to sustain the human population.” the results could be “widespread social unrest, economic instability, and loss of human life.” Biodiversity loss is a “threat multiplier” that, by pushing societies to the brink of collapse, will exacerbate existing conflicts and introduce entirely new struggles between state and non-state actors. Indeed, it could even fuel the rise of terrorism biodiversity loss constitutes an existential threat it ought to be considered alongside nuclear weapons as one of the most significant contemporary risks to human prosperity and survival
ecosystems can undergo abrupt irreversible shifts we may approach a tipping point in global ecosystem catastrophic for civilization results could be unrest, economic instability, and loss of life Biod loss is a “threat multiplier” pushing societies to collapse, will exacerbate conflicts and fuel terrorism biod constitutes an existential threat along nuc s as one significant risks to human survival
Catastrophic consequences for civilization. The consequences of this rapid pruning of the evolutionary tree of life extend beyond the obvious. There could be surprising effects of biodiversity loss that scientists are unable to fully anticipate in advance. For example, prior research has shown that localized ecosystems can undergo abrupt and irreversible shifts when they reach a tipping point. According to a 2012 paper published in Nature, there are reasons for thinking that we may be approaching a tipping point of this sort in the global ecosystem, beyond which the consequences could be catastrophic for civilization. As the authors write, a planetary-scale transition could precipitate “substantial losses of ecosystem services required to sustain the human population.” An ecosystem service is any ecological process that benefits humanity, such as food production and crop pollination. If the global ecosystem were to cross a tipping point and substantial ecosystem services were lost, the results could be “widespread social unrest, economic instability, and loss of human life.” According to Missouri Botanical Garden ecologist Adam Smith, one of the paper’s co-authors, this could occur in a matter of decades—far more quickly than most of the expected consequences of climate change, yet equally destructive. Biodiversity loss is a “threat multiplier” that, by pushing societies to the brink of collapse, will exacerbate existing conflicts and introduce entirely new struggles between state and non-state actors. Indeed, it could even fuel the rise of terrorism. (After all, climate change has been linked to the emergence of ISIS in Syria, and multiple high-ranking US officials, such as former US Defense Secretary Chuck Hagel and CIA director John Brennan, have affirmed that climate change and terrorism are connected.) The reality is that we are entering the sixth mass extinction in the 3.8-billion-year history of life on Earth, and the impact of this event could be felt by civilization “in as little as three human lifetimes,” as the aforementioned 2012 Nature paper notes. Furthermore, the widespread decline of biological populations could plausibly initiate a dramatic transformation of the global ecosystem on an even faster timescale: perhaps a single human lifetime. The unavoidable conclusion is that biodiversity loss constitutes an existential threat in its own right. As such, it ought to be considered alongside climate change and nuclear weapons as one of the most significant contemporary risks to human prosperity and survival.
2,565
<h4>It’s a <u>highly probable</u> existential threat from <u>direct</u> effects and <u>multiplying</u> related risk of conflict---<u>global</u> tipping points are possible</h4><p>Phil <strong>Torres 16</strong>, Affiliate Scholar at the Institute for Ethics and Emerging Technologies, Founder of the X-Risks Institute, Writer Appearing in Skeptic, Free Inquiry, Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists, Salon, Truthout, Erkenntnis, Metaphilosophy, “Biodiversity Loss: An Existential Risk Comparable To Climate Change”, Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists, 4/11/2016, https://thebulletin.org/2016/04/biodiversity-loss-an-existential-risk-comparable-to-climate-change/</p><p>Catastrophic consequences for civilization. <u>The consequences of</u> this <u>rapid pruning of the evolutionary tree of life extend beyond the obvious</u>. There could be surprising effects of biodiversity loss that scientists are unable to fully anticipate in advance. For example, prior research has shown that <u>localized <mark>ecosystems can undergo <strong>abrupt</strong></mark> and <strong><mark>irreversible</strong> shifts</mark> when they reach a <strong>tipping point</u></strong>. According to a 2012 paper published in Nature, there are reasons for thinking that <u><mark>we may</mark> be <strong><mark>approach</strong></mark>ing <mark>a <strong>tipping point</u></strong></mark> of this sort <u><mark>in</mark> the <strong><mark>global</strong> ecosystem</mark>, beyond which the consequences could be <strong><mark>catastrophic for civilization</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>As the authors write, <u>a <strong>planetary-scale transition</strong> could precipitate “<strong>substantial losses</strong> of ecosystem services <strong>required to sustain the human population</strong>.”</u> An ecosystem service is any ecological process that benefits humanity, such as food production and crop pollination. If the global ecosystem were to cross a tipping point and substantial ecosystem services were lost, <u>the <mark>results could be</mark> “<strong>widespread social <mark>unrest</strong>, <strong>economic instability</strong>, and <strong>loss of</mark> human <mark>life</strong></mark>.”</u> According to Missouri Botanical Garden ecologist Adam Smith, one of the paper’s co-authors, this could occur in a matter of decades—far more quickly than most of the expected consequences of climate change, yet equally destructive.</p><p><u><strong><mark>Biod</strong></mark>iversity <mark>loss is a <strong>“threat multiplier”</strong></mark> that, by <mark>pushing societies to</mark> the brink of <mark>collapse, will <strong>exacerbate</mark> existing <mark>conflicts</strong> and</mark> introduce entirely new struggles between state and non-state actors. Indeed, it could even <mark>fuel</mark> the rise of <strong><mark>terrorism</u></strong></mark>. (After all, climate change has been linked to the emergence of ISIS in Syria, and multiple high-ranking US officials, such as former US Defense Secretary Chuck Hagel and CIA director John Brennan, have affirmed that climate change and terrorism are connected.)</p><p>The reality is that we are entering the sixth mass extinction in the 3.8-billion-year history of life on Earth, and the impact of this event could be felt by civilization “in as little as three human lifetimes,” as the aforementioned 2012 Nature paper notes. Furthermore, the widespread decline of biological populations could plausibly initiate a dramatic transformation of the global ecosystem on an even faster timescale: perhaps a single human lifetime.</p><p>The unavoidable conclusion is that <u><strong><mark>biod</strong></mark>iversity loss <mark>constitutes an <strong>existential threat</u></strong></mark> in its own right. As such, <u>it ought to be considered <strong><mark>along</strong></mark>side</u> climate change and <u><strong><mark>nuc</strong></mark>lear weapon<strong><mark>s</strong> as one</mark> of the <strong>most <mark>significant</mark> contemporary <mark>risks</strong> to <strong>human</mark> prosperity and <mark>survival</u></strong></mark>.</p>
1NR
Federalism DA
1NC---Case
4,040
1,876
58,230
./documents/hspolicy20/MontgomeryBell/MePa/Montgomery%20Bell-Meacham-Pacconi-Neg-New%20Trier-Octas.docx
735,173
N
New Trier
Octas
Chaminade AH
Jake Lee, Aasiyah Bhaiji, Brian Box
1AC - Habeas Corpus 1NC - T Enact Litigation PIC Federal Prisons CP Neolib K Court Clog DA Federalism DA 2NR - Federalism DA
hspolicy20/MontgomeryBell/MePa/Montgomery%20Bell-Meacham-Pacconi-Neg-New%20Trier-Octas.docx
null
62,696
MePa
Montgomery Bell MePa
null
Sa.....
Me.....
Ja.....
Pa.....
21,723
MontgomeryBell
Montgomery Bell
TN
null
1,019
hspolicy20
HS Policy 2020-21
2,020
cx
hs
2
4,553,010
Behold the image of the disgusting disabled child, which causes one to wince in the face of egoistic empathy. This is self-reflection, a process constitutive of the psyche that results in the disability drive, the culmination of primary pity where the non-disabled subject embodies itself in the position of the disabled object, and secondary pity, which portrays the ego’s overcompensation to regain its position and pushes a desire from lack for the eradication of disability.
Mollow 15
Mollow 15 Anna (2015): The Disability Drive, A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in English in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Professor Kent Puckett, Chair Professor Celeste G. Langan Professor Melinda Y. Chen Spring 2015 https://digitalassets.lib.berkeley.edu/etd/ucb/text/Mollow_berkeley_0028E_15181.pdf SJCP//JG
“Piss on pity,” declares a well-known disability activist bumper sticker a field that since its inception has vigorously resisted the imposition of pity upon disabled people, Tiny Tim is anathema Tiny Tim is used to drum up pity for disabled people; the widespread circulation of this affect, disability scholars have compellingly argued, does not alleviate the social barriers that we face but instead reinforces our oppression “No one wants to be pitied,” if nobody wants to be pitied, who, if anyone, wants to feel pity? At first glance, the answer to the latter question might seem to be “everyone.” If it can be fun to perform pity, perhaps this is because pity gives a boost to the ego of the pitying person. “You are broken, and I am whole,” the pitier says to the one who is pitied. “I look down on you because you suffer.” Naturally, disabled people resist performing this service for the nondisabled. “Spare us your pity,” we say, because pity is felt to be demeaning. 73 Yet an incoherence structures this familiar account of pity: if pity fortifies the ego of the subject who feels it, then why do people so often resist feeling pity? “I have no pity for you.” This is the attitude that Scrooge takes toward Tiny Tim Edelman argues that compassion (which, of course, is a close relative of pity) is fundamentally narcissistic When we call ourselves compassionate, we think we’re feeling for the other; but, Edelman contends, we’re really only feeling for ourselves (83). That is, compassion involves projecting one’s own ego onto the object of one’s compassion. In this schema, the pitied person is used as a vehicle for the pitier to feel sorry for his or her own self. But in calling compassion a cover for narcissism, Edelman may inadvertently point to a connection between compassion and the drive. suggests that although some forms of narcissism can bolster the ego, other forms can do just the opposite. “primary” and “secondary” narcissism provides the basis for a contrast that I wish to draw between what could be called primary and secondary pity the image of a child at its mother’s breast. “primary narcissism” to the perfect autoerotic pleasure in which the child luxuriates. This pleasure takes place in the absence of a stable self, as the child does not yet conceive of itself as a distinct entity, undifferentiated from its external environment It’s the best of times, but it can’t last But still, we keep seeking that lost, best time: because humans are “incapable of giving up a satisfaction” that we have “once enjoyed,” we continually try to return to the primary narcissism of childhood. We do this by engaging in secondary narcissism familiar attitudes and behaviors that one tends to think of when one disparages someone as “narcissistic” fall into the category of what Freud defined as secondary narcissism: the puffed up ego, the feeling of superiority over others. But even secondary narcissism, with its many patent problems, does not only aim to aggrandize the ego secondary narcissism, after all, is to return to a state in which the ego as such does not exist autoerotic enjoyment at its mother’s breast is pleasurable in part because the child is not yet a subject. As with the death drive’s impulsion to return to “an earlier state of things,” secondary narcissism draws the subject back toward a prior time when the ego did not exist To be drawn back to primary narcissism would be to imagine the abolition of one’s self. For this reason, even though secondary narcissism may threaten to break down the ego, it also entails a defense against the threat/pleasure of that breaking down To be clear, pity and narcissism are not the same thing: if narcissism can be understood as love of the self, pity involves a complex affective reaction to the suffering of someone else. Primary pity entails a response to the image of another person succumbing to what I have termed the “tragedy of disability.” Primary pity arises when one witnesses a fall of the self, a collapse of the ego; such falling is at once painful and pleasurable to observe. In other words, primary pity could be described as a vicarious experience of the tragedy of disability. A great deal of the pain and pleasure of primary pity center on questions about what, or who, this fallen self is we purport to “feel for the other.” primary pity entails a mixing up of self and other such that the ego, in becoming permeable to pain that may properly belong to “someone else,” is profoundly threatened in its integrity This affective response can feel unbearable, as seen in Siebers’s formulation: one “cannot bear to look…but also cannot bear not to look.” Primary pity is difficult to bear because it involves a drive toward disability (one cannot bear not to look), which menaces the ego’s investments in health, pleasure, and control—because to contemplate another person’s suffering is to confront the question, “Could this happen to me?” Secondary pity is something else, although it cannot wholly be differentiated from primary pity. Secondary pity attempts to heal primary pity’s self-rupturing effects by converting primary pity into a feeling that is bearable. As with secondary narcissism, secondary pity involves both an attempt to get back to that ego-shattering state of painfully pleasurable primary pity, and at the same time to defend against that threat to the ego by aggrandizing oneself at someone else’s expense. Secondary pity refers to all those ego-bolstering behaviors that most people think of when they talk about pity “conspicuous contribution,” the insistence that “they” (i.e., nondisabled people) could never endure such suffering. More commonly known in our culture simply as “pity,” secondary pity encompasses our culture’s most clichéd reactions to disability: charity, tears, and calls for a cure. obligatory claims that disabled people’s suffering is “inspiring secondary pity, as a defense against primary pity’s incursions, reinforces the ego’s fantasy of sovereignty. Secondary pity, in other words, can be seen as a variation of secondary narcissism: these affects enlarge the ego of the pitier or the narcissist at the expense of someone else the temporal shift from primary to secondary pity happens much more quickly than this. It happens in an instant: that moment in which we feel primary pity and then, almost before we can blink, deny that we feel or have felt it. The denial is understandable: who wants to admit that one gets pleasure from the sight of another person’s suffering—or, to make matters worse, that this pleasure derives in part from the specter of disability’s transferability, the possibility that this suffering could be—and, fantasmatically, perhaps already is—an image of one‟s own self undone the tale that Freud tells about masochism takes much the same form. In this story, subject loves object; subject loses object; and subject tries to get object back by becoming object, that is, by identifying with the object in such a way that object starts to seem—and perhaps in some ways is—part of subject’s self. This last phase is a dysfunctional and disabling form of identification, Freud makes clear. Subject is still angry at object for having left it, and it takes out that anger on the object that is now part of itself. This is the reason that people suffering from melancholia are so hard on themselves, If sadism and masochism are ultimately indistinguishable obverses of each other, then pity, in both its primary and its secondary forms, would have to be both sadistic and masochistic. Indeed, primary pity is so unsettling that our culture has been driven to “mercifully” kill people in the name of secondary pity. We have also been driven to lock people in institutions, to let them languish on the streets, to stare, to punish, and to sentimentalize—all, I would suggest, in the interest of not owning, not naming, not acknowledging that self-shattering, ego-dissolving, instantaneous and intolerable moment of primary pity. Because primary pity is tied up with the disability drive, it must, like the drive itself, be regarded as unrepresentable. Guest’s account of a nonconsensual administration of an unwanted medical treatment is especially difficult to bear because it gives the reader no recourse to secondary pity: the passage offers no “lesson” to be learned, no invitation to feel “inspired,” nothing to make one feel in any way okay about what has happened. The medical violence that Guest recounts seems particularly devastating because it is readable as sexual: it takes the form of forced penetration, and it results in a “feeling of powerlessness, of violation”
pity gives a boost to the ego of the pitying person You are broken, and I am whole fortifies the ego of the subject involves projecting one’s own ego onto the object of one’s compassion some narcissism can bolster the ego other the opposite Primary pity arises when one witnesses a fall of the self at once painful and pleasurable to observe we feel for the other one cannot bear to look but also not to look Primary pity involves a drive toward disability menaces ego’s investments contemplate Could this happen to me Secondary pity attempts to heal primary pity’s effects by converting primary to bearable involves both an attempt to get back to ego-shattering state of pleasurable primary pity and defend against that threat someone else’s expense primary pity is so unsettling our culture mercifully” kill people in secondary interest of ego-dissolving pity medical violence results in violation
A Tale of Two Pities “Piss on pity,” declares a well-known disability activist bumper sticker. A more polite companion to this tag, the slogan “No pity” is a rallying cry of the disability rights movement.119 For disability studies, a field that since its inception has vigorously resisted the imposition of pity upon disabled people, Tiny Tim is anathema. Understandably so: every year, the image of Tiny Tim is used to drum up pity for disabled people; the widespread circulation of this affect, disability scholars have compellingly argued, does not alleviate the social barriers that we face but instead reinforces our oppression. Indispensable as this disability studies analysis is, it leaves some important questions about pity unanswered. For example: if, as is commonly said, “No one wants to be pitied,” then why is this so? And also, if nobody wants to be pitied, who, if anyone, wants to feel pity? At first glance, the answer to the latter question might seem to be “everyone.” Certainly, multitudes of moviegoers appear to enjoy our culture’s annual recitations of Tiny Tim’s pity inducing tale. If it can be fun to perform pity, perhaps this is because pity gives a boost to the ego of the pitying person. “You are broken, and I am whole,” the pitier says to the one who is pitied. “I look down on you because you suffer.” Naturally, disabled people resist performing this service for the nondisabled. “Spare us your pity,” we say, because pity is felt to be demeaning. 73 Yet an incoherence structures this familiar account of pity: if pity fortifies the ego of the subject who feels it, then why do people so often resist feeling pity? Some folks get pissed when they are prodded to pity. “Your appeals to pity won’t work,” they say. “I have no pity for you.” This is the attitude that Scrooge takes toward Tiny Tim. It’s also the stance that Edelman invites queers to take in relation to the Child—and not only to the Child per se, but also to anyone who calls for a performance of pity. Edelman argues that compassion (which, of course, is a close relative of pity) is fundamentally narcissistic (73). When we call ourselves compassionate, we think we’re feeling for the other; but, Edelman contends, we’re really only feeling for ourselves (83). That is, compassion involves projecting one’s own ego onto the object of one’s compassion. In this schema, the pitied person is used as a vehicle for the pitier to feel sorry for his or her own self. But in calling compassion a cover for narcissism, Edelman may inadvertently point to a connection between compassion and the drive. Freud’s theorization of narcissism, which is a precursor to his idea of the death drive, suggests that although some forms of narcissism can bolster the ego, other forms can do just the opposite. “On Narcissism” posits a distinction between what Freud calls “primary” and “secondary” narcissism; this distinction provides the basis for a contrast that I wish to draw between what could be called primary and secondary pity. To elucidate these two pities, let us look at the tale that Freud tells about two narcissisms. The story begins, as many Freudian narratives do, with the image of a child at its mother’s breast. Freud gives the name “primary narcissism” to the perfect autoerotic pleasure in which the child luxuriates. This pleasure takes place in the absence of a stable self, as the child does not yet conceive of itself as a distinct entity, undifferentiated from its external environment (87-88). It’s the best of times, but it can’t last: the child’s primary narcissism, Freud recounts, is exposed to numerous “disturbances,” ranging from the castration complex (in which boys fear losing the penis and girls, Freud assumes, wish that they had one) to parental discipline and criticism.120 But still, we keep seeking that lost, best time: because humans are “incapable of giving up a satisfaction” that we have “once enjoyed,” we continually try to return to the primary narcissism of childhood. We do this by engaging in secondary narcissism. All the familiar attitudes and behaviors that one tends to think of when one disparages someone as “narcissistic” fall into the category of what Freud defined as secondary narcissism: the puffed up ego, the feeling of superiority over others. But even secondary narcissism, with its many patent problems, does not only aim to aggrandize the ego. The impetus of secondary narcissism, after all, is to return to a state in which the ego as such does not exist. The child’s autoerotic enjoyment at its mother’s breast is pleasurable in part because the child is not yet a subject. As with the death drive’s impulsion to return to “an earlier state of things,” secondary narcissism draws the subject back toward a prior time when the ego did not exist (Beyond 45). Yet if primary narcissism is looked back upon as the best of times, it must, from the vantage point of a fully constituted ego, appear as the worst of times, too. To be drawn back to primary narcissism would be to imagine the abolition of one’s self. For this reason, even though secondary narcissism may threaten to break down the ego, it also entails a defense against the threat/pleasure of that breaking down. Much as the differentiation between the inseparable processes of primary and secondary narcissism rests on a distinction between building up and breaking down the ego, a similar heuristic distinction gives structure to my concepts of primary and secondary pity. To be clear, pity and narcissism are not the same thing: if narcissism can be understood as love of the self, pity involves a complex affective reaction to the suffering of someone else. Primary pity entails a response to the image of another person succumbing to what I have termed the “tragedy of disability.”121 Primary pity arises when one witnesses a fall of the self, a collapse of the ego; such falling is at once painful and pleasurable to observe. In other words, primary pity could be described as a vicarious experience of the tragedy of disability. A great deal of the pain and pleasure of primary pity center on questions about what, or who, this fallen self is. When most people think about pity, we refer to an affect in which, to adopt Edelman’s phrase, we purport to “feel for the other.” But as with primary narcissism, in which the self has not yet been constituted, and therefore cannot be said to enter into intersubjective relations with an “other,” primary pity entails a mixing up of self and other such that the ego, in becoming permeable to pain that may properly belong to “someone else,” is profoundly threatened in its integrity. Primary pity is that intense pain-pleasure complex that is provoked by the image of a suffering other who, it seems momentarily, both is and is not one’s self. This affective response can feel unbearable, as seen in Siebers’s formulation: one “cannot bear to look…but also cannot bear not to look.” Primary pity is difficult to bear because it involves a drive toward disability (one cannot bear not to look), which menaces the ego’s investments in health, pleasure, and control—because to contemplate another person’s suffering is to confront the question, “Could this happen to me?” Such a prospect, although frightening, may also be compelling; in this way, primary pity replicates the self-rupturing aspects of sexuality. Indeed, the unbearability of primary pity reflects its coextensiveness with sexuality. Sex, or the Unbearable, a book coauthored by Edelman and by Lauren Berlant, argues that sex “unleashes unbearable contradictions that we nonetheless struggle to bear” (back cover). This claim accords with Freud’s account of sexuality as a “pleasurable” “unpleasure” that the ego can never fully master or control (Three 49,75). As Leo Bersani puts it in his reading of Freud, “the pleasurable unpleasurable tension of sexual enjoyment occurs when the body’s „normal‟ range of sensation is exceeded, and when the organization of the self is momentarily disturbed”; thus, “sexuality would be that which is intolerable to the structured self” (Freudian 38). Primary pity is also intolerable to the structured self, because it entails a fascination with the fantasy of a self in a state of disintegration or disablement. Secondary pity is something else, although it cannot wholly be differentiated from primary pity. Secondary pity attempts to heal primary pity’s self-rupturing effects by converting primary pity into a feeling that is bearable. As with secondary narcissism, secondary pity involves both an attempt to get back to that ego-shattering state of painfully pleasurable primary pity, and at the same time to defend against that threat to the ego by aggrandizing oneself at someone else’s expense. Secondary pity refers to all those ego-bolstering behaviors that most people think of when they talk about pity. Disabled people are all too familiar with these behaviors: the saccharin sympathy, the telethon rituals of “conspicuous contribution,” the insistence that “they” (i.e., nondisabled people) could never endure such suffering. More commonly known in our culture simply as “pity,” secondary pity encompasses our culture’s most clichéd reactions to disability: charity, tears, and calls for a cure. Correlatives of these commonplace manifestations of secondary pity are the obligatory claims that disabled people’s suffering is “inspiring.” Indeed, the speed with which conventional cultural representations of disability segue from overt expressions of pity to celebrations of “the triumph of the human spirit” highlights the ways in which secondary pity, as a defense against primary pity’s incursions, reinforces the ego’s fantasy of sovereignty. Secondary pity, in other words, can be seen as a variation of secondary narcissism: these affects enlarge the ego of the pitier or the narcissist at the expense of someone else. But primary pity is not the same as either primary narcissism, secondary narcissism, or secondary pity. Unlike primary narcissism, a feeling that emerges out of a relation to the world in which notions of “self” and “other” do not obtain, primary pity does depend upon the constructs of self and other, although these constructions are unstable and are continually threatening to come undone. Primary pity can thus be envisioned as a threshold category occupying a liminal position between the total denial of the other that is inherent to primary narcissism and the rigid structure of (superior) self and (inferior) other that constitutes secondary narcissism and secondary pity. My concept of primary versus secondary pity also differs from Freud’s primarysecondary narcissism distinction at the level of genealogy. Like Freud’s account of primary and secondary narcissisms, my model of primary and secondary pities involves a temporal transition; but whereas Freud imagines the movement from primary to secondary narcissism as a passage from an earlier to a later stage of an individual’s development, the temporal shift from primary to secondary pity happens much more quickly than this. It happens in an instant: that moment in which we feel primary pity and then, almost before we can blink, deny that we feel or have felt it. The denial is understandable: who wants to admit that one gets pleasure from the sight of another person’s suffering—or, to make matters worse, that this pleasure derives in part from the specter of disability’s transferability, the possibility that this suffering could be—and, fantasmatically, perhaps already is—an image of one‟s own self undone? Indeed, the model of primary pity that I have been constructing may sound a bit too close to sadism for some people’s liking. Pity does come close to sadism, and at the same time, to masochism, which Freud theorizes as sadism’s obverse. In “Mourning and Melancholia,” an essay that can be read as a sequel to “On Narcissism,” Freud approaches a distinction between primary and secondary masochism, which accords with my primary-secondary pity heuristic.122 If the story that I traced in “On Narcissism” could be summarized as “child gets breast; child loses breast; child gets breast back, albeit in a secondary, adulterated form,” the tale that Freud tells about masochism takes much the same form. In this story, subject loves object; subject loses object; and subject tries to get object back by becoming object, that is, by identifying with the object in such a way that object starts to seem—and perhaps in some ways is—part of subject’s self. This last phase is a dysfunctional and disabling form of identification, Freud makes clear. Subject is still angry at object for having left it, and it takes out that anger on the object that is now part of itself. This is the reason that people suffering from melancholia are so hard on themselves, Freud says; the “diminution in…self-regard” that typically accompanies melancholia results from the subject’s attacks on the loved-and-lost object that the subject has incorporated into its ego (“Mourning” 246). Freud had not wanted there to be such a thing as primary masochism; for a long time, he had insisted that sadism, or “aggression,” was the primary instinct, and that masochism was only a turning-inward of this originary aggression. But in “Mourning and Melancholia,” although Freud does not yet use the term “primary masochism,” he nonetheless gets at this concept. The problem of suicide, Freud notes in this essay, raises the possibility that the ego “can treat itself as an object” that it wants to destroy (252). When it comes to such an extreme act as suicide, the possibility of carrying “such a purpose through to execution” must, Freud surmises, involve more than a sadistic wish to punish others. Perhaps, then, there is an innate desire to destroy one’s own self, Freud hypothesizes. If so, this self would not be a single thing: it would be “me” and at the same time, the lost object whose image “I” have internalized. Freud’s notion of a primary masochism is tied very closely to his conceptualization of the drive. Beyond the Pleasure Principle, the text in which Freud first used the term “death drive,” was published three years after “Mourning and Melancholia.” In the later text, Freud’s speculations about the death drive lead him to acknowledge that “there might be such a thing as primary masochism” (66). After all, Freud points out, the idea that either sadism or masochism definitively takes precedence over the other does not ultimately make much sense, as “there is no difference in principle between an instinct turning from the object to the ego and its turning from the ego to an object” (66). If sadism and masochism are ultimately indistinguishable obverses of each other, then pity, in both its primary and its secondary forms, would have to be both sadistic and masochistic. This is a deeply troubling possibility, but I suggest that trying to overcome pity will only make matters worse. There are many ways of trying to overcome primary pity, and each one ultimately aggravates the violence of primary pity. One way is the “pitiless” refusal of compassion that Edelman advocates (70). Another is the disability activist “No pity” injunction. A third example is secondary pity, as in the query, commonly addressed to disabled people, “Have you ever thought of killing yourself?”123 In this question, disabled people correctly hear the wish, “I’d like to kill you.” Indeed, primary pity is so unsettling that our culture has been driven to “mercifully” kill people in the name of secondary pity. We have also been driven to lock people in institutions, to let them languish on the streets, to stare, to punish, and to sentimentalize—all, I would suggest, in the interest of not owning, not naming, not acknowledging that self-shattering, ego-dissolving, instantaneous and intolerable moment of primary pity. Because primary pity is tied up with the disability drive, it must, like the drive itself, be regarded as unrepresentable. However, I will quote at length from a passage of writing that comes close not only to representing primary pity but also perhaps to producing it. In his memoir, One More Theory About Happiness, Paul Guest describes an experience that he had in the hospital after sustaining a spinal cord injury when he was twelve years old: My stomach still roiled and it was hard to keep anything down. Late one night, a doctor came to my bedside, leaning over me, his hands knotted together. He seemed vexed, not quite ready to say anything. Used to the look, I waited. And then he began. “The acids in your stomach, Paul, because of everything you’re going through, it’s like your body, everything about it, is upset. That’s why you feel so nauseous all the time. We’re going to treat that by putting a tube into your nose and down into your stomach, so we can give you medicine, OK?” When he walked away, I felt something begin to give way inside me. Up until then, I’d faced more misery and indignity than I would have thought possible. I lay there, numb and sick in a diaper, helpless. It was too much to bear, too frightening, a last invasion I could experience and not break, utterly. When he returned with nurses, I was already sobbing. Anyone so limited could hardly fight, but I tried. I tried. The neck collar prevented much movement, and any was dangerous, but I turned my head side to side, just slightly, a pitiful, unacceptable range. Fat tears rolled down my face like marbles. I begged them all, no, no, no, please no. “Hold him, hold him still,” the doctor said. Nurses gripped my head on either side. From a sterile pack, the doctor fished out a long transparent tube and dabbed its head in a clear lubricant. He paused almost as if to warn me but then said nothing. 77 Then the tube entered one nostril, its gauge slight enough to pass through, down my throat and into my stomach. I couldn’t thrash or resist. I could only relent. To the pain, the discomfort, but most distressingly the feeling of powerlessness, of violation. It was in that moment, I think, that the weight of everything which had happened fell upon me, undeniably, and the knowledge of it crushed me. (23-24) “Too much to bear,” Guest writes. The word “unbearable” would indeed be an accurate descriptor of this passage: both the experience of violence that it narrates and also the retelling of that experience produce sensations that, as in Berlant and Edelman’s account of sexuality, one cannot bear but must nonetheless “struggle to bear” (back cover). Guest’s account of a nonconsensual administration of an unwanted medical treatment is especially difficult to bear because it gives the reader no recourse to secondary pity: the passage offers no “lesson” to be learned, no invitation to feel “inspired,” nothing to make one feel in any way okay about what has happened. The medical violence that Guest recounts seems particularly devastating because it is readable as sexual: it takes the form of forced penetration, and it results in a “feeling of powerlessness, of violation” that resonates with experiences recounted by survivors of sexual assault.
19,146
<h4>Behold the image of the disgusting disabled child, which causes one to wince in the face of egoistic empathy. This is self-reflection, a process constitutive of the psyche that results in the disability drive, the culmination of primary pity where the non-disabled subject embodies itself in the position of the disabled object, and secondary pity, which portrays the ego’s overcompensation to regain its position and pushes a desire from lack for the eradication of disability.</h4><p><strong>Mollow 15</strong> Anna (2015): The Disability Drive, A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in English in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Professor Kent Puckett, Chair Professor Celeste G. Langan Professor Melinda Y. Chen Spring 2015 https://digitalassets.lib.berkeley.edu/etd/ucb/text/Mollow_berkeley_0028E_15181.pdf SJCP//JG</p><p>A Tale of Two Pities <u><strong>“Piss on pity,” declares a well-known disability activist bumper sticker</u></strong>. A more polite companion to this tag, the slogan “No pity” is a rallying cry of the disability rights movement.119 For disability studies, <u><strong>a field that since its inception has vigorously resisted the imposition of pity upon disabled people, Tiny Tim is anathema</u></strong>. Understandably so: every year, the image of <u><strong>Tiny Tim is used to drum up pity for disabled people; the widespread circulation of this affect, disability scholars have compellingly argued, does not alleviate the social barriers that we face but instead reinforces our oppression</u></strong>. Indispensable as this disability studies analysis is, it leaves some important questions about pity unanswered. For example: if, as is commonly said, <u><strong>“No one wants to be pitied,”</u></strong> then why is this so? And also, <u><strong>if nobody wants to be pitied, who, if anyone, wants to feel pity? At first glance, the answer to the latter question might seem to be “everyone.”</u></strong> Certainly, multitudes of moviegoers appear to enjoy our culture’s annual recitations of Tiny Tim’s pity inducing tale. <u><strong>If it can be fun to perform pity, perhaps this is because <mark>pity gives a boost to the ego of the pitying person</mark>. “<mark>You are broken, and I am whole</mark>,” the pitier says to the one who is pitied. “I look down on you because you suffer.” Naturally, disabled people resist performing this service for the nondisabled. “Spare us your pity,” we say, because pity is felt to be demeaning. 73 Yet an incoherence structures this familiar account of pity: if pity <mark>fortifies the ego of the subject</mark> who feels it, then why do people so often resist feeling pity?</u></strong> Some folks get pissed when they are prodded to pity. “Your appeals to pity won’t work,” they say. <u><strong>“I have no pity for you.” This is the attitude that Scrooge takes toward Tiny Tim</u></strong>. It’s also the stance that Edelman invites queers to take in relation to the Child—and not only to the Child per se, but also to anyone who calls for a performance of pity. <u><strong>Edelman argues that compassion (which, of course, is a close relative of pity) is fundamentally narcissistic</u></strong> (73). <u><strong>When we call ourselves compassionate, we think we’re feeling for the other; but, Edelman contends, we’re really only feeling for ourselves (83). That is, compassion <mark>involves projecting one’s own ego onto the object of one’s compassion</mark>. In this schema, the pitied person is used as a vehicle for the pitier to feel sorry for his or her own self. But in calling compassion a cover for narcissism, Edelman may inadvertently point to a connection between compassion and the drive.</u></strong> Freud’s theorization of narcissism, which is a precursor to his idea of the death drive, <u><strong>suggests that although <mark>some</mark> forms of <mark>narcissism can bolster the ego</mark>, <mark>other</mark> forms can do just <mark>the opposite</mark>.</u></strong> “On Narcissism” posits a distinction between what Freud calls <u><strong>“primary” and “secondary” narcissism</u></strong>; this distinction <u><strong>provides the basis for a contrast that I wish to draw between what could be called primary and secondary pity</u></strong>. To elucidate these two pities, let us look at the tale that Freud tells about two narcissisms. The story begins, as many Freudian narratives do, with <u><strong>the image of a child at its mother’s breast.</u></strong> Freud gives the name <u><strong>“primary narcissism” to the perfect autoerotic pleasure in which the child luxuriates. This pleasure takes place in the absence of a stable self, as the child does not yet conceive of itself as a distinct entity, undifferentiated from its external environment</u></strong> (87-88). <u><strong>It’s the best of times, but it can’t last</u></strong>: the child’s primary narcissism, Freud recounts, is exposed to numerous “disturbances,” ranging from the castration complex (in which boys fear losing the penis and girls, Freud assumes, wish that they had one) to parental discipline and criticism.120 <u><strong>But still, we keep seeking that lost, best time: because humans are “incapable of giving up a satisfaction” that we have “once enjoyed,” we continually try to return to the primary narcissism of childhood. We do this by engaging in secondary narcissism</u></strong>. All the <u><strong>familiar attitudes and behaviors that one tends to think of when one disparages someone as “narcissistic” fall into the category of what Freud defined as secondary narcissism: the puffed up ego, the feeling of superiority over others. But even secondary narcissism, with its many patent problems, does not only aim to aggrandize the ego</u></strong>. The impetus of <u><strong>secondary narcissism, after all, is to return to a state in which the ego as such does not exist</u></strong>. The child’s <u><strong>autoerotic enjoyment at its mother’s breast is pleasurable in part because the child is not yet a subject. As with the death drive’s impulsion to return to “an earlier state of things,” secondary narcissism draws the subject back toward a prior time when the ego did not exist</u></strong> (Beyond 45). Yet if primary narcissism is looked back upon as the best of times, it must, from the vantage point of a fully constituted ego, appear as the worst of times, too. <u><strong>To be drawn back to primary narcissism would be to imagine the abolition of one’s self. For this reason, even though secondary narcissism may threaten to break down the ego, it also entails a defense against the threat/pleasure of that breaking down</u></strong>. Much as the differentiation between the inseparable processes of primary and secondary narcissism rests on a distinction between building up and breaking down the ego, a similar heuristic distinction gives structure to my concepts of primary and secondary pity. <u><strong>To be clear, pity and narcissism are not the same thing: if narcissism can be understood as love of the self, pity involves a complex affective reaction to the suffering of someone else. Primary pity entails a response to the image of another person succumbing to what I have termed the “tragedy of disability.”</u></strong>121 <u><strong><mark>Primary pity arises when one witnesses a fall of the self</mark>, a collapse of the ego; such falling is <mark>at once painful and pleasurable to observe</mark>. In other words, primary pity could be described as a vicarious experience of the tragedy of disability. A great deal of the pain and pleasure of primary pity center on questions about what, or who, this fallen self is</u></strong>. When most people think about pity, we refer to an affect in which, to adopt Edelman’s phrase, <u><strong><mark>we</mark> purport to “<mark>feel for the other</mark>.”</u></strong> But as with primary narcissism, in which the self has not yet been constituted, and therefore cannot be said to enter into intersubjective relations with an “other,” <u><strong>primary pity entails a mixing up of self and other such that the ego, in becoming permeable to pain that may properly belong to “someone else,” is profoundly threatened in its integrity</u></strong>. Primary pity is that intense pain-pleasure complex that is provoked by the image of a suffering other who, it seems momentarily, both is and is not one’s self. <u><strong>This affective response can feel unbearable, as seen in Siebers’s formulation: <mark>one</mark> “<mark>cannot bear to look</mark>…<mark>but</mark> <mark>also</mark> cannot bear <mark>not to look</mark>.” <mark>Primary pity</mark> is difficult to bear because it <mark>involves a drive toward disability</mark> (one cannot bear not to look), which <mark>menaces</mark> the <mark>ego’s</mark> <mark>investments</mark> in health, pleasure, and control—because to <mark>contemplate</mark> another person’s suffering is to confront the question, “<mark>Could this happen to me</mark>?”</u></strong> Such a prospect, although frightening, may also be compelling; in this way, primary pity replicates the self-rupturing aspects of sexuality. Indeed, the unbearability of primary pity reflects its coextensiveness with sexuality. Sex, or the Unbearable, a book coauthored by Edelman and by Lauren Berlant, argues that sex “unleashes unbearable contradictions that we nonetheless struggle to bear” (back cover). This claim accords with Freud’s account of sexuality as a “pleasurable” “unpleasure” that the ego can never fully master or control (Three 49,75). As Leo Bersani puts it in his reading of Freud, “the pleasurable unpleasurable tension of sexual enjoyment occurs when the body’s „normal‟ range of sensation is exceeded, and when the organization of the self is momentarily disturbed”; thus, “sexuality would be that which is intolerable to the structured self” (Freudian 38). Primary pity is also intolerable to the structured self, because it entails a fascination with the fantasy of a self in a state of disintegration or disablement. <u><strong>Secondary pity is something else, although it cannot wholly be differentiated from primary pity. <mark>Secondary pity attempts to heal primary pity’s</mark> self-rupturing <mark>effects by converting</mark> <mark>primary</mark> pity in<mark>to</mark> a feeling that is <mark>bearable</mark>. As with secondary narcissism, secondary pity <mark>involves both an attempt to get back to</mark> that <mark>ego-shattering state of</mark> painfully <mark>pleasurable primary pity</mark>, <mark>and</mark> at the same time to <mark>defend against that threat</mark> to the ego by aggrandizing oneself at <mark>someone else’s expense</mark>. Secondary pity refers to all those ego-bolstering behaviors that most people think of when they talk about pity</u></strong>. Disabled people are all too familiar with these behaviors: the saccharin sympathy, the telethon rituals of <u><strong>“conspicuous contribution,” the insistence that “they” (i.e., nondisabled people) could never endure such suffering. More commonly known in our culture simply as “pity,” secondary pity encompasses our culture’s most clichéd reactions to disability: charity, tears, and calls for a cure.</u></strong> Correlatives of these commonplace manifestations of secondary pity are the <u><strong>obligatory claims that disabled people’s suffering is “inspiring</u></strong>.” Indeed, the speed with which conventional cultural representations of disability segue from overt expressions of pity to celebrations of “the triumph of the human spirit” highlights the ways in which <u><strong>secondary pity, as a defense against primary pity’s incursions, reinforces the ego’s fantasy of sovereignty. Secondary pity, in other words, can be seen as a variation of secondary narcissism: these affects enlarge the ego of the pitier or the narcissist at the expense of someone else</u></strong>. But primary pity is not the same as either primary narcissism, secondary narcissism, or secondary pity. Unlike primary narcissism, a feeling that emerges out of a relation to the world in which notions of “self” and “other” do not obtain, primary pity does depend upon the constructs of self and other, although these constructions are unstable and are continually threatening to come undone. Primary pity can thus be envisioned as a threshold category occupying a liminal position between the total denial of the other that is inherent to primary narcissism and the rigid structure of (superior) self and (inferior) other that constitutes secondary narcissism and secondary pity. My concept of primary versus secondary pity also differs from Freud’s primarysecondary narcissism distinction at the level of genealogy. Like Freud’s account of primary and secondary narcissisms, my model of primary and secondary pities involves a temporal transition; but whereas Freud imagines the movement from primary to secondary narcissism as a passage from an earlier to a later stage of an individual’s development, <u><strong>the temporal shift from primary to secondary pity happens much more quickly than this. It happens in an instant: that moment in which we feel primary pity and then, almost before we can blink, deny that we feel or have felt it. The denial is understandable: who wants to admit that one gets pleasure from the sight of another person’s suffering—or, to make matters worse, that this pleasure derives in part from the specter of disability’s transferability, the possibility that this suffering could be—and, fantasmatically, perhaps already is—an image of one‟s own self undone</u></strong>? Indeed, the model of primary pity that I have been constructing may sound a bit too close to sadism for some people’s liking. Pity does come close to sadism, and at the same time, to masochism, which Freud theorizes as sadism’s obverse. In “Mourning and Melancholia,” an essay that can be read as a sequel to “On Narcissism,” Freud approaches a distinction between primary and secondary masochism, which accords with my primary-secondary pity heuristic.122 If the story that I traced in “On Narcissism” could be summarized as “child gets breast; child loses breast; child gets breast back, albeit in a secondary, adulterated form,” <u><strong>the tale that Freud tells about masochism takes much the same form. In this story, subject loves object; subject loses object; and subject tries to get object back by becoming object, that is, by identifying with the object in such a way that object starts to seem—and perhaps in some ways is—part of subject’s self. This last phase is a dysfunctional and disabling form of identification, Freud makes clear. Subject is still angry at object for having left it, and it takes out that anger on the object that is now part of itself. This is the reason that people suffering from melancholia are so hard on themselves,</u></strong> Freud says; the “diminution in…self-regard” that typically accompanies melancholia results from the subject’s attacks on the loved-and-lost object that the subject has incorporated into its ego (“Mourning” 246). Freud had not wanted there to be such a thing as primary masochism; for a long time, he had insisted that sadism, or “aggression,” was the primary instinct, and that masochism was only a turning-inward of this originary aggression. But in “Mourning and Melancholia,” although Freud does not yet use the term “primary masochism,” he nonetheless gets at this concept. The problem of suicide, Freud notes in this essay, raises the possibility that the ego “can treat itself as an object” that it wants to destroy (252). When it comes to such an extreme act as suicide, the possibility of carrying “such a purpose through to execution” must, Freud surmises, involve more than a sadistic wish to punish others. Perhaps, then, there is an innate desire to destroy one’s own self, Freud hypothesizes. If so, this self would not be a single thing: it would be “me” and at the same time, the lost object whose image “I” have internalized. Freud’s notion of a primary masochism is tied very closely to his conceptualization of the drive. Beyond the Pleasure Principle, the text in which Freud first used the term “death drive,” was published three years after “Mourning and Melancholia.” In the later text, Freud’s speculations about the death drive lead him to acknowledge that “there might be such a thing as primary masochism” (66). After all, Freud points out, the idea that either sadism or masochism definitively takes precedence over the other does not ultimately make much sense, as “there is no difference in principle between an instinct turning from the object to the ego and its turning from the ego to an object” (66). <u><strong>If sadism and masochism are ultimately indistinguishable obverses of each other, then pity, in both its primary and its secondary forms, would have to be both sadistic and masochistic.</u></strong> This is a deeply troubling possibility, but I suggest that trying to overcome pity will only make matters worse. There are many ways of trying to overcome primary pity, and each one ultimately aggravates the violence of primary pity. One way is the “pitiless” refusal of compassion that Edelman advocates (70). Another is the disability activist “No pity” injunction. A third example is secondary pity, as in the query, commonly addressed to disabled people, “Have you ever thought of killing yourself?”123 In this question, disabled people correctly hear the wish, “I’d like to kill you.” <u><strong>Indeed, <mark>primary pity is so unsettling</mark> that <mark>our culture</mark> has been driven to “<mark>mercifully” kill people</mark> <mark>in</mark> the name of <mark>secondary</mark> pity. We have also been driven to lock people in institutions, to let them languish on the streets, to stare, to punish, and to sentimentalize—all, I would suggest, in the <mark>interest of</mark> not owning, not naming, not acknowledging that self-shattering, <mark>ego-dissolving</mark>, instantaneous and intolerable moment of primary <mark>pity</mark>. Because primary pity is tied up with the disability drive, it must, like the drive itself, be regarded as unrepresentable.</u></strong> However, I will quote at length from a passage of writing that comes close not only to representing primary pity but also perhaps to producing it. In his memoir, One More Theory About Happiness, Paul Guest describes an experience that he had in the hospital after sustaining a spinal cord injury when he was twelve years old: My stomach still roiled and it was hard to keep anything down. Late one night, a doctor came to my bedside, leaning over me, his hands knotted together. He seemed vexed, not quite ready to say anything. Used to the look, I waited. And then he began. “The acids in your stomach, Paul, because of everything you’re going through, it’s like your body, everything about it, is upset. That’s why you feel so nauseous all the time. We’re going to treat that by putting a tube into your nose and down into your stomach, so we can give you medicine, OK?” When he walked away, I felt something begin to give way inside me. Up until then, I’d faced more misery and indignity than I would have thought possible. I lay there, numb and sick in a diaper, helpless. It was too much to bear, too frightening, a last invasion I could experience and not break, utterly. When he returned with nurses, I was already sobbing. Anyone so limited could hardly fight, but I tried. I tried. The neck collar prevented much movement, and any was dangerous, but I turned my head side to side, just slightly, a pitiful, unacceptable range. Fat tears rolled down my face like marbles. I begged them all, no, no, no, please no. “Hold him, hold him still,” the doctor said. Nurses gripped my head on either side. From a sterile pack, the doctor fished out a long transparent tube and dabbed its head in a clear lubricant. He paused almost as if to warn me but then said nothing. 77 Then the tube entered one nostril, its gauge slight enough to pass through, down my throat and into my stomach. I couldn’t thrash or resist. I could only relent. To the pain, the discomfort, but most distressingly the feeling of powerlessness, of violation. It was in that moment, I think, that the weight of everything which had happened fell upon me, undeniably, and the knowledge of it crushed me. (23-24) “Too much to bear,” Guest writes. The word “unbearable” would indeed be an accurate descriptor of this passage: both the experience of violence that it narrates and also the retelling of that experience produce sensations that, as in Berlant and Edelman’s account of sexuality, one cannot bear but must nonetheless “struggle to bear” (back cover). <u><strong>Guest’s account of a nonconsensual administration of an unwanted medical treatment is especially difficult to bear because it gives the reader no recourse to secondary pity: the passage offers no “lesson” to be learned, no invitation to feel “inspired,” nothing to make one feel in any way okay about what has happened. The <mark>medical violence</mark> that Guest recounts seems particularly devastating because it is readable as sexual: it takes the form of forced penetration, and it <mark>results in</mark> a “feeling of powerlessness, of <mark>violation</mark>”</u></strong> that resonates with experiences recounted by survivors of sexual assault.</p>
1ac v mountain house es
null
1ac
325,333
517
150,124
./documents/hsld22/Jordan/VeSh/Jordan-VeSh-Aff-Heart-of-Texas-Invitational-hosted-by-St-Marks-Round-1.docx
937,041
A
St Marks
1
Mountain House ES
Dylan Jones
1ac - mollow 1nc - tfw, lowkey kinda insane case push 1ar - all 2nr - tfw 2ar - tfw (rfd: elizabeth won on tfw)
hsld22/Jordan/VeSh/Jordan-VeSh-Aff-Heart-of-Texas-Invitational-hosted-by-St-Marks-Round-1.docx
2023-03-03 04:41:40
79,298
VeSh
Jordan VeSh
they/them either fb messenger or [email protected] - just contact me and i'll cooperate with anything - auto I meet if you dont text and ask (disclosure, spec, accommodations, ect) the content i read is lowk wild - please tell me any content you would like me to void pre-round - stuff i read includes violence, graphic descriptions, suicide, etc. - accessibility requests - 1) please please please delineate lines/analytics, ie. exactly what im doing in this section. or if you're not going to do that give me some time to do it pre-speech because i actually cant read them otherwise 2) I have really bad adhd so I might have a hard time processing information - plz comply if I ask to repeat args you made, or other accessibility stuff. 3) ask consent before u spread, i have a processing issue that makes it borderline impossible for me to spread at times 4) stop extemping stuff in the 1ac/1nc - if you are going to plz just say "off the doc" or something like that before you do so
Ve.....
Sh.....
null
null
26,547
Jordan
Jordan
TX
null
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
3,638,635
1] Fission proves personal identity is reductionist – psychological continuity doesn’t exist.
Olson summarizes
Olson summarizes – Eric T. Olson, professor of philosophy at the University of Sheffield ("Personal Identity", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2017 Edition), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/identity-personal/,)
you could be psychologically continuous with two past or future people at once. If your cerebrum—the upper part of the brain largely responsible for mental features—were transplanted, the recipient would be psychologically continuous with you by anyone’s lights But now suppose that both hemispheres are transplanted, each into a different empty head The two recipients—call them Lefty and Righty—will each be psychologically continuous with you It follows that you are Lefty and Righty. But that cannot be: if you and Lefty are one and you and Righty are one, Lefty and Righty cannot be two suppose Lefty is hungry at a time when Righty isn’t If you are Lefty and Righty, you are both hungry and not hungry at once: a contradiction
If your cerebrum were transplanted, the recipient would be psychologically continuous with you But suppose both hemispheres are transplanted, each into a different head The two recipients will each be psychologically continuous with you It follows that you are Lefty and Righty. But that cannot be: if you and Lefty are one and you and Righty are one, Lefty and Righty cannot be two : a contradiction
A more serious worry for psychological-continuity views is that you could be psychologically continuous with two past or future people at once. If your cerebrum—the upper part of the brain largely responsible for mental features—were transplanted, the recipient would be psychologically continuous with you by anyone’s lights (even though there would also be important psychological differences). The psychological-continuity view implies that she would be you. If we destroyed one of your cerebral hemispheres, the resulting being would also be psychologically continuous with you. (Hemispherectomy—even the removal of the left hemisphere, which controls speech—is considered a drastic but acceptable treatment for otherwise-inoperable brain tumors: see Rigterink 1980.) What if we did both at once, destroying one hemisphere and transplanting the other? Then too, the one who got the transplanted hemisphere would be psychologically continuous with you, and would be you according to the psychological-continuity view. But now suppose that both hemispheres are transplanted, each into a different empty head. (We needn’t pretend, as some authors do, that the hemispheres are exactly alike.) The two recipients—call them Lefty and Righty—will each be psychologically continuous with you. The psychological-continuity view as we have stated it implies that any future being who is psychologically continuous with you must be you. It follows that you are Lefty and also that you are Righty. But that cannot be: if you and Lefty are one and you and Righty are one, Lefty and Righty cannot be two. And yet they are. To put the point another way, suppose Lefty is hungry at a time when Righty isn’t. If you are Lefty, you are hungry at that time. If you are Righty, you aren’t. If you are Lefty and Righty, you are both hungry and not hungry at once: a contradiction.
1,863
<h4>1] Fission proves personal identity is reductionist – psychological continuity doesn’t exist. </h4><p><strong>Olson summarizes </strong>–<strong> </strong>Eric T. Olson, professor of philosophy at the University of Sheffield ("Personal Identity", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2017 Edition), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/identity-personal/,)</p><p>A more serious worry for psychological-continuity views is that <u><strong>you could be psychologically continuous with two past or future people at once. <mark>If your cerebrum</mark>—the upper part of the brain largely responsible for mental features—<mark>were transplanted, the recipient would be psychologically continuous with you</mark> by anyone’s lights</u></strong> (even though there would also be important psychological differences). The psychological-continuity view implies that she would be you. If we destroyed one of your cerebral hemispheres, the resulting being would also be psychologically continuous with you. (Hemispherectomy—even the removal of the left hemisphere, which controls speech—is considered a drastic but acceptable treatment for otherwise-inoperable brain tumors: see Rigterink 1980.) What if we did both at once, destroying one hemisphere and transplanting the other? Then too, the one who got the transplanted hemisphere would be psychologically continuous with you, and would be you according to the psychological-continuity view. <u><strong><mark>But</mark> now <mark>suppose</mark> that <mark>both hemispheres are transplanted, each into a different</mark> empty <mark>head</u></strong></mark>. (We needn’t pretend, as some authors do, that the hemispheres are exactly alike.) <u><strong><mark>The two recipients</mark>—call them Lefty and Righty—<mark>will each be psychologically continuous with you</u></strong></mark>. The psychological-continuity view as we have stated it implies that any future being who is psychologically continuous with you must be you. <u><strong><mark>It follows that you are Lefty and</u></strong></mark> also that you are <u><strong><mark>Righty. But that cannot be: if you and Lefty are one and you and Righty are one, Lefty and Righty cannot be two</u></strong></mark>. And yet they are. To put the point another way, <u><strong>suppose Lefty is hungry at a time when Righty isn’t</u></strong>. If you are Lefty, you are hungry at that time. If you are Righty, you aren’t. <u><strong>If you are Lefty and Righty, you are both hungry and not hungry at once<mark>: a contradiction</u></strong></mark>.</p>
1AC
Deportations AC
F/W
369,332
213
121,496
./documents/hsld17/StrakeJesuit/Ch/Strake%20Jesuit-Chen-Aff-TOC-Quads.docx
813,526
A
TOC
Quads
all
all
null
hsld17/StrakeJesuit/Ch/Strake%20Jesuit-Chen-Aff-TOC-Quads.docx
null
69,687
MaCh
Strake Jesuit MaCh
null
Ma.....
Ch.....
null
null
23,597
StrakeJesuit
Strake Jesuit
null
null
1,025
hsld17
HS LD 2017-18
2,017
ld
hs
1
629,259
Nuclear war causes extinction – ozone losses, firestorms, and agricultural disruption.
Starr ’17
Starr ’17 (Steven; Steven Starr is the director of the University of Missouri’s Clinical Laboratory Science Program, as well as a senior scientist at the Physicians for Social Responsibility. He has been published in the Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists and the Strategic Arms Reduction (STAR) website of the Moscow Institute of Physics and Technology; Jan 09, 2017; “Turning a Blind Eye Towards Armageddon — U.S. Leaders Reject Nuclear Winter Studies”; Federation of American Scientists; https://fas.org/2017/01/turning-a-blind-eye-towards-armageddon-u-s-leaders-reject-nuclear-winter-studies/; DOA December 8, 2019; JPark)
The detonation of an atomic bomb will instantly ignite fires over three to five square miles. In recent studies scientists calculated the blast from a war fought with 100 bombs could produce direct fatalities comparable to all those in World War II the environmental effects could disrupt the global weather for at least a decade likely result in global famine. nuclear firestorms would cause five million tons of black carbon smoke to rise smoke would circle the Earth in less than two weeks and form a smoke layer remain for more than a decade smoke would absorb warming sunlight producing ozone losses of 20 to 50 percent This would create UV-B indices unprecedented in human history. smoke would produce the coldest average surface temperatures global food production would decrease by 20 to 40 percent cause up to two billion people to perish from famine. thermonuclear weapons possessed by the U S , Russia, China, France, and England were 1,000 times more powerful than an atomic bomb. Strategic nuclear weapons produce larger nuclear firestorms than atomic bombs A war fought with thousands of U.S. and Russian strategic nuclear weapons would ignite immense firestorms produce up to 180 million tons of black carbon soot and smoke and block 70 percent of sunlight it would only require a matter of days or weeks for daily temperatures to fall below freezing colder than the height of the last Ice Age Growing seasons would be eliminated which would doom the human population.
an atomic bomb will instantly ignite fires the blast could produce direct fatalities comparable to World War II disrupt the global weather for a decade five million tons of carbon smoke in less than two weeks and remain for more than a decade producing ozone losses of 20 to 50 percent unprecedented in history thermonuclear weapons were 1,000 times more than an atomic bomb larger nuclear firestorms A war with strategic nuclear weapons produce 180 million tons of black carbon block 70 percent of sunlight temperatures to fall below freezing Growing seasons would be eliminated which doom the human population
The detonation of an atomic bomb with this explosive power will instantly ignite fires over a surface area of three to five square miles. In the recent studies, the scientists calculated that the blast, fire, and radiation from a war fought with 100 atomic bombs could produce direct fatalities comparable to all of those worldwide in World War II, or to those once estimated for a “counterforce” nuclear war between the superpowers. However, the long-term environmental effects of the war could significantly disrupt the global weather for at least a decade, which would likely result in a vast global famine. The scientists predicted that nuclear firestorms in the burning cities would cause at least five million tons of black carbon smoke to quickly rise above cloud level into the stratosphere, where it could not be rained out. The smoke would circle the Earth in less than two weeks and would form a global stratospheric smoke layer that would remain for more than a decade. The smoke would absorb warming sunlight, which would heat the smoke to temperatures near the boiling point of water, producing ozone losses of 20 to 50 percent over populated areas. This would almost double the amount of UV-B reaching the most populated regions of the mid-latitudes, and it would create UV-B indices unprecedented in human history. In North America and Central Europe, the time required to get a painful sunburn at mid-day in June could decrease to as little as six minutes for fair-skinned individuals. As the smoke layer blocked warming sunlight from reaching the Earth’s surface, it would produce the coldest average surface temperatures in the last 1,000 years. The scientists calculated that global food production would decrease by 20 to 40 percent during a five-year period following such a war. Medical experts have predicted that the shortening of growing seasons and corresponding decreases in agricultural production could cause up to two billion people to perish from famine. The climatologists also investigated the effects of a nuclear war fought with the vastly more powerful modern thermonuclear weapons possessed by the United States, Russia, China, France, and England. Some of the thermonuclear weapons constructed during the 1950s and 1960s were 1,000 times more powerful than an atomic bomb. During the last 30 years, the average size of thermonuclear or “strategic” nuclear weapons has decreased. Yet today, each of the approximately 3,540 strategic weapons deployed by the United States and Russia is seven to 80 times more powerful than the atomic bombs modeled in the India-Pakistan study. The smallest strategic nuclear weapon has an explosive power of 100,000 tons of TNT, compared to an atomic bomb with an average explosive power of 15,000 tons of TNT. Strategic nuclear weapons produce much larger nuclear firestorms than do atomic bombs. For example, a standard Russian 800-kiloton warhead, on an average day, will ignite fires covering a surface area of 90 to 152 square miles. A war fought with hundreds or thousands of U.S. and Russian strategic nuclear weapons would ignite immense nuclear firestorms covering land surface areas of many thousands or tens of thousands of square miles. The scientists calculated that these fires would produce up to 180 million tons of black carbon soot and smoke, which would form a dense, global stratospheric smoke layer. The smoke would remain in the stratosphere for 10 to 20 years, and it would block as much as 70 percent of sunlight from reaching the surface of the Northern Hemisphere and 35 percent from the Southern Hemisphere. So much sunlight would be blocked by the smoke that the noonday sun would resemble a full moon at midnight. Under such conditions, it would only require a matter of days or weeks for daily minimum temperatures to fall below freezing in the largest agricultural areas of the Northern Hemisphere, where freezing temperatures would occur every day for a period of between one to more than two years. Average surface temperatures would become colder than those experienced 18,000 years ago at the height of the last Ice Age, and the prolonged cold would cause average rainfall to decrease by up to 90%. Growing seasons would be completely eliminated for more than a decade; it would be too cold and dark to grow food crops, which would doom the majority of the human population.
4,379
<h4><strong>Nuclear war causes extinction – ozone losses, firestorms, and agricultural disruption<u></strong>.</h4><p></u><strong>Starr ’17<u></strong> (Steven; Steven Starr is the director of the University of Missouri’s Clinical Laboratory Science Program, as well as a senior scientist at the Physicians for Social Responsibility. He has been published in the Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists and the Strategic Arms Reduction (STAR) website of the Moscow Institute of Physics and Technology; Jan 09, 2017; “Turning a Blind Eye Towards Armageddon — U.S. Leaders Reject Nuclear Winter Studies”; Federation of American Scientists; https://fas.org/2017/01/turning-a-blind-eye-towards-armageddon-u-s-leaders-reject-nuclear-winter-studies/; DOA December 8, 2019; JPark)</p><p>The detonation of <mark>an atomic bomb</u></mark> with this explosive power <u><mark>will instantly ignite fires</mark> over</u> a surface area of <u>three to five square miles.</u> <u>In</u> the <u>recent studies</u>, the <u>scientists calculated</u> that <u><mark>the blast</u></mark>, fire, and radiation <u>from a war fought with 100 </u>atomic<u> bombs <strong><mark>could produce direct fatalities</strong> comparable to</u></mark> <u>all</u> of <u>those</u> worldwide <u>in <mark>World War II</u></mark>, or to those once estimated for a “counterforce” nuclear war between the superpowers. However, <u>the</u> long-term <u>environmental effects </u>of the war <u>could</u> significantly <u><mark>disrupt the global weather for</mark> at least <mark>a decade</u></mark>, which would <u>likely result in</u> a vast <u>global famine. </u>The scientists predicted that <u>nuclear firestorms</u> in the burning cities <u>would cause</u> at least <u><mark>five million tons of </mark>black <mark>carbon smoke </mark>to</u> quickly <u>rise</u> above cloud level into the stratosphere, where it could not be rained out. The <u>smoke would circle the Earth <mark>in less than two weeks</u> <u>and</u></mark> would <u>form a</u> global stratospheric <u>smoke layer</u> that would <u><mark>remain</u> <u>for more than a decade</u></mark>. The <u>smoke would absorb warming sunlight</u>, which would heat the smoke to temperatures near the boiling point of water, <u><mark>producing ozone losses of 20 to 50 percent</mark> </u>over populated areas. <u>This would</u> almost double the amount of UV-B reaching the most populated regions of the mid-latitudes, and it would <u>create UV-B indices <mark>unprecedented in</mark> human <mark>history</mark>.</u> In North America and Central Europe, the time required to get a painful sunburn at mid-day in June could decrease to as little as six minutes for fair-skinned individuals. As the <u>smoke</u> layer blocked warming sunlight from reaching the Earth’s surface, it <u>would produce the coldest average surface temperatures</u> in the last 1,000 years. The scientists calculated that <u>global food production would decrease by 20 to 40 percent</u> during a five-year period following such a war. Medical experts have predicted that the shortening of growing seasons and corresponding decreases in agricultural production could <u>cause up to two billion people to perish from famine. </u>The climatologists also investigated the effects of a nuclear war fought with the vastly more powerful modern <u><mark>thermonuclear weapons</mark> possessed by the U</u>nited <u>S</u>tates<u>, Russia, China, France, and England</u>. Some of the thermonuclear weapons constructed during the 1950s and 1960s <u><mark>were 1,000 times more</mark> powerful <mark>than an atomic bomb</mark>. </u>During the last 30 years, the average size of thermonuclear or “strategic” nuclear weapons has decreased. Yet today, each of the approximately 3,540 strategic weapons deployed by the United States and Russia is seven to 80 times more powerful than the atomic bombs modeled in the India-Pakistan study. The smallest strategic nuclear weapon has an explosive power of 100,000 tons of TNT, compared to an atomic bomb with an average explosive power of 15,000 tons of TNT. <u>Strategic nuclear weapons produce</u> much <u><mark>larger nuclear firestorms</mark> than</u> do <u>atomic bombs</u>. For example, a standard Russian 800-kiloton warhead, on an average day, will ignite fires covering a surface area of 90 to 152 square miles. <u><mark>A war</mark> fought <mark>with</u></mark> hundreds or <u>thousands of U.S. and Russian <mark>strategic nuclear weapons</mark> would ignite immense</u> nuclear <u>firestorms</u> covering land surface areas of many thousands or tens of thousands of square miles. The scientists calculated that these fires would <u><mark>produce </mark>up to <mark>180 million tons</mark> <mark>of black carbon </mark>soot and smoke</u>, which would form a dense, global stratospheric smoke layer. The smoke would remain in the stratosphere for 10 to 20 years, <u>and</u> it would <u><mark>block</u></mark> as much as<u> <mark>70 percent of sunlight</u></mark> from reaching the surface of the Northern Hemisphere and 35 percent from the Southern Hemisphere. So much sunlight would be blocked by the smoke that the noonday sun would resemble a full moon at midnight. Under such conditions,<u> it would only require a matter of days or weeks for daily</u> minimum <u><mark>temperatures to fall below freezing</u></mark> in the largest agricultural areas of the Northern Hemisphere, where freezing temperatures would occur every day for a period of between one to more than two years. Average surface temperatures would become <u>colder than </u>those experienced 18,000 years ago at <u>the height of the last Ice Age</u>, and the prolonged cold would cause average rainfall to decrease by up to 90%. <u><mark>Growing seasons would</mark> <mark>be</u></mark> completely <u><mark>eliminated</u></mark> for more than a decade; it would be too cold and dark to grow food crops, <u><mark>which</mark> would <mark>doom the</u></mark> majority of the <u><mark>human population</mark>.</p></u>
null
null
1AC---Prolif
11,696
1,360
11,785
./documents/hsld19/Needham/Lu/Needham-Lu-Aff-TOC-Round4.docx
845,226
A
TOC
4
Cardinal Gibbons RS
John Boals
1ac - prolif w extra card 1nc - spark adv cp nfu stuff cbw da case 1ar - all condo 2nr - cp da case 2ar - those things
hsld19/Needham/Lu/Needham-Lu-Aff-TOC-Round4.docx
null
72,132
ZaLu
Needham ZaLu
null
Za.....
Lu.....
null
null
24,238
Needham
Needham
MA
null
1,027
hsld19
HS LD 2019-20
2,019
ld
hs
1
2,906,239
Nuclear war between India and Pakistan destroys the world
Johnson 19
Johnson 19 [Scott K Johnson is an educator and recovering hydrogeologist who has been covering the geosciences for Ars since 2011.] “Misery of a nuclear war between India and Pakistan would be global.” Ars Technica. October 4, 2019. https://arstechnica.com/science/2019/10/misery-of-a-nuclear-war-between-india-and-pakistan-would-be-global/ TG
**this is about/cites the Toon study The catastrophe would not be restricted by national borders. Nuclear explosions burn sizable areas around the target, with heat so intense that near-complete incineration is possible. The soot particles generated by these fires would be lifted into the upper troposphere much of it would absorb sunlight, heating the surround air and riding the resultant rising motion into the stratosphere. Once in the stratosphere, it can stay suspended much longer and encircle the planet researchers ran climate-model simulations of what the soot—16 to 36 million metric tons of it—would do in the atmosphere produced a simulation soot would block about 20% to 30% of the Sun's light, globally The result would be a 2°C to 5°C (about 4°F to 9°F) global cooling. Temperatures would reach their lowest after about three years and maintain that level for another four years. The cooling would slow the hydrologic cycle and decrease rainfall by 15% to 30% percent globally, In India and Central China, for example, precipitation would drop to nearly zero. The Northeastern and Midwestern United States would see a decline of 50%. India and Pakistan alone could suffer 50 to 125 million fatalities severe short-term climate perturbations, with temperatures declining to values not seen on Earth since the middle of the last Ice Age, would be triggered by smoke from burning cities, a global disaster threatening food production worldwide and mass starvation, as well as severe disruption to natural ecosystems."
Nuclear explosions burn sizable areas 36 million tons of soot would block 30% of the Sun's light 5°C cooling. decrease rainfall by 30% percent globally India and China precipitation would drop to zero United States decline 50%. India and Pakistan could suffer 125 million fatalities temperatures declining to the last Ice Age and mass starvation
**this is about/cites the Toon study The catastrophe would not be restricted by national borders. Nuclear explosions burn sizable areas around the target, with heat so intense that near-complete incineration is possible. The soot particles generated by these fires would be lifted into the upper troposphere. Some of that would fall to the ground with rain, but much of it would absorb sunlight, heating the surround air and riding the resultant rising motion into the stratosphere. Once in the stratosphere, it can stay suspended much longer and encircle the planet. (This is also how some volcanic eruptions produce a global climate impact.) With estimates of fire extent and the amount of combustible material in those areas, the researchers ran climate-model simulations of what the soot—16 to 36 million metric tons of it—would do in the atmosphere. They actually used the same model that recently produced a simulation of the Chicxulub impact at the end-Cretaceous mass extinction. Simply put, soot would block about 20% to 30% of the Sun's light, globally. That's a decrease of about 30W to 60W per square meter of the Earth's surface. For comparison, the 1991 eruption of Mount Pinatubo caused a decrease of 4W per square meter. The result would be a 2°C to 5°C (about 4°F to 9°F) global cooling. Temperatures would reach their lowest after about three years and maintain that level for another four years. Getting back to previous temperatures would take over a decade. The cooling would slow the hydrologic cycle and decrease rainfall by 15% to 30% percent globally, with impacts varying in different regions. In India and Central China, for example, precipitation would drop to nearly zero. The Northeastern and Midwestern United States would see a decline of 50%. "Should a war between India and Pakistan ever occur, as assumed here," the researchers write, "these countries alone could suffer 50 to 125 million fatalities, a regional catastrophe. In addition, severe short-term climate perturbations, with temperatures declining to values not seen on Earth since the middle of the last Ice Age, would be triggered by smoke from burning cities, a global disaster threatening food production worldwide and mass starvation, as well as severe disruption to natural ecosystems."
2,286
<h4>Nuclear war between India and Pakistan destroys the world</h4><p><strong>Johnson 19</strong> [Scott K Johnson is an educator and recovering hydrogeologist who has been covering the geosciences for Ars since 2011.] “Misery of a nuclear war between India and Pakistan would be global.” Ars Technica. October 4, 2019. <u>https://arstechnica.com/science/2019/10/misery-of-a-nuclear-war-between-india-and-pakistan-would-be-global/</u> TG</p><p><u>**this is about/cites the Toon study</p><p>The catastrophe would not be restricted by national borders. <mark>Nuclear explosions burn sizable areas</mark> around the target, with heat so intense that near-complete incineration is possible. The soot particles generated by these fires would be lifted into the upper troposphere</u>. Some of that would fall to the ground with rain, but <u>much of it would absorb sunlight, heating the surround air and riding the resultant rising motion into the stratosphere. Once in the stratosphere, it can stay suspended much longer and encircle the planet</u>. (This is also how some volcanic eruptions produce a global climate impact.) With estimates of fire extent and the amount of combustible material in those areas, the <u>researchers ran climate-model simulations of what the soot—16 to <mark>36 million </mark>metric <mark>tons of</mark> it—would do in the atmosphere</u>. They actually used the same model that recently <u>produced a simulation</u> of the Chicxulub impact at the end-Cretaceous mass extinction. Simply put, <u><mark>soot would block</mark> about 20% to <mark>30% of the Sun's light</mark>, globally</u>. That's a decrease of about 30W to 60W per square meter of the Earth's surface. For comparison, the 1991 eruption of Mount Pinatubo caused a decrease of 4W per square meter. <u>The result would be a 2°C to <mark>5°C</mark> (about 4°F to 9°F) global <mark>cooling. </mark>Temperatures would reach their lowest after about three years and maintain that level for another four years. </u>Getting back to previous temperatures would take over a decade. <u>The cooling would slow the hydrologic cycle and <mark>decrease rainfall by</mark> 15% to <mark>30% percent globally</mark>,</u> with impacts varying in different regions. <u>In <mark>India and</mark> Central <mark>China</mark>, for example, <mark>precipitation would drop to</mark> nearly <mark>zero</mark>. The Northeastern and Midwestern <mark>United States </mark>would see a <mark>decline </mark>of <mark>50%.</mark> </u>"Should a war between <u><mark>India and Pakistan</u></mark> ever occur, as assumed here," the researchers write, "these countries <u>alone <mark>could suffer </mark>50 to <mark>125 million fatalities</u></mark>, a regional catastrophe. In addition, <u>severe short-term climate perturbations, with <mark>temperatures declining to </mark>values not seen on Earth since the middle of <mark>the last Ice Age</mark>, would be triggered by smoke from burning cities, a global disaster threatening food production worldwide <mark>and mass starvation</mark>, as well as severe disruption to natural ecosystems."</p></u>
null
AC
Contention
355,590
339
93,672
./documents/hsld19/McDowell/Pa/McDowell-Patel-Aff-UPenn-Round3.docx
844,294
A
UPenn
3
Lexington FV
Shannon Rodgers
1AC-Lay 1NC-Lay and so on
hsld19/McDowell/Pa/McDowell-Patel-Aff-UPenn-Round3.docx
null
72,021
KiPa
McDowell KiPa
null
Ki.....
Pa.....
null
null
24,206
McDowell
McDowell
PA
null
1,027
hsld19
HS LD 2019-20
2,019
ld
hs
1
1,927,637
“The United States federal government” is the national government in DC.
Black’s Law ‘4
Black’s Law ‘4 – Black’s Law Dictionary, 8th Edition, June 1, 2004, pg.716.
Federal government A national government that exercises control over smallerpolitical units Also termed (in federal states) central government the U.S. government termed national government
Federal government national government that exercises control over smaller units
Federal government. 1. A national government that exercises some degree of control over smallerpolitical units that have surrendered some degree of power in exchange for the right to participate in national politics matters – Also termed (in federal states) central government. 2.  the U.S. government – Also termed national government. [Cases: United States -1 C.J.S. United States - - 2-3]
391
<h4>“The United States federal government” is the <u>national government</u> in DC.</h4><p><strong>Black’s Law ‘4</strong> – Black’s Law Dictionary, 8th Edition, June 1, 2004, pg.716.</p><p><u><mark>Federal government</u></mark>. 1. <u>A <mark>national<strong> government</strong> that exercises</u></mark> some degree of <u><mark>control over smaller</mark>political <mark>units</u></mark> that have surrendered some degree of power in exchange for the right to participate in national politics matters – <u>Also termed (in federal states) <strong>central government</u></strong>. 2.  <u><strong>the U.S. government</u></strong> – Also <u><strong>termed national government</u></strong>. [Cases: United States -1 C.J.S. United States - - 2-3]</p>
1NC
null
OFF
16,298
212
56,934
./documents/hspolicy20/Lowell/SaTs/Lowell-Satovsky-Tsan-Neg-10%20-%20Cal-Triples.docx
733,737
N
10 - Cal
Triples
Nevada Union GW
Sophie Rahman, Ana Bittner, Adam Hall
1AC - Settler Semiotics 1NC - T-USFG - GND CP - Turtle Island CP - Heg DA 2NR - Heg DA
hspolicy20/Lowell/SaTs/Lowell-Satovsky-Tsan-Neg-10%20-%20Cal-Triples.docx
null
62,615
SaTs
Lowell SaTs
null
Je.....
Sa.....
Ta.....
Ts.....
21,701
Lowell
Lowell
CA
null
1,019
hspolicy20
HS Policy 2020-21
2,020
cx
hs
2
2,302,784
Empirics prove compulsory voting decreases partisanship by compelling more moderate, non-voters.
Badger 17 ] JJ
Badger 17 [Emily Badger, New York time Journalist and Urban policy writer, “Mandatory Voting as a Cure for Extreme Partisanship?” https://psmag.com/news/mandatory-voting-as-a-cure-for-extreme-partisanship-18582] JJ
People who don't follow politics — and don't have rabid views on the most polarizing topics of the day — tend not to vote. They leave alone at the polls motivated voters with extreme views likely to elect equally extreme politicians who are, as a result, unable to work with each other. You have a kind of reinforcement where politicians appeal to more ideologically inspired voters, who then reinforce politicians who respond to them," It's not easy to interrupt a vicious cycle. It's one of the hardest things to do in life — and certainly in politics." Galston's solution is a fairly radical intervention: Make everyone vote If the people who turn up voluntarily at the polls reinforce our worst political instincts toward conflict and obstruction, we could dilute their influence by roping absolutely everyone into the process. the American population eligible to vote is considerably more moderate than the subset of people who actually do vote Non-voters look like the classic bell curve if we rate them on an ideological spectrum from left to right The Disappearing Center That's not what the electorate looks like," he added. Galston, though, is convinced the evidence is on his side. And a significant increase in voter participation would statistically bump up the percentage of self-described moderates in the electorate. "There's just no question there," Galston said. He even cites evidence that compulsory voting laws work: Australia passed one in the 1920s after officials grew alarmed by what they considered low turnout rates below 60 percent Today, deterred by a fine the equivalent of a cheap parking ticket, typically 95 percent of Australians show
People who don't have rabid views on polarizing topics — tend not to vote. They leave alone voters with likely to elect extreme politicians It's a vicious cycle we could dilute their influence the American population is considerably more moderate Non-voters look like the classic bell curve evidence is on his side. a significant increase in voter participation would bump up moderates Australia passed one in the 1920s a 95 percent of Australians show
Political scientists will inevitably get more evidence this fall for a pattern particularly true of midterm elections: People who don't follow politics — and don't have rabid views on the most polarizing topics of the day — tend not to vote. They leave alone at the polls motivated voters with extreme views likely to elect equally extreme politicians who are, as a result, unable to work with each other. "You have a kind of reinforcement where politicians appeal to more ideologically inspired voters, who then reinforce politicians who respond to them," said William Galston, a senior fellow at the Brookings Institution. "I've spent a lot of time thinking and doing research on this problem. It's not easy to interrupt a vicious cycle. It's one of the hardest things to do in life — and certainly in politics." Galston's solution is a fairly radical intervention: Make everyone vote. If the people who turn up voluntarily at the polls reinforce our worst political instincts toward conflict and obstruction, we could dilute their influence by roping absolutely everyone into the process. Research, after all, has shown that the American population eligible to vote is considerably more moderate than the subset of people who actually do vote "Non-voters look like the classic bell curve," Galston said, if we rate them on an ideological spectrum from left to right (see Emory political scientist Alan Abramowitz's new book The Disappearing Center). "That's not what the electorate looks like," he added. Galston's proposal is, at this stage, more an intriguing thought experiment than anything else. He knows — "America being the kind of viscerally libertarian place that it is" — that the idea would be greeted by many as a gross government invasion of individual liberties. (It's an equally fun thought experiment to ponder how Tea Party patriots would react to a government mandate requiring them to fulfill what is an arguably patriotic duty.) Galston, though, is convinced the evidence is on his side. Congress has become measurably more polarized over the years, a crisis that consumes countless think-thank hours in Washington. And a significant increase in voter participation would statistically bump up the percentage of self-described moderates in the electorate. "There's just no question there," Galston said. He even cites evidence that compulsory voting laws work: Australia passed one in the 1920s after officials grew alarmed by what they considered low turnout rates below 60 percent (America's turnout in the most recent midterm election: 37 percent). Today, deterred by a fine the equivalent of a cheap parking ticket, typically 95 percent of Australians show up. Austria, Belgium, Greece and France all have varying versions of compulsory voting, some with enforcement, some without.
2,808
<h4>Empirics prove compulsory voting decreases partisanship by compelling more moderate, non-voters. </h4><p><u><strong>Badger 17</u></strong> [Emily Badger, New York time Journalist and Urban policy writer, “Mandatory Voting as a Cure for Extreme Partisanship?” https://psmag.com/news/mandatory-voting-as-a-cure-for-extreme-partisanship-18582<u><strong>] JJ</p><p></u></strong>Political scientists will inevitably get more evidence this fall for a pattern particularly true of midterm elections: <u><strong><mark>People who don't </mark>follow politics — and don't <mark>have rabid views on</mark> the most <mark>polarizing topics</mark> of the day <mark>— tend not to vote.</u></strong></mark> <u><strong><mark>They leave alone</mark> at the polls motivated <mark>voters with </mark>extreme views <mark>likely to elect </mark>equally<mark> extreme politicians</mark> who are, as a result, unable to work with each other.</p><p></u></strong>"<u><strong>You have a kind of reinforcement where politicians appeal to more ideologically inspired voters, who then reinforce politicians who respond to them,"</u></strong> said William Galston, a senior fellow at the Brookings Institution. "I've spent a lot of time thinking and doing research on this problem. <u><strong><mark>It's</mark> not easy to interrupt <mark>a vicious cycle</mark>. It's one of the hardest things to do in life — and certainly in politics."</p><p>Galston's solution is a fairly radical intervention: Make everyone vote</u></strong>. <u><strong>If the people who turn up voluntarily at the polls reinforce our worst political instincts toward conflict and obstruction, <mark>we could dilute their influence</mark> by roping absolutely everyone into the process.</p><p></u></strong>Research, after all, has shown that <u><strong><mark>the American population </mark>eligible to vote <mark>is considerably more moderate</mark> than the subset of people who actually do vote</p><p></u></strong>"<u><strong><mark>Non-voters look like the classic bell curve</u></strong></mark>," Galston said, <u><strong>if we rate them on an ideological spectrum from left to right </u></strong>(see Emory political scientist Alan Abramowitz's new book <u><strong>The Disappearing Center</u></strong>). "<u><strong>That's not what the electorate looks like," he added.</p><p></u></strong>Galston's proposal is, at this stage, more an intriguing thought experiment than anything else. He knows — "America being the kind of viscerally libertarian place that it is" — that the idea would be greeted by many as a gross government invasion of individual liberties. (It's an equally fun thought experiment to ponder how Tea Party patriots would react to a government mandate requiring them to fulfill what is an arguably patriotic duty.)</p><p><u><strong>Galston, though, is convinced the <mark>evidence is on his side.</u></strong></mark> Congress has become measurably more polarized over the years, a crisis that consumes countless think-thank hours in Washington. <u><strong>And <mark>a significant increase in voter participation would</mark> statistically <mark>bump up</mark> the percentage of self-described <mark>moderates</mark> in the electorate. "There's just no question there," Galston said.</p><p>He even cites evidence that compulsory voting laws work: <mark>Australia passed one in the 1920s a</mark>fter officials grew alarmed by what they considered low turnout rates below 60 percent</u></strong> (America's turnout in the most recent midterm election: 37 percent). <u><strong>Today, deterred by a fine the equivalent of a cheap parking ticket, typically <mark>95 percent of Australians show</u></strong></mark> up. Austria, Belgium, Greece and France all have varying versions of compulsory voting, some with enforcement, some without.</p>
null
null
1NC - OFF
910,334
211
72,552
./documents/hsld20/Oxford/Me/Oxford-Mehta-Neg-The%20Tradition-Finals.docx
870,040
N
The Tradition
Finals
San Mateo YR
Richard Cook, Connor Henson, Candis Tate, Henry Khadka, Alex Bravo
1AC - CJS and Populism Lay 1NC - Privatization DA Grid DA Compulsory Voting CP Case Lay 1AR - All 2NR - Privatization DA Populism Turns 2AR - Same
hsld20/Oxford/Me/Oxford-Mehta-Neg-The%20Tradition-Finals.docx
null
73,609
ViMe
Oxford ViMe
null
Vi.....
Me.....
null
null
24,667
Oxford
Oxford
CA
null
1,028
hsld20
HS LD 2020-21
2,020
ld
hs
1
342,700
Global economic wars escalate---collapse overcomes traditional barriers to conflict.
Sundaram & Popov 19
Jomo Kwame Sundaram & Vladimir Popov 19. Former economics professor, was United Nations Assistant Secretary-General for Economic Development, and received the Wassily Leontief Prize for Advancing the Frontiers of Economic Thought in 2007. Former senior economics researcher in the Soviet Union, Russia and the United Nations Secretariat, is now Research Director at the Dialogue of Civilizations Research Institute in Berlin “Economic Crisis Can Trigger World War.” http://www.ipsnews.net/2019/02/economic-crisis-can-trigger-world-war/.
As fears rise of yet another international financial crisis there are growing concerns about the increased possibility of large-scale military conflict the current political landscape, prolonged economic crisis, combined with rising economic inequality, chauvinistic ethno-populism as well as aggressive jingoist rhetoric, including threats could easily spin out of control and ‘morph’ into military conflict, and worse, world war. The 2008-2009 global financial crisis almost ‘bankrupted’ governments and caused systemic collapse Policymakers managed to pull the world economy from the brink, but soon switched from counter-cyclical fiscal efforts to unconventional monetary measures, primarily ‘quantitative easing’ and very low, if not negative real interest rates As monetary tightening checks asset price bubbles, another economic crisis — possibly more severe than the last, as the economy has become less responsive to such blunt monetary interventions — is considered likely. A decade of such unconventional monetary policies, with very low interest rates, has greatly depleted their ability to revive the economy. another round of economic stress is deemed likely to foment unrest, conflict, even war as it is blamed on the foreign. Liberalization’s discontents Rising economic insecurity increase social tensions and turmoil, especially among the growing precariat and others who feel vulnerable or threatened. ethno-populist inspired chauvinistic nationalism may exacerbate tensions leading to conflicts and tensions among countries, as in the 1930s. protracted economic distress, economic conflicts or another financial crisis could lead to military confrontation by the protagonists, even if unintended.
financial crisis growing concerns about the increased possibility of large-scale military conflict the current political landscape, prolonged economic crisis could spin out of control and ‘morph’ into military conflict, and world war. 2008 almost ‘bankrupted’ governments Policymakers managed to pull the world economy from the brink, primarily ‘quantitative easing’ and low interest rates another economic crisis more severe than the last is likely another round of economic stress foment unrest, conflict, even war insecurity increase social tensions and turmoil, especially among the growing precariat and others who feel vulnerable or threatened. ethno-populist nationalism may exacerbate tensions leading to conflicts economic conflicts or financial crisis could lead to military confrontation even if unintended.
Economic recovery efforts since the 2008-2009 global financial crisis have mainly depended on unconventional monetary policies. As fears rise of yet another international financial crisis, there are growing concerns about the increased possibility of large-scale military conflict. More worryingly, in the current political landscape, prolonged economic crisis, combined with rising economic inequality, chauvinistic ethno-populism as well as aggressive jingoist rhetoric, including threats, could easily spin out of control and ‘morph’ into military conflict, and worse, world war. Crisis responses limited The 2008-2009 global financial crisis almost ‘bankrupted’ governments and caused systemic collapse. Policymakers managed to pull the world economy from the brink, but soon switched from counter-cyclical fiscal efforts to unconventional monetary measures, primarily ‘quantitative easing’ and very low, if not negative real interest rates. But while these monetary interventions averted realization of the worst fears at the time by turning the US economy around, they did little to address underlying economic weaknesses, largely due to the ascendance of finance in recent decades at the expense of the real economy. Since then, despite promising to do so, policymakers have not seriously pursued, let alone achieved, such needed reforms. Instead, ostensible structural reformers have taken advantage of the crisis to pursue largely irrelevant efforts to further ‘casualize’ labour markets. This lack of structural reform has meant that the unprecedented liquidity central banks injected into economies has not been well allocated to stimulate resurgence of the real economy. From bust to bubble Instead, easy credit raised asset prices to levels even higher than those prevailing before 2008. US house prices are now 8% more than at the peak of the property bubble in 2006, while its price-to-earnings ratio in late 2018 was even higher than in 2008 and in 1929, when the Wall Street Crash precipitated the Great Depression. As monetary tightening checks asset price bubbles, another economic crisis — possibly more severe than the last, as the economy has become less responsive to such blunt monetary interventions — is considered likely. A decade of such unconventional monetary policies, with very low interest rates, has greatly depleted their ability to revive the economy. The implications beyond the economy of such developments and policy responses are already being seen. Prolonged economic distress has worsened public antipathy towards the culturally alien — not only abroad, but also within. Thus, another round of economic stress is deemed likely to foment unrest, conflict, even war as it is blamed on the foreign. International trade shrank by two-thirds within half a decade after the US passed the Smoot-Hawley Tariff Act in 1930, at the start of the Great Depression, ostensibly to protect American workers and farmers from foreign competition! Liberalization’s discontents Rising economic insecurity, inequalities and deprivation are expected to strengthen ethno-populist and jingoistic nationalist sentiments, and increase social tensions and turmoil, especially among the growing precariat and others who feel vulnerable or threatened. Thus, ethno-populist inspired chauvinistic nationalism may exacerbate tensions, leading to conflicts and tensions among countries, as in the 1930s. Opportunistic leaders have been blaming such misfortunes on outsiders and may seek to reverse policies associated with the perceived causes, such as ‘globalist’ economic liberalization. Policies which successfully check such problems may reduce social tensions, as well as the likelihood of social turmoil and conflict, including among countries. However, these may also inadvertently exacerbate problems. The recent spread of anti-globalization sentiment appears correlated to slow, if not negative per capita income growth and increased economic inequality. To be sure, globalization and liberalization are statistically associated with growing economic inequality and rising ethno-populism. Declining real incomes and growing economic insecurity have apparently strengthened ethno-populism and nationalistic chauvinism, threatening economic liberalization itself, both within and among countries. Insecurity, populism, conflict Thomas Piketty has argued that a sudden increase in income inequality is often followed by a great crisis. Although causality is difficult to prove, with wealth and income inequality now at historical highs, this should give cause for concern. Of course, other factors also contribute to or exacerbate civil and international tensions, with some due to policies intended for other purposes. Nevertheless, even if unintended, such developments could inadvertently catalyse future crises and conflicts. Publics often have good reason to be restless, if not angry, but the emotional appeals of ethno-populism and jingoistic nationalism are leading to chauvinistic policy measures which only make things worse. At the international level, despite the world’s unprecedented and still growing interconnectedness, multilateralism is increasingly being eschewed as the US increasingly resorts to unilateral, sovereigntist policies without bothering to even build coalitions with its usual allies. Avoiding Thucydides’ iceberg Thus, protracted economic distress, economic conflicts or another financial crisis could lead to military confrontation by the protagonists, even if unintended. Less than a decade after the Great Depression started, the Second World War had begun as the Axis powers challenged the earlier entrenched colonial powers. They patently ignored Thucydides’ warning, in chronicling the Peloponnesian wars over two millennia before, when the rise of Athens threatened the established dominance of Sparta! Anticipating and addressing such possibilities may well serve to help avoid otherwise imminent disasters by undertaking pre-emptive collective action, as difficult as that may be.
6,039
<h4><u>Global economic wars</u> escalate---<u>collapse</u> overcomes traditional <u>barriers to conflict</u>.</h4><p>Jomo Kwame <strong>Sundaram &</strong> Vladimir <strong>Popov 19</strong>. Former economics professor, was United Nations Assistant Secretary-General for Economic Development, and received the Wassily Leontief Prize for Advancing the Frontiers of Economic Thought in 2007. Former senior economics researcher in the Soviet Union, Russia and the United Nations Secretariat, is now Research Director at the Dialogue of Civilizations Research Institute in Berlin “Economic Crisis Can Trigger World War.” http://www.ipsnews.net/2019/02/economic-crisis-can-trigger-world-war/. </p><p>Economic recovery efforts since the 2008-2009 global financial crisis have mainly depended on unconventional monetary policies. <u>As fears rise of yet another international <mark>financial crisis</u></mark>, <u><strong>there are <mark>growing concerns about the increased possibility of large-scale military conflict</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>More worryingly, in <u><mark>the current political landscape, prolonged economic crisis</mark>, combined with rising economic inequality, chauvinistic ethno-populism as well as aggressive jingoist rhetoric, including threats</u>, <u><strong><mark>could</mark> easily <mark>spin out of control and ‘morph’ into military conflict, and</mark> worse, <mark>world war.</p><p></u></strong></mark>Crisis responses limited</p><p><u>The <mark>2008</mark>-2009 global financial crisis <mark>almost ‘bankrupted’ governments</mark> and caused systemic collapse</u>. <u><mark>Policymakers managed to pull the world economy from the brink,</mark> but soon switched from counter-cyclical fiscal efforts to unconventional monetary measures, <mark>primarily ‘quantitative easing’ and</mark> very <mark>low</mark>, if not negative real <mark>interest rates</u></mark>.</p><p>But while these monetary interventions averted realization of the worst fears at the time by turning the US economy around, they did little to address underlying economic weaknesses, largely due to the ascendance of finance in recent decades at the expense of the real economy. Since then, despite promising to do so, policymakers have not seriously pursued, let alone achieved, such needed reforms.</p><p>Instead, ostensible structural reformers have taken advantage of the crisis to pursue largely irrelevant efforts to further ‘casualize’ labour markets. This lack of structural reform has meant that the unprecedented liquidity central banks injected into economies has not been well allocated to stimulate resurgence of the real economy.</p><p>From bust to bubble</p><p>Instead, easy credit raised asset prices to levels even higher than those prevailing before 2008. US house prices are now 8% more than at the peak of the property bubble in 2006, while its price-to-earnings ratio in late 2018 was even higher than in 2008 and in 1929, when the Wall Street Crash precipitated the Great Depression.</p><p><u>As monetary tightening checks asset price bubbles, <mark>another economic crisis</mark> — possibly <mark>more severe than the last</mark>, as the economy has become less responsive to such blunt monetary interventions — <mark>is</mark> considered <strong><mark>likely</strong></mark>. A decade of such unconventional monetary policies, with very low interest rates, has greatly depleted their ability to revive the economy.</p><p></u>The implications beyond the economy of such developments and policy responses are already being seen. Prolonged economic distress has worsened public antipathy towards the culturally alien — not only abroad, but also within. Thus, <u><mark>another round of economic stress</mark> is deemed likely to <strong><mark>foment unrest, conflict, even war</strong></mark> as it is blamed on the foreign.</p><p></u>International trade shrank by two-thirds within half a decade after the US passed the Smoot-Hawley Tariff Act in 1930, at the start of the Great Depression, ostensibly to protect American workers and farmers from foreign competition!</p><p><u><strong>Liberalization’s discontents</p><p>Rising economic <mark>insecurity</u></strong></mark>, inequalities and deprivation are expected to strengthen ethno-populist and jingoistic nationalist sentiments, and <u><strong><mark>increase social tensions and turmoil, especially among the growing precariat and others who feel vulnerable or threatened.</p><p></u></strong></mark>Thus, <u><strong><mark>ethno-populist</mark> inspired chauvinistic <mark>nationalism may exacerbate tensions</u></strong></mark>, <u><mark>leading to conflicts</mark> and tensions among countries, as in the 1930s.</u> Opportunistic leaders have been blaming such misfortunes on outsiders and may seek to reverse policies associated with the perceived causes, such as ‘globalist’ economic liberalization.</p><p>Policies which successfully check such problems may reduce social tensions, as well as the likelihood of social turmoil and conflict, including among countries. However, these may also inadvertently exacerbate problems. The recent spread of anti-globalization sentiment appears correlated to slow, if not negative per capita income growth and increased economic inequality.</p><p>To be sure, globalization and liberalization are statistically associated with growing economic inequality and rising ethno-populism. Declining real incomes and growing economic insecurity have apparently strengthened ethno-populism and nationalistic chauvinism, threatening economic liberalization itself, both within and among countries.</p><p>Insecurity, populism, conflict</p><p>Thomas Piketty has argued that a sudden increase in income inequality is often followed by a great crisis. Although causality is difficult to prove, with wealth and income inequality now at historical highs, this should give cause for concern.</p><p>Of course, other factors also contribute to or exacerbate civil and international tensions, with some due to policies intended for other purposes. Nevertheless, even if unintended, such developments could inadvertently catalyse future crises and conflicts.</p><p>Publics often have good reason to be restless, if not angry, but the emotional appeals of ethno-populism and jingoistic nationalism are leading to chauvinistic policy measures which only make things worse.</p><p>At the international level, despite the world’s unprecedented and still growing interconnectedness, multilateralism is increasingly being eschewed as the US increasingly resorts to unilateral, sovereigntist policies without bothering to even build coalitions with its usual allies.</p><p>Avoiding Thucydides’ iceberg</p><p>Thus, <u><strong>protracted economic distress, <mark>economic conflicts or</mark> another <mark>financial crisis could lead to military confrontation</mark> by the protagonists, <mark>even if unintended.</u></strong></mark> Less than a decade after the Great Depression started, the Second World War had begun as the Axis powers challenged the earlier entrenched colonial powers.</p><p>They patently ignored Thucydides’ warning, in chronicling the Peloponnesian wars over two millennia before, when the rise of Athens threatened the established dominance of Sparta!</p><p>Anticipating and addressing such possibilities may well serve to help avoid otherwise imminent disasters by undertaking pre-emptive collective action, as difficult as that may be.</p>
1AC
1AC
Adv---1AC
2,125
1,020
4,375
./documents/ndtceda22/Emory/SaSh/Emory-SaSh-Aff-Owen-L-Coon-Memorial-Tournament-at-Northwestern-Round-3.docx
925,736
A
Owen L Coon Memorial Tournament at Northwestern
3
Wake Forest RT
Lowery
1AC - AVs 1NC - K 2NR - K
ndtceda22/Emory/SaSh/Emory-SaSh-Aff-Owen-L-Coon-Memorial-Tournament-at-Northwestern-Round-3.docx
2022-09-17 22:37:55
80,500
SaSh
Emory SaSh
null
Je.....
Sa.....
Ja.....
Sh.....
27,030
Emory
Emory
null
null
2,001
ndtceda22
NDT/CEDA College 2022-23
2,022
cx
college
2
2,388,759
Lethal autonomous weapons don’t originate with states, but private manufacturers and companies.
Rohrlich 19
Rohrlich 19 Justin Rohrlich, 11-11-2019, "With no laws to stop them, defense firms are on track to make killer robots a reality," Quartz, https://qz.com/1746154/lacking-regulation-firms-on-track-to-make-killer-robots-reality/ SJCP//JG
Weapons built by defense manufacturers that can think for themselves lethal autonomous weapons systems, are designed to make life-or-death decisions on their own But Pax has identified at least 30 global arms manufacturers that don’t have policies against developing these kinds of weapons systems Defense firms don’t produce weapons in a vacuum these weapons are developed because companies believe that’s what militaries want in their arsenals companies like Lockheed Martin and Raytheon do almost all of their business with militaries, so they face little risk from the negative reaction of consumers Pax sent questionnaires to 50 arms manufacturers that produce military systems, asking each if it had policies regarding autonomous weapons
Weapons built by defense manufacturers lethal autonomous weapons global arms manufacturers don’t have policies against developing these weapons Defense firms develop because militaries want in arsenals companies do almost all business with militaries
Weapons built by defense manufacturers that can think for themselves are getting smarter, which mean the much-feared killer robot could be a reality sooner than later. That’s the warning contained in a new report from Pax, a nonprofit based in the Netherlands that campaigns for peace around the world. Killer robots, or lethal autonomous weapons systems, are designed to make life-or-death decisions on their own, without human control. It’s a worrying leap that’s been called the “third revolution in warfare,” after gunpowder and the atomic bomb. Both activists and military leaders have called for international regulations to govern these weapons, or even ban them outright, but key governments—like the United States and Russia—have so far resisted. As far as anyone knows, militaries have yet to actually deploy killer robots on the battlefield, at least offensively. But Pax has identified at least 30 global arms manufacturers that don’t have policies against developing these kinds of weapons systems, and are reportedly doing so at a rate that is outpacing regulation. The companies include US defense firms Lockheed Martin, Boeing, and Raytheon, the Chinese state-owned conglomerates AVIC and CASC, Israeli firms IAI, Elbit, and Rafael, Rostec of Russia, and Turkey’s STM. “As long as states haven’t agreed to collectively come up with some kind of regulatory regime, or ideally, a preemptive ban, the fear is very real that companies will be crossing this plane and will develop and produce and eventually field weapons that lack sufficient human control,” the report’s author, Frank Slijper, told Quartz. Activists don’t believe that military use of some degree of artificial intelligence is problematic in it itself. The US military is already employing full autonomy in some of its defensive weapons platforms, like the US Navy’s Aegis shipboard missile defense system, which is designed to intercept enemy fire on its own. The US Army is developing an AI-capable cannon, which would select and engage targets on its own, as well as AI-assisted tanks that, as Quartz first reported, will be able to “acquire, identify, and engage targets” at least three times faster than any human. But these systems still all require a person to pull the trigger, so to speak. PAX is more concerned about the potential deployment of AI in offensive systems that would select and attack targets on their own without human oversight. The group questions how these weapons would distinguish between combatants and civilians, or judge proportional responses. Legal experts still don’t know who would be held responsible if an autonomous weapon broke international law. And without lives on the line, these weapons could make it easier to go to war, and for those wars to escalate more quickly. The report warns that such weapons would “violate fundamental legal and ethical principles and would destabilize international peace and security.” What they’re building Defense firms don’t produce weapons in a vacuum, Slijper said. Instead, he said, these weapons are developed because companies believe that’s what militaries want in their arsenals. And unlike Google or Amazon, which have both faced public and internal backlash for their work on military systems, companies like Lockheed Martin and Raytheon do almost all of their business with militaries, so they face little risk from the negative reaction of consumers. For its report, Pax sent questionnaires to 50 arms manufacturers that produce military systems, asking each if it had policies regarding autonomous weapons. Just eight firms said they had in place principals guiding their AI work. The rest did not reply.
3,672
<h4>Lethal autonomous weapons don’t originate with states, but private manufacturers and companies.</h4><p><strong>Rohrlich 19</strong> Justin Rohrlich, 11-11-2019, "With no laws to stop them, defense firms are on track to make killer robots a reality," Quartz, https://qz.com/1746154/lacking-regulation-firms-on-track-to-make-killer-robots-reality/ SJCP//JG</p><p><u><strong><mark>Weapons</mark> <mark>built by defense manufacturers</mark> that can think for themselves</u></strong> are getting smarter, which mean the much-feared killer robot could be a reality sooner than later. That’s the warning contained in a new report from Pax, a nonprofit based in the Netherlands that campaigns for peace around the world. Killer robots, or <u><strong><mark>lethal autonomous weapons</mark> systems, are designed to make life-or-death decisions on their own</u></strong>, without human control. It’s a worrying leap that’s been called the “third revolution in warfare,” after gunpowder and the atomic bomb. Both activists and military leaders have called for international regulations to govern these weapons, or even ban them outright, but key governments—like the United States and Russia—have so far resisted. As far as anyone knows, militaries have yet to actually deploy killer robots on the battlefield, at least offensively. <u><strong>But Pax has identified at least 30 <mark>global arms manufacturers</mark> that <mark>don’t have policies</mark> <mark>against developing these</mark> kinds of <mark>weapons</mark> systems</u></strong>, and are reportedly doing so at a rate that is outpacing regulation. The companies include US defense firms Lockheed Martin, Boeing, and Raytheon, the Chinese state-owned conglomerates AVIC and CASC, Israeli firms IAI, Elbit, and Rafael, Rostec of Russia, and Turkey’s STM. “As long as states haven’t agreed to collectively come up with some kind of regulatory regime, or ideally, a preemptive ban, the fear is very real that companies will be crossing this plane and will develop and produce and eventually field weapons that lack sufficient human control,” the report’s author, Frank Slijper, told Quartz. Activists don’t believe that military use of some degree of artificial intelligence is problematic in it itself. The US military is already employing full autonomy in some of its defensive weapons platforms, like the US Navy’s Aegis shipboard missile defense system, which is designed to intercept enemy fire on its own. The US Army is developing an AI-capable cannon, which would select and engage targets on its own, as well as AI-assisted tanks that, as Quartz first reported, will be able to “acquire, identify, and engage targets” at least three times faster than any human. But these systems still all require a person to pull the trigger, so to speak. PAX is more concerned about the potential deployment of AI in offensive systems that would select and attack targets on their own without human oversight. The group questions how these weapons would distinguish between combatants and civilians, or judge proportional responses. Legal experts still don’t know who would be held responsible if an autonomous weapon broke international law. And without lives on the line, these weapons could make it easier to go to war, and for those wars to escalate more quickly. The report warns that such weapons would “violate fundamental legal and ethical principles and would destabilize international peace and security.” What they’re building <u><strong><mark>Defense firms</mark> don’t produce weapons in a vacuum</u></strong>, Slijper said. Instead, he said, <u><strong>these weapons are <mark>develop</mark>ed <mark>because</mark> companies believe that’s what <mark>militaries want in</mark> their <mark>arsenals</u></strong></mark>. And unlike Google or Amazon, which have both faced public and internal backlash for their work on military systems, <u><strong><mark>companies</mark> like Lockheed Martin and Raytheon <mark>do almost all</mark> of their <mark>business with militaries</mark>, so they face little risk from the negative reaction of consumers</u></strong>. For its report, <u><strong>Pax sent questionnaires to 50 arms manufacturers that produce military systems, asking each if it had policies regarding autonomous weapons</u></strong>. Just eight firms said they had in place principals guiding their AI work. The rest did not reply.</p>
null
2
1NC – Offense
270,890
178
76,378
./documents/hsld20/StrakeJesuit/Ch/Strake%20Jesuit-Chen-Neg-Heart%20of%20Texas-Round1.docx
874,770
N
Heart of Texas
1
John H Guyer SB
Mark Kivimaki
1ac - nuke laws 1nc - t korsgaard ai winter da 1ar - all 2n - korsgaard 2ar - ac nc
hsld20/StrakeJesuit/Ch/Strake%20Jesuit-Chen-Neg-Heart%20of%20Texas-Round1.docx
null
73,802
VaCh
Strake Jesuit VaCh
null
Va.....
Ch.....
null
null
24,736
StrakeJesuit
Strake Jesuit
TX
null
1,028
hsld20
HS LD 2020-21
2,020
ld
hs
1
4,548,459
Job Lock hinders Innovation – Health Insurance Coverage is the critical Internal Link.
Teirlinck and Stoilova 20
Teirlinck and Stoilova 20 Bertrand Teirlinck and Dani Stoilova Last Cited 2020 "Portable Benefits: Unlocking Innovation and Job Mobility" https://edc.nyc/insights/portable-benefits-unlocking-innovation-and-job-mobility (Policy Analyst and Intern at NY EDC)//Elmer
The phenomenon known as “job lock” suppresses innovation and economic growth, but portable benefits—benefits tied to an individual, not to an employer—could free people to work the best jobs for themselves and for the economy as a whole Advances in globalization and technology have turned traditional definitions of employment on their heads and have opened doors to unconventional career pathways. Unfortunately, the phenomenon known as “job lock” stands in the way of this workforce of the future Economists use the term job lock to characterize the inability of workers to leave undesirable positions due to a loss of benefits—in most cases, healthcare or retirement The Urban Institute’s Health Reform Monitoring Survey has found that health insurance affects 40 percent of Americans’ employment decisions—ranging from changing jobs and altering the number of hours worked to starting a business of their own. the most common form of health insurance is employer-sponsored Rising costs of healthcare and declining rates of insurance have caused workers to become hesitant about making a career change, continuing their education, or pursuing entrepreneurship to avoid losing their benefits showed that employees placed great emphasis on employer-provided benefits such as health insurance and paid leave As a result, job lock suppresses innovation, one of the key drivers of economic growth. According to a report by the Center for Economic and Policy Research, compared to other wealthy democracies, the US has one of the smallest small business sectors (by share of employment in small firms), the third lowest share of small research and development firms (25.3 percent), and the second lowest rates of self-employment (7.2 percent).6 The subsequent misallocation of labor, caused by job lock, can lead to additional inefficiencies; these include decreased productivity and production capability for firms.
Advances in technology opened unconventional career pathways job lock stands in the way inability of workers to leave positions due to a loss of healthcare health insurance affects 40 percent of Americans’ employment decisions most common is employer-sponsored Rising costs of healthcare caused workers to become hesitant about making a career change or pursuing entrepreneurship As a result, job lock suppresses innovation the US has the smallest small business sectors small r and d firms misallocation of labor, caused by job lock, can lead to decreased productivity
The phenomenon known as “job lock” suppresses innovation and economic growth, but portable benefits—benefits tied to an individual, not to an employer—could free people to work the best jobs for themselves and for the economy as a whole. Advances in globalization and technology have turned traditional definitions of employment on their heads and have opened doors to unconventional career pathways. Gone are the days of nine-to-fives and power lunches, in favor of freelance work and flexible schedules. Unfortunately, the phenomenon known as “job lock” stands in the way of this workforce of the future. Economists use the term job lock to characterize the inability of workers to leave undesirable positions due to a loss of benefits—in most cases, healthcare or retirement. As a possible solution to this complex problem, policy analysts and economists have proposed the concept of portable benefits. Stuck for the Coverage The Urban Institute’s Health Reform Monitoring Survey has found that health insurance affects 40 percent of Americans’ employment decisions—ranging from changing jobs and altering the number of hours worked to starting a business of their own.1 In the US, the most common form of health insurance is employer-sponsored, but the likelihood that firms offer employer-sponsored coverage declined approximately 10 percentage points from 1997 to 2010 (64.4% to 56.5%).2 Part-time and contracted workers are specifically disadvantaged as they are least likely to be eligible for employer-sponsored insurance.3 Rising costs of healthcare and declining rates of insurance have caused workers to become hesitant about making a career change, continuing their education, or pursuing entrepreneurship to avoid losing their benefits.4 This is consistent with findings of a recent survey of New York City residents by NYCEDC, which showed that employees placed great emphasis on employer-provided benefits such as health insurance and paid leave.5 Employment-Based Health Insurance Coverage Rates by Incomes as Percentage of Poverty Line United States Census Bureau: Survey of Income and Program Participation Employment-Based Health Insurance Coverage Rates by Incomes as Percentage of Poverty Line United States Census Bureau, Employment Base Health Insurance: 2010. (2) February 2013. As a result, job lock suppresses innovation, one of the key drivers of economic growth. According to a report by the Center for Economic and Policy Research, compared to other wealthy democracies, the US has one of the smallest small business sectors (by share of employment in small firms), the third lowest share of small research and development firms (25.3 percent), and the second lowest rates of self-employment (7.2 percent).6 The US, home of the American Dream, appears not to provide as much support for small-business employment as do other advanced countries. The subsequent misallocation of labor, caused by job lock, can lead to additional inefficiencies; these include decreased productivity and production capability for firms.
3,046
<h4>Job Lock <u>hinders</u> Innovation – Health Insurance Coverage is the critical <u>Internal Link</u>. </h4><p><strong>Teirlinck and Stoilova 20</strong> Bertrand Teirlinck and Dani Stoilova Last Cited 2020 "Portable Benefits: Unlocking Innovation and Job Mobility" https://edc.nyc/insights/portable-benefits-unlocking-innovation-and-job-mobility <u>(Policy Analyst and Intern at NY EDC)//Elmer</p><p>The phenomenon known as “job lock” suppresses innovation and economic growth, but portable benefits—benefits tied to an individual, not to an employer—could free people to work the best jobs for themselves and for the economy as a whole</u>. <u><strong><mark>Advances in</strong> </mark>globalization and <strong><mark>technology</strong> </mark>have turned traditional definitions of employment on their heads and have <strong><mark>opened</strong> </mark>doors to <strong><mark>unconventional career pathways</strong></mark>.</u> Gone are the days of nine-to-fives and power lunches, in favor of freelance work and flexible schedules. <u>Unfortunately, the phenomenon known as “<strong><mark>job lock</strong></mark>” <strong><mark>stands in the way </mark>of</strong> this <strong>workforce of the future</u></strong>. <u>Economists use the term job lock to characterize the <strong><mark>inability of workers to leave </mark>undesirable <mark>positions due to a loss of </mark>benefits</strong>—<strong>in most cases</strong>, <strong><mark>healthcare</strong> </mark>or retirement</u>. As a possible solution to this complex problem, policy analysts and economists have proposed the concept of portable benefits. Stuck for the Coverage <u>The Urban Institute’s Health Reform Monitoring Survey has found that <strong><mark>health insurance</strong> <strong>affects</strong> <strong>40 percent of Americans’ employment decisions</strong></mark>—ranging from changing jobs and altering the number of hours worked to starting a business of their own.</u>1 In the US, <u>the <strong><mark>most common</strong> </mark>form of <strong>health insurance <mark>is employer-sponsored</u></strong></mark>, but the likelihood that firms offer employer-sponsored coverage declined approximately 10 percentage points from 1997 to 2010 (64.4% to 56.5%).2 Part-time and contracted workers are specifically disadvantaged as they are least likely to be eligible for employer-sponsored insurance.3 <u><strong><mark>Rising</strong> <strong>costs of healthcare</strong> </mark>and declining rates of insurance have <strong><mark>caused</strong> <strong>workers to become hesitant about</strong> <strong>making a career change</strong></mark>, continuing their education, <strong><mark>or pursuing entrepreneurship</strong> </mark>to avoid losing their benefits</u>.4 This is consistent with findings of a recent survey of New York City residents by NYCEDC, which <u>showed that employees placed great emphasis on employer-provided benefits such as health insurance and paid leave</u>.5 Employment-Based Health Insurance Coverage Rates by Incomes as Percentage of Poverty Line United States Census Bureau: Survey of Income and Program Participation Employment-Based Health Insurance Coverage Rates by Incomes as Percentage of Poverty Line United States Census Bureau, Employment Base Health Insurance: 2010. (2) February 2013. <u><strong><mark>As a result, job lock suppresses innovation</strong></mark>, one of the key drivers of economic growth. According to a report by the Center for Economic and Policy Research, compared to other wealthy democracies, <strong><mark>the US has</strong></mark> one of <strong><mark>the smallest small business sectors</strong> </mark>(by share of employment in small firms), the third lowest share of <strong><mark>small r</strong></mark>esearch <strong><mark>and</strong> <strong>d</strong></mark>evelopment <strong><mark>firms</strong> </mark>(25.3 percent), and the second lowest rates of self-employment (7.2 percent).6</u> The US, home of the American Dream, appears not to provide as much support for small-business employment as do other advanced countries. <u>The subsequent <strong><mark>misallocation of labor, caused by job lock, can lead to</strong></mark> additional inefficiencies; these include <strong><mark>decreased productivity</strong> </mark>and production capability for firms.</p></u>
null
null
1AC: Access
327,091
184
149,914
./documents/hsld22/HoustonMemorial/BeDu/HoustonMemorial-BeDu-Aff-Grapevine-Classic-Round-4.docx
922,866
A
Grapevine Classic
4
Greenhill SK
Jack Quisenberry
1AC - Stock 1NC - PTX DA States CP Case 1AR - Condo Bad 50 States Bad Case PTX DA States CP 2NR - Condo Bad 50 States Bad PTX DA States CP 2AR - 50 States Bad States CP
hsld22/HoustonMemorial/BeDu/HoustonMemorial-BeDu-Aff-Grapevine-Classic-Round-4.docx
2022-09-10 21:04:53
79,279
BeDu
Houston Memorial BeDu
null
Be.....
Du.....
null
null
26,529
HoustonMemorial
Houston Memorial
TX
null
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
2,287,385
Compulsory voting reverses our progress of closing the political gender gap by leading to arbitrary votes that reinforce systemic biases.
Wauters and Devroe 15 http://www.absp.be/wp-content/uploads/2015/12/Wauters-Devroe-The-effect-of-compulsory-voting-on-womens-descriptive.pdf] JJ
Wauters and Devroe 15 [Bram Wauters and Robin Devroe, associate professor at the department of political sciences of the Ghent University and the director of GASPAR, http://www.absp.be/wp-content/uploads/2015/12/Wauters-Devroe-The-effect-of-compulsory-voting-on-womens-descriptive.pdf] JJ
compulsory voting systems are linked with lower levels of women’s descriptive representation can be due to different effects. The explanations for why potential non‐voters would vote significantly less for women can be divided into two broad categories. First, potential non‐voters are thought to vote in a less sophisticated manner The provision of compulsory voting forces also voters with low interest in politics to vote. This has several consequences on voting behavior. The most extreme consequence is compulsory voting leads to arbitrary votes that voters with low levels of political interest will make fewer use of preferential voting, when forced to vote non‐voters vote more for incumbents, i.e. existing holders of a political office. Incumbents have structural advantages over non‐incumbents during elections: they often have more name recognition because of their previous work in the office and they have easier 9 Related is the advantage enjoyed by the head of list. Maddens et al (2006) indicate that candidates in prominent positions on the ballot form draw automatically more votes, even when other factors are controlled for. ). At the most recent elections of 2014, about 29 per cent of all heads of lists were women ( This means that most women continue to occupy less attractive places on the list. Male party elites are often reluctant to lose their power position and while they agree to introduce quota regulations, they are often mitigating these regulations in practice The ranking of candidates on the list is determined by the party. Women still face a major barrier in the attitudes of selectors and do not make it to the top of the ballo . These attitudes may be particularly influential in preventing women from being selected to fight contests at the top. In sum, one major explanation is that potential non‐voters do not seem to deliberately vote less for women, but vote less sophisticated (more list, head of list and incumbency voting
compulsory voting systems are linked with lower levels of women’s representation non‐voters vote in a less sophisticated manner non‐voters vote more for incumbents they often have more name recognition because of previous work Related is the advantage enjoyed by the head of list candidates in prominent positions draw more votes, women continue to occupy less attractive places on the list These attitudes may be influential in preventing women from being selected to fight contests non‐voters do not deliberately vote less for women, but vote less sophisticated (more list, head of list
The fact that compulsory voting systems are linked with lower levels of women’s descriptive representation can be due to different effects. Since no explanations have been provided by other scholars so far, it is our intention to broaden this understanding. The explanations for why potential non‐voters would vote significantly less for women can be divided into two broad categories. First, potential non‐voters are thought to vote in a less sophisticated manner and, second, they are considered as being less convinced of the importance of political participation by women. First, Reuchamps et al (2015) found a strong link between potential absenteeism and political interest. Those who are not interested in politics, will not participate in elections. The provision of compulsory voting forces also voters with low interest in politics to vote. This has several consequences on voting behavior. The most extreme consequence is, what Reuchamps et al (2015) and IDEA (2015) suggest: compulsory voting leads to arbitrary votes, as it forces electors who would otherwise abstain to cast any vote. Potential non‐voters check off a candidate at random. But consequences could also be more subtle, in the sense that voters with low levels of political interest will make fewer use of preferential voting, when forced to vote. According to the resource model (Marsh, 1985), casting a preference vote is more demanding on the part of voters, since this requires to learn about candidates and compare them (Shugart et al 2005). Since potential non‐ voters are less politically interested, they are less likely to make the effort to cast a preference vote. André et al (2012), using data from the Belgian 2009 regional elections, indeed come to the conclusion that a higher degree of political interest and resources is more likely to be translated into candidate‐based voting. Preferential voting in general, and specifically for women (who often take positions lower down the list), can thus be considered as sophisticated electoral behavior that requires skills and attitudes (Mariën et al, forthcoming). Another effect is that potential non‐voters vote more for incumbents, i.e. existing holders of a political office. Incumbents have structural advantages over non‐incumbents during elections: they often have more name recognition because of their previous work in the office and they have easier 9 | P a g e access to campaign finance (Boundless, 2015). Related is the advantage enjoyed by the head of list. Maddens et al (2006) indicate that candidates in prominent positions on the ballot form draw automatically more votes, even when other factors are controlled for. This effect can be labelled Ballot Position Effect (Maddens et al, 2006; Geys and Heyndels, 2003; Lutz, 2010). In Belgian elections, the most favorable positions are those at the top and the bottom of the list of main candidates. Female candidates used to be underrepresented at the top of the list. For that reason, the revised quota law required that in 2003 elections at least one of the three top places on the list should be reserved for a woman. Parties initially complied in a minimalistic way with the quota regulations concerning the top positions, but recently progress has been made (Wauters et al, 2014). At the most recent elections of 2014, about 29 per cent of all heads of lists were women (Smulders et al, 2014). This means that most women continue to occupy less attractive places on the list. Male party elites are often reluctant to lose their power position and while they agree to introduce quota regulations, they are often mitigating these regulations in practice (Dahlerup, 2007). The ranking of candidates on the list is determined by the party. Women still face a major barrier in the attitudes of selectors and do not make it to the top of the ballot. Rasmussen (1983) points to the fact that party selectors and other supporters hold sex role stereotypes which reinforce images of women in traditional roles, and thereby undermine the qualities and experience which women bring to public life. These attitudes may be particularly influential in preventing women from being selected to fight contests at the top. The crucial point is thus that political parties have the power to compensate for the skewed nature of their pool of aspirants through the use of party rules, but that they are often reluctant to do this. In sum, one major explanation is that potential non‐voters do not seem to deliberately vote less for women, but vote less sophisticated (more list, head of list and incumbency voting), which is a disadvantage for women, because often they are not on top of the ballot and have less political experience
4,721
<h4>Compulsory voting reverses our progress of closing the political gender gap by leading to arbitrary votes that reinforce systemic biases.<strong> </h4><p><u>Wauters and Devroe 15</u> </strong>[Bram Wauters and Robin Devroe, associate professor at the department of political sciences of the Ghent University and the director of GASPAR, <u><strong>http://www.absp.be/wp-content/uploads/2015/12/Wauters-Devroe-The-effect-of-compulsory-voting-on-womens-descriptive.pdf] JJ </p><p></u></strong>The fact that <u><strong><mark>compulsory voting systems are linked with lower levels of women’s</mark> descriptive <mark>representation</mark> can be due to different effects.</u></strong> Since no explanations have been provided by other scholars so far, it is our intention to broaden this understanding. <u><strong>The explanations for why potential non‐voters would vote significantly less for women can be divided into two broad categories. </p><p>First, potential <mark>non‐voters</mark> are thought to <mark>vote in a less sophisticated manner</u></strong></mark> and, second, they are considered as being less convinced of the importance of political participation by women. First, Reuchamps et al (2015) found a strong link between potential absenteeism and political interest. Those who are not interested in politics, will not participate in elections. <u><strong>The provision of compulsory voting forces also voters with low interest in politics to vote. This has several consequences on voting behavior. The most extreme consequence is</u></strong>, what Reuchamps et al (2015) and IDEA (2015) suggest: <u><strong>compulsory voting leads to arbitrary votes</u></strong>, as it forces electors who would otherwise abstain to cast any vote. Potential non‐voters check off a candidate at random.</p><p>But consequences could also be more subtle, in the sense <u><strong>that voters with low levels of political interest will make fewer use of preferential voting, when forced to vote</u></strong>. According to the resource model (Marsh, 1985), casting a preference vote is more demanding on the part of voters, since this requires to learn about candidates and compare them (Shugart et al 2005). Since potential non‐ voters are less politically interested, they are less likely to make the effort to cast a preference vote. André et al (2012), using data from the Belgian 2009 regional elections, indeed come to the conclusion that a higher degree of political interest and resources is more likely to be translated into candidate‐based voting. Preferential voting in general, and specifically for women (who often take positions lower down the list), can thus be considered as sophisticated electoral behavior that requires skills and attitudes (Mariën et al, forthcoming). </p><p>Another effect is that potential <u><strong><mark>non‐voters vote more for incumbents</mark>, i.e. existing holders of a political office. Incumbents have structural advantages over non‐incumbents during elections: <mark>they often have more name recognition because of</mark> their <mark>previous work</mark> in the office and they have easier 9</u></strong> | P a g e access to campaign finance (Boundless, 2015). <u><strong><mark>Related is the advantage enjoyed by the head of list</mark>. Maddens et al (2006) indicate that <mark>candidates in prominent positions</mark> on the ballot form <mark>draw</mark> automatically <mark>more votes,</mark> even when other factors are controlled for.</u></strong> This effect can be labelled Ballot Position Effect (Maddens et al, 2006; Geys and Heyndels, 2003; Lutz, 2010). In Belgian elections, the most favorable positions are those at the top and the bottom of the list of main candidates. Female candidates used to be underrepresented at the top of the list. For that reason, the revised quota law required that in 2003 elections at least one of the three top places on the list should be reserved for a woman. Parties initially complied in a minimalistic way with the quota regulations concerning the top positions, but recently progress has been made (Wauters et al, 2014<u><strong>). At the most recent elections of 2014, about 29 per cent of all heads of lists were women (</u></strong>Smulders et al, 2014). <u><strong>This means that most <mark>women continue to occupy less attractive places on the list</mark>. Male party elites are often reluctant to lose their power position and while they agree to introduce quota regulations, they are often mitigating these regulations in practice</u></strong> (Dahlerup, 2007). </p><p><u><strong>The ranking of candidates on the list is determined by the party. Women still face a major barrier in the attitudes of selectors and do not make it to the top of the ballo</u></strong>t. Rasmussen (1983) points to the fact that party selectors and other supporters hold sex role stereotypes which reinforce images of women in traditional roles, and thereby undermine the qualities and experience which women bring to public life<u><strong>. <mark>These attitudes may be</mark> particularly <mark>influential</mark> <mark>in preventing women from being selected to fight contests</mark> at the top.</u></strong> The crucial point is thus that political parties have the power to compensate for the skewed nature of their pool of aspirants through the use of party rules, but that they are often reluctant to do this.</p><p><u><strong>In sum, one major explanation is that potential <mark>non‐voters do not</mark> seem to <mark>deliberately vote less for women, but vote less sophisticated (more list, head of list</mark> and incumbency voting</u></strong>), which is a disadvantage for women, because often they are not on top of the ballot and have less political experience</p>
1NC
Women’s Reps
null
351,721
189
71,907
./documents/hsld20/NashuaSouth/Gu/Nashua%20South-Gu-Neg-Valley-Round1.docx
868,883
N
Valley
1
Loyola IB
Ashley Ellis
1AC - US aff 1NC - T a Elections DA Representations DA States CP Case Turns 2NR - States CP Elections DA Case Turn
hsld20/NashuaSouth/Gu/Nashua%20South-Gu-Neg-Valley-Round1.docx
null
73,550
EnGu
Nashua South EnGu
null
En.....
Gu.....
null
null
24,642
NashuaSouth
Nashua South
NH
null
1,028
hsld20
HS LD 2020-21
2,020
ld
hs
1
1,754,034
Otherwise—enlargement fuels arms control failure from cheating and pullout—that wrecks NPT norms, causing proliferation.
Kuhn 16
Kuhn 16—(PhD in political science from Hamburg University, senior researcher at the Institute for Peace Research and Security Policy at the University of Hamburg). Ulrich Kuhn. 2016. Cornell University, Reppy Institute. Selected Essays on the Transition to a New Nuclear Order. “Cooperative Arms Control in Europe and the Global Nuclear Order: Rethinking Decision-Making and Institutions in Light of the Ukraine Conflict.” https://pacs.einaudi.cornell.edu/sites/pacs/files/Selected%20Essays.OP%2032_0.pdf.
Cooperative arms control aims at increasing mutual security and predictability through reciprocity, inclusiveness, dialogue, a defensive orientation, transparency, confidence-building, and arms limitations These central tenets are intended to help generate interstate relations ‘in which disputes are expected to occur, but they are expected to do so within the limits of agreed upon norms and established procedures. let us first turn to a number of realist variables addressing questions of power. The first variable is non-compliance. non-compliance is usually only the final stage in a sequential process of political decisions culminating in exit from a cooperative agreement. Russian non-compliance is neither the sole nor the most important reason behind institutional decay. The second variable was the shift in U.S.-Soviet/Russian capabilities with the end of the Cold War. This had (over the long term) a cooperation-disabling effect. it led Gorbachev Against the rapidly declining economic capabilities decided to prioritize the economy and seek cooperation with the West Gorbachev’s aim was to downsize the costly Soviet military and to get financial aid from the West in return. Against the background of the relative Russian weakness, the United States could pursue its preferred policies in its dealings with Moscow while, at the same time, negating Russian core interests (such as not enlarging NATO further to the East). The results were Russian perceptions of inequality, dissatisfaction with post-Cold War Europe, continued calls for re-negotiation, protracted negotiations, and increasing acts of non-compliance. during the 2000s, Russia started to (partially) exit institutions of cooperative arms control in Europe. The third variable stems from the increasingly offensive orientation of the United States since the end of the Cold War. offensively-oriented states complicate cooperation. From 1994 onwards, the United States acted in accordance with this orientation with three rounds of NATO enlargement (1999, 2004, and 2009). cooperation between Washington and Moscow on enlargement did not take place due to the offensive orientation of U.S. policy. Washington linked the defensive policy of cooperative security to policy offensive in nature (i.e. enlargement). These led, over time, to increased Russian frustration but deprived Russia de facto of an equal say in all European security matters. The fourth variable responsible for decay was a loss of interest by both sides. The fifth variable was the constant rejection of Russian core interests. Russian calls for renegotiating elements of the post-Cold War security architecture or the system as a whole have been apparent from the mid-1990s onwards. Moscow never achieved its overriding goal of codifying an end to NATO enlargement. Washington and its allies continued to resist any such attempt. This fact only deepened Russian dissatisfaction. Beyond realist power variables Russia feels it is being treated unfairly – which has led to increasingly negative ramifications. Russian notions of injustice and inequality are linked to NATO enlargement . The consequences of the Russian notions of being treated unfairly have been retreat from institutional cooperative security, and norm-challenging behavior. Both the United States and Russia have acted as norm challengers . In conjunction with NATO enlargement the 1999 Yugoslavia bombing , the Russian CFE “suspension”, the Russian-Georgian war of 2008, and the annexation of Crimea, both states have challenged existing normative injunctions Taken together, unconstrained power, conflicting ambitions for power, and a long process of normative erosion has led to the decay of the regime complex of cooperative arms control in Europe. The two key players in European security affairs have contributed substantially to that process. The Ramifications for the Global Nuclear Order The crisis create a negative domino effect at the level of multilateral nuclear arms control, disarmament, and non-proliferation governance. The first aspect concerns international efforts to prevent states from acquiring a nuc . there are powerful arguments to go nuclear . However, the survival concern will always be central to any international negotiations aimed at convincing states not to acquire nuclear weapons . a prolonged stalemate in further nuclear reductions between the United States and Russia. Article VI of the NPT binds officially recognized nuclear weapon states to pursue negotiations in good faith with the aim of the total elimination of nuclear weapons. U.S.-Russia arsenals account for over 90 percent of all nuc s worldwide. This increases mutual responsibility of Washington and Moscow to continue to lead global nuclear disarmament efforts. Both have done so since the end of the Cold War. The stalemate and even possible erosion of the U.S.-Russian nuclear disarmament dialogue might well throw the precarious NPT bargain out of balance. neither the complete disarmament commitment nor a Middle East WMD-free zone has become reality. the Arab States have been dissatisfied . If, in addition, the two largest nuclear weapons possessors freeze their disarmament commitments, the NPT bargain and the treaty as a whole might erode more quickly . A possible U.S.-Russian stalemate in disarmament efforts would serve as a good smokescreen for Arab states to voice their continued dissatisfaction and to seek – under worst circumstances – exit to the NPT. Without a balanced and operational NPT in place efforts to prevent the spread of nuclear weapons and nuclear materials might seriously suffer as well. What pertains to the level of state-led efforts to acquire a nuclear weapons capability applies as well to criminal trans-national networks and terrorist groups struggling to obtain weapons-grade nuclear material. The latest decision by Moscow in 2014, obviously influenced by the Ukraine crisis, to end the last remains of nuclear security cooperation with the United States65 is a serious setback for efforts to halt nuclear proliferation. Prior to the decision, Moscow had already refused to extend the 20-years old Cooperative Threat Reduction Program (CTR) in 2012. Under the program, initiated at the end of the Cold War, surplus Russian nuclear bombers, missiles, submarines and warheads were dismantled, fissile material safeguarded and sensitive sites upgraded with the newest security technology. In the midst of the chaotic breakup of the USSR this U.S.-sponsored initiative was key to preventing the uncontrolled spread of nuclear materials and knowledge. The end of CTR and the latest decision to cut off nuclear security cooperation with the United States signal the departure of Russia from multi-national efforts to secure nuclear materials and a return to the imperative of national safeguarding policies. Other states could follow this example, which would essentially mean that the successful U.S. policy of collecting nuclear weapon-grade materials under the framework of the Nuclear Security Summits might come to an end as well.
Cooperative arms control generate relations ‘in which disputes are expected but within limits of agreed upon norms . , non-compliance is only the final stage of political decisions culminating in exit . Gorbachev decided to seek coop with the West . the U S pursue preferred policies with Moscow while enlarging NATO ). results were Russian perceptions of inequality and non-compliance. during the 2000s, Russia started to exit arms control . with three rounds of enlargement coop did not take place due to offensive U.S. policy Moscow never achieved its overriding goal of an end to enlargement. Russian notions of injustice are linked to enlargement decay of a c in Europe create a domino effect of non-prolif . the NPT binds n w s to negotiat in good faith . U.S.-Russia arsenals account for 90 percent worldwide. This increases mutual responsibility to lead global disarm . Both have done so since the Cold War. erosion of nuclear dialogue might throw the NPT out of balance. neither disarm nor a Middle East WMD-free zone has become reality. . If the two largest possessors freeze their commitments the treaty as a whole might erode quickly . A stalemate would serve as a smokescreen for Arab states to exit the NPT. efforts to prevent spread of nuclear materials might suffer applies as well to trans-national terrorist s
Cooperative arms control in Europe is basically a neologism consisting of the terms ‘cooperative security’ and ‘arms control’. The concept of cooperative security is understood to include a number of central tenets.2 It aims at increasing mutual security and predictability through reciprocity, inclusiveness, dialogue, a defensive orientation, transparency, confidence-building, and arms limitations.3 These central tenets are intended to help generate interstate relations ‘in which disputes are expected to occur, but they are expected to do so within the limits of agreed upon norms and established procedures.’4 The politics of cooperative security in Europe have often been identified with the institution of the OSCE.5 The concept of arms control is very closely related to this. Bull sees ‘peace through the manipulation of force’6 as the grand scheme under which to place the concept theoretically. In relation to the early period of the bipolar arms race, arms control’s foremost objective was the prevention of (nuclear) war.7 In a more operational sense, arms control is ‘any agreement among states to regulate some aspect of their military capability or potential. The agreement may apply to the location, amount, readiness, or types of military forces, weapons, or facilities. Whatever their scope or terms, however, all plans for arms control have one common factor: they presuppose some form of cooperation or joint action among participants with respect to their military programs.’8 With the end of the Cold War standoff, the ‘manipulation of force’, that is power, gave way to a more normative connotation of shaping and governing peace through a whole range of institutions of which most of them – though not all – are found within the framework of the OSCE. And this is where the two concepts meet. Combining the two is an attempt to analyze two concepts which are technically in very close proximity, but whose theoretical origins link the concept – strongly influenced by American realism – of manipulating power with the normative concept, originating in Europe, of governing peace. This effort is intended to help analyze two basic premises of international cooperation – that is that ‘political action must be based on a coordination of morality and power.’9 The genesis of cooperative arms control in Europe can be traced back to the final days of détente. In 1973, Moscow accepted the long-standing U.S. demand to enter into talks about conventional forces in Europe to address the imbalance in the conventional realm, which was to the detriment of the United States and its NATO allies. The talks, known as Mutual and Balanced Force Reduction (MBFR) talks, continued for almost 16 years without any concrete result and were finally replaced by the CFE negotiations in 1989. For the Soviet Union, amongst the reasons for agreeing to MBFR was the start of formal negotiations on the mandate for a Conference on Security and Cooperation in Europe (CSCE) in 1972. MBFR and the CSCE can be seen as ‘two sprouts from one bulb.’10 The one ‘sprout’, MBFR, dealt with manipulating power at a largely bilateral, U.S.-Soviet, level. The other was multilateral in nature and sought to create a normative framework for securing a “cold peace”. The latter achieved a voluntary and, thus, fragile balancing act between the Soviet demand to devise status quo-cementing principles such as the ‘indivisibility of security’ and the ‘non-interference in internal affairs’11 and the Western demand for individual human rights. Over the next forty years, and particularly in the first few years following the end of the Cold War, a dense network of overlapping agreements, a regime complex in the most recent understanding of complexity research12, developed. Five elemental regimes form the complex of cooperative arms control in Europe. The first regime evolved around conventional arms control and was kick-started by MBFR. It acquired its full shape with the end of the Cold War and the signing of CFE in 1990 and a number of accompanying agreements, such as the Treaty on Open Skies, a monitoring instrument.13 The regime was updated at the end of the 1990s, but today it is extremely outdated technically and politically deadlocked due to disputes between Washington and Moscow. The second regime developed in the realm of confidence- and security-building measures (CSBMs) and has its roots in the 1975 Helsinki accords. It evolved through the Stockholm Conference on CSBMs and Disarmament in Europe (1984-1986) and acquired its full shape during the early 1990s with the elaboration of a whole range of politically binding agreements – most prominently the Vienna Document (VD).14 Today, the regime is still functioning, but some of the instruments, such as the VD, are in need of a timely update to better address contemporary security challenges, such as the employment of forces without national insignia as seen in the Russian annexation of Crimea. The third regime developed in the realm of political and military cooperation under the auspices of NATO. It includes cooperation mechanisms, such as the Partnership for Peace framework, the Euro-Atlantic Partnership Council, the NATO-Russia Founding Act, and the NATO-Russia Council (NRC).15 Today, the regime is functioning where military and political cooperation mechanisms involving third states are concerned. In NATO’s political and military dealings with Russia, the regime is dysfunctional and politically deadlocked. The most obvious example is the NRC which has been suspended by NATO member states at the working level as a reaction to Russian actions in Ukraine. The fourth regime emerged out of the need to achieve sub-regional stability for the war-torn countries of the Balkans.16 In a top-down approach led by the United States, important elements of the regime were designed along the lines of the CFE Treaty and the VD. This regime is still functioning. As inductive research has shown17, all four regimes share a significant number of principles and norms.18 Some of them were already listed almost word for word in the 1975 CSCE Helsinki Decalogue. The conclusion is that the historical roots of the regime complex are in the Helsinki accords. This influence on the meta-level of key principles and norms did not stop with the Helsinki stipulations, but was continuously fostered through their repetition and extension in the declaratory agreements of the CSCE and later the OSCE, particularly in the Charter of Paris for a New Europe (1990) and the Charter for European Security (1999) and in the organization of the OSCE itself. Their significance for the overall regime complex points to a special position within this complex, which can be described as a ‘meta-regime’19. Thereby, the fifth and most important regime is a meta-regime in the sense of a constant multiplier and reinforcer of principles and norms, informing the whole complex. Applying network analysis,20 the normative CSCE/OSCE stipulations and their organizational manifestation (the OSCE) form an overarching canon of values which frames the whole regime complex. Below this meta-regime, a dense regime complex of four regimes with a high degree of interaction among the different nodes (the regimes) of the complex is present. The nodes are interconnected through links at different levels. Links refer to interactions at the level of crossshared principles and norms, political-historical linkages, direct references of a design and/or textual nature, and partially overlapping membership21. Latest basic research has shown that the complex displays a high degree of density and a low degree of centrality.22 On the one hand, interactions among the nodes are frequent and lively. On the other hand, no node has considerably more links than the others. The regime complex of cooperative arms control in Europe is, thus, neither centralized nor fragmented, but displays a high degree of density. As already mentioned, the regimes on conventional arms control, CSBMs under the auspices of the OSCE, and political-military cooperation under the auspices of NATO, all show increasing signs of decay – though, to different degrees. During the last 15 years, signs of decay have rapidly increased and have reached a peak with the Ukraine conflict. In addition, the OSCE meta-regime of principles and norms is very badly affected. Every time a key principle or norm of cooperative arms control in Europe is violated, the meta-regime suffers indirectly. Almost all key principles or norms of cooperative arms control in Europe have been violated in the ongoing Ukraine conflict.23 All in all, the whole complex itself is characterized by decay. The Reasons for Decay The decay of institutionalized cooperation can be approached from different theoretical angles. In order to stick with Carr’s dictum of the importance of power and morality, let us first turn to a number of realist variables addressing questions of power. The first variable is non-compliance. Non-compliance – or as rationalists would put it – the “incentive to cheat” – is a crucial factor furthering cooperation decay.24 When speaking of cooperative arms control in Europe, increasing acts of non-compliance almost always involve Russia. Be it the illegal annexation of Crimea and the (covert) resort to force in Eastern Ukraine, the five-day war with Georgia in 2008, or the “suspension” of CFE in 2007 (an action not in accordance with the formal stipulations of the treaty)25, Russia has always been a problematic actor when it comes to compliance. However, non-compliance is usually only the final stage in a sequential process of political decisions culminating in the decision to exit from a cooperative agreement. Even more so, Russian non-compliance is neither the sole nor the most important reason behind institutional decay. The second variable was the massive shift in U.S.-Soviet/Russian capabilities in conjunction with the end of the Cold War. This shift had a cooperation-enabling and (over the long term) a cooperation-disabling effect. On the one hand, it led the Soviet Union under Gorbachev to focus relatively more on the economic capabilities of the USSR than on the military. Against the background of rapidly declining economic capabilities, Moscow decided to prioritize the economy and seek cooperation with the West. Gorbachev’s aim was to downsize the costly Soviet military and to get economic and financial aid from the West in return.26 On the other hand, the loss of relative capabilities on the Soviet side left Washington with relatively more capabilities. Against the background of the relative Soviet – and later Russian – weakness, the United States could largely pursue its preferred policies in its dealings with Moscow while, at the same time, negating Russian core interests (such as not enlarging NATO further to the East). The results were Russian perceptions of inequality, dissatisfaction with the post-Cold War security design of Europe, continued calls for re-negotiation, protracted negotiations, and increasing acts of non-compliance. After another minor shift in economic capabilities with the relative recovery of the Russian economy during the 2000s, Russia started to (partially) exit from the institutions of cooperative arms control in Europe. The third variable stems from the increasingly offensive orientation of the United States since the end of the Cold War. According to Robert Jervis, offensively-oriented states complicate cooperation.27 From 1994 onwards, the United States acted in accordance with this orientation, which resulted in further change to the existing relative distribution of power in Europe – with the three rounds of NATO enlargement (1999, 2004, and 2009). Direct cooperation between Washington and Moscow on enlargement did not take place due to the offensive orientation of U.S. policy.28 However, tacitly, Washington sought to cushion Russia’s unease with enlargement through cooperative arms control in Europe. The establishment of the 1997 NATO-Russia Founding Act, the adaptation of CFE, and the adaptation of the OSCE were all measures designed to accommodate Moscow and to support the weak Yeltsin government at home.29 At the same time, Washington rejected Russian counterproposals (such as replacing NATO with the OSCE)30 and linked important strands of the defensively-oriented normative policy of cooperative security to a power policy which was offensive in nature (i.e. enlargement). These interlinked policies not only led, over time, to increased Russian frustration31 but deprived Russia de facto of an equal say in all European security matters. The fourth variable responsible for decay was a loss of interest by both sides. Both states shared an overriding interest in cooperation throughout the Cold War due to – according to Realism – their mutual concern about survival in conjunction with the scenario of mutual assured destruction.32 The mutual interest in cooperation continued in the direct post-Cold War period – though for different reasons: Russia for economic reasons, the United States – under Bill Clinton – because it was concerned about possible backsliding of Russia into authoritarianism if the Yeltsin government would fail.33 With the 9/11 attacks, the survival concern of Washington finally shifted away from Russia to the War on Terror and the Islamic World and, later, towards a rising China. Russia dropped out of focus. Cooperation with Moscow was not a direct priority anymore. In turn, Moscow under Putin shifted its priority towards economic consolidation and strengthening its influence in the Near Abroad. This mutual diminished interest in cooperation led to the U.S. perception that issues of European security were basically non-problematic in nature and, later, to mutually non-compromising behavior when it came to issue-specific divergent interests, such as in the cases of CFE, the future of NATO, or the on-going conflict over Ukraine. The fifth variable was the constant rejection of Russian core interests. Russian calls for renegotiating elements of the post-Cold War security architecture or the system as a whole have been apparent from the mid-1990s onwards.34 They contributed to the adaptation of CFE, failed efforts to achieve a legal personality for the OSCE in the second half of the 1990s, and the establishment of the NRC in 2002. They increased within the OSCE during the 2000s and culminated in the two unsuccessful security treaty drafts by Dmitry Medvedev in 2008 and the ensuing so-called Corfu Process of the OSCE.35 Russian calls for re-negotiation were, thus, partially successful. However, Moscow never achieved its (indirect) overriding goal of either subordinating NATO to a higher security institution or codifying an end to NATO enlargement. Washington and its allies continued to resist any such attempt. This fact only deepened Russian dissatisfaction. Beyond realist power variables, aspects of morality contributed to institutional decay as well. Particularly with respect to the normative foundations of cooperative arms control in Europe, there is a precarious mix of divergent interpretations of norms, norm-challenging speech and behavior, and notions of injustice. The first aspect stems from the inequitable distribution of gains from cooperation. Inequity can lead to dissatisfaction with cooperation.36 As explained above, Moscow did not achieve its preferred interest in the different processes of cooperation with the United States on the design of post-Cold War European security. Here, realism has little to offer, apart from insisting that the distribution of gains is always relative to the underlying relative distribution of power.37 Nevertheless, this assumption does not change the fact that Russia feels it is being treated unfairly – an assessment which has led to increasingly negative ramifications. Identifying a pivotal moment of the start of Russian perceptions of inequity is extremely hard. In hindsight, the 1999 NATO air strikes against the Federal Republic of Yugoslavia seemed to have a crucial impact on Moscow.38 Since then, Russian statements delivered to the OSCE have been full of complaints about double standards and the unevenly directed critique of the organization in relation to its so-called “third basket”, which addresses human rights issues.39 The continued calls by Russia for re-negotiation are indicative of the Russian perception of being treated unequally. The most prominent example of vocal dissatisfaction was the 2007 Munich Security Conference speech of Vladimir Putin.40 The second aspect is the presence of institutional birth defects. According to institutionalists, intra-regime contradictions can significantly constrain successful institutionalized cooperation.41 Intra-regime contradictions are included in the 1975 Helsinki accords. The first Helsinki principle speaks of ‘sovereign equality [and the] respect for the rights inherent in sovereignty’. This principle explicitly includes the right ‘to be or not to be a party to bilateral or multilateral treaties including the right to be or not to be a party to treaties of alliance’. It follows directly after recognition in the preamble of the ‘indivisibility of security in Europe’42. Over the years, both stipulations have become key principles of the regime complex of cooperative arms control in Europe. The agreements of the regime of political-military cooperation under the auspices of NATO, in particular, have made the principle of the ‘indivisibility of security’ a central declaratory element of the new post-Cold War order.43 These two principles are still at the declaratory heart of the regime complex of cooperative arms control in Europe. In relation to each other, they form a classic paragon of an internal contradiction as every party could basically find any sovereign decision of any other party to join any treaty or alliance to be an infringement on its security and hence as contrary to the indivisibility of security. Lawyers call such discrepancy a contradictio in adjecto. This example shows that the Helsinki accords were designed to allow for a declaratory understanding against the background of strongly divergent interests. Since the Helsinki accords are at the heart of the normative basis of the regime complex, they continue to have declaratory validity 40 years later. Their partially contradictory nature allows for diverse understandings and divergent interpretations of the normative base, serves as a reference frame for continued Russian calls for re-negotiation, and even allows justifying acts of non-compliance with reference to divergent interpretations of the normative basis44 The third aspect is divergence in norm interpretation. Divergent interpretations of norms can complicate institutionalized cooperation. Nevertheless, they are quite common in international cooperative efforts.45 They are not a problem as long as states are able to bring their divergent interpretations in line constructively. On cooperative arms control in Europe, they have led to justifications of divergent interests and acts of non-compliance, most visibly in the on-going Ukraine conflict. As an example, Russia’s occupation of parts of Ukraine has been interpreted by most Ukrainian and Western politicians as destabilizing, not just for Ukraine, but also for the Russian-Ukrainian relationship as well as for NATO-Russian relations.46 From the Russian perspective, it is the possible prospect of future NATO membership of Ukraine which is perceived as de-stabilizing.47 In essence, the two do not share a common understanding of the Helsinki norm of ‘strengthening stability’ and interpret “stability” quite differently. Qualitative assessment of U. S. and Russian statements to the OSCE shows that a number of key norms have constantly been subject to divergent interpretations since the late 1990s.48 This fact leads to the assumption that Moscow and Washington (almost) never really shared a common understanding of key principles and norms of the regime complex. The fourth aspect is what critical constructivists have identified as a cooperation-disabling interplay between norm-challenging speech and norm-challenging behavior.49 Acts of normchallenging speech have occurred increasingly on the Russian side from the late 1990s onwards in the forum of the OSCE.50 Norm-challenging speech, as such, is already a problem because it incorporates the notion that something is fundamentally wrong with a certain norm. Normchallenging speech in conjunction with justice claims is a particularly salient type of norm contestation.51 Russian notions of injustice and inequality are linked to NATO enlargement, the U.S. foreign and security policy which, Russia claims, employs double standards, and the role of the OSCE.52 The consequences of the Russian notions of being treated unfairly have been increasing acts of norm-challenging speech, a (partial) retreat from the institutional structures of cooperative security, and the (partial) ignoring of the normative basis of the regime complex. The repeated and increasing use of norm-challenging speech has actively prepared the way for norm-challenging behavior. Both the United States and Russia have acted as norm challengers at different times. In conjunction with NATO enlargement (in the Russian perception a U.S. violation of the principle of the ‘indivisibility of security’), the 1999 Yugoslavia bombing53, the Russian CFE “suspension”, the Russian-Georgian war of 2008, and the annexation of Crimea, both states have challenged existing normative injunctions, which are inherent parts of the regime complex. Since these states are the two main actors in the institutionalized system of cooperative arms control in Europe and since both have repeatedly and increasingly challenged existing norms, their actions are all the more serious. The decay of the institutions of cooperative arms control in Europe was not the reason for the current Ukraine conflict. However, it provided fertile ground for the crisis to spiral out of control. Without CFE and its successor (ACFE), no meaningful transparency mechanisms or limitations for the Russian military buildup at the Ukrainian border are available. The politically binding stipulations of the VD are not designed to address the current situation. Efforts to craft more intrusive transparency measures for the VD have failed in the past.54 Suspending the NRC at the working level has deprived NATO member states of an important forum for communication with Russia. The deadlocked OSCE still provides the only forum. However, due to its consensus design, the OSCE is dependent on the general political climate between the West and Russia. In addition, the neglect of the security dimension of that organization by the United States during the last 15 years has left the OSCE with few and mostly outdated policy instruments to address the conflict. Taken together, unconstrained power, conflicting ambitions for power, and a long process of normative erosion has led to the decay of the regime complex of cooperative arms control in Europe. The two key players in European security affairs have contributed substantially to that process. Since the end of the 1990s, the United States and NATO have failed to achieve a coordination of power with respect to Russia. By disengaging from the power realm of arms control – most notably through non-ratification of ACFE55 – and the continued policy of expanding NATO’s frontiers the West has contributed to the whole system of cooperative arms control in Europe getting out of balance. At the same time, Russian policy has increasingly lacked any co-ordination of morality, as can be seen in the manifold norm violations in conjunction with the Ukraine conflict but also in earlier instances.56 As long as neither is able to adjust their diverging positions on power and morality, misunderstandings and the de facto potential for hidden or open conflict will continue to thwart meaningful cooperation on European security. The Ramifications for the Global Nuclear Order The European security crisis in conjunction with the Ukraine conflict is not an isolated case. What is additionally worrisome is the fact that the conflict is about to create a negative domino effect at the level of multilateral nuclear arms control, disarmament, and non-proliferation governance. The first effects will become obvious at the 2015 Review Conference of the Treaty on the Non-Proliferation of Nuclear Weapons (NPT). They might increase over time and could seriously affect the global nuclear order. Four aspects of the Ukraine conflict are particularly worrisome for the international community. The first aspect concerns international efforts to prevent additional states from acquiring a nuclear weapons capability. Since the beginning of the nuclear age, nuclear weapons have, at least to some extent, promised an enhanced survival guarantee for the possessors against conventional attack. This perception notwithstanding, there are other powerful arguments to go nuclear, such as prestige, international status, and the political leverage that comes with nuclear weapons possession.57 However, the survival concern will always be central to any possible international negotiations aimed at convincing states not to acquire a nuclear weapons capability. Negative security assurances by the official nuclear weapons possessors have been a meaningful political instrument in that process. In the past, this was particularly the case in conjunction with the breakup of the Soviet Union. The Russian annexation of Crimea and the covert incursions into Eastern Ukraine are, thus, not only violations of international and, particularly, European legal norms, they are also a breach of the negative security assurances Russia, the United States and the United Kingdom gave to the new Ukrainian state in 1994. Under the so called Budapest Memorandum58, Kyiv gave up its approximately 1,800 nuclear warheads and joined NPT and the START I agreements in exchange for official recognition of its sovereignty and territorial integrity.59 The Machiavellian impudence with which Russia has broken these promises in March 2014 sets an extremely negative precedent for the further value of negative security assurances. States such as Iran or North Korea will have closely watched Moscow devaluing these political instruments. They might already have drawn their lessons from this. The second aspect is the prospect of a prolonged stalemate in further nuclear reductions between the United States and Russia. Article VI of the NPT binds all officially recognized nuclear weapon states to pursue negotiations in good faith, with the aim of the total elimination of nuclear weapons. Today, U.S.-Russian arsenals still account for over 90 percent of all nuclear weapons worldwide.60 This fact alone increases the mutual responsibility of Washington and Moscow to continue to lead global nuclear disarmament efforts. Both have done so since the end of the Cold War. The latest New START agreement sets equal ceilings of 1,550 nuclear warheads for each side.61 New START stipulates that these limits be reached by February 2018. The Ukraine crisis has not only dashed hopes that both could pursue a follow-on agreement with even lower ceilings, as put forward in a public proposal by Barack Obama in 201362 but recent voices from Moscow seem to indicate that Russia might reconsider its stance towards the agreement if the current conflict continues.63 The stalemate and even possible erosion of the U.S.-Russian nuclear disarmament dialogue might well throw the precarious NPT bargain out of balance. This bargain is of a rather inequitable nature with five states (China, France, Russia, the United Kingdom, and the United States) allowed to possess nuclear weapons, while the others are not. In order to alleviate concerns over this obvious double standard and allow for universal ratification, non-nuclear-weapon States have pressed for inclusion of the disarmament clause. In 1995, NPT Parties to the Treaty agreed to an indefinite extension of the treaty in exchange for increased commitments by the nuclear possessors to pursue nuclear disarmament and to contribute to negotiations on a Middle East zone free of nuclear weapons as well as other weapons of mass destruction (WMD).64 Twenty years later, neither the complete disarmament commitment nor a Middle East WMD-free zone has become reality. For obvious reasons, the Arab States, in particular, have been dissatisfied with the general state of the treaty for a long time already. If, in addition, the two largest nuclear weapons possessors freeze their disarmament commitments, the NPT bargain and the treaty as a whole might erode more quickly than anticipated. A possible U.S.-Russian stalemate in disarmament efforts would serve as a good smokescreen for Arab states to voice their continued dissatisfaction and to seek – under worst circumstances – exit to the NPT. The third factor is closely related to the NPT disarmament clause. Without a balanced and operational NPT in place, efforts to prevent the spread of nuclear weapons and nuclear materials might seriously suffer as well. What pertains to the level of state-led efforts to acquire a nuclear weapons capability (as in the case of Iran) applies as well to criminal trans-national networks and terrorist groups struggling to obtain weapons-grade nuclear material. The latest decision by Moscow in 2014, obviously influenced by the Ukraine crisis, to end the last remains of nuclear security cooperation with the United States65 is a serious setback for efforts to halt nuclear proliferation. Prior to the decision, Moscow had already refused to extend the 20-years old Cooperative Threat Reduction Program (CTR) in 2012. Under the program, initiated at the end of the Cold War, surplus Russian nuclear bombers, missiles, submarines and warheads were dismantled, fissile material safeguarded and sensitive sites upgraded with the newest security technology. In the midst of the chaotic breakup of the USSR this U.S.-sponsored initiative was key to preventing the uncontrolled spread of nuclear materials and knowledge. The end of CTR and the latest decision to cut off nuclear security cooperation with the United States signal the departure of Russia from multi-national efforts to secure nuclear materials and a return to the imperative of national safeguarding policies. Other states could follow this example, which would essentially mean that the successful U.S. policy of collecting nuclear weapon-grade materials under the framework of the Nuclear Security Summits might come to an end as well.
30,783
<h4>Otherwise—enlargement fuels <u>arms control failure</u> from <u>cheating</u> and <u>pullout</u>—that wrecks <u>NPT norms</u>, causing <u>proliferation</u>.</h4><p><u><strong>Kuhn 16</u></strong>—(PhD in political science from Hamburg University, senior researcher at the Institute for Peace Research and Security Policy at the University of Hamburg). Ulrich Kuhn. 2016. Cornell University, Reppy Institute. Selected Essays on the Transition to a New Nuclear Order. “Cooperative Arms Control in Europe and the Global Nuclear Order: Rethinking Decision-Making and Institutions in Light of the Ukraine Conflict.” https://pacs.einaudi.cornell.edu/sites/pacs/files/Selected%20Essays.OP%2032_0.pdf.</p><p><u><strong><mark>Cooperative arms control</u></strong></mark> in Europe is basically a neologism consisting of the terms ‘cooperative security’ and ‘arms control’. The concept of cooperative security is understood to include a number of central tenets.2 It <u><strong>aims at increasing mutual security and predictability through reciprocity, inclusiveness, dialogue, a defensive orientation, transparency, confidence-building, and arms limitations</u></strong>.3 <u><strong>These central tenets are intended to help <mark>generate</mark> interstate <mark>relations ‘in which disputes are expected </mark>to occur, <mark>but </mark>they are expected to do so <mark>within </mark>the <mark>limits of agreed upon norms </mark>and established procedures<mark>.</u></strong></mark>’4 The politics of cooperative security in Europe have often been identified with the institution of the OSCE.5 The concept of arms control is very closely related to this. Bull sees ‘peace through the manipulation of force’6 as the grand scheme under which to place the concept theoretically. In relation to the early period of the bipolar arms race, arms control’s foremost objective was the prevention of (nuclear) war.7 In a more operational sense, arms control is ‘any agreement among states to regulate some aspect of their military capability or potential. The agreement may apply to the location, amount, readiness, or types of military forces, weapons, or facilities. Whatever their scope or terms, however, all plans for arms control have one common factor: they presuppose some form of cooperation or joint action among participants with respect to their military programs.’8 With the end of the Cold War standoff, the ‘manipulation of force’, that is power, gave way to a more normative connotation of shaping and governing peace through a whole range of institutions of which most of them – though not all – are found within the framework of the OSCE. And this is where the two concepts meet. Combining the two is an attempt to analyze two concepts which are technically in very close proximity, but whose theoretical origins link the concept – strongly influenced by American realism – of manipulating power with the normative concept, originating in Europe, of governing peace. This effort is intended to help analyze two basic premises of international cooperation – that is that ‘political action must be based on a coordination of morality and power.’9 The genesis of cooperative arms control in Europe can be traced back to the final days of détente. In 1973, Moscow accepted the long-standing U.S. demand to enter into talks about conventional forces in Europe to address the imbalance in the conventional realm, which was to the detriment of the United States and its NATO allies. The talks, known as Mutual and Balanced Force Reduction (MBFR) talks, continued for almost 16 years without any concrete result and were finally replaced by the CFE negotiations in 1989. For the Soviet Union, amongst the reasons for agreeing to MBFR was the start of formal negotiations on the mandate for a Conference on Security and Cooperation in Europe (CSCE) in 1972. MBFR and the CSCE can be seen as ‘two sprouts from one bulb.’10 The one ‘sprout’, MBFR, dealt with manipulating power at a largely bilateral, U.S.-Soviet, level. The other was multilateral in nature and sought to create a normative framework for securing a “cold peace”. The latter achieved a voluntary and, thus, fragile balancing act between the Soviet demand to devise status quo-cementing principles such as the ‘indivisibility of security’ and the ‘non-interference in internal affairs’11 and the Western demand for individual human rights. Over the next forty years, and particularly in the first few years following the end of the Cold War, a dense network of overlapping agreements, a regime complex in the most recent understanding of complexity research12, developed. Five elemental regimes form the complex of cooperative arms control in Europe. The first regime evolved around conventional arms control and was kick-started by MBFR. It acquired its full shape with the end of the Cold War and the signing of CFE in 1990 and a number of accompanying agreements, such as the Treaty on Open Skies, a monitoring instrument.13 The regime was updated at the end of the 1990s, but today it is extremely outdated technically and politically deadlocked due to disputes between Washington and Moscow. The second regime developed in the realm of confidence- and security-building measures (CSBMs) and has its roots in the 1975 Helsinki accords. It evolved through the Stockholm Conference on CSBMs and Disarmament in Europe (1984-1986) and acquired its full shape during the early 1990s with the elaboration of a whole range of politically binding agreements – most prominently the Vienna Document (VD).14 Today, the regime is still functioning, but some of the instruments, such as the VD, are in need of a timely update to better address contemporary security challenges, such as the employment of forces without national insignia as seen in the Russian annexation of Crimea. The third regime developed in the realm of political and military cooperation under the auspices of NATO. It includes cooperation mechanisms, such as the Partnership for Peace framework, the Euro-Atlantic Partnership Council, the NATO-Russia Founding Act, and the NATO-Russia Council (NRC).15 Today, the regime is functioning where military and political cooperation mechanisms involving third states are concerned. In NATO’s political and military dealings with Russia, the regime is dysfunctional and politically deadlocked. The most obvious example is the NRC which has been suspended by NATO member states at the working level as a reaction to Russian actions in Ukraine. The fourth regime emerged out of the need to achieve sub-regional stability for the war-torn countries of the Balkans.16 In a top-down approach led by the United States, important elements of the regime were designed along the lines of the CFE Treaty and the VD. This regime is still functioning. As inductive research has shown17, all four regimes share a significant number of principles and norms.18 Some of them were already listed almost word for word in the 1975 CSCE Helsinki Decalogue. The conclusion is that the historical roots of the regime complex are in the Helsinki accords. This influence on the meta-level of key principles and norms did not stop with the Helsinki stipulations, but was continuously fostered through their repetition and extension in the declaratory agreements of the CSCE and later the OSCE, particularly in the Charter of Paris for a New Europe (1990) and the Charter for European Security (1999) and in the organization of the OSCE itself. Their significance for the overall regime complex points to a special position within this complex, which can be described as a ‘meta-regime’19. Thereby, the fifth and most important regime is a meta-regime in the sense of a constant multiplier and reinforcer of principles and norms, informing the whole complex. Applying network analysis,20 the normative CSCE/OSCE stipulations and their organizational manifestation (the OSCE) form an overarching canon of values which frames the whole regime complex. Below this meta-regime, a dense regime complex of four regimes with a high degree of interaction among the different nodes (the regimes) of the complex is present. The nodes are interconnected through links at different levels. Links refer to interactions at the level of crossshared principles and norms, political-historical linkages, direct references of a design and/or textual nature, and partially overlapping membership21. Latest basic research has shown that the complex displays a high degree of density and a low degree of centrality.22 On the one hand, interactions among the nodes are frequent and lively. On the other hand, no node has considerably more links than the others. The regime complex of cooperative arms control in Europe is, thus, neither centralized nor fragmented, but displays a high degree of density. As already mentioned, the regimes on conventional arms control, CSBMs under the auspices of the OSCE, and political-military cooperation under the auspices of NATO, all show increasing signs of decay – though, to different degrees. During the last 15 years, signs of decay have rapidly increased and have reached a peak with the Ukraine conflict. In addition, the OSCE meta-regime of principles and norms is very badly affected. Every time a key principle or norm of cooperative arms control in Europe is violated, the meta-regime suffers indirectly. Almost all key principles or norms of cooperative arms control in Europe have been violated in the ongoing Ukraine conflict.23 All in all, the whole complex itself is characterized by decay. The Reasons for Decay The decay of institutionalized cooperation can be approached from different theoretical angles. In order to stick with Carr’s dictum of the importance of power and morality, <u><strong>let us first turn to a number of realist variables addressing questions of power. The first variable is non-compliance.</u></strong> Non-compliance – or as rationalists would put it – the “incentive to cheat” – is a crucial factor furthering cooperation decay.24 When speaking of cooperative arms control in Europe, increasing acts of non-compliance almost always involve Russia. Be it the illegal annexation of Crimea and the (covert) resort to force in Eastern Ukraine, the five-day war with Georgia in 2008, or the “suspension” of CFE in 2007 (an action not in accordance with the formal stipulations of the treaty)25, Russia has always been a problematic actor when it comes to compliance. However<mark>,<u><strong></mark> <mark>non-compliance is</mark> usually <mark>only the final stage</mark> in a sequential process <mark>of political decisions culminating in</mark> </u></strong>the decision to<u><strong> <mark>exit </mark>from a cooperative agreement<mark>.</u></strong></mark> Even more so,<u><strong> Russian non-compliance is neither the sole nor the most important reason behind institutional decay. The second variable was the </u></strong>massive<u><strong> shift in U.S.-Soviet/Russian capabilities </u></strong>in conjunction<u><strong> with the end of the Cold War. This </u></strong>shift<u><strong> had </u></strong>a cooperation-enabling and<u><strong> (over the long term) a cooperation-disabling effect. </u></strong>On the one hand,<u><strong> it led </u></strong>the Soviet Union under<u><strong> <mark>Gorbachev</mark> </u></strong>to focus relatively more on the economic capabilities of the USSR than on the military.<u><strong> Against the </u></strong>background of<u><strong> rapidly declining economic capabilities</u></strong>, Moscow <u><strong><mark>decided to</mark> prioritize the economy and <mark>seek coop</mark>eration <mark>with the West</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong>Gorbachev’s aim was to downsize the costly Soviet military and to get </u></strong>economic and<u><strong> financial aid from the West in return<mark>.</u></strong></mark>26<u><strong> </u></strong>On the other hand, the loss of relative capabilities on the Soviet side left Washington with relatively more capabilities.<u><strong> Against the background of the relative </u></strong>Soviet – and later<u><strong> Russian </u></strong>– <u><strong>weakness, <mark>the U</mark>nited <mark>S</mark>tates could </u></strong>largely<u><strong> <mark>pursue</mark> its <mark>preferred policies</mark> in its dealings <mark>with Moscow while</mark>, at the same time, negating Russian core interests (such as not <mark>enlarging NATO </mark>further to the East<mark>). </mark>The <mark>results were Russian perceptions of inequality</mark>, dissatisfaction with </u></strong>the<u><strong> post-Cold War </u></strong>security design of<u><strong> Europe, continued calls for re-negotiation, protracted negotiations, <mark>and </mark>increasing acts of <mark>non-compliance.</mark> </u></strong>After another minor shift in economic capabilities with the relative recovery of the Russian economy <u><strong><mark>during the 2000s, Russia started to</mark> (partially) <mark>exit</mark> </u></strong>from the<u><strong> institutions of cooperative <mark>arms control</mark> in Europe<mark>.</mark> The third variable stems from the increasingly offensive orientation of the United States since the end of the Cold War. </u></strong>According to Robert Jervis,<u><strong> offensively-oriented states complicate cooperation.</u></strong>27<u><strong> From 1994 onwards, the United States acted in accordance with this orientation</u></strong>, which resulted in further change to the existing relative distribution of power in Europe –<u><strong> <mark>with</mark> </u></strong>the<u><strong> <mark>three rounds of </mark>NATO <mark>enlargement</mark> (1999, 2004, and 2009). </u></strong>Direct<u><strong> <mark>coop</mark>eration between Washington and Moscow on enlargement <mark>did not take place due to</mark> the <mark>offensive </mark>orientation of <mark>U.S. policy</mark>.</u></strong>28<u><strong> </u></strong>However, tacitly, Washington sought to cushion Russia’s unease with enlargement through cooperative arms control in Europe. The establishment of the 1997 NATO-Russia Founding Act, the adaptation of CFE, and the adaptation of the OSCE were all measures designed to accommodate Moscow and to support the weak Yeltsin government at home.29 At the same time,<u><strong> Washington </u></strong>rejected Russian counterproposals (such as replacing NATO with the OSCE)30 and<u><strong> linked </u></strong>important strands of<u><strong> the defensive</u></strong>ly-oriented normative <u><strong>policy of cooperative security to </u></strong>a power<u><strong> policy </u></strong>which was<u><strong> offensive in nature (i.e. enlargement). These </u></strong>interlinked policies not only<u><strong> led, over time, to increased Russian frustration</u></strong>31<u><strong> but deprived Russia de facto of an equal say in all European security matters. The fourth variable responsible for decay was a loss of interest by both sides. </u></strong>Both states shared an overriding interest in cooperation throughout the Cold War due to – according to Realism – their mutual concern about survival in conjunction with the scenario of mutual assured destruction.32 The mutual interest in cooperation continued in the direct post-Cold War period – though for different reasons: Russia for economic reasons, the United States – under Bill Clinton – because it was concerned about possible backsliding of Russia into authoritarianism if the Yeltsin government would fail.33 With the 9/11 attacks, the survival concern of Washington finally shifted away from Russia to the War on Terror and the Islamic World and, later, towards a rising China. Russia dropped out of focus. Cooperation with Moscow was not a direct priority anymore. In turn, Moscow under Putin shifted its priority towards economic consolidation and strengthening its influence in the Near Abroad. This mutual diminished interest in cooperation led to the U.S. perception that issues of European security were basically non-problematic in nature and, later, to mutually non-compromising behavior when it came to issue-specific divergent interests, such as in the cases of CFE, the future of NATO, or the on-going conflict over Ukraine.<u><strong> The fifth variable was the constant rejection of Russian core interests. Russian calls for renegotiating elements of the post-Cold War security architecture or the system as a whole have been apparent from the mid-1990s onwards.</u></strong>34<u><strong> </u></strong>They contributed to the adaptation of CFE, failed efforts to achieve a legal personality for the OSCE in the second half of the 1990s, and the establishment of the NRC in 2002. They increased within the OSCE during the 2000s and culminated in the two unsuccessful security treaty drafts by Dmitry Medvedev in 2008 and the ensuing so-called Corfu Process of the OSCE.35 Russian calls for re-negotiation were, thus, partially successful. However,<u><strong> <mark>Moscow never achieved its</mark> </u></strong>(indirect) <u><strong><mark>overriding goal of</mark> </u></strong>either subordinating NATO to a higher security institution or<u><strong> codifying <mark>an end to </mark>NATO <mark>enlargement.</mark> Washington and its allies continued to resist any such attempt. This fact only deepened Russian dissatisfaction. Beyond realist power variables</u></strong>, aspects of morality contributed to institutional decay as well. Particularly with respect to the normative foundations of cooperative arms control in Europe, there is a precarious mix of divergent interpretations of norms, norm-challenging speech and behavior, and notions of injustice. The first aspect stems from the inequitable distribution of gains from cooperation. Inequity can lead to dissatisfaction with cooperation.36 As explained above, Moscow did not achieve its preferred interest in the different processes of cooperation with the United States on the design of post-Cold War European security. Here, realism has little to offer, apart from insisting that the distribution of gains is always relative to the underlying relative distribution of power.37 Nevertheless, this assumption does not change the fact that<u><strong> Russia feels it is being treated unfairly – </u></strong>an assessment<u><strong> which has led to increasingly negative ramifications. </u></strong>Identifying a pivotal moment of the start of Russian perceptions of inequity is extremely hard. In hindsight, the 1999 NATO air strikes against the Federal Republic of Yugoslavia seemed to have a crucial impact on Moscow.38 Since then, Russian statements delivered to the OSCE have been full of complaints about double standards and the unevenly directed critique of the organization in relation to its so-called “third basket”, which addresses human rights issues.39 The continued calls by Russia for re-negotiation are indicative of the Russian perception of being treated unequally. The most prominent example of vocal dissatisfaction was the 2007 Munich Security Conference speech of Vladimir Putin.40 The second aspect is the presence of institutional birth defects. According to institutionalists, intra-regime contradictions can significantly constrain successful institutionalized cooperation.41 Intra-regime contradictions are included in the 1975 Helsinki accords. The first Helsinki principle speaks of ‘sovereign equality [and the] respect for the rights inherent in sovereignty’. This principle explicitly includes the right ‘to be or not to be a party to bilateral or multilateral treaties including the right to be or not to be a party to treaties of alliance’. It follows directly after recognition in the preamble of the ‘indivisibility of security in Europe’42. Over the years, both stipulations have become key principles of the regime complex of cooperative arms control in Europe. The agreements of the regime of political-military cooperation under the auspices of NATO, in particular, have made the principle of the ‘indivisibility of security’ a central declaratory element of the new post-Cold War order.43 These two principles are still at the declaratory heart of the regime complex of cooperative arms control in Europe. In relation to each other, they form a classic paragon of an internal contradiction as every party could basically find any sovereign decision of any other party to join any treaty or alliance to be an infringement on its security and hence as contrary to the indivisibility of security. Lawyers call such discrepancy a contradictio in adjecto. This example shows that the Helsinki accords were designed to allow for a declaratory understanding against the background of strongly divergent interests. Since the Helsinki accords are at the heart of the normative basis of the regime complex, they continue to have declaratory validity 40 years later. Their partially contradictory nature allows for diverse understandings and divergent interpretations of the normative base, serves as a reference frame for continued Russian calls for re-negotiation, and even allows justifying acts of non-compliance with reference to divergent interpretations of the normative basis44 The third aspect is divergence in norm interpretation. Divergent interpretations of norms can complicate institutionalized cooperation. Nevertheless, they are quite common in international cooperative efforts.45 They are not a problem as long as states are able to bring their divergent interpretations in line constructively. On cooperative arms control in Europe, they have led to justifications of divergent interests and acts of non-compliance, most visibly in the on-going Ukraine conflict. As an example, Russia’s occupation of parts of Ukraine has been interpreted by most Ukrainian and Western politicians as destabilizing, not just for Ukraine, but also for the Russian-Ukrainian relationship as well as for NATO-Russian relations.46 From the Russian perspective, it is the possible prospect of future NATO membership of Ukraine which is perceived as de-stabilizing.47 In essence, the two do not share a common understanding of the Helsinki norm of ‘strengthening stability’ and interpret “stability” quite differently. Qualitative assessment of U. S. and Russian statements to the OSCE shows that a number of key norms have constantly been subject to divergent interpretations since the late 1990s.48 This fact leads to the assumption that Moscow and Washington (almost) never really shared a common understanding of key principles and norms of the regime complex. The fourth aspect is what critical constructivists have identified as a cooperation-disabling interplay between norm-challenging speech and norm-challenging behavior.49 Acts of normchallenging speech have occurred increasingly on the Russian side from the late 1990s onwards in the forum of the OSCE.50 Norm-challenging speech, as such, is already a problem because it incorporates the notion that something is fundamentally wrong with a certain norm. Normchallenging speech in conjunction with justice claims is a particularly salient type of norm contestation.51 <u><strong><mark>Russian notions of injustice </mark>and inequality <mark>are linked to </mark>NATO <mark>enlargement</u></strong></mark>, the U.S. foreign and security policy which, Russia claims, employs double standards, and the role of the OSCE<u><strong>.</u></strong>52 <u><strong>The consequences of the Russian notions of being treated unfairly have been </u></strong>increasing acts of norm-challenging speech, a (partial)<u><strong> retreat from </u></strong>the<u><strong> institutional </u></strong>structures of<u><strong> cooperative security, and</u></strong> the (partial) ignoring of the normative basis of the regime complex. The repeated and increasing use of norm-challenging speech has actively prepared the way for<u><strong> norm-challenging behavior. Both the United States and Russia have acted as norm challengers </u></strong>at different times<u><strong>. In conjunction with NATO enlargement </u></strong>(in the Russian perception a U.S. violation of the principle of the ‘indivisibility of security’), <u><strong>the 1999 Yugoslavia bombing</u></strong>53<u><strong>, the Russian CFE “suspension”, the Russian-Georgian war of 2008, and the annexation of Crimea, both states have challenged existing normative injunctions</u></strong>, which are inherent parts of the regime complex. Since these states are the two main actors in the institutionalized system of cooperative arms control in Europe and since both have repeatedly and increasingly challenged existing norms, their actions are all the more serious. The decay of the institutions of cooperative arms control in Europe was not the reason for the current Ukraine conflict. However, it provided fertile ground for the crisis to spiral out of control. Without CFE and its successor (ACFE), no meaningful transparency mechanisms or limitations for the Russian military buildup at the Ukrainian border are available. The politically binding stipulations of the VD are not designed to address the current situation. Efforts to craft more intrusive transparency measures for the VD have failed in the past.54 Suspending the NRC at the working level has deprived NATO member states of an important forum for communication with Russia. The deadlocked OSCE still provides the only forum. However, due to its consensus design, the OSCE is dependent on the general political climate between the West and Russia. In addition, the neglect of the security dimension of that organization by the United States during the last 15 years has left the OSCE with few and mostly outdated policy instruments to address the conflict.<u><strong> Taken together, unconstrained power, conflicting ambitions for power, and a long process of normative erosion has led to the <mark>decay</mark> of the regime complex <mark>of</mark> cooperative <mark>a</mark>rms <mark>c</mark>ontrol <mark>in Europe</mark>. The two key players in European security affairs have contributed substantially to that process.</u></strong> Since the end of the 1990s, the United States and NATO have failed to achieve a coordination of power with respect to Russia. By disengaging from the power realm of arms control – most notably through non-ratification of ACFE55 – and the continued policy of expanding NATO’s frontiers the West has contributed to the whole system of cooperative arms control in Europe getting out of balance. At the same time, Russian policy has increasingly lacked any co-ordination of morality, as can be seen in the manifold norm violations in conjunction with the Ukraine conflict but also in earlier instances.56 As long as neither is able to adjust their diverging positions on power and morality, misunderstandings and the de facto potential for hidden or open conflict will continue to thwart meaningful cooperation on European security. <u><strong>The Ramifications for the Global Nuclear Order The</u></strong> European security <u><strong>crisis</u></strong> in conjunction with the Ukraine conflict is not an isolated case. What is additionally worrisome is the fact that the conflict is about to<u><strong> <mark>create a </mark>negative <mark>domino effect</u></strong> <u><strong></mark>at the level <mark>of </mark>multilateral nuclear arms control, disarmament, and <mark>non-prolif</mark>eration governance<mark>.</u></strong></mark> The first effects will become obvious at the 2015 Review Conference of the Treaty on the Non-Proliferation of Nuclear Weapons (NPT). They might increase over time and could seriously affect the global nuclear order. Four aspects of the Ukraine conflict are particularly worrisome for the international community. <u><strong>The first aspect concerns international efforts to prevent </u></strong>additional<u><strong> states from acquiring a nuc</u></strong>lear weapons capability<u><strong>.</u></strong> Since the beginning of the nuclear age, nuclear weapons have, at least to some extent, promised an enhanced survival guarantee for the possessors against conventional attack. This perception notwithstanding, <u><strong>there are</u></strong> other <u><strong>powerful arguments to go nuclear</u></strong>, such as prestige, international status, and the political leverage that comes with nuclear weapons possession<u><strong>.</u></strong>57 <u><strong>However, the survival concern will always be central to any </u></strong>possible<u><strong> international negotiations aimed at convincing states not to acquire </u></strong>a <u><strong>nuclear weapons </u></strong>capability<u><strong>.</u></strong> Negative security assurances by the official nuclear weapons possessors have been a meaningful political instrument in that process. In the past, this was particularly the case in conjunction with the breakup of the Soviet Union. The Russian annexation of Crimea and the covert incursions into Eastern Ukraine are, thus, not only violations of international and, particularly, European legal norms, they are also a breach of the negative security assurances Russia, the United States and the United Kingdom gave to the new Ukrainian state in 1994. Under the so called Budapest Memorandum58, Kyiv gave up its approximately 1,800 nuclear warheads and joined NPT and the START I agreements in exchange for official recognition of its sovereignty and territorial integrity.59 The Machiavellian impudence with which Russia has broken these promises in March 2014 sets an extremely negative precedent for the further value of negative security assurances. States such as Iran or North Korea will have closely watched Moscow devaluing these political instruments. They might already have drawn their lessons from this. The second aspect is the prospect of <u><strong>a prolonged stalemate in further nuclear reductions between the United States and Russia. Article VI of <mark>the NPT binds</u></strong></mark> all <u><strong>officially recognized <mark>n</mark>uclear <mark>w</mark>eapon <mark>s</mark>tates <mark>to </mark>pursue <mark>negotiat</mark>ions<mark> in good faith</u></strong></mark>, <u><strong>with the aim of the total elimination of nuclear weapons<mark>.</u></strong></mark> Today, <u><strong><mark>U.S.-Russia</u></strong></mark>n<u><strong><mark> arsenals</mark> </u></strong>still<u><strong> <mark>account for </mark>over <mark>90 percent </mark>of all nuc</u></strong>lear weapon<u><strong>s <mark>worldwide.</u></strong></mark>60 <u><strong><mark>This</mark> </u></strong>fact alone <u><strong><mark>increases</mark> </u></strong>the <u><strong><mark>mutual responsibility</mark> of Washington and Moscow <mark>to</mark> continue to <mark>lead global</mark> nuclear <mark>disarm</mark>ament efforts<mark>. Both have done so since the </mark>end of the <mark>Cold War.</mark> </u></strong>The latest New START agreement sets equal ceilings of 1,550 nuclear warheads for each side.61 New START stipulates that these limits be reached by February 2018. The Ukraine crisis has not only dashed hopes that both could pursue a follow-on agreement with even lower ceilings, as put forward in a public proposal by Barack Obama in 201362 but recent voices from Moscow seem to indicate that Russia might reconsider its stance towards the agreement if the current conflict continues.63 <u><strong>The stalemate and even possible <mark>erosion of</mark> the U.S.-Russian <mark>nuclear</mark> disarmament <mark>dialogue might</mark> well <mark>throw the </mark>precarious <mark>NPT </mark>bargain <mark>out of balance.</mark> </u></strong>This bargain is of a rather inequitable nature with five states (China, France, Russia, the United Kingdom, and the United States) allowed to possess nuclear weapons, while the others are not. In order to alleviate concerns over this obvious double standard and allow for universal ratification, non-nuclear-weapon States have pressed for inclusion of the disarmament clause. In 1995, NPT Parties to the Treaty agreed to an indefinite extension of the treaty in exchange for increased commitments by the nuclear possessors to pursue nuclear disarmament and to contribute to negotiations on a Middle East zone free of nuclear weapons as well as other weapons of mass destruction (WMD).64 Twenty years later, <u><strong><mark>neither</mark> the complete <mark>disarm</mark>ament commitment <mark>nor a Middle East WMD-free zone has become reality.</u></strong></mark> For obvious reasons, <u><strong>the Arab States</u></strong>, in particular, <u><strong>have been dissatisfied </u></strong>with the general state of the treaty for a long time already<u><strong><mark>.</u></strong></mark> <u><strong><mark>If</mark>, in addition, <mark>the two largest </mark>nuclear weapons <mark>possessors freeze their</mark> disarmament <mark>commitments</mark>, the NPT bargain and <mark>the treaty as a whole might erode</mark> more <mark>quickly</u></strong></mark> than anticipated<u><strong><mark>. A</mark> possible U.S.-Russian <mark>stalemate</mark> in disarmament efforts <mark>would serve as a</mark> good <mark>smokescreen for Arab states to</mark> voice their continued dissatisfaction and to seek – under worst circumstances – <mark>exit</mark> to <mark>the NPT.</mark> </u></strong>The third factor is closely related to the NPT disarmament clause. <u><strong>Without a balanced and operational NPT in place</u></strong>, <u><strong><mark>efforts to prevent</mark> the <mark>spread of</mark> nuclear weapons and <mark>nuclear materials might</mark> seriously <mark>suffer</mark> as well. What pertains to the level of state-led efforts to acquire a nuclear weapons capability</u></strong> (as in the case of Iran) <u><strong><mark>applies as well to</mark> criminal <mark>trans-national</mark> networks and <mark>terrorist</mark> group<mark>s</strong></mark> struggling to obtain weapons-grade nuclear material. The latest decision by Moscow in 2014, obviously influenced by the Ukraine crisis, to end the last remains of nuclear security cooperation with the United States65 is a serious setback for efforts to halt nuclear proliferation. Prior to the decision, Moscow had already refused to extend the 20-years old Cooperative Threat Reduction Program (CTR) in 2012. Under the program, initiated at the end of the Cold War, surplus Russian nuclear bombers, missiles, submarines and warheads were dismantled, fissile material safeguarded and sensitive sites upgraded with the newest security technology. In the midst of the chaotic breakup of the USSR this U.S.-sponsored initiative was key to preventing the uncontrolled spread of nuclear materials and knowledge. The end of CTR and the latest decision to cut off nuclear security cooperation with the United States signal the departure of Russia from multi-national efforts to secure nuclear materials and a return to the imperative of national safeguarding policies. Other states could follow this example, which would essentially mean that the successful U.S. policy of collecting nuclear weapon-grade materials under the framework of the Nuclear Security Summits might come to an end as well.</p></u>
AFF Kentucky rd 5
Enlargement: 1AC—Send
AC: 1AC
770,732
173
51,791
./documents/ndtceda20/Minnesota/FrMo/Minnesota-Frese-Moriarty-Aff-Kentucky-Round5.docx
620,475
A
Kentucky
5
Wyoming PR
Garner
1AC - Enlargement (Ukr-Geo) 2NR - T-LTCReduce
ndtceda20/Minnesota/FrMo/Minnesota-Frese-Moriarty-Aff-Kentucky-Round5.docx
null
52,401
FrMo
Minnesota FrMo
null
Jo.....
Fr.....
Pe.....
Mo.....
19,336
Minnesota
Minnesota
null
null
1,010
ndtceda20
NDT/CEDA 2020-21
2,020
cx
college
2
1,963,948
US innovation regulation is key to prevent multiple scenarios for extinction
Jain 19
Ash Jain 19, senior fellow with the Scowcroft Center for Strategy and Security, where he oversees the Atlantic Council’s Democratic Order Initiative and D10 Strategy Forum; and Matthew Kroenig, deputy director for strategy in the Scowcroft Center for Strategy and Security and associate professor of government and foreign service at Georgetown University, 10/30/19, “Present at the Re-Creation: A Global Strategy for Revitalizing, Adapting, and Defending a Rules-Based International System,” https://www.atlanticcouncil.org/wp-content/uploads/2019/10/Present-at-the-Recreation.pdf
The system must be adapted to deal with emerging and disruptive technology, including AI, additive manufacturing 3D printing quantum computing genetic engineering, robotics, directed energy, the IOT), 5G, space, cyber these innovations promise great benefits, but also carry serious downside risks AI is generating new security challenges autonomous weapons could eventually turn on their creators, resulting in human extinction. The other technologies on this lisgt similarly balance great potential upside with great downside risk. 3D printing can be used by revisionist and rogue states to print component parts for advanced weapons systems or WMD spurring arms races and weapons proliferation Genetic engineering can wipe out entire classes of people through genetically engineered superbugs. Directed-energy missile defenses may defend against incoming missile attacks, while undermining global strategic stability the greatest risk to global strategic stability from new technology comes from the risk revisionist autocracies may win the new tech arms race stability has been maintained in Europe and Asia because the U S and its democratic allies possessed a favorable economic and military balance of power If China succeeds in mastering the technologies of the future before the democratic core this could lead to a drastic and rapid shift in the balance of power, upsetting global strategic stability, and the call for a democratic- led, rules-based system
AI 3D printing genetic engineering directed energy, the IOT), 5G, space, cyber promise benefits, but carry risks autonomous weapons could result in extinction 3D printing can be used by rogue states spurring prolif G e can wipe out classes of people Directed-energy may undermin global stability greatest risk comes from risk autocracies win the tech race If China master tech this could lead to a rapid shift in the balance of power,
The system must also be adapted to deal with new issues that were not envisioned when the existing order was designed. Foremost among these issues is emerging and disruptive technology, including AI, additive manufacturing (or 3D printing), quantum computing, genetic engineering, robotics, directed energy, the Internet of things (IOT), 5G, space, cyber, and many others. Like other disruptive technologies before them, these innovations promise great benefits, but also carry serious downside risks. For example, AI is already resulting in massive efficiencies and cost savings in the private sector. Routine tasks and other more complicated jobs, such as radiology, are already being automated. In the future, autonomous weapons systems may go to war against each other as human soldiers remain out of harm’s way. Yet, AI is also transforming economies and societies, and generating new security challenges. Automation will lead to widespread unemployment. The final realization of driverless cars, for example, will put out of work millions of taxi, Uber, and long-haul truck drivers. Populist movements in the West have been driven by those disaffected by globalization and technology, and mass unemployment caused by automation will further grow those ranks and provide new fuel to grievance politics. Moreover, some fear that autonomous weapons systems will become “killer robots” that select and engage targets without human input, and could eventually turn on their creators, resulting in human extinction. The other technologies on this lisgt similarly balance great potential upside with great downside risk. 3D printing, for example, can be used to “make anything anywhere,” reducing costs for a wide range of manufactured goods and encouraging a return of local manufacturing industries.61 At the same time, advanced 3D printers can also be used by revisionist and rogue states to print component parts for advanced weapons systems or even WMD programs, spurring arms races and weapons proliferation.62 Genetic engineering can wipe out entire classes of disease through improved medicine, or wipe out entire classes of people through genetically engineered superbugs. Directed-energy missile defenses may defend against incoming missile attacks, while also undermining global strategic stability. Perhaps the greatest risk to global strategic stability from new technology, however, comes from the risk that revisionist autocracies may win the new tech arms race. Throughout history, states that have dominated the commanding heights of technological progress have also dominated international relations. The United States has been the world’s innovation leader from Edison’s light bulb to nuclear weapons and the Internet. Accordingly, stability has been maintained in Europe and Asia for decades because the United States and its democratic allies possessed a favorable economic and military balance of power in those key regions. Many believe, however, that China may now have the lead in the new technologies of the twenty-first century, including AI, quantum, 5G, hypersonic missiles, and others. If China succeeds in mastering the technologies of the future before the democratic core, then this could lead to a drastic and rapid shift in the balance of power, upsetting global strategic stability, and the call for a democratic- led, rules-based system outlined in these pages.63
3,399
<h4>US innovation regulation is key to prevent multiple scenarios for extinction</h4><p>Ash <strong>Jain 19</strong>, senior fellow with the Scowcroft Center for Strategy and Security, where he oversees the Atlantic Council’s Democratic Order Initiative and D10 Strategy Forum; and Matthew Kroenig, deputy director for strategy in the Scowcroft Center for Strategy and Security and associate professor of government and foreign service at Georgetown University, 10/30/19, “Present at the Re-Creation: A Global Strategy for Revitalizing, Adapting, and Defending a Rules-Based International System,” https://www.atlanticcouncil.org/wp-content/uploads/2019/10/Present-at-the-Recreation.pdf</p><p><u>The system must</u> also <u>be adapted to deal with</u> new issues that were not envisioned when the existing order was designed. Foremost among these issues is <u>emerging and disruptive technology, including <strong><mark>AI</strong></mark>, <strong>additive manufacturing</u></strong> (or <u><strong><mark>3D printing</u></strong></mark>), <u>quantum computing</u>, <u><strong><mark>genetic engineering</strong></mark>, <strong>robotics</strong>, <strong><mark>directed energy</strong>, the</u></mark> Internet of things (<u><strong><mark>IOT</strong>), <strong>5G</strong>, <strong>space</strong>, <strong>cyber</u></strong></mark>, and many others. Like other disruptive technologies before them, <u>these innovations <mark>promise</mark> great <mark>benefits, but</mark> also <mark>carry</mark> <strong>serious downside <mark>risks</u></strong></mark>. For example, AI is already resulting in massive efficiencies and cost savings in the private sector. Routine tasks and other more complicated jobs, such as radiology, are already being automated. In the future, autonomous weapons systems may go to war against each other as human soldiers remain out of harm’s way.</p><p>Yet, <u>AI is</u> also transforming economies and societies, and <u>generating new security challenges</u>. Automation will lead to widespread unemployment. The final realization of driverless cars, for example, will put out of work millions of taxi, Uber, and long-haul truck drivers. Populist movements in the West have been driven by those disaffected by globalization and technology, and mass unemployment caused by automation will further grow those ranks and provide new fuel to grievance politics. Moreover, some fear that <u><mark>autonomous weapons</u></mark> systems will become “killer robots” that select and engage targets without human input, and <u><mark>could</mark> eventually <strong>turn on their creators, <mark>result</mark>ing <mark>in</mark> human <mark>extinction</strong></mark>. The other technologies on this lisgt similarly balance great potential upside with great downside risk. <mark>3D printing</u></mark>, for example, can be used to “make anything anywhere,” reducing costs for a wide range of manufactured goods and encouraging a return of local manufacturing industries.61 At the same time, advanced 3D printers <u><mark>can</u></mark> also <u><mark>be used by</mark> revisionist and <mark>rogue states </mark>to print component parts for advanced weapons systems or</u> even <u>WMD</u> programs, <u><strong><mark>spurring </mark>arms races and weapons <mark>prolif</mark>eration</u></strong>.62 <u><strong><mark>G</strong></mark>enetic <strong><mark>e</strong></mark>ngineering <mark>can</u></mark> wipe out entire classes of disease through improved medicine, or <u><mark>wipe out</mark> entire <mark>classes of people</mark> through genetically engineered superbugs. <mark>Directed-energy</mark> missile defenses <mark>may</mark> defend against incoming missile attacks, while</u> also <u><strong><mark>undermin</mark>ing <mark>global</mark> strategic <mark>stability</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>Perhaps <u>the <mark>greatest risk</mark> to global strategic stability from new technology</u>, however, <u><mark>comes from</mark> the <mark>risk</u></mark> that <u><strong>revisionist <mark>autocracies</mark> may <mark>win the</mark> new <mark>tech</mark> arms <mark>race</u></strong></mark>. Throughout history, states that have dominated the commanding heights of technological progress have also dominated international relations. The United States has been the world’s innovation leader from Edison’s light bulb to nuclear weapons and the Internet. Accordingly, <u>stability has been maintained in Europe and Asia</u> for decades <u>because the <strong>U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates <u>and its democratic allies possessed a favorable economic and military balance of power</u> in those key regions. Many believe, however, that China may now have the lead in the new technologies of the twenty-first century, including AI, quantum, 5G, hypersonic missiles, and others. <u><mark>If</mark> <mark>China</mark> succeeds in <mark>master</mark>ing the <mark>tech</mark>nologies of the future before the democratic core</u>, then <u><mark>this could lead to a</mark> drastic and <strong><mark>rapid shift in the balance of power</strong>, </mark>upsetting <strong>global strategic stability</strong>, and the call for a democratic- led, rules-based system</u> outlined in these pages.63</p>
1NC---Emory Round 3
OFF
DA---1NC
1,628
956
57,999
./documents/hspolicy20/MontgomeryBell/ClPi/Montgomery%20Bell-Climaco-Pierce-Neg-9%20-%20Emory-Round3.docx
735,380
N
9 - Emory
3
Woodward GR
Kareem Safieddine
1AC - 13th Amendment 1NC - 13th Amendment PIC NGA CP Federalism DA DOJ DA Stimulus DA 2NR - PIC Community Policing Bad
hspolicy20/MontgomeryBell/ClPi/Montgomery%20Bell-Climaco-Pierce-Neg-9%20-%20Emory-Round3.docx
null
62,699
ClPi
Montgomery Bell ClPi
null
Ch.....
Cl.....
Do.....
Pi.....
21,723
MontgomeryBell
Montgomery Bell
TN
null
1,019
hspolicy20
HS Policy 2020-21
2,020
cx
hs
2
1,432,205
Warming causes extinction
Ramanathan et al. 17
Ramanathan et al. 17 [Veerabhadran Ramanathan is Victor Alderson Professor of Applied Ocean Sciences and director of the Center for Atmospheric Sciences at the Scripps Institution of Oceanography, University of California, San Diego, Dr. William Collins is an internationally recognized expert in climate modeling and climate change science. He is the Director of the Climate and Ecosystem Sciences Division (CESD) for the Earth and Environmental Sciences Area (EESA) at the Lawrence Berkeley National Laboratory (LBNL), Prof. Dr Mark Lawrence, Ph.D. is scientific director at the Institute for Advanced Sustainability Studies (IASS) in Potsdam, Örjan Gustafsson is a Professor in the Department of Environmental Science and Analytic Chemistry at Stockholm University, Shichang Kang is Professor, Cold and Arid Regions Environmental and Engineering Research Institute, Chinese Academy of Sciences (CAS); CAS Center for Excellence in Tibetan Plateau Earth Sciences, and Molina, M.J., Zaelke, D., Borgford-Parnell, N., Xu, Y., Alex, K., Auffhammer, M., Bledsoe, P., Croes, B., Forman, F., Haines, A., Harnish, R., Jacobson, M.Z., Lawrence, M., Leloup, D., Lenton, T., Morehouse, T., Munk, W., Picolotti, R., Prather, K., Raga, G., Rignot, E., Shindell, D., Singh, A.K., Steiner, A., Thiemens, M., Titley, D.W., Tucker, M.E., Tripathi, S., & Victor, D., authors come from the following 9 countries - US, Switzerland, Sweden, UK, China, Germany, Australia, Mexico, India, “Well Under 2 Degrees Celsius: Fast Action Policies to Protect People and the Planet from Extreme Climate Change,” Report of the Committee to Prevent Extreme Climate Change, September 2017, http://www.igsd.org/wp-content/uploads/2017/09/Well-Under-2-Degrees-Celsius-Report-2017.pdf] TDI
Climate change is becoming an existential threat with warming in excess of 2°C within the next three decades and 4°C to 6°C within the next several decades. Warming of such magnitudes will expose as many as 75% of the world’s population to deadly heat stress in addition to disrupting the climate and weather worldwide. Climate change is an urgent problem requiring urgent solutions. This paper lays out urgent and practical solutions that are ready for implementation now, will deliver benefits in the next few critical decades emissions of greenhouse gases and air pollutants can be decoupled from economic growth. Another favorable sign is that growth rates of worldwide carbon emissions have reduced from 2.9% per year during the first decade of this century to 1.3% from 2011 to 2014 and near zero growth rates during the last few years. The carbon emission curve is bending, but we have a long way to go and very little time for achieving carbon neutrality. The climate has already warmed by 1°C. The problem is running ahead of us, and under current trends we will likely reach 1.5°C in the next fifteen years and surpass the 2°C guardrail by mid-century with a 50% probability of reaching 4°C by end of century. 3°C is likely to be a global catastrophe for three major reasons: • Warming in the range of 3°C to 5°C is suggested as the threshold for several tipping points in the physical and geochemical systems; a warming of about 3°C has a probability of over 40% to cross over multiple tipping points, while a warming close to 5°C increases it to nearly 90%, compared with a baseline warming of less than 1.5°C, which has only just over a 10% probability of exceeding any tipping point. • Health effects of such warming are emerging as a major if not dominant source of concern. Warming of 4°C or more will expose more than 70% of the population, i.e. about 7 billion by the end of the century, to deadly heat stress and expose about 2.4 billion to vector borne diseases such as Dengue, Chikengunya, and Zika virus among others. can become a major causal factor for exposing more than 50% of all species to extinction. 20% of species are in danger of extinction now due to population, habitat destruction, and climate change. there may still be time to avert such catastrophic changes supporting climate policies must be strengthened substantially within the next five years to bend the emissions curve down faster, stabilize climate, and prevent catastrophic warming ecosystems will be forced to contend with substantial needs for adaptation—a burden that will fall disproportionately on the poorest three billion who are least responsible for causing the climate change problem A massive effort will be needed to stop warming at 2°C, and time is of the essence. With unchecked business-as-usual emissions, global warming has a 50% likelihood of exceeding 4ºC and a 5% probability of exceeding 6ºC in this century, raising existential questions for most, but especially the poorest three billion people. A 4ºC warming is likely to expose as many as 75% of the global population to deadly heat It is likely that as we cross the 1.5°C to 2°C thresholds we will trigger so called “tipping points” for abrupt and nonlinear changes in the climate system with catastrophic consequences for humanity and the environment (Lenton, 2008; Drijfhout et al., 2015). Once the tipping points are passed, the resulting impacts will range in timescales from: disruption of monsoon systems (transition in a year), loss of sea ice (approximately a decade for transition), dieback of major forests (nearly half a century for transition), reorganization of ocean circulation (approximately a century for transition), to loss of ice sheets and subsequent sea-level rise (transition over hundreds of years) (Lenton et al., 2008). Regardless of timescale, once underway many of these changes would be irreversible (Lontzek et al., 2015). There is also a likelihood of crossing over multiple tipping points simultaneously. Warming of close to 3°C would subject the system to a 46% probability of crossing multiple tipping points, while warming of close to 5°C would increase the risk to 87% (Cai et al., 2016). Recent modeling work shows a “cluster” of these tipping points could be triggered between 1.5°C and 2°C warming (Figure 2), including melting of land and sea ice and changes in highlatitude ocean circulation (deep convection) (Drijfhout et al., 2015). This is consistent with existing observations and understanding that the polar regions are particularly sensitive to global warming and have several potentially imminent tipping points. The Arctic is warming nearly twice as quickly as the global average, which makes the abrupt changes in the Arctic more likely at a lower level of global warming (IPCC, 2013). Similarly, the Himalayas are warming at roughly the same rate as the Arctic and are thus also more susceptible to incremental changes in temperature (UNEP-WMO, 2011). This gives further justifcation for limiting warming to no more than 1.5°C. self-amplifying feedbacks that once set in motion increase warming in such a way that they perpetuate yet even more warming. Declining Arctic sea ice, thawing permafrost, and the poleward migration of cloud systems are all examples of self-amplifying feedback mechanisms, where initial warming feeds upon itself to cause still more warming acting as a force multiplier (Schuur et al., 2015).
Climate change is an existential threat with warming in excess of 2°C within the next three decades and 4 to 6 in the next several Warming of such magnitudes expose 75% of the world’s population to deadly heat stress emissions can be decoupled from economic growth The climate has already warmed by 1°C. and under current trends we will surpass 2°C by mid-century with a 50% probability of reaching 4°C by end of century Warming of 3°C has a probability of over 40% to cross multiple tipping points, while 5°C increases it to nearly 90 4°C or more will expose more than 7 billion to deadly heat stress and vector borne diseases there may still be time to avert catastrophic changes policies must be strengthened substantially within the next five years catastrophic warming adaptation will fall disproportionately on the poorest three billion to stop warming at 2°C time is of the essence as we cross 2°C thresholds we will trigger tipping points” for nonlinear changes with catastrophic consequences initial warming feeds upon itself as a force multiplier
Climate change is becoming an existential threat with warming in excess of 2°C within the next three decades and 4°C to 6°C within the next several decades. Warming of such magnitudes will expose as many as 75% of the world’s population to deadly heat stress in addition to disrupting the climate and weather worldwide. Climate change is an urgent problem requiring urgent solutions. This paper lays out urgent and practical solutions that are ready for implementation now, will deliver benefits in the next few critical decades, and places the world on a path to achieving the longterm targets of the Paris Agreement and near-term sustainable development goals. The approach consists of four building blocks and 3 levers to implement ten scalable solutions described in this report by a team of climate scientists, policy makers, social and behavioral scientists, political scientists, legal experts, diplomats, and military experts from around the world. These solutions will enable society to decarbonize the global energy system by 2050 through efficiency and renewables, drastically reduce short-lived climate pollutants, and stabilize the climate well below 2°C both in the near term (before 2050) and in the long term (post 2050). It will also reduce premature mortalities by tens of millions by 2050. As an insurance against policy lapses, mitigation delays and faster than projected climate changes, the solutions include an Atmospheric Carbon Extraction lever to remove CO2 from the air. The amount of CO2 that must be removed ranges from negligible, if the emissions of CO2 from the energy system and SLCPs start to decrease by 2020 and carbon neutrality is achieved by 2050, to a staggering one trillion tons if the carbon lever is not pulled and emissions of climate pollutants continue to increase until 2030. There are numerous living laboratories including 53 cities, many universities around the world, the state of California, and the nation of Sweden, who have embarked on a carbon neutral pathway. These laboratories have already created 8 million jobs in the clean energy industry; they have also shown that emissions of greenhouse gases and air pollutants can be decoupled from economic growth. Another favorable sign is that growth rates of worldwide carbon emissions have reduced from 2.9% per year during the first decade of this century to 1.3% from 2011 to 2014 and near zero growth rates during the last few years. The carbon emission curve is bending, but we have a long way to go and very little time for achieving carbon neutrality. We need institutions and enterprises that can accelerate this bending by scaling-up the solutions that are being proven in the living laboratories. We have less than a decade to put these solutions in place around the world to preserve nature and our quality of life for generations to come. The time is now. The Paris Agreement is an historic achievement. For the first time, effectively all nations have committed to limiting their greenhouse gas emissions and taking other actions to limit global temperature change. Specifically, 197 nations agreed to hold “the increase in the global average temperature to well below 2°C above pre-industrial levels and pursue efforts to limit the temperature increase to 1.5°C above pre-industrial levels,” and achieve carbon neutrality in the second half of this century. The climate has already warmed by 1°C. The problem is running ahead of us, and under current trends we will likely reach 1.5°C in the next fifteen years and surpass the 2°C guardrail by mid-century with a 50% probability of reaching 4°C by end of century. Warming in excess of 3°C is likely to be a global catastrophe for three major reasons: • Warming in the range of 3°C to 5°C is suggested as the threshold for several tipping points in the physical and geochemical systems; a warming of about 3°C has a probability of over 40% to cross over multiple tipping points, while a warming close to 5°C increases it to nearly 90%, compared with a baseline warming of less than 1.5°C, which has only just over a 10% probability of exceeding any tipping point. • Health effects of such warming are emerging as a major if not dominant source of concern. Warming of 4°C or more will expose more than 70% of the population, i.e. about 7 billion by the end of the century, to deadly heat stress and expose about 2.4 billion to vector borne diseases such as Dengue, Chikengunya, and Zika virus among others. Ecologists and paleontologists have proposed that warming in excess of 3°C, accompanied by increased acidity of the oceans by the buildup of CO2 , can become a major causal factor for exposing more than 50% of all species to extinction. 20% of species are in danger of extinction now due to population, habitat destruction, and climate change. The good news is that there may still be time to avert such catastrophic changes. The Paris Agreement and supporting climate policies must be strengthened substantially within the next five years to bend the emissions curve down faster, stabilize climate, and prevent catastrophic warming. To the extent those efforts fall short, societies and ecosystems will be forced to contend with substantial needs for adaptation—a burden that will fall disproportionately on the poorest three billion who are least responsible for causing the climate change problem. The fast mitigation plan of requiring emissions reductions to begin by 2020, which means that many countries need to cut now, is urgently needed to limit the warming to well under 2°C. Climate change is not a linear problem. Instead, we are facing non-linear climate tipping points that can lead to self-reinforcing and cascading climate change impacts. Tipping points and selfreinforcing feedbacks are wild cards that are more likely with increased temperatures, and many of the potential abrupt climate shifts could happen as warming goes from 1.5°C in 15 years to 2°C by 2050, with the potential to push us well beyond the Paris Agreement goals. Where Do We Go from Here? A massive effort will be needed to stop warming at 2°C, and time is of the essence. With unchecked business-as-usual emissions, global warming has a 50% likelihood of exceeding 4ºC and a 5% probability of exceeding 6ºC in this century, raising existential questions for most, but especially the poorest three billion people. A 4ºC warming is likely to expose as many as 75% of the global population to deadly heat. Dangerous to catastrophic impacts on the health of people including generations yet to be born, on the health of ecosystems, and on species extinction have emerged as major justifications for mitigating climate change well below 2ºC, although we must recognize that the uncertainties intrinsic in climate and social systems make it hard to pin down exactly the level of warming that will trigger possibly catastrophic impacts. To avoid these consequences, we must act now, and we must act fast and effectively. This report sets out a specific plan for reducing climate change in both the near- and long-term. With aggressive urgent actions, we can protect ourselves. Acting quickly to prevent catastrophic climate change by decarbonization will save millions of lives, trillions of dollars in economic costs, and massive suffering and dislocation to people around the world. This is a global security imperative, as it can avoid the migration and destabilization of entire societies and countries and reduce the likelihood of environmentally driven civil wars and other conflicts. 2. Tipping Points: It is likely that as we cross the 1.5°C to 2°C thresholds we will trigger so called “tipping points” for abrupt and nonlinear changes in the climate system with catastrophic consequences for humanity and the environment (Lenton, 2008; Drijfhout et al., 2015). Once the tipping points are passed, the resulting impacts will range in timescales from: disruption of monsoon systems (transition in a year), loss of sea ice (approximately a decade for transition), dieback of major forests (nearly half a century for transition), reorganization of ocean circulation (approximately a century for transition), to loss of ice sheets and subsequent sea-level rise (transition over hundreds of years) (Lenton et al., 2008). Regardless of timescale, once underway many of these changes would be irreversible (Lontzek et al., 2015). There is also a likelihood of crossing over multiple tipping points simultaneously. Warming of close to 3°C would subject the system to a 46% probability of crossing multiple tipping points, while warming of close to 5°C would increase the risk to 87% (Cai et al., 2016). Recent modeling work shows a “cluster” of these tipping points could be triggered between 1.5°C and 2°C warming (Figure 2), including melting of land and sea ice and changes in highlatitude ocean circulation (deep convection) (Drijfhout et al., 2015). This is consistent with existing observations and understanding that the polar regions are particularly sensitive to global warming and have several potentially imminent tipping points. The Arctic is warming nearly twice as quickly as the global average, which makes the abrupt changes in the Arctic more likely at a lower level of global warming (IPCC, 2013). Similarly, the Himalayas are warming at roughly the same rate as the Arctic and are thus also more susceptible to incremental changes in temperature (UNEP-WMO, 2011). This gives further justifcation for limiting warming to no more than 1.5°C. While all climate tipping points have the potential to rapidly destabilize climate, social, and economic systems, some are also self-amplifying feedbacks that once set in motion increase warming in such a way that they perpetuate yet even more warming. Declining Arctic sea ice, thawing permafrost, and the poleward migration of cloud systems are all examples of self-amplifying feedback mechanisms, where initial warming feeds upon itself to cause still more warming acting as a force multiplier (Schuur et al., 2015).
10,033
<h4><u><strong>Warming causes extinction</h4><p></u>Ramanathan et al. 17</strong> [Veerabhadran Ramanathan is Victor Alderson Professor of Applied Ocean Sciences and director of the Center for Atmospheric Sciences at the Scripps Institution of Oceanography, University of California, San Diego, Dr. William Collins is an internationally recognized expert in climate modeling and climate change science. He is the Director of the Climate and Ecosystem Sciences Division (CESD) for the Earth and Environmental Sciences Area (EESA) at the Lawrence Berkeley National Laboratory (LBNL), Prof. Dr Mark Lawrence, Ph.D. is scientific director at the Institute for Advanced Sustainability Studies (IASS) in Potsdam, Örjan Gustafsson is a Professor in the Department of Environmental Science and Analytic Chemistry at Stockholm University, Shichang Kang is Professor, Cold and Arid Regions Environmental and Engineering Research Institute, Chinese Academy of Sciences (CAS); CAS Center for Excellence in Tibetan Plateau Earth Sciences, and Molina, M.J., Zaelke, D., Borgford-Parnell, N., Xu, Y., Alex, K., Auffhammer, M., Bledsoe, P., Croes, B., Forman, F., Haines, A., Harnish, R., Jacobson, M.Z., Lawrence, M., Leloup, D., Lenton, T., Morehouse, T., Munk, W., Picolotti, R., Prather, K., Raga, G., Rignot, E., Shindell, D., Singh, A.K., Steiner, A., Thiemens, M., Titley, D.W., Tucker, M.E., Tripathi, S., & Victor, D., authors come from the following 9 countries - US, Switzerland, Sweden, UK, China, Germany, Australia, Mexico, India, “Well Under 2 Degrees Celsius: Fast Action Policies to Protect People and the Planet from Extreme Climate Change,” Report of the Committee to Prevent Extreme Climate Change, September 2017, http://www.igsd.org/wp-content/uploads/2017/09/Well-Under-2-Degrees-Celsius-Report-2017.pdf] TDI</p><p><u><strong><mark>Climate change is</mark> becoming <mark>an existential threat with warming in excess of 2°C within the next three decades and 4</mark>°C <mark>to 6</mark>°C with<mark>in the next several</mark> decades. <mark>Warming of such magnitudes</mark> will <mark>expose</mark> as many as <mark>75% of the world’s population to deadly heat stress</mark> in addition to disrupting the climate and weather worldwide. Climate change is an urgent problem requiring urgent solutions. This paper lays out urgent and practical solutions that are ready for implementation now, will deliver benefits in the next few critical decades</u></strong>, and places the world on a path to achieving the longterm targets of the Paris Agreement and near-term sustainable development goals. The approach consists of four building blocks and 3 levers to implement ten scalable solutions described in this report by a team of climate scientists, policy makers, social and behavioral scientists, political scientists, legal experts, diplomats, and military experts from around the world. These solutions will enable society to decarbonize the global energy system by 2050 through efficiency and renewables, drastically reduce short-lived climate pollutants, and stabilize the climate well below 2°C both in the near term (before 2050) and in the long term (post 2050). It will also reduce premature mortalities by tens of millions by 2050. As an insurance against policy lapses, mitigation delays and faster than projected climate changes, the solutions include an Atmospheric Carbon Extraction lever to remove CO2 from the air. The amount of CO2 that must be removed ranges from negligible, if the emissions of CO2 from the energy system and SLCPs start to decrease by 2020 and carbon neutrality is achieved by 2050, to a staggering one trillion tons if the carbon lever is not pulled and emissions of climate pollutants continue to increase until 2030.</p><p>There are numerous living laboratories including 53 cities, many universities around the world, the state of California, and the nation of Sweden, who have embarked on a carbon neutral pathway. These laboratories have already created 8 million jobs in the clean energy industry; they have also shown that <u><strong><mark>emissions</mark> of greenhouse gases and air pollutants <mark>can be decoupled from economic growth</mark>. Another favorable sign is that growth rates of worldwide carbon emissions have reduced from 2.9% per year during the first decade of this century to 1.3% from 2011 to 2014 and near zero growth rates during the last few years. The carbon emission curve is bending, but we have a long way to go and very little time for achieving carbon neutrality.</u></strong> We need institutions and enterprises that can accelerate this bending by scaling-up the solutions that are being proven in the living laboratories. We have less than a decade to put these solutions in place around the world to preserve nature and our quality of life for generations to come. The time is now.</p><p>The Paris Agreement is an historic achievement. For the first time, effectively all nations have committed to limiting their greenhouse gas emissions and taking other actions to limit global temperature change. Specifically, 197 nations agreed to hold “the increase in the global average temperature to well below 2°C above pre-industrial levels and pursue efforts to limit the temperature increase to 1.5°C above pre-industrial levels,” and achieve carbon neutrality in the second half of this century.</p><p><u><strong><mark>The climate has already warmed by 1°C.</mark> The problem is running ahead of us, <mark>and under current trends we will</mark> likely reach 1.5°C in the next fifteen years and <mark>surpass </mark>the <mark>2°C</mark> guardrail <mark>by mid-century with a 50% probability of reaching 4°C by end of century</mark>.</u></strong> Warming in excess of<u><strong> 3°C is likely to be a global catastrophe for three major reasons:</p><p>• <mark>Warming</mark> in the range of 3°C to 5°C is suggested as the threshold for several tipping points in the physical and geochemical systems; a warming <mark>of</mark> about <mark>3°C has a probability of over 40% to cross</mark> over <mark>multiple tipping points, while</mark> a warming close to <mark>5°C increases it to nearly 90</mark>%, compared with a baseline warming of less than 1.5°C, which has only just over a 10% probability of exceeding any tipping point.</p><p>• Health effects of such warming are emerging as a major if not dominant source of concern. Warming of <mark>4°C or more will expose more than </mark>70% of the population, i.e. about <mark>7 billion</mark> by the end of the century, <mark>to deadly heat stress and</mark> expose about 2.4 billion to <mark>vector borne diseases</mark> such as Dengue, Chikengunya, and Zika virus among others.</u></strong> Ecologists and paleontologists have proposed that warming in excess of 3°C, accompanied by increased acidity of the oceans by the buildup of CO2 ,<u><strong> can become a major causal factor for exposing more than 50% of all species to extinction. 20% of species are in danger of extinction now due to population, habitat destruction, and climate change.</p><p></u></strong>The good news is that <u><strong><mark>there may still be time to avert</mark> such <mark>catastrophic changes</u></strong></mark>. The Paris Agreement and <u><strong>supporting climate <mark>policies must be strengthened substantially within the next five years</mark> to bend the emissions curve down faster, stabilize climate, and prevent <mark>catastrophic warming</u></strong></mark>. To the extent those efforts fall short, societies and <u><strong>ecosystems will be forced to contend with substantial needs for <mark>adaptation</mark>—a burden that <mark>will fall disproportionately on the poorest three billion</mark> </p><p>who are least responsible for causing the climate change problem</u>.</p><p></strong>The fast mitigation plan of requiring emissions reductions to begin by 2020, which means that many countries need to cut now, is urgently needed to limit the warming to well under 2°C. Climate change is not a linear problem. Instead, we are facing non-linear climate tipping points that can lead to self-reinforcing and cascading climate change impacts. Tipping points and selfreinforcing feedbacks are wild cards that are more likely with increased temperatures, and many of the potential abrupt climate shifts could happen as warming goes from 1.5°C in 15 years to 2°C by 2050, with the potential to push us well beyond the Paris Agreement goals.</p><p>Where Do We Go from Here?</p><p><u><strong>A massive effort will be needed <mark>to stop warming at 2°C</mark>, and <mark>time is of the essence</mark>. With unchecked business-as-usual emissions, global warming has a 50% likelihood of exceeding 4ºC and a 5% probability of exceeding 6ºC in this century, raising existential questions for most, but especially the poorest three billion people. A 4ºC warming is likely to expose as many as 75% of the global population to deadly heat</u>.</strong> Dangerous to catastrophic impacts on the health of people including generations yet to be born, on the health of ecosystems, and on species extinction have emerged as major justifications for mitigating climate change well below 2ºC, although we must recognize that the uncertainties intrinsic in climate and social systems make it hard to pin down exactly the level of warming that will trigger possibly catastrophic impacts. To avoid these consequences, we must act now, and we must act fast and effectively. This report sets out a specific plan for reducing climate change in both the near- and long-term. With aggressive urgent actions, we can protect ourselves. Acting quickly to prevent catastrophic climate change by decarbonization will save millions of lives, trillions of dollars in economic costs, and massive suffering and dislocation to people around the world. This is a global security imperative, as it can avoid the migration and destabilization of entire societies and countries and reduce the likelihood of environmentally driven civil wars and other conflicts.</p><p>2. Tipping Points<strong>: <u>It is likely that <mark>as we cross </mark>the 1.5°C to <mark>2°C thresholds we will trigger</mark> so called “<mark>tipping points” for </mark>abrupt and <mark>nonlinear changes</mark> in the climate system <mark>with catastrophic consequences</mark> for humanity and the environment (Lenton, 2008; Drijfhout et al., 2015). Once the tipping points are passed, the resulting impacts will range in timescales from: disruption of monsoon systems (transition in a year), loss of sea ice (approximately a decade for transition), dieback of major forests (nearly half a century for transition), reorganization of ocean circulation (approximately a century for transition), to loss of ice sheets and subsequent sea-level rise (transition over hundreds of years) (Lenton et al., 2008). Regardless of timescale, once underway many of these changes would be irreversible (Lontzek et al., 2015). There is also a likelihood of crossing over multiple tipping points simultaneously. Warming of close to 3°C would subject the system to a 46% probability of crossing multiple tipping points, while warming of close to 5°C would increase the risk to 87% (Cai et al., 2016). Recent modeling work shows a “cluster” of these tipping points could be triggered between 1.5°C and 2°C warming (Figure 2), including melting of land and sea ice and changes in highlatitude ocean circulation (deep convection) (Drijfhout et al., 2015). This is consistent with existing observations and understanding that the polar regions are particularly sensitive to global warming and have several potentially imminent tipping points. The Arctic is warming nearly twice as quickly as the global average, which makes the abrupt changes in the Arctic more likely at a lower level of global warming (IPCC, 2013). Similarly, the Himalayas are warming at roughly the same rate as the Arctic and are thus also more susceptible to incremental changes in temperature (UNEP-WMO, 2011). This gives further justifcation for limiting warming to no more than 1.5°C.</p><p></u></strong>While all climate tipping points have the potential to rapidly destabilize climate, social, and economic systems, some are also<u><strong> self-amplifying feedbacks that once set in motion increase warming in such a way that they perpetuate yet even more warming. Declining Arctic sea ice, thawing permafrost, and the poleward migration of cloud systems are all examples of self-amplifying feedback mechanisms, where <mark>initial warming feeds upon itself</mark> to cause still more warming acting <mark>as a force multiplier</mark> (Schuur et al., 2015).</p></u></strong>
null
1NC- Case
Impact
21,542
427
39,214
./documents/hsld21/ImmaculateHeart/We/Immaculate%20Heart-WegmannGatarz-Neg-Palm%20Classic-Round4.docx
889,878
N
Palm Classic
4
Claudia Taylor Johnson AP
Ben Erdmann
1AC- Disabled futurity K aff 1NC- TFW Framing impact 1AR- NC AC 2NR- TFW Framing Case 2AR- Case T Framing
hsld21/ImmaculateHeart/We/Immaculate%20Heart-WegmannGatarz-Neg-Palm%20Classic-Round4.docx
null
74,798
AvWe
Immaculate Heart AvWe
null
Av.....
We.....
null
null
25,023
ImmaculateHeart
Immaculate Heart
CA
null
1,029
hsld21
HS LD 2021-22
2,021
ld
hs
1
4,175,830
1. HARDENING---military proofing is key---cyber-attacks on NATO assets create cascading effects and destroys deterrence absent military hardening.
Unal 19
Beyza Unal 19. Senior research fellow with the International Security Department at Chatham House. “Cybersecurity of NATO's Space-based Strategic Assets.” Chatham House. The Royal Institute of International Affairs. pp. 7-11. 07-10-2019. https://www.chathamhouse.org/2019/07/cybersecurity-natos-space-based-strategic-assets-0/about-author //EM
In the military domain some of the major vulnerabilities include the use of commercial companies for military purposes ‘back-doors’ in encryption and the supply-chain security of satellites Risks also arise from the dual-use of most space technology where the technology can be used for civilian and military purposes communications satellites and broadcasting satellite s have both civilian and military utility utilization of satellite capability in the civilian sphere for earth observations environmental monitoring and the provision of oceanographic data There is an increasing need to apply higher-grade military hardening and cyber protection to civilian capabilities that have the potential to be used in support of military applications NATO allies procure equipment to be integrated into their defence architecture The commercial chain is embedded in every aspect of military equipment This may not necessarily be a particular vulnerability However if military standards are not met, items procured may expose NATO’s systems to additional vulnerabilities Civil satellites operated by private companies may be used to fulfil missions in locations where NATO allies do not have their own space equipment Ground stations constitute further elements that are relevant From a cybersecurity each interface could present a vulnerability and become a weakness Vulnerabilities can stem from A higher number of data interfaces use of old and proprietary hardware and software failure or inability to conduct software updates Space systems provide mission-critical information both for NATO’s member states as a whole NATO relies on space-based assets for almost all of its operations and missions NATO uses a mix of military civilian commercial and national/ assets The joint use of these assets however comes with an acceptance of inherent risk, to the alliance as a whole. There is increased dependence on space-based systems in modern engagement Cyber vulnerabilities undermine confidence in systems they increase uncertainty in information which impacts the credibility of deterrence and stability Loss of trust in technology has implications for attribution and calculus in crisis decision-making and increase the risk of misperception This dependency has major implications for NATO systems rely on so-called ‘ BLOS communication via satellites especially in times of crisis and conflict Yet cyberattacks on space technology may lead them to misinterpret commands NATO’s space-dependent capabilities have individual functions These capabilities are coupled to each other with complex cross-dependencies so that the loss of one capability may have a collateral impact on other capabilities most of the assets that transmit communications are dependent on GPS for timing and synchronization
major vulnerabilities include use of commercial companies ‘back-doors’ and supply-chain security Risks There is an increasing need to apply military hardening to civilian capabilities used in military s NATO chain embedded in every aspect of equipment Civil satellites used to fulfil missions where allies do not have equipment each interface present a vulnerability vulnerabilities undermine confidence increase uncertainty impacts credibility of deterrence Loss of trust has implications for attribution increase misperception NATO’s capabilities are coupled with complex dependencies loss of one have a collateral impact on other s
In the military domain, some of the major system vulnerabilities include the use of commercial companies for military purposes; ‘back-doors’ in encryption; and the supply-chain security of satellites.27 This list can also be extended to include physical, personnel and procedural vulnerabilities. Risks also arise from the dual-use aspect of most of the space-related technology – where the technology can be used for both civilian and military purposes. For instance – whether fixed or mobile units – communications satellites and broadcasting satellite services have both civilian and military utility. Similarly, the utilization of satellite imagery capability in the civilian sphere for earth observations, environmental monitoring, and the provision of oceanographic and cartographic data, also extends to the military domain.28 There is an increasing need to apply higher-grade military hardening and cyber protection specifications to civilian capabilities that have the potential to be used in support of military applications. These capabilities aside, terminals located in ground stations constitute a critical vulnerability, as a terminal is an access point to a satellite and is usually not protected by authentication in order not to hinder operational actions. Terminals house software systems that can be compromised and require patching and upgrading. Moreover, software embedded in weapons systems (such as precision-guided munitions) could also be compromised. At times, NATO allies procure equipment and software to be integrated into their national defence architecture, which becomes part of the overall NATO capability. The commercial supply chain is embedded in nearly every aspect of military equipment. This may not necessarily be a particular vulnerability, as long as commercial equipment is designed to military standards and is secure. However, if military standards are not met, items procured from commercial industry with design flaws may expose NATO’s systems to additional vulnerabilities. While the absence of data is easy to detect, the manipulation of data or erosion of confidentiality at such an interface is potentially more difficult to discern. Civil satellites, operated by private companies, may be used to fulfil specific missions in locations where NATO allies do not have their own space equipment. Ground stations constitute further elements that are relevant for the data flow. From a cybersecurity point of view, each interface could present a vulnerability and could become a weakness, as an interface typically requires manual processes to establish its operation, and/or the administration of the components involved. Adversaries infiltrating ground- or space-based systems could exploit weak software implementation, or the incompatibility of network or data transfer protocols in the chain. While the absence of data is easy to detect, the manipulation of data or erosion of confidentiality at such an interface is potentially more difficult to discern. Vulnerabilities can stem from: A higher number of data exchange interfaces used between the military and civil sectors; The fact that each actor has its own isolated view of its data network, protected by its own security standard; The use of old and proprietary IT hardware and software; and The failure or inability to conduct regular software updates to remove known vulnerabilities. In such an environment, it seems difficult to ensure security of the information delivered. Space-specific risks for the NATO alliance and for key NATO countries Space systems, which include both satellites and ground stations, as well as related space products and services, provide mission-critical information both for NATO’s member states and for the alliance as a whole. NATO relies on space-based assets for almost all of its operations and missions.29 Some of the critical missions that rely on space assets include: defence of NATO’s territory and the neighbouring regions; peacekeeping missions; humanitarian assistance and disaster relief; counterterrorism; and conflict prevention activities. NATO does not own satellites. It owns and operates a few terrestrial elements, such as satellite communications (SATCOM) anchor stations and terminals. It requests access to products and services but does not have direct access to satellites, leaving it up to its allies to determine whether they provide access to their satellite capabilities. NATO has established memoranda of understanding with allies for possible use of space products and services. Originally, in the US, space systems used by the military were separated from commercial and civilian assets in terms of their development and operation.30 One of the reasons for this separation was to protect the military structure against physical and cyberthreats. Military space system safety and security requirements were also higher and more stringent than in the commercial sphere (for example, requirements to invest in survivability enhancement mechanisms in order to resist jamming, or special design approaches for military space architecture). In recent years commercial methods, for instance the capture and analysis of satellite imagery, have been shown to be as effective as military means. As a result, NATO uses a mix of military, civilian, commercial, and national/multinational assets to conduct its operations. The joint use of these assets, however, comes with an acceptance of inherent risk, not only to the countries that provide such capability but also to the alliance as a whole. In response, the European Defence Agency, through its Governmental Satellite Communications (GOVSATCOM) development programme, decided to build an intermediary class of satellites between commercial SATCOM and military SATCOM, with security requirements able to address the needs of critical missions, including crisis management.31 There is increased dependence on space-based systems in modern military engagement. During the US engagement in Iraq in 2003, 68 per cent of munitions were guided utilizing space-based means (including laser-, infrared- and satellite-guided munitions); this percentage had risen sharply from 10 per cent in 1990–91, during the first Gulf war.32 In its operations in Afghanistan in 2001, 60 per cent of the weapons used by the US were precision-guided munitions: these included bombs, missiles, and other weapons, many of which had the capability to correct their own positioning to hit the target, using space-derived information.33 Cyber vulnerabilities undermine confidence in strategic systems; they increase uncertainty in information and analysis, which impacts the credibility of deterrence and strategic stability. Loss of trust in technology also has implications for attribution and strategic calculus in crisis decision-making and may increase the risk of misperception. This dependency on space-based technology has major implications for the way NATO conducts warfare today, and how it will do so in the future. For instance, in order to conduct precision strikes or earth observation through the use of unmanned aerial vehicles (UAVs – such as military drones), systems rely on so-called ‘beyond-line-of-sight’ (BLOS) communication via satellites – especially in times of crisis and conflict, since ground-based line-of-sight communications are vulnerable to physical attacks. Yet, cyberattacks on space technology or on the UAVs may lead them to misinterpret commands, or to lose contact with the command centre and fail in operation. ***TABLE 1 OMITTED*** Identification is another important capability that is used in the NATO maritime domain for coastal tracking, and for identifying and locating ships and vessels. Using automatic identification systems (AIS), data is electronically transmitted between ships and the coastal stations. By providing similar functions, AIS supplements and provides resilience to maritime radar and is fundamental for avoiding collisions.36 NATO’s space-dependent capabilities have individual functions, as described above. These capabilities are also coupled to each other, with complex cross-dependencies, so that the loss of one capability may have a collateral impact on other capabilities. For instance, most of the assets that transmit communications to support command and control are also dependent on GPS for timing and synchronization.37 Although there would be a number of contenders for technologies of utmost importance to NATO missions and operations, preliminary research indicates that PNT signals (which utilize GPS) are a much-needed priority capability in almost all NATO operations.
8,645
<h4>1. HARDENING---military proofing is key---cyber-attacks on NATO assets create cascading effects and destroys deterrence absent military hardening. </h4><p>Beyza <strong>Unal 19</strong>. Senior research fellow with the International Security Department at Chatham House. “Cybersecurity of NATO's Space-based Strategic Assets.” Chatham House. The Royal Institute of International Affairs. pp. 7-11. 07-10-2019. https://www.chathamhouse.org/2019/07/cybersecurity-natos-space-based-strategic-assets-0/about-author //EM</p><p><u>In the <strong>military domain</u></strong>, <u>some</u> <u>of the <mark>major</u></mark> system <u><strong><mark>vulnerabilities</strong> include</mark> the <strong><mark>use of commercial</u></strong> <u>companies</u></mark> <u>for military purposes</u>; <u><strong><mark>‘back-doors’</strong></mark> in encryption</u>; <u><mark>and</mark> the <strong><mark>supply-chain</u></strong> <u>security</mark> of satellites</u>.27 This list can also be extended to include physical, personnel and procedural vulnerabilities. <u><mark>Risks</mark> also arise</u> <u>from the <strong>dual-use</u></strong> aspect <u>of most</u> of the <u>space</u>-related <u>technology</u> – <u>where the technology</u> <u>can be used for </u>both <u><strong>civilian</u></strong> <u>and <strong>military</u></strong> <u>purposes</u>. For instance – whether fixed or mobile units – <u>communications satellites</u> <u>and</u> <u>broadcasting satellite</u> service<u>s have both</u> <u>civilian</u> <u>and military utility</u>. Similarly, the <u>utilization of</u> <u>satellite</u> imagery <u>capability</u> <u>in the civilian</u> <u>sphere</u> <u>for</u> <u><strong>earth observations</u></strong>, <u>environmental</u> <u><strong>monitoring</u></strong>, <u>and the provision</u> <u>of <strong>oceanographic</u></strong> and cartographic <u>data</u>, also extends to the military domain.28 <u><mark>There is an increasing need to</u> <u>apply</u></mark> <u>higher-grade <strong><mark>military hardening</u></strong></mark> <u>and cyber <strong>protection</u></strong> specifications <u><mark>to civilian</u> <u>capabilities</u></mark> <u>that have the <strong>potential</u></strong> <u>to be <mark>used in</mark> support</u> <u>of <strong><mark>military</mark> application<mark>s</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>These capabilities aside, terminals located in ground stations constitute a critical vulnerability, as a terminal is an access point to a satellite and is usually not protected by authentication in order not to hinder operational actions. Terminals house software systems that can be compromised and require patching and upgrading. Moreover, software embedded in weapons systems (such as precision-guided munitions) could also be compromised.</p><p>At times, <u><mark>NATO</mark> allies <strong>procure equipment</u></strong> and software <u>to be <strong>integrated</strong> into their</u> national <u>defence architecture</u>, which becomes part of the overall NATO capability. <u>The commercial</u> supply <u><mark>chain</mark> is <strong><mark>embedded</strong> in</u></mark> nearly <u><strong><mark>every aspect</strong> of</mark> military</u> <u><mark>equipment</u></mark>. <u>This may not necessarily</u> <u>be a <strong>particular vulnerability</u></strong>, as long as commercial equipment is designed to military standards and is secure. <u>However</u>, <u>if military standards</u> <u>are <strong>not met</strong>,</u> <u>items</u> <u>procured</u> from commercial industry with design flaws <u>may <strong>expose</u></strong> <u>NATO’s</u> <u>systems to <strong>additional vulnerabilities</u></strong>.</p><p>While the absence of data is easy to detect, the manipulation of data or erosion of confidentiality at such an interface is potentially more difficult to discern.</p><p><u><strong><mark>Civil</strong> satellites</u></mark>, <u>operated by <strong>private</strong> companies</u>, <u>may be <mark>used</u> <u>to fulfil</mark> </u>specific <u><mark>missions</u></mark> <u>in <strong>locations</strong> <mark>where</mark> NATO</u> <u><mark>allies</u> <u>do not have</mark> their</u> <u><strong>own space <mark>equipment</u></strong></mark>. <u>Ground stations</u> <u>constitute</u> <u><strong>further</strong> <strong>elements</u></strong> <u>that are relevant</u> for the data flow. <u>From a cybersecurity</u> point of view, <u><strong><mark>each interface</strong></mark> could</u> <u><mark>present a vulnerability</u></mark> <u>and</u> could <u>become a <strong>weakness</u></strong>, as an interface typically requires manual processes to establish its operation, and/or the administration of the components involved. Adversaries infiltrating ground- or space-based systems could exploit weak software implementation, or the incompatibility of network or data transfer protocols in the chain. While the absence of data is easy to detect, the manipulation of data or erosion of confidentiality at such an interface is potentially more difficult to discern. <u>Vulnerabilities can stem from</u>:</p><p><u>A <strong>higher number</strong> of data</u> exchange <u>interfaces</u> used between the military and civil sectors;</p><p>The fact that each actor has its own isolated view of its data network, protected by its own security standard;</p><p>The <u>use of <strong>old</strong> and</u> <u><strong>proprietary</u></strong> IT <u>hardware and software</u>; and</p><p>The <u>failure or <strong>inability</u></strong> <u>to conduct</u> regular <u>software updates</u> to remove known vulnerabilities.</p><p>In such an environment, it seems difficult to ensure security of the information delivered.</p><p>Space-specific risks for the NATO alliance and for key NATO countries</p><p><u>Space systems</u>, which include both satellites and ground stations, as well as related space products and services, <u>provide <strong>mission-critical</u></strong> <u>information both for</u> <u>NATO’s member states</u> and for the alliance <u>as a whole</u>. <u>NATO relies on <strong>space-based</u></strong> <u>assets</u> <u><strong>for almost all</strong> of</u> <u>its operations</u> <u>and missions</u>.29 Some of the critical missions that rely on space assets include: defence of NATO’s territory and the neighbouring regions; peacekeeping missions; humanitarian assistance and disaster relief; counterterrorism; and conflict prevention activities.</p><p>NATO does not own satellites. It owns and operates a few terrestrial elements, such as satellite communications (SATCOM) anchor stations and terminals. It requests access to products and services but does not have direct access to satellites, leaving it up to its allies to determine whether they provide access to their satellite capabilities. NATO has established memoranda of understanding with allies for possible use of space products and services.</p><p>Originally, in the US, space systems used by the military were separated from commercial and civilian assets in terms of their development and operation.30 One of the reasons for this separation was to protect the military structure against physical and cyberthreats. Military space system safety and security requirements were also higher and more stringent than in the commercial sphere (for example, requirements to invest in survivability enhancement mechanisms in order to resist jamming, or special design approaches for military space architecture). In recent years commercial methods, for instance the capture and analysis of satellite imagery, have been shown to be as effective as military means. As a result, <u>NATO uses a <strong>mix</strong> of military</u>, <u>civilian</u>, <u><strong>commercial</u></strong>, <u>and national/</u>multinational <u>assets</u> to conduct its operations. <u>The <strong>joint use</strong> of these assets</u>, <u>however</u>, <u>comes with an <strong>acceptance of inherent risk,</u></strong> not only to the countries that provide such capability but also <u>to the <strong>alliance as a whole.</u></strong> In response, the European Defence Agency, through its Governmental Satellite Communications (GOVSATCOM) development programme, decided to build an intermediary class of satellites between commercial SATCOM and military SATCOM, with security requirements able to address the needs of critical missions, including crisis management.31</p><p><u>There is <strong>increased dependence</strong> on</u> <u>space-based systems in</u> <u><strong>modern</u></strong> military <u>engagement</u>. During the US engagement in Iraq in 2003, 68 per cent of munitions were guided utilizing space-based means (including laser-, infrared- and satellite-guided munitions); this percentage had risen sharply from 10 per cent in 1990–91, during the first Gulf war.32 In its operations in Afghanistan in 2001, 60 per cent of the weapons used by the US were precision-guided munitions: these included bombs, missiles, and other weapons, many of which had the capability to correct their own positioning to hit the target, using space-derived information.33</p><p><u>Cyber <mark>vulnerabilities</u> <u><strong>undermine confidence</u></strong></mark> <u>in</u> strategic <u>systems</u>; <u>they <mark>increase <strong>uncertainty</u></strong></mark> <u>in information</u> and analysis, <u>which <strong><mark>impacts</mark> the <mark>credibility</strong></mark> <mark>of</u> <u><strong>deterrence</u></strong></mark> <u>and</u> strategic <u>stability</u>. <u><strong><mark>Loss of trust</strong></mark> in technology</u> also <u><mark>has implications</u> <u>for <strong>attribution</u></strong></mark> <u>and</u> strategic <u><strong>calculus</strong> in crisis</u> <u>decision-making and</u> may <u><mark>increase</mark> the risk of <strong><mark>misperception</u></strong></mark>.</p><p><u>This <strong>dependency</u></strong> on space-based technology <u>has major <strong>implications</u></strong> <u>for</u> the way <u>NATO</u> conducts warfare today, and how it will do so in the future. For instance, in order to conduct precision strikes or earth observation through the use of unmanned aerial vehicles (UAVs – such as military drones), <u>systems</u> <u>rely on so-called ‘</u>beyond-line-of-sight’ (<u><strong>BLOS</u></strong>) <u>communication via satellites</u> – <u>especially in times of <strong>crisis and conflict</u></strong>, since ground-based line-of-sight communications are vulnerable to physical attacks. <u>Yet</u>, <u>cyberattacks</u> <u>on space technology</u> or on the UAVs <u>may lead them</u> <u>to <strong>misinterpret</strong> commands</u>, or to lose contact with the command centre and fail in operation. ***TABLE 1 OMITTED*** Identification is another important capability that is used in the NATO maritime domain for coastal tracking, and for identifying and locating ships and vessels. Using automatic identification systems (AIS), data is electronically transmitted between ships and the coastal stations. By providing similar functions, AIS supplements and provides resilience to maritime radar and is fundamental for avoiding collisions.36</p><p><u><mark>NATO’s</mark> space-dependent</u> <u><mark>capabilities</u></mark> <u>have <strong>individual</u></strong> <u>functions</u>, as described above. <u>These capabilities</u> <u><mark>are</u></mark> also <u><strong><mark>coupled</strong></mark> to each other</u>, <u><mark>with <strong>complex</mark> cross-<mark>dependencies</u></strong></mark>, <u>so that the <strong><mark>loss of one</u></strong></mark> <u>capability</u> <u>may <mark>have a <strong>collateral impact</strong> on other</mark> capabilitie<mark>s</u></mark>. For instance, <u>most of the assets that</u> <u>transmit</u> <u>communications</u> to support command and control <u>are</u> also <u><strong>dependent</strong> on GPS</u> <u>for <strong>timing</strong> and <strong>synchronization</u></strong>.37 Although there would be a number of contenders for technologies of utmost importance to NATO missions and operations, preliminary research indicates that PNT signals (which utilize GPS) are a much-needed priority capability in almost all NATO operations.</p>
1AC---SPACE ASSETS
1AC---SPACE ASSETS
1AC---SOLVENCY
1,651,124
777
143,522
./documents/hspolicy22/GlenbrookNorth/ElKe/GlenbrookNorth-ElKe-Aff-MSU-Round-4.docx
951,708
A
MSU
4
Niles North SG
Bennett
1AC - Cyber Space Assets 1NC - Security K, T - A5 2NR - Security K
hspolicy22/GlenbrookNorth/ElKe/GlenbrookNorth-ElKe-Aff-MSU-Round-4.docx
2022-12-03 19:07:33
83,727
ElKe
Glenbrook North ElKe
null
Ky.....
El.....
Ki.....
Ke.....
26,739
GlenbrookNorth
Glenbrook North
IL
3,557
2,002
hspolicy22
HS Policy 2022-23
2,022
cx
hs
2
4,743,979
That escalates every existential threat – nuclear war, global warming, and mass structural violence
Gregory 19
Gregory 19 [Madeleine Gregory, "Nationalism Is an Environmental Disaster," VICE, 10-2-2019, https://www.vice.com/en/article/xwe4vz/nationalism-is-an-environmental-disaster] //marlborough-oo/
Blind nationalism is the enemy of the environment. What it will do is divide populations of animal species, fragment and degrade ecosystems, and bulldoze landmark environmental measures A 2005 law called the Real ID Act gives U.S. Customs and Border Protection the authority to waive any law at the border in the name of national security through this law environmental protections are ignored Science has generated enough information to say has had a negative effect on wildlife and ecosystems 2018 BioScience article had more than 2,000 scientist signatures nationalism’s can incite conflict with serious environmental side effects, hinder global climate action, spell doom for wildlife, and facilitates eco-fasicsm—the marriage of extreme racism with paltry environmentalism By straining international relations blind nationalism stymies research in the borderlands knowledge sharing have long taken part in to achieve environmental goals scientists have collaborated across borderlands in U.S., Mexico, Canada to protect migratory species The borderlands form the bridge between the Rockies above and the tropics below Erecting a wall nationalism end cooperation or make collaboration much more difficult to understand this transition zone, where many different species and ecosystems meet Stopping international climate action Nationalism’s potential for environmental hazard scales all the way up to planet-wide existential risk Disputes over water rights, endangered species, natural disasters, land development, changing weather patterns lead to wars, displace millions of people, and cause mass extinction of species Having neighboring countries with contradictory and self-serving environmental protections spell trouble for addressing climate crisis Many countries see reducing emissions as an economic sacrifice, one they don’t want to make if any other countries aren't following the program 2015 Paris Agreement Trump’s decision to pull out exactly the kind of blind nationalism that acts against every major environmental goal Nationalistic views are pure ignorance We must act globally because climate change affects the whole world Nationalism breeds conflict, and conflict is bad for the environment Conflict requires intensive resource extraction, can degrade ecosystems, and can contaminate the environment Military vehicles contaminate the air and water of warzones impacting the local region and feeding climate change from 1965 to 1971, the US sprayed nearly 4,000 kilometres squared of Vietnamese land with herbicides If nuclear weapons get involved radiation contamination severely degrade ecosystem health, threatening the lives of humans and animals Two recent mass shooters have espoused eco-fascism, an ideology that uses impending climate catastrophe as a backdrop to spread extreme racism Eco-fascism scapegoats immigrants for environmental degradation while letting corporations and governments prop them up off the hook Environmentalism necessitates that humans act as part of ecosystems and international networks, while nationalism and eco-fascism entrench anthropocentrism
nationalism will divide species, fragment and degrade ecosystems, and bulldoze environmental measures nationalism’ hinder global climate action and facilitates eco-fasicsm— By straining international relations nationalism stymies research knowledge sharing Nationalism’s environmental hazard existential risk. Disputes over water species natural disasters, land changing weather lead to wars displace millions and cause mass extinction countries see reducing emissions as sacrifice one they don’t make if any other countries aren't following the program We must act globally Nationalism breeds conflict and intensive resource extraction If nuclear weapons get involved radiation contamination severely degrade ecosystem health, threatening the lives of humans and animals Eco-fascism scapegoats immigrants for degradation
Blind nationalism is the enemy of the environment. Consider President Donald Trump's infamous expanding border wall, a physical manifestation of the current administration's xenophobic, blatantly racist nationalism. The wall's intended purpose—to exclude people from Latin America from this country—likely won’t be achieved. Many undocumented immigrants are already in this country, and a wall won't solve the problems that xenophobes claim they're worried about. It also won’t keep out the majority of undocumented immigrants, those who overstay work visas rather than hop the border. What it will do, besides serve as a monument to cruelty, is divide populations of animal species, fragment and degrade ecosystems, and bulldoze landmark environmental measures in the name of national security. A 2005 law called the Real ID Act gives U.S. Customs and Border Protection the authority to waive pretty much any law at the border in the name of national security. It's through this law that environmental protections are ignored to build Trump's wall. “Science has generated enough information to say beyond doubt that the wall has, will have, and has had a negative effect on wildlife and ecosystems,” said Mexican conservation biologist Rurik List. List was one of the signatories of a 2018 BioScience article decrying the wall. The article had more than 2,000 scientist signatures, including well-known biologists E.O. Wilson and Michael Soulé. Blind nationalism’s harm to the environment doesn’t stop at the wall: It can incite conflict with serious environmental side effects, hinder global climate action, spell doom for wildlife, and facilitates eco-fasicsm—the marriage of extreme racism with paltry environmentalism. “Usually when something impacts the environment, there’s a large chunk of mitigation money to restore habitats or protect alternative habitat. Those mitigation dollars [are] drying up or not being offered at all,” said Dan Millis, an organizer with the Sierra Club Borderlands group. “People are treating the most vibrant areas of our country like a sacrifice zone.” Disrupting borderlands research By building a wall and straining international relations, blind nationalism stymies research in the borderlands. The basic function of science is knowledge sharing, a tradition that scientists from the U.S. and Mexico have long taken part in to achieve environmental goals; scientists have collaborated across the borderlands, and lawmakers in the U.S., Mexico, Canada, and other nations have signed joint treaties to protect migratory species. Our countries are inextricably physically connected, divided only by an arbitrary border that no animal, plant, or ecosystem respects. The borderlands form the bridge between the Rockies above and the tropics below. Erecting a wall (nationalism) could functionally end much of the cooperation—or, at least, make collaboration much more difficult—to understand this transition zone, where many different species and ecosystems meet. Trump's border wall would end American return of jaguar “Scientists are encountering real challenges doing research near the border because there’s so much security,” said Jennie Miller, a senior scientist at the conservation non-profit Defenders of Wildlife and another signatory of the BioScience border wall article. “If they can’t do research, we won’t be able to document what the border wall is doing to the ecosystem.” Having data on such a unique ecosystem is particularly important when facing the climate crisis, where understanding ecosystem response to climate change is pivotal in further protecting nature. Climate change is forcing many species to move to find more suitable habitats, which is far more difficult with a wall in the way. Stopping international climate action Nationalism’s potential for environmental hazard scales all the way up to planet-wide existential risk. Climate change is a global problem that affects every aspect of our world. Disputes over water rights, endangered species, natural disasters, land development, changing weather patterns: these could lead to wars, displace millions of people, and cause mass extinction of species. Having neighboring countries with contradictory and self-serving environmental protections can spell trouble for addressing the climate crisis. Many countries still see reducing emissions as an economic sacrifice, one they don’t want to make if any other countries aren't following the program. That’s why the 2015 Paris Agreement was so pivotal—every major world power agreed to work on climate action together. Trump’s decision to pull out of the deal in the name of putting "America first" is exactly the kind of blind nationalism that acts against every major environmental goal. “Nationalistic views are pure ignorance,” List said. “We must act globally because climate change affects the whole world.” Nationalism, war, and eco-fascism Yet another facet of nationalism's negative environmental effects is war. Nationalism breeds conflict, and conflict is bad for the environment. Conflict requires intensive resource extraction, can degrade ecosystems, and can contaminate the environment. Military vehicles contaminate both the air and water of warzones, for example, impacting the local region and feeding climate change. Environmental destruction has also been used as a war tactic. For example, from 1965 to 1971, the US sprayed nearly 4,000 kilometres squared of Vietnamese land with herbicides. If nuclear weapons get involved, radiation contamination can severely degrade ecosystem health, threatening the lives of humans and other animals. Already, some far-right groups have chosen to marry violence and xenophobia with a kind of warped environmentalism. Two recent mass shooters have espoused eco-fascism, an ideology that essentially uses the impending climate catastrophe as a backdrop to spread extreme racism. Eco-fascism scapegoats immigrants for environmental degradation while letting profiteering corporations and the governments that prop them up off the hook. This is hardly environmentalism’s first brush with racism, but eco-fascism’s growing strength and capacity to incite violence cast those oft-overlooked prejudices in a fresh light. Not only is this marriage between environmentalism, nationalism, and violence destructive and disturbing, it’s also misguided. Environmentalism necessitates that humans act as part of ecosystems and international networks, while nationalism and eco-fascism entrench anthropocentrism and strengthen borders. As we begin to feel the effects of climate change more acutely, relocating people out of potential disaster zones is critical. If every border becomes a wall, these planned retreats will be a logistical and human rights nightmare. Our world is simultaneously more connected and more divided than it ever has been. Those divisions, if weaponized, will continue to drive us towards climate crisis and human misery. That connectivity, if utilized, is our best shot at a livable world.
7,029
<h4>That escalates <u>every existential threat</u> – nuclear war, global warming, and mass structural violence</h4><p><strong>Gregory 19</strong> [Madeleine Gregory, "Nationalism Is an Environmental Disaster," VICE, 10-2-2019, https://www.vice.com/en/article/xwe4vz/nationalism-is-an-environmental-disaster] //marlborough-oo/</p><p><u>Blind <mark>nationalism </mark>is the enemy of the environment.</u> Consider President Donald Trump's infamous expanding border wall, a physical manifestation of the current administration's xenophobic, blatantly racist nationalism. The wall's intended purpose—to exclude people from Latin America from this country—likely won’t be achieved. Many undocumented immigrants are already in this country, and a wall won't solve the problems that xenophobes claim they're worried about. It also won’t keep out the majority of undocumented immigrants, those who overstay work visas rather than hop the border. <u>What it <mark>will</mark> do</u>, besides serve as a monument to cruelty, <u>is <mark>divide </mark>populations of animal <mark>species, fragment and degrade ecosystems, and bulldoze </mark>landmark <mark>environmental measures</u></mark> in the name of national security. <u>A 2005 law called the Real ID Act gives U.S. Customs and Border Protection the authority to waive</u> pretty much <u>any law at the border in the name of national security</u>. It's <u>through this law</u> that <u>environmental protections are ignored </u>to build Trump's wall. “<u>Science has generated enough information to say </u>beyond doubt that the wall has, will have, and<u> has had a negative effect on wildlife and ecosystems</u>,” said Mexican conservation biologist Rurik List. List was one of the signatories of a <u>2018 BioScience article</u> decrying the wall. The article <u>had more than 2,000 scientist signatures</u>, including well-known biologists E.O. Wilson and Michael Soulé. Blind <u><mark>nationalism’</mark>s</u> harm to the environment doesn’t stop at the wall: It<u> can incite conflict with serious environmental side effects, <mark>hinder global climate action</mark>, spell doom for wildlife, <mark>and facilitates eco-fasicsm—</mark>the marriage of extreme racism with paltry environmentalism</u>. “Usually when something impacts the environment, there’s a large chunk of mitigation money to restore habitats or protect alternative habitat. Those mitigation dollars [are] drying up or not being offered at all,” said Dan Millis, an organizer with the Sierra Club Borderlands group. “People are treating the most vibrant areas of our country like a sacrifice zone.” Disrupting borderlands research <u><mark>By</u></mark> building a wall and <u><mark>straining international relations</u></mark>, <u>blind <mark>nationalism stymies research</mark> in the borderlands</u>. The basic function of science is <u><mark>knowledge sharing</u></mark>, a tradition that scientists from the U.S. and Mexico <u>have long taken part in to achieve environmental goals</u>; <u>scientists have collaborated across</u> the <u>borderlands</u>, and lawmakers <u>in</u> the <u>U.S., Mexico, Canada</u>, and other nations have signed joint treaties <u>to protect migratory species</u>. Our countries are inextricably physically connected, divided only by an arbitrary border that no animal, plant, or ecosystem respects. <u>The borderlands form the bridge between the Rockies above and the tropics below</u>. <u>Erecting a wall</u> (<u>nationalism</u>) could functionally <u>end</u> much of the <u>cooperation</u>—<u>or</u>, at least, <u>make collaboration much more difficult</u>—<u>to</u> <u>understand this transition zone, where many different species and ecosystems meet</u>. Trump's border wall would end American return of jaguar “Scientists are encountering real challenges doing research near the border because there’s so much security,” said Jennie Miller, a senior scientist at the conservation non-profit Defenders of Wildlife and another signatory of the BioScience border wall article. “If they can’t do research, we won’t be able to document what the border wall is doing to the ecosystem.” Having data on such a unique ecosystem is particularly important when facing the climate crisis, where understanding ecosystem response to climate change is pivotal in further protecting nature. Climate change is forcing many species to move to find more suitable habitats, which is far more difficult with a wall in the way. <u>Stopping international climate action <mark>Nationalism’s </mark>potential for <mark>environmental hazard </mark>scales all the way up to planet-wide <mark>existential risk</u>.</mark> Climate change is a global problem that affects every aspect of our world. <u><mark>Disputes</mark> <mark>over water</mark> rights, endangered <mark>species</mark>, <mark>natural disasters, land</mark> development, <mark>changing</mark> <mark>weather</mark> patterns</u>: these could <u><mark>lead to wars</mark>, <mark>displace</mark> <mark>millions</mark> of people, <mark>and cause mass</mark> <mark>extinction</mark> of species</u>. <u>Having neighboring countries with contradictory and self-serving environmental protections</u> can <u>spell trouble for addressing</u> the <u>climate crisis</u>. <u>Many <mark>countries</u></mark> still <u><mark>see</mark> <mark>reducing</mark> <mark>emissions</mark> <mark>as</mark> an economic <mark>sacrifice</mark>, <mark>one</mark> <mark>they</mark> <mark>don’t</mark> want to<mark> make</mark> <mark>if</mark> <mark>any</mark> <mark>other</mark> <mark>countries</mark> <mark>aren't following the program</u></mark>. That’s why the <u>2015 Paris Agreement</u> was so pivotal—every major world power agreed to work on climate action together. <u>Trump’s decision to pull out</u> of the deal in the name of putting "America first" is <u>exactly the kind of blind nationalism that acts against every major environmental goal</u>. “<u>Nationalistic views are pure ignorance</u>,” List said. “<u><mark>We</u></mark> <u><mark>must act globally</mark> because climate change affects the whole world</u>.” Nationalism, war, and eco-fascism Yet another facet of nationalism's negative environmental effects is war. <u><mark>Nationalism breeds conflict</mark>, <mark>and</mark> conflict is bad for the environment</u>. <u>Conflict</u> <u>requires <mark>intensive resource extraction</mark>, can degrade ecosystems, and can contaminate the environment</u>. <u>Military vehicles</u> <u>contaminate</u> both <u>the air and water of warzones</u>, for example, <u>impacting the local region and feeding climate change</u>. Environmental destruction has also been used as a war tactic. For example, <u>from 1965 to 1971, the US sprayed nearly 4,000 kilometres squared of Vietnamese land with herbicides</u>. <u><mark>If nuclear weapons</u> <u>get</u> <u>involved</u></mark>, <u><mark>radiation contamination</u></mark> can <u><mark>severely degrade ecosystem health, threatening the lives of humans and</u></mark> other <u><mark>animals</u></mark>. Already, some far-right groups have chosen to marry violence and xenophobia with a kind of warped environmentalism. <u>Two recent mass shooters have espoused eco-fascism, an ideology that</u> essentially <u>uses</u> the <u>impending climate catastrophe as a backdrop to spread extreme racism</u>. <u><mark>Eco-fascism</u> <u>scapegoats immigrants for</mark> environmental <mark>degradation</mark> while letting</u> profiteering <u>corporations and</u> the <u>governments</u> that <u>prop them up off the hook</u>. This is hardly environmentalism’s first brush with racism, but eco-fascism’s growing strength and capacity to incite violence cast those oft-overlooked prejudices in a fresh light. Not only is this marriage between environmentalism, nationalism, and violence destructive and disturbing, it’s also misguided. <u>Environmentalism necessitates that humans act as part of ecosystems and international networks, while nationalism and eco-fascism entrench anthropocentrism </u>and strengthen borders. As we begin to feel the effects of climate change more acutely, relocating people out of potential disaster zones is critical. If every border becomes a wall, these planned retreats will be a logistical and human rights nightmare. Our world is simultaneously more connected and more divided than it ever has been. Those divisions, if weaponized, will continue to drive us towards climate crisis and human misery. That connectivity, if utilized, is our best shot at a livable world. </p>
null
null
3
21,490
261
165,786
./documents/hsld22/Marlborough/HoLe/Marlborough-HoLe-Neg-Golden-Desert-Octas.docx
976,519
N
Golden Desert
Octas
Peninsula AY
panel
1ac - maritime 1nc - t borders, adv cp, populism da, cap k, pandemics pic, case 1ar - all, condo nr - adv cp, populism da 2ar - cp, da, case
hsld22/Marlborough/HoLe/Marlborough-HoLe-Neg-Golden-Desert-Octas.docx
2023-02-14 18:42:54
80,412
HoLe
Marlborough HoLe
null
Ho.....
Le.....
null
null
26,925
Marlborough
Marlborough
CA
null
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
4,768,894
Regional Frameworks that start and are driven by ASEAN are key – unity, leadership, and integration are key to Centrality.
Teodoro 16
Teodoro 16 Joycee A Teodoro December 2016 "Distracted ASEAN? Where To For ASEAN Centrality?" https://fsi.gov.ph/distracted-asean-where-to-for-asean-centrality/ (Experienced Public Policy Specialist with a demonstrated history of working in the public policy industry for more than eight years.)//Elmer
The ASEAN Charter and key documents, such as the ASEAN Community Vision 2025: Forging Ahead Together, explicitly state that ASEAN maintains its centrality in the regional processes and in the conduct of its external affairs Maintaining centrality is crucial to ASEAN’s success as a regional bloc and critical to its relevance in the international arena Moreover, through ASEAN centrality, a rules-based regional order is promoted and developed, consequently diffusing potential tension and conflict between and among states, whether big or small ASEAN centrality rests on the idea ASEAN has the capacity to play a leading and driver role vis-à-vis regional agenda setting puts premium on ASEAN’s ability to act as leader, driver, and fulcrum of regional initiatives in relating with its external partners while promoting, first and foremost, ASEAN’s own interests . However, the assertion of this centrality draws strength from a politically cohesive, strategically coherent and economically prosperous ASEAN. These will serve as strong foundations for ASEAN in playing and asserting with credibility this centrality role Their domestic politics/concerns may distract the respective governments to deal with regional issues Also, due to different appreciation of issues such as geostrategic ones, the AMS may be susceptible into making compromises that may only be beneficial to a few but not to the entire ASEAN region. that there is a need to have a two-level mindset wherein the AMS do not only think about their national interests “but posit them against regional interests”. Drawing ASEAN centrality from internal progress ASEAN’s next steps on the deepening and broadening of regional community building efforts have been laid down by the ASEAN Community Vision 2025 The vision of achieving an integrated ASEAN will bear into fruition if these regional commitments are translated down to the domestic level The alignment of the regional instruments to the national policies is crucial if ASEAN intends to fast track the implementation of regional commitments down to the respective AMS. The successful realization of the vision and action lines, therefore, will result in a more progressive and stable ASEAN. These positive developments will undoubtedly help ASEAN in solidifying its stronghold on centrality. pressing issues faced by ASEAN, as a whole, and Member States, individually, should serve as a constant reminder to behave and act coherently. ASEAN centrality will not hold true even if the concept is established in the ASEAN Charter. Efforts and commitment are needed to ensure that centrality is not only on paper but practiced by ASEAN
centrality crucial to ASEAN’s relevance in the international arena the idea ASEAN a leading and driver role vis-à-vis regional agenda setting leader, driver, and fulcrum with its while promoting ASEAN’s own interests centrality draws prosperous ASEAN. serve as foundations for ASEAN with credibility Drawing centrality from internal progress next steps on broadening regional community building alignment of regional instruments will help ASEAN in solidifying centrality a constant reminder to behave and act coherently Efforts needed to ensure centrality is not on paper but practiced
The ASEAN Charter and key documents, such as the ASEAN Community Vision 2025: Forging Ahead Together, explicitly state that ASEAN maintains its centrality in the regional processes and in the conduct of its external affairs. Maintaining centrality is crucial to ASEAN’s success as a regional bloc and critical to its relevance in the international arena. Moreover, through ASEAN centrality, a rules-based regional order is promoted and developed, consequently diffusing potential tension and conflict between and among states, whether big or small. ASEAN centrality rests on the idea that ASEAN has the capacity to play a leading and driver role vis-à-vis regional agenda setting.1 It also puts premium on ASEAN’s ability to act as leader, driver, and fulcrum of regional initiatives in relating with its external partners, while promoting, first and foremost, ASEAN’s own interests. ASEAN centrality is defined as ASEAN’s role in the regional security architecture, regional order, and the power dynamics between and among external powers that have interests in the region. However, the assertion of this centrality draws strength from a politically cohesive, strategically coherent and economically prosperous ASEAN. These will serve as strong foundations for ASEAN in playing and asserting with credibility this centrality role. However, ASEAN’s cohesion, coherence and relations within ASEAN are showing cracks. The setbacks in recent years, most especially in the political-security issues, have only highlighted the internal friction between and among the AMS, due in part to the differences in threat perception on strategic issues they face in common. Moreover, the AMS are facing domestic issues that may divide their attention—whether attending first to the needs of the country and their constituents or attending to their regional commitments. It is against this backdrop that ASEAN is having a hard time in asserting with confidence its centrality. Distracted ASEAN? The imperative on the AMS to deliver on the regional commitments as outlined by past and newly adopted blueprints cannot be overemphasized. More so, the expectation on ASEAN to make a unified stand on key strategic issues becomes more pressing not only because ASEAN is now formally a Community, but because the dynamic geostrategic environment demands it to be one. But looking closely as to how ASEAN has responded as a bloc to strategic issues, one may be led to think that ASEAN may be falling short of expectations; the implications of which falls heavily on its credibility to assert a central role. In recent months, ASEAN was faced with situations wherein its unity and resolve as a bloc was put under stress. The setbacks in Kunming during the Special ASEAN-China Foreign Ministers’ Meeting and the non-issuance of an ASEAN statement with regard to the Permanent Court of Arbitration’s ruling on the Philippines’ case are some examples that show ASEAN is falling behind expectations. Rather than being able to come up with a common voice, these situations only highlight that with respect to pressing developments, the AMS are not all on the same side of the fence. These also point to the bigger picture that the appreciation of issues, or threat perception among the countries, remains different among the AMS. With respect to domestic issues, the individual AMS are also faced with concerns that need immediate attention. The possible implication of such a situation is that these may more likely to take precedence over the regional concerns. Domestic politics, no doubt, will have a ripple effect on ASEAN. For instance, several AMS are facing political and economic uncertainties. In Cambodia, there is a growing concern on the escalation of political tensions between the government and the opposition as the general election in 2018 draws near. Malaysia has been grappling with questions on the political legitimacy of its leadership due to governance issues. Myanmar, while undergoing numerous changes since a new leadership was installed, is facing some setbacks, in particular on the peace process with the indigenous groups (e.g., Rohingya). Under a new leadership, the Philippines is recalibrating its policy directions, with a strong focus on internal peace and order situation, in particular fighting drugs and criminality. Also, the country’s foreign policy is undergoing some calibrations under the new administration. In Thailand, there is a cloud of uncertainty on the country’s political future as it transitions to a new era without the guidance of its revered leader King Bhumibol Addulyadej, the anchor of the Thai society. Indonesia, meanwhile, is relatively less engaged regionally as it was before and the effect of which is palpable because Indonesia is regarded as the natural leader of ASEAN. As a result, ASEAN has been devoid of Indonesia’s leadership and guidance.2 On the other hand, this may also provide an opportunity for other AMS to take on the responsibility of leading ASEAN in sectors where they are believed to be at the forefront. Without question, all of these developments affect the regional bloc. Their domestic politics/concerns may distract the respective governments to deal with regional issues. Also, due to different appreciation of issues such as geostrategic ones, the AMS may be susceptible into making compromises that may only be beneficial to a few but not to the entire ASEAN region. It may be timely to remember what S. Rajaratnam, one of the Founding Fathers of ASEAN said during the signing of the Bangkok Declaration – that there is a need to have a two-level mindset wherein the AMS do not only think about their national interests “but posit them against regional interests”. He furthered that while these two may conflict, ASEAN needs to face these painful adjustments if the bloc intends to succeed. Drawing ASEAN centrality from internal progress ASEAN’s next steps on the deepening and broadening of regional community building efforts have been laid down by the ASEAN Community Vision 2025. In addition, the recently adopted Initiative for ASEAN Integration Work Plan III and the Master Plan on ASEAN Connectivity 2025 will complement the Community Pillars’ blueprints to ensure that community building remains on track. More importantly, the Leaders, through the Kuala Lumpur Declaration on ASEAN 2025, resolved that the AMS together with the ASEAN Organs and Bodies shall implement the action lines identified in these documents. These documents are aimed at delivering tangible benefits to the region, to the individual AMS, and more importantly, to the peoples of ASEAN. The vision of achieving an integrated ASEAN will bear into fruition if these regional commitments are translated down to the domestic level. The work is cut out for the AMS. Institutionally, the AMS are expected to take heed of regional developments so that the implementation of commitments is not constrained by the respective bureaucratic set-ups. The alignment of the regional instruments to the national policies is crucial if ASEAN intends to fast track the implementation of regional commitments down to the respective AMS. The successful realization of the vision and action lines, therefore, will result in a more progressive and stable ASEAN. These positive developments will undoubtedly help ASEAN in solidifying its stronghold on centrality. The pressing issues faced by ASEAN, as a whole, and Member States, individually, should serve as a constant reminder to behave and act coherently. ASEAN centrality will not hold true even if the concept is established in the ASEAN Charter. Efforts and commitment are needed to ensure that centrality is not only on paper but practiced by ASEAN.
7,733
<h4>Regional Frameworks that <u>start</u> and are <u>driven</u> by ASEAN are key – <u>unity</u>, <u>leadership</u>, and <u>integration</u> are key to Centrality. </h4><p><strong>Teodoro 16</strong> Joycee A Teodoro December 2016 "Distracted ASEAN? Where To For ASEAN Centrality?" https://fsi.gov.ph/distracted-asean-where-to-for-asean-centrality/ (Experienced Public Policy Specialist with a demonstrated history of working in the public policy industry for more than eight years.)//Elmer </p><p><u>The ASEAN Charter and key documents, such as the ASEAN Community Vision 2025: Forging Ahead Together, explicitly state that ASEAN maintains its centrality in the regional processes and in the conduct of its external affairs</u>. <u><strong>Maintaining <mark>centrality</strong> </mark>is <strong><mark>crucial to ASEAN’s</strong> </mark>success as a regional bloc and critical to its <strong><mark>relevance</strong> <strong>in the international arena</u></strong></mark>. <u>Moreover, through ASEAN centrality, <strong>a rules-based regional order is promoted</strong> and developed, consequently <strong>diffusing</strong> potential <strong>tension and conflict</strong> between and among states, whether big or small</u>. <u>ASEAN</u> <u><strong>centrality</u></strong> <u><strong>rests on <mark>the idea</u></strong> </mark>that <u><strong><mark>ASEAN </mark>has the capacity to play <mark>a leading and driver role vis-à-vis regional agenda setting</u></strong></mark>.1 It also <u><strong>puts premium on ASEAN’s ability to act as <mark>leader, driver, and fulcrum</u></strong> <u></mark>of regional initiatives in relating</u> <u><strong><mark>with its </mark>external partners</u></strong>, <u><strong><mark>while</u></strong> <u><strong>promoting</strong></mark>, first and foremost,</u> <u><strong><mark>ASEAN’s own interests</u></strong></mark>. ASEAN centrality is defined as ASEAN’s role in the regional security architecture, regional order, and the power dynamics between and among external powers that have interests in the region<u>. However, the assertion of this <strong><mark>centrality</strong> <strong>draws</strong> </mark>strength <strong>from</strong> a <strong>politically cohesive</strong>, <strong>strategically coherent</strong> <strong>and economically <mark>prosperous ASEAN.</u></strong></mark> <u>These will <strong><mark>serve</strong> <strong>as</strong> </mark>strong <strong><mark>foundations</strong> <strong>for ASEAN</strong> </mark>in playing and asserting <strong><mark>with credibility</strong> </mark>this centrality role</u>. However, ASEAN’s cohesion, coherence and relations within ASEAN are showing cracks. The setbacks in recent years, most especially in the political-security issues, have only highlighted the internal friction between and among the AMS, due in part to the differences in threat perception on strategic issues they face in common. Moreover, the AMS are facing domestic issues that may divide their attention—whether attending first to the needs of the country and their constituents or attending to their regional commitments. It is against this backdrop that ASEAN is having a hard time in asserting with confidence its centrality. Distracted ASEAN? The imperative on the AMS to deliver on the regional commitments as outlined by past and newly adopted blueprints cannot be overemphasized. More so, the expectation on ASEAN to make a unified stand on key strategic issues becomes more pressing not only because ASEAN is now formally a Community, but because the dynamic geostrategic environment demands it to be one. But looking closely as to how ASEAN has responded as a bloc to strategic issues, one may be led to think that ASEAN may be falling short of expectations; the implications of which falls heavily on its credibility to assert a central role. In recent months, ASEAN was faced with situations wherein its unity and resolve as a bloc was put under stress. The setbacks in Kunming during the Special ASEAN-China Foreign Ministers’ Meeting and the non-issuance of an ASEAN statement with regard to the Permanent Court of Arbitration’s ruling on the Philippines’ case are some examples that show ASEAN is falling behind expectations. Rather than being able to come up with a common voice, these situations only highlight that with respect to pressing developments, the AMS are not all on the same side of the fence. These also point to the bigger picture that the appreciation of issues, or threat perception among the countries, remains different among the AMS. With respect to domestic issues, the individual AMS are also faced with concerns that need immediate attention. The possible implication of such a situation is that these may more likely to take precedence over the regional concerns. Domestic politics, no doubt, will have a ripple effect on ASEAN. For instance, several AMS are facing political and economic uncertainties. In Cambodia, there is a growing concern on the escalation of political tensions between the government and the opposition as the general election in 2018 draws near. Malaysia has been grappling with questions on the political legitimacy of its leadership due to governance issues. Myanmar, while undergoing numerous changes since a new leadership was installed, is facing some setbacks, in particular on the peace process with the indigenous groups (e.g., Rohingya). Under a new leadership, the Philippines is recalibrating its policy directions, with a strong focus on internal peace and order situation, in particular fighting drugs and criminality. Also, the country’s foreign policy is undergoing some calibrations under the new administration. In Thailand, there is a cloud of uncertainty on the country’s political future as it transitions to a new era without the guidance of its revered leader King Bhumibol Addulyadej, the anchor of the Thai society. Indonesia, meanwhile, is relatively less engaged regionally as it was before and the effect of which is palpable because Indonesia is regarded as the natural leader of ASEAN. As a result, ASEAN has been devoid of Indonesia’s leadership and guidance.2 On the other hand, this may also provide an opportunity for other AMS to take on the responsibility of leading ASEAN in sectors where they are believed to be at the forefront. Without question, all of these developments affect the regional bloc. <u>Their domestic politics/concerns may distract the respective governments to deal with regional issues</u>. <u>Also, due to different appreciation of issues such as geostrategic ones, the AMS may be susceptible into making compromises that may only be beneficial to a few but not to the entire ASEAN region. </u>It may be timely to remember what S. Rajaratnam, one of the Founding Fathers of ASEAN said during the signing of the Bangkok Declaration – <u>that there is a need to have a two-level mindset wherein the AMS do not only think about their national interests “but posit them against regional interests”.</u> He furthered that while these two may conflict, ASEAN needs to face these painful adjustments if the bloc intends to succeed. <u><strong><mark>Drawing</strong> </mark>ASEAN <strong><mark>centrality from internal progress</strong> </mark>ASEAN’s <strong><mark>next steps on</strong> </mark>the deepening and <strong><mark>broadening</strong> </mark>of <strong><mark>regional community building</strong> </mark>efforts have been laid down by the ASEAN Community Vision 2025</u>. In addition, the recently adopted Initiative for ASEAN Integration Work Plan III and the Master Plan on ASEAN Connectivity 2025 will complement the Community Pillars’ blueprints to ensure that community building remains on track. More importantly, the Leaders, through the Kuala Lumpur Declaration on ASEAN 2025, resolved that the AMS together with the ASEAN Organs and Bodies shall implement the action lines identified in these documents. These documents are aimed at delivering tangible benefits to the region, to the individual AMS, and more importantly, to the peoples of ASEAN. <u>The vision of achieving an integrated ASEAN will bear into fruition if these regional commitments are translated down to the domestic level</u>. The work is cut out for the AMS. Institutionally, the AMS are expected to take heed of regional developments so that the implementation of commitments is not constrained by the respective bureaucratic set-ups. <u>The <strong><mark>alignment</strong> <strong>of</strong> </mark>the <strong><mark>regional instruments</strong> </mark>to the national policies is crucial if ASEAN intends to fast track the implementation of regional commitments down to the respective AMS. The successful realization of the vision and action lines, therefore, <strong><mark>will</strong> </mark>result in a more progressive and stable ASEAN.</u> <u>These positive developments will undoubtedly <strong><mark>help ASEAN</strong> <strong>in solidifying</strong> </mark>its stronghold on <strong><mark>centrality</strong></mark>. </u>The <u>pressing issues faced by ASEAN, as a whole, and Member States, individually, should serve as <strong><mark>a constant reminder to</strong> <strong>behave and act coherently</strong></mark>. ASEAN centrality will not hold true even if the concept is established in the ASEAN Charter. <strong><mark>Efforts</strong> </mark>and commitment are <strong><mark>needed to ensure</strong> </mark>that <strong><mark>centrality is not</strong> </mark>only <strong><mark>on paper but practiced</strong> </mark>by ASEAN</u>.</p>
null
null
1AC Centrality
1,700,106
172
166,864
./documents/hsld22/PlanoEast/AaWa/PlanoEast-AaWa-Aff-Harvard-Round-3.docx
981,231
A
Harvard
3
Cary HA
Wyatt Hatfield
1AC ASEAN 1NC T-nebel, terror da, Myanmar conditions 1AR bible quote shell, condo, process bad, case all 2NR terror DA 2AR bible quote shell
hsld22/PlanoEast/AaWa/PlanoEast-AaWa-Aff-Harvard-Round-3.docx
2023-02-19 22:29:33
80,624
AaWa
Plano East AaWa
null
Aa.....
Wa.....
null
null
27,063
PlanoEast
Plano East
TX
null
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
1,836,685
Aff fails to solve
Guardiancich 17
Igor Guardiancich 17, Assistant Professor in the Department of Political Science and Public Management of the University of Southern Denmark, 3/3/2017, “Absorb, Coopt and Recast: Global Neoliberalism’s Resilience through Local Translation”, http://www.euvisions.eu/neoliberalisms-resilience-translation/
rather than a mass-produced, slightly shrunk, and off-the-rack ideological suit, neoliberalism is a bespoke outfit made from a dynamic fabric that absorbs local color Even under a full-out attack against some of its basic assumptions such as the one unleashed in the immediate wake of the global financial crisis neoliberalism proved resilient beyond its many architects’ wildest dreams. Its capacity to absorb, coopt and recast selected ideas of oppositional social forces has been the valuable asset guaranteeing its survival The socialist government of José Luis Rodríguez Zapatero tried to salvage the social-democratic legacies of the Spanish economy by engineering a Keynesian rescue package. Only later, when the disaster of the cajas became apparent and the emergency intensified, did conservative PM Mariano Rajoy embrace more deregulation In Romania, local policymakers further radicalized in the aftermath of the Lehman Brothers’ crisis, thereby outbidding the IMF on austerity and structural reforms. Instead of shielding lower-income groups, the opposite strategy of upward redistribution was chosen , despite the challenges, neoliberalism is alive and kicking
Even under a full-out attack against its basic assumptions unleashed in the financial crisis, neoliberalism proved resilient beyond its architects’ wildest dreams. Its capacity to absorb, coopt and recast guarantee its survival The socialist government of Zapatero tried to salvage the social-democratic legacies the disaster of the cajas intensified In Romania, local policymakers further radicalized despite challenges, neoliberalism is alive and kicking
One powerful message permeating the book, and which gives a forceful explanation to Colin Crouch’s punchy title is that: “rather than a mass-produced, slightly shrunk, and off-the-rack ideological suit, neoliberalism is a bespoke outfit made from a dynamic fabric that absorbs local color” (5). Even under a full-out attack against some of its basic assumptions, such as the one unleashed in the immediate wake of the global financial crisis, neoliberalism proved resilient beyond its many architects’ wildest dreams. Its capacity to absorb, coopt and recast selected ideas of oppositional social forces has been the most valuable asset guaranteeing its survival. Again, the comparison of the responses to the crisis in Spain and Romania show such adaptability in full.¶ The socialist government of José Luis Rodríguez Zapatero tried to salvage the social-democratic legacies of the Spanish economy by engineering a Keynesian rescue package. Only later, when the disaster of the cajas became apparent and the emergency intensified, did conservative PM Mariano Rajoy embrace more deregulation in the labour market (inspired by the Hartz IV reform) and extensive cuts in the public sector under the strong external pressure of the European Central Bank and of international financial markets.¶ In Romania, local policymakers further radicalized in the aftermath of the Lehman Brothers’ crisis, thereby outbidding the IMF on austerity and structural reforms. Instead of shielding lower-income groups, the opposite strategy of upward redistribution was chosen. By heroically withstanding the external attempts at moderation, the Romanian economy retained an unenviable mix of libertarian achievements (flat-tax rates), experimental neoliberalism (privatized pensions) and mainstream neoliberal orthodoxy (sound finance, labour market deregulation, social policy targeting, privatization of all public companies). Pure laissez-faire ideas such as the replacement of the welfare state by a voluntary, private, Christian charity system were not unheard of.¶ Hence, through an insightful analysis of the ideational underpinnings of its local interpretations, this book shows us that, despite the challenges, neoliberalism is alive and kicking. Ban guides us through half a century of policymaking in Spain and Romania, and embeds his analysis within the related nuances of contemporary liberal economic thought. The research is a valuable addition to a growing literature on the origin of current ideational frames and comfortably sits alongside contemporary classics, such as Mark Blyth’s Austerity: The History of a Dangerous Idea
2,624
<h4>Aff fails to solve</h4><p>Igor <strong>Guardiancich 17</strong>, Assistant Professor in the Department of Political Science and Public Management of the University of Southern Denmark, 3/3/2017, “Absorb, Coopt and Recast: Global Neoliberalism’s Resilience through Local Translation”, http://www.euvisions.eu/neoliberalisms-resilience-translation/ </p><p>One powerful message permeating the book, and which gives a forceful explanation to Colin Crouch’s punchy title is that: “<u>rather than a mass-produced, slightly shrunk, and off-the-rack ideological suit, neoliberalism is a bespoke outfit made from a dynamic fabric that absorbs local color</u>” (5). <u><mark>Even under a <strong>full-out attack</strong> against</mark> some of <mark>its basic assumptions</u></mark>, <u>such as the one <mark>unleashed in the</mark> immediate wake of the global <mark>financial crisis</u>, <u>neoliberalism proved resilient beyond its</mark> many <strong><mark>architects’ wildest dreams.</u></strong> <u>Its capacity to absorb, coopt and recast</mark> selected ideas of oppositional social forces has been the </u>most <u>valuable asset <mark>guarantee</mark>ing <mark>its survival</u></mark>. Again, the comparison of the responses to the crisis in Spain and Romania show such adaptability in full.¶ <u><mark>The socialist government of</mark> José Luis Rodríguez <mark>Zapatero</mark> <mark>tried to salvage the social-democratic legacies</mark> of the Spanish economy by engineering a Keynesian rescue package. Only later, when <mark>the disaster of the cajas</mark> became apparent and the emergency <mark>intensified</mark>, did conservative PM Mariano Rajoy embrace more deregulation</u> in the labour market (inspired by the Hartz IV reform) and extensive cuts in the public sector under the strong external pressure of the European Central Bank and of international financial markets.¶ <u><mark>In Romania, local policymakers further radicalized</mark> in the aftermath of the Lehman Brothers’ crisis, thereby outbidding the IMF on austerity and structural reforms. Instead of shielding lower-income groups, the opposite strategy of upward redistribution was chosen</u>. By heroically withstanding the external attempts at moderation, the Romanian economy retained an unenviable mix of libertarian achievements (flat-tax rates), experimental neoliberalism (privatized pensions) and mainstream neoliberal orthodoxy (sound finance, labour market deregulation, social policy targeting, privatization of all public companies). Pure laissez-faire ideas such as the replacement of the welfare state by a voluntary, private, Christian charity system were not unheard of.¶ Hence, through an insightful analysis of the ideational underpinnings of its local interpretations, this book shows us that<u>, <mark>despite</mark> the <mark>challenges, neoliberalism is <strong>alive and kicking</u></mark>. Ban guides us through half a century of policymaking in Spain and Romania, and embeds his analysis within the related nuances of contemporary liberal economic thought. The research is a valuable addition to a growing literature on the origin of current ideational frames and comfortably sits alongside contemporary classics, such as Mark Blyth’s Austerity: The History of a Dangerous Idea</p></strong>
Blake Round 5
1NC
Case
29,556
196
53,819
./documents/hspolicy20/Altamont/AnYa/Altamont-Anders-Yalamanchilli-Neg-Blake-Round5.docx
724,143
N
Blake
5
Bronx Science TD
Jefferson Yahom
Open Source
hspolicy20/Altamont/AnYa/Altamont-Anders-Yalamanchilli-Neg-Blake-Round5.docx
null
61,806
AnYa
Altamont AnYa
null
Ar.....
An.....
Ma.....
Ya.....
21,499
Altamont
Altamont
AL
null
1,019
hspolicy20
HS Policy 2020-21
2,020
cx
hs
2
2,103,999
1. Actor specificity – There is no act omission distinction for states since their implicit approvals of actions still entail moral responsibility.
Sunstein 05
Sunstein 05 [Cass R. Sunstein and Adrian Vermeule. The University of Chicago Law School. “Is Capital Punishment Morally Required? The Relevance of Life‐Life Tradeoffs.” JOHN M. OLIN LAW & ECONOMICS WORKING PAPER NO. 239. The Chicago Working Paper Series. March 2005] AJ
both the argument from causation and the argument from intention overlook the distinctive features of government unlike individuals, governments always and necessarily face a choice between policies for regulating third parties. government creat permissions and prohibitions. When it implicitly authorizes private action, it is not refusing to act. Moreover, the distinction between authorized and unauthorized private action—for example, private killing—becomes obscure when the government formally forbids private action, but chooses a set of policy instruments that do not fully discourage it.
unlike individuals, governments always face a choice between regulating third parties When it authorizes private action, it is not refusing to act the distinction between authorized and unauthorized action— becomes obscure when the government formally forbids private action, but do not fully discourage it.
In our view, both the argument from causation and the argument from intention go wrong by overlooking the distinctive features of government as a moral agent. Whatever the general status of the act-omission distinction as a matter of moral philosophy,38 the distinction is least impressive when applied to government.39 The most fundamental point is that unlike individuals, governments always and necessarily face a choice between or among possible policies for regulating third parties. The distinction between acts and omissions may not be intelligible in this context, and even if it is, the distinction does not make a morally relevant difference. Most generally, government is in the business of creating permissions and prohibitions. When it explicitly or implicitly authorizes private action, it is not omitting to do anything, or refusing to act.40 Moreover, the distinction between authorized and unauthorized private action—for example, private killing—becomes obscure when the government formally forbids private action, but chooses a set of policy instruments that do not adequately or fully discourage it.
1,119
<h4>1. Actor specificity – There is no act omission distinction for states since their implicit approvals of actions still entail moral responsibility<strong>.</h4><p>Sunstein 05</p><p>[Cass R. Sunstein and Adrian Vermeule. The University of Chicago Law School. “Is Capital Punishment Morally Required? The Relevance of Life‐Life Tradeoffs.” JOHN M. OLIN LAW & ECONOMICS WORKING PAPER NO. 239. The Chicago Working Paper Series<u></strong>. March 2005] AJ</p><p></u>In our view, <u>both the argument from causation and the argument from intention </u>go wrong by <u>overlook</u>ing <u>the distinctive features of government </u>as a moral agent. Whatever the general status of the act-omission distinction as a matter of moral philosophy,38 the distinction is least impressive when applied to government.39 The most fundamental point is that<u> <mark>unlike individuals, governments always </mark>and necessarily <mark>face a choice between </u></mark>or among possible<u> policies for <mark>regulating third parties</mark>. </u>The distinction between acts and omissions may not be intelligible in this context, and even if it is, the distinction does not make a morally relevant difference. Most generally,<u> government </u>is in the business of <u>creat</u>ing<u> permissions and prohibitions. <mark>When it </u></mark>explicitly or<u> implicitly <mark>authorizes private action, it is not</mark> </u>omitting to do anything, or<u> <mark>refusing to act</mark>.</u>40<u> Moreover, <mark>the distinction between authorized and unauthorized </mark>private <mark>action—</mark>for example, private killing—<mark>becomes obscure when the government formally forbids private action, but </mark>chooses a set of policy instruments that <mark>do not</mark> </u>adequately or<u> <mark>fully discourage it.</p></u></mark>
null
1AC
Framework
327,858
393
63,013
./documents/hsld20/Brophy/Ag/Brophy-Agha-Aff-Alta-Round2.docx
854,900
A
Alta
2
Salem Hills CB
Reshovsky, Zachary
contact tracing
hsld20/Brophy/Ag/Brophy-Agha-Aff-Alta-Round2.docx
null
72,787
SaAg
Brophy SaAg
null
Sa.....
Ag.....
null
null
24,442
Brophy
Brophy
AZ
null
1,028
hsld20
HS LD 2020-21
2,020
ld
hs
1
1,130,990
Warming causes extinction from oxygen, disease, ice melt, and cognitive failure.
McKibben ’19
McKibben ’19 [Bill; April 9; Schumann Distinguished Scholar at Middlebury College, Fellow of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences; Rolling Stone, “This Is How Human Extinction Could Play Out,” https://www.rollingstone.com/politics/politics-features/bill-mckibben-falter-climate-change-817310/]
it could get very bad if the world’s oceans kept warming, by 2100 they might become hot enough to “stop oxygen production by phyto-plankton by disrupting the process of photosynthesis.” Given that two-thirds of the Earth’s oxygen comes from phytoplankton, that would “likely result in the mass mortality of animals and humans.” permafrost is a preserver of microbes and viruses revive Spanish flu virus, smallpox, and bubonic plague as ice sheets melt, they take weight off land, and that can trigger earthquakes wiping all life There’s even this: if we keep raising carbon dioxide levels, we may not be able to think straight anymore human cognitive ability falls 21 percent those skills are what we need most
if oceans warm they stop plankton disrupting photosynthesis.” Given two-thirds of oxygen comes that result in mass mortality permafrost revive Spanish flu smallpox, and plague as ice melt, they trigger earthquakes wiping all life if we rais carbon we may not think straight cognitive ability falls skills we need most
Oh, it could get very bad. In 2015, a study in the Journal of Mathematical Biology pointed out that if the world’s oceans kept warming, by 2100 they might become hot enough to “stop oxygen production by phyto-plankton by disrupting the process of photosynthesis.” Given that two-thirds of the Earth’s oxygen comes from phytoplankton, that would “likely result in the mass mortality of animals and humans.” A year later, above the Arctic Circle, in Siberia, a heat wave thawed a reindeer carcass that had been trapped in the permafrost. The exposed body released anthrax into nearby water and soil, infecting two thousand reindeer grazing nearby, and they in turn infected some humans; a twelve-year-old boy died. As it turns out, permafrost is a “very good preserver of microbes and viruses, because it is cold, there is no oxygen, and it is dark” — scientists have managed to revive an eight-million-year-old bacterium they found beneath the surface of a glacier. Researchers believe there are fragments of the Spanish flu virus, smallpox, and bubonic plague buried in Siberia and Alaska. Or consider this: as ice sheets melt, they take weight off land, and that can trigger earthquakes — seismic activity is already increasing in Greenland and Alaska. Meanwhile, the added weight of the new seawater starts to bend the Earth’s crust. “That will give you a massive increase in volcanic activity. It’ll activate faults to create earthquakes, submarine landslides, tsunamis, the whole lot,” explained the director of University College London’s Hazard Centre. Such a landslide happened in Scandinavia about eight thousand years ago, as the last Ice Age retreated and a Kentucky-size section of Norway’s continental shelf gave way, “plummeting down to the abyssal plain and creating a series of titanic waves that roared forth with a vengeance,” wiping all signs of life from coastal Norway to Greenland and “drowning the Wales-sized landmass that once connected Britain to the Netherlands, Denmark, and Germany.” When the waves hit the Shetlands, they were sixty-five feet high. There’s even this: if we keep raising carbon dioxide levels, we may not be able to think straight anymore. At a thousand parts per million (which is within the realm of possibility for 2100), human cognitive ability falls 21 percent. “The largest effects were seen for Crisis Response, Information Usage, and Strategy,” a Harvard study reported, which is too bad, as those skills are what we seem to need most.
2,489
<h4>Warming causes <u>extinction</u> from <u>oxygen</u>, <u>disease</u>, <u>ice melt</u>, and <u>cognitive failure</u>. </h4><p><strong>McKibben ’19 </strong>[Bill; April 9; Schumann Distinguished Scholar at Middlebury College, Fellow of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences; Rolling Stone, “This Is How Human Extinction Could Play Out,” https://www.rollingstone.com/politics/politics-features/bill-mckibben-falter-climate-change-817310/]</p><p>Oh, <u>it could get very bad</u>.</p><p>In 2015, a study in the Journal of Mathematical Biology pointed out that <u><mark>if</mark> the world’s <mark>oceans</mark> kept <strong><mark>warm</strong></mark>ing, by 2100 <mark>they</mark> might become hot enough to “<strong><mark>stop</mark> oxygen production</strong> by <strong>phyto-<mark>plankton</strong></mark> by <strong><mark>disrupting</mark> the process</strong> of <strong><mark>photosynthesis</strong>.” Given</mark> that <strong><mark>two-thirds of</mark> the Earth’s <mark>oxygen</strong> comes</mark> from phytoplankton, <mark>that</mark> would “likely <strong><mark>result in</mark> the <mark>mass mortality</strong></mark> of animals and <strong>humans</strong>.”</p><p></u>A year later, above the Arctic Circle, in Siberia, a heat wave thawed a reindeer carcass that had been trapped in the permafrost. The exposed body released anthrax into nearby water and soil, infecting two thousand reindeer grazing nearby, and they in turn infected some humans; a twelve-year-old boy died. As it turns out, <u><mark>permafrost</mark> is a</u> “very good <u>preserver of <strong>microbes</strong> and <strong>viruses</u></strong>, because it is cold, there is no oxygen, and it is dark” — scientists have managed to <u><mark>revive</u></mark> an eight-million-year-old bacterium they found beneath the surface of a glacier. Researchers believe there are fragments of the <u><strong><mark>Spanish flu</strong></mark> virus, <strong><mark>smallpox</strong>, and</mark> <strong>bubonic <mark>plague</u></strong></mark> buried in Siberia and Alaska.</p><p>Or consider this: <u><mark>as <strong>ice</mark> sheets <mark>melt</strong>, they</mark> take weight off land, and that can <mark>trigger <strong>earthquakes</u></strong></mark> — seismic activity is already increasing in Greenland and Alaska. Meanwhile, the added weight of the new seawater starts to bend the Earth’s crust. “That will give you a massive increase in volcanic activity. It’ll activate faults to create earthquakes, submarine landslides, tsunamis, the whole lot,” explained the director of University College London’s Hazard Centre. Such a landslide happened in Scandinavia about eight thousand years ago, as the last Ice Age retreated and a Kentucky-size section of Norway’s continental shelf gave way, “plummeting down to the abyssal plain and creating a series of titanic waves that roared forth with a vengeance,” <u><strong><mark>wiping all</u></strong></mark> signs of <u><strong><mark>life</u></strong></mark> from coastal Norway to Greenland and “drowning the Wales-sized landmass that once connected Britain to the Netherlands, Denmark, and Germany.” When the waves hit the Shetlands, they were sixty-five feet high.</p><p><u>There’s even this: <mark>if we</mark> keep <strong><mark>rais</strong></mark>ing <mark>carbon</mark> dioxide levels, <mark>we <strong>may not</mark> be able to <mark>think straight</strong></mark> anymore</u>. At a thousand parts per million (which is within the realm of possibility for 2100), <u>human <strong><mark>cognitive ability</strong> falls</mark> 21 percent</u>. “The largest effects were seen for Crisis Response, Information Usage, and Strategy,” a Harvard study reported, which is too bad, as <u>those <mark>skills</mark> are what <mark>we</u></mark> seem to <u><strong><mark>need most</u></strong></mark>.</p>
1NC---Finals
1nc---Budget Bill DA
null
7,201
431
27,824
./documents/hspolicy21/Lovejoy/ZaRa/Lovejoy-Zanzuri-Ramirez-Neg-San%20Angelo%20Blue-Finals.docx
750,313
N
San Angelo Blue
Finals
Wimberly BQ
no name
1AC - Bad MPAs 1NC - T Oceans DA EPA DA Budget Bill CP Stafford Act Case 2NR - DA Budget Bill Case Win
hspolicy21/Lovejoy/ZaRa/Lovejoy-Zanzuri-Ramirez-Neg-San%20Angelo%20Blue-Finals.docx
null
64,015
ZaRa
Lovejoy ZaRa
null
Jo.....
Za.....
Se.....
Ra.....
22,038
Lovejoy
Lovejoy
TX
null
1,020
hspolicy21
HS Policy 2021-22
2,021
cx
hs
2
3,954,833
Shifts in regime perception threatens CCP’s legitimacy from nationalist hardliners
Weiss 19
Weiss 19 Jessica Weiss 1-29-2019 “Authoritarian Audiences, Rhetoric, and Propaganda in International Crises: Evidence from China” http://www.jessicachenweiss.com/uploads/3/0/6/3/30636001/19-01-24-elite-statements-isq-ca.pdf (Associate Professor of Government at Cornell University)//Elmer
Public support matters to many autocracies. modern dictatorships are “highly conscious of public opinion and make major efforts to affect it.”6 Mao Zedong told his comrades: “When you make revolution, you must first manage public opinion.”7 Because autocracies often rely on nationalist mythmaking,8 success or failure in defending the national honor in international crises could burnish the leadership’s patriotic credentials or spark opposition. Shared outrage at the regime’s foreign policy failures could galvanize street protests or elite fissures, creating intraparty upheaval or inviting military officers to step in to restore order. Fearing a domestic backlash, authoritarian leaders may feel compelled to take a tough international stance. ouster often weigh heavily on autocrats seeking to maximize their tenure in office. even a small increase in the probability of ouster could alter authoritarian incentives in international crises. history of nationalist uprisings make Chinese citizens and leaders especially aware of the linkage between international disputes and domestic unrest. weakness of the PRC’s predecessor in defending Chinese sovereignty galvanized protests and a general strike, forcing the government to sack three officials These precedents have made Chinese officials particularly sensitive to the appearance of hewing to public opinion. As the People’s Daily chief editor wrote: “History and reality have shown us that public opinion and regime safety are inseparable.”10 One Chinese scholar even claimed: “the Chinese government probably knows the public’s opinion better and reacts to it more directly than even the U.S. government.”11
autocracies rely on nationalist mythmaking success or failure in defending national honor in international crises could spark opposition. Shared outrage at foreign policy failures could galvanize protests or elite fissures, creating intraparty upheaval Fearing domestic backlash, authoritarian leaders may feel compelled to take a tough international stance. even a small increase in probability of ouster could alter incentives in international crises. history of nationalist uprisings make Chinese aware of linkage between international disputes and domestic unrest.
Public support—or the appearance of it—matters to many autocracies. As Ithiel de Sola Pool writes, modern dictatorships are “highly conscious of public opinion and make major efforts to affect it.”6 Mao Zedong told his comrades: “When you make revolution, you must first manage public opinion.”7 Because autocracies often rely on nationalist mythmaking,8 success or failure in defending the national honor in international crises could burnish the leadership’s patriotic credentials or spark opposition. Shared outrage at the regime’s foreign policy failures could galvanize street protests or elite fissures, creating intraparty upheaval or inviting military officers to step in to restore order. Fearing a domestic backlash, authoritarian leaders may feel compelled to take a tough international stance. Although authoritarian leaders are rarely held accountable to public opinion through free and fair elections, fears of popular unrest and irregular ouster often weigh heavily on autocrats seeking to maximize their tenure in office. Considering the harsh consequences that authoritarian elites face if pushed out of office, even a small increase in the probability of ouster could alter authoritarian incentives in international crises.9 A history of nationalist uprisings make Chinese citizens and leaders especially aware of the linkage between international disputes and domestic unrest. The weakness of the PRC’s predecessor in defending Chinese sovereignty at the Paris Peace Conference in 1919 galvanized protests and a general strike, forcing the government to sack three officials and reject the Treaty of Versailles, which awarded territories in China to Japan. These precedents have made Chinese officials particularly sensitive to the appearance of hewing to public opinion. As the People’s Daily chief editor wrote: “History and reality have shown us that public opinion and regime safety are inseparable.”10 One Chinese scholar even claimed: “the Chinese government probably knows the public’s opinion better and reacts to it more directly than even the U.S. government.”11
2,091
<h4>Shifts in regime perception threatens CCP’s legitimacy from nationalist hardliners</h4><p><strong>Weiss 19</strong> Jessica Weiss 1-29-2019 “Authoritarian Audiences, Rhetoric, and Propaganda in International Crises: Evidence from China” http://www.jessicachenweiss.com/uploads/3/0/6/3/30636001/19-01-24-elite-statements-isq-ca.pdf (Associate Professor of Government at Cornell University<u>)//Elmer</p><p>Public support</u>—or the appearance of it—<u>matters to many autocracies.</u> As Ithiel de Sola Pool writes, <u>modern dictatorships are “<strong>highly conscious of public opinion</strong> and <strong>make major efforts to affect it</strong>.”6 Mao Zedong told his comrades: “When you make revolution, you must first manage public opinion.”7 Because <mark>autocracies</mark> often <mark>rely on <strong>nationalist mythmaking</strong></mark>,8 <mark>success or failure in defending</mark> the <mark>national honor in international crises could </mark>burnish the leadership’s patriotic credentials or <mark>spark opposition. <strong>Shared outrage at</mark> the regime’s <mark>foreign policy failures could galvanize</mark> street <mark>protests or elite fissures, creating intraparty upheaval</strong> </mark>or inviting military officers to step in to restore order. <mark>Fearing</mark> a <mark>domestic backlash, authoritarian leaders may feel compelled to take a tough international stance.</u></mark> Although authoritarian leaders are rarely held accountable to public opinion through free and fair elections, fears of popular unrest and irregular<u> ouster often weigh heavily on autocrats seeking to maximize their tenure in office.</u> Considering the harsh consequences that authoritarian elites face if pushed out of office, <u><strong><mark>even a small increase</strong> in</mark> the <mark>probability of ouster could alter</mark> authoritarian <mark>incentives in international crises.</u></mark>9 A <u><strong><mark>history of nationalist uprisings</strong> make</mark> <mark>Chinese</mark> citizens and leaders especially <mark>aware of</mark> the <mark>linkage between <strong>international disputes</strong> and <strong>domestic unrest</strong>.</u></mark> The <u>weakness of the PRC’s predecessor in defending Chinese sovereignty </u>at the Paris Peace Conference in 1919 <u>galvanized protests and a general strike, forcing the government to sack three officials</u> and reject the Treaty of Versailles, which awarded territories in China to Japan. <u>These <strong>precedents</strong> have made Chinese officials particularly sensitive to the appearance of hewing to public opinion. As the People’s Daily chief editor wrote: “History and reality have shown us that <strong>public opinion and regime safety are inseparable</strong>.”10 One Chinese scholar even claimed: “the Chinese government probably knows the public’s opinion better and reacts to it more directly than even the U.S. government.”11</p></u>
1nc TOC r2
Off
4
336,057
169
133,101
./documents/hsld21/Stockdale/Pr/Stockdale-Pradhan-Neg-TOC-Round2.docx
899,555
N
TOC
2
Harvard-Westlake IC
Nick Fleming
1ac - starlink 1nc - new affs bad T-Subsets ADR CP Hindi CP Xi Disad case 1ar - all 2nr - T Case 2ar - T Case
hsld21/Stockdale/Pr/Stockdale-Pradhan-Neg-TOC-Round2.docx
null
75,353
RiPr
Stockdale RiPr
null
Ri.....
Pr.....
null
null
25,175
Stockdale
Stockdale
CA
null
1,029
hsld21
HS LD 2021-22
2,021
ld
hs
1
1,542,741
Nuclear war causes extinction.
Trevithick and Rogoway ’19
Trevithick and Rogoway ’19 [Joseph and Tyler; February 27; Military Analyst, M.A. in Conflict Resolution from Georgetown University, B.A. in the History and Policy of International Relations at Carnegie-Mellon University; Defense Journalist; The Drive, “Yes, India And Pakistan Could End The World As We Know It Through A Nuclear Exchange,” https://www.thedrive.com/the-war-zone/26674/yes-india-and-pakistan-could-end-the-world-as-we-know-it-through-a-nuclear-exchange] brett
India and Pakistan's nuclear arsenals are tiny United States and Russia but that does not mean they're purely regional threats nuclear weapons create lasting and far-reaching effects that could upend life on Earth if parties use them in sufficient numbers. In 2012 it might not take a large amount of nuclear weapons to create "Nuclear Winter." this occurs when soot from nuclear explosions block sunlight from earth's surface, leading to a drop in temperatures that results in crop failure and widespread famine writing "Even a 'small' nuclear war between India and Pakistan, with each country detonating 50 Hiroshima-size bombs – only about 0.03 percent of the global arsenal's power could produce smoke that temperatures would fall below the Little Ice Age threatening the global food supply there would be massive ozone depletion Little Boy results from Indian and Pakistani nuclear testing indicate both countries meet this threshold and weapons programs matured in decades at least 20 million people second order impacts would be even worse This study concluded detonation of 100 bombs in a purely regional conflict would result in "multi-decadal global cooling" and "would trigger a global nuclear famine." critics have questioned the impacts could be more severe if India and Pakistan use a larger number weapons or higher yields, which both belligerents readily have Nuclear Winter is just one of the things that might happen following a nuclear exchange A detonation of dozens of nuclear weapons, even small ones, would throw fallout into the air that could carry material far and wide ground zeroes a nuclear exchange could cut off water and food supplies melted down and exploded exclusion zone There would be major second-order "spillover" effects, as individuals fled areas, putting economic and political strains on neighboring regions. This could inflame existing tensions not directly related to conflict between India or Pakistan or lead to all new violent competition for limited resources. India already threatened to weaponize water access in its spat with the Pakistanis Any impacts on food and water or economic upheavals would have cascading impact across South Asia some negative reactions markets would certainly collapse after nuclear exchange We can only hope the two countries find a diplomatic solution and avoid any escalation. If things spiral out of control and lead to nuclear weapons, it would threaten all of humanity
nuclear weapons create "Nuclear Winter." explosions block sunlight results in crop failure and famine 50 bombs produce Ice Age ozone depletion purely regional conflict result in global cooling" and nuclear famine." detonation throw fallout into the air second-order effects inflame tensions cascading impact threaten all of humanity
A global threat India and Pakistan's nuclear arsenals are tiny compared to those of the United States and Russia, and these weapons are focused primarily on deterring each other, but that does not mean they're purely regional threats. Unlike conventional weapons, nuclear weapons create lasting and far-reaching effects that scientists have posited could upend life on Earth if warring parties were to use them in sufficient numbers. In 2012, Alan Robock, a distinguished professor in the Department of Environmental  Sciences and Associate Director of the Center for Environmental Prediction at Rutgers University, and Owen Brian Toon, a professor in the Department of Atmospheric and Oceanic Sciences and a research associate at  the Laboratory for Atmospheric and Space Physics at the University of Colorado, Boulder, argued that it might not take a large amount of nuclear weapons to create a scenario commonly known as "Nuclear Winter." In general, this hypothesized event occurs when smoke and soot from nuclear explosions block significant amounts of sunlight from reaching the earth's surface, leading to a precipitous drop in temperatures that results in mass crop failure and widespread famine. Robcock and Toon summarized their findings, which were based in part on their previous work, in an article in the Bulletin of The Atomic Scientists, writing: "Even a 'small' nuclear war between India and Pakistan, with each country detonating 50 Hiroshima-size atom bombs – only about 0.03 percent of the global nuclear arsenal's explosive power – as airbursts in urban areas, could produce so much smoke that temperatures would fall below those of the Little Ice Age of the fourteenth to nineteenth centuries, shortening the growing season around the world and threatening the global food supply. Furthermore, there would be massive ozone depletion, allowing more ultraviolet radiation to reach Earth's surface. Recent studies predict that agricultural production in parts of the United States and China would decline by about 20 percent for four years, and by 10 percent for a decade. The bomb the United States dropped on Hiroshima Japan, known as Little Boy, was an inefficient and essentially experimental design with a yield of around 15 kilotons. The reported results from Indian and Pakistani nuclear testing indicate that both countries can meet this threshold and both countries' weapons programs have almost certainly matured in the decades since. In previous studies, Robcock, working with others, postulated that temperature changes could begin within 10 days of a limited nuclear exchange and the effects from the detonations of 100 nuclear weapons in the 15-kiloton class would directly result in the deaths of at least 20 million people. The second order impacts would be even worse in the years that followed. In 2014, Michael Mills and Julia Lee-Taylor, both then working at the federally-funded National Center for Atmospheric Research's (NCAR) Earth System Laboratory, authored another paper with Robcock and Toon. This study concluded again that detonation of 100 15-kiloton yield bombs in a purely regional conflict would result in "multi-decadal global cooling" and "would put significant pressures on global food supplies and could trigger a global nuclear famine." It is important to note that critics have questioned whether the Nuclear Winter concept relies on too many assumptions and would ever actually occur. At the center of many of these rebuttals are debates about whether the nuclear explosions would truly create the amount of smoke and soot necessary for major climate change, as well as the specific conditions for those particles to remain in the atmosphere for a prolonged period of time. The studies here do indicate significant impacts based on a relatively limited number of nuclear detonations of smaller yield devices, though. But even if the impacts are less pronounced than projected in this particular scenario, they could be far more severe if India and Pakistan were to use a larger number weapons and/or ones of higher yields, which both belligerents readily have. In addition, Nuclear Winter is just one of the potential things that might happen following a nuclear exchange between the longtime foes. A detonation of dozens of nuclear weapons, even small ones, would throw hazardous nuclear fallout into the air that, depending on the weather pattern, could carry that material far and wide, causing both near- and short-term health impacts. The various ground zeroes themselves would be irritated and potentially hazardous for many years to come. Depending on where the detonations occur, a nuclear exchange could potentially cut people off from critical water and food supplies, putting increased and potentially unsustainable strains on uncontaminated areas.  After the Chernobyl nuclear power plant, situated in Ukraine, melted down and exploded in 1986, authorities established a 1,000 square mile restricted access "exclusion zone" that remains in place today. There would also be a major danger of second-order "spillover" effects, as individuals fled affected areas, putting economic and political strains on neighboring regions. This could inflame existing tensions not directly related to the inter-state conflict between India or Pakistan or lead to all new and potentially violent competition for what might already be limited resources. India has already threatened to weaponize water access in its latest spat with the Pakistanis. Any serious impacts on food and water supplies, or other economic upheavals as a direct or indirect result of the conflict, would have cascading impact across South Asia and beyond, as well. The very threat of a potential India-Pakistan war of any kind already caused some negative reactions in regional financial markets. Those markets would certainly collapse after an unprecedented nuclear exchange actually occurred, and that is before the long-term physical impacts of such an event would even manifest themselves. Overall, we are talking about a sudden and dramatic geopolitical, financial, and environmental shift that would change our reality in a matter of hours. Even then, the darkness, both figuratively and literally, that could propagate over the weeks, months, and years would be far more damaging. How great is the risk? So far, India and Pakistan have not made any clear indications that the fighting is close to crossing their nuclear thresholds. Pakistan's warnings about the risks of escalation seem more calculated to try and prompt India to back down. India itself has a so-called "no first use" policy, which means it has publicly pledged to use its nuclear weapons only in retaliation to a nuclear strike. However, experts have increasingly called into question whether this is truly the case and whether India might be developing delivery systems more suited to a first strike should there be a need to shift policies. Pakistan, however, does not have a no first use policy and has insisted on its right to employ nuclear weapons to defend itself even in the face of purely conventional threat. Pakistani officials have, in the past, specifically cited this policy as way of deterring India, which has a much larger and in some cases more advanced conventional force, and preventing larger wars. The concern, then, is that this policy appears to have failed, at least to some degree, with India's strike on undisputed Pakistani territory on Feb. 26, 2019. India, however, did not target Pakistani forces in that instance and exchanges between the two countries have been limited, at least so far, to the disputed Jammu and Kashmir region, where violent skirmishes occur semi-regularly without precipitating a larger confrontation. We can only hope that the two countries will find a diplomatic solution to this latest conflict and avoid any further escalation. If things were to spiral out of control and lead to the use of nuclear weapons, it would be something that would threaten all of humanity.
8,027
<h4>Nuclear war causes <u>extinction</u>.</h4><p><strong>Trevithick and Rogoway ’19 </strong>[Joseph and Tyler; February 27; Military Analyst, M.A. in Conflict Resolution from Georgetown University, B.A. in the History and Policy of International Relations at Carnegie-Mellon University; Defense Journalist; The Drive, “Yes, India And Pakistan Could End The World As We Know It Through A Nuclear Exchange,” https://www.thedrive.com/the-war-zone/26674/yes-india-and-pakistan-could-end-the-world-as-we-know-it-through-a-nuclear-exchange] brett</p><p>A global threat</p><p><u>India and Pakistan's nuclear arsenals are tiny</u> compared to those of the <u>United States and Russia</u>, and these weapons are focused primarily on deterring each other, <u>but that does <strong>not mean</strong> they're <strong>purely regional</strong> threats</u>. Unlike conventional weapons, <u><mark>nuclear weapons </mark>create <strong>lasting</strong> and <strong>far-reaching</strong> effects that</u> scientists have posited <u>could <strong>upend life on Earth</strong> if</u> warring <u>parties</u> were to <u>use them in sufficient numbers.</p><p>In 2012</u>, Alan Robock, a distinguished professor in the Department of Environmental  Sciences and Associate Director of the Center for Environmental Prediction at Rutgers University, and Owen Brian Toon, a professor in the Department of Atmospheric and Oceanic Sciences and a research associate at  the Laboratory for Atmospheric and Space Physics at the University of Colorado, Boulder, argued that <u>it might not take a <strong>large amount</strong> of nuclear weapons to <mark>create</u></mark> a scenario commonly known as <u><mark>"<strong>Nuclear Winter</strong>."</u></mark> </p><p>In general, <u>this</u> hypothesized event <u>occurs when</u> smoke and <u>soot from nuclear <mark>explosions block</u></mark> significant amounts of <u><mark>sunlight</mark> from</u> reaching the <u>earth's surface, leading to a</u> precipitous <u>drop in temperatures that <mark>results in</u></mark> mass <u><strong><mark>crop failure</strong> and</mark> <strong>widespread <mark>famine</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>Robcock and Toon summarized their findings, which were based in part on their previous work, in an article in the Bulletin of The Atomic Scientists, <u>writing</u>:</p><p><u>"Even a '<strong>small</strong>' nuclear war between <strong>India</strong> and <strong>Pakistan</strong>, with each country detonating <strong><mark>50</mark> Hiroshima-size</u></strong> atom <u><mark>bombs</mark> – only about <strong>0.03 percent</strong> of the global</u> nuclear <u>arsenal's</u> explosive <u>power</u> – as airbursts in urban areas, <u>could <mark>produce</u></mark> so much <u>smoke that temperatures would fall below </u>those of <u>the</u> <u>Little <strong><mark>Ice Age</u></strong></mark> of the fourteenth to nineteenth centuries, shortening the growing season around the world and <u>threatening the global food supply</u>. Furthermore, <u>there would be massive <strong><mark>ozone depletion</u></strong></mark>, allowing more ultraviolet radiation to reach Earth's surface. Recent studies predict that agricultural production in parts of the United States and China would decline by about 20 percent for four years, and by 10 percent for a decade.</p><p>The bomb the United States dropped on Hiroshima Japan, known as <u>Little Boy</u>, was an inefficient and essentially experimental design with a yield of around 15 kilotons. The reported <u>results from Indian and Pakistani <strong>nuclear testing</strong> indicate</u> that <u>both countries</u> can <u><strong>meet this threshold</strong> and</u> both countries' <u>weapons programs</u> have almost certainly <u>matured in</u> the <u>decades</u> since.</p><p>In previous studies, Robcock, working with others, postulated that temperature changes could begin within 10 days of a limited nuclear exchange and the effects from the detonations of 100 nuclear weapons in the 15-kiloton class would directly result in the deaths of <u>at least 20 million people</u>. The <u><strong>second order</strong> impacts would be even worse</u> in the years that followed. </p><p>In 2014, Michael Mills and Julia Lee-Taylor, both then working at the federally-funded National Center for Atmospheric Research's (NCAR) Earth System Laboratory, authored another paper with Robcock and Toon. <u>This study concluded</u> again that <u>detonation of 100</u> 15-kiloton yield <u>bombs in a <strong><mark>purely regional</strong> conflict</mark> would <mark>result in</mark> "multi-decadal <strong><mark>global cooling</strong>" and</mark> "would</u> put significant pressures on global food supplies and could <u>trigger a global <strong><mark>nuclear famine</strong>."</p><p></u></mark>It is important to note that<u> critics have questioned</u> whether the Nuclear Winter concept relies on too many assumptions and would ever actually occur. At the center of many of these rebuttals are debates about whether the nuclear explosions would truly create the amount of smoke and soot necessary for major climate change, as well as the specific conditions for those particles to remain in the atmosphere for a prolonged period of time. </p><p>The studies here do indicate significant impacts based on a relatively limited number of nuclear detonations of smaller yield devices, though. But even if <u>the impacts</u> are less pronounced than projected in this particular scenario, they <u>could be</u> far <u>more severe if India and Pakistan</u> were to <u>use a larger number weapons</u> and/<u>or</u> ones of <u><strong>higher yields</strong>, which both belligerents readily have</u>. </p><p>In addition, <u>Nuclear Winter is just <strong>one</strong> of the</u> potential <u>things that might happen following a nuclear exchange</u> between the longtime foes. <u>A <mark>detonation</mark> of <strong>dozens</strong> of nuclear weapons, <strong>even small ones</strong>, would <mark>throw</u></mark> hazardous nuclear <u><mark>fallout <strong>into the air</strong></mark> that</u>, depending on the weather pattern, <u>could <strong>carry</u></strong> that <u><strong>material</u></strong> <u>far and wide</u>, causing both near- and short-term health impacts. The various <u>ground zeroes</u> themselves would be irritated and potentially hazardous for many years to come.</p><p>Depending on where the detonations occur, <u>a nuclear exchange could</u> potentially <u>cut</u> people <u>off</u> from critical <u><strong>water</strong> and <strong>food</strong> supplies</u>, putting increased and potentially unsustainable strains on uncontaminated areas.  After the Chernobyl nuclear power plant, situated in Ukraine, <u>melted down and exploded</u> in 1986, authorities established a 1,000 square mile restricted access "<u>exclusion zone</u>" that remains in place today. </p><p><u>There would</u> also <u>be</u> a <u>major</u> danger of <u><strong><mark>second-order</strong></mark> "spillover" <strong><mark>effects</strong></mark>, as individuals fled</u> affected <u>areas, putting <strong>economic</strong> and <strong>political strains</strong> on neighboring regions. This could <strong><mark>inflame</strong></mark> existing <mark>tensions</mark> <strong>not directly related</strong> to</u> the inter-state <u>conflict between India or Pakistan or lead to all new</u> and potentially <u><strong>violent competition</strong> for</u> what might already be <u><strong>limited resources</strong>. India</u> has <u>already threatened to <strong>weaponize water</strong> access in its</u> latest <u>spat with the Pakistanis</u>.</p><p><u>Any</u> serious <u>impacts on food and water</u> supplies,<u> or</u> other <u>economic upheavals</u> as a direct or indirect result of the conflict, <u>would have <strong><mark>cascading impact</strong></mark> across <strong>South Asia</u></strong> and beyond, as well. The very threat of a potential India-Pakistan war of any kind already caused <u>some negative reactions</u> in regional financial markets. Those <u>markets would <strong>certainly collapse</strong> after</u> an unprecedented <u>nuclear exchange</u> actually occurred, and that is before the long-term physical impacts of such an event would even manifest themselves. </p><p>Overall, we are talking about a sudden and dramatic geopolitical, financial, and environmental shift that would change our reality in a matter of hours. Even then, the darkness, both figuratively and literally, that could propagate over the weeks, months, and years would be far more damaging. </p><p>How great is the risk?</p><p>So far, India and Pakistan have not made any clear indications that the fighting is close to crossing their nuclear thresholds. Pakistan's warnings about the risks of escalation seem more calculated to try and prompt India to back down.</p><p>India itself has a so-called "no first use" policy, which means it has publicly pledged to use its nuclear weapons only in retaliation to a nuclear strike. However, experts have increasingly called into question whether this is truly the case and whether India might be developing delivery systems more suited to a first strike should there be a need to shift policies.</p><p>Pakistan, however, does not have a no first use policy and has insisted on its right to employ nuclear weapons to defend itself even in the face of purely conventional threat. Pakistani officials have, in the past, specifically cited this policy as way of deterring India, which has a much larger and in some cases more advanced conventional force, and preventing larger wars.</p><p>The concern, then, is that this policy appears to have failed, at least to some degree, with India's strike on undisputed Pakistani territory on Feb. 26, 2019. India, however, did not target Pakistani forces in that instance and exchanges between the two countries have been limited, at least so far, to the disputed Jammu and Kashmir region, where violent skirmishes occur semi-regularly without precipitating a larger confrontation.</p><p><u>We can only hope</u> that <u>the two countries</u> will <u>find a diplomatic solution</u> to this latest conflict <u>and avoid any</u> further <u>escalation. If things</u> were to <u><strong>spiral out of control</strong> and lead to</u> the use of <u><strong>nuclear weapons</strong>, it would</u> be something that would <u><mark>threaten <strong>all of humanity</u></strong></mark>.</p>
null
null
1AC---Debris
13,882
675
44,177
./documents/hsld21/Sammamish/Wa/Sammamish-Wang-Aff-Strake-Round6.docx
897,749
A
Strake
6
Siddhartha Rana
Alison Aldridge
1ac - constellations 1nc - ttpremissibilitypresumption CSA OS spec innovation da 1ar - all 2n - csa 2ar - case csa
hsld21/Sammamish/Wa/Sammamish-Wang-Aff-Strake-Round6.docx
null
75,292
LyWa
Sammamish LyWa
null
Ly.....
Wa.....
null
null
25,152
Sammamish
Sammamish
WA
null
1,029
hsld21
HS LD 2021-22
2,021
ld
hs
1
1,630,493
Procedurally limited debate facilitates fair division of ground and good argumentation – No debater has the time or energy to be well read in every critical subfield – their conception of debate destroys complexity of clash.
Grossberg ‘15:
Grossberg ‘15: Lawrence Grossberg, Morris Davis Distinguished Professor @ the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill, in Lawrence and Wishart, in 2015 ["We All Want To Change The World The Paradox of the US Left: a polemic ", https://www.lwbooks.co.uk/sites/default/files/free-book/we_all_want_to_change_the_world.pdf, 3-4-2020]AR
the explosion of publication creates an ever-expanding circle in which there is always too much to read too many positions, too many arguments, too much contradictory evidence It has become impossible to read everything one must read This has serious consequences First, expertise becomes defined in increasingly narrow terms, resulting in the proliferation of sub-fields. For example, one might point to , , , , code studies, , , etc. while each of them is valuable they rarely say anything new or surprising They frequently simply re-discover in their own empirical "pocket" universe what others have said previously in other fields within each subfield, one gets the impression of witnessing endless redistributions of a highly circumscribed set of citations and authors, under a series of ever-changing terms to describe their positions academics create an endlessly self-referential closed system of citations, a numbingly predictable, circular tissue of references. Second, one is less likely to read work that appears tangential but may nevertheless be absolutely decisive to producing truly interesting and insightful research any investigation is likely to open up to an entire history of problematization, of conversations and debates, but who can afford the time and energy anymore Third, one tends to read only the most recent work since so much is being published so rapidly that there is little time to go back and read Fourth, one tends to select one's sources according to criteria that have more to do with political sympathies than with an understanding of research as a conversation with difference One reads selectively, finding those ideas that are already in line with what one assumes one already knows complexity goes out the door as one increasingly "sees the world in a grain of sand
the explosion of publication creates too many positions It has become impossible to read everything This has serious consequences proliferation of security studies transition studies, game studies hip-hop studies, horror studies, while each of them is valuable academics create an endlessly self-referential system of citations, a numbingly circular tissue of references one is less likely to produc research any investigation is likely to open up to an entire history of debates, but who can afford the time and energy One reads selectively, finding ideas that are already in line with what one knows complexity goes out the door
I will, in the following description, focus on the situation in the human sciences (rather than the hard sciences), where the explosion of publication creates an ever-expanding circle in which there is always too much to read—too many positions, too many arguments, too much contradictory evidence—so that scholars have to rely on either the author's stature or theoretical and/or political agreement. It has become almost impossible to read everything one must read, everything necessary to legitimate, at least in traditional terms, the claim of academic expertise or scholarship. In fact, given this situation (and its consequences as I will describe below), the most surprising thing is how much good work continues to be produced. This situation has serious consequences: First, one's expertise becomes defined in increasingly narrow terms, resulting in the proliferation of sub-fields.9 [insert footnote 9] For example, one might point to security studies, surveillance studies, transition studies, game studies, code studies, hip-hop studies, horror studies, etc. [Footnote 9 ends] And while each of them is valuable for their interdisciplinary efforts around a new empirical field, they all too often act as if the questions (and the realities they interrogate) are new; unfortunately, they rarely say anything new or surprising, anything that has not been said elsewhere. They frequently simply re-discover in their own empirical "pocket" universe what others have said previously in other fields. For example, all sorts of technologically defined sub-fields rediscover the rather old assumption that media audiences are active. This is partly because, within each subfield, one gets the impression of witnessing endless redistributions of a highly circumscribed set of citations and authors, under a series of ever-changing terms to describe their fields or positions. So, academics create ever shrinking circles in which authors cite a few theoretically and politically compatible works, and then follow the footnotes, all of which ultimately lead back to the original authors, creating an endlessly self-referential closed system of citations, a numbingly predictable, circular tissue of references. Second, one is less likely to read work that appears tangential but may nevertheless be absolutely decisive to producing truly interesting and insightful research. Asking significant questions should demand that one makes reference to all sorts of concepts and questions which would lead one to follow other unexpected traditions and lines of research, since any investigation (e.g., around questions of participation, publics, or leadership, to use only a few examples that have irked me recently) is likely to open up to an entire history of problematization, of conversations and debates, but who can afford the time and energy anymore. Third, one tends to read only the most recent work since so much is being published—in various media—so rapidly that there is little time to go back and read. Fourth, one tends to select one's sources according to criteria that have more to do with theoretical and political sympathies than with an understanding of research as a conversation with difference. One reads selectively, finding those ideas that are already in line with what one assumes one already knows, and one establishes a body of near-sacred texts; fifth, one selects topics that are au courant, partly because there is less scaffolding that one has to build upon and partly because one's work is more likely to gain visibility and impact. Sixth, complexity goes out the door as one increasingly "sees the world in a grain of sand." One can no longer be satisfied claiming to have discovered merely a new piece of a complex puzzle or even an interesting redeployment of an older practice or structure, because such claims do not bring fame and glory—either to oneself or the university. Instead, one has to have discovered the leading edge, the new key or essence. One good but relatively small idea is expanded into a metonym for the entire economy, culture or society. Instead of seeking new discursive forms to embody complexity, uncertainty and humility, one goes with elegance, hyperbole and the ever receding new.
4,240
<h4><strong>Procedurally <u>limited debate</u> facilitates fair division of <u>ground</u> and good <u>argumentation</u> – No debater has the <u>time</u> or <u>energy</u> to be well read in every critical subfield – their conception of debate destroys complexity of clash.</h4><p>Grossberg ‘15:</p><p></strong>Lawrence Grossberg, Morris Davis Distinguished Professor @ the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill, in Lawrence and Wishart, in 2015 ["We All Want To Change The World The Paradox of the US Left: a polemic ", https://www.lwbooks.co.uk/sites/default/files/free-book/we_all_want_to_change_the_world.pdf, 3-4-2020]AR</p><p>I will, in the following description, focus on the situation in the human sciences (rather than the hard sciences), where <u><strong><mark>the</mark> <mark>explosion of publication creates</strong></mark> an ever-expanding circle in which there is always <strong>too much to read</u></strong>—<u><strong><mark>too many</strong> <strong>positions</strong></mark>, <strong>too many</strong> arguments, too much contradictory evidence</u>—so that scholars have to rely on either the author's stature or theoretical and/or political agreement. <u><strong><mark>It has become</strong> </u></mark>almost <u><strong><mark>impossible to read everything</strong></mark> one must read</u>, everything necessary to legitimate, at least in traditional terms, the claim of academic expertise or scholarship. In fact, given this situation (and its consequences as I will describe below), the most surprising thing is how much good work continues to be produced. <u><strong><mark>This</u></strong></mark> situation <u><strong><mark>has</strong> <strong>serious consequences</u></strong></mark>: <u>First,</u> one's <u>expertise becomes defined in increasingly narrow terms, resulting in the <mark>proliferation of</mark> sub-fields.</u>9 <strong>[insert footnote 9] <u></strong>For example, one might point to </u><mark>security studies<u></mark>, </u>surveillance studies<u>, </u><mark>transition studies<u>, </u>game studies<u></mark>, code studies, </u><mark>hip-hop studies<u>, </u>horror studies<u>,</mark> etc.</u><strong> [Footnote 9 ends] </strong>And <u><strong><mark>while each of them is valuable</u></mark> </strong>for their interdisciplinary efforts around a new empirical field, they all too often act as if the questions (and the realities they interrogate) are new; unfortunately, <u>they rarely say anything new or surprising</u>, anything that has not been said elsewhere. <u>They frequently simply re-discover in their own empirical "pocket" universe what others have said previously in other fields</u>. For example, all sorts of technologically defined sub-fields rediscover the rather old assumption that media audiences are active. This is partly because, <u>within each subfield, one gets the impression of witnessing endless redistributions of a highly circumscribed set of citations and authors, under a series of ever-changing terms to describe their</u> fields or <u>positions</u>. So, <u><strong><mark>academics create</u></strong></mark> ever shrinking circles in which authors cite a few theoretically and politically compatible works, and then follow the footnotes, all of which ultimately lead back to the original authors, creating <u><strong><mark>an endlessly self-referential</mark> closed <mark>system of citations, a numbingly</mark> predictable, <mark>circular tissue of references</strong></mark>. Second, <strong><mark>one is less likely to</strong></mark> read work that appears tangential but may nevertheless be absolutely decisive to <strong><mark>produc</strong></mark>ing truly interesting and insightful <strong><mark>research</u></strong></mark>. Asking significant questions should demand that one makes reference to all sorts of concepts and questions which would lead one to follow other unexpected traditions and lines of research, since <u><strong><mark>any</strong> <strong>investigation</u></strong></mark> (e.g., around questions of participation, publics, or leadership, to use only a few examples that have irked me recently) <u><strong><mark>is</strong> <strong>likely to open up to an</strong> <strong>entire history</strong> <strong>of</strong></mark> problematization, of conversations and <strong><mark>debates, but</u></strong></mark> <u><strong><mark>who can afford the time and energy</mark> anymore</u></strong>. <u>Third, one tends to read only the most recent work since so much is being published</u>—in various media—<u>so rapidly that there is <strong>little time to go back and read</u></strong>. <u>Fourth, one tends to select one's sources according to criteria that have more to do with</u> theoretical and <u>political sympathies than with an understanding of research as <strong>a conversation with difference</u></strong>. <u><mark>O<strong>ne reads selectively, finding</strong></mark> those <strong><mark>ideas that are already in line with what one</strong></mark> assumes one already <strong><mark>knows</u></strong></mark>, and one establishes a body of near-sacred texts; fifth, one selects topics that are au courant, partly because there is less scaffolding that one has to build upon and partly because one's work is more likely to gain visibility and impact. Sixth, <u><strong><mark>complexity goes out the door</u></strong></mark> <u>as one increasingly "sees the world in a grain of sand</u>." One can no longer be satisfied claiming to have discovered merely a new piece of a complex puzzle or even an interesting redeployment of an older practice or structure, because such claims do not bring fame and glory—either to oneself or the university. Instead, one has to have discovered the leading edge, the new key or essence. One good but relatively small idea is expanded into a metonym for the entire economy, culture or society. Instead of seeking new discursive forms to embody complexity, uncertainty and humility, one goes with elegance, hyperbole and the ever receding new.</p>
null
null
Framework
13,201
346
48,789
./documents/nfald21/WesternKentucky/Mo/Western%20Kentucky-Morton-Aff-Lewis%20and%20Clark-Octas.docx
920,109
A
Lewis and Clark
Octas
Jacob Everett
Shane Brewer, Mary Talemantez, Colin Quinn
null
nfald21/WesternKentucky/Mo/Western%20Kentucky-Morton-Aff-Lewis%20and%20Clark-Octas.docx
null
79,254
MiMo
Western Kentucky MiMo
null
Mi.....
Mo.....
null
null
26,506
WesternKentucky
Western Kentucky
null
null
1,040
nfald21
NFA LD 2020-21
2,021
ld
college
1
4,173,053
Chinese tech leadership is key to multilateralism.
Yamei 18
Shen Yamei 18, Deputy Director and Associate Research Fellow of Department for American Studies, China Institute of International Studies, 1-9-2018, "Probing into the “Chinese Solution” for the Transformation of Global Governance," CAIFC, http://www.caifc.org.cn/en/content.aspx?id=4491
As the world is in a period of great development, transformation and adjustment, the international power comparison is undergoing profound changes, global governance is reshuffling and traditional governance concepts and models are confronted with challenges. The international community is expecting China to play a bigger role in global governance, which has given birth to the Chinese solution. The “shortcomings” of the existing global governance system are prominent, which can hardly ensure global development. First, the traditional dominant forces are seriously imbalanced. The US and Europe have been beset with structural problems These countries have not fully reformed and adjusted themselves well, but rather pointed their fingers at globalization and resorted to retreat for self-insurance or were busy with their own affairs without any wish or ability to participate in global governance, which has encouraged the growth of “anti-globalization” trend into an interference factor to global governance Second, the global governance mechanism is relatively lagging behind. Over the years of development, the strength of emerging economies has increased dramatically, which has substantially upset the international power structure, as the developing countries as a whole have made 80 percent of the contributions to global economic growth These countries have expressed their appeal for new governance and begun policy coordination among themselves the traditional governance mechanisms such as the World Bank, IMF and G7 failed to reflect the demand of the new pattern, in addition to their lack of representation and inclusiveness. Third, the global governance rules are developing in a fragmented way, with governance deficits existing in some key areas. As relevant efforts are usually temporary and limited to specific partners or issues, global governance driven by requests of “diversified governance” lacks systematic and comprehensive solutions Since the beginning of this year, there have been risks of running into an acephalous state in such key areas as global economic governance and climate change Such emerging issues as nuclear security and international terrorism have suffered injustice because of power politics The governance areas in deficit, such as cyber security, polar region and oceans, have “reversely forced” certain countries and organizations to respond hastily All of these have made the global governance system trapped in a dilemma and call urgently for a clear direction of advancement. Although the developing countries as represented by China acknowledge the positive role played by the post-war international order in safeguarding peace, boosting prosperity and promoting globalization, they criticize the existing order for lack of inclusiveness in politics and equality in economy, as well as double standard in security, believing it has failed to reflect the multi-polarization trend of the world and is an exclusive “circle club China, to lead the transformation of the global governance system and international order not only supports the efforts of the developing countries to uphold multilateralism rather than unilateralism, advocate the rule of law rather than the law of the jungle and practice democracy rather than power politics in international relations but also is an important subject concerning whether China could gain the discourse power and development space corresponding to its own strength and interests in the process of innovating and perfecting the framework of international order. in the existing international system guided by the “Western-Centrism”, the Western civilization has always had the self-righteous superiority, conflicting with the interests and mentality of other countries and having failed to find the path to co-existing peacefully and harmoniously with other civilizations So to speak, many problems of today, including the growing gap in economic development between the developed and developing countries against the background of globalization, the Middle East trapped in chaos and disorder, the failure of Russia and Turkey to “integrate into the West”, etc., can be directly attributed to lack of exchanges, communication and integration among civilizations. China will rebalance the international pattern from a more inclusive civilization perspective and with more far-sighted strategic mindset, or at least correct the bisected or predominated world order so as to promote the parallel development of the Eastern and Western civilizations through mutual learning, integration and encouragement. Today, China has become a source of stability in an international situation full of uncertainties. Over the past 5 years, China has made outstanding contributions to the recovery of world economy under relatively great pressure of its own economic downturn. Encouraged by the “four confidences”, the whole of the Chinese society has burst out innovation vitality and produced innovation achievements the Chinese solution is more practical and intimate to people as well as emphasizes inclusive cooperation, as China is full of confidence to break the monopoly of the Western model on global development, “offering mankind a Chinese solution to explore a better social system”, and “providing a brand new option for the nations and peoples who are hoping both to speed up development and maintain independence”. Over the past years’ efforts, China has the ability to transform itself from “grasping the opportunity” for development to “creating opportunity” and “sharing opportunity” for common development, hoping to pass on the longing of the Chinese people for a better life to the people of other countries and promoting the development of the global governance system toward a more just and rational end. It has become the major power’s conscious commitment of China to lead the transformation of the global governance system in a profound way. The Chinese solution composed of these contents, not only fundamentally different from the old roads of industrial revolution and colonial expansion in history, but also different from the market-driven neo-liberalism model currently advocated by Western countries and international organizations, stands at the height of the world and even mankind, seeking for global common development and having widened the road for the developing countries to modernization, which is widely welcomed by the international community. . Currently, the international political practice in global governance is mostly problem-driven without creating a set of relatively independent, centralized and integral power structures, resulting in the existing global governance systemcharacterized as both extensive and unbalanced China has been engaged in reform and innovation, while maintaining and constructing the existing systems, producing some thinking and method with Chinese characteristics. First, China sees the UN as a mirror that reflects the status quo of global governance, which should act as the leader of global governance, and actively safeguards the global governance system with the UN at the core. Second, China is actively promoting the transforming process of such recently emerged international mechanisms as G20, BRICS and SCO Thus, in leading the transformation of the global governance system, China has not overthrown the existing systems and started all over again, but been engaged in innovating and perfecting; China has proactively undertaken international responsibilities, but has to do everything in its power and act according to its ability. Many of the problems facing global governance today are deeply rooted in such a cause that the dominant power of the existing governance system has taken it as the tool to realize its own national interests first and a platform to pursue its political goals. On the contrary, the interests and agendas of China, as a major power of the world, are open to the whole world, and China in the future “will provide the world with broader market, more sufficient capital, more abundant goods and more precious opportunities for cooperation”, while having the ability to make the world listen to its voice more attentively. With regard to the subject of global governance, China has advocated that what global governance system is better cannot be decided upon by any single country, as the destiny of the world should be in the hands of the people of all countries. In principle, all the parties should stick to the principle of mutual consultation, joint construction and co-sharing, resolve disputes through dialog and differences through consultation China has also proposed international public security views on nuclear security, maritime cooperation and cyber space order, calling for efforts to make the global village into a “grand stage for seeking common development” rather than a “wrestling arena”; we cannot “set up a stage here, while pulling away a prop there”, but “complement each other to put on a grand show” As the biggest developing country and fast growing major power, China has the same appeal and proposal for governance as other developing countries and already began policy coordination with them, as China should comply with historical tide and continue to support the increase of the developing countries’ voice in the global governance system. To this end, China has pursued the policy of “dialog but not confrontation, partnership but not alliance”, attaching importance to the construction of new type of major power relationship and global partnership network, while making a series proposals in the practice of global governance that could represent the legitimate interests of the developing countries and be conducive to safeguarding global justice, including supporting an open, inclusive, universal, balanced and win-win economic globalization; promoting the reforms on share and voting mechanism of IMF to increase the voting rights and representation of the emerging market economies; financing the infrastructure construction and industrial upgrading of other developing countries through various bilateral or regional funds; and helping other developing countries to respond to such challenges as famine, refugees, climate change and public hygiene by debt forgiveness and assistance.
shortcomings” of global governance are prominent which can hardly ensure development traditional dominant forces are seriously imbalanced traditional mechanisms such as the World Bank, IMF failed to reflect the demand of the new pattern in addition to their lack of representation there have been risks in such key areas as economic governance and climate change nuclear security and terrorism cyber security polar region and oceans in the existing international system guided by the “Western-Centrism”, the Western civilization has always had superiority many problems of today can be directly attributed to lack of exchanges, communication and integration among civilizations China will rebalance the pattern from a more inclusive civilization perspective the Chinese solution is more practical emphasizes inclusive coop China has not overthrown the existing systems but been engaged in innovating and perfecting China undertaken international responsibilities but has act according to its ability. China proposed public security views on nuclear security, maritime coop and cyber space order, calling for common development”
As the world is in a period of great development, transformation and adjustment, the international power comparison is undergoing profound changes, global governance is reshuffling and traditional governance concepts and models are confronted with challenges. The international community is expecting China to play a bigger role in global governance, which has given birth to the Chinese solution. A. To Lead the Transformation of the Global Governance System. The “shortcomings” of the existing global governance system are prominent, which can hardly ensure global development. First, the traditional dominant forces are seriously imbalanced. The US and Europe that used to dominate the global governance system have been beset with structural problems, with their economic development stalling, social contradictions intensifying, populism and secessionism rising, and states trapped in internal strife and differentiation. These countries have not fully reformed and adjusted themselves well, but rather pointed their fingers at globalization and resorted to retreat for self-insurance or were busy with their own affairs without any wish or ability to participate in global governance, which has encouraged the growth of “anti-globalization” trend into an interference factor to global governance. Second, the global governance mechanism is relatively lagging behind. Over the years of development, the strength of emerging economies has increased dramatically, which has substantially upset the international power structure, as the developing countries as a whole have made 80 percent of the contributions to global economic growth. These countries have expressed their appeal for new governance and begun policy coordination among themselves, which has initiated the transition of global governance form “Western governance” to “East-West joint governance”, but the traditional governance mechanisms such as the World Bank, IMF and G7 failed to reflect the demand of the new pattern, in addition to their lack of representation and inclusiveness. Third, the global governance rules are developing in a fragmented way, with governance deficits existing in some key areas. With the diversification and in-depth integration of international interests, the domain of global governance has continued to expand, with actors multiplying by folds and action intentions becoming complicated. As relevant efforts are usually temporary and limited to specific partners or issues, global governance driven by requests of “diversified governance” lacks systematic and comprehensive solutions. Since the beginning of this year, there have been risks of running into an acephalous state in such key areas as global economic governance and climate change. Such emerging issues as nuclear security and international terrorism have suffered injustice because of power politics. The governance areas in deficit, such as cyber security, polar region and oceans, have “reversely forced” certain countries and organizations to respond hastily. All of these have made the global governance system trapped in a dilemma and call urgently for a clear direction of advancement. B. To Innovate and Perfect the International Order. Currently, whether the developing countries or the Western countries of Europe and the US are greatly discontent with the existing international order as well as their appeals and motivation for changing the order are unprecedentedly strong. The US is the major creator and beneficiary of the existing hegemonic order, but it is now doubtful that it has gained much less than lost from the existing order, faced with the difficulties of global economic transformation and obsessed with economic despair and political dejection. Although the developing countries as represented by China acknowledge the positive role played by the post-war international order in safeguarding peace, boosting prosperity and promoting globalization, they criticize the existing order for lack of inclusiveness in politics and equality in economy, as well as double standard in security, believing it has failed to reflect the multi-polarization trend of the world and is an exclusive “circle club”. Therefore, there is much room for improvement. For China, to lead the transformation of the global governance system and international order not only supports the efforts of the developing countries to uphold multilateralism rather than unilateralism, advocate the rule of law rather than the law of the jungle and practice democracy rather than power politics in international relations, but also is an important subject concerning whether China could gain the discourse power and development space corresponding to its own strength and interests in the process of innovating and perfecting the framework of international order. C. To Promote Integration of the Eastern and Western Civilizations. Dialog among civilizations, which is the popular foundation for any country’s diplomatic proposals, runs like a trickle moistening things silently. Nevertheless, in the existing international system guided by the “Western-Centrism”, the Western civilization has always had the self-righteous superiority, conflicting with the interests and mentality of other countries and having failed to find the path to co-existing peacefully and harmoniously with other civilizations. So to speak, many problems of today, including the growing gap in economic development between the developed and developing countries against the background of globalization, the Middle East trapped in chaos and disorder, the failure of Russia and Turkey to “integrate into the West”, etc., can be directly attributed to lack of exchanges, communication and integration among civilizations. Since the 18th National Congress of CPC, Xi Jinping has raised the concept of “Chinese Dream” that reflects both Chinese values and China’s pursuit, re-introducing to the world the idea of “all living creatures grow together without harming one another and ways run parallel without interfering with one another”, which is the highest ideal in Chinese traditional culture, and striving to shape China into a force that counter-balance the Western civilization. He has also made solemn commitment that “we respect the diversity of civilizations …… cannot be puffed up with pride and depreciate other civilizations and nations”; “facing the people deeply trapped in misery and wars, we should have not only compassion and sympathy, but also responsibility and action …… do whatever we can to extend assistance to those people caught in predicament”, etc. China will rebalance the international pattern from a more inclusive civilization perspective and with more far-sighted strategic mindset, or at least correct the bisected or predominated world order so as to promote the parallel development of the Eastern and Western civilizations through mutual learning, integration and encouragement. D. To Pass on China’s Confidence. Only a short while ago, some Western countries had called for “China’s responsibility” and made it an inhibition to “regulate” China’s development orientation. Today, China has become a source of stability in an international situation full of uncertainties. Over the past 5 years, China has made outstanding contributions to the recovery of world economy under relatively great pressure of its own economic downturn. Encouraged by the “four confidences”, the whole of the Chinese society has burst out innovation vitality and produced innovation achievements, making people have more sense of gain and more optimistic about the national development prospect. It is the heroism of the ordinary Chinese to overcome difficulties and realize the ideal destiny that best explains China’s confidence. When this confidence is passed on in the field of diplomacy, it is expressed as: first, China’s posture is seen as more forging ahead and courageous to undertake responsibilities ---- proactively shaping the international agendas rather than passively accepting them; having clear-cut attitudes on international disputes rather than being equivocal; and extending international cooperation to comprehensive and dimensional development rather than based on the theory of “economy only”. In sum, China will actively seek understanding and support from other countries rather than imposing its will on others with clear-cut Chinese characteristics, Chinese style and Chinese manner. Second, China’s discourse is featured as a combination of inflexibility and yielding as well as magnanimous ---- combining the internationally recognized diplomatic principles with the excellent Chinese cultural traditions through digesting the Chinese and foreign humanistic classics assisted with philosophical speculations to make “China Brand, Chinese Voice and China’s Image get more and more recognized”. Third, the Chinese solution is more practical and intimate to people as well as emphasizes inclusive cooperation, as China is full of confidence to break the monopoly of the Western model on global development, “offering mankind a Chinese solution to explore a better social system”, and “providing a brand new option for the nations and peoples who are hoping both to speed up development and maintain independence”. II.Path Searching of the “Chinese Solution” for Global Governance Over the past years’ efforts, China has the ability to transform itself from “grasping the opportunity” for development to “creating opportunity” and “sharing opportunity” for common development, hoping to pass on the longing of the Chinese people for a better life to the people of other countries and promoting the development of the global governance system toward a more just and rational end. It has become the major power’s conscious commitment of China to lead the transformation of the global governance system in a profound way. A. To Construct the Theoretical System for Global Governance. The theoretical system of global governance has been the focus of the party central committee’s diplomatic theory innovation since the 18th National Congress of CPC as well as an important component of the theory of socialism with Chinese characteristics for a new era, which is not only the sublimation of China’s interaction with the world from “absorbing and learning” to “cooperation and mutual learning”, but also the cause why so many developing countries have turned from “learning from the West” to “exploring for treasures in the East”. In the past 5 years, the party central committee, based on precise interpretation of the world pattern today and serious reflection on the future development of mankind, has made a sincere call to the world for promoting the development of global governance system toward a more just and rational end, and proposed a series of new concepts and new strategies including engaging in major power diplomacy with Chinese characteristics, creating the human community with common destiny, promoting the construction of new international relationship rooted in the principle of cooperation and win-win, enriching the strategic thinking of peaceful development, sticking to the correct benefit view, formulating the partnership network the world over, advancing the global economic governance in a way of mutual consultation, joint construction and co-sharing, advocating the joint, comprehensive, cooperative and sustainable security concept, and launching the grand “Belt and Road” initiative. The Chinese solution composed of these contents, not only fundamentally different from the old roads of industrial revolution and colonial expansion in history, but also different from the market-driven neo-liberalism model currently advocated by Western countries and international organizations, stands at the height of the world and even mankind, seeking for global common development and having widened the road for the developing countries to modernization, which is widely welcomed by the international community. B. To Supplement and Perfect the Global Governance System. Currently, the international political practice in global governance is mostly problem-driven without creating a set of relatively independent, centralized and integral power structures, resulting in the existing global governance systemcharacterized as both extensive and unbalanced. China has been engaged in reform and innovation, while maintaining and constructing the existing systems, producing some thinking and method with Chinese characteristics. First, China sees the UN as a mirror that reflects the status quo of global governance, which should act as the leader of global governance, and actively safeguards the global governance system with the UN at the core. Second, China is actively promoting the transforming process of such recently emerged international mechanisms as G20, BRICS and SCO, perfecting them through practice, and boosting Asia-Pacific regional cooperation and the development of economic globalization. China is also promoting the construction of regional security mechanism through the Six-Party Talks on Korean Peninsula nuclear issue, Boao Forum for Asia, CICA and multilateral security dialog mechanisms led by ASEAN so as to lay the foundation for the future regional security framework. Third, China has initiated the establishment of AIIB and the New Development Bank of BRICS, creating a precedent for developing countries to set up multilateral financial institutions. The core of the new relationship between China and them lies in “boosting rather than controlling” and “public rather than private”, which is much different from the management and operation model of the World Bank, manifesting the increasing global governance ability of China and the developing countries as well as exerting pressure on the international economic and financial institution to speed up reforms. Thus, in leading the transformation of the global governance system, China has not overthrown the existing systems and started all over again, but been engaged in innovating and perfecting; China has proactively undertaken international responsibilities, but has to do everything in its power and act according to its ability. C. To Reform the Global Governance Rules. Many of the problems facing global governance today are deeply rooted in such a cause that the dominant power of the existing governance system has taken it as the tool to realize its own national interests first and a platform to pursue its political goals. Since the beginning of this year, the US has for several times requested the World Bank, IMF and G20 to make efforts to mitigate the so-called global imbalance, abandoned its commitment to support trade openness, cut down investment projects to the middle-income countries, and deleted commitment to support the efforts to deal with climate change financially, which has made the international systems accessories of the US domestic economic agendas, dealing a heavy blow to the global governance system. On the contrary, the interests and agendas of China, as a major power of the world, are open to the whole world, and China in the future “will provide the world with broader market, more sufficient capital, more abundant goods and more precious opportunities for cooperation”, while having the ability to make the world listen to its voice more attentively. With regard to the subject of global governance, China has advocated that what global governance system is better cannot be decided upon by any single country, as the destiny of the world should be in the hands of the people of all countries. In principle, all the parties should stick to the principle of mutual consultation, joint construction and co-sharing, resolve disputes through dialog and differences through consultation. Regarding the critical areas, opening to the outer world does not mean building one’s own backyard, but building the spring garden for co-sharing; the “Belt and Road” initiative is not China’s solo, but a chorus participated in by all countries concerned. China has also proposed international public security views on nuclear security, maritime cooperation and cyber space order, calling for efforts to make the global village into a “grand stage for seeking common development” rather than a “wrestling arena”; we cannot “set up a stage here, while pulling away a prop there”, but “complement each other to put on a grand show”. From the orientation of reforms, efforts should be made to better safeguard and expand the legitimate interests of the developing countries and increase the influence of the emerging economies on global governance. Over the past 5 years, China has attached importance to full court diplomacy, gradually coming to the center stage of international politics and proactively establishing principles for global governance. By hosting such important events as IAELM, CICA Summit, G20 Summit, the Belt and Road International Cooperation Forum and BRICS Summit, China has used theseplatforms to elaborate the Asia-Pacific Dream for the first time to the world, expressing China’s views on Asian security and global economic governance, discussing with the countries concerned with the Belt and Road about the synergy of their future development strategies and setting off the “BRICS plus” capacity expansion mechanism, in which China not only contributes its solution and shows its style, but also participates in the shaping of international principles through practice. On promoting the resolution of hot international issues, China abides by the norms governing international relations based on the purposes and principles of the UN Charter, and insists on justice, playing a constructive role as a responsible major power in actively promoting the political accommodation in Afghanistan, mediating the Djibouti-Eritrea dispute, promoting peace talks in the Middle East, devoting itself to the peaceful resolution of the South China Sea dispute through negotiations. In addition, China’s responsibility and quick response to international crises have gained widespread praises, as seen in such cases as assisting Africa in its fight against the Ebola epidemic, sending emergency fresh water to the capital of Maldives and buying rice from Cambodia to help relieve its financial squeeze, which has shown the simple feelings of the Chinese people to share the same breath and fate with the people of other countries. D. To Support the Increase of the Developing Countries’ Voice. The developing countries, especially the emerging powers, are not only the important participants of the globalization process, but also the important direction to which the international power system is transferring. With the accelerating shift of global economic center to emerging markets and developing economies, the will and ability of the developing countries to participate in global governance have been correspondingly strengthened. As the biggest developing country and fast growing major power, China has the same appeal and proposal for governance as other developing countries and already began policy coordination with them, as China should comply with historical tide and continue to support the increase of the developing countries’ voice in the global governance system. To this end, China has pursued the policy of “dialog but not confrontation, partnership but not alliance”, attaching importance to the construction of new type of major power relationship and global partnership network, while making a series proposals in the practice of global governance that could represent the legitimate interests of the developing countries and be conducive to safeguarding global justice, including supporting an open, inclusive, universal, balanced and win-win economic globalization; promoting the reforms on share and voting mechanism of IMF to increase the voting rights and representation of the emerging market economies; financing the infrastructure construction and industrial upgrading of other developing countries through various bilateral or regional funds; and helping other developing countries to respond to such challenges as famine, refugees, climate change and public hygiene by debt forgiveness and assistance.
20,257
<h4>Chinese tech leadership is key to multilateralism.</h4><p>Shen <strong>Yamei 18<u></strong>, Deputy Director and Associate Research Fellow of Department for American Studies, China Institute of International Studies, 1-9-2018, "Probing into the “Chinese Solution” for the Transformation of Global Governance," CAIFC, http://www.caifc.org.cn/en/content.aspx?id=4491</p><p>As the world is in a period of great development, transformation and adjustment, the international power comparison is undergoing profound changes, global governance is reshuffling and traditional governance concepts and models are confronted with challenges. The international community is expecting China to play a bigger role in global governance, which has given birth to the Chinese solution. </u>A. To Lead the Transformation of the Global Governance System. <u><strong>The “<mark>shortcomings” of </mark>the existing <mark>global governance </mark>system <mark>are prominent</mark>, <mark>which can hardly ensure</mark> global <mark>development</mark>. First, the <mark>traditional dominant forces are seriously imbalanced</strong></mark>. The US and Europe</u> that used to dominate the global governance system <u>have been beset with structural problems</u>, with their economic development stalling, social contradictions intensifying, populism and secessionism rising, and states trapped in internal strife and differentiation. <u>These countries have not fully reformed and adjusted themselves well, but rather pointed their fingers at globalization and resorted to retreat for self-insurance or were busy with their own affairs without any wish or ability to participate in global governance, which has encouraged the growth of “anti-globalization” trend into an interference factor to global governance</u>. <u>Second, the global governance mechanism is relatively lagging behind.</u> <u>Over the years of development, the strength of emerging economies has increased dramatically, which has substantially upset the international power structure, as the developing countries as a whole have made 80 percent of the contributions to global economic growth</u>. <u>These countries have expressed their appeal for new governance and begun policy coordination among themselves</u>, which has initiated the transition of global governance form “Western governance” to “East-West joint governance”, but <u><strong>the <mark>traditional</mark> governance <mark>mechanisms such as the World Bank, IMF</mark> and G7 <mark>failed to reflect the demand of the new pattern</mark>, <mark>in addition to their lack of representation</mark> and inclusiveness. </strong>Third, the global governance rules are developing in a fragmented way, with governance deficits existing in some key areas.</u> With the diversification and in-depth integration of international interests, the domain of global governance has continued to expand, with actors multiplying by folds and action intentions becoming complicated. <u>As relevant efforts are usually temporary and limited to specific partners or issues, global governance driven by requests of “diversified governance” lacks systematic and comprehensive solutions</u>. <u>Since the beginning of this year, <mark>there have been risks </mark>of running into an acephalous state <strong><mark>in such key areas as</mark> global <mark>economic governance and climate change</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong>Such emerging issues as <mark>nuclear security and</mark> international <mark>terrorism </mark>have suffered injustice because of power politics</u></strong>. <u><strong>The governance areas in deficit, such as <mark>cyber security</mark>, <mark>polar region and oceans</mark>, have “reversely forced” certain countries and organizations to respond hastily</u></strong>. <u>All of these have made the global governance system trapped in a dilemma and call urgently for a clear direction of advancement. </u>B. To Innovate and Perfect the International Order. Currently, whether the developing countries or the Western countries of Europe and the US are greatly discontent with the existing international order as well as their appeals and motivation for changing the order are unprecedentedly strong. The US is the major creator and beneficiary of the existing hegemonic order, but it is now doubtful that it has gained much less than lost from the existing order, faced with the difficulties of global economic transformation and obsessed with economic despair and political dejection. <u>Although the developing countries as represented by China acknowledge the positive role played by the post-war international order in safeguarding peace, boosting prosperity and promoting globalization, they criticize the existing order for lack of inclusiveness in politics and equality in economy, as well as double standard in security, believing it has failed to reflect the multi-polarization trend of the world and is an exclusive “circle club</u>”. Therefore, there is much room for improvement. For <u>China, to lead the transformation of the global governance system and international order not only supports the efforts of the developing countries to uphold multilateralism rather than unilateralism, advocate the rule of law rather than the law of the jungle and practice democracy rather than power politics in international relations</u>, <u>but also is an important subject concerning whether China could gain the discourse power and development space corresponding to its own strength and interests in the process of innovating and perfecting the framework of international order. </u>C. To Promote Integration of the Eastern and Western Civilizations. Dialog among civilizations, which is the popular foundation for any country’s diplomatic proposals, runs like a trickle moistening things silently. Nevertheless, <u><mark>in the existing international system guided by the “Western-Centrism”, the Western civilization has always had</mark> the self-righteous <mark>superiority</mark>, conflicting with the interests and mentality of other countries and having failed to find the path to co-existing peacefully and harmoniously with other civilizations</u>. <u><strong>So to speak, <mark>many problems of today</mark>, including the growing gap in economic development between the developed and developing countries against the background of globalization, the Middle East trapped in chaos and disorder, the failure of Russia and Turkey to “integrate into the West”, etc., <mark>can be directly attributed to lack of exchanges, communication and integration among civilizations</mark>. </u></strong>Since the 18th National Congress of CPC, Xi Jinping has raised the concept of “Chinese Dream” that reflects both Chinese values and China’s pursuit, re-introducing to the world the idea of “all living creatures grow together without harming one another and ways run parallel without interfering with one another”, which is the highest ideal in Chinese traditional culture, and striving to shape China into a force that counter-balance the Western civilization. He has also made solemn commitment that “we respect the diversity of civilizations …… cannot be puffed up with pride and depreciate other civilizations and nations”; “facing the people deeply trapped in misery and wars, we should have not only compassion and sympathy, but also responsibility and action …… do whatever we can to extend assistance to those people caught in predicament”, etc. <u><mark>China will rebalance the</mark> international <mark>pattern from a more inclusive civilization perspective</mark> and with more far-sighted strategic mindset, or at least correct the bisected or predominated world order so as to promote the parallel development of the Eastern and Western civilizations through mutual learning, integration and encouragement. </u>D. To Pass on China’s Confidence. Only a short while ago, some Western countries had called for “China’s responsibility” and made it an inhibition to “regulate” China’s development orientation. <u>Today, China has become a source of stability in an international situation full of uncertainties. Over the past 5 years, China has made outstanding contributions to the recovery of world economy under relatively great pressure of its own economic downturn.</u> <u>Encouraged by the “four confidences”, the whole of the Chinese society has burst out innovation vitality and produced innovation achievements</u>, making people have more sense of gain and more optimistic about the national development prospect. It is the heroism of the ordinary Chinese to overcome difficulties and realize the ideal destiny that best explains China’s confidence. When this confidence is passed on in the field of diplomacy, it is expressed as: first, China’s posture is seen as more forging ahead and courageous to undertake responsibilities ---- proactively shaping the international agendas rather than passively accepting them; having clear-cut attitudes on international disputes rather than being equivocal; and extending international cooperation to comprehensive and dimensional development rather than based on the theory of “economy only”. In sum, China will actively seek understanding and support from other countries rather than imposing its will on others with clear-cut Chinese characteristics, Chinese style and Chinese manner. Second, China’s discourse is featured as a combination of inflexibility and yielding as well as magnanimous ---- combining the internationally recognized diplomatic principles with the excellent Chinese cultural traditions through digesting the Chinese and foreign humanistic classics assisted with philosophical speculations to make “China Brand, Chinese Voice and China’s Image get more and more recognized”. Third, <u><mark>the Chinese solution is more practical </mark>and intimate to people as well as <mark>emphasizes inclusive coop</mark>eration, as China is full of confidence to break the monopoly of the Western model on global development, “offering mankind a Chinese solution to explore a better social system”, and “providing a brand new option for the nations and peoples who are hoping both to speed up development and maintain independence”.</u> II.Path Searching of the “Chinese Solution” for Global Governance <u>Over the past years’ efforts, China has the ability to transform itself from “grasping the opportunity” for development to “creating opportunity” and “sharing opportunity” for common development, hoping to pass on the longing of the Chinese people for a better life to the people of other countries and promoting the development of the global governance system toward a more just and rational end. It has become the major power’s conscious commitment of China to lead the transformation of the global governance system in a profound way. </u>A. To Construct the Theoretical System for Global Governance. The theoretical system of global governance has been the focus of the party central committee’s diplomatic theory innovation since the 18th National Congress of CPC as well as an important component of the theory of socialism with Chinese characteristics for a new era, which is not only the sublimation of China’s interaction with the world from “absorbing and learning” to “cooperation and mutual learning”, but also the cause why so many developing countries have turned from “learning from the West” to “exploring for treasures in the East”. In the past 5 years, the party central committee, based on precise interpretation of the world pattern today and serious reflection on the future development of mankind, has made a sincere call to the world for promoting the development of global governance system toward a more just and rational end, and proposed a series of new concepts and new strategies including engaging in major power diplomacy with Chinese characteristics, creating the human community with common destiny, promoting the construction of new international relationship rooted in the principle of cooperation and win-win, enriching the strategic thinking of peaceful development, sticking to the correct benefit view, formulating the partnership network the world over, advancing the global economic governance in a way of mutual consultation, joint construction and co-sharing, advocating the joint, comprehensive, cooperative and sustainable security concept, and launching the grand “Belt and Road” initiative. <u>The Chinese solution composed of these contents, not only fundamentally different from the old roads of industrial revolution and colonial expansion in history, but also different from the market-driven neo-liberalism model currently advocated by Western countries and international organizations, stands at the height of the world and even mankind, seeking for global common development and having widened the road for the developing countries to modernization, which is widely welcomed by the international community. </u>B. To Supplement and Perfect the Global Governance System<u>. Currently, the international political practice in global governance is mostly problem-driven without creating a set of relatively independent, centralized and integral power structures, resulting in the existing global governance systemcharacterized as both extensive and unbalanced</u>. <u>China has been engaged in reform and innovation, while maintaining and constructing the existing systems, producing some thinking and method with Chinese characteristics. First, China sees the UN as a mirror that reflects the status quo of global governance, which should act as the leader of global governance, and actively safeguards the global governance system with the UN at the core. Second, China is actively promoting the transforming process of such recently emerged international mechanisms as G20, BRICS and SCO</u>, perfecting them through practice, and boosting Asia-Pacific regional cooperation and the development of economic globalization. China is also promoting the construction of regional security mechanism through the Six-Party Talks on Korean Peninsula nuclear issue, Boao Forum for Asia, CICA and multilateral security dialog mechanisms led by ASEAN so as to lay the foundation for the future regional security framework. Third, China has initiated the establishment of AIIB and the New Development Bank of BRICS, creating a precedent for developing countries to set up multilateral financial institutions. The core of the new relationship between China and them lies in “boosting rather than controlling” and “public rather than private”, which is much different from the management and operation model of the World Bank, manifesting the increasing global governance ability of China and the developing countries as well as exerting pressure on the international economic and financial institution to speed up reforms. <u><strong>Thus, in leading the transformation of the global governance system, <mark>China has not overthrown the existing systems</mark> and started all over again, <mark>but been engaged in innovating and perfecting</mark>; <mark>China </mark>has proactively <mark>undertaken international responsibilities</mark>, <mark>but has</mark> to do everything in its power and <mark>act according to its ability.</u></strong></mark> C. To Reform the Global Governance Rules. <u>Many of the problems facing global governance today are deeply rooted in such a cause that the dominant power of the existing governance system has taken it as the tool to realize its own national interests first and a platform to pursue its political goals.</u> Since the beginning of this year, the US has for several times requested the World Bank, IMF and G20 to make efforts to mitigate the so-called global imbalance, abandoned its commitment to support trade openness, cut down investment projects to the middle-income countries, and deleted commitment to support the efforts to deal with climate change financially, which has made the international systems accessories of the US domestic economic agendas, dealing a heavy blow to the global governance system. <u>On the contrary, the interests and agendas of China, as a major power of the world, are open to the whole world, and China in the future “will provide the world with broader market, more sufficient capital, more abundant goods and more precious opportunities for cooperation”, while having the ability to make the world listen to its voice more attentively.</u> <u>With regard to the subject of global governance, China has advocated that what global governance system is better cannot be decided upon by any single country, as the destiny of the world should be in the hands of the people of all countries. In principle, all the parties should stick to the principle of mutual consultation, joint construction and co-sharing, resolve disputes through dialog and differences through consultation</u>. Regarding the critical areas, opening to the outer world does not mean building one’s own backyard, but building the spring garden for co-sharing; the “Belt and Road” initiative is not China’s solo, but a chorus participated in by all countries concerned. <u><strong><mark>China</mark> has also <mark>proposed</mark> international <mark>public security views on nuclear security, maritime coop</mark>eration<mark> and cyber space order, calling for </mark>efforts to make the global village into a “grand stage for seeking<mark> common development”</mark> rather than a “wrestling arena”; we cannot “set up a stage here, while pulling away a prop there”, but “complement each other to put on a grand show”</u></strong>. From the orientation of reforms, efforts should be made to better safeguard and expand the legitimate interests of the developing countries and increase the influence of the emerging economies on global governance. Over the past 5 years, China has attached importance to full court diplomacy, gradually coming to the center stage of international politics and proactively establishing principles for global governance. By hosting such important events as IAELM, CICA Summit, G20 Summit, the Belt and Road International Cooperation Forum and BRICS Summit, China has used theseplatforms to elaborate the Asia-Pacific Dream for the first time to the world, expressing China’s views on Asian security and global economic governance, discussing with the countries concerned with the Belt and Road about the synergy of their future development strategies and setting off the “BRICS plus” capacity expansion mechanism, in which China not only contributes its solution and shows its style, but also participates in the shaping of international principles through practice. On promoting the resolution of hot international issues, China abides by the norms governing international relations based on the purposes and principles of the UN Charter, and insists on justice, playing a constructive role as a responsible major power in actively promoting the political accommodation in Afghanistan, mediating the Djibouti-Eritrea dispute, promoting peace talks in the Middle East, devoting itself to the peaceful resolution of the South China Sea dispute through negotiations. In addition, China’s responsibility and quick response to international crises have gained widespread praises, as seen in such cases as assisting Africa in its fight against the Ebola epidemic, sending emergency fresh water to the capital of Maldives and buying rice from Cambodia to help relieve its financial squeeze, which has shown the simple feelings of the Chinese people to share the same breath and fate with the people of other countries. D. To Support the Increase of the Developing Countries’ Voice. The developing countries, especially the emerging powers, are not only the important participants of the globalization process, but also the important direction to which the international power system is transferring. With the accelerating shift of global economic center to emerging markets and developing economies, the will and ability of the developing countries to participate in global governance have been correspondingly strengthened. <u>As the biggest developing country and fast growing major power, China has the same appeal and proposal for governance as other developing countries and already began policy coordination with them, as China should comply with historical tide and continue to support the increase of the developing countries’ voice in the global governance system. To this end, China has pursued the policy of “dialog but not confrontation, partnership but not alliance”, attaching importance to the construction of new type of major power relationship and global partnership network, while making a series proposals in the practice of global governance that could represent the legitimate interests of the developing countries and be conducive to safeguarding global justice, including supporting an open, inclusive, universal, balanced and win-win economic globalization; promoting the reforms on share and voting mechanism of IMF to increase the voting rights and representation of the emerging market economies; financing the infrastructure construction and industrial upgrading of other developing countries through various bilateral or regional funds; and helping other developing countries to respond to such challenges as famine, refugees, climate change and public hygiene by debt forgiveness and assistance.</p></u>
2NC
China Tech Good
2NC---Leadership---Multilat
10,200
211
143,399
./documents/hspolicy22/GlenbrookSouth/AlWa/GlenbrookSouth-AlWa-Neg-5---Blake-Round-4.docx
956,807
N
5 - Blake
4
Walter Payton SW
Josh Lamet
1AC - Quantum 1NC - Security K - T-DoD - Burden Sharing QPQ CP - Oversight CP - Germany PIC - Tetlock CP - China Tech Lead Good 2NR - Oversight CP
hspolicy22/GlenbrookSouth/AlWa/GlenbrookSouth-AlWa-Neg-5---Blake-Round-4.docx
2022-12-18 23:12:33
80,010
AlWa
Glenbrook South AlWa
2A - Aayan Ali (he/him) - [email protected] 2N - Harlan Warnsman (he/him) - [email protected]
Aa.....
Al.....
Ha.....
Wa.....
26,718
GlenbrookSouth
Glenbrook South
IL
null
2,002
hspolicy22
HS Policy 2022-23
2,022
cx
hs
2
1,709,522
‘Substantially limiting’ requires a broad restriction---it excludes single conditions
Signorello 1
Pamela Signorello 1, JD at Cornell University, “The Failure of the ADA - Achieving Parity with Respect to Mental and Physical Health Care Coverage in the Private Employment Realm”, Cornell Journal of Law and Public Policy
A substantial limitation is evident when one is "significantly restricted in the ability to perform a broad range of jobs in various classes one's inability to perform a single job does not constitute a substantial limitation
A substantial limitation is when one is "significantly restricted in a broad range in various classes inability to perform a single job does not constitute a substantial limitation
A substantial limitation of the major life activity of working is evident when one is "significantly restricted in the ability to perform either a class of jobs or a broad range of jobs in various classes as compared to the average- person having comparable training, skills, and abilities. '25 Hence, one's inability to perform a single job does not constitute a substantial limitation. 26
390
<h4>‘Substantially limiting’ requires a <u>broad</u> restriction---it <u>excludes</u> single conditions</h4><p>Pamela <strong>Signorello 1</strong>, JD at Cornell University, “The Failure of the ADA - Achieving Parity with Respect to Mental and Physical Health Care Coverage in the Private Employment Realm”, Cornell Journal of Law and Public Policy</p><p><u><mark>A <strong>substantial limitation</u></strong></mark> of the major life activity of working <u><mark>is</mark> evident <mark>when one is "significantly restricted in</mark> the ability to perform</u> either a class of jobs or <u><strong><mark>a broad range</mark> of jobs <mark>in various classes</u></strong></mark> as compared to the average- person having comparable training, skills, and abilities. '25 Hence, <u>one's <mark>inability to perform a <strong>single job</strong> does <strong>not</strong> constitute a substantial limitation</u></mark>. 26</p>
1NC
OFF
1NC
516,046
186
50,804
./documents/ndtceda20/Kentucky/DiGr/Kentucky-Di-Griffith-Neg-00%20NDT-Round5.docx
619,251
N
00 NDT
5
Emory GK
Val McIntosh, Patrick Waldinger, Alex Brown
1AC - Philippines Entrapment 1NC - T-Its T-Subs Infrastructure DA China Trade DA Assurances DA ConCon Cp National Referendum CP CMR Turn DCA Turn Block - DCA Turn China Trade DA 2NR - China Trade DA
ndtceda20/Kentucky/DiGr/Kentucky-Di-Griffith-Neg-00%20NDT-Round5.docx
null
52,345
DiGr
Kentucky DiGr
null
Jo.....
Di.....
Da.....
Gr.....
19,330
Kentucky
Kentucky
null
null
1,010
ndtceda20
NDT/CEDA 2020-21
2,020
cx
college
2
1,839,007
Interpretation --- Criminal justice refers to the entire complex of institutions and people involved with crime
Shinnar and Shinnar 75 -
Shlomo Shinnar and Reuel Shinnar, 75 - Albert Einstein College of Medicine, and School of Engineering; both from the City College of New York (“The Effects of the Criminal Justice System on the Control of Crime: A Quantitative
We use the term "criminal justice to denote the entire complex of institutions and people involved in dealing with crime and criminals.
criminal justice denote the entire complex of institutions and people dealing with crime and criminals
Approach” Law & Society Review, Vol. 9, No. 4 (Summer, 1975), pp. 581-612, JSTOR //DH 5. We use the term "criminal justice system" to denote the entire complex of institutions and people involved in dealing with crime and criminals. These include the police, the district attorney's office, the judiciary, the parole system and the prisons
339
<h4>Interpretation --- Criminal justice refers to the entire complex of institutions and people involved with crime</h4><p>Shlomo <strong>Shinnar and</strong> Reuel <strong>Shinnar</strong>, <strong>75 - </strong>Albert Einstein College of Medicine, and School of Engineering; both from the City College of New York (“The Effects of the Criminal Justice System on the Control of Crime: A Quantitative</p><p>Approach” Law & Society Review, Vol. 9, No. 4 (Summer, 1975), pp. 581-612, JSTOR //DH</p><p> 5. <u>We use the term "<mark>criminal justice</u></mark> system" <u>to <mark>denote the entire complex of institutions and people</mark> involved in <mark>dealing with crime and criminals</mark>.</u> These include the police, the district attorney's office, the judiciary, the parole system and the prisons</p>
1NC
null
OFF-T
56,642
339
53,890
./documents/hspolicy20/BlueValleyNorthwest/ScIn/Blue%20Valley%20Northwest-Schiffman-InglesNguyen-Neg-Iowa%20caucus-Round1.docx
725,405
N
Iowa caucus
1
Bluevalley West VB
Arriq Singleton
1AC- Abolish ice 1NC- T civil T policing T "in the us" NGA Borders K 2NR- NGA
hspolicy20/BlueValleyNorthwest/ScIn/Blue%20Valley%20Northwest-Schiffman-InglesNguyen-Neg-Iowa%20caucus-Round1.docx
null
61,898
ScIn
Blue Valley Northwest ScIn
null
St.....
Sc.....
Kr.....
In.....
21,520
BlueValleyNorthwest
Blue Valley Northwest
KS
null
1,019
hspolicy20
HS Policy 2020-21
2,020
cx
hs
2